Quotations.ch
  Directory : Essays on Political Economy (part of Munera Pulveris)
GUIDE SUPPORT US BLOG
  • The Project Gutenberg eBook, Unto This Last and Other Essays on Political
  • Economy, by John Ruskin
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
  • almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
  • re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
  • with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
  • Title: Unto This Last and Other Essays on Political Economy
  • Author: John Ruskin
  • Release Date: June 27, 2011 [eBook #36541]
  • Language: English
  • ***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK UNTO THIS LAST AND OTHER ESSAYS ON
  • POLITICAL ECONOMY***
  • E-text prepared by David Clarke and the Online Distributed Proofreading
  • Team (http://www.pgdp.net)
  • UNTO THIS LAST AND OTHER ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY
  • by
  • JOHN RUSKIN
  • London
  • Melbourne & Toronto
  • Ward Lock & Co Limited
  • 1912
  • CONTENTS.
  • PART I.
  • PAGE
  • THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF ART 7
  • LECTURE I. 11
  • 1. Discovery 23
  • 2. Application 28
  • LECTURE II. 46
  • 3. Accumulation 46
  • 4. Distribution 65
  • ADDENDA 86
  • Note 1.--"Fatherly Authority" 86
  • " 2.--"Right to Public Support" 90
  • " 3.--"Trial Schools" 95
  • " 4.--"Public Favour" 101
  • " 5.--"Invention of new wants" 102
  • " 6.--"Economy of Literature" 104
  • " 7.--"Pilots of the State" 106
  • " 8.--"Silk and Purple" 107
  • PART II.
  • UNTO THIS LAST 117
  • ESSAY
  • I.--The Roots of Honour 127
  • II.--The Veins of Wealth 143
  • III.--"Qui Judicatis Terram" 156
  • IV.--Ad Valorem 173
  • PART III.
  • ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY[A]
  • I.--MAINTENANCE OF LIFE: WEALTH, MONEY AND RICHES 207
  • Section 1. Wealth 214
  • " 2. Money 219
  • " 3. Riches 222
  • II.--NATURE OF WEALTH, VARIATIONS OF VALUE, THE NATIONAL
  • STORE, NATURE OF LABOUR, VALUE AND PRICE, THE CURRENCY 225
  • III.--THE CURRENCY-HOLDERS AND STORE-HOLDERS, THE DISEASE
  • OF DESIRE 252
  • IV.--LAWS AND GOVERNMENTS: LABOUR AND RICHES 278
  • [A] These Essays were afterwards revised and amplified, and
  • published with others under the title "Munera Pulveris."
  • THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF ART.
  • PREFACE.
  • The greater part of the following treatise remains in the exact form
  • in which it was read at Manchester; but the more familiar passages of
  • it, which were trusted to extempore delivery, have been since written
  • with greater explicitness and fullness than I could give them in
  • speaking; and a considerable number of notes are added, to explain the
  • points which could not be sufficiently considered in the time I had at
  • my disposal in the lecture-room.
  • Some apology may be thought due to the reader, for an endeavour to
  • engage his attention on a subject of which no profound study seems
  • compatible with the work in which I am usually employed. But profound
  • study is not, in this case, necessary either to writer or reader,
  • while accurate study, up to a certain point, is necessary for us all.
  • Political economy means, in plain English, nothing more than
  • "citizens' economy"; and its first principles ought, therefore, to be
  • understood by all who mean to take the responsibility of citizens, as
  • those of household economy by all who take the responsibility of
  • householders. Nor are its first principles in the least obscure: they
  • are, many of them, disagreeable in their practical requirements, and
  • people in general pretend that they cannot understand, because they
  • are unwilling to obey them; or, rather, by habitual disobedience,
  • destroy their capacity of understanding them. But there is not one of
  • the really great principles of the science which is either obscure or
  • disputable--which might not be taught to a youth as soon as he can be
  • trusted with an annual allowance, or to a young lady as soon as she is
  • of age to be taken into counsel by the housekeeper.
  • I might, with more appearance of justice, be blamed for thinking it
  • necessary to enforce what everybody is supposed to know. But this
  • fault will hardly be found with me, while the commercial events
  • recorded daily in our journals, and still more the explanations
  • attempted to be given of them, show that a large number of our
  • so-called merchants are as ignorant of the nature of money as they are
  • reckless, unjust, and unfortunate in its employment.
  • The statements of economical principle given in the text, though I
  • know that most, if not all, of them are accepted by existing
  • authorities on the science, are not supported by references, because I
  • have never read any author on political economy, except Adam Smith,
  • twenty years ago.[1] Whenever I have taken up any modern book upon
  • this subject, I have usually found it encumbered with inquiries into
  • accidental or minor commercial results, for the pursuit of which an
  • ordinary reader could have no leisure, and, by the complication of
  • which, it seemed to me, the authors themselves had been not
  • unfrequently prevented from seeing to the root of the business.
  • [1] 1857.
  • Finally, if the reader should feel inclined to blame me for too
  • sanguine a statement of future possibilities in political practice,
  • let him consider how absurd it would have appeared in the days of
  • Edward I. if the present state of social economy had been then
  • predicted as necessary, or even described as possible. And I believe
  • the advance from the days of Edward I. to our own, great as it is
  • confessedly, consists, not so much in what we have actually
  • accomplished, as in what we are now enabled to conceive.
  • LECTURE I.
  • Among the various characteristics of the age in which we live, as
  • compared with other ages of this not yet _very_ experienced world, one
  • of the most notable appears to me to be the just and wholesome
  • contempt in which we hold poverty. I repeat, the _just_ and
  • _wholesome_ contempt; though I see that some of my hearers look
  • surprised at the expression. I assure them, I use it in sincerity; and
  • I should not have ventured to ask you to listen to me this evening,
  • unless I had entertained a profound respect for wealth--true wealth,
  • that is to say; for, of course, we ought to respect neither wealth nor
  • anything else that is false of its kind: and the distinction between
  • real and false wealth is one of the points on which I shall have a few
  • words presently to say to you. But true wealth I hold, as I said, in
  • great honour; and sympathize, for the most part, with that
  • extraordinary feeling of the present age which publicly pays this
  • honour to riches. I cannot, however, help noticing how extraordinary
  • it is, and how this epoch of ours differs from all bygone epochs in
  • having no philosophical nor religious worshippers of the ragged
  • godship of poverty. In the classical ages, not only there were people
  • who voluntarily lived in tubs, and who used gravely to maintain the
  • superiority of tub-life to town-life, but the Greeks and Latins seem
  • to have looked on these eccentric, and I do not scruple to say, absurd
  • people, with as much respect as we do upon large capitalists and
  • landed proprietors; so that really, in those days, no one could be
  • described as purse proud, but only as empty-purse proud. And no less
  • distinct than the honour which those curious Greek people pay to their
  • conceited poor, is the disrespectful manner in which they speak of
  • the rich; so that one cannot listen long either to them, or to the
  • Roman writers who imitated them, without finding oneself entangled in
  • all sorts of plausible absurdities; hard upon being convinced of the
  • uselessness of collecting that heavy yellow substance which we call
  • gold, and led generally to doubt all the most established maxims of
  • political economy. Nor are matters much better in the middle ages. For
  • the Greeks and Romans contented themselves with mocking at rich
  • people, and constructing merry dialogues between Charon and Diogenes
  • or Menippus, in which the ferryman and the cynic rejoiced together as
  • they saw kings and rich men coming down to the shore of Acheron, in
  • lamenting and lamentable crowds, casting their crowns into the dark
  • waters, and searching, sometimes in vain, for the last coin out of all
  • their treasures that could ever be of use to them. But these Pagan
  • views of the matter were indulgent, compared with those which were
  • held in the middle ages, when wealth seems to have been looked upon by
  • the best men not only as contemptible, but as criminal. The purse
  • round the neck is, then, one of the principal signs of condemnation in
  • the pictured Inferno; and the Spirit of Poverty is reverenced with
  • subjection of heart, and faithfulness of affection, like that of a
  • loyal knight for his lady, or a loyal subject for his queen. And
  • truly, it requires some boldness to quit ourselves of these feelings,
  • and to confess their partiality or their error, which, nevertheless,
  • we are certainly bound to do. For wealth is simply one of the greatest
  • powers which can be entrusted to human hands: a power, not indeed to
  • be envied, because it seldom makes us happy; but still less to be
  • abdicated or despised; while, in these days, and in this country, it
  • has become a power all the more notable, in that the possessions of a
  • rich man are not represented, as they used to be, by wedges of gold or
  • coffers of jewels, but by masses of men variously employed, over whose
  • bodies and minds the wealth, according to its direction, exercises
  • harmful or helpful influence, and becomes, in that alternative, Mammon
  • either of Unrighteousness or of Righteousness.
  • Now, it seemed to me that since, in the name you have given to this
  • great gathering of British pictures, you recognise them as
  • Treasures--that is, I suppose, as part and parcel of the real wealth
  • of the country--you might not be uninterested in tracing certain
  • commercial questions connected with this particular form of wealth.
  • Most persons express themselves as surprised at its quantity; not
  • having known before to what an extent good art had been accumulated in
  • England: and it will, therefore, I should think, be held a worthy
  • subject of consideration, what are the political interests involved in
  • such accumulations; what kind of labour they represent, and how this
  • labour may in general be applied and economized, so as to produce the
  • richest results.
  • Now, you must have patience with me, if in approaching the specialty
  • of this subject, I dwell a little on certain points of general
  • political science already known or established: for though thus, as I
  • believe, established, some which I shall have occasion to rest
  • arguments on are not yet by any means universally accepted; and
  • therefore, though I will not lose time in any detailed defence of
  • them, it is necessary that I should distinctly tell you in what form I
  • receive, and wish to argue from them; and this the more, because there
  • may perhaps be a part of my audience who have not interested
  • themselves in political economy, as it bears on ordinary fields of
  • labour, but may yet wish to hear in what way its principles can be
  • applied to Art. I shall, therefore, take leave to trespass on your
  • patience with a few elementary statements in the outset, and with, the
  • expression of some general principles, here and there, in the course
  • of our particular inquiry.
  • To begin, then, with one of these necessary truisms: all economy,
  • whether of states, households, or individuals, may be defined to be
  • the art of managing labour. The world is so regulated by the laws of
  • Providence, that a man's labour, well applied, is always amply
  • sufficient to provide him during his life with all things needful to
  • him, and not only with those, but with many pleasant objects of
  • luxury; and yet farther, to procure him large intervals of healthful
  • rest and serviceable leisure. And a nation's labour, well applied, is
  • in like manner, amply sufficient to provide its whole population with
  • good food and comfortable habitation; and not with those only, but
  • with good education besides, and objects of luxury, art treasures,
  • such as these you have around you now. But by those same laws of
  • Nature and Providence, if the labour of the nation or of the
  • individual be misapplied, and much more if it be insufficient,--if the
  • nation or man be indolent and unwise,--suffering and want result,
  • exactly in proportion to the indolence and improvidence,--to the
  • refusal of labour, or to the misapplication of it. Wherever you see
  • want, or misery, or degradation, in this world about you, there, be
  • sure, either industry has been wanting, or industry has been in error.
  • It is not accident, it is not Heaven-commanded calamity, it is not the
  • original and inevitable evil of man's nature, which fill your streets
  • with lamentation, and your graves with prey. It is only that, when
  • there should have been providence, there has been waste; when there
  • should have been labour, there has been lasciviousness; and,
  • wilfulness, when there should have been subordination.[2]
  • [2] Proverbs xiii. 23: "Much food is in the tillage of the poor:
  • but there is that is destroyed for want of judgment."
  • Now, we have warped the word "economy" in our English: language into a
  • meaning which it has no business whatever to bear. In our use of it,
  • it constantly signifies merely sparing or saving; economy of money
  • means saving money--economy of time, sparing time, and so on. But that
  • is a wholly barbarous use of the word--barbarous in a double sense,
  • for it is not English, and it is bad Greek; barbarous in a treble
  • sense, for it is not English, it is bad Greek, and it is worse sense.
  • Economy no more means saving money than it means spending money. It
  • means, the administration of a house; its stewardship; spending or
  • saving, that is, whether money or time, or anything else, to the best
  • possible advantage. In the simplest and clearest definition of it,
  • economy, whether public or private, means the wise management of
  • labour; and it means this mainly in three senses: namely, first,
  • _applying_ your labour rationally; secondly, _preserving_ its produce
  • carefully; lastly, _distributing_ its produce seasonably.
  • I say first, applying your labour rationally; that is, so as to obtain
  • the most precious things you can, and the most lasting things, by it:
  • not growing oats in land where you can grow wheat, nor putting fine
  • embroidery on a stuff that will not wear. Secondly, preserving its
  • produce carefully; that is to say, laying up your wheat wisely in
  • storehouses for the time of famine, and keeping your embroidery
  • watchfully from the moth: and lastly, distributing its produce
  • seasonably; that is to say, being able to carry your corn at once to
  • the place where the people are hungry, and your embroideries to the
  • places where they are gay, so fulfilling in all ways the Wise Man's
  • description, whether of the queenly housewife or queenly nation. "She
  • riseth while it is yet night, and giveth meat to her household, and a
  • portion to her maidens. She maketh herself coverings of tapestry, her
  • clothing is silk and purple. Strength and honour are in her clothing,
  • and she shall rejoice in time to come."
  • Now, you will observe that in this description of the perfect
  • economist, or mistress of a household, there is a studied expression
  • of the balanced division of her care between the two great objects of
  • utility and splendour; in her right hand, food and flax, for life and
  • clothing; in her left hand, the purple and the needlework, for honour
  • and for beauty. All perfect housewifery or national economy is known
  • by these two divisions; wherever either is wanting, the economy is
  • imperfect. If the motive of pomp prevails, and the care of the
  • national economist is directed only to the accumulation of gold, and
  • of pictures, and of silk and marble, you know at once that the time
  • must soon come when all these treasures shall be scattered and blasted
  • in national ruin. If, on the contrary, the element of utility
  • prevails, and the nation disdains to occupy itself in any wise with
  • the arts of beauty or delight, not only a certain quantity of its
  • energy calculated for exercise in those arts alone must be entirely
  • wasted, which is bad economy, but also the passions connected with the
  • utilities of property become morbidly strong, and a mean lust of
  • accumulation merely for the sake of accumulation, or even of labour
  • merely for the sake of labour, will banish at last the serenity and
  • the morality of life, as completely, and perhaps more ignobly, than
  • even the lavishness of pride and the lightness of pleasure. And
  • similarly, and much more visibly, in private and household economy,
  • you may judge always of its perfectness by its fair balance between
  • the use and the pleasure of its possessions. You will see the wise
  • cottager's garden trimly divided between its well-set vegetables, and
  • its fragrant flowers; you will see the good housewife taking pride in
  • her pretty table-cloth, and her glittering shelves, no less than in
  • her well-dressed dish, and her full storeroom; the care in her
  • countenance will alternate with gaiety, and though you will reverence
  • her in her seriousness, you will know her best by her smile.
  • Now, as you will have anticipated, I am going to address you, on this
  • and our succeeding evening, chiefly on the subject of that economy
  • which relates rather to the garden than the farm-yard. I shall ask you
  • to consider with me the kind of laws by which we shall best distribute
  • the beds of our national garden, and raise in it the sweetest
  • succession of trees pleasant to the sight, and (in no forbidden sense)
  • to be desired to make us wise. But, before proceeding to open this
  • specialty of our subject, let me pause for a few moments to plead with
  • you for the acceptance of that principle of government or authority
  • which must be at the root of all economy, whether for use or for
  • pleasure. I said, a few minutes ago, that a nation's labour, well
  • applied, was amply sufficient to provide its whole population with
  • good food, comfortable clothing, and pleasant luxury. But the good,
  • instant, and constant application is everything. We must not, when our
  • strong hands are thrown out of work, look wildly about for want of
  • something to do with them. If ever we feel that want, it is a sign
  • that all our household is out of order. Fancy a farmer's wife, to whom
  • one or two of her servants should come at twelve o'clock at noon,
  • crying that they had got nothing to do; that they did not know what to
  • do next: and fancy still farther, the said farmer's wife looking
  • hopelessly about her rooms and yard, they being all the while
  • considerably in disorder, not knowing where to set the spare
  • hand-maidens to work, and at last complaining bitterly that she had
  • been obliged to give them their dinner for nothing. That's the type of
  • the kind of political economy we practise too often in England. Would
  • you not at once assert of such a mistress that she knew nothing of her
  • duties? and would you not be certain, if the household were rightly
  • managed, the mistress would be only too glad at any moment to have the
  • help of any number of spare hands; that she would know in an instant
  • what to set them to;--in an instant what part of to-morrow's work
  • might be most serviceably forwarded, what part of next month's work
  • most wisely provided for, or what new task of some profitable kind
  • undertaken? and when the evening came, and she dismissed her servants
  • to their recreation or their rest, or gathered them to the reading
  • round the work-table, under the eaves in the sunset, would you not be
  • sure to find that none of them had been overtasked by her, just
  • because none had been left idle; that everything had been accomplished
  • because all had been employed; that the kindness of the mistress had
  • aided her presence of mind, and the slight labour had been entrusted
  • to the weak, and the formidable to the strong; and that as none had
  • been dishonoured by inactivity so none had been broken by toil?
  • Now, the precise counterpart of such a household would be seen in a
  • nation in which political economy was rightly understood. You complain
  • of the difficulty of finding work for your men. Depend upon it, the
  • real difficulty rather is to find men for your work. The serious
  • question for you is not how many you have to feed, but how much you
  • have to do; it is our inactivity, not our hunger, that ruins us: let
  • us never fear that our servants should have a good appetite--our
  • wealth is in their strength, not in their starvation. Look around this
  • island of yours, and see what you have to do in it. The sea roars
  • against your harbourless cliffs--you have to build the breakwater, and
  • dig the port of refuge; the unclean pestilence ravins in your
  • streets--you have to bring the full stream from the hills, and to send
  • the free winds through the thoroughfare; the famine blanches your lips
  • and eats away your flesh--you have to dig the moor and dry the marsh,
  • to bid the morass give forth instead of engulphing, and to wring the
  • honey and oil out of the rock. These things, and thousands such, we
  • have to do, and shall have to do constantly, on this great farm of
  • ours; for do not suppose that it is anything else than that. Precisely
  • the same laws of economy which apply to the cultivation of a farm or
  • an estate apply to the cultivation of a province or of an island.
  • Whatever rebuke you would address to the improvident master of an
  • ill-managed patrimony, precisely that rebuke we should address to
  • ourselves, so far as we leave our population in idleness and our
  • country in disorder. What would you say to the lord of an estate who
  • complained to you of his poverty and disabilities, and, when you
  • pointed out to him that his land was half of it overrun with weeds,
  • and that his fences were all in ruin, and that his cattle-sheds were
  • roofless, and his labourers lying under the hedges faint for want of
  • food, he answered to you that it would ruin him to weed his land or to
  • roof his sheds--that those were too costly operations for him to
  • undertake, and that he knew not how to feed his labourers nor pay
  • them? Would you not instantly answer, that instead of ruining him to
  • weed his fields, it would save him; that his inactivity was his
  • destruction, and that to set his labourers to work was to feed them?
  • Now, you may add acre to acre, and estate to estate, as far as you
  • like, but you will never reach a compass of ground which shall escape
  • from the authority of these simple laws. The principles which are
  • right in the administration of a few fields, are right also in the
  • administration of a great country from horizon to horizon: idleness
  • does not cease to be ruinous because it is extensive, nor labour to be
  • productive because it is universal.
  • Nay, but you reply, there is one vast difference between the nation's
  • economy and the private man's: the farmer has full authority over his
  • labourers; he can direct them to do what is needed to be done, whether
  • they like it or not; and he can turn them away if they refuse to work,
  • or impede others in their working, or are disobedient, or quarrelsome.
  • There _is_ this great difference; it is precisely this difference on
  • which I wish to fix your attention, for it is precisely this
  • difference which you have to do away with. We know the necessity of
  • authority in farm, or in fleet, or in army; but we commonly refuse to
  • admit it in the body of the nation. Let us consider this point a
  • little.
  • In the various awkward and unfortunate efforts which the French have
  • made at the development of a social system, they have at least stated
  • one true principle, that of fraternity or brotherhood. Do not be
  • alarmed; they got all wrong in their experiments, because they quite
  • forgot that this fact of fraternity implied another fact quite as
  • important--that of paternity or fatherhood. That is to say, if they
  • were to regard the nation as one family, the condition of unity in
  • that family consisted no less in their having a head, or a father,
  • than in their being faithful and affectionate members, or brothers.
  • But we must not forget this, for we have long confessed it with our
  • lips, though we refuse to confess it in our lives. For half an hour
  • every Sunday we expect a man in a black gown, supposed to be telling
  • us truth, to address us as brethren, though we should be shocked at
  • the notion of any brotherhood existing among us out of church. And we
  • can hardly read a few sentences on any political subject without
  • running a chance of crossing the phrase "paternal government," though
  • we should be utterly horror-struck at the idea of governments claiming
  • anything like a father's authority over us. Now, I believe those two
  • formal phrases are in both instances perfectly binding and accurate,
  • and that the image of the farm and its servants which I have hitherto
  • used, as expressing a wholesome national organization, fails only of
  • doing so, not because it is too domestic, but because it is not
  • domestic enough; because the real type of a well-organized nation must
  • be presented, not by a farm cultivated by servants who wrought for
  • hire, and might be turned away if they refused to labour, but by a
  • farm in which the master was a father, and in which all the servants
  • were sons; which implied, therefore, in all its regulations, not
  • merely the order of expediency, but the bonds of affection and
  • responsibilities of relationship; and in which all acts and services
  • were not only to be sweetened by brotherly concord, but to be enforced
  • by fatherly authority.[3]
  • [3] See note 1st, in Addenda [p. 86].
  • Observe, I do not mean in the least that we ought to place such an
  • authority in the hands of any one person, or of any class or body of
  • persons. But I do mean to say that as an individual who conducts
  • himself wisely must make laws for himself which at some time or other
  • may appear irksome or injurious, but which, precisely at the time they
  • appear most irksome, it is most necessary he should obey, so a nation
  • which means to conduct itself wisely, must establish authority over
  • itself, vested either in kings, councils, or laws, which it must
  • resolve to obey, even at times when the law or authority appears
  • irksome to the body of the people, or injurious to certain masses of
  • it. And this kind of national law has hitherto been only judicial;
  • contented, that is, with an endeavour to prevent and punish violence
  • and crime: but, as we advance in our social knowledge; we shall
  • endeavour to make our government paternal as well as judicial; that
  • is, to establish such laws and authorities as may at once direct us in
  • our occupations, protect us against our follies, and visit us in our
  • distresses: a government which shall repress dishonesty, as now it
  • punishes theft; which shall show how the discipline of the masses may
  • be brought to aid the toils of peace, as discipline of the masses has
  • hitherto knit the sinews of battle; a government which shall have its
  • soldiers of the ploughshare as well as its soldiers of the sword, and
  • which shall distribute more proudly its golden crosses of
  • industry--golden as the glow of the harvest, than now it grants its
  • bronze crosses of honour--bronzed with the crimson of blood.
  • I have not, of course, time to insist on the nature or details of
  • government of this kind; only I wish to plead for your several and
  • future consideration of this one truth, that the notion of Discipline
  • and Interference lies at the very root of all human progress or power;
  • that the "Let alone" principle is, in all things which man has to do
  • with, the principle of death; that it is ruin to him, certain and
  • total, if he lets his land alone--if he lets his fellow-men alone--if
  • he lets his own soul alone. That his whole life, on the contrary,
  • must, if it is healthy life, be continually one of ploughing and
  • pruning, rebuking and helping, governing and punishing; and that
  • therefore it is only in the concession of some great principle of
  • restraint and interference in national action that he can ever hope to
  • find the secret of protection against national degradation. I believe
  • that the masses have a right to claim education from their government;
  • but only so far as they acknowledge the duty of yielding obedience to
  • their government. I believe they have a right to claim employment from
  • their governours; but only so far as they yield to the governour the
  • direction and discipline of their labour; and it is only so far as
  • they grant to the men whom they may set over them the father's
  • authority to check the childishnesses of national fancy, and direct
  • the waywardnesses of national energy, that they have a right to ask
  • that none of their distresses should be unrelieved, none of their
  • weaknesses unwatched; and that no grief, nor nakedness, nor peril
  • should exist for them, against which the father's hand was not
  • outstretched, or the father's shield uplifted.[4]
  • [4] Compare Wordsworth's Essay on the Poor-Law Amendment Bill.
  • I quote one important passage:--"But, if it be not safe to
  • touch the abstract question of man's right in a social state
  • to help himself even in the last extremity, may we not still
  • contend for the duty of a Christian government, standing _in
  • loco parentis_ towards all its subjects, to make such
  • effectual provision that no one shall be in danger of
  • perishing either through the neglect or harshness of its
  • legislation? Or, waiving this, is it not indisputable that
  • the claim of the State to the allegiance, involves the
  • protection of the subject? And, as all rights in one party
  • impose a correlative duty upon another, it follows that the
  • right of the State to require the services of its members,
  • even to the jeoparding of their lives in the common defence,
  • establishes a right in the people (not to be gainsaid by
  • utilitarians and economists) to public support when, from
  • any cause, they may be unable to support themselves."--(See
  • note 2nd in Addenda [p. 90]).
  • Now, I have pressed this upon you at more length than is needful or
  • proportioned to our present purposes of inquiry, because I would not
  • for the first time speak to you on this subject of political economy
  • without clearly stating what I believe to be its first grand
  • principle. But its bearing on the matter in hand is chiefly to prevent
  • you from at once too violently dissenting from me when what I may
  • state to you as advisable economy in art appears to imply too much
  • restraint or interference with the freedom of the patron or artist. We
  • are a little apt, though, on the whole a prudent nation, to act too
  • immediately on our impulses, even in matters merely commercial; much
  • more in those involving continual appeals to our fancies. How far,
  • therefore, the proposed systems or restraints may be advisable, it is
  • for you to judge; only I pray you not to be offended with them merely
  • because they _are_ systems and restraints. Do you at all recollect
  • that interesting passage of Carlyle, in which he compares, in this
  • country and at this day, the understood and commercial value of man
  • and horse; and in which he wonders that the horse, with its inferior
  • brains and its awkward hoofiness, instead of handiness, should be
  • always worth so many tens or scores of pounds in the market, while the
  • man, so far from always commanding his price in the market, would
  • often be thought to confer a service on the community by simply
  • killing himself out of their way? Well, Carlyle does not answer his
  • own question, because he supposes we shall at once see the answer. The
  • value of the horse consists simply in the fact of your being able to
  • put a bridle on him. The value of the man consists precisely in the
  • same thing. If you can bridle him, or which is better, if he can
  • bridle himself, he will be a valuable creature directly. Otherwise, in
  • a commercial point of view, his value is either nothing, or accidental
  • only. Only, of course, the proper bridle of man is not a leathern one:
  • what kind of texture it is rightly made of, we find from that command,
  • "Be ye not as the horse or as the mule which have no understanding,
  • whose mouths must be held in with bit and bridle." You are not to be
  • without the reins, indeed, but they are to be of another kind; "I will
  • guide thee with mine Eye." So the bridle of man is to be the Eye of
  • God; and if he rejects that guidance, then the next best for him is
  • the horse's and the mule's, which have no understanding; and if he
  • rejects that, and takes the bit fairly in his teeth, then there is
  • nothing left for him than the blood that comes out of the city, up to
  • the horsebridles.
  • Quitting, however, at last these general and serious laws of
  • government--or rather bringing them down to our own business in
  • hand--we have to consider three points of discipline in that
  • particular branch of human labour which is concerned, not with
  • procuring of food, but the expression of emotion; we have to consider
  • respecting art: first, how to apply our labour to it; then, how to
  • accumulate or preserve the results of labour; and then, how to
  • distribute them. But since in art the labour which we have to employ
  • is the labour of a particular class of men--men who have special
  • genius for the business, we have not only to consider how to apply the
  • labour, but first of all, how to produce the labourer; and thus the
  • question in this particular case becomes fourfold: first, how to get
  • your man of genius; then, how to employ your man of genius; then, how
  • to accumulate and preserve his work in the greatest quantity; and
  • lastly, how to distribute his work to the best national advantage. Let
  • us take up these questions in succession.
  • I. DISCOVERY.--How are we to get our men of genius: that is to say, by
  • what means may we produce among us, at any given time, the greatest
  • quantity of effective art-intellect? A wide question, you say,
  • involving an account of all the best means of art education. Yes, but
  • I do not mean to go into the consideration of those; I want only to
  • state the few principles which lie at the foundation of the matter. Of
  • these, the first is that you have always to find your artist, not to
  • make him; you can't manufacture him, any more than you can manufacture
  • gold. You can find him, and refine him: you dig him out as he lies
  • nugget-fashion in the mountain-stream; you bring him home; and you
  • make him into current coin, or household plate, but not one grain of
  • him can you originally produce. A certain quantity of art-intellect is
  • born annually in every nation, greater or less according to the nature
  • and cultivation of the nation or race of men; but a perfectly fixed
  • quantity annually, not increaseable by one grain. You may lose it, or
  • you may gather it; you may let it lie loose in the ravine, and buried
  • in the sands, or you may make kings' thrones of it, and overlay temple
  • gates with it, as you choose: but the best you can do with it is
  • always merely sifting, melting, hammering, purifying--never creating.
  • And there is another thing notable about this artistical gold; not
  • only is it limited in quantity, but in use. You need not make thrones
  • or golden gates with it unless you like, but assuredly you can't do
  • anything else with it. You can't make knives of it, nor armour, nor
  • railroads. The gold won't cut you, and it won't carry you; put it to a
  • mechanical use, and you destroy it at once. It is quite true that in
  • the greatest artists, their proper artistical faculty is united with
  • every other; and you may make use of the other faculties, and let the
  • artistical one lie dormant. For aught I know, there may be two or
  • three Leonardo da Vincis employed at this moment in your harbours and
  • railroads: but you are not employing their Leonardesque or golden
  • faculty there, you are only oppressing and destroying it. And the
  • artistical gift in average men is not joined with others; your born
  • painter, if you don't make a painter of him, won't be a first-rate
  • merchant, or lawyer; at all events, whatever he turns out, his own
  • special gift is unemployed by you; and in no wise helps him in that
  • other business. So here you have a certain quantity of a particular
  • sort of intelligence, produced for you annually by providential laws,
  • which you can only make use of by setting it to its own proper work,
  • and which any attempt to use otherwise involves the dead loss of so
  • much human energy. Well, then, supposing we wish to employ it, how is
  • it to be best discovered and refined? It is easily enough discovered.
  • To wish to employ it is to discover it. All that you need is, a school
  • of trial[5] in every important town, in which those idle farmers' lads
  • whom their masters never can keep out of mischief, and those stupid
  • tailors' 'prentices who are always stitching the sleeves in wrong way
  • upwards, may have a try at this other trade; only this school of trial
  • must not be entirely regulated by formal laws of art education, but
  • must ultimately be the workshop of a good master painter, who will try
  • the lads with one kind of art and another, till he finds out what they
  • are fit for. Next, after your trial school, you want your easy and
  • secure employment, which is the matter of chief importance. For, even
  • on the present system, the boys who have really intense art capacity,
  • generally make painters of themselves; but then, the best half of
  • their early energy is lost in the battle of life. Before a good
  • painter can get employment, his mind has always been embittered, and
  • his genius distorted. A common mind usually stoops, in plastic chill,
  • to whatever is asked of it, and scrapes or daubs its way complacently
  • into public favour.[6] But your great men quarrel with you, and you
  • revenge yourselves by starving them for the first half of their lives.
  • Precisely in the degree in which any painter possesses original
  • genius, is at present the increase of moral certainty that during his
  • early years he will have a hard battle to fight; and that just at the
  • time when his conceptions ought to be full and happy, his temper
  • gentle, and his hopes enthusiastic--just at that most critical period,
  • his heart is full of anxieties and household cares; he is chilled by
  • disappointments, and vexed by injustice; he becomes obstinate in his
  • errors, no less than in his virtues, and the arrows of his aims are
  • blunted, as the reeds of his trust are broken.
  • [5] See note 3rd, in Addenda [p. 95].
  • [6] See note 4th, in Addenda [p. 101].
  • What we mainly want, therefore, is a means of sufficient and
  • unagitated employment: not holding out great prizes for which young
  • painters are to scramble; but furnishing all with adequate support,
  • and opportunity to display such power as they possess without
  • rejection or mortification. I need not say that the best field of
  • labour of this kind would be presented by the constant progress of
  • public works involving various decoration; and we will presently
  • examine what kind of public works may thus, advantageously for the
  • nation, be in constant progress. But a more important matter even than
  • this of steady employment, is the kind of criticism with which you,
  • the public, receive the works of the young men submitted to you. You
  • may do much harm by indiscreet praise and by indiscreet blame; but
  • remember, the chief harm is always done by blame. It stands to reason
  • that a young man's work cannot be perfect. It _must_ be more or less
  • ignorant; it must be more or less feeble; it is likely that it may be
  • more or less experimental, and if experimental, here and there
  • mistaken. If, therefore, you allow yourself to launch out into sudden
  • barking at the first faults you see, the probability is that you are
  • abusing the youth for some defect naturally and inevitably belonging
  • to that stage of his progress; and that you might just as rationally
  • find fault with a child for not being as prudent as a privy
  • councillor, or with a kitten for not being as grave as a cat. But
  • there is one fault which you may be quite sure is unnecessary, and
  • therefore a real and blameable fault: that is haste, involving
  • negligence. Whenever you see that a young man's work is either bold or
  • slovenly, then you may attack it firmly; sure of being right. If his
  • work is bold, it is insolent; repress his insolence: if it is
  • slovenly, it is indolent; spur his indolence. So long as he works in
  • that dashing or impetuous way, the best hope for him is in your
  • contempt: and it is only by the fact of his seeming not to seek your
  • approbation that you may conjecture he deserves it.
  • But if he does deserve it, be sure that you give it him, else you not
  • only run a chance of driving him from the right road by want of
  • encouragement, but you deprive yourselves of the happiest privilege
  • you will ever have of rewarding his labour. For it is only the young
  • who can receive much reward from men's praise: the old, when they are
  • great, get too far beyond and above you to care what you think of
  • them. You may urge them then with sympathy, and surround them then
  • with acclamation; but they will doubt your pleasure, and despise your
  • praise. You might have cheered them in their race through the asphodel
  • meadows of their youth; you might have brought the proud, bright
  • scarlet into their faces, if you had but cried once to them "Well
  • done," as they dashed up to the first goal of their early ambition.
  • But now, their pleasure is in memory, and their ambition is in heaven.
  • They can be kind to you, but you never more can be kind to them. You
  • may be fed with the fruit and fullness of their old age, but you were
  • as the nipping blight to them in their blossoming, and your praise is
  • only as the warm winds of autumn to the dying branches.
  • There is one thought still, the saddest of all, bearing on this
  • withholding of early help. It is possible, in some noble natures, that
  • the warmth and the affections of childhood may remain unchilled,
  • though unanswered; and that the old man's heart may still be capable
  • of gladness, when the long-withheld sympathy is given at last. But in
  • these noble natures it nearly always happens, that the chief motive of
  • earthly ambition has not been to give delight to themselves, but to
  • their parents. Every noble youth looks back, as to the chiefest joy
  • which this world's honour ever gave him, to the moment when first he
  • saw his father's eyes flash with pride, and his mother turn away her
  • head lest he should take her tears for tears of sorrow. Even the
  • lover's joy, when some worthiness of his is acknowledged before his
  • mistress, is not so great as that, for it is not so pure--the desire
  • to exalt himself in her eyes mixes with that of giving her delight;
  • but he does not need to exalt himself in his parents' eyes: it is
  • with the pure hope of giving them pleasure that he comes to tell them
  • what he has done, or what has been said of him; and therefore he has a
  • purer pleasure of his own. And this purest and best of rewards you
  • keep from him if you can: you feed him in his tender youth with ashes
  • and dishonour; and then you come to him, obsequious, but too late,
  • with your sharp laurel crown, the dew all dried from off its leaves;
  • and you thrust it into his languid hand, and he looks at you
  • wistfully. What shall he do with it? What can he do, but go and lay it
  • on his mother's grave?
  • Thus, then, you see that you have to provide for your young men:
  • first, the searching or discovering school; then the calm employment;
  • then the justice of praise: one thing more you have to do for them in
  • preparing them for full service--namely, to make, in the noble sense
  • of the word, gentlemen of them; that is to say, to take care that
  • their minds receive such training, that in all they paint they shall
  • see and feel the noblest things. I am sorry to say, that of all parts
  • of an artist's education this is the most neglected among us; and that
  • even where the natural taste and feeling of the youth have been pure
  • and true, where there was the right stuff in him to make a gentleman
  • of, you may too frequently discern some jarring rents in his mind, and
  • elements of degradation in his treatment of subject, owing to want of
  • gentle training, and of the liberal influence of literature. This is
  • quite visible in our greatest artists, even in men like Turner and
  • Gainsborough; while in the common grade of our second-rate painters
  • the evil attains a pitch which is far too sadly manifest to need my
  • dwelling upon it. Now, no branch of art economy is more important than
  • that of making the intellect at your disposal pure as well as
  • powerful; so that it may always gather for you the sweetest and
  • fairest things. The same quantity of labour from the same man's hand,
  • will, according as you have trained him, produce a lovely and useful
  • work, or a base and hurtful one, and depend upon it, whatever value it
  • may possess, by reason of the painter's skill, its chief and final
  • value, to any nation, depends upon its being able to exalt and refine,
  • as well as to please; and that the picture which most truly deserves
  • the name of an art-treasure, is that which has been painted by a good
  • man.
  • You cannot but see how far this would lead, if I were to enlarge upon
  • it. I must take it up as a separate subject some other time: only
  • noticing at present that no money could be better spent by a nation
  • than in providing a liberal and disciplined education for its
  • painters, as they advance into the critical period of their youth; and
  • that also, a large part of their power during life depends upon the
  • kind of subjects which you, the public, ask them for, and therefore
  • the kind of thoughts with which you require them to be habitually
  • familiar. I shall have more to say on this head when we come to
  • consider what employment they should have in public buildings.
  • There are many other points of nearly as much importance as these, to
  • be explained with reference to the development of genius; but I should
  • have to ask you to come and hear six lectures instead of two if I were
  • to go into their detail. For instance, I have not spoken of the way in
  • which you ought to look for those artificers in various manual trades,
  • who, without possessing the order of genius which you would desire to
  • devote to higher purposes, yet possess wit, and humour, and sense of
  • colour, and fancy for form--all commercially valuable as quantities of
  • intellect, and all more or less expressible in the lower arts of
  • ironwork, pottery, decorative sculpture, and such like. But these
  • details, interesting as they are, I must commend to your own
  • consideration, or leave for some future inquiry. I want just now only
  • to set the bearings of the entire subject broadly before you, with
  • enough of detailed illustration to make it intelligible; and therefore
  • I must quit the first head of it here, and pass to the second, namely,
  • how best to employ the genius we discover. A certain quantity of able
  • hands and heads being placed at our disposal, what shall we most
  • advisably set them upon?
  • II. APPLICATION.--There are three main points the economist has to
  • attend to in this.
  • First, To set his men to various work.
  • Secondly, To easy work.
  • Thirdly, To lasting work.
  • I shall briefly touch on the first two, for I want to arrest your
  • attention on the last.
  • I say first, to various work. Supposing you have two men of equal
  • power as landscape painters--and both of them have an hour at your
  • disposal. You would not set them both to paint the same piece of
  • landscape. You would, of course, rather have two subjects than a
  • repetition of one.
  • Well, supposing them sculptors, will not the same rule hold? You
  • naturally conclude at once that it will; but you will have hard work
  • to convince your modern architects of that. They will put twenty men
  • to work, to carve twenty capitals; and all shall be the same. If I
  • could show you the architects' yards in England just now, all open at
  • once, perhaps you might see a thousand clever men, all employed in
  • carving the same design. Of the degradation and deathfulness to the
  • art-intellect of the country involved in such a habit, I have more or
  • less been led to speak before now; but I have not hitherto marked its
  • definite tendency to increase the price of _work_, as such. When men
  • are employed continually in carving the same ornaments, they get into
  • a monotonous and methodical habit of labour--precisely correspondent
  • to that in which they would break stones, or paint house-walls. Of
  • course, what they do so constantly, they do easily; and if you excite
  • them temporarily by an increase of wages, you may get much work done
  • by them in a little time. But, unless so stimulated, men condemned to
  • a monotonous exertion, work--and always, by the laws of human nature,
  • _must_ work--only at a tranquil rate, not producing by any means a
  • maximum result in a given time. But if you allow them to vary their
  • designs, and thus interest their heads and hearts in what they are
  • doing, you will find them become eager, first, to get their ideas
  • expressed, and then to finish the expression of them; and the moral
  • energy thus brought to bear on the matter quickens, and therefore
  • cheapens, the production in a most important degree. Sir Thomas Deane,
  • the architect of the new Museum at Oxford, told me, as I passed
  • through Oxford on my way here, that he found that, owing to this
  • cause alone, capitals of various design could be executed cheaper than
  • capitals of similar design (the amount of hand labour in each being
  • the same) by about 30 per cent.
  • Well, that is the first way, then, in which you will employ your
  • intellect well; and the simple observance of this plain rule of
  • political economy will effect a noble revolution in your architecture,
  • such as you cannot at present so much as conceive. Then the second way
  • in which we are to guard against waste is by setting our men to the
  • easiest, and therefore the quickest, work which will answer the
  • purpose. Marble, for instance, lasts quite as long as granite, and is
  • much softer to work; therefore, when you get hold of a good sculptor,
  • give him marble to carve--not granite. That, you say, is obvious
  • enough. Yes; but it is not so obvious how much of your workmen's time
  • you waste annually in making them cut glass, after it has got hard,
  • when you ought to make them mould it while it is soft. It is not so
  • obvious how much expense you waste in cutting diamonds and rubies,
  • which are the hardest things you can find, into shapes that mean
  • nothing, when the same men might be cutting sandstone and freestone
  • into shapes that meant something. It is not so obvious how much of the
  • artists' time in Italy you waste, by forcing them to make wretched
  • little pictures for you out of crumbs of stone glued together at
  • enormous cost, when the tenth of the time would make good and noble
  • pictures for you out of water-colour. I could go on giving you almost
  • numberless instances of this great commercial mistake; but I should
  • only weary and confuse you. I therefore commend also this head of our
  • subject to your own meditation, and proceed to the last I named--the
  • last I shall task your patience with to-night. You know we are now
  • considering how to apply our genius; and we were to do it as
  • economists, in three ways:--
  • To _various_ work;
  • To _easy_ work;
  • To _lasting_ work.
  • This lasting of the work, then, is our final question.
  • Many of you may, perhaps, remember that Michael Angelo was once
  • commanded by Pietro di Medici to mould a statue out of snow, and that
  • he obeyed the command.[7] I am glad, and we have all reason to be
  • glad, that such a fancy ever came into the mind of the unworthy
  • prince, and for this cause: that Pietro di Medici then gave, at the
  • period of one great epoch of consummate power in the arts, the
  • perfect, accurate; and intensest possible type of the greatest error
  • which nations and princes can commit, respecting the power of genius
  • entrusted to their guidance. You had there, observe, the strongest
  • genius in the most perfect obedience; capable of iron independence,
  • yet wholly submissive to the patron's will; at once the most highly
  • accomplished and the most original, capable of doing as much as man
  • could do, in any direction that man could ask. And its governour, and
  • guide, and patron sets it to build a statue in snow--to put itself
  • into the service of annihilation--to make a cloud of itself, and pass
  • away from the earth.
  • [7] See the noble passage on this tradition in "Casa Guidi
  • Windows."
  • Now this, so precisely and completely done by Pietro di Medici, is
  • what we are all doing, exactly in the degree in which we direct the
  • genius under our patronage to work in more or less perishable
  • materials. So far as we induce painters to work in fading colours, or
  • architects to build with imperfect structure, or in any other way
  • consult only immediate ease and cheapness in the production of what we
  • want, to the exclusion of provident thought as to its permanence and
  • serviceableness in after ages; so far we are forcing our Michael
  • Angelos to carve in snow. The first duty of the economist in art is,
  • to see that no intellect shall thus glitter merely in the manner of
  • hoar-frost; but that it shall be well vitrified, like a painted
  • window, and shall be set so between shafts of stone and bands of iron,
  • that it shall bear the sunshine upon it, and send the sunshine through
  • it, from generation to generation.
  • I can conceive, however, some political economist to interrupt me
  • here, and say, "If you make your art wear too well, you will soon have
  • too much of it; you will throw your artists quite out of work. Better
  • allow for a little wholesome evanescence--beneficent destruction: let
  • each age provide art for itself, or we shall soon have so many good
  • pictures that we shall not know what to do with them."
  • Remember, my dear hearers, who are thus thinking, that political
  • economy, like every other subject, cannot be dealt with effectively if
  • we try to solve two questions at a time instead of one. It is one
  • question, how to get plenty of a thing; and another, whether plenty of
  • it will be good for us. Consider these two matters separately; never
  • confuse yourself by interweaving one with the other. It is one
  • question, how to treat your fields so as to get a good harvest;
  • another, whether you wish to have a good harvest, or would rather like
  • to keep up the price of corn. It is one question, how to graft your
  • trees so as to grow most apples; and quite another, whether having
  • such a heap of apples in the store-room will not make them all rot.
  • Now, therefore, that we are talking only about grafting and growing,
  • pray do not vex yourselves with thinking what you are to do with the
  • pippins. It may be desirable for us to have much art, or little--we
  • will examine that by and by; but just now, let us keep to the simple
  • consideration how to get plenty of good art if we want it. Perhaps it
  • might be just as well that a man of moderate income should be able to
  • possess a good picture, as that any work of real merit should cost
  • £500 or £1,000; at all events, it is certainly one of the branches of
  • political economy to ascertain how, if we like, we can get things in
  • quantities--plenty of corn, plenty of wine, plenty of gold, or plenty
  • of pictures.
  • It has just been said, that the first great secret is to produce work
  • that will last. Now, the conditions of work lasting are twofold: it
  • must not only be in materials that will last, but it must be itself of
  • a quality that will last--it must be good enough to bear the test of
  • time. If it is not good, we shall tire of it quickly, and throw it
  • aside--we shall have no pleasure in the accumulation of it. So that
  • the first question of a good art-economist respecting any work is,
  • Will it lose its flavour by keeping? It may be very amusing now, and
  • look much like a work of genius. But what will be its value a hundred
  • years hence?
  • You cannot always ascertain this. You may get what you fancy to be
  • work of the best quality, and yet find to your astonishment that it
  • won't keep. But of one thing you may be sure, that art which is
  • produced hastily will also perish hastily; and that what is cheapest
  • to you now, is likely to be dearest in the end.
  • I am sorry to say, the great tendency of this age is to expend its
  • genius in perishable art of this kind, as if it were a triumph to burn
  • its thoughts away in bonfires. There is a vast quantity of intellect
  • and of labour consumed annually in our cheap illustrated publications;
  • you triumph in them; and you think it is so grand a thing to get so
  • many woodcuts for a penny. Why, woodcuts, penny and all, are as much
  • lost to you as if you had invested your money in gossamer. More lost,
  • for the gossamer could only tickle your face, and glitter in your
  • eyes; it could not catch your feet and trip you up: but the bad art
  • can, and does; for you can't like good woodcuts as long as you look at
  • the bad ones. If we were at this moment to come across a Titian
  • woodcut, or a Durer woodcut, we should not like it--those of us at
  • least who are accustomed to the cheap work of the day. We don't like,
  • and can't like, _that_ long; but when we are tired of one bad cheap
  • thing, we throw it aside and buy another bad cheap thing; and so keep
  • looking at bad things all our lives. Now, the very men who do all that
  • quick bad work for us are capable of doing perfect work. Only, perfect
  • work can't be hurried, and therefore it can't be cheap beyond a
  • certain point. But suppose you pay twelve times as much as you do now,
  • and you have one woodcut for a shilling instead of twelve; and the one
  • woodcut for a shilling is as good as art can be, so that you will
  • never tire of looking at it; and is struck on good paper with good
  • ink, so that you will never wear it out by handling it; while you are
  • sick of your penny-each cuts by the end of the week, and have torn
  • them mostly in half too. Isn't your shilling's worth the best bargain?
  • It is not, however, only in getting prints or woodcuts of the best
  • kind that you will practise economy. There is a certain quality about
  • an original drawing which you cannot get in a woodcut, and the best
  • part of the genius of many men is only expressible in original work,
  • whether with pen and ink--pencil or colours. This is not always the
  • case; but in general, the best men are those who can only express
  • themselves on paper or canvass; and you will, therefore, in the long
  • run, get most for your money by buying original work; proceeding on
  • the principle already laid down, that the best is likely to be the
  • cheapest in the end. Of course, original work cannot be produced under
  • a certain cost. If you want a man to make you a drawing which takes
  • him six days, you must, at all events, keep him for six days in bread
  • and water, fire and lodging; that is the lowest price at which he can
  • do it for you, but that is not very dear: and the best bargain which
  • can possibly be made honestly in art--the very ideal of a cheap
  • purchase to the purchaser--is the original work of a great man fed for
  • as many days as are necessary on bread and water, or perhaps we may
  • say with as many onions as will keep him in good humour. That is the
  • way by which you will always get most for your money; no mechanical
  • multiplication or ingenuity of commercial arrangements will ever get
  • you a better penny's worth of art than that.
  • Without, however, pushing our calculations quite to this
  • prison-discipline extreme, we may lay it down as a rule in
  • art-economy, that original work is, on the whole, cheapest and best
  • worth having. But precisely in proportion to the value of it as a
  • production, becomes the importance of having it executed in permanent
  • materials. And here we come to note the second main error of the day,
  • that we not only ask our workmen for bad art, but we make them put it
  • into bad substance. We have, for example, put a great quantity of
  • genius, within the last twenty years, into water-colour drawing, and
  • we have done this with the most reckless disregard whether either the
  • colours or the paper will stand. In most instances, neither will. By
  • accident, it may happen that the colours in a given drawing have been
  • of good quality, and its paper uninjured by chemical processes. But
  • you take not the least care to ensure these being so; I have myself
  • seen the most destructive changes take place in water-colour drawings
  • within twenty years after they were painted; and from all I can gather
  • respecting the recklessness of modern paper manufacture, my belief is,
  • that though you may still handle an Albert Durer engraving, two
  • hundred years old, fearlessly, not one-half of that time will have
  • passed over your modern water-colours, before most of them will be
  • reduced to mere white or brown rags; and your descendants, twitching
  • them contemptuously into fragments between finger and thumb, will
  • mutter against you, half in scorn and half in anger, "Those wretched
  • nineteenth-century people! they kept vapouring and fuming about the
  • world, doing what they called business, and they couldn't make a sheet
  • of paper that wasn't rotten." And note that this is no unimportant
  • portion of your art economy at this time. Your water-colour painters
  • are becoming every day capable of expressing greater and better
  • things; and their material is especially adapted to the turn of your
  • best artists' minds. The value which you could accumulate in work of
  • this kind would soon become a most important item in the national
  • art-wealth, if only you would take the little pains necessary to
  • secure its permanence. I am inclined to think, myself, that
  • water-colour ought not to be used on paper at all, but only on vellum,
  • and then, if properly taken care of, the drawing would be almost
  • imperishable. Still, paper is a much more convenient material for
  • rapid work; and it is an infinite absurdity not to secure the goodness
  • of its quality, when we could do so without the slightest trouble.
  • Among the many favours which I am going to ask from our paternal
  • government, when we get it, will be that it will supply its little
  • boys with good paper. You have nothing to do but to let the government
  • establish a paper manufactory, under the superintendence of any of our
  • leading chemists, who should be answerable for the safety and
  • completeness of all the processes of the manufacture. The government
  • stamp on the corner of your sheet of drawing-paper, made in the
  • perfect way, should cost you a shilling, which would add something to
  • the revenue; and when you bought a water-colour drawing for fifty or a
  • hundred guineas, you would have merely to look in the corner for your
  • stamp, and pay your extra shilling for the security that your hundred
  • guineas were given really for a drawing, and not for a coloured rag.
  • There need be no monopoly or restriction in the matter; let the paper
  • manufacturers compete with the government, and if people liked to save
  • their shilling, and take their chance, let them; only, the artist and
  • purchaser might then be sure of good material, if they liked, and now
  • they cannot be.
  • I should like also to have a government colour manufactory; though
  • that is not so necessary, as the quality of colour is more within the
  • artist's power of testing, and I have no doubt that any painter may
  • get permanent colour from the respectable manufacturers, if he
  • chooses. I will not attempt to follow the subject out at all as it
  • respects architecture, and our methods of modern building; respecting
  • which I have had occasion to speak before now.
  • But I cannot pass without some brief notice our habit--continually, as
  • it seems to me, gaining strength--of putting a large quantity of
  • thought and work, annually, into things which are either in their
  • nature necessarily perishable, as dress; or else into compliances with
  • the fashion of the day, in things not necessarily perishable, as
  • plate. I am afraid almost the first idea of a young rich couple
  • setting up house in London, is, that they must have new plate. Their
  • father's plate may be very handsome, but the fashion is changed. They
  • will have a new service from the leading manufacturer, and the old
  • plate, except a few apostle spoons, and a cup which Charles the Second
  • drank a health in to their pretty ancestress, is sent to be melted
  • down, and made up with new flourishes and fresh lustre. Now, so long
  • as this is the case--so long, observe, as fashion has influence on the
  • manufacture of plate--so long _you cannot have a goldsmith's art in
  • this country_. Do you suppose any workman worthy the name will put his
  • brains into a cup or an urn, which he knows is to go to the melting
  • pot in half a score years? He will not; you don't ask or expect it of
  • him. You ask of him nothing but a little quick handicraft--a clever
  • twist of a handle here, and a foot there, a convolvulus from the
  • newest school of design, a pheasant from Landseer's game cards; a
  • couple of sentimental figures for supporters, in the style of the
  • signs of insurance offices, then a clever touch with the burnisher,
  • and there's your epergne, the admiration of all the footmen at the
  • wedding-breakfast, and the torment of some unfortunate youth who
  • cannot see the pretty girl opposite to him, through its tyrannous
  • branches.
  • But you don't suppose that _that's_ goldsmith's work? Goldsmith's work
  • is made to last, and made with the man's whole heart and soul in it;
  • true goldsmith's work, when it exists, is generally the means of
  • education of the greatest painters and sculptors of the day. Francia
  • was a goldsmith; Francia was not his own name, but that of his master
  • the jeweller; and he signed his pictures almost always, "Francia, the
  • goldsmith," for love of his master; Ghirlandajo was a goldsmith, and
  • was the master of Michael Angelo; Verrocchio was a goldsmith, and was
  • the master of Leonardo da Vinci. Ghiberti was a goldsmith, and beat
  • out the bronze gates which Michael Angelo said might serve for gates
  • of Paradise.[8] But if ever you want work like theirs again, you must
  • keep it, though it should have the misfortune to become old fashioned.
  • You must not break it up, nor melt it any more. There is no economy in
  • that; you could not easily waste intellect more grievously. Nature may
  • melt her goldsmith's work at every sunset if she chooses; and beat it
  • out into chased bars again at every sunrise; but you must not. The way
  • to have a truly noble service of plate, is to keep adding to it, not
  • melting it. At every marriage, and at every birth, get a new piece of
  • gold or silver if you will, but with noble workmanship on it, done for
  • all time, and put it among your treasures; that is one of the chief
  • things which gold was made for, and made incorruptible for. When we
  • know a little more of political economy, we shall find that none but
  • partially savage nations need, imperatively, gold for their
  • currency;[9] but gold has been given us, among other things, that we
  • might put beautiful work into its imperishable splendour, and that the
  • artists who have the most wilful fancies may have a material which
  • will drag out, and beat out, as their dreams require, and will hold
  • itself together with fantastic tenacity, whatever rare and delicate
  • service they set it upon.
  • [8] Several reasons may account for the fact that goldsmith's
  • work is so wholesome for young artists; first, that it gives
  • great firmness of hand to deal for some time with a solid
  • substance; again, that it induces caution and steadiness--a
  • boy trusted with chalk and paper suffers an immediate
  • temptation to scrawl upon it and play with it, but he dares
  • not scrawl on gold, and he cannot play with it; and, lastly,
  • that it gives great delicacy and precision of touch to work
  • upon minute forms, and to aim at producing richness and
  • finish of design correspondent to the preciousness of the
  • material.
  • [9] See note in Addenda on the nature of property [p. 107].
  • So here is one branch of decorative art in which rich people may
  • indulge themselves unselfishly; if they ask for good art in it, they
  • may be sure in buying gold and silver plate that they are enforcing
  • useful education on young artists. But there is another branch of
  • decorative art in which I am sorry to say we cannot, at least under
  • existing circumstances, indulge ourselves, with the hope of doing good
  • to anybody, I mean the great and subtle art of dress.
  • And here I must interrupt the pursuit of our subject for a moment or
  • two, in order to state one of the principles of political economy,
  • which, though it is, I believe, now sufficiently understood and
  • asserted by the leading masters of the science, is not yet, I grieve
  • to say, acted upon by the plurality of those who have the management
  • of riches. Whenever we spend money, we of course set people to work:
  • that is the meaning of spending money; we may, indeed, lose it without
  • employing anybody; but, whenever we spend it, we set a number of
  • people to work, greater or less, of course, according to the rate of
  • wages, but, in the long run, proportioned to the sum we spend. Well,
  • your shallow people, because they see that however they spend money
  • they are always employing somebody, and, therefore, doing some good,
  • think and say to themselves, that it is all one _how_ they spend
  • it--that all their apparently selfish luxury is, in reality,
  • unselfish, and is doing just as much good as if they gave all their
  • money away, or perhaps more good; and I have heard foolish people even
  • declare it as a principle of political economy, that whoever invented
  • a new want[10] conferred a good on the community. I have not words
  • strong enough--at least I could not, without shocking you, use the
  • words which would be strong enough--to express my estimate of the
  • absurdity and the mischievousness of this popular fallacy. So, putting
  • a great restraint upon myself, and using no hard words, I will simply
  • try to state the nature of it, and the extent of its influence.
  • [10] See note 5th, in Addenda [p. 102].
  • Granted, that whenever we spend money for whatever purpose, we set
  • people to work; and, passing by, for the moment, the question whether
  • the work we set them to is all equally healthy and good for them, we
  • will assume that whenever we spend a guinea we provide an equal number
  • of people with healthy maintenance for a given time. But, by the way
  • in which we spend it, we entirely direct the labour of those people
  • during that given time. We become their masters or mistresses, and we
  • compel them to produce, within a certain period, a certain article.
  • Now, that article may be a useful and lasting one, or it may be a
  • useless and perishable one--it may be one useful to the whole
  • community, or useful only to ourselves. And our selfishness and folly,
  • or our virtue and prudence, are shown, not by our spending money, but
  • by our spending it for the wrong or the right thing; and we are wise
  • and kind, not in maintaining a certain number of people for a given
  • period, but only in requiring them to produce, during that period, the
  • kind of things which shall be useful to society, instead of those
  • which are only useful to ourselves.
  • Thus, for instance: if you are a young lady, and employ a certain
  • number of sempstresses for a given time, in making a given number of
  • simple and serviceable dresses, suppose, seven; of which you can wear
  • one yourself for half the winter, and give six away to poor girls who
  • have none, you are spending your money unselfishly. But if you employ
  • the same number of sempstresses for the same number of days, in
  • making four, or five, or six beautiful flounces for your own
  • ball-dress--flounces which will clothe no one but yourself, and which
  • you will yourself be unable to wear at more than one ball--you are
  • employing your money selfishly. You have maintained, indeed, in each
  • case, the same number of people; but in the one case you have directed
  • their labour to the service of the community; in the other case you
  • have consumed it wholly upon yourself. I don't say you are never to do
  • so; I don't say you ought not sometimes to think of yourselves only,
  • and to make yourselves as pretty as you can; only do not confuse
  • coquettishness with benevolence, nor cheat yourselves into thinking
  • that all the finery you can wear is so much put into the hungry mouths
  • of those beneath you: it is not so; it is what you yourselves, whether
  • you will or no, must sometimes instinctively feel it to be--it is what
  • those who stand shivering in the streets, forming a line to watch you
  • as you step out of your carriages, _know_ it to be; those fine dresses
  • do not mean that so much has been put into their mouths, but that so
  • much has been taken out of their mouths. The real politico-economical
  • signification of every one of those beautiful toilettes, is just this;
  • that you have had a certain number of people put for a certain
  • number of days wholly under your authority, by the sternest of
  • slave-masters--hunger and cold; and you have said to them, "I will
  • feed you, indeed, and clothe you, and give you fuel for so many days;
  • but during those days you shall work for me only: your little brothers
  • need clothes, but you shall make none for them: your sick friend needs
  • clothes, but you shall make none for her: you yourself will soon need
  • another, and a warmer dress; but you shall make none for yourself. You
  • shall make nothing but lace and roses for me; for this fortnight to
  • come, you shall work at the patterns and petals, and then I will crush
  • and consume them away in an hour." You will perhaps answer--"It may
  • not be particularly benevolent to do this, and we won't call it so;
  • but at any rate we do no wrong in taking their labour when we pay them
  • their wages: if we pay for their work we have a right to it." No;--a
  • thousand times no. The labour which you have paid for, does indeed
  • become, by the act of purchase, your own labour: you have bought the
  • hands and the time of those workers; they are, by right and justice,
  • your own hands, your own time. But, have you a right to spend your own
  • time, to work with your own hands, only for your own advantage?--much
  • more, when, by purchase, you have invested your own person with the
  • strength of others; and added to your own life, a part of the life of
  • others? You may, indeed, to a certain extent, use their labour for
  • your delight: remember, I am making no general assertions against
  • splendour of dress, or pomp of accessories of life; on the contrary,
  • there are many reasons for thinking that we do not at present attach
  • enough importance to beautiful dress, as one of the means of
  • influencing general taste and character. But I _do_ say, that you must
  • weigh the value of what you ask these workers to produce for you in
  • its own distinct balance; that on its own worthiness or desirableness
  • rests the question of your kindness, and not merely on the fact of
  • your having employed people in producing it: and I say farther, that
  • as long as there are cold and nakedness in the land around you, so
  • long there can be no question at all but that splendour of dress is a
  • crime. In due time, when we have nothing better to set people to work
  • at, it may be right to let them make lace and cut jewels; but, as long
  • as there are any who have no blankets for their beds, and no rags for
  • their bodies, so long it is blanket-making and tailoring we must set
  • people to work at--not lace.
  • And it would be strange, if at any great assembly which, while it
  • dazzled the young and the thoughtless, beguiled the gentler hearts
  • that beat beneath the embroidery, with a placid sensation of luxurious
  • benevolence--as if by all that they wore in waywardness of beauty,
  • comfort had been first given to the distressed, and aid to the
  • indigent; it would be strange, I say, if, for a moment, the spirits of
  • Truth and of Terror, which walk invisibly among the masques of the
  • earth, would lift the dimness from our erring thoughts, and show us
  • how--inasmuch as the sums exhausted for that magnificence would have
  • given back the failing breath to many an unsheltered outcast on moor
  • and street--they who wear it have literally entered into partnership
  • with Death; and dressed themselves in his spoils. Yes, if the veil
  • could be lifted not only from your thoughts, but from your human
  • sight, you would see--the angels do see--on those gay white dresses of
  • yours, strange dark spots, and crimson patterns that you knew not
  • of--spots of the inextinguishable red that all the seas cannot wash
  • away; yes, and among the pleasant flowers that crown your fair heads,
  • and glow on your wreathed hair, you would see that one weed was always
  • twisted which no one thought of--the grass that grows on graves.
  • It was not, however, this last, this clearest and most appalling view
  • of our subject, that I intended to ask you to take this evening; only
  • it is impossible to set any part of the matter in its true light,
  • until we go to the root of it. But the point which it is our special
  • business to consider is, not whether costliness of dress is contrary
  • to charity; but whether it is not contrary to mere worldly wisdom:
  • whether, even supposing we knew that splendour of dress did not cost
  • suffering or hunger, we might not put the splendour better in other
  • things than dress. And, supposing our mode of dress were really
  • graceful or beautiful, this might be a very doubtful question; for I
  • believe true nobleness of dress to be an important means of education,
  • as it certainly is a necessity to any nation which wishes to possess
  • living art, concerned with portraiture of human nature. No good
  • historical painting ever yet existed, or ever can exist, where the
  • dresses of the people of the time are not beautiful: and had it not
  • been for the lovely and fantastic dressing of the 13th to the 16th
  • centuries, neither French, nor Florentine, nor Venetian art could have
  • risen to anything like the rank it reached. Still, even then, the best
  • dressing was never the costliest; and its effect depended much more on
  • its beautiful and, in early times, modest, arrangement, and on the
  • simple and lovely masses of its colour, than on gorgeousness of clasp
  • or embroidery. Whether we can ever return to any of those more perfect
  • types of form, is questionable; but there can be no question, that all
  • the money we spend on the forms of dress at present worn, is, so far
  • as any good purpose is concerned, wholly lost. Mind, in saying this, I
  • reckon among good purposes, the purpose which young ladies are said
  • sometimes to entertain--of being married; but they would be married
  • quite as soon (and probably to wiser and better husbands) by dressing
  • quietly, as by dressing brilliantly: and I believe it would only be
  • needed to lay fairly and largely before them the real good which might
  • be effected by the sums they spend in toilettes, to make them trust at
  • once only to their bright eyes and braided hair for all the mischief
  • they have a mind to. I wish we could, for once, get the statistics of
  • a London season. There was much complaining talk in Parliament last
  • week, of the vast sum the nation has given for the best Paul Veronese
  • in Venice--£14,000: I wonder what the nation meanwhile has given for
  • its ball-dresses! Suppose we could see the London milliners' bills,
  • simply for unnecessary breadths of slip and flounce, from April to
  • July; I wonder whether £14,000 would cover _them_. But the breadths of
  • slip and flounce are by this time as much lost and vanished as last
  • year's snow; only they have done less good: but the Paul Veronese will
  • last for centuries, if we take care of it; and yet we grumble at the
  • price given for the painting, while no one grumbles at the price of
  • pride.
  • Time does not permit me to go into any farther illustration of the
  • various modes in which we build our statue out of snow, and waste our
  • labour on things that vanish. I must leave you to follow out the
  • subject for yourselves, as I said I should, and proceed, in our next
  • lecture, to examine the two other branches of our subject, namely, how
  • to accumulate our art, and how to distribute it. But, in closing, as
  • we have been much on the topic of good government, both of ourselves
  • and others, let me just give you one more illustration of what it
  • means, from that old art of which, next evening, I shall try to
  • convince you that the value, both moral and mercantile, is greater
  • than we usually suppose.
  • One of the frescoes by Ambrozio Lorenzetti, in the town-hall of Siena,
  • represents, by means of symbolical figures, the principles of Good
  • Civic Government and of Good Government in general. The figure
  • representing this noble Civic Government is enthroned, and surrounded
  • by figures representing the Virtues, variously supporting or
  • administering its authority. Now, observe what work is given
  • to each of these virtues. Three winged ones--Faith, Hope, and
  • Charity--surround the head of the figure, not in mere compliance with
  • the common and heraldic laws of precedence among Virtues, such as we
  • moderns observe habitually, but with peculiar purpose on the part of
  • the painter. Faith, as thus represented, ruling the thoughts of the
  • Good Governour, does not mean merely religious faith, understood in
  • those times to be necessary to all persons--governed no less than
  • governours--but it means the faith which enables work to be carried
  • out steadily, in spite of adverse appearances and expediencies; the
  • faith in great principles, by which a civic ruler looks past all the
  • immediate checks and shadows that would daunt a common man, knowing
  • that what is rightly done will have a right issue, and holding his way
  • in spite of pullings at his cloak and whisperings in his ear,
  • enduring, as having in him a faith which is evidence of things unseen.
  • And Hope, in like manner, is here not the heavenward hope which ought
  • to animate the hearts of all men; but she attends upon Good
  • Government, to show that all such government is _expectant_ as well
  • as _conservative_; that if it ceases to be hopeful of better things,
  • it ceases to be a wise guardian of present things: that it ought
  • never, as long as the world lasts, to be wholly content with any
  • existing state of institution or possession, but to be hopeful still
  • of more wisdom and power; not clutching at it restlessly or hastily,
  • but feeling that its real life consists in steady ascent from high to
  • higher: conservative, indeed, and jealously conservative of old
  • things, but conservative of them as pillars, not as pinnacles--as
  • aids, but not as idols; and hopeful chiefly, and active, in times of
  • national trial or distress, according to those first and notable words
  • describing the queenly nation. "She riseth, _while it is yet night_."
  • And again, the winged Charity which is attendant on Good Government
  • has, in this fresco, a peculiar office. Can you guess what? If you
  • consider the character of contest which so often takes place among
  • kings for their crowns, and the selfish and tyrannous means they
  • commonly take to aggrandize or secure their power, you will, perhaps,
  • be surprised to hear that the office of Charity is to crown the King.
  • And yet, if you think of it a little, you will see the beauty of the
  • thought which sets her in this function: since in the first place, all
  • the authority of a good governor should be desired by him only for the
  • good of his people, so that it is only Love that makes him accept or
  • guard his crown: in the second place, his chief greatness consists in
  • the exercise of this love, and he is truly to be revered only so far
  • as his acts and thoughts are those of kindness; so that Love is the
  • light of his crown, as well as the giver of it: lastly, because his
  • strength depends on the affections of his people, and it is only their
  • love which can securely crown him, and for ever. So that Love is the
  • strength of his crown as well as the light of it.
  • Then, surrounding the King, or in various obedience to him, appear the
  • dependent virtues, as Fortitude, Temperance, Truth, and other
  • attendant spirits, of all which I cannot now give account, wishing you
  • only to notice the one to whom are entrusted the guidance and
  • administration of the public revenues. Can you guess which it is
  • likely to be? Charity, you would have thought, should have something
  • to do with the business; but not so, for she is too hot to attend
  • carefully to it. Prudence, perhaps, you think of in the next place.
  • No, she is too timid, and loses opportunities in making up her mind.
  • Can it be Liberality then? No: Liberality is entrusted with some small
  • sums; but she is a bad accountant, and is allowed no important place
  • in the exchequer. But the treasures are given in charge to a virtue of
  • which we hear too little in modern times, as distinct from others;
  • Magnanimity: largeness of heart: not softness or weakness of heart,
  • mind you--but capacity of heart--the great _measuring_ virtue, which
  • weighs in heavenly balances all that may be given, and all that may be
  • gained; and sees how to do noblest things in noblest ways: which of
  • two goods comprehends and therefore chooses the greatest: which of two
  • personal sacrifices dares and accepts the largest: which, out of the
  • avenues of beneficence, treads always that which opens farthest into
  • the blue fields of futurity: that character, in fine, which, in those
  • words taken by us at first for the description of a Queen among the
  • nations, looks less to the present power than to the distant promise;
  • "Strength and honour are in her clothing--and she shall rejoice IN
  • TIME TO COME."
  • LECTURE II.
  • The heads of our subject which remain for our consideration this
  • evening are, you will remember, the accumulation and the distribution
  • of works of art. Our complete inquiry fell into four divisions--first,
  • how to get our genius; then, how to apply our genius; then, how to
  • accumulate its results; and lastly, how to distribute them. We
  • considered, last evening, how to discover and apply it;--we have
  • to-night to examine the modes of its preservation and distribution.
  • III. ACCUMULATION.--And now, in the outset, it will be well to face
  • that objection which we put aside a little while ago; namely, that
  • perhaps it is not well to have a great deal of good art; and that it
  • should not be made too cheap.
  • "Nay," I can imagine some of the more generous among you, exclaiming,
  • "we will not trouble you to disprove that objection; of course it is a
  • selfish and base one: good art, as well as other good things, ought to
  • be made as cheap as possible, and put as far as we can within the
  • reach of everybody."
  • Pardon me, I am not prepared to admit that. I rather side with the
  • selfish objectors, and believe that art ought not to be made cheap,
  • beyond a certain point; for the amount of pleasure that you can
  • receive from any great work, depends wholly on the quantity of
  • attention and energy of mind you can bring to bear upon it. Now, that
  • attention and energy depend much more on the freshness of the thing
  • than you would at all suppose; unless you very carefully studied the
  • movements of your own minds. If you see things of the same kind and of
  • equal value very frequently, your reverence for them is infallibly
  • diminished, your powers of attention get gradually wearied, and your
  • interest and enthusiasm worn out; and you cannot in that state bring
  • to any given work the energy necessary to enjoy it. If, indeed, the
  • question were only between enjoying a great many pictures each a
  • little, or one picture very much, the sum of enjoyment being in each
  • case the same, you might rationally desire to possess rather the
  • larger quantity, than the small; both because one work of art always
  • in some sort illustrates another, and because quantity diminishes the
  • chances of destruction. But the question is not a merely arithmetical
  • one of this kind. Your fragments of broken admirations will not, when
  • they are put together, make up one whole admiration; two and two, in
  • this case, do not make four, nor anything like four. Your good
  • picture, or book, or work of art of any kind, is always in some degree
  • fenced and closed about with difficulty. You may think of it as of a
  • kind of cocoa-nut, with very often rather an unseemly shell, but good
  • milk and kernel inside. Now, if you possess twenty cocoa-nuts, and
  • being thirsty, go impatiently from one to the other, giving only a
  • single scratch with the point of your knife to the shell of each, you
  • will get no milk from all the twenty. But if you leave nineteen of
  • them alone, and give twenty cuts to the shell of one, you will get
  • through it, and at the milk of it. And the tendency of the human mind
  • is always to get tired before it has made its twenty cuts; and to try
  • another nut; and moreover, even if it has perseverance enough to crack
  • its nuts, it is sure to try to eat too many, and so choke itself.
  • Hence, it is wisely appointed for us that few of the things we desire
  • can be had without considerable labour, and at considerable intervals
  • of time. We cannot generally get our dinner without working for it,
  • and that gives us appetite for it; we cannot get our holiday without
  • waiting for it, and that gives us zest for it; and we ought not to get
  • our picture without paying for it, and that gives us a mind to look at
  • it. Nay, I will even go so far as to say, that we ought not to get
  • books too cheaply. No book, I believe, is ever worth half so much to
  • its reader as one that has been coveted for a year at a bookstall, and
  • bought out of saved half-pence; and perhaps a day or two's fasting.
  • That's the way to get at the cream of a book. And I should say more on
  • this matter, and protest as energetically as I could against the
  • plague of cheap literature, with which we are just now afflicted, but
  • that I fear your calling me to order, as being unpractical, because I
  • don't quite see my way at present to making everybody fast for their
  • books. But one may see that a thing is desirable and possible, even
  • though one may not at once know the best way to it--and in my island
  • of Barataria, when I get it well into order, I assure you no book
  • shall be sold for less than a pound sterling; if it can be published
  • cheaper than that, the surplus shall all go into my treasury, and save
  • my subjects taxation in other directions; only people really poor, who
  • cannot pay the pound, shall be supplied with the books they want for
  • nothing, in a certain limited quantity. I haven't made up my mind
  • about the number yet, and there are several other points in the system
  • yet unsettled; when they are all determined, if you will allow me, I
  • will come and give you another lecture, on the political economy of
  • literature.[11]
  • [11] See note 6th, in Addenda [p. 104].
  • Meantime, returning to our immediate subject, I say to my generous
  • hearers, who want to shower Titians and Turners upon us, like falling
  • leaves, "Pictures ought not to be too cheap;" but in much stronger
  • tone I would say to those who want to keep up the prices of pictorial
  • property, that pictures ought not to be too dear, that is to say, not
  • as dear as they are. For, as matters at present stand, it is wholly
  • impossible for any man in the ordinary circumstances of English life
  • to possess himself of a piece of great art. A modern drawing of
  • average merit, or a first-class engraving, may perhaps, not without
  • some self-reproach, be purchased out of his savings by a man of narrow
  • income; but a satisfactory example of first-rate art--masterhands'
  • work--is wholly out of his reach. And we are so accustomed to look
  • upon this as the natural course and necessity of things, that we never
  • set ourselves in any wise to diminish the evil; and yet it is an evil
  • perfectly capable of diminution. It is an evil precisely similar in
  • kind to that which existed in the middle ages, respecting good books,
  • and which everybody then, I suppose, thought as natural as we do now
  • our small supply of good pictures. You could not then study the work
  • of a great historian, or great poet, any more than you can now study
  • that of a great painter, but at heavy cost. If you wanted a book, you
  • had to get it written out for you, or to write it out for yourself.
  • But printing came, and the poor man may read his Dante and his Homer;
  • and Dante and Homer are none the worse for that. But it is only in
  • literature that private persons of moderate fortune can possess and
  • study greatness: they can study at home no greatness in art; and the
  • object of that accumulation which we are at present aiming at, as our
  • third object in political economy, is to bring great art in some
  • degree within the reach of the multitude; and, both in larger and more
  • numerous galleries than we now possess, and by distribution, according
  • to his wealth and wish, in each man's home, to render the influence of
  • art somewhat correspondent in extent to that of literature. Here,
  • then, is the subtle balance which your economist has to strike: to
  • accumulate so much art as to be able to give the whole nation a supply
  • of it, according to its need, and yet to regulate its distribution so
  • that there shall be no glut of it, nor contempt.
  • A difficult balance, indeed, for us to hold, if it were left merely to
  • our skill to poise; but the just point between poverty and profusion
  • has been fixed for us accurately by the wise laws of Providence. If
  • you carefully watch for all the genius you can detect, apply it to
  • good service, and then reverently preserve what it produces, you will
  • never have too little art; and if, on the other hand, you never force
  • an artist to work hurriedly, for daily bread, nor imperfectly, because
  • you would rather have showy works than complete ones, you will never
  • have too much. Do not force the multiplication of art, and you will
  • not have it too cheap; do not wantonly destroy it, and you will not
  • have it too dear.
  • "But who wantonly destroys it?" you will ask. Why, we all do. Perhaps
  • you thought, when I came to this part of our subject, corresponding to
  • that set forth in our housewife's economy by the "keeping her
  • embroidery from the moth," that I was going to tell you only how to
  • take better care of pictures, how to clean them, and varnish them, and
  • where to put them away safely when you went out of town. Ah, not at
  • all. The utmost I have to ask of you is, that you will not pull them
  • to pieces, and trample them under your feet. "What!" you will say,
  • "when do we do such things? Haven't we built a perfectly beautiful
  • gallery for all the pictures we have to take care of?" Yes, you have,
  • for the pictures which are definitely sent to Manchester to be taken
  • care of. But there are quantities of pictures out of Manchester which
  • it is your business, and mine too, to take care of no less than of
  • these, and which we are at this moment employing ourselves in pulling
  • to pieces by deputy. I will tell you what they are, and where they
  • are, in a minute; only first let me state one more of those main
  • principles of political economy on which the matter hinges.
  • I must begin a little apparently wide of the mark, and ask you to
  • reflect if there is any way in which we waste money more in England,
  • than in building fine tombs? Our respect for the dead, when they are
  • _just_ dead, is something wonderful, and the way we show it more
  • wonderful still. We show it with black feathers and black horses; we
  • show it with black dresses and bright heraldries; we show it with
  • costly obelisks and sculptures of sorrow, which spoil half of our most
  • beautiful cathedrals. We show it with frightful gratings and vaults,
  • and lids of dismal stone, in the midst of the quiet grass; and last,
  • and not least, we show it by permitting ourselves to tell any number
  • of lies we think amiable or credible, in the epitaph. This feeling is
  • common to the poor as well as the rich, and we all know how many a
  • poor family will nearly ruin themselves, to testify their respect for
  • some member of it in his coffin, whom they never much cared for when
  • he was out of it; and how often it happens that a poor old woman will
  • starve herself to death, in order that she may be respectably buried.
  • Now, this being one of the most complete and special ways of wasting
  • money;--no money being less productive of good, or of any percentage
  • whatever, than that which we shake away from the ends of undertakers'
  • plumes--it is of course the duty of all good economists, and kind
  • persons, to prove and proclaim continually, to the poor as well as the
  • rich, that respect for the dead is not really shown by laying great
  • stones on them to tell us where they are laid; but by remembering
  • where they are laid, without a stone to help us; trusting them to the
  • sacred grass and saddened flowers; and still more, that respect and
  • love are shown to them, not by great monuments to them which we build
  • with _our_ hands, but by letting the monuments stand, which they built
  • with _their own_. And this is the point now in question.
  • Observe, there are two great reciprocal duties concerning industry,
  • constantly to be exchanged between the living and the dead. We, as we
  • live and work, are to be always thinking of those who are to come
  • after us; that what we do may be serviceable, as far as we can make it
  • so, to them as well as to us. Then, when we die, it is the duty of
  • those who come after us to accept this work of ours with thanks and
  • remembrance, not thrusting it aside or tearing it down the moment they
  • think they have no use for it. And each generation will only be happy
  • or powerful to the pitch that it ought to be, in fulfilling these two
  • duties to the Past and the Future. Its own work will never be rightly
  • done, even for itself--never good, or noble, or pleasurable to its own
  • eyes--if it does not prepare it also for the eyes of generations yet
  • to come. And its own possessions will never be enough for it, and its
  • own wisdom never enough for it, unless it avails itself gratefully and
  • tenderly of the treasures and the wisdom bequeathed to it by its
  • ancestors.
  • For, be assured, that all the best things and treasures of this world
  • are not to be produced by each generation for itself; but we are all
  • intended, not to carve our work in snow that will melt, but each and
  • all of us to be continually rolling a great white gathering snowball,
  • higher and higher--larger and larger--along the Alps of human power.
  • Thus the science of nations is to be accumulative from father to son:
  • each learning a little more and a little more; each receiving all that
  • was known, and adding its own gain: the history and poetry of nations
  • are to be accumulative; each generation treasuring the history and the
  • songs of its ancestors, adding its own history and its own songs: and
  • the art of nations is to be accumulative, just as science and history
  • are; the work of living men not superseding, but building itself upon
  • the work of the past. Nearly every great and intellectual race of the
  • world has produced, at every period of its career, an art with some
  • peculiar and precious character about it, wholly unattainable by any
  • other race, and at any other time; and the intention of Providence
  • concerning that art, is evidently that it should all grow together
  • into one mighty temple; the rough stones and the smooth all finding
  • their place, and rising, day by day, in richer and higher pinnacles to
  • heaven.
  • Now, just fancy what a position the world, considered as one great
  • workroom--one great factory in the form of a globe--would have been in
  • by this time, if it had in the least understood this duty, or been
  • capable of it. Fancy what we should have had around us now, if,
  • instead of quarrelling and fighting over their work, the nations had
  • aided each other in their work, or if even in their conquests, instead
  • of effacing the memorials of those they succeeded and subdued, they
  • had guarded the spoils of their victories. Fancy what Europe would be
  • now, if the delicate statues and temples of the Greeks,--if the broad
  • roads and massy walls of the Romans,--if the noble and pathetic
  • architecture of the middle ages, had not been ground to dust by mere
  • human rage. You talk of the scythe of Time, and the tooth of Time: I
  • tell you, Time is scytheless and toothless; it is we who gnaw like the
  • worm--we who smite like the scythe. It is ourselves who
  • abolish--ourselves who consume: we are the mildew, and the flame, and
  • the soul of man is to its own work as the moth, that frets when it
  • cannot fly, and as the hidden flame that blasts where it cannot
  • illumine. All these lost treasures of human intellect have been wholly
  • destroyed by human industry of destruction; the marble would have
  • stood its two thousand years as well in the polished statue as in the
  • Parian cliff; but we men have ground it to powder, and mixed it with
  • our own ashes. The walls and the ways would have stood--it is we who
  • have left not one stone upon another, and restored its pathlessness to
  • the desert; the great cathedrals of old religion would have stood--it
  • is we who have dashed down the carved work with axes and hammers, and
  • bid the mountain-grass bloom upon the pavement, and the sea-winds
  • chaunt in the galleries.
  • You will perhaps think all this was somehow necessary for the
  • development of the human race. I cannot stay now to dispute that,
  • though I would willingly; but do you think it is _still_ necessary for
  • that development? Do you think that in this nineteenth century it is
  • still necessary for the European nations to turn all the places where
  • their principal art-treasures are into battle-fields? For that is what
  • they are doing even while I speak; the great firm of the world is
  • managing its business at this moment, just as it has done in past
  • time. Imagine what would be the thriving circumstances of a
  • manufacturer of some delicate produce--suppose glass, or china--in
  • whose workshop and exhibition rooms all the workmen and clerks began
  • fighting at least once a day, first blowing off the steam, and
  • breaking all the machinery they could reach; and then making
  • fortresses of all the cupboards, and attacking and defending the
  • show-tables, the victorious party finally throwing everything they
  • could get hold of out of the window, by way of showing their triumph,
  • and the poor manufacturer picking up and putting away at last a cup
  • here and a handle there. A fine prosperous business that would be,
  • would it not? and yet that is precisely the way the great
  • manufacturing firm of the world carries on its business.
  • It has so arranged its political squabbles for the last six or seven
  • hundred years, that not one of them could be fought out but in the
  • midst of its most precious art; and it so arranges them to this day.
  • For example, if I were asked to lay my finger, in a map of the world,
  • on the spot of the world's surface which contained at this moment the
  • most singular concentration of art-teaching and art-treasure, I should
  • lay it on the name of the town of Verona. Other cities, indeed,
  • contain more works of carriageable art, but none contain so much of
  • the glorious local art, and of the springs and sources of art, which
  • can by no means be made subjects of package or porterage, nor, I
  • grieve to say, of salvage. Verona possesses, in the first place, not
  • the largest, but the most perfect and intelligible Roman amphitheatre
  • that exists, still unbroken in circle of step, and strong in
  • succession of vault and arch: it contains minor Roman monuments,
  • gateways, theatres, baths, wrecks of temples, which give the streets
  • of its suburbs a character of antiquity unexampled elsewhere, except
  • in Rome itself. But it contains, in the next place, what Rome does not
  • contain--perfect examples of the great twelfth-century Lombardic
  • architecture, which was the root of all the mediæval art of Italy,
  • without which no Giottos, no Angelicos, no Raphaels would have been
  • possible: it contains that architecture, not in rude forms, but in the
  • most perfect and loveliest types it ever attained--contains those, not
  • in ruins, nor in altered and hardly decipherable fragments, but in
  • churches perfect from porch to apse, with all their carving fresh,
  • their pillars firm, their joints unloosened. Besides these, it
  • includes examples of the great thirteenth- and fourteenth-century
  • Gothic of Italy, not merely perfect, but elsewhere unrivalled. At
  • Rome, the Roman--at Pisa, the Lombard, architecture may be seen in
  • greater or in equal nobleness; but not at Rome, nor Pisa, nor
  • Florence, nor in any city of the world, is there a great mediæval
  • Gothic like the Gothic of Verona. Elsewhere, it is either less pure in
  • type or less lovely in completion: only at Verona may you see it in
  • the simplicity of its youthful power, and the tenderness of its
  • accomplished beauty. And Verona possesses, in the last place, the
  • loveliest Renaissance architecture of Italy, not disturbed by pride,
  • nor defiled by luxury, but rising in fair fulfilment of domestic
  • service, serenity of effortless grace, and modesty of home seclusion;
  • its richest work given to the windows that open on the narrowest
  • streets and most silent gardens. All this she possesses, in the midst
  • of natural scenery such as assuredly exists nowhere else in the
  • habitable globe--a wild Alpine river foaming at her feet, from whose
  • shore the rocks rise in a great crescent, dark with cypress, and misty
  • with olive: illimitably, from before her southern gates, the tufted
  • plains of Italy sweep and fade in golden light; around her, north and
  • west, the Alps crowd in crested troops, and the winds of Benacus bear
  • to her the coolness of their snows.
  • And this is the city--such, and possessing such things as these--at
  • whose gates the decisive battles of Italy are fought continually:
  • three days her towers trembled with the echo of the cannon of Arcola;
  • heaped pebbles of the Mincio divide her fields to this hour with lines
  • of broken rampart, whence the tide of war rolled back to Novara; and
  • now on that crescent of her eastern cliffs, whence the full moon used
  • to rise through the bars of the cypresses in her burning summer
  • twilights, touching with soft increase of silver light the rosy
  • marbles of her balconies--along the ridge of that encompassing rock,
  • other circles are increasing now, white and pale; walled towers of
  • cruel strength, sable-spotted with cannon-courses. I tell you, I have
  • seen, when the thunderclouds came down on those Italian hills, and all
  • their crags were dipped in the dark, terrible purple, as if the
  • winepress of the wrath of God had stained their mountain-raiment--I
  • have seen the hail fall in Italy till the forest branches stood
  • stripped and bare as if blasted by the locust; but the white hail
  • never fell from those clouds of heaven as the black hail will fall
  • from the clouds of hell, if ever one breath of Italian life stirs
  • again in the streets of Verona.
  • Sad as you will feel this to be, I do not say that you can directly
  • prevent it; you cannot drive the Austrians out of Italy, nor prevent
  • them from building forts where they choose. But I do say,[12] that you,
  • and I, and all of us, ought to be both acting and feeling with a full
  • knowledge and understanding of these things, and that, without trying
  • to excite revolutions or weaken governments, we may give our own
  • thoughts and help, so as in a measure to prevent needless destruction.
  • We should do this, if we only realized the thing thoroughly. You drive
  • out day by day through your own pretty suburbs, and you think only of
  • making, with what money you have to spare, your gateways handsomer,
  • and your carriage-drives wider--and your drawing-rooms more splendid,
  • having a vague notion that you are all the while patronizing and
  • advancing art, and you make no effort to conceal the fact, that within
  • a few hours' journey of you, there are gateways and drawing-rooms
  • which might just as well be yours as these, all built already;
  • gateways built by the greatest masters of sculpture that ever struck
  • marble; drawing-rooms, painted by Titian and Veronese; and you won't
  • accept, nor save these as they are, but you will rather fetch the
  • house-painter from over the way, and let Titian and Veronese house the
  • rats. "Yes," of course, you answer; "we want nice houses here, not
  • houses in Verona. What should we do with houses in Verona?" And I
  • answer, do precisely what you do with the most expensive part of your
  • possessions here: take pride in them--only a noble pride. You know
  • well, when you examine your own hearts, that the greater part of the
  • sums you spend on possessions are spent for pride. Why are your
  • carriages nicely painted and finished outside? You don't see the
  • outsides as you sit in them--the outsides are for other people to see.
  • Why are your exteriors of houses so well finished, your furniture so
  • polished and costly, but for other people to see? You are just as
  • comfortable yourselves, writing on your old friend of a desk, with the
  • white cloudings in his leather, and using the light of a window which
  • is nothing but a hole in the brick wall. And all that is desirable to
  • be done in this matter, is merely to take pride in preserving great
  • art, instead of in producing mean art; pride in the possession of
  • precious and enduring things, a little way off, instead of slight and
  • perishing things near at hand. You know, in old English times, our
  • kings liked to have lordships and dukedoms abroad, and why should not
  • you merchant princes like to have lordships and estates abroad?
  • Believe me, rightly understood, it would be a prouder, and in the full
  • sense of our English word, more "respectable" thing to be lord of a
  • palace at Verona, or of a cloister full of frescos at Florence, than
  • to have a file of servants dressed in the finest liveries that ever
  • tailor stitched, as long as would reach from here to Bolton:--yes, and
  • a prouder thing to send people to travel in Italy, who would have to
  • say every now and then, of some fair piece of art, "Ah! this was
  • _kept_ here for us by the good people of Manchester," than to bring
  • them travelling all the way here, exclaiming of your various art
  • treasures, "These were _brought_ here for us, (not altogether without
  • harm) by the good people of Manchester." "Ah!" but you say, "the Art
  • Treasures Exhibition will pay; but Veronese palaces won't." Pardon me.
  • They _would_ pay, less directly, but far more richly. Do you suppose
  • it is in the long run good for Manchester, or good for England, that
  • the Continent should be in the state it is? Do you think the perpetual
  • fear of revolution, or the perpetual repression of thought and energy
  • that clouds and encumbers the nations of Europe, is eventually
  • profitable for _us_? Were we any the better of the course of affairs
  • in '48; or has the stabling of the dragoon horses in the great houses
  • of Italy, any distinct effect in the promotion of the cotton-trade?
  • Not so. But every stake that you could hold in the stability of the
  • Continent, and every effort that you could make to give example of
  • English habits and principles on the Continent, and every kind deed
  • that you could do in relieving distress and preventing despair on the
  • Continent, would have tenfold reaction on the prosperity of England,
  • and open and urge, in a thousand unforeseen directions, the sluices of
  • commerce and the springs of industry.
  • [12] The reader can hardly but remember Mrs. Browning's beautiful
  • appeal for Italy, made on the occasion of the first great
  • Exhibition of Art in England:--
  • "O Magi of the east and of the west,
  • Your incense, gold, and myrrh are excellent!--
  • What gifts for Christ, then, bring ye with the rest?
  • Your hands have worked well. Is your courage spent
  • In handwork only? Have you nothing best,
  • Which generous souls may perfect and present,
  • And He shall thank the givers for? no light
  • Of teaching, liberal nations, for the poor,
  • Who sit in darkness when it is not night?
  • No cure for wicked children? Christ,--no cure,
  • No help for women, sobbing out of sight
  • Because men made the laws? no brothel-lure
  • Burnt out by popular lightnings? Hast thou found
  • No remedy, my England, for such woes?
  • No outlet, Austria, for the scourged and bound,
  • No call back for the exiled? no repose,
  • Russia, for knouted Poles worked underground,
  • And gentle ladies bleached among the snows?
  • No mercy for the slave, America?
  • No hope for Rome, free France, chivalric France?
  • Alas, great nations have great shames, I say.
  • No pity, O world, no tender utterance
  • Of benediction, and prayers stretched this way
  • For poor Italia, baffled by mischance?
  • O gracious nations, give some ear to me!
  • You all go to your Fair, and I am one
  • Who at the roadside of humanity
  • Beseech your alms,--God's justice to be done.
  • So, prosper!"
  • I could press, if I chose, both these motives upon you, of pride and
  • self-interest, with more force, but these are not motives which ought
  • to be urged upon you at all. The only motive that I ought to put
  • before you is simply that it would be right to do this; that the
  • holding of property abroad, and the personal efforts of Englishmen to
  • redeem the condition of foreign nations, are among the most direct
  • pieces of duty which our wealth renders incumbent upon us. I do
  • not--and in all truth and deliberateness I say this--I do not know
  • anything more ludicrous among the self-deceptions of well-meaning
  • people than their notion of patriotism, as requiring them to limit
  • their efforts to the good of their own country;--the notion that
  • charity is a geographical virtue, and that what it is holy and
  • righteous to do for people on one bank of a river, it is quite
  • improper and unnatural to do for people on the other. It will be a
  • wonderful thing, some day or other, for the Christian world to
  • remember, that it went on thinking for two thousand years that
  • neighbours were neighbours at Jerusalem, but not at Jericho; a
  • wonderful thing for us English to reflect, in after-years, how long it
  • was before we could shake hands with anybody across that shallow salt
  • wash, which the very chalk-dust of its two shores whitens from
  • Folkestone to Ambleteuse.
  • Nor ought the motive of gratitude, as well as that of mercy, to be
  • without its influence on you, who have been the first to ask to see,
  • and the first to show to us, the treasures which this poor lost Italy
  • has given to England. Remember all these things that delight you here
  • were hers--hers either in fact or in teaching; hers, in fact, are all
  • the most powerful and most touching paintings of old time that now
  • glow upon your walls; hers in teaching are all the best and greatest
  • of descendant souls--your Reynolds and your Gainsborough never could
  • have painted but for Venice; and the energies which have given the
  • only true life to your existing art were first stirred by voices of
  • the dead, that haunted the Sacred Field of Pisa.
  • Well, all these motives for some definite course of action on our part
  • towards foreign countries rest upon very serious facts; too serious,
  • perhaps you will think, to be interfered with; for we are all of us in
  • the habit of leaving great things alone, as if Providence would mind
  • them, and attending ourselves only to little things which we know,
  • practically, Providence doesn't mind unless we do. We are ready enough
  • to give care to the growing of pines and lettuces, knowing that they
  • don't grow Providentially sweet or large unless we look after them;
  • but we don't give any care to the good of Italy or Germany, because we
  • think that they will grow Providentially happy without any of our
  • meddling.
  • Let us leave the great things, then, and think of little things; not
  • of the destruction of whole provinces in war, which it may not be any
  • business of ours to prevent; but of the destruction of poor little
  • pictures in peace, from which it surely would not be much out of our
  • way to save them. You know I said, just now, we were all of us engaged
  • in pulling pictures to pieces by deputy, and you did not believe me.
  • Consider, then, this similitude of ourselves. Suppose you saw (as I
  • doubt not you often do see) a prudent and kind young lady sitting at
  • work, in the corner of a quiet room, knitting comforters for her
  • cousins, and that just outside, in the hall, you saw a cat and her
  • kittens at play among the family pictures; amusing themselves
  • especially with the best Vandykes, by getting on the tops of the
  • frames, and then scrambling down the canvasses by their claws; and on
  • someone's informing the young lady of these proceedings of the cat and
  • kittens, suppose she answered that it wasn't her cat, but her
  • sister's, and the pictures weren't hers, but her uncle's, and she
  • couldn't leave her work, for she had to make so many pairs of
  • comforters before dinner. Would you not say that the prudent and kind
  • young lady was, on the whole, answerable for the additional touches of
  • claw on the Vandykes? Now, that is precisely what we prudent and kind
  • English are doing, only on a larger scale. Here we sit in Manchester,
  • hard at work, very properly, making comforters for our cousins all
  • over the world. Just outside there in the hall--that beautiful marble
  • hall of Italy--the cats and kittens and monkeys are at play among the
  • pictures: I assure you, in the course of the fifteen years in which I
  • have been working in those places in which the most precious remnants
  • of European art exist, a sensation, whether I would or no, was
  • gradually made distinct and deep in my mind, that I was living and
  • working in the midst of a den of monkeys;--sometimes amiable and
  • affectionate monkeys, with all manner of winning ways and kind
  • intentions;--more frequently selfish and malicious monkeys, but,
  • whatever their disposition, squabbling continually about nuts, and the
  • best places on the barren sticks of trees; and that all this monkeys'
  • den was filled, by mischance, with precious pictures, and the witty
  • and wilful beasts were always wrapping themselves up and going to
  • sleep in pictures, or tearing holes in them to grin through; or
  • tasting them and spitting them out again, or twisting them up into
  • ropes and making swings of them; and that sometimes only, by watching
  • one's opportunity, and bearing a scratch or a bite, one could rescue
  • the corner of a Tintoret, or Paul Veronese, and push it through the
  • bars into a place of safety. Literally, I assure you, this was, and
  • this is, the fixed impression on my mind of the state of matters in
  • Italy. And see how. The professors of art in Italy, having long
  • followed a method of study peculiar to themselves, have at last
  • arrived at a form of art peculiar to themselves; very different from
  • that which was arrived at by Correggio and Titian. Naturally, the
  • professors like their own form the best; and, as the old pictures are
  • generally not so startling to the eye as the modern ones, the dukes
  • and counts who possess them, and who like to see their galleries look
  • new and fine (and are persuaded also that a celebrated chef-d'oeuvre
  • ought always to catch the eye at a quarter of a mile off), believe the
  • professors who tell them their sober pictures are quite faded, and
  • good for nothing, and should all be brought bright again; and,
  • accordingly, give the sober pictures to the professors, to be put
  • right by rules of art. Then, the professors repaint the old pictures
  • in all the principal places, leaving perhaps only a bit of background
  • to set off their own work. And thus the professors come to be
  • generally figured in my mind, as the monkeys who tear holes in the
  • pictures, to grin through. Then the picture-dealers, who live by the
  • pictures, cannot sell them to the English in their old and pure state;
  • all the good work must be covered with new paint, and varnished so as
  • to look like one of the professorial pictures in the great gallery,
  • before it is saleable. And thus the dealers come to be imaged, in my
  • mind, as the monkeys who make ropes of the pictures, to swing by.
  • Then, every now and then, in some old stable or wine-cellar, or
  • timber-shed, behind some forgotten vats or faggots, somebody finds a
  • fresco of Perugino's or Giotto's, but doesn't think much of it, and
  • has no idea of having people coming into his cellar, or being obliged
  • to move his faggots; and so he whitewashes the fresco, and puts the
  • faggots back again; and these kind of persons, therefore, come
  • generally to be imaged in my mind, as the monkeys who taste the
  • pictures, and spit them out, not finding them nice. While, finally,
  • the squabbling for nuts and apples (called in Italy "bella
  • libertà") goes on all day long.
  • Now, all this might soon be put an end to, if we English, who are so
  • fond of travelling in the body, would also travel a little in soul. We
  • think it a great triumph to get our packages and our persons carried
  • at a fast pace, but we never take the slightest trouble to put any
  • pace into our perceptions; we stay usually at home in thought, or if
  • we ever mentally see the world, it is at the old stage-coach or waggon
  • rate. Do but consider what an odd sight it would be, if it were only
  • quite clear to you how things are really going on--how, here in
  • England, we are making enormous and expensive efforts to produce new
  • art of all kinds, knowing and confessing all the while that the
  • greater part of it is bad, but struggling still to produce new
  • patterns of wall-papers, and new shapes of tea-pots, and new pictures,
  • and statues, and architecture; and pluming and cackling if ever a
  • tea-pot or a picture has the least good in it;--all the while taking
  • no thought whatever of the best possible pictures, and statues, and
  • wall-patterns already in existence, which require nothing but to be
  • taken common care of, and kept from damp and dust: but we let the
  • walls fall that Giotto patterned, and the canvasses rot that Tintoret
  • painted, and the architecture be dashed to pieces that St. Louis
  • built, while we are furnishing our drawing-rooms with prize
  • upholstery, and writing accounts of our handsome warehouses to the
  • country papers. Don't think I use my words vaguely or generally: I
  • speak of literal facts. Giotto's frescos at Assisi are perishing at
  • this moment for want of decent care; Tintoret's pictures in San
  • Sebastian at Venice, are at this instant rotting piecemeal into grey
  • rags; St. Louis's Chapel, at Carcassonne, is at this moment lying in
  • shattered fragments in the market-place. And here we are all cawing
  • and crowing, poor little half-fledged daws as we are, about the pretty
  • sticks and wool in our own nests. There's hardly a day passes, when I
  • am at home, but I get a letter from some well-meaning country
  • clergyman, deeply anxious about the state of his parish church, and
  • breaking his heart to get money together that he may hold up some
  • wretched remnant of Tudor tracery, with one niche in the corner and no
  • statue--when all the while the mightiest piles of religious
  • architecture and sculpture that ever the world saw are being blasted
  • and withered away, without one glance of pity or regret. The country
  • clergyman does not care for _them_--he has a sea-sick imagination that
  • cannot cross Channel. What is it to him, if the angels of Assisi fade
  • from its vaults, or the queens and kings of Chartres fall from their
  • pedestals? They are not in his parish.
  • "What!" you will say, "are we not to produce any new art, nor take
  • care of our parish churches?" No, certainly not, until you have taken
  • proper care of the art you have got already, and of the best churches
  • out of the parish. Your first and proper standing is not as
  • churchwardens and parish overseers in an English county, but as
  • members of the great Christian community of Europe. And as members of
  • that community (in which alone, observe, pure and precious ancient art
  • exists, for there is none in America, none in Asia, none in Africa),
  • you conduct yourselves precisely as a manufacturer would, who attended
  • to his looms, but left his warehouse without a roof. The rain floods
  • your warehouse, the rats frolic in it, the spiders spin in it, the
  • choughs build in it, the wall-plague frets and festers in it, and
  • still you keep weave, weave, weaving at your wretched webs, and
  • thinking you are growing rich, while more is gnawed out of your
  • warehouse in an hour than you can weave in a twelvemonth.
  • Even this similitude is not absurd enough to set us rightly forth. The
  • weaver would, or might, at least, hope that his new woof was as stout
  • as the old ones, and that, therefore, in spite of rain and ravage, he
  • would have something to wrap himself in when he needed it. But _our_
  • webs rot as we spin. The very fact that we despise the great art of
  • the past shows that we cannot produce great art now. If we could do
  • it, we should love it when we saw it done--if we really cared for it,
  • we should recognise it and keep it; but we don't care for it. It is
  • not art that we want; it is amusement, gratification of pride, present
  • gain--anything in the world but art: let it rot, we shall always have
  • enough to talk about and hang over our sideboards.
  • You will (I hope) finally ask me what is the outcome of all this,
  • practicable, to-morrow morning by us who are sitting here? These are
  • the main practical outcomes of it: In the first place, don't grumble
  • when you hear of a new picture being bought by Government at a large
  • price. There are many pictures in Europe now in danger of destruction
  • which are, in the true sense of the word, priceless; the proper price
  • is simply that which it is necessary to give to get and to save them.
  • If you can get them for fifty pounds, do; if not for less than a
  • hundred, do; if not for less than five thousand, do; if not for less
  • than twenty thousand, do; never mind being imposed upon: there is
  • nothing disgraceful in being imposed upon; the only disgrace is in
  • imposing; and you can't in general get anything much worth having, in
  • the way of Continental art, but it must be with the help or connivance
  • of numbers of people who, indeed, ought to have nothing to do with the
  • matter, but who practically have, and always will have, everything to
  • do with it; and if you don't choose to submit to be cheated by them
  • out of a ducat here and a zecchin there, you will be cheated by them
  • out of your picture; and whether you are most imposed upon in losing
  • that, or the zecchins, I think I may leave you to judge; though I know
  • there are many political economists, who would rather leave a bag of
  • gold on a garret-table, than give a porter sixpence extra to carry it
  • downstairs.
  • That, then, is the first practical outcome of the matter. Never
  • grumble, but be glad when you hear of a new picture being bought at a
  • large price. In the long run, the dearest pictures are always the best
  • bargains; and, I repeat (for else you might think I said it in mere
  • hurry of talk, and not deliberately), there are some pictures which
  • are without price. You should stand, nationally, at the edge of Dover
  • cliffs--Shakespeare's--and wave blank cheques in the eyes of the
  • nations on the other side of the sea, freely offered, for such and
  • such canvasses of theirs.
  • Then the next practical outcome of it is: Never buy a copy of a
  • picture, under any circumstances whatever. All copies are bad; because
  • no painter who is worth a straw ever _will_ copy. He will make a study
  • of a picture he likes, for his own use, in his own way; but he won't
  • and can't copy; whenever you buy a copy, you buy so much
  • misunderstanding of the original, and encourage a dull person in
  • following a business he is not fit for, besides increasing ultimately
  • chances of mistake and imposture, and farthering, as directly as
  • money _can_ farther, the cause of ignorance in all directions. You
  • may, in fact, consider yourself as having purchased a certain quantity
  • of mistakes; and, according to your power, being engaged in
  • disseminating them.
  • I do not mean, however, that copies should never be made. A certain
  • number of dull persons should always be employed by a Government in
  • making the most accurate copies possible of all good pictures; these
  • copies, though artistically valueless, would be historically and
  • documentarily valuable, in the event of the destruction of the
  • original picture. The studies also made by great artists for their own
  • use, should be sought after with the greatest eagerness; they are
  • often to be bought cheap; and in connection with the mechanical
  • copies, would become very precious: tracings from frescos and other
  • large works are also of great value; for though a tracing is liable to
  • just as many mistakes as a copy, the mistakes in a tracing are of one
  • kind only, which may be allowed for, but the mistakes of a common
  • copyist are of all conceivable kinds: finally, engravings, in so far
  • as they convey certain facts about the pictures, without pretending
  • adequately to represent or give an idea of the pictures, are often
  • serviceable and valuable. I can't, of course, enter into details in
  • these matters just now; only this main piece of advice I can safely
  • give you--never to buy copies of pictures (for your private
  • possession) which pretend to give a _facsimile_ that shall be in any
  • wise representative of, or equal to, the original. Whenever you do so,
  • you are only lowering your taste, and wasting your money. And if you
  • are generous and wise, you will be ready rather to subscribe as much
  • as you would have given for a copy of a great picture, towards its
  • purchase, or the purchase of some other like it, by the nation. There
  • ought to be a great National Society instituted for the purchase of
  • pictures; presenting them to the various galleries in our great
  • cities, and watching there over their safety: but in the meantime, you
  • can always act safely and beneficially by merely allowing your artist
  • friends to buy pictures for you, when they see good ones. Never buy
  • for yourselves, nor go to the foreign dealers; but let any painter
  • whom you know be entrusted, when he finds a neglected old picture in
  • an old house, to try if he cannot get it for you; then, if you like
  • it, keep it; if not, send it to the hammer, and you will find that you
  • do not lose money on pictures so purchased.
  • And the third and chief practical outcome of the matter is this
  • general one: Wherever you go, whatever you do, act more for
  • _preservation_ and less for _production_. I assure you, the world is,
  • generally speaking, in calamitous disorder, and just because you have
  • managed to thrust some of the lumber aside, and get an available
  • corner for yourselves, you think you should do nothing but sit
  • spinning in it all day long--while, as householders and economists,
  • your first thought and effort should be, to set things more square all
  • about you. Try to set the ground floors in order, and get the
  • rottenness out of your granaries. _Then_ sit and spin, but not till
  • then.
  • IV. DISTRIBUTION.--And now, lastly, we come to the fourth great head
  • of our inquiry, the question of the wise distribution of the art we
  • have gathered and preserved. It must be evident to us, at a moment's
  • thought, that the way in which works of art are on the whole most
  • useful to the nation to which they belong, must be by their collection
  • in public galleries, supposing those galleries properly managed. But
  • there is one disadvantage attached necessarily to gallery exhibition,
  • namely, the extent of mischief which may be done by one foolish
  • curator. As long as the pictures which form the national wealth are
  • disposed in private collections, the chance is always that the people
  • who buy them will be just the people who are fond of them; and that
  • the sense of exchangeable value in the commodity they possess, will
  • induce them, even if they do not esteem it themselves, to take such
  • care of it as will preserve its value undiminished. At all events, so
  • long as works of art are scattered through the nation, no universal
  • destruction of them is possible; a certain average only are lost by
  • accidents from time to time. But when they are once collected in a
  • large public gallery, if the appointment of curator becomes in any way
  • a matter of formality, or the post is so lucrative as to be disputed
  • by place-hunters, let but one foolish or careless person get
  • possession of it, and perhaps you may have all your fine pictures
  • repainted, and the national property destroyed, in a month. That is
  • actually the case at this moment, in several great foreign galleries.
  • They are the places of execution of pictures: over their doors you
  • only want the Dantesque inscription, "Lasciate ogni speranza, voi che
  • entrate."
  • Supposing, however, this danger properly guarded against, as it would
  • be always by a nation which either knew the value, or understood the
  • meaning, of painting,[13] arrangement in a public gallery is the
  • safest, as well as the most serviceable, method of exhibiting
  • pictures; and it is the only mode in which their historical value can
  • be brought out, and their historical meaning made clear. But great
  • good is also to be done by encouraging the private possession of
  • pictures; partly as a means of study (much more being always
  • discovered in any work of art by a person who has it perpetually near
  • him than by one who only sees it from time to time), and also as a
  • means of refining the habits and touching the hearts of the masses of
  • the nation in their domestic life.
  • [13] It would be a great point gained towards the preservation
  • of pictures if it were made a rule that at every operation
  • they underwent, the exact spots in which they have been
  • re-painted should be recorded in writing.
  • For these last purposes the most serviceable art is the living art of
  • the time; the particular tastes of the people will be best met, and
  • their particular ignorances best corrected, by painters labouring in
  • the midst of them, more or less guided to the knowledge of what is
  • wanted by the degree of sympathy with which their work is received. So
  • then, generally, it should be the object of government, and of all
  • patrons of art, to collect, as far as may be, the works of dead
  • masters in public galleries, arranging them so as to illustrate the
  • history of nations, and the progress and influence of their arts; and
  • to encourage the private possession of the works of _living_ masters.
  • And the first and best way in which to encourage such private
  • possession is, of course, to keep down the prices of them as far as
  • you can.
  • I hope there are not a great many painters in the room; if there are,
  • I entreat their patience for the next quarter of an hour: if they will
  • bear with me for so long, I hope they will not, finally, be offended
  • by what I am going to say.
  • I repeat, trusting to their indulgence in the interim, that the first
  • object of our national economy, as respects the distribution of modern
  • art, should be steadily and rationally to limit its prices, since by
  • doing so, you will produce two effects; you will make the painters
  • produce more pictures, two or three instead of one, if they wish to
  • make money; and you will, by bringing good pictures within the reach
  • of people of moderate income, excite the general interest of the
  • nation in them, increase a thousandfold the demand for the commodity,
  • and therefore its wholesome and natural production.
  • I know how many objections must arise in your minds at this moment to
  • what I say; but you must be aware that it is not possible for me in an
  • hour to explain all the moral and commercial bearings of such a
  • principle as this. Only, believe me, I do not speak lightly; I think I
  • have considered all the objections which could be rationally brought
  • forward, though I have time at present only to glance at the main one,
  • namely, the idea that the high prices paid for modern pictures are
  • either honourable, or serviceable, to the painter. So far from this
  • being so, I believe one of the principal obstacles to the progress of
  • modern art to be the high prices given for good modern pictures. For
  • observe, first, the action of this high remuneration on the artist's
  • mind. If he "gets on," as it is called, catches the eye of the public,
  • and especially of the public of the upper classes, there is hardly any
  • limit to the fortune he may acquire; so that, in his early years, his
  • mind is naturally led to dwell on this worldly and wealthy eminence as
  • the main thing to be reached by his art; if he finds that he is not
  • gradually rising towards it, he thinks there is something wrong in his
  • work; or, if he is too proud to think that, still the bribe of wealth
  • and honour warps him from his honest labour into efforts to attract
  • attention; and he gradually loses both his power of mind and his
  • rectitude of purpose. This, according to the degree of avarice or
  • ambition which exists in any painter's mind, is the necessary
  • influence upon him of the hope of great wealth and reputation. But the
  • harm is still greater, in so far as the possibility of attaining
  • fortune of this kind tempts people continually to become painters who
  • have no real gift for the work; and on whom these motives of mere
  • worldly interest have exclusive influence;--men who torment and abuse
  • the patient workers, eclipse or thrust aside all delicate and good
  • pictures by their own gaudy and coarse ones, corrupt the taste of the
  • public, and do the greatest amount of mischief to the schools of art
  • in their day which it is possible for their capacities to effect; and
  • it is quite wonderful how much mischief may be done even by small
  • capacity. If you could by any means succeed in keeping the prices of
  • pictures down, you would throw all these disturbers out of the way at
  • once.
  • You may perhaps think that this severe treatment would do more harm
  • than good, by withdrawing the wholesome element of emulation, and
  • giving no stimulus to exertion; but I am sorry to say that artists
  • will always be sufficiently jealous of one another, whether you pay
  • them large or low prices; and as for stimulus to exertion, believe me,
  • no good work in this world was ever done for money, nor while the
  • slightest thought of money affected the painter's mind. Whatever idea
  • of pecuniary value enters into his thoughts as he works, will, in
  • proportion to the distinctness of its presence, shorten his power. A
  • real painter will work for you exquisitely, if you give him, as I told
  • you a little while ago, bread and water and salt; and a bad painter
  • will work badly and hastily, though you give him a palace to live in,
  • and a princedom to live upon. Turner got, in his earlier years,
  • half-a-crown a day and his supper (not bad pay, neither); and he
  • learned to paint upon that. And I believe that there is no chance of
  • art's truly flourishing in any country, until you make it a simple and
  • plain business, providing its masters with an easy competence, but
  • rarely with anything more. And I say this, not because I despise the
  • great painter, but because I honour him; and I should no more think of
  • adding to his respectability or happiness by giving him riches, than,
  • if Shakespeare or Milton were alive, I should think we added to
  • _their_ respectability, or were likely to get better work from them,
  • by making them millionaires.
  • But, observe, it is not only the painter himself whom you injure, by
  • giving him too high prices; you injure all the inferior painters of
  • the day. If they are modest, they will be discouraged and depressed by
  • the feeling that their doings are worth so little, comparatively, in
  • your eyes;--if proud, all their worst passions will be aroused, and
  • the insult or opprobrium which they will try to cast on their
  • successful rival will not only afflict and wound him, but at last sour
  • and harden him: he cannot pass through such a trial without grievous
  • harm.
  • That, then, is the effect you produce on the painter of mark, and on
  • the inferior ones of his own standing. But you do worse than this; you
  • deprive yourselves, by what you give for the fashionable picture, of
  • the power of helping the younger men who are coming forward. Be it
  • admitted, for argument's sake if you are not convinced by what I have
  • said, that you do no harm to the great man by paying him well; yet
  • certainly you do him no special good. His reputation is established,
  • and his fortune made; he does not care whether you buy or not: he
  • thinks he is rather doing you a favour than otherwise by letting you
  • have one of his pictures at all. All the good you do him is to help
  • him to buy a new pair of carriage horses; whereas, with that same sum
  • which thus you cast away, you might have relieved the hearts and
  • preserved the health of twenty young painters; and if among those
  • twenty, you but chanced on one in whom a true latent power had been
  • hindered by his poverty, just consider what a far-branching,
  • far-embracing good you have wrought with that lucky expenditure of
  • yours. I say, "Consider it" in vain; you cannot consider it, for you
  • cannot conceive the sickness of heart with which a young painter of
  • deep feeling toils through his first obscurity;--his sense of the
  • strong voice within him, which you will not hear;--his vain, fond,
  • wondering witness to the things you will not see;--his far away
  • perception of things that he could accomplish if he had but peace, and
  • time, all unapproachable and vanishing from him, because no one will
  • leave him peace or grant him time: all his friends falling back from
  • him; those whom he would most reverently obey rebuking and paralysing
  • him; and last and worst of all, those who believe in him the most
  • faithfully suffering by him the most bitterly;--the wife's eyes, in
  • their sweet ambition, shining brighter as the cheek wastes away; and
  • the little lips at his side parched and pale, which one day, he knows,
  • though he may never see it, will quiver so proudly when they name his
  • name, calling him "our father." You deprive yourselves, by your large
  • expenditure for pictures of mark, of the power of relieving and
  • redeeming _this_ distress; you injure the painter whom you pay so
  • largely;--and what, after all, have you done for yourselves, or got
  • for yourselves? It does not in the least follow that the hurried work
  • of a fashionable painter will contain more for your money than the
  • quiet work of some unknown man. In all probability, you will find, if
  • you rashly purchase what is popular at a high price, that you have got
  • one picture you don't care for, for a sum which would have bought
  • twenty you would have delighted in. For remember always that the price
  • of a picture by a living artist, never represents, never _can_
  • represent, the quantity of labour or value in it. Its price
  • represents, for the most part, the degree of desire which the rich
  • people of the country have to possess it. Once get the wealthy classes
  • to imagine that the possession of pictures by a given artist adds to
  • their "gentility," and there is no price which his work may not
  • immediately reach, and for years maintain; and in buying at that
  • price, you are not getting value for your money, but merely disputing
  • for victory in a contest of ostentation. And it is hardly possible to
  • spend your money in a worse or more wasteful way; for though you may
  • not be doing it for ostentation yourself, you are, by your
  • pertinacity, nourishing the ostentation of others; you meet them in
  • their game of wealth, and continue it for them; if they had not found
  • an opposite player, the game would have been done; for a proud man can
  • find no enjoyment in possessing himself of what nobody disputes with
  • him. So that by every farthing you give for a picture beyond its fair
  • price--that is to say, the price which will pay the painter for his
  • time--you are not only cheating yourself and buying vanity, but you
  • are stimulating the vanity of others; paying literally, for the
  • cultivation of pride. You may consider every pound that you spend
  • above the just price of a work of art, as an investment in a cargo of
  • mental quick-lime or guano, which, being laid on the fields of human
  • nature, is to grow a harvest of pride. You are in fact ploughing and
  • harrowing, in a most valuable part of your land, in order to reap the
  • whirlwind; you are setting your hand stoutly to Job's agriculture,
  • "Let thistles grow instead of wheat, and cockle instead of barley."
  • Well, but you will say, there is one advantage in high prices, which
  • more than counterbalances all this mischief, namely, that by great
  • reward we both urge and enable a painter to produce rather one perfect
  • picture than many inferior ones: and one perfect picture (so you tell
  • us, and we believe it) is worth a great number of inferior ones.
  • It is so; but you cannot get it by paying for it. A great work is only
  • done when the painter gets into the humour for it, likes his subject,
  • and determines to paint it as well as he can, whether he is paid for
  • it or not; but bad work, and generally the worst sort of bad work, is
  • done when he is trying to produce a showy picture, or one that shall
  • appear to have as much labour in it as shall be worth a high
  • price.[14]
  • [14] When this lecture was delivered, I gave here some data for
  • approximate estimates of the average value of good modern
  • pictures of different classes; but the subject is too
  • complicated to be adequately treated in writing, without
  • introducing more detail than the reader will have patience
  • for. But I may state, roughly, that prices above a hundred
  • guineas are in general extravagant for water-colours, and
  • above five hundred for oils. An artist almost always does
  • wrong who puts more work than these prices will remunerate
  • him for into any single canvass--his talent would be better
  • employed in painting two pictures than one so elaborate. The
  • water-colour painters also are getting into the habit of
  • making their drawings too large, and in a measure attaching
  • their price rather to breadth and extent of touch than to
  • thoughtful labour. Of course marked exceptions occur here
  • and there, as in the case of John Lewis, whose drawings are
  • wrought with unfailing precision throughout, whatever their
  • scale. Hardly any price can be remunerative for such work.
  • There is however, another point, and a still more important one,
  • bearing on this matter of purchase, than the keeping down of prices to
  • a rational standard. And that is, that you pay your prices into the
  • hands of living men, and do not pour them into coffins.
  • For observe that, as we arrange our payment of pictures at present, no
  • artist's work is worth half its proper value while he is alive. The
  • moment he dies, his pictures, if they are good, reach double their
  • former value; but, that rise of price represents simply a profit made
  • by the intelligent dealer or purchaser on his past purchases. So that
  • the real facts of the matter are, that the British public, spending a
  • certain sum annually in art, determines that, of every thousand it
  • pays, only five hundred shall go to the painter, or shall be at all
  • concerned in the production of art; and that the other five hundred
  • shall be paid merely as a testimonial to the intelligent dealer, who
  • knew what to buy. Now, testimonials are very pretty and proper things,
  • within due limits; but testimonial to the amount of a hundred per
  • cent. on the total expenditure is not good political economy. Do not
  • therefore, in general, unless you see it to be necessary for its
  • preservation, buy the picture of a dead artist. If you fear that it
  • may be exposed to contempt or neglect, buy it; its price will then,
  • probably, not be high: if you want to put it into a public gallery,
  • buy it; you are sure, then, that you do not spend your money
  • selfishly: or, if you loved the man's work while he was alive, and
  • bought it then, buy it also now, if you can see no living work equal
  • to it. But if you did not buy it while the man was living, never buy
  • it after he is dead: you are then doing no good to him, and you are
  • doing some shame to yourself. Look around you for pictures that you
  • really like, and in buying which you can help some genius yet
  • unperished--that is the best atonement you can make to the one you
  • have neglected--and give to the living and struggling painter at once
  • wages, and testimonial.
  • So far, then, of the motives which should induce us to keep down the
  • prices of modern art, and thus render it, as a private possession,
  • attainable by greater numbers of people than at present. But we should
  • strive to render it accessible to them in other ways also--chiefly by
  • the permanent decoration of public buildings; and it is in this field
  • that I think we may look for the profitable means of providing that
  • constant employment for young painters of which we were speaking last
  • evening.
  • The first and most important kind of public buildings which we are
  • always sure to want, are schools: and I would ask you to consider very
  • carefully, whether we may not wisely introduce some great changes in
  • the way of school decoration. Hitherto, as far as I know, it has
  • either been so difficult to give all the education we wanted to our
  • lads, that we have been obliged to do it, if at all, with cheap
  • furniture in bare walls; or else we have considered that cheap
  • furniture and bare walls are a proper part of the means of education;
  • and supposed that boys learned best when they sat on hard forms, and
  • had nothing but blank plaster about and above them whereupon to employ
  • their spare attention; also, that it was as well they should be
  • accustomed to rough and ugly conditions of things, partly by way of
  • preparing them for the hardships of life, and partly that there might
  • be the least possible damage done to floors and forms, in the event of
  • their becoming, during the master's absence, the fields or instruments
  • of battle. All this is so far well and necessary, as it relates to the
  • training of country lads, and the first training of boys in general.
  • But there certainly comes a period in the life of a well educated
  • youth, in which one of the principal elements of his education is, or
  • ought to be, to give him refinement of habits; and not only to teach
  • him the strong exercises of which his frame is capable, but also to
  • increase his bodily sensibility and refinement, and show him such
  • small matters as the way of handling things properly, and treating
  • them considerately. Not only so, but I believe the notion of fixing
  • the attention by keeping the room empty, is a wholly mistaken one: I
  • think it is just in the emptiest room that the mind wanders most; for
  • it gets restless, like a bird, for want of a perch, and casts about
  • for any possible means of getting out and away. And even if it be
  • fixed, by an effort, on the business in hand, that business becomes
  • itself repulsive, more than it need be, by the vileness of its
  • associations; and many a study appears dull or painful to a boy when
  • it is pursued on a blotted deal desk, under a wall with nothing on it
  • but scratches and pegs, which would have been pursued pleasantly
  • enough in a curtained corner of his father's library, or at the
  • lattice window of his cottage. Nay, my own belief is, that the best
  • study of all is the most beautiful; and that a quiet glade of forest,
  • or the nook of a lake shore, are worth all the schoolrooms in
  • Christendom, when once you are past the multiplication table; but be
  • that as it may, there is no question at all but that a time ought to
  • come in the life of a well trained youth, when he can sit at a writing
  • table without wanting to throw the inkstand at his neighbour; and when
  • also he will feel more capable of certain efforts of mind with
  • beautiful and refined forms about him than with ugly ones. When that
  • time comes, he ought to be advanced into the decorated schools; and
  • this advance ought to be one of the important and honourable epochs of
  • his life.
  • I have not time, however, to insist on the mere serviceableness to our
  • youth of refined architectural decoration, as such; for I want you to
  • consider the probable influence of the particular kind of decoration
  • which I wish you to get for them, namely, historical painting. You
  • know we have hitherto been in the habit of conveying all our
  • historical knowledge, such as it is, by the ear only, never by the
  • eye; all our notions of things being ostensibly derived from verbal
  • description, not from sight. Now, I have no doubt that, as we grow
  • gradually wiser--and we are doing so every day--we shall discover at
  • last that the eye is a nobler organ than the ear; and that through the
  • eye we must, in reality, obtain, or put into form, nearly all the
  • useful information we are to have about this world. Even as the matter
  • stands, you will find that the knowledge which a boy is supposed to
  • receive from verbal description is only available to him so far as in
  • any underhand way he gets a sight of the thing you are talking about.
  • I remember well that, for many years of my life, the only notion I had
  • of the look of a Greek knight was complicated between recollection of
  • a small engraving in my pocket Pope's Homer, and reverent study of the
  • Horse Guards. And though I believe that most boys collect their ideas
  • from more varied sources, and arrange them more carefully than I did;
  • still, whatever sources they seek must always be ocular: if they are
  • clever boys, they will go and look at the Greek vases and sculptures
  • in the British Museum, and at the weapons in our armouries--they will
  • see what real armour is like in lustre, and what Greek armour was like
  • in form, and so put a fairly true image together, but still not, in
  • ordinary cases, a very living or interesting one. Now, the use of your
  • decorative painting would be, in myriads of ways, to animate their
  • history for them, and to put the living aspect of past things before
  • their eyes as faithfully as intelligent invention can; so that the
  • master shall have nothing to do but once to point to the schoolroom
  • walls, and for ever afterwards the meaning of any word would be fixed
  • in a boy's mind in the best possible way. Is it a question of
  • classical dress--what a tunic was like, or a chlamys, or a peplus? At
  • this day, you have to point to some vile woodcut, in the middle of a
  • dictionary page, representing the thing hung upon a stick, but then,
  • you would point to a hundred figures, wearing the actual dress, in its
  • fiery colours, in all actions of various stateliness or strength; you
  • would understand at once how it fell round the people's limbs as they
  • stood, how it drifted from their shoulders as they went, how it veiled
  • their faces as they wept, how it covered their heads in the day of
  • battle. _Now_, if you want to see what a weapon is like, you refer, in
  • like manner, to a numbered page, in which there are spear-heads in
  • rows, and sword-hilts in symmetrical groups; and gradually the boy
  • gets a dim mathematical notion how one scymitar is hooked to the right
  • and another to the left, and one javelin has a knob to it and another
  • none: while one glance at your good picture would show him,--and the
  • first rainy afternoon in the schoolroom would for ever fix in his
  • mind,--the look of the sword and spear as they fell or flew; and how
  • they pierced, or bent, or shattered--how men wielded them, and how men
  • died by them. But far more than all this, is it a question not of
  • clothes or weapons, but of men? how can we sufficiently estimate the
  • effect on the mind of a noble youth, at the time when the world opens
  • to him, of having faithful and touching representations put before him
  • of the acts and presences of great men--how many a resolution, which
  • would alter and exalt the whole course of his after-life, might be
  • formed, when in some dreamy twilight he met, through his own tears,
  • the fixed eyes of those shadows of the great dead, unescapable and
  • calm, piercing to his soul; or fancied that their lips moved in dread
  • reproof or soundless exhortation. And if but for one out of many this
  • were true--if yet, in a few, you could be sure that such influence had
  • indeed changed their thoughts and destinies, and turned the eager and
  • reckless youth, who would have cast away his energies on the
  • race-horse or the gambling-table, to that noble life-race, that holy
  • life-hazard, which should win all glory to himself and all good to his
  • country--would not that, to some purpose, be "political economy of
  • art?"
  • And observe, there could be no monotony, no exhaustibleness, in the
  • scenes required to be thus pourtrayed. Even if there were, and you
  • wanted for every school in the kingdom, one death of Leonidas; one
  • battle of Marathon; one death of Cleobis and Bito; there need not
  • therefore be more monotony in your art than there was in the
  • repetition of a given cycle of subjects by the religious painters of
  • Italy. But we ought not to admit a cycle at all. For though we had as
  • many great schools as we have great cities (one day I hope we _shall_
  • have), centuries of painting would not exhaust, in all the number of
  • them, the noble and pathetic subjects which might be chosen from the
  • history of even one noble nation. But, besides this, you will not, in
  • a little while, limit your youths' studies to so narrow fields as you
  • do now. There will come a time--I am sure of it--when it will be found
  • that the same practical results, both in mental discipline, and in
  • political philosophy, are to be attained by the accurate study of
  • mediæval and modern as of ancient history; and that the facts of
  • mediæval and modern history are, on the whole, the most important
  • to us. And among these noble groups of constellated schools which I
  • foresee arising in our England, I foresee also that there will be
  • divided fields of thought; and that while each will give its scholars
  • a great general idea of the world's history, such as all men should
  • possess--each will also take upon itself, as its own special duty, the
  • closer study of the course of events in some given place or time. It
  • will review the rest of history, but it will exhaust its own special
  • field of it; and found its moral and political teaching on the most
  • perfect possible analysis of the results of human conduct in one
  • place, and at one epoch. And then, the galleries of that school will
  • be painted with the historical scenes belonging to the age which it
  • has chosen for its special study.
  • So far, then, of art as you may apply it to that great series of
  • public buildings which you devote to the education of youth. The next
  • large class of public buildings in which we should introduce it, is
  • one which I think a few years more of national progress will render
  • more serviceable to us than they have been lately. I mean, buildings
  • for the meetings of guilds of trades.
  • And here, for the last time, I must again interrupt the course of our
  • chief inquiry, in order to state one other principle of political
  • economy, which is perfectly simple and indisputable; but which,
  • nevertheless, we continually get into commercial embarrassments for
  • want of understanding; and not only so, but suffer much hindrance in
  • our commercial discoveries, because many of our business men do not
  • practically admit it.
  • Supposing half a dozen or a dozen men were cast ashore from a wreck on
  • an uninhabited island and left to their own resources, one of course,
  • according to his capacity, would be set to one business and one to
  • another; the strongest to dig and to cut wood, and to build huts for
  • the rest: the most dexterous to make shoes out of bark and coats out
  • of skins; the best educated to look for iron or lead in the rocks, and
  • to plan the channels for the irrigation of the fields. But though
  • their labours were thus naturally severed, that small group of
  • shipwrecked men would understand well enough that the speediest
  • progress was to be made by helping each other,--not by opposing each
  • other; and they would know that this help could only be properly given
  • so long as they were frank and open in their relations, and the
  • difficulties which each lay under properly explained to the rest. So
  • that any appearance of secresy or separateness in the actions of any
  • of them would instantly, and justly, be looked upon with suspicion by
  • the rest, as the sign of some selfish or foolish proceeding on the
  • part of the individual. If, for instance, the scientific man were
  • found to have gone out at night, unknown to the rest, to alter the
  • sluices, the others would think, and in all probability rightly think,
  • that he wanted to get the best supply of water to his own field; and
  • if the shoemaker refused to show them where the bark grew which he
  • made the sandals of, they would naturally think, and in all
  • probability rightly think, that he didn't want them to see how much
  • there was of it, and that he meant to ask from them more corn and
  • potatoes in exchange for his sandals than the trouble of making them
  • deserved. And thus, although each man would have a portion of time to
  • himself in which he was allowed to do what he chose without let or
  • inquiry,--so long as he was working in that particular business which
  • he had undertaken for the common benefit, any secresy on his part
  • would be immediately supposed to mean mischief; and would require to
  • be accounted for, or put an end to: and this all the more because,
  • whatever the work might be, certainly there would be difficulties
  • about it which, when once they were well explained, might be more or
  • less done away with by the help of the rest; so that assuredly every
  • one of them would advance with his labour not only more happily, but
  • more profitably and quickly, by having no secrets, and by frankly
  • bestowing, and frankly receiving, such help as lay in his way to get
  • or to give.
  • And, just as the best and richest result of wealth and happiness to
  • the whole of them, would follow on their perseverance in such a system
  • of frank communication and of helpful labour;--so precisely the worst
  • and poorest result would be obtained by a system of secresy and of
  • enmity; and each man's happiness and wealth would assuredly be
  • diminished in proportion to the degree in which jealousy and
  • concealment became their social and economical principles. It would
  • not, in the long run, bring good, but only evil, to the man of
  • science, if, instead of telling openly where he had found good iron,
  • he carefully concealed every new bed of it, that he might ask, in
  • exchange for the rare ploughshare, more corn from the farmer, or in
  • exchange for the rude needle, more labour from the sempstress: and it
  • would not ultimately bring good, but only evil, to the farmers, if
  • they sought to burn each other's cornstacks, that they might raise the
  • value of their grain, or if the sempstresses tried to break each
  • other's needles, that each might get all the stitching to herself.
  • Now, these laws of human action are precisely as authoritative in
  • their application to the conduct of a million of men, as to that of
  • six or twelve. All enmity, jealousy, opposition, and secresy are
  • wholly, and in all circumstances, destructive in their nature--not
  • productive; and all kindness, fellowship, and communicativeness are
  • invariably productive in their operation,--not destructive; and the
  • evil principles of opposition and exclusiveness are not rendered less
  • fatal, but more fatal, by their acceptance among large masses of men;
  • more fatal, I say, exactly in proportion as their influence is more
  • secret. For though the opposition does always its own simple,
  • necessary, direct quantity of harm, and withdraws always its own
  • simple, necessary, measurable quantity of wealth from the sum
  • possessed by the community, yet, in proportion to the size of the
  • community, it does another and more refined mischief than this, by
  • concealing its own fatality under aspects of mercantile complication
  • and expediency, and giving rise to multitudes of false theories based
  • on a mean belief in narrow and immediate appearances of good done here
  • and there by things which have the universal and everlasting nature of
  • evil. So that the time and powers of the nation are wasted, not only
  • in wretched struggling against each other, but in vain complaints, and
  • groundless discouragements, and empty investigations, and useless
  • experiments in laws, and elections, and inventions; with hope always
  • to pull wisdom through some new-shaped slit in a ballot-box, and to
  • drag prosperity down out of the clouds along some new knot of electric
  • wire; while all the while Wisdom stands calling at the corners of the
  • streets, and the blessing of heaven waits ready to rain down upon us,
  • deeper than the rivers and broader than the dew, if only we will obey
  • the first plain principles of humanity, and the first plain precepts
  • of the skies; "Execute true judgment, and show mercy and compassion,
  • every man to his brother; and let none of you imagine evil against his
  • brother in your heart."[15]
  • [15] It would be well if, instead of preaching continually about
  • the doctrine of faith and good works, our clergymen would
  • simply explain to their people a little what good works
  • mean. There is not a chapter in all the Book we profess to
  • believe, more specially and directly written for England,
  • than the second of Habakkuk, and I never in all my life
  • heard one of its practical texts preached from. I suppose
  • the clergymen are all afraid, and know that their flocks,
  • while they will sit quite politely to hear syllogisms out of
  • the epistle to the Romans, would get restive directly if
  • they ever pressed a practical text home to them. But we
  • should have no mercantile catastrophes, and no distressful
  • pauperism, if we only read often, and took to heart, those
  • plain words:--"Yea, also, because he is a proud man, neither
  • keepeth at home, who enlargeth his desire as hell, and
  • cannot be satisfied,--Shall not all these take up a parable
  • against him, and a taunting proverb against him, and say,
  • 'Woe to him that increaseth that which is not his: and to
  • him that _ladeth himself with thick clay_.'" (What a
  • glorious history, in one metaphor, of the life of a man
  • greedy of fortune.) "Woe to him that coveteth an evil
  • covetousness that he may set his nest on high. Woe to him
  • that buildeth a town with blood, and stablisheth a city by
  • iniquity. Behold, is it not of the Lord of Hosts that the
  • people shall labour in the very fire, and the people shall
  • weary themselves for very vanity."
  • The Americans, who have been sending out ships with sham
  • bolt-heads on their timbers, and only half their bolts, may
  • meditate on that "buildeth a town with blood."
  • Therefore, I believe most firmly, that as the laws of national
  • prosperity get familiar to us, we shall more and more cast our toil
  • into social and communicative systems; and that one of the first means
  • of our doing so, will be the re-establishing guilds of every important
  • trade in a vital, not formal, condition;--that there will be a great
  • council or government house for the members of every trade, built in
  • whatever town of the kingdom occupies itself principally in such
  • trade, with minor council halls in other cities; and to each
  • council-hall, officers attached, whose first business may be to
  • examine into the circumstances of every operative, in that trade, who
  • chooses to report himself to them when out of work, and to set him to
  • work, if he is indeed able and willing, at a fixed rate of wages,
  • determined at regular periods in the council-meetings; and whose next
  • duty may be to bring reports before the council of all improvements
  • made in the business, and means of its extension: not allowing private
  • patents of any kind, but making all improvements available to every
  • member of the guild, only allotting, after successful trial of them, a
  • certain reward to the inventors.
  • For these, and many other such purposes, such halls will be again, I
  • trust, fully established, and then, in the paintings and decorations
  • of them, especial effort ought to be made to express the worthiness
  • and honourableness of the trade for whose members they are founded.
  • For I believe one of the worst symptoms of modern society to be, its
  • notion of great inferiority, and ungentlemanliness, as necessarily
  • belonging to the character of a tradesman. I believe tradesmen may be,
  • ought to be--often are, more gentlemen than idle and useless people:
  • and I believe that art may do noble work by recording in the hall of
  • each trade, the services which men belonging to that trade have done
  • for their country, both preserving the portraits, and recording the
  • important incidents in the lives, of those who have made great
  • advances in commerce and civilization. I cannot follow out this
  • subject, it branches too far, and in too many directions; besides, I
  • have no doubt you will at once see and accept the truth of the main
  • principle, and be able to think it out for yourselves. I would fain
  • also have said something of what might be done, in the same manner,
  • for almshouses and hospitals, and for what, as I shall try to explain
  • in notes to this lecture, we may hope to see, some day, established
  • with a different meaning in their name than that they now
  • bear--workhouses; but I have detained you too long already, and cannot
  • permit myself to trespass further on your patience except only to
  • recapitulate, in closing, the simple principles respecting wealth
  • which we have gathered during the course of our inquiry; principles
  • which are nothing more than the literal and practical acceptance of
  • the saying, which is in all good men's mouths; namely, that they are
  • stewards or ministers of whatever talents are entrusted to them. Only,
  • is it not a strange thing, that while we more or less accept the
  • meaning of that saying, so long as it is considered metaphorical, we
  • never accept its meaning in its own terms? You know the lesson is
  • given us under the form of a story about money. Money was given to the
  • servants to make use of: the unprofitable servant dug in the earth,
  • and hid his Lord's money. Well, we, in our poetical and spiritual
  • application of this, say, that of course money doesn't mean money, it
  • means wit, it means intellect, it means influence in high quarters, it
  • means everything in the world except itself. And do not you see what a
  • pretty and pleasant come-off there is for most of us, in this
  • spiritual application? Of course, if we had wit, we would use it for
  • the good of our fellow-creatures. But we haven't wit. Of course, if we
  • had influence with the bishops, we would use it for the good of the
  • Church; but we haven't any influence with the bishops. Of course, if
  • we had political power, we would use it for the good of the nation;
  • but we have no political power; we have no talents entrusted to _us_
  • of any sort or kind. It is true we have a little money, but the
  • parable can't possibly mean anything so vulgar as money; our money's
  • our own.
  • I believe, if you think seriously of this matter, you will feel that
  • the first and most literal application is just as necessary a one as
  • any other--that the story does very specially mean what it says--plain
  • money; and that the reason we don't at once believe it does so, is a
  • sort of tacit idea that while thought, wit, and intellect, and all
  • power of birth and position, are indeed _given_ to us, and, therefore,
  • to be laid out for the Giver,--our wealth has not been given to us;
  • but we have worked for it, and have a right to spend it as we choose.
  • I think you will find that is the real substance of our understanding
  • in this matter. Beauty, we say, is given by God--it is a talent;
  • strength is given by God--it is a talent; position is given by God--it
  • is a talent; but money is proper wages for our day's work--it is not a
  • talent, it is a due. We may justly spend it on ourselves, if we have
  • worked for it.
  • And there would be some shadow of excuse for this, were it not that
  • the very power of making the money is itself only one of the
  • applications of that intellect or strength which we confess to be
  • talents. Why is one man richer than another? Because he is more
  • industrious, more persevering, and more sagacious. Well, who made him
  • more persevering or more sagacious than others? That power of
  • endurance, that quickness of apprehension, that calmness of judgment,
  • which enable him to seize the opportunities that others lose, and
  • persist in the lines of conduct in which others fail--are these not
  • talents?--are they not, in the present state of the world, among the
  • most distinguished and influential of mental gifts? And is it not
  • wonderful, that while we should be utterly ashamed to use a
  • superiority of body, in order to thrust our weaker companions aside
  • from some place of advantage, we unhesitatingly use our superiorities
  • of mind to thrust them back from whatever good that strength of mind
  • can attain? You would be indignant if you saw a strong man walk into a
  • theatre or a lecture-room, and, calmly choosing the best place, take
  • his feeble neighbour by the shoulder, and turn him out of it into the
  • back seats, or the street. You would be equally indignant if you saw a
  • stout fellow thrust himself up to a table where some hungry children
  • were being fed, and reach his arm over their heads and take their
  • bread from them. But you are not the least indignant if, when a man
  • has stoutness of thought and swiftness of capacity, and, instead of
  • being long-armed only, has the much greater gift of being
  • long-headed--you think it perfectly just that he should use his
  • intellect to take the bread out of the mouths of all the other men in
  • the town who are of the same trade with him; or use his breadth and
  • sweep of sight to gather some branch of the commerce of the country
  • into one great cobweb, of which he is himself to be the central
  • spider, making every thread vibrate with the points of his claws, and
  • commanding every avenue with the facets of his eyes. You see no
  • injustice in this.
  • But there is injustice; and, let us trust, one of which honourable men
  • will at no very distant period disdain to be guilty. In some degree,
  • however, it is indeed not unjust; in some degree it is necessary and
  • intended. It is assuredly just that idleness should be surpassed by
  • energy; that the widest influence should be possessed by those who are
  • best able to wield it; and that a wise man, at the end of his career,
  • should be better off than a fool. But for that reason, is the fool to
  • be wretched, utterly crushed down, and left in all the suffering which
  • his conduct and capacity naturally inflict?--Not so. What do you
  • suppose fools were made for? That you might tread upon them, and
  • starve them, and get the better of them in every possible way? By no
  • means. They were made that wise people might take care of them. That
  • is the true and plain fact concerning the relations of every strong
  • and wise man to the world about him. He has his strength given him,
  • not that he may crush the weak, but that he may support and guide
  • them. In his own household he is to be the guide and the support of
  • his children; out of his household he is still to be the father, that
  • is, the guide and support of the weak and the poor; not merely of the
  • meritoriously weak and the innocently poor, but of the guiltily and
  • punishably poor; of the men who ought to have known better--of the
  • poor who ought to be ashamed of themselves. It is nothing to give
  • pension and cottage to the widow who has lost her son; it is nothing
  • to give food and medicine to the workman who has broken his arm, or
  • the decrepit woman wasting in sickness. But it is something to use
  • your time and strength to war with the waywardness and thoughtlessness
  • of mankind; to keep the erring workman in your service till you have
  • made him an unerring one; and to direct your fellow-merchant to the
  • opportunity which his dullness would have lost. This is much; but it
  • is yet more, when you have fully achieved the superiority which is due
  • to you, and acquired the wealth which is the fitting reward of your
  • sagacity, if you solemnly accept the responsibility of it, as it is
  • the helm and guide of labour far and near. For you who have it in your
  • hands, are in reality the pilots of the power and effort of the
  • State.[16] It is entrusted to you as an authority to be used for good
  • or evil, just as completely as kingly authority was ever given to a
  • prince, or military command to a captain. And, according to the
  • quantity of it that you have in your hands you are the arbiters of the
  • will and work of England; and the whole issue, whether the work of the
  • State shall suffice for the State or not, depends upon you. You may
  • stretch out your sceptre over the heads of the English labourers, and
  • say to them, as they stoop to its waving, "Subdue this obstacle that
  • has baffled our fathers, put away this plague that consumes our
  • children; water these dry places, plough these desert ones, carry this
  • food to those who are in hunger; carry this light to those who are in
  • darkness; carry this life to those who are in death;" or on the other
  • side you may say to her labourers: "Here am I; this power is in my
  • hand; come, build a mound here for me to be throned upon, high and
  • wide; come, make crowns for my head, that men may see them shine from
  • far away; come, weave tapestries for my feet, that I may tread softly
  • on the silk and purple;[17] come, dance before me, that I may be gay;
  • and sing sweetly to me, that I may slumber; so shall I live in joy,
  • and die in honour." And better than such an honourable death, it were
  • that the day had perished wherein we were born, and the night in which
  • it was said there is a child conceived.
  • [16] See note 7th, in Addenda [p. 106].
  • [17] See note 8th, in Addenda [p. 107].
  • I trust, that in a little while, there will be few of our rich men
  • who, through carelessness or covetousness, thus forfeit the glorious
  • office which is intended for their hands. I said, just now, that
  • wealth ill used was as the net of the spider, entangling and
  • destroying: but wealth well used, is as the net of the sacred fisher
  • who gathers souls of men out of the deep. A time will come--I do not
  • think even now it is far from us--when this golden net of the world's
  • wealth will be spread abroad as the flaming meshes of morning cloud
  • are over the sky; bearing with them the joy of light and the dew of
  • the morning, as well as the summons to honourable and peaceful toil.
  • What less can we hope from your wealth than this, rich men of
  • England, when once you feel fully how, by the strength of your
  • possessions--not, observe, by the exhaustion, but by the
  • administration of them and the power--you can direct the
  • acts,--command the energies,--inform the ignorance,--prolong the
  • existence, of the whole human race; and how, even of worldly wisdom,
  • which man employs faithfully, it is true, not only that her ways are
  • pleasantness, but that her paths are peace; and that, for all the
  • children of men, as well as for those to whom she is given, Length of
  • days are in her right hand, as in her left hand Riches and Honour?
  • ADDENDA.
  • Note, p. 19.--"_Fatherly authority._"
  • This statement could not, of course, be heard without displeasure by a
  • certain class of politicians; and in one of the notices of these
  • lectures given in the Manchester journals at the time, endeavour was
  • made to get quit of it by referring to the Divine authority, as the
  • only Paternal power with respect to which men were truly styled
  • "brethren." Of course it is so, and, equally of course, all human
  • government is nothing else than the executive expression of this
  • Divine authority. The moment government ceases to be the practical
  • enforcement of Divine law, it is tyranny; and the meaning which I
  • attach to the words, "paternal government," is, in more extended
  • terms, simply this--"The executive fulfilment, by formal human
  • methods, of the will of the Father of mankind respecting His
  • children." I could not give such a definition of Government as this in
  • a popular lecture; and even in written form, it will necessarily
  • suggest many objections, of which I must notice and answer the most
  • probable.
  • Only, in order to avoid the recurrence of such tiresome phrases as "it
  • may be answered in the second place," and "it will be objected in the
  • third place," etc., I will ask the reader's leave to arrange the
  • discussion in the form of simple dialogue, letting _O._ stand for
  • objector, and _R._ for response.
  • _O._--You define your paternal government to be the executive
  • fulfilment, by formal human methods, of the Divine will. But,
  • assuredly, that will cannot stand in need of aid or expression from
  • human laws. It cannot fail of its fulfilment.
  • _R._--In the final sense it cannot; and in that sense, men who are
  • committing murder and stealing are fulfilling the will of God as much
  • as the best and kindest people in the world. But in the limited and
  • present sense, the only sense with which _we_ have anything to do,
  • God's will concerning man is fulfilled by some men, and thwarted by
  • others. And those men who either persuade or enforce the doing of it,
  • stand towards those who are rebellious against it exactly in the
  • position of faithful children in a family, who, when the father is out
  • of sight, either compel or persuade the rest to do as their father
  • would have them, were he present; and in so far as they are expressing
  • and maintaining, for the time, the paternal authority, they exercise,
  • in the exact sense in which I mean the phrase to be understood,
  • paternal government over the rest.
  • _O._--But, if Providence has left a liberty to man in many things in
  • order to prove him, why should human law abridge that liberty, and
  • take upon itself to compel what the great Lawgiver does not compel?
  • _R._--It is confessed, in the enactment of any law whatsoever, that
  • human lawgivers have a right to do this. For, if you have no right to
  • abridge any of the liberty which Providence has left to man, you have
  • no right to punish any one for committing murder or robbery. You ought
  • to leave them to the punishment of God and Nature. But if you think
  • yourself under obligation to punish, as far as human laws can, the
  • violation of the will of God by those great sins, you are certainly
  • under the same obligation to punish, with proportionately less
  • punishment, the violation of His will in less sins.
  • _O._--No; you must not attempt to punish less sins by law, because you
  • cannot properly define nor ascertain them. Everybody can determine
  • whether murder has been committed or not, but you cannot determine how
  • far people have been unjust or cruel in minor matters, and therefore
  • cannot make or execute laws concerning minor matters.
  • _R._--If I propose to you to punish faults which cannot be defined, or
  • to execute laws which cannot be made equitable, reject the laws I
  • propose. But do not generally object to the principle of law.
  • _O._--Yes; I generally object to the principle of law as applied to
  • minor things; because, if you could succeed (which you cannot) in
  • regulating the entire conduct of men by law in little things as well
  • as great, you would take away from human life all its probationary
  • character, and render many virtues and pleasures impossible. You would
  • reduce virtue to the movement of a machine, instead of the act of a
  • spirit.
  • _R._--You have just said, parenthetically, and I fully and willingly
  • admit it, that it is impossible to regulate all minor matters by law.
  • Is it not probable, therefore, that the degree in which it is
  • _possible_ to regulate them by it, is also the degree in which it is
  • _right_ to regulate them by it? Or what other means of judgment will
  • you employ, to separate the things which ought to be formally
  • regulated from the things which ought not. You admit that great sins
  • should be legally repressed; but you say that small sins should not be
  • legally repressed. How do you distinguish between great and small
  • sins; and how do you intend to determine, or do you in practice of
  • daily life determine, on what occasions you should compel people to do
  • right, and on what occasions you should leave them the option of doing
  • wrong?
  • _O._--I think you cannot make any accurate or logical distinction in
  • such matters; but that common sense and instinct have, in all
  • civilized nations, indicated certain crimes of great social
  • harmfulness, such as murder, theft, adultery, slander, and such like,
  • which it is proper to repress legally; and that common sense and
  • instinct indicate also the kind of crimes which it is proper for laws
  • to let alone, such as miserliness, ill-natured speaking, and many of
  • those commercial dishonesties which I have a notion you want your
  • paternal government to interfere with.
  • _R._--Pray do not alarm yourself about what my paternal government is
  • likely to interfere with, but keep to the matter in hand. You say that
  • "common sense and instinct" have, in all civilized nations,
  • distinguished between the sins that ought to be legally dealt with and
  • that ought not. Do you mean that the laws of all civilized nations are
  • perfect?
  • _O._--No; certainly not.
  • _R._--Or that they are perfect at least in their discrimination of
  • what crimes they should deal with, and what crimes they should let
  • alone?
  • _O._--No; not exactly.
  • _R._--What _do_ you mean, then?
  • _O._--I mean that the general tendency is right in the laws of
  • civilized nations; and that, in due course of time, natural sense and
  • instinct point out the matters they should be brought to bear upon.
  • And each question of legislation must be made a separate subject of
  • inquiry as it presents itself: you cannot fix any general principles
  • about what should be dealt with legally, and what should not.
  • _R._--Supposing it to be so, do you think there are any points in
  • which our English legislation is capable of amendment, as it bears on
  • commercial and economical matters, in this present time?
  • _O._--Of course I do.
  • _R._--Well, then, let us discuss these together quietly; and if the
  • points that I want amended seem to you incapable of amendment, or not
  • in need of amendment, say so: but don't object, at starting, to the
  • mere proposition of applying law to things which have not had law
  • applied to them before. You have admitted the fitness of my
  • expression, "paternal government:" it only has been, and remains, a
  • question between us, how far such government should extend. Perhaps
  • you would like it only to regulate, among the children, the length of
  • their lessons; and perhaps I should like it also to regulate the
  • hardness of their cricket-balls: but cannot you wait quietly till you
  • know what I want it to do, before quarrelling with the thing itself?
  • _O._--No; I cannot wait quietly: in fact I don't see any use in
  • beginning such a discussion at all, because I am quite sure from the
  • first, that you want to meddle with things that you have no business
  • with, and to interfere with healthy liberty of action in all sorts of
  • ways; and I know that you can't propose any laws that would be of real
  • use.[18]
  • [18] If the reader is displeased with me for putting this foolish
  • speech into his mouth, I entreat his pardon; but he may be
  • assured that it is a speech which would be made by many
  • people, and the substance of which would be tacitly felt by
  • many more, at this point of the discussion. I have really
  • tried, up to this point, to make the objector as intelligent
  • a person as it is possible for an author to imagine anybody
  • to be, who differs with him.
  • _R._--If you indeed know that, you would be wrong to hear me any
  • farther. But if you are only in painful doubt about me, which makes
  • you unwilling to run the risk of wasting your time, I will tell you
  • beforehand what I really do think about this same liberty of action,
  • namely, that whenever we can make a perfectly equitable law about any
  • matter, or even a law securing, on the whole, more just conduct than
  • unjust, we ought to make that law; and that there will yet, on these
  • conditions, always remain a number of matters respecting which
  • legalism and formalism are impossible; enough, and more than enough,
  • to exercise all human powers of individual judgment, and afford all
  • kinds of scope to individual character. I think this; but of course it
  • can only be proved by separate examination of the possibilities of
  • formal restraint in each given field of action; and these two lectures
  • are nothing more than a sketch of such a detailed examination in one
  • field, namely, that of art. You will find, however, one or two other
  • remarks on such possibilities in the next note.
  • Note 2nd, p. 21.--"_Right to public support._"
  • It did not appear to me desirable, in the course of the spoken
  • lecture, to enter into details or offer suggestions on the questions
  • of the regulation of labour and distribution of relief, as it would
  • have been impossible to do so without touching in many disputed or
  • disputable points, not easily handled before a general audience. But I
  • must now supply what is wanting to make my general statement clear.
  • I believe, in the first place, that no Christian nation has any
  • business to see one of its members in distress without helping him,
  • though, perhaps, at the same time punishing him: help, of course--in
  • nine cases out of ten--meaning guidance, much more than gift, and,
  • therefore, interference with liberty. When a peasant mother sees one
  • of her careless children fall into a ditch, her first proceeding is to
  • pull him out; her second, to box his ears; her third, ordinarily, to
  • lead him carefully a little way by the hand, or send him home for the
  • rest of the day. The child usually cries, and very often would clearly
  • prefer remaining in the ditch; and if he understood any of the terms
  • of politics, would certainly express resentment at the interference
  • with his individual liberty: but the mother has done her duty.
  • Whereas the usual call of the mother nation to any of her children,
  • under such circumstances, has lately been nothing more than the
  • foxhunter's,--"Stay still there; I shall clear you." And if we always
  • _could_ clear them, their requests to be left in muddy independence
  • might be sometimes allowed by kind people, or their cries for help
  • disdained by unkind ones. But we can't clear them. The whole nation
  • is, in fact, bound together, as men are by ropes on a glacier--if one
  • falls, the rest must either lift him or drag him along with them[19]
  • as dead weight, not without much increase of danger to themselves. And
  • the law of right being manifestly in this, as, whether manifestly or
  • not, it is always, the law of prudence, the only question is, how this
  • wholesome help and interference are to be administered.
  • [19] It is very curious to watch the efforts of two shopkeepers
  • to ruin each other, neither having the least idea that his
  • ruined neighbour must eventually be supported at his own
  • expense, with an increase of poor rates; and that the
  • contest between them is not in reality which shall get
  • everything for himself, but which shall first take upon
  • himself and his customers the gratuitous maintenance of the
  • other's family.
  • The first interference should be in education. In order that men may
  • be able to support themselves when they are grown, their strength must
  • be properly developed while they are young; and the state should
  • always see to this--not allowing their health to be broken by too
  • early labour, nor their powers to be wasted for want of knowledge.
  • Some questions connected with this matter are noticed farther on under
  • the head "Trial Schools:" one point I must notice here, that I believe
  • all youths of whatever rank, ought to learn some manual trade
  • thoroughly; for it is quite wonderful how much a man's views of life
  • are cleared by the attainment of the capacity of doing any one thing
  • well with his hands and arms. For a long time, what right life there
  • was in the upper classes of Europe depended in no small degree on the
  • necessity which each man was under of being able to fence; at this
  • day, the most useful things which boys learn at public schools, are, I
  • believe, riding, rowing, and cricketing. But it would be far better
  • that members of Parliament should be able to plough straight, and make
  • a horseshoe, than only to feather oars neatly or point their toes
  • prettily in stirrups. Then, in literary and scientific teaching, the
  • great point of economy is to give the discipline of it through
  • knowledge which will immediately bear on practical life. Our literary
  • work has long been economically useless to us because too much
  • concerned with dead languages; and our scientific work will yet, for
  • some time, be a good deal lost, because scientific men are too fond or
  • too vain of their systems, and waste the student's time in
  • endeavouring to give him large views, and make him perceive
  • interesting connections of facts; when there is not one student, no,
  • nor one man, in a thousand, who can feel the beauty of a system, or
  • even take it clearly into his head; but nearly all men can understand,
  • and most will be interested in, the facts which bear on daily life.
  • Botanists have discovered some wonderful connection between nettles
  • and figs, which a cowboy who will never see a ripe fig in his life
  • need not be at all troubled about; but it will be interesting to him
  • to know what effect nettles have on hay, and what taste they will give
  • to porridge; and it will give him nearly a new life if he can be got
  • but once, in a spring time, to look well at the beautiful circlet of
  • the white nettle blossom, and work out with his schoolmaster the
  • curves of its petals, and the way it is set on its central mast. So,
  • the principle of chemical equivalents, beautiful as it is, matters far
  • less to a peasant boy, and even to most sons of gentlemen, than their
  • knowing how to find whether the water is wholesome in the back-kitchen
  • cistern, or whether the seven-acre field wants sand or chalk.
  • Having, then, directed the studies of our youth so as to make them
  • practically serviceable men at the time of their entrance into life,
  • that entrance should always be ready for them in cases where their
  • private circumstances present no opening. There ought to be government
  • establishments for every trade, in which all youths who desired it
  • should be received as apprentices on their leaving school; and men
  • thrown out of work received at all times. At these government
  • manufactories the discipline should be strict, and the wages steady,
  • not varying at all in proportion to the demand for the article, but
  • only in proportion to the price of food; the commodities produced
  • being laid up in store to meet sudden demands, and sudden fluctuations
  • in prices prevented:--that gradual and necessary fluctuation only
  • being allowed which is properly consequent on larger or more limited
  • supply of raw material and other natural causes. When there was a
  • visible tendency to produce a glut of any commodity, that tendency
  • should be checked by directing the youth at the government schools
  • into other trades; and the yearly surplus of commodities should be the
  • principal means of government provision for the poor. That provision
  • should be large, and not disgraceful to them. At present there are
  • very strange notions in the public mind respecting the receiving of
  • alms: most people are willing to take them in the form of a pension
  • from government, but unwilling to take them in the form of a pension
  • from their parishes. There may be some reason for this singular
  • prejudice, in the fact of the government pension being usually given
  • as a definite acknowledgment of some service done to the country;--but
  • the parish pension is, or ought to be, given precisely on the same
  • terms. A labourer serves his country with his spade, just as a man in
  • the middle ranks of life serves it with his sword, pen, or lancet: if
  • the service is less, and therefore the wages during health less, then
  • the reward, when health is broken, may be less, but not, therefore,
  • less honourable; and it ought to be quite as natural and
  • straightforward a matter for a labourer to take his pension from his
  • parish, because he has deserved well of his parish, as for a man in
  • higher rank to take his pension from his country, because he has
  • deserved well of his country. If there be any disgrace in coming to
  • the parish, because it may imply improvidence in early life, much more
  • is there disgrace in coming to the government: since improvidence is
  • far less justifiable in a highly educated than in an imperfectly
  • educated man; and far less justifiable in a high rank, where
  • extravagance must have been luxury, than in a low rank, where it may
  • only have been comfort. So that the real fact of the matter is, that
  • people will take alms delightedly, consisting of a carriage and
  • footmen, because those do not look like alms to the people in the
  • street; but they will not take alms consisting only of bread and water
  • and coals, because everybody would understand what those meant. Mind,
  • I do not want any one to refuse the carriage who ought to have it; but
  • neither do I want them to refuse the coals. I should indeed be sorry
  • if any change in our views on these subjects involved the least
  • lessening of self-dependence in the English mind: but the common
  • shrinking of men from the acceptance of public charity is not
  • self-dependence, but mere base and selfish pride. It is not that they
  • are unwilling to live at their neighbours' expense, but that they are
  • unwilling to confess they do: it is not dependence they wish to avoid,
  • but gratitude. They will take places in which they know there is
  • nothing to be done--they will borrow money they know they cannot
  • repay--they will carry on a losing business with other people's
  • capital--they will cheat the public in their shops, or sponge on their
  • friends at their houses; but to say plainly they are poor men, who
  • need the nation's help, and go into an almshouse--this they loftily
  • repudiate, and virtuously prefer being thieves to being paupers.
  • I trust that these deceptive efforts of dishonest men to appear
  • independent, and the agonizing efforts of unfortunate men to remain
  • independent, may both be in some degree checked by a better
  • administration and understanding of laws respecting the poor. But the
  • ordinances for relief and the ordinances for labour must go together;
  • otherwise distress caused by misfortune will always be confounded, as
  • it is now, with distress caused by idleness, unthrift, and fraud. It
  • is only when the state watches and guides the middle life of men, that
  • it can, without disgrace to them, protect their old age, acknowledging
  • in that protection that they have done their duty, or at least some
  • portion of their duty, in better days.
  • I know well how strange, fanciful, or impracticable these suggestions
  • will appear to most of the business men of this day; men who conceive
  • the proper state of the world to be simply that of a vast and
  • disorganized mob, scrambling each for what he can get, trampling down
  • its children and old men in the mire, and doing what work it finds
  • _must_ be done with any irregular squad of labourers it can bribe or
  • inveigle together, and afterwards scatter to starvation. A great deal
  • may, indeed, be done in this way by a nation strong-elbowed and
  • strong-hearted as we are--not easily frightened by pushing, nor
  • discouraged by falls. But it is still not the right way of doing
  • things for people who call themselves Christians. Every so named soul
  • of man claims from every other such soul, protection and education in
  • childhood--help or punishment in middle life--reward or relief, if
  • needed, in old age; all of these should be completely and unstintingly
  • given; and they can only be given by the organization of such a system
  • as I have described.
  • Note 3rd, p. 24.--"_Trial Schools._"
  • It may be seriously questioned by the reader how much of painting
  • talent we really lose on our present system,[20] and how much we
  • should gain by the proposed trial schools. For it might be thought,
  • that as matters stand at present, we have more painters than we ought
  • to have, having so many bad ones, and that all youths who had true
  • painters' genius forced their way out of obscurity.
  • [20] It will be observed that, in the lecture, it is _assumed_
  • that works of art are national treasures; and that it is
  • desirable to withdraw all the hands capable of painting or
  • carving from other employments, in order that they may
  • produce this kind of wealth. I do not, in assuming this,
  • mean that works of art add to the monetary resources of a
  • nation, or form part of its wealth, in the vulgar sense. The
  • result of the sale of a picture in the country itself is
  • merely that a certain sum of money is transferred from the
  • hands of B. the purchaser, to those of A. the producer; the
  • sum ultimately to be distributed remaining the same, only A.
  • ultimately spending it instead of B., while the labour of A.
  • has been in the meantime withdrawn from productive channels;
  • he has painted a picture which nobody can live upon, or live
  • in, when he might have grown corn or built houses; when the
  • sale therefore is effected in the country itself, it does
  • not add to, but diminishes, the monetary resources of the
  • country, except only so far as it may appear probable, on
  • other grounds, that A. is likely to spend the sum he
  • receives for his picture more rationally and usefully than
  • B. would have spent it. If, indeed, the picture, or other
  • work of art, be sold in foreign countries, either the money
  • or the useful products of the foreign country being imported
  • in exchange for it, such sale adds to the monetary resources
  • of the selling, and diminishes those of the purchasing
  • nation. But sound political economy, strange as it may at
  • first appear to say so, has nothing whatever to do with
  • separations between national interests. Political economy
  • means the management of the affairs of _citizens_; and it
  • either regards exclusively the administration of the affairs
  • of one nation, or the administration of the affairs of the
  • world considered as one nation. So when a transaction
  • between individuals which enriches A., impoverishes B. in
  • precisely the same degree, the sound economist considers it
  • an unproductive transaction between the individuals; and if
  • a trade between two nations which enriches one, impoverishes
  • the other in the same degree, the sound eoonomist considers
  • it an unproductive trade between the nations. It is not a
  • general question of political economy, but only a particular
  • question of local expediency, whether an article in itself
  • valueless, may bear a value of exchange in transactions with
  • some other nation. The economist considers only the actual
  • value of the thing done or produced; and if he sees a
  • quantity of labour spent, for instance, by the Swiss, in
  • producing woodwork for sale to the English, he at once sets
  • the commercial impoverishment of the English purchaser
  • against the commercial enrichment of the Swiss seller; and
  • considers the whole transaction productive only so far as
  • the woodwork itself is a real addition to the wealth of the
  • world. For the arrangement of the laws of a nation so as to
  • procure the greatest advantages to itself, and leave the
  • smallest advantages to other nations, is not a part of the
  • science of political economy, but merely a broad application
  • of the science of fraud. Considered thus in the abstract,
  • pictures are not an _addition_ to the monetary wealth of the
  • world, except in the amount of pleasure or instruction to be
  • got out of them day by day: but there is a certain
  • protective effect on wealth exercised by works of high art
  • which must always be included in the estimate of their
  • value. Generally speaking, persons who decorate their houses
  • with pictures, will not spend so much money in papers,
  • carpets, curtains, or other expensive and perishable
  • luxuries as they would otherwise. Works of good art, like
  • books, exercise a conservative effect on the rooms they are
  • kept in; and the wall of the library or picture gallery
  • remains undisturbed, when those of other rooms are
  • re-papered or re-panelled. Of course, this effect is still
  • more definite when the picture is on the walls themselves,
  • either on canvass stretched into fixed shapes on their
  • panels, or in fresco; involving, of course, the preservation
  • of the building from all unnecessary and capricious
  • alteration. And generally speaking, the occupation of a
  • large number of hands in painting or sculpture in any nation
  • may be considered as tending to check the disposition to
  • indulge in perishable luxury. I do not, however, in my
  • assumption that works of art are treasures, take much into
  • consideration this collateral monetary result. I consider
  • them treasures, merely as permanent means of pleasure and
  • instruction; and having at other times tried to show the
  • several ways in which they can please and teach, assume here
  • that they are thus useful; and that it is desirable to make
  • as many painters as we can.
  • This is not so. It is difficult to analyse the characters of mind
  • which cause youths to mistake their vocation, and to endeavour to
  • become artists, when they have no true artist's gift. But the fact is,
  • that multitudes of young men do this, and that by far the greater
  • number of living artists are men who have mistaken their vocation. The
  • peculiar circumstances of modern life, which exhibit art in almost
  • every form to the sight of the youths in our great cities, have a
  • natural tendency to fill their imaginations with borrowed ideas, and
  • their minds with imperfect science; the mere dislike of mechanical
  • employments, either felt to be irksome, or believed to be degrading,
  • urges numbers of young men to become painters, in the same temper in
  • which they would enlist or go to sea; others, the sons of engravers or
  • artists, taught the business of the art by their parents, and having
  • no gift for it themselves, follow it as the means of livelihood, in an
  • ignoble patience; or, if ambitious, seek to attract regard, or
  • distance rivalry, by fantastic, meretricious, or unprecedented
  • applications of their mechanical skill; while finally, many men
  • earnest in feeling, and conscientious in principle, mistake their
  • desire to be useful for a love of art, and their quickness of emotion
  • for its capacity, and pass their lives in painting moral and
  • instructive pictures, which might almost justify us in thinking nobody
  • could be a painter but a rogue. On the other hand, I believe that much
  • of the best artistical intellect is daily lost in other avocations.
  • Generally, the temper which would make an admirable artist is humble
  • and observant, capable of taking much interest in little things, and
  • of entertaining itself pleasantly in the dullest circumstances.
  • Suppose, added to these characters, a steady conscientiousness which
  • seeks to do its duty wherever it may be placed, and the power, denied
  • to few artistical minds, of ingenious invention in almost any
  • practical department of human skill, and it can hardly be doubted that
  • the very humility and conscientiousness which would have perfected the
  • painter, have in many instances prevented his becoming one; and that
  • in the quiet life of our steady craftsmen--sagacious manufacturers and
  • uncomplaining clerks--there may frequently be concealed more genius
  • than ever is raised to the direction of our public works, or to be the
  • mark of our public praises.
  • It is indeed probable, that intense disposition for art will conquer
  • the most formidable obstacles, if the surrounding circumstances are
  • such as at all to present the idea of such conquest, to the mind; but
  • we have no ground for concluding that Giotto would ever have been more
  • than a shepherd, if Cimabue had not by chance found him drawing; or
  • that among the shepherds of the Apennines there were no other Giottos,
  • undiscovered by Cimabue. We are too much in the habit of considering
  • happy accidents as what are called "special Providences;" and thinking
  • that when any great work needs to be done, the man who is to do it
  • will certainly be pointed out by Providence, be he shepherd or
  • sea-boy; and prepared for his work by all kinds of minor providences,
  • in the best possible way. Whereas all the analogies of God's
  • operations in other matters prove the contrary of this; we find that
  • "of thousand seeds, He often brings but one to bear," often not one;
  • and the one seed which He appoints to bear is allowed to bear crude or
  • perfect fruit according to the dealings of the husbandman with it. And
  • there cannot be a doubt in the mind of any person accustomed to take
  • broad and logical views of the world's history, that its events are
  • ruled by Providence in precisely the same manner as its harvests; that
  • the seeds of good and evil are broadcast among men, just as the seeds
  • of thistles and fruits are; and that according to the force of our
  • industry, and wisdom of our husbandry, the ground will bring forth to
  • us figs or thistles. So that when it seems needed that a certain work
  • should be done for the world, and no man is there to do it, we have no
  • right to say that God did not wish it to be done, and therefore sent
  • no man able to do it. The probability (if I wrote my own convictions,
  • I should say certainty) is, that He sent many men, hundreds of men,
  • able to do it; and that we have rejected them, or crushed them; by our
  • previous folly of conduct or of institution, we have rendered it
  • impossible to distinguish, or impossible to reach them; and when the
  • need for them comes, and we suffer for the want of them, it is not
  • that God refuses to send us deliverers, and specially appoints all our
  • consequent sufferings; but that He has sent, and we have refused, the
  • deliverers; and the pain is then wrought out by His eternal law, as
  • surely as famine is wrought out by eternal law for a nation which
  • will neither plough nor sow. No less are we in error in supposing, as
  • we so frequently do, that if a man be found, he is sure to be in all
  • respects fitted for the work to be done, as the key is to the lock;
  • and that every accident which happened in the forging him, only
  • adapted him more truly to the wards. It is pitiful to hear historians
  • beguiling themselves and their readers, by tracing in the early
  • history of great men, the minor circumstances which fitted them for
  • the work they did, without ever taking notice of the other
  • circumstances which as assuredly unfitted them for it; so concluding
  • that miraculous interposition prepared them in all points for
  • everything and that they did all that could have been desired or hoped
  • for from them: whereas the certainty of the matter is that, throughout
  • their lives, they were thwarted and corrupted by some things as
  • certainly as they were helped and disciplined by others; and that, in
  • the kindliest and most reverent view which can justly be taken of
  • them, they were but poor mistaken creatures, struggling with a world
  • more profoundly mistaken than they;--assuredly sinned against, or
  • sinning in thousands of ways, and bringing out at last a maimed
  • result--not what they might or ought to have done, but all that could
  • be done against the world's resistance, and in spite of their own
  • sorrowful falsehood to themselves.
  • And this being so, it is the practical duty of a wise nation,
  • first to withdraw, as far as may be, its youth from destructive
  • influences;--then to try its material as far as possible, and to lose
  • the use of none that is good. I do not mean by "withdrawing from
  • destructive influences" the keeping of youths out of trials; but the
  • keeping them out of the way of things purely and absolutely
  • mischievous. I do not mean that we should shade our green corn in all
  • heat, and shelter it in all frost, but only that we should dyke out
  • the inundation from it, and drive the fowls away from it. Let your
  • youth labour and suffer; but do not let it starve, nor steal, nor
  • blaspheme.
  • It is not, of course, in my power here to enter into details of
  • schemes of education; and it will be long before the results of
  • experiments now in progress will give data for the solution of the
  • most difficult questions connected with the subject, of which the
  • principal one is the mode in which the chance of advancement in life
  • is to be extended to all, and yet made compatible with contentment in
  • the pursuit of lower avocations by those whose abilities do not
  • qualify them for the higher. But the general principle of trial
  • schools lies at the root of the matter--of schools, that is to say, in
  • which the knowledge offered and discipline enforced shall be all a
  • part of a great assay of the human soul, and in which the one shall be
  • increased, the other directed, as the tried heart and brain will best
  • bear, and no otherwise. One thing, however, I must say, that in this
  • trial I believe all emulation to be a false motive, and all giving of
  • prizes a false means. All that you can depend upon in a boy, as
  • significative of true power, likely to issue in good fruit, is his
  • will to work for the work's sake, not his desire to surpass his
  • schoolfellows; and the aim of the teaching you give him ought to be,
  • to prove to him and strengthen in him his own separate gift, not to
  • puff him into swollen rivalry with those who are everlastingly greater
  • than he: still less ought you to hang favours and ribands about the
  • neck of the creature who is the greatest, to make the rest envy him.
  • Try to make them love him and follow him, not struggle with him.
  • There must, of course, be examination to ascertain and attest both
  • progress and relative capacity; but our aim should be to make the
  • students rather look upon it as a means of ascertaining their own true
  • positions and powers in the world, than as an arena in which to carry
  • away a present victory. I have not, perhaps, in the course of the
  • lecture, insisted enough on the nature of relative capacity and
  • individual character, as the roots of all real _value_ in Art. We are
  • too much in the habit, in these days, of acting as if Art worth a
  • price in the market were a commodity which people could be generally
  • taught to produce, and as if the _education_ of the artist, not his
  • _capacity_, gave the sterling value to his work. No impression can
  • possibly be more absurd or false. Whatever people can teach each other
  • to do, they will estimate, and ought to estimate, only as common
  • industry; nothing will ever fetch a high price but precisely that
  • which cannot be taught, and which nobody can do but the man from whom
  • it is purchased. No state of society, nor stage of knowledge, ever
  • does away with the natural pre-eminence of one man over another; and
  • it is that pre-eminence, and that only, which will give work high
  • value in the market, or which ought to do so. It is a bad sign of the
  • judgment, and bad omen for the progress, of a nation, if it supposes
  • itself to possess many artists of equal merit. Noble art is nothing
  • less than the expression of a great soul; and great souls are not
  • common things. If ever we confound their work with that of others, it
  • is not through liberality, but through blindness.
  • Note 4th, p. 24.--"_Public favour._"
  • There is great difficulty in making any short or general statement of
  • the difference between great and ignoble minds in their behaviour to
  • the "public." It is by no means _universally_ the case that a mean
  • mind, as stated in the text, will bend itself to what you ask of it:
  • on the contrary, there is one kind of mind, the meanest of all, which
  • perpetually complains of the public, contemplates and proclaims itself
  • as a "genius," refuses all wholesome discipline or humble office, and
  • ends in miserable and revengeful ruin; also, the greatest minds are
  • marked by nothing more distinctly than an inconceivable humility, and
  • acceptance of work or instruction in any form, and from any quarter.
  • They will learn from everybody, and do anything that anybody asks of
  • them, so long as it involves only toil, or what other men would think
  • degradation. But the point of quarrel, nevertheless, assuredly rises
  • some day between the public and them, respecting some matter, not of
  • humiliation, but of Fact. Your great man always at last comes to see
  • something the public don't see. This something he will assuredly
  • persist in asserting, whether with tongue or pencil, to be as _he_
  • sees it, not as _they_ see it; and all the world in a heap on the
  • other side will not get him to say otherwise. Then, if the world
  • objects to the saying, he may happen to get stoned or burnt for it,
  • but that does not in the least matter to him; if the world has no
  • particular objection to the saying, he may get leave to mutter it to
  • himself till he dies, and be merely taken for an idiot; that also
  • does not matter to him--mutter it he will, according to what he
  • perceives to be fact, and not at all according to the roaring of the
  • walls of Red sea on the right hand or left of him. Hence the quarrel,
  • sure at some time or other to be started between the public and him;
  • while your mean man, though he will spit and scratch spiritedly at the
  • public, while it does not attend to him, will bow to it for its clap
  • in any direction, and say anything when he has got its ear, which he
  • thinks will bring him another clap; and thus, as stated in the text,
  • he and it go on smoothly together.
  • There are, however, times when the obstinacy of the mean man looks
  • very like the obstinacy of the great one; but if you look closely into
  • the matter, you will always see that the obstinacy of the first is in
  • the pronunciation of "I;" and of the second, in the pronunciation of
  • "It."
  • Note 5th, p. 38.--"_Invention of new wants._"
  • It would have been impossible for political economists long to have
  • endured the error spoken of in the text,[21] had they not been
  • confused by an idea, in part well founded, that the energies and
  • refinements, as well as the riches of civilized life arose from
  • imaginary wants. It is quite true, that the savage who knows no needs
  • but those of food, shelter, and sleep, and after he has snared his
  • venison and patched the rents of his hut, passes the rest of his time
  • in animal repose, is in a lower state than the man who labours
  • incessantly that he may procure for himself the luxuries of
  • civilization; and true also, that the difference between one and
  • another nation in progressive power depends in great part on vain
  • desires; but these idle motives are merely to be considered as giving
  • exercise to the national body and mind; they are not sources of
  • wealth, except so far as they give the habits of industry and
  • acquisitiveness. If a boy is clumsy and lazy, we shall do good if we
  • can persuade him to carve cherrystones and fly kites; and this use of
  • his fingers and limbs may eventually be the cause of his becoming a
  • wealthy and happy man; but we must not therefore argue that
  • cherrystones are valuable property, or that kite-flying is a
  • profitable mode of passing time. In like manner, a nation always
  • wastes its time and labour _directly_, when it invents a new want of a
  • frivolous kind, and yet the invention of such a want may be the sign
  • of a healthy activity, and the labour undergone to satisfy the new
  • want may lead, _indirectly_, to useful discoveries or to noble arts;
  • so that a nation is not to be discouraged in its fancies when it is
  • either too weak or foolish to be moved to exertion by anything but
  • fancies, or has attended to its serious business first. If a nation
  • will not forge iron, but likes distilling lavender, by all means give
  • it lavender to distil; only do not let its economists suppose that
  • lavender is as profitable to it as oats, or that it helps poor people
  • to live, any more than the schoolboy's kite provides him his dinner.
  • Luxuries, whether national or personal, must be paid for by labour
  • withdrawn from useful things; and no nation has a right to indulge in
  • them until all its poor are comfortably housed and fed.
  • [21] I have given the political economists too much credit in
  • saying this. Actually, while these sheets are passing
  • through the press, the blunt, broad, unmitigated fallacy is
  • enunciated, formally and precisely, by the Common Councilmen
  • of New York, in their report on the present commercial
  • crisis. Here is their collective opinion, published in the
  • _Times_ of November 23rd, 1857:--"Another erroneous idea is
  • that luxurious living, extravagant dressing, splendid
  • turn-outs and fine houses, are the cause of distress to a
  • nation. No more erroneous impression could exist. Every
  • extravagance that the man of 100,000 or 1,000,000 dollars
  • indulges in adds to the means, the support, the wealth of
  • ten or a hundred who had little or nothing else but their
  • labour, their intellect, or their taste. If a man of
  • 1,000,000 dollars spends principal and interest in ten
  • years, and finds himself beggared at the end of that time,
  • he has actually made a hundred who have catered to his
  • extravagance, employers or employed, so much richer by the
  • division of his wealth. He may be ruined, but the nation is
  • better off and richer, for one hundred minds and hands, with
  • 10,000 dollars apiece, are far more productive than one with
  • the whole."
  • Yes, gentlemen of the Common Council! but what has been
  • doing in the time of the transfer? The spending of the
  • fortune has taken a certain number of years (suppose ten),
  • and during that time 1,000,000 dollars' worth of work has
  • been done by the people, who have been paid that sum for it.
  • Where is the product of that work? By your own statement,
  • wholly consumed; for the man for whom it has been done is
  • now a beggar. You have given, therefore, as a nation,
  • 1,000,000 dollars' worth of work, and ten years of time, and
  • you have produced, as ultimate result, one beggar! Excellent
  • economy, gentlemen! and sure to conduce, in due sequence, to
  • the production of _more_ than one beggar. Perhaps the matter
  • may be made clearer to you, however, by a more familiar
  • instance. If a schoolboy goes out in the morning with five
  • shillings in his pocket, and comes home at night penniless,
  • having spent his all in tarts; principal and interest are
  • gone, and fruiterer and baker are enriched. So far so good.
  • But suppose the schoolboy, instead, has bought a book and a
  • knife; principal and interest are gone, and bookseller and
  • cutler are enriched. But the schoolboy is enriched also, and
  • may help his schoolfellows next day with knife and book,
  • instead of lying in bed and incurring a debt to the doctor.
  • The enervating influence of luxury, and its tendencies to increase
  • vice, are points which I keep entirely out of consideration in the
  • present essay; but, so far as they bear on any question discussed,
  • they merely furnish additional evidence on the side which I have
  • taken. Thus, in the present case, I assume that the luxuries of
  • civilized life are in possession harmless, and in acquirement,
  • serviceable as a motive for exertion; and even on these favourable
  • terms, we arrive at the conclusion that the nation ought not to
  • indulge in them except under severe limitations. Much less ought it to
  • indulge in them if the temptation consequent on their possession, or
  • fatality incident to their manufacture, more than counterbalances the
  • good done by the effort to obtain them.
  • Note 6th, p. 48.--"_Economy of Literature._"
  • I have been much impressed lately by one of the results of the
  • quantity of our books; namely, the stern impossibility of getting
  • anything understood, that required patience to understand. I observe
  • always, in the case of my own writings, that if ever I state anything
  • which has cost me any trouble to ascertain, and which, therefore, will
  • probably require a minute or two of reflection from the reader before
  • it can be accepted,--that statement will not only be misunderstood,
  • but in all probability taken to mean something very nearly the reverse
  • of what it does mean. Now, whatever faults there may be in my modes of
  • expression, I know that the words I use will always be found, by
  • Johnson's dictionary, to bear, first of all, the sense I use them in;
  • and that the sentences, whether awkwardly turned or not, will, by the
  • ordinary rules of grammar, bear no other interpretation than that I
  • mean them to bear; so that the misunderstanding of them must result,
  • ultimately, from the mere fact that their matter sometimes requires a
  • little patience. And I see the same kind of misinterpretation put on
  • the words of other writers, whenever they require the same kind of
  • thought.
  • I was at first a little despondent about this; but, on the whole, I
  • believe it will have a good effect upon our literature for some time
  • to come; and then, perhaps, the public may recover its patience again.
  • For certainly it is excellent discipline for an author to feel that he
  • must say all he has to say in the fewest possible words, or his reader
  • is sure to skip them; and in the plainest possible words, or his
  • reader will certainly misunderstand them. Generally, also, a downright
  • fact may be told in a plain way; and we want downright facts at
  • present more than any thing else. And though I often hear moral people
  • complaining of the bad effects of want of thought, for my part, it
  • seems to me that one of the worst diseases to which the human creature
  • is liable is its disease of thinking. If it would only just _look_[22]
  • at a thing instead of thinking what it must be like, or _do_ a thing,
  • instead of thinking it cannot be done, we should all get on far
  • better.
  • [22] There can be no question, however, of the mischievous
  • tendency of the hurry of the present day, in the way people
  • undertake this very _looking_. I gave three years' close and
  • incessant labour to the examination of the chronology of the
  • architecture of Venice; two long winters being wholly spent
  • in the drawing of details on the spot: and yet I see
  • constantly that architects who pass three or four days in a
  • gondola going up and down the Grand Canal, think that their
  • first impressions are just as likely to be true as my
  • patiently wrought conclusions. Mr. Street, for instance,
  • glances hastily at the façade of the Ducal Palace--so hastily
  • that he does not even see what its pattern is, and misses the
  • alternation of red and black in the centres of its
  • squares--and yet he instantly ventures on an opinion on the
  • chronology of its capitals, which is one of the most
  • complicated and difficult subjects in the whole range of
  • Gothic archæology. It may, nevertheless, be ascertained with
  • very fair probability of correctness by any person who will
  • give a month's hard work to it, but it can be ascertained no
  • otherwise.
  • Note 7th, p. 84.--"_Pilots of the State._"
  • While, however, undoubtedly, these responsibilities attach to every
  • person possessed of wealth, it is necessary both to avoid any
  • stringency of statement respecting the benevolent modes of spending
  • money, and to admit and approve so much liberty of spending it for
  • selfish pleasures as may distinctly make wealth a personal _reward_
  • for toil, and secure in the minds of all men the right of property.
  • For although, without doubt, the purest pleasures it can procure are
  • not selfish, it is only as a means of personal gratification that it
  • will be desired by a large majority of workers; and it would be no
  • less false ethics than false policy to check their energy by any forms
  • of public opinion which bore hardly against the wanton expenditure of
  • honestly got wealth. It would be hard if a man who had passed the
  • greater part of his life at the desk or counter could not at last
  • innocently gratify a caprice; and all the best and most sacred ends of
  • almsgiving would be at once disappointed, if the idea of a moral claim
  • took the place of affectionate gratitude in the mind of the receiver.
  • Some distinction is made by us naturally in this respect between
  • earned and inherited wealth; that which is inherited appearing to
  • involve the most definite responsibilities, especially when consisting
  • in revenues derived from the soil. The form of taxation which
  • constitutes rental of lands places annually a certain portion of the
  • national wealth in the hands of the nobles, or other proprietors of
  • the soil, under conditions peculiarly calculated to induce them to
  • give their best care to its efficient administration. The want of
  • instruction in even the simplest principles of commerce and economy,
  • which hitherto has disgraced our schools and universities, has indeed
  • been the cause of ruin or total inutility of life to multitudes of our
  • men of estate; but this deficiency in our public education cannot
  • exist much longer, and it appears to be highly advantageous for the
  • State that a certain number of persons distinguished by race should be
  • permitted to set examples of wise expenditure, whether in the
  • advancement of science, or in patronage of art and literature; only
  • they must see to it that they take their right standing more firmly
  • than they have done hitherto, for the position of a rich man in
  • relation to those around him is, in our present real life, and is also
  • contemplated generally by political economists as being, precisely the
  • reverse of what it ought to be. A rich man ought to be continually
  • examining how he may spend his money for the advantage of others: at
  • present, others are continually plotting how they may beguile him into
  • spending it apparently for his own. The aspect which he presents to
  • the eyes of the world is generally that of a person holding a bag of
  • money with a staunch grasp, and resolved to part with none of it
  • unless he is forced, and all the people about him are plotting how
  • they may force him; that is to say, how they may persuade him that he
  • wants this thing or that; or how they may produce things that he will
  • covet and buy. One man tries to persuade him that he wants perfumes;
  • another that he wants jewellery; another that he wants sugarplums;
  • another that he wants roses at Christmas. Anybody who can invent a new
  • want for him is supposed to be a benefactor to society: and thus the
  • energies of the poorer people about him are continually directed to
  • the production of covetable, instead of serviceable things; and the
  • rich man has the general aspect of a fool, plotted against by all the
  • world. Whereas the real aspect which he ought to have is that of a
  • person wiser than others, entrusted with the management of a larger
  • quantity of capital, which he administers for the profit of all,
  • directing each man to the labour which is most healthy for him, and
  • most serviceable for the community.
  • Note 8th, p. 84.--"_Silk and Purple._"
  • In various places throughout these lectures I have had to allude to
  • the distinction between productive and unproductive labour, and
  • between true and false wealth. I shall here endeavour, as clearly as I
  • can, to explain the distinction I mean.
  • Property may be divided generally into two kinds; that which produces
  • life, and that which produces the objects of life. That which produces
  • or maintains life consists of food, in so far as it is nourishing; of
  • furniture and clothing, in so far as they are protective or
  • cherishing; of fuel; and of all land, instruments, or materials,
  • necessary to produce food, houses, clothes and fuel. It is specially
  • and rightly called useful property.
  • The property which produces the objects of life consists of all that
  • gives pleasure or suggests and preserves thought: of food, furniture,
  • and land, in so far as they are pleasing to the appetite or the eye,
  • of luxurious dress; and all other kinds of luxuries; of books,
  • pictures, and architecture. But the modes of connection of certain
  • minor forms of property with human labour render it desirable to
  • arrange them under more than these two heads. Property may therefore
  • be conveniently considered as of five kinds.
  • 1st. Property necessary to life, but not producible by labour, and
  • therefore belonging of right, in a due measure, to every human being
  • as soon as he is born, and morally unalienable. As, for instance, his
  • proper share of the atmosphere, without which he cannot breathe, and
  • of water, which he needs to quench his thirst. As much land as he
  • needs to feed from is also inalienable; but in well regulated
  • communities this quantity of land may often be represented by other
  • possessions, or its need supplied by wages and privileges.
  • 2. Property necessary to life, but only producible by labour, and of
  • which the possession is morally connected with labour, so that no
  • person capable of doing the work necessary for its production has a
  • right to it until he has done that work:--"he that will not work,
  • neither should he eat." It consists of simple food, clothing, and
  • habitation, with their seeds and materials, or instruments and
  • machinery, and animals used for necessary draught or locomotion, etc.
  • It is to be observed of this kind of property, that its increase
  • cannot usually be carried beyond a certain point, because it depends
  • not on labour only, but on things of which the supply is limited by
  • nature. The possible accumulation of corn depends on the quantity of
  • corn-growing land possessed or commercially accessible; and that of
  • steel, similarly, on the accessible quantity of coal and ironstone. It
  • follows from this natural limitation of supply that the accumulation
  • of property of this kind in large masses at one point, or in one
  • person's hands, commonly involves, more or less, the scarcity of it at
  • another point and in other persons' hands; so that the accidents or
  • energies which may enable one man to procure a great deal of it, may,
  • and in all likelihood will partially prevent other men procuring a
  • sufficiency of it, however willing they may be to work for it;
  • therefore, the modes of its accumulation and distribution need to be
  • in some degree regulated by law and by national treaties, in order to
  • secure justice to all men.
  • Another point requiring notice respecting this sort of property is,
  • that no work can be wasted in producing it, provided only the kind of
  • it produced be preservable and distributable, since for every grain of
  • such commodities we produce we are rendering so much more life
  • possible on earth.[23] But though we are sure, thus, that we are
  • employing people well, we cannot be sure we might not have employed
  • them _better_; for it is possible to direct labour to the production
  • of life, until little or none is left for that of the objects of life,
  • and thus to increase population at the expense of civilization,
  • learning, and morality: on the other hand, it is just as possible--and
  • the error is one to which the world is, on the whole, more liable--to
  • direct labour to the objects of life till too little is left for life,
  • and thus to increase luxury or learning at the expense of population.
  • Right political economy holds its aim poised justly between the two
  • extremes, desiring neither to crowd its dominions with a race of
  • savages, nor to found courts and colleges in the midst of a desert.
  • [23] This point has sometimes been disputed; for instance,
  • opening Mill's "Political Economy" the other day, I chanced
  • on a passage in which he says that a man who makes a coat,
  • if the person who wears the coat does nothing useful while
  • he wears it, has done no more good to society than the man
  • who has only raised a pineapple. But this is a fallacy
  • induced by endeavour after too much subtlety. None of us
  • have a right to say that the life of a man is of no use to
  • _him_, though it may be of no use to _us_; and the man who
  • made the coat, and thereby prolonged another man's life, has
  • done a gracious and useful work, whatever may come of the
  • life so prolonged. We may say to the wearer of the coat,
  • "You who are wearing coats, and doing nothing in them, are
  • at present wasting your own life and other people's;" but we
  • have no right to say that his existence, however wasted, is
  • wasted _away_. It may be just dragging itself on, in its
  • thin golden line, with nothing dependent upon it, to the
  • point where it is to strengthen into good chain cable, and
  • have thousands of other lives dependent on it. Meantime, the
  • simple fact respecting the coat-maker is, that he has given
  • so much life to the creature, the results of which he cannot
  • calculate; they may be--in all probability will be--infinite
  • results in some way. But the raiser of pines, who has only
  • given a pleasant taste in the mouth to some one, may see
  • with tolerable clearness to the end of the taste in the
  • mouth, and of all conceivable results therefrom.
  • 3. The third kind of property is that which conduces to bodily
  • pleasures and conveniences, without directly tending to sustain life;
  • perhaps sometimes indirectly tending to destroy it. All dainty (as
  • distinguished from nourishing) food, and means of producing it; all
  • scents not needed for health; substances valued only for their
  • appearance and rarity (as gold and jewels); flowers of difficult
  • culture; animals used for delight (as horses for racing), and such
  • like, form property of this class; to which the term "luxury, or
  • luxuries," ought exclusively to belong.
  • Respecting which we have to note first, that all such property is of
  • doubtful advantage even to its possessor. Furniture tempting to
  • indolence, sweet odours, and luscious food, are more or less injurious
  • to health: while jewels, liveries, and other such common belongings of
  • wealthy people, certainly convey no pleasure to their owners
  • proportionate to their cost.
  • Farther, such property, for the most part, perishes in the using.
  • Jewels form a great exception--but rich food, fine dresses, horses and
  • carriages, are consumed by the owner's use. It ought much oftener to
  • be brought to the notice of rich men what sums of interest of money
  • they are paying towards the close of their lives, for luxuries
  • consumed in the middle of them. It would be very interesting, for
  • instance, to know the exact sum which the money spent in London for
  • ices, at its desserts and balls, during the last twenty years, had it
  • been saved and put out at compound interest, would at this moment have
  • furnished for useful purposes.
  • Also, in most cases, the enjoyment of such property is wholly selfish,
  • and limited to its possessor. Splendid dress and equipage, however,
  • when so arranged as to produce real beauty of effect, may often be
  • rather a generous than a selfish channel of expenditure. They will,
  • however, necessarily in such case involve some of the arts of design;
  • and therefore take their place in a higher category than that of
  • luxuries merely.
  • 4. The fourth kind of property is that which bestows intellectual or
  • emotional pleasure, consisting of land set apart for purposes of
  • delight more than for agriculture, of books, works of art, and objects
  • of natural history.
  • It is, of course, impossible to fix an accurate limit between property
  • of the last class and of this class, since things which are a mere
  • luxury to one person are a means of intellectual occupation to
  • another. Flowers in a London ball-room are a luxury; in a botanical
  • garden, a delight of the intellect; and in their native fields, both;
  • while the most noble works of art are continually made material of
  • vulgar luxury or of criminal pride; but, when rightly used, property
  • of this fourth class is the only kind which deserves the name of
  • _real_ property; it is the only kind which a man can truly be said to
  • "possess." What a man eats, or drinks, or wears, so long as it is only
  • what is needful for life, can no more be thought of as his possession
  • than the air he breathes. The air is as needful to him as the food;
  • but we do not talk of a man's wealth of air; and what food or clothing
  • a man possesses more than he himself requires, must be for others to
  • use (and, to him, therefore, not a real property in itself, but only a
  • means of obtaining some real property in exchange for it). Whereas the
  • things that give intellectual or emotional enjoyment may be
  • accumulated and do not perish in using; but continually supply new
  • pleasures and new powers of giving pleasures to others. And these,
  • therefore, are the only things which can rightly be thought of as
  • giving "wealth" or "well being." Food conduces only to "being," but
  • these to "_well_ being." And there is not any broader general
  • distinction between lower and higher orders of men than rests on their
  • possession of this real property. The human race may be properly
  • divided by zoologists into "men who have gardens, libraries, or works
  • of art; and who have none;" and the former class will include all
  • noble persons, except only a few who make the world their garden or
  • museum; while the people who have not, or, which is the same thing, do
  • not care for gardens or libraries, but care for nothing but money or
  • luxuries, will include none but ignoble persons: only it is necessary
  • to understand that I mean by the term "garden" as much the
  • Carthusian's plot of ground fifteen feet square between his monastery
  • buttresses, as I do the grounds of Chatsworth or Kew; and I mean by
  • the term "art" as much the old sailor's print of the Arethusa bearing
  • up to engage the Belle Poule, as I do Raphael's "Disputa," and even
  • rather more; for when abundant, beautiful possessions of this kind are
  • almost always associated with vulgar luxury, and become then anything
  • but indicative of noble character in their possessors. The ideal of
  • human life is a union of Spartan simplicity of manners with Athenian
  • sensibility and imagination, but in actual results, we are continually
  • mistaking ignorance for simplicity, and sensuality for refinement.
  • 5. The fifth kind of property is representative property, consisting
  • of documents or money, or rather documents only, for money itself is
  • only a transferable document, current among societies of men, giving
  • claim, at sight, to some definite benefit or advantage, most commonly
  • to a certain share of real property existing in those societies. The
  • money is only genuine when the property it gives claim to is real, or
  • the advantages it gives claim to certain; otherwise, it is false
  • money, and may be considered as much "forged" when issued by a
  • government, or a bank, as when by an individual. Thus, if a dozen of
  • men, cast ashore on a desert island, pick up a number of stones, put a
  • red spot on each stone, and pass a law that every stone marked with a
  • red spot shall give claim to a peck of wheat;--so long as no wheat
  • exists, or can exist, on the island, the stones are not money. But the
  • moment as much wheat exists as shall render it possible for the
  • society always to give a peck for every spotted stone, the spotted
  • stones would become money, and might be exchanged by their possessors
  • for whatever other commodities they chose, to the value of the peck of
  • wheat which the stones represented. If more stones were issued than
  • the quantity of wheat could answer the demand of, the value of the
  • stone coinage would be depreciated, in proportion to its increase
  • above the quantity needed to answer it.
  • Again, supposing a certain number of the men so cast ashore were set
  • aside by lot, or any other convention, to do the rougher labour
  • necessary for the whole society, they themselves being maintained by
  • the daily allotment of a certain quantity of food, clothing, etc.
  • Then, if it were agreed that the stones spotted with red should be
  • signs of a Government order for the labour of these men; and that any
  • person presenting a spotted stone at the office of the labourers,
  • should be entitled to a man's work for a week or a day, the red stones
  • would be money; and might--probably would--immediately pass current in
  • the island for as much food, or clothing, or iron, or any other
  • article as a man's work for the period secured by the stone was worth.
  • But if the Government issued so many spotted stones that it was
  • impossible for the body of men they employed to comply with the
  • orders; as, suppose, if they only employed twelve men, and issued
  • eighteen spotted stones daily, ordering a day's work each, then the
  • six extra stones would be forged or false money; and the effect of
  • this forgery would be the depreciation of the value of the whole
  • coinage by one-third, that being the period of shortcoming which
  • would, on the average, necessarily ensue in the execution of each
  • order. Much occasional work may be done in a state or society, by help
  • of an issue of false money (or false promises) by way of stimulants;
  • and the fruit of this work, if it comes into the promiser's hands, may
  • sometimes enable the false promises at last to be fulfilled: hence the
  • frequent issue of false money by governments and banks, and the not
  • unfrequent escapes from the natural and proper consequences of such
  • false issues, so as to cause a confused conception in most people's
  • minds of what money really is. I am not sure whether some quantity of
  • such false issue may not really be permissible in a nation, accurately
  • proportioned to the minimum average produce of the labour it excites;
  • but all such procedures are more or less unsound; and the notion of
  • unlimited issue of currency is simply one of the absurdest and most
  • monstrous that ever came into disjointed human wits.
  • The use of objects of real or supposed value for currency, as gold,
  • jewellery, etc., is barbarous; and it always expresses either the
  • measure of the distrust in the society of its own government, or the
  • proportion of distrustful or barbarous nations with whom it has to
  • deal. A metal not easily corroded or imitated, is a desirable medium
  • of currency for the sake of cleanliness and convenience, but were it
  • possible to prevent forgery, the more worthless the metal itself, the
  • better. The use of worthless media, unrestrained by the use of
  • valuable media, has always hitherto involved, and is therefore
  • supposed to involve necessarily, unlimited, or at least improperly
  • extended, issue; but we might as well suppose that a man must
  • necessarily issue unlimited promises because his words cost nothing.
  • Intercourse with foreign nations must, indeed, for ages yet to come,
  • at the world's present rate of progress, be carried on by valuable
  • currencies; but such transactions are nothing more than forms of
  • barter. The gold used at present as a currency is not, in point of
  • fact, currency at all, but the real property[24] which the currency
  • gives claim to, stamped to measure its quantity, and mingling with the
  • real currency occasionally by barter.
  • [24] Or rather, equivalent, to such real property, because
  • everybody has been accustomed to look upon it as valuable:
  • and therefore everybody is willing to give labour or goods
  • for it. But real property does ultimately consist only in
  • things that nourish body or mind; gold would be useless to
  • us if we could not get mutton or books for it. Ultimately
  • all commercial mistakes and embarrassments result from
  • people expecting to get goods without working for them, or
  • wasting them after they have got them. A nation which
  • labours, and takes care of the fruits of labour, would be
  • rich and happy; though there were no gold in the universe. A
  • nation which is idle, and wastes the produce of what work it
  • does, would be poor and miserable, though all its mountains
  • were of gold, and had glens filled with diamonds instead of
  • glacier.
  • The evils necessarily resulting from the use of baseless currencies
  • have been terribly illustrated while these sheets have been passing
  • through the press; I have not had time to examine the various
  • conditions of dishonest or absurd trading which have led to the late
  • "panic" in America and England; this only I know, that no merchant
  • deserving the name ought to be more liable to "panic" than a soldier
  • should; for his name should never be on more paper than he can at any
  • instant meet the call of, happen what will. I do not say this without
  • feeling at the same time how difficult it is to mark, in existing
  • commerce, the just limits between the spirit of enterprise and of
  • speculation. Something of the same temper which makes the English
  • soldier do always all that is possible, and attempt more than is
  • possible, joins its influence with that of mere avarice in tempting
  • the English merchant into risks which he cannot justify, and efforts
  • which he cannot sustain; and the same passion for adventure which our
  • travellers gratify every summer on perilous snow wreaths, and
  • cloud-encompassed precipices, surrounds with a romantic fascination
  • the glittering of a hollow investment, and gilds the clouds that curl
  • round gulfs of ruin. Nay, a higher and a more serious feeling
  • frequently mingles in the motley temptation; and men apply themselves
  • to the task of growing rich, as to a labour of providential
  • appointment, from which they cannot pause without culpability, nor
  • retire without dishonour. Our large trading cities bear to me very
  • nearly the aspect of monastic establishments in which the roar of the
  • mill-wheel and the crane takes the place of other devotional music;
  • and in which the worship of Mammon or Moloch is conducted with a
  • tender reverence and an exact propriety; the merchant rising to his
  • Mammon matins with the self-denial of an anchorite, and expiating the
  • frivolities into which he may be beguiled, in the course of the day by
  • late attendance at Mammon vespers. But, with every allowance that can
  • be made for these conscientious and romantic persons, the fact remains
  • the same, that by far the greater number of the transactions which
  • lead to these times of commercial embarrassment may be ranged simply
  • under two great heads,--gambling and stealing; and both of these in
  • their most culpable form, namely, gambling with money which is not
  • ours, and stealing from those who trust us. I have sometimes thought a
  • day might come, when the nation would perceive that a well-educated
  • man who steals a hundred thousand pounds, involving the entire means
  • of subsistence of a hundred families, deserves, on the whole, as
  • severe a punishment as an ill-educated man who steals a purse from a
  • pocket, or a mug from a pantry. But without hoping for this excess of
  • clearsightedness, we may at least labour for a system of greater
  • honesty and kindness in the minor commerce of our daily life; since
  • the great dishonesty of the great buyers and sellers is nothing more
  • than the natural growth and outcome from the little dishonesty of the
  • little buyers and sellers. Every person who tries to buy an article
  • for less than its proper value, or who tries to sell it at more than
  • its proper value--every consumer who keeps a tradesman waiting for his
  • money, and every tradesman who bribes a consumer to extravagance by
  • credit, is helping forward, according to his own measure of power, a
  • system of baseless and dishonourable commerce, and forcing his country
  • down into poverty and shame. And people of moderate means and average
  • powers of mind would do far more real good by merely carrying out
  • stern principles of justice and honesty in common matters of trade,
  • than by the most ingenious schemes of extended philanthropy, or
  • vociferous declarations of theological doctrine. There are three
  • weighty matters of the law--justice, mercy, and truth; and of these
  • the Teacher puts truth last, because that cannot be known but by a
  • course of acts of justice and love. But men put, in all their efforts,
  • truth first, because they mean by it their own opinions; and thus,
  • while the world has many people who would suffer martyrdom in the
  • cause of what they call truth, it has few who will suffer even a
  • little inconvenience, in that of justice and mercy.
  • UNTO THIS LAST:
  • FOUR ESSAYS ON THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY.
  • "FRIEND, I DO THEE NO WRONG. DID'ST NOT THOU AGREE WITH ME
  • FOR A PENNY? TAKE THAT THINE IS, AND GO THY WAY. I WILL GIVE
  • UNTO THIS LAST EVEN AS UNTO THEE."
  • "IF YE THINK GOOD, GIVE ME MY PRICE; AND IF NOT, FORBEAR. SO
  • THEY WEIGHED FOR MY PRICE THIRTY PIECES OF SILVER."
  • PREFACE.
  • The four following essays were published eighteen months ago in the
  • _Cornhill Magazine_, and were reprobated in a violent manner, as far
  • as I could hear, by most of the readers they met with.
  • Not a whit the less, I believe them to be the best, that is to say,
  • the truest, rightest-worded, and most serviceable things I have ever
  • written; and the last of them, having had especial pains spent on it,
  • is probably the best I shall ever write.
  • "This," the reader may reply, "it might be, yet not therefore well
  • written." Which, in no mock humility, admitting, I yet rest satisfied
  • with the work, though with nothing else that I have done; and
  • purposing shortly to follow out the subjects opened in these papers,
  • as I may find leisure, I wish the introductory statements to be within
  • the reach of any one who may care to refer to them. So I republish the
  • essays as they appeared. One word only is changed, correcting the
  • estimate of a weight; and no word is added.
  • Although, however, I find nothing to modify in these papers, it is a
  • matter of regret to me that the most startling of all the statements
  • in them--that respecting the necessity of the organization of labour,
  • with fixed wages,--should have found its way into the first essay; it
  • being quite one of the least important, though by no means the least
  • certain, of the positions to be defended. The real gist of these
  • papers, their central meaning and aim, is to give, as I believe for
  • the first time in plain English--it has often been incidentally given
  • in good Greek by Plato and Xenophon, and good Latin by Cicero and
  • Horace,--a logical definition of WEALTH: such definition being
  • absolutely needed for a basis of economical science. The most reputed
  • essay on that subject which has appeared in modern times, after
  • opening with the statement that "writers on political economy
  • profess to teach, or to investigate,[25] the nature of wealth," thus
  • follows up the declaration of its thesis--"Every one has a notion,
  • sufficiently correct for common purposes, of what is meant by
  • wealth." ... "It is no part of the design of this treatise to aim
  • at metaphysical nicety of definition."[26]
  • [25] Which? for where investigation is necessary, teaching is
  • impossible.
  • [26] "Principles of Political Economy." By J. S. Mill.
  • Preliminary remarks, p. 2.
  • Metaphysical nicety, we assuredly do not need; but physical nicety,
  • and logical accuracy, with respect to a physical subject, we as
  • assuredly do.
  • Suppose the subject of inquiry, instead of being House-law
  • (_Oikonomia_), had been Star-law (_Astronomia_), and that, ignoring
  • distinction between stars fixed and wandering, as here between wealth
  • radiant and wealth reflective, the writer had begun thus: "Every one
  • has a notion, sufficiently correct for common purposes, of what is
  • meant by stars. Metaphysical nicety in the definition of a star is not
  • the object of this treatise;"--the essay so opened might yet have been
  • far more true in its final statements, and a thousand-fold more
  • serviceable to the navigator, than any treatise on wealth, which
  • founds its conclusions on the popular conception of wealth, can ever
  • become to the economist.
  • * * * * *
  • It was, therefore, the first object of these following papers to give
  • an accurate and stable definition of wealth. Their second object was
  • to show that the acquisition of wealth was finally possible only under
  • certain moral conditions of society, of which quite the first was a
  • belief in the existence and even, for practical purposes, in the
  • attainability of honesty.
  • Without venturing to pronounce--since on such a matter human judgment
  • is by no means conclusive--what is, or is not, the noblest of God's
  • works, we may yet admit so much of Pope's assertion as that an honest
  • man is among His best works presently visible, and, as things stand, a
  • somewhat rare one; but not an incredible or miraculous work; still
  • less an abnormal one. Honesty is not a disturbing force, which
  • deranges the orbits of economy; but a consistent and commanding force,
  • by obedience to which--and by no other obedience--those orbits can
  • continue clear of chaos.
  • It is true, I have sometimes heard Pope condemned for the lowness,
  • instead of the height, of his standard:--"Honesty is indeed a
  • respectable virtue; but how much higher may men attain! Shall nothing
  • more be asked of us than that we be honest?"
  • For the present, good friends, nothing. It seems that in our
  • aspirations to be more than that, we have to some extent lost sight of
  • the propriety of being so much as that. What else we may have lost
  • faith in, there shall be here no question; but assuredly we have lost
  • faith in common honesty, and in the working power of it. And this
  • faith, with the facts on which it may rest, it is quite our first
  • business to recover and keep: not only believing, but even by
  • experience assuring ourselves, that there are yet in the world men who
  • can be restrained from fraud otherwise than by the fear of losing
  • employment;[27] nay that it is even accurately in proportion to the
  • number of such men in any State, that the said State does or can
  • prolong its existence.
  • [27] "The effectual discipline which is exercised over a workman
  • is not that of his corporation, but of his customers. It is
  • the fear of losing their employment which restrains his
  • frauds, and corrects his negligence" (_Wealth of Nations_,
  • Book I. chap. 10).
  • To these two points, then, the following essays are mainly directed.
  • The subject of the organization of labour is only casually touched
  • upon; because, if we once can get a sufficient quantity of honesty in
  • our captains, the organization of labour is easy, and will develop
  • itself without quarrel or difficulty; but if we cannot get honesty in
  • our captains, the organization of labour is for evermore impossible.
  • The several conditions of its possibility I purpose to examine at
  • length in the sequel. Yet, lest the reader should be alarmed by the
  • hints thrown out during the following investigation of first
  • principles, as if they were leading him into unexpectedly dangerous
  • ground, I will, for his better assurance, state at once the worst of
  • the political creed at which I wish him to arrive.
  • 1. First,--that there should be training schools for youth
  • established, at Government cost,[28] and under Government discipline,
  • over the whole country; that every child born in the country should,
  • at the parent's wish, be permitted (and, in certain cases, be under
  • penalty required) to pass through them; and that, in these schools,
  • the child should (with other minor pieces of knowledge hereafter to be
  • considered) imperatively be taught, with the best skill of teaching
  • that the country could produce, the following three things:--
  • (_a_) the laws of health, and the exercises enjoined by them;
  • (_b_) habits of gentleness and justice; and
  • (_c_) the calling by which he is to live.
  • [28] It will probably be inquired by near-sighted persons, out of
  • what funds such schools could be supported. The expedient
  • modes of direct provision for them I will examine hereafter;
  • indirectly, they would be far more than self-supporting. The
  • economy in crime alone (quite one of the most costly
  • articles of luxury in the modern European market), which
  • such schools would induce, would suffice to support them ten
  • times over. Their economy of labour would be pure gain, and
  • that too large to be presently calculable.
  • 2. Secondly,--that, in connection with these training schools, there
  • should be established, also entirely under Government regulation,
  • manufactories and workshops, for the production and sale of every
  • necessary of life, and for the exercise of every useful art. And that,
  • interfering no whit with private enterprise, nor setting any
  • restraints or tax on private trade, but leaving both to do their best,
  • and beat the Government if they could,--there should, at these
  • Government manufactories and shops, be authoritatively good and
  • exemplary work done, and pure and true substance sold; so that a man
  • could be sure, if he chose to pay the Government price, that he got
  • for his money bread that was bread, ale that was ale, and work that
  • was work.
  • 3. Thirdly,--that any man, or woman, or boy, or girl, out of
  • employment, should be at once received at the nearest Government
  • school, and set to such work as it appeared, on trial, they were fit
  • for, at a fixed rate of wages determinable every year:--that, being
  • found incapable of work through ignorance, they should be taught, or
  • being found incapable of work through sickness, should be tended; but
  • that being found objecting to work, they should be set, under
  • compulsion of the strictest nature, to the more painful and degrading
  • forms of necessary toil, especially to that in mines and other places
  • of danger (such danger being, however, diminished to the utmost by
  • careful regulation and discipline) and the due wages of such work be
  • retained--cost of compulsion first abstracted--to be at the workman's
  • command, so soon as he has come to sounder mind respecting the laws of
  • employment.
  • 4. Lastly,--that for the old and destitute, comfort and home should be
  • provided; which provision, when misfortune had been by the working of
  • such a system sifted from guilt, would be honourable instead of
  • disgraceful to the receiver. For (I repeat this passage out of my
  • _Political Economy of Art_, to which the reader is referred for
  • farther detail[29]) "a labourer serves his country with his spade,
  • just as a man in the middle ranks of life serves it with sword, pen,
  • or lancet: if the service is less, and, therefore the wages during
  • health less, then the reward, when health is broken, may be less, but
  • not, therefore, less honourable; and it ought to be quite as natural
  • and straightforward a matter for a labourer to take his pension from
  • his parish, because he has deserved well of his parish, as for a man
  • in higher rank to take his pension from his country, because he has
  • deserved well of his country."
  • [29] "The Political Economy of Art:" Addenda, p. 93.
  • To which statement, I will only add, for conclusion, respecting the
  • discipline and pay of life and death, that, for both high and low,
  • Livy's last words touching Valerius Publicola, "_de publico est
  • elatus_,"[30] ought not to be a dishonourable close of epitaph.
  • [30] "P. Valerius, omnium consensu princeps belli pacisque
  • artibus, anno post moritur; gloriâ ingenti, copiis
  • familiaribus adeo exiguis, ut funeri sumtus deesset: de
  • publico est elatus. Luxêre matronæ ut Brutum."--Lib. II.
  • c. xvi.
  • These things, then, I believe, and am about, as I find power, to
  • explain and illustrate in their various bearings; following out also
  • what belongs to them of collateral inquiry. Here I state them only in
  • brief, to prevent the reader casting about in alarm for my ultimate
  • meaning; yet requesting him, for the present to remember, that in a
  • science dealing with so subtle elements as those of human nature, it
  • is only possible to answer for the final truth of principles, not for
  • the direct success of plans: and that in the best of these last, what
  • can be immediately accomplished is always questionable, and what can
  • be finally accomplished, inconceivable.
  • _Denmark Hill, 10th May, 1862._
  • ESSAY I.
  • THE ROOTS OF HONOUR.
  • Among the delusions which at different periods have possessed
  • themselves of the minds of large masses of the human race, perhaps
  • the most curious--certainly the least creditable--is the modern
  • _soi-disant_ science of political economy, based on the idea that an
  • advantageous code of social action may be determined irrespectively of
  • the influence of social affection.
  • Of course, as in the instances of alchemy, astrology, witchcraft, and
  • other such popular creeds, political economy has a plausible idea at
  • the root of it. "The social affections," says the economist, "are
  • accidental and disturbing elements in human nature; but avarice and
  • the desire of progress are constant elements. Let us eliminate the
  • inconstants, and, considering the human being merely as a covetous
  • machine, examine by what laws of labour, purchase, and sale, the
  • greatest accumulative result in wealth is obtainable. Those laws once
  • determined, it will be for each individual afterwards to introduce as
  • much of the disturbing affectionate element as he chooses, and to
  • determine for himself the result on the new conditions supposed."
  • This would be a perfectly logical and successful method of analysis,
  • if the accidentals afterwards to be introduced were of the same nature
  • as the powers first examined. Supposing a body in motion to be
  • influenced by constant and inconstant forces, it is usually the
  • simplest way of examining its course to trace it first under the
  • persistent conditions, and afterwards introduce the causes of
  • variation. But the disturbing elements in the social problem are not
  • of the same nature as the constant ones; they alter the essence of
  • the creature under examination the moment they are added; they
  • operate, not mathematically, but chemically, introducing conditions
  • which render all our previous knowledge unavailable. We made learned
  • experiments upon pure nitrogen, and have convinced ourselves that it
  • is a very manageable gas: but behold! the thing which we have
  • practically to deal with is its chloride; and this, the moment we
  • touch it on our established principles, sends us and our apparatus
  • through the ceiling.
  • Observe, I neither impugn nor doubt the conclusions of the science, if
  • its terms are accepted. I am simply uninterested in them, as I should
  • be in those of a science of gymnastics which assumed that men had no
  • skeletons. It might be shown, on that supposition, that it would be
  • advantageous to roll the students up into pellets, flatten them into
  • cakes, or stretch them into cables; and that when these results were
  • effected, the re-insertion of the skeleton would be attended with
  • various inconveniences to their constitution. The reasoning might be
  • admirable, the conclusions true, and the science deficient only in
  • applicability. Modern political economy stands on a precisely similar
  • basis. Assuming, not that the human being has no skeleton, but that it
  • is all skeleton, it founds an ossifiant theory of progress on this
  • negation of a soul; and having shown the utmost that may be made of
  • bones, and constructed a number of interesting geometrical figures
  • with death's-heads and humeri, successfully proves the inconvenience
  • of the reappearance of a soul among these corpuscular structures. I do
  • not deny the truth of this theory: I simply deny its applicability to
  • the present phase of the world.
  • This inapplicability has been curiously manifested during the
  • embarrassment caused by the late strikes of our workmen. Here occurs
  • one of the simplest cases, in a pertinent and positive form, of the
  • first vital problem which political economy has to deal with (the
  • relation between employer and employed); and at a severe crisis, when
  • lives in multitudes, and wealth in masses, are at stake, the political
  • economists are helpless--practically mute; no demonstrable solution of
  • the difficulty can be given by them, such as may convince or calm the
  • opposing parties. Obstinately the masters take one view of the
  • matter; obstinately the operatives another; and no political science
  • can set them at one.
  • It would be strange if it could, it being not by "science" of any kind
  • that men were ever intended to be set at one. Disputant after
  • disputant vainly strives to show that the interests of the masters
  • are, or are not, antagonistic to those of the men: none of the
  • pleaders ever seeming to remember that it does not absolutely or
  • always follow that the persons must be antagonistic because their
  • interests are. If there is only a crust of bread in the house, and
  • mother and children are starving, their interests are not the same. If
  • the mother eats it, the children want it; if the children eat it, the
  • mother must go hungry to her work. Yet it does not necessarily follow
  • that there will be "antagonism" between them, that they will fight for
  • the crust, and that the mother, being strongest, will get it, and eat
  • it. Neither, in any other case, whatever the relations of the persons
  • may be, can it be assumed for certain that, because their interests
  • are diverse, they must necessarily regard each other with hostility,
  • and use violence or cunning to obtain the advantage.
  • Even if this were so, and it were as just as it is convenient to
  • consider men as actuated by no other moral influences than those which
  • affect rats or swine, the logical conditions of the question are still
  • indeterminable. It can never be shown generally either that the
  • interests of master and labourer are alike, or that they are opposed;
  • for, according to circumstances, they may be either. It is, indeed,
  • always the interest of both that the work should be rightly done, and
  • a just price obtained for it; but, in the division of profits, the
  • gain of the one may or may not be the loss of the other. It is not the
  • master's interest to pay wages so low as to leave the men sickly and
  • depressed, nor the workman's interest to be paid high wages if the
  • smallness of the master's profit hinders him from enlarging his
  • business, or conducting it in a safe and liberal way. A stoker ought
  • not to desire high pay if the company is too poor to keep the
  • engine-wheels in repair.
  • And the varieties of circumstance which influence these reciprocal
  • interests are so endless, that all endeavour to deduce rules of action
  • from balance of expediency is in vain. And it is meant to be in vain.
  • For no human actions ever were intended by the Maker of men to be
  • guided by balances of expediency, but by balances of justice. He has
  • therefore rendered all endeavours to determine expediency futile for
  • evermore. No man ever knew or can know, what will be the ultimate
  • result to himself, or to others, of any given line of conduct. But
  • every man may know, and most of us do know, what is a just and unjust
  • act. And all of us may know also, that the consequences of justice
  • will be ultimately the best possible, both to others and ourselves,
  • though we can neither say what _is_ best, or how it is likely to come
  • to pass.
  • I have said balances of justice, meaning, in the term justice, to
  • include affection,--such affection as one man _owes_ to another. All
  • right relations between master and operative, and all their best
  • interests, ultimately depend on these.
  • We shall find the best and simplest illustration of the relations of
  • master and operative in the position of domestic servants.
  • We will suppose that the master of a household desires only to get as
  • much work out of his servants as he can, at the rate of wages he
  • gives. He never allows them to be idle; feeds them as poorly and
  • lodges them as ill as they will endure, and in all things pushes his
  • requirements to the exact point beyond which he cannot go without
  • forcing the servant to leave him. In doing this, there is no violation
  • on his part of what is commonly called "justice." He agrees with the
  • domestic for his whole time and service, and takes them;--the limits
  • of hardship in treatment being fixed by the practice of other masters
  • in his neighbourhood; that is to say, by the current rate of wages for
  • domestic labour. If the servant can get a better place, he is free to
  • take one, and the master can only tell what is the real market value
  • of his labour, by requiring as much as he will give.
  • This is the politico-economical view of the case, according to the
  • doctors of that science; who assert that by this procedure the
  • greatest average of work will be obtained from the servant, and
  • therefore, the greatest benefit to the community, and through the
  • community, by reversion, to the servant himself.
  • That, however, is not so. It would be so if the servant were an
  • engine of which the motive power was steam, magnetism, gravitation, or
  • any other agent of calculable force. But he being, on the contrary, an
  • engine whose motive power is a Soul, the force of this very peculiar
  • agent, as an unknown quantity, enters into all the political
  • economist's equations, without his knowledge, and falsifies every one
  • of their results. The largest quantity of work will not be done by
  • this curious engine for pay, or under pressure, or by help of any kind
  • of fuel which may be supplied by the chaldron. It will be done only
  • when the motive force, that is to say, the will or spirit of the
  • creature, is brought to its greatest strength by its own proper fuel;
  • namely, by the affections.
  • It may indeed happen, and does happen often, that if the master is a
  • man of sense and energy, a large quantity of material work may be done
  • under mechanical pressure, enforced by strong will and guided by wise
  • method; also it may happen, and does happen often, that if the master
  • is indolent and weak (however good-natured), a very small quantity of
  • work, and that bad, may be produced by the servant's undirected
  • strength, and contemptuous gratitude. But the universal law of the
  • matter is that, assuming any given quantity of energy and sense in
  • master and servant, the greatest material result obtainable by them
  • will be, not through antagonism to each other, but through affection
  • for each other; and that if the master, instead of endeavouring to get
  • as much work as possible from the servant, seeks rather to render his
  • appointed and necessary work beneficial to him, and to forward his
  • interests in all just and wholesome ways, the real amount of work
  • ultimately done, or of good rendered, by the person so cared for, will
  • indeed be the greatest possible.
  • Observe, I say, "of good rendered," for a servant's work is not
  • necessarily or always the best thing he can give his master. But good
  • of all kinds, whether in material service, in protective watchfulness
  • of his master's interest and credit, or in joyful readiness to seize
  • unexpected and irregular occasions of help.
  • Nor is this one whit less generally true because indulgence will be
  • frequently abused, and kindness met with ingratitude. For the servant
  • who, gently treated, is ungrateful, treated ungently, will be
  • revengeful; and the man who is dishonest to a liberal master will be
  • injurious to an unjust one.
  • In any case, and with any person, this unselfish treatment will
  • produce the most effective return. Observe, I am here considering the
  • affections wholly as a motive power; not at all as things in
  • themselves desirable or noble, or in any other way abstractedly good.
  • I look at them simply as an anomalous force, rendering every one of
  • the ordinary political economist's calculations nugatory; while, even
  • if he desired to introduce this new element into his estimates, he has
  • no power of dealing with it; for the affections only become a true
  • motive power when they ignore every other motive and condition of
  • political economy. Treat the servant kindly, with the idea of turning
  • his gratitude to account, and you will get, as you deserve, no
  • gratitude, nor any value for your kindness; but treat him kindly
  • without any economical purpose, and all economical purposes will be
  • answered; in this, as in all other matters, whosoever will save his
  • life shall lose it, whoso loses it shall find it.[31]
  • [31] The difference between the two modes of treatment, and
  • between their effective material results, may be seen very
  • accurately by a comparison of the relations of Esther and
  • Charlie in _Bleak House_, with those of Miss Brass and the
  • Marchioness in _Master Humphrey's Clock_.
  • The essential value and truth of Dickens's writings have
  • been unwisely lost sight of by many thoughtful persons,
  • merely because he presents his truth with some colour of
  • caricature. Unwisely, because Dickens's caricature, though
  • often gross, is never mistaken. Allowing for his manner of
  • telling them, the things he tells us are always true. I wish
  • that he could think it right to limit his brilliant
  • exaggeration to works written only for public amusement; and
  • when he takes up a subject of high national importance, such
  • as that which he handled in _Hard Times_, that he would use
  • severer and more accurate analysis. The usefulness of that
  • work (to my mind, in several respects, the greatest he has
  • written) is with many persons seriously diminished because
  • Mr. Bounderby is a dramatic monster, instead of a
  • characteristic example of a worldly master; and Stephen
  • Blackpool a dramatic perfection, instead of a characteristic
  • example of an honest workman. But let us not lose the use of
  • Dickens's wit and insight, because he chooses to speak in a
  • circle of stage fire. He is entirely right in his main drift
  • and purpose in every book he has written; and all of them,
  • but especially _Hard Times_, should be studied with close
  • and earnest care by persons interested in social questions.
  • They will find much that is partial, and, because partial,
  • apparently unjust; but if they examine all the evidence on
  • the other side, which Dickens seems to overlook, it will
  • appear, after all their trouble, that his view was the
  • finally right one, grossly and sharply told.
  • The next clearest and simplest example of relation between master and
  • operative is that which exists between the commander of a regiment and
  • his men.
  • Supposing the officer only desires to apply the rules of discipline so
  • as, with least trouble to himself, to make the regiment most
  • effective, he will not be able, by any rules, or administration of
  • rules, on this selfish principle, to develop the full strength of his
  • subordinates. If a man of sense and firmness, he may, as in the former
  • instance, produce a better result than would be obtained by the
  • irregular kindness of a weak officer; but let the sense and firmness
  • be the same in both cases, and assuredly the officer who has the most
  • direct personal relations with his men, the most care for their
  • interests, and the most value for their lives, will develop their
  • effective strength, through their affection for his own person, and
  • trust in his character, to a degree wholly unattainable by other
  • means. The law applies still more stringently as the numbers concerned
  • are larger; a charge may often be successful, though the men dislike
  • their officers; a battle has rarely been won, unless they loved their
  • general.
  • Passing from these simple examples to the more complicated relations
  • existing between a manufacturer and his workmen, we are met first by
  • certain curious difficulties, resulting, apparently, from a harder and
  • colder state of moral elements. It is easy to imagine an enthusiastic
  • affection existing among soldiers for the colonel, not so easy to
  • imagine an enthusiastic affection among cotton-spinners for the
  • proprietor of the mill. A body of men associated for purposes of
  • robbery (as a Highland clan in ancient times) shall be animated by
  • perfect affection, and every member of it be ready to lay down his
  • life for the life of his chief. But a band of men associated for
  • purposes of legal production and accumulation is usually animated, it
  • appears, by no such emotions, and none of them are in anywise willing
  • to give his life for the life of his chief. Not only are we met by
  • this apparent anomaly, in moral matters, but by others connected with
  • it, in administration of system. For a servant or a soldier is
  • engaged at a definite rate of wages, for a definite period; but a
  • workman at a rate of wages variable according to the demand for
  • labour, and with the risk of being at any time thrown out of his
  • situation by chances of trade. Now, as, under these contingencies, no
  • action of the affections can take place, but only an explosive action
  • of _dis_affections, two points offer themselves for consideration in
  • the matter.
  • The first--How far the rate of wages may be so regulated as not to
  • vary with the demand for labour.
  • The second--How far it is possible that bodies of workmen may be
  • engaged and maintained at such fixed rate of wages (whatever the state
  • of trade may be), without enlarging or diminishing their number, so as
  • to give them permanent interest in the establishment with which they
  • are connected, like that of the domestic servants in an old family, or
  • an _esprit de corps_, like that of the soldiers in a crack regiment.
  • The first question is, I say, how far it may be possible to fix the
  • rate of wages irrespectively of the demand for labour.
  • Perhaps one of the most curious facts in the history of human error is
  • the denial by the common political economist of the possibility of
  • thus regulating wages; while, for all the important, and much of the
  • unimportant, labour on the earth, wages are already so regulated.
  • We do not sell our prime-ministership by Dutch auction; nor, on
  • the decease of a bishop, whatever may be the general advantages of
  • simony, do we (yet) offer his diocese to the clergyman who will
  • take the episcopacy at the lowest contract. We (with exquisite
  • sagacity of political economy!) do indeed sell commissions, but not,
  • openly, generalships: sick, we do not inquire for a physician who
  • takes less than a guinea; litigious, we never think of reducing
  • six-and-eightpence to four-and-sixpence; caught in a shower, we do not
  • canvass the cabmen, to find one who values his driving at less than a
  • sixpence a mile.
  • It is true that in all these cases there is, and in every conceivable
  • case there must be, ultimate reference to the presumed difficulty of
  • the work, or number of candidates for the office. If it were thought
  • that the labour necessary to make a good physician would be gone
  • through by a sufficient number of students with the prospect of only
  • half-guinea fees, public consent would soon withdraw the unnecessary
  • half-guinea. In this ultimate sense, the price of labour is indeed
  • always regulated by the demand for it; but so far as the practical and
  • immediate administration of the matter is regarded, the best labour
  • always has been, and is, as _all_ labour ought to be, paid by an
  • invariable standard.
  • "What!" the reader, perhaps, answers amazedly: "pay good and bad
  • workmen alike?"
  • Certainly. The difference between one prelate's sermons and his
  • successor's,--or between one physician's opinion and another's,--is
  • far greater, as respects the qualities of mind involved, and far more
  • important in result to you personally, than the difference between
  • good and bad laying of bricks (though that is greater than most people
  • suppose). Yet you pay with equal fee, contentedly, the good and bad
  • workmen upon your soul, and the good and bad workmen upon your body;
  • much more may you pay, contentedly, with equal fees, the good and bad
  • workmen upon your house.
  • "Nay, but I choose my physician and (?) my clergyman, thus indicating
  • my sense of the quality of their work." By all means, also, choose
  • your bricklayer; that is the proper reward of the good workman, to be
  • "chosen." The natural and right system respecting all labour is, that
  • it should be paid at a fixed rate, but the good workman employed, and
  • the bad workmen unemployed. The false, unnatural, and destructive
  • system is, when the bad workman is allowed to offer his work at
  • half-price, and either take the place of the good, or force him by his
  • competition to work for an inadequate sum.
  • This equality of wages, then, being the first object towards which we
  • have to discover the directest available road; the second is, as above
  • stated, that of maintaining constant numbers of workmen in employment,
  • whatever may be the accidental demand for the article they produce.
  • I believe the sudden and extensive inequalities of demand which
  • necessarily arise in the mercantile operations of an active nation,
  • constitute the only essential difficulty which has to be overcome in a
  • just organization of labour. The subject opens into too many branches
  • to admit of being investigated in a paper of this kind; but the
  • following general facts bearing on it may be noted.
  • The wages which enable any workman to live are necessarily higher, if
  • his work is liable to intermission, than if it is assured and
  • continuous; and however severe the struggle for work may become, the
  • general law will always hold, that men must get more daily pay if, on
  • the average, they can only calculate on work three days a week, than
  • they would require if they were sure of work six days a week.
  • Supposing that a man cannot live on less than a shilling a day, his
  • seven shillings he must get, either for three days' violent work, or
  • six days' deliberate work. The tendency of all modern mercantile
  • operations is to throw both wages and trade into the form of a
  • lottery, and to make the workman's pay depend on intermittent
  • exertion, and the principal's profit on dexterously used chance.
  • In what partial degree, I repeat, this may be necessary, in
  • consequence of the activities of modern trade, I do not here
  • investigate; contenting myself with the fact, that in its fatallest
  • aspects it is assuredly unnecessary, and results merely from love of
  • gambling on the part of the masters, and from ignorance and sensuality
  • in the men. The masters cannot bear to let any opportunity of gain
  • escape them, and frantically rush at every gap and breach in the walls
  • of Fortune, raging to be rich, and affronting, with impatient
  • covetousness, every risk of ruin; while the men prefer three days of
  • violent labour, and three days of drunkenness, to six days of moderate
  • work and wise rest. There is no way in which a principal, who really
  • desires to help his workmen, may do it more effectually than by
  • checking these disorderly habits both in himself and them; keeping his
  • own business operations on a scale which will enable him to pursue
  • them securely, not yielding to temptations of precarious gain; and, at
  • the same time, leading his workmen into regular habits of labour and
  • life, either by inducing them rather to take low wages in the form of
  • a fixed salary, than high wages, subject to the chance of their being
  • thrown out of work; or, if this be impossible, by discouraging the
  • system of violent exertion for nominally high day wages, and leading
  • the men to take lower pay for more regular labour.
  • In effecting any radical changes of this kind, doubtless there would
  • be great inconvenience and loss incurred by all the originators of
  • movement. That which can be done with perfect convenience and without
  • loss, is not always the thing that most needs to be done, or which we
  • are most imperatively required to do.
  • I have already alluded to the difference hitherto existing between
  • regiments of men associated for purposes of violence, and for
  • purposes of manufacture; in that the former appear capable of
  • self-sacrifice--the latter, not; which singular fact is the real
  • reason of the general lowness of estimate in which the profession of
  • commerce is held, as compared with that of arms. Philosophically, it
  • does not, at first sight, appear reasonable (many writers have
  • endeavoured to prove it unreasonable) that a peaceable and rational
  • person, whose trade is buying and selling, should be held in less
  • honour than an unpeaceable and often irrational person, whose trade is
  • slaying. Nevertheless, the consent of mankind has always, in spite of
  • the philosophers, given precedence to the soldier.
  • And this is right.
  • For the soldier's trade, verily and essentially, is not slaying, but
  • being slain. This, without well knowing its own meaning, the world
  • honours it for. A bravo's trade is slaying; but the world has never
  • respected bravos more than merchants: the reason it honours the
  • soldier is, because he holds his life at the service of the State.
  • Reckless he may be--fond of pleasure or of adventure--all kinds of
  • bye-motives and mean impulses may have determined the choice of his
  • profession, and may affect (to all appearance exclusively) his daily
  • conduct in it; but our estimate of him is based on this ultimate
  • fact--of which we are well assured--that, put him in a fortress
  • breach, with all the pleasures of the world behind him, and only
  • death and his duty in front of him, he will keep his face to the
  • front; and he knows that this choice may be put to him at any moment,
  • and has beforehand taken his part--virtually takes such part
  • continually--does, in reality, die daily.
  • Not less is the respect we pay to the lawyer and physician, founded
  • ultimately on their self-sacrifice. Whatever the learning or acuteness
  • of a great lawyer, our chief respect for him depends on our belief
  • that, set in a judge's seat, he will strive to judge justly, come of
  • it what may. Could we suppose that he would take bribes, and use his
  • acuteness and legal knowledge to give plausibility to iniquitous
  • decisions, no degree of intellect would win for him our respect.
  • Nothing will win it, short of our tacit conviction, that in all
  • important acts of his life justice is first with him; his own
  • interest, second.
  • In the case of a physician, the ground of the honour we render him is
  • clearer still. Whatever his science, we should shrink from him in
  • horror if we found him regard his patients merely as subjects to
  • experiment upon; much more, if we found that, receiving bribes from
  • persons interested in their deaths, he was using his best skill to
  • give poison in the mask of medicine.
  • Finally, the principle holds with utmost clearness as it respects
  • clergymen. No goodness of disposition will excuse want of science in a
  • physician, or of shrewdness in an advocate; but a clergyman, even
  • though his power of intellect be small, is respected on the presumed
  • ground of his unselfishness and serviceableness.
  • Now there can be no question but that the tact, foresight, decision,
  • and other mental powers, required for the successful management of a
  • large mercantile concern, if not such as could be compared with those
  • of a great lawyer, general, or divine, would at least match the
  • general conditions of mind required in the subordinate officers of a
  • ship, or of a regiment, or in the curate of a country parish. If,
  • therefore, all the efficient members of the so-called liberal
  • professions are still, somehow, in public estimate of honour,
  • preferred before the head of a commercial firm, the reason must lie
  • deeper than in the measurement of their several powers of mind.
  • And the essential reason for such preference will be found to lie in
  • the fact that the merchant is presumed to act always selfishly. His
  • work may be very necessary to the community; but the motive of it is
  • understood to be wholly personal. The merchant's first object in all
  • his dealings must be (the public believe) to get as much for himself,
  • and leave as little to his neighbour (or customer) as possible.
  • Enforcing this upon him, by political statute, as the necessary
  • principle of his action; recommending it to him on all occasions, and
  • themselves reciprocally adopting it; proclaiming vociferously, for law
  • of the universe, that a buyer's function is to cheapen, and a seller's
  • to cheat,--the public, nevertheless, involuntarily condemn the man of
  • commerce for his compliance with their own statement, and stamp him
  • for ever as belonging to an inferior grade of human personality.
  • This they will find, eventually, they must give up doing. They must
  • not cease to condemn selfishness; but they will have to discover a
  • kind of commerce which is not exclusively selfish. Or, rather, they
  • will have to discover that there never was, or can be, any other kind
  • of commerce; that this which they have called commerce was not
  • commerce at all, but cozening; and that a true merchant differs as
  • much from a merchant according to laws of modern political economy, as
  • the hero of the _Excursion_ from Autolycus. They will find that
  • commerce is an occupation which gentlemen will every day see more need
  • to engage in, rather than in the businesses of talking to men, or
  • slaying them; that, in true commerce, as in true preaching, or true
  • fighting, it is necessary to admit the idea of occasional voluntary
  • loss; that sixpences have to be lost, as well as lives, under a sense
  • of duty; that the market may have its martyrdoms as well as the
  • pulpit; and trade its heroisms, as well as war.
  • May have--in the final issue, must have--and only has not had yet,
  • because men of heroic temper have always been misguided in their youth
  • into other fields, not recognizing what is in our days, perhaps, the
  • most important of all fields; so that, while many a zealous person
  • loses his life in trying to teach the form of a gospel, very few will
  • lose a hundred pounds in showing the practice of one.
  • The fact is, that people never have had clearly explained to them the
  • true functions of a merchant with respect to other people. I should
  • like the reader to be very clear about this.
  • Five great intellectual professions, relating to daily necessities
  • of life, have hitherto existed--three exist necessarily, in every
  • civilized nation:
  • The Soldier's profession is to _defend_ it.
  • The Pastor's, to _teach_ it.
  • The Physician's, to _keep it in health_.
  • The Lawyer's, to _enforce justice_ in it.
  • The Merchant's, _to provide_ for it.
  • And the duty of all these men is, on due occasion, to _die_ for it.
  • "On due occasion," namely:--
  • The Soldier, rather than leave his post in battle.
  • The Physician, rather than leave his post in plague.
  • The Pastor, rather than teach Falsehood.
  • The Lawyer, rather than countenance Injustice.
  • The Merchant--What is _his_ "due occasion" of death? It is the main
  • question for the merchant, as for all of us. For, truly, the man who
  • does not know when to die, does not know how to live.
  • Observe, the merchant's function (or manufacturer's, for in the broad
  • sense in which it is here used the word must be understood to include
  • both) is to provide for the nation. It is no more his function to get
  • profit for himself out of that provision than it is a clergyman's
  • function to get his stipend. The stipend is a due and necessary
  • adjunct, but not the object, of his life, if he be a true clergyman,
  • any more than his fee (or _honorarium_) is the object of life to a
  • true physician. Neither is his fee the object of life to a true
  • merchant. All three, if true men, have a work to be done irrespective
  • of fee--to be done even at any cost, or for quite the contrary of fee;
  • the pastor's function being to teach, the physician's to heal, and the
  • merchant's, as I have said, to provide. That is to say, he has to
  • understand to their very root the qualities of the thing he deals in,
  • and the means of obtaining or producing it; and he has to apply all
  • his sagacity and energy to the producing or obtaining it in perfect
  • state, and distributing it at the cheapest possible price where it is
  • most needed.
  • And because the production or obtaining of any commodity involves
  • necessarily the agency of many lives and hands, the merchant becomes
  • in the course of his business the master and governor of large masses
  • of men in a more direct, though less confessed way, than a military
  • officer or pastor; so that on him falls, in great part, the
  • responsibility for the kind of life they lead: and it becomes his
  • duty, not only to be always considering how to produce what he sells
  • in the purest and cheapest forms, but how to make the various
  • employments involved in the production, or transference of it, most
  • beneficial to the men employed.
  • And as into these two functions, requiring for their right exercise
  • the highest intelligence, as well as patience, kindness, and tact, the
  • merchant is bound to put all his energy, so for their just discharge
  • he is bound, as soldier or physician is bound, to give up, if need be,
  • his life, in such way as it may be demanded of him. Two main points he
  • has in his providing function to maintain: first, his engagements
  • (faithfulness to engagements being the real root of all possibilities
  • in commerce); and, secondly, the perfectness and purity of the thing
  • provided; so that, rather than fail in any engagement, or consent to
  • any deterioration, adulteration, or unjust and exorbitant price of
  • that which he provides, he is bound to meet fearlessly any form of
  • distress, poverty, or labour, which may, through maintenance of these
  • points, come upon him.
  • Again: in his office as governor of the men employed by him, the
  • merchant or manufacturer is invested with a distinctly paternal
  • authority and responsibility. In most cases, a youth entering a
  • commercial establishment is withdrawn altogether from home influence;
  • his master must become his father, else he has, for practical and
  • constant help, no father at hand: in all cases the master's authority,
  • together with the general tone and atmosphere of his business, and the
  • character of the men with whom the youth is compelled in the course of
  • it to associate, have more immediate and pressing weight than the home
  • influence, and will usually neutralize it either for good or evil; so
  • that the only means which the master has of doing justice to the men
  • employed by him is to ask himself sternly whether he is dealing with
  • such subordinate as he would with his own son, if compelled by
  • circumstances to take such a position.
  • Supposing the captain of a frigate saw it right, or were by any chance
  • obliged, to place his own son in the position of a common sailor; as
  • he would then treat his son, he is bound always to treat every one of
  • the men under him. So, also; supposing the master of a manufactory
  • saw it right, or were by any chance obliged, to place his own son in
  • the position of an ordinary workman; as he would then treat his son,
  • he is bound always to treat every one of his men. This is the only
  • effective true, or practical RULE which can be given on this point of
  • political economy.
  • And as the captain of a ship is bound to be the last man to leave his
  • ship in case of wreck, and to share his last crust with the sailors in
  • case of famine, so the manufacturer, in any commercial crisis or
  • distress, is bound to take the suffering of it with his men, and even
  • to take more of it for himself than he allows his men to feel; as a
  • father would in a famine, shipwreck, or battle, sacrifice himself for
  • his son.
  • All which sounds very strange: the only real strangeness in the matter
  • being, nevertheless, that it should so sound. For all this is true,
  • and that not partially nor theoretically, but everlastingly and
  • practically: all other doctrine than this respecting matters political
  • being false in premises, absurd in deduction, and impossible in
  • practice, consistently with any progressive state of national life;
  • all the life which we now possess as a nation showing itself in the
  • resolute denial and scorn, by a few strong minds and faithful hearts,
  • of the economic principles taught to our multitudes, which principles,
  • so far as accepted, lead straight to national destruction. Respecting
  • the modes and forms of destruction to which they lead, and, on the
  • other hand, respecting the farther practical working of true polity,
  • I hope to reason further in a following paper.
  • ESSAY II.
  • THE VEINS OF WEALTH.
  • The answer which would be made by any ordinary political economist to
  • the statements contained in the preceding paper, is in few words as
  • follows:--
  • "It is indeed true that certain advantages of a general nature may be
  • obtained by the development of social affections. But political
  • economists never professed, nor profess, to take advantages of a
  • general nature into consideration. Our science is simply the science
  • of getting rich. So far from being a fallacious or visionary one, it
  • is found by experience to be practically effective. Persons who follow
  • its precepts do actually become rich, and persons who disobey them
  • become poor. Every capitalist of Europe has acquired his fortune by
  • following the known laws of our science, and increases his capital
  • daily by an adherence to them. It is vain to bring forward tricks of
  • logic, against the force of accomplished facts. Every man of business
  • knows by experience how money is made, and how it is lost."
  • Pardon me. Men of business do indeed know how they themselves made
  • their money, or how, on occasion, they lost it. Playing a
  • long-practised game, they are familiar with the chances of its cards,
  • and can rightly explain their losses and gains. But they neither know
  • who keeps the bank of the gambling-house, nor what other games may be
  • played with the same cards, nor what other losses and gains, far away
  • among the dark streets, are essentially, though invisibly, dependent
  • on theirs in the lighted rooms. They have learned a few, and only a
  • few, of the laws of mercantile economy; but not one of those of
  • political economy.
  • Primarily, which is very notable and curious, I observe that men of
  • business rarely know the meaning of the word "rich." At least if they
  • know, they do not in their reasonings allow for the fact that it is a
  • relative word, implying its opposite "poor" as positively as the word
  • "north" implies its opposite "south." Men nearly always speak and
  • write as if riches were absolute, and it were possible, by following
  • certain scientific precepts, for everybody to be rich. Whereas riches
  • are a power like that of electricity, acting only through inequalities
  • or negations of itself. The force of the guinea you have in your
  • pocket depends wholly on the default of a guinea in your neighbour's
  • pocket. If he did not want it, it would be of no use to you; the
  • degree of power it possesses depends accurately upon the need or
  • desire he has for it,--and the art of making yourself rich, in the
  • ordinary mercantile economist's sense, is therefore equally and
  • necessarily the art of keeping your neighbour poor.
  • I would not contend in this matter (and rarely in any matter), for the
  • acceptance of terms. But I wish the reader clearly and deeply to
  • understand the difference between the two economies, to which the
  • terms "Political" and "Mercantile" might not unadvisably be attached.
  • Political economy (the economy of a State, or of citizens) consists
  • simply in the production, preservation, and distribution, at fittest
  • time and place, of useful or pleasurable things. The farmer who cuts
  • his hay at the right time; the shipwright who drives his bolts well
  • home in sound wood; the builder who lays good bricks in well-tempered
  • mortar; the housewife who takes care of her furniture in the parlour,
  • and guards against all waste in her kitchen; and the singer who
  • rightly disciplines, and never overstrains her voice: are all
  • political economists in the true and final sense; adding continually
  • to the riches and well-being of the nation to which they belong.
  • But mercantile economy, the economy of "merces" or of "pay," signifies
  • the accumulation, in the hands of individuals, of legal, or moral
  • claim upon, or power over, the labour of others; every such claim
  • implying precisely as much poverty or debt on one side, as it implies
  • riches or right on the other.
  • It does not, therefore, necessarily involve an addition to the actual
  • property, or well-being, of the State in which it exists. But since
  • this commercial wealth, or power over labour, is nearly always
  • convertible at once into real property, while real property is not
  • always convertible at once into power over labour, the idea of riches
  • among active men in civilized nations, generally refers to commercial
  • wealth; and in estimating their possessions, they rather calculate the
  • value of their horses and fields by the number of guineas they could
  • get for them, than the value of their guineas by the number of horses
  • and fields they could buy with them.
  • There is, however, another reason for this habit of mind; namely, that
  • an accumulation of real property is of little use to its owner,
  • unless, together with it, he has commercial power over labour. Thus,
  • suppose any person to be put in possession of a large estate of
  • fruitful land, with rich beds of gold in its gravel, countless herds
  • of cattle in its pastures; houses, and gardens, and storehouses full
  • of useful stores; but suppose, after all, that he could get no
  • servants? In order that he may be able to have servants, some one in
  • his neighbourhood must be poor, and in want of his gold--or his corn.
  • Assume that no one is in want of either, and that no servants are to
  • be had. He must, therefore, bake his own bread, make his own clothes,
  • plough his own ground, and shepherd his own flocks. His gold will be
  • as useful to him as any other yellow pebbles on his estate. His stores
  • must rot, for he cannot consume them. He can eat no more than another
  • man could eat, and wear no more than another man could wear. He must
  • lead a life of severe and common labour to procure even ordinary
  • comforts; he will be ultimately unable to keep either houses in
  • repair, or fields in cultivation; and forced to content himself with a
  • poor man's portion of cottage and garden, in the midst of a desert of
  • waste land, trampled by wild cattle, and encumbered by ruins of
  • palaces, which he will hardly mock at himself by calling "his own."
  • The most covetous of mankind would, with small exultation, I presume,
  • accept riches of this kind on these terms. What is really desired,
  • under the name of riches, is, essentially, power over men; in its
  • simplest sense, the power of obtaining for our own advantage the
  • labour of servant, tradesman, and artist; in wider sense, authority
  • of directing large masses of the nation to various ends (good,
  • trivial, or hurtful, according to the mind of the rich person). And
  • this power of wealth of course is greater or less in direct proportion
  • to the poverty of the men over whom it is exercised, and in inverse
  • proportion to the number of persons who are as rich as ourselves, and
  • who are ready to give the same price for an article of which the
  • supply is limited. If the musician is poor, he will sing for small
  • pay, as long as there is only one person who can pay him; but if there
  • be two or three, he will sing for the one who offers him most. And
  • thus the power of the riches of the patron (always imperfect and
  • doubtful, as we shall see presently, even when most authoritative)
  • depends first on the poverty of the artist, and then on the limitation
  • of the number of equally wealthy persons, who also wants seats at the
  • concert. So that, as above stated, the art of becoming "rich," in the
  • common sense, is not absolutely nor finally the art of accumulating
  • much money for ourselves, but also of contriving that our neighbours
  • shall have less. In accurate terms, it is "the art of establishing the
  • maximum inequality in our own favour."
  • Now the establishment of such inequality cannot be shown in the
  • abstract to be either advantageous or disadvantageous to the body of
  • the nation. The rash and absurd assumption that such inequalities are
  • necessarily advantageous, lies at the root of most of the popular
  • fallacies on the subject of political economy. For the eternal and
  • inevitable law in this matter is, that the beneficialness of the
  • inequality depends, first, on the methods by which it was
  • accomplished, and, secondly, on the purposes to which it is applied.
  • Inequalities of wealth, unjustly established, have assuredly injured
  • the nation in which they exist during their establishment; and,
  • unjustly directed, injure it yet more during their existence. But
  • inequalities of wealth justly established, benefit the nation in the
  • course of their establishment; and, nobly used, aid it yet more by
  • their existence. That is to say, among every active and well-governed
  • people, the various strength of individuals, tested by full exertion
  • and specially applied to various need, issues in unequal, but
  • harmonious results, receiving reward or authority according to its
  • class and service;[32] while, in the inactive or ill-governed nation,
  • the gradations of decay and the victories of treason work out also
  • their own rugged system of subjection and success; and substitute, for
  • the melodious inequalities of concurrent power, the iniquitous
  • dominances and depressions of guilt and misfortune.
  • [32] I have been naturally asked several times, with respect
  • to the sentence in the first of these papers, "the bad
  • workmen unemployed," "But what are you to do with your bad
  • unemployed workmen?" Well, it seems to me the question might
  • have occurred to you before. Your housemaid's place is
  • vacant--you give twenty pounds a year--two girls come for
  • it, one neatly dressed, the other dirtily; one with good
  • recommendations, the other with none. You do not, under
  • these circumstances, usually ask the dirty one if she will
  • come for fifteen pounds, or twelve; and, on her consenting,
  • take her instead of the well-recommended one. Still less do
  • you try to beat both down by making them bid against each
  • other, till you can hire both, one at twelve pounds a year,
  • and the other at eight. You simply take the one fittest for
  • the place, and send away the other, not perhaps concerning
  • yourself quite as much as you should with the question which
  • you now impatiently put to me, "What is to become of her?"
  • For all that I advise you to do, is to deal with workmen as
  • with servants; and verily the question is of weight: "Your
  • bad workman, idler, and rogue--what are you to do with him?"
  • We will consider of this presently: remember that the
  • administration of a complete system of national commerce and
  • industry cannot be explained in full detail within the space
  • of twelve pages. Meantime, consider whether, there being
  • confessedly some difficulty in dealing with rogues and
  • idlers, it may not be advisable to produce as few of them as
  • possible. If you examine into the history of rogues, you
  • will find they are as truly manufactured articles as
  • anything else, and it is just because our present system of
  • political economy gives so large a stimulus to that
  • manufacture that you may know it to be a false one. We had
  • better seek for a system which will develop honest men, than
  • for one which will deal cunningly with vagabonds. Let us
  • reform our schools, and we shall find little reform needed
  • in our prisons.
  • Thus the circulation of wealth in a nation resembles that of the blood
  • in the natural body. There is one quickness of the current which comes
  • of cheerful emotion or wholesome exercise; and another which comes of
  • shame or of fever. There is a flush of the body which is full of
  • warmth and life; and another which will pass into putrefaction.
  • The analogy will hold, down even to minute particulars. For as
  • diseased local determination of the blood involves depression of the
  • general health of the system, all morbid local action of riches will
  • be found ultimately to involve a weakening of the resources of the
  • body politic.
  • The mode in which this is produced may be at once understood by
  • examining one or two instances of the development of wealth in the
  • simplest possible circumstances.
  • Suppose two sailors cast away on an uninhabited coast, and obliged to
  • maintain themselves there by their own labour for a series of years.
  • If they both kept their health, and worked steadily, and in amity with
  • each other, they might build themselves a convenient house, and in
  • time come to possess a certain quantity of cultivated land, together
  • with various stores laid up for future use. All these things would be
  • real riches or property; and, supposing the men both to have worked
  • equally hard, they would each have right to equal share or use of it.
  • Their political economy would consist merely in careful preservation
  • and just division of these possessions. Perhaps, however, after some
  • time one or other might be dissatisfied with the results of their
  • common farming; and they might in consequence agree to divide the land
  • they had brought under the spade into equal shares, so that each might
  • thenceforward work in his own field and live by it. Suppose that after
  • this arrangement had been made, one of them were to fall ill, and be
  • unable to work on his land at a critical time--say of sowing or
  • harvest.
  • He would naturally ask the other to sow or reap for him.
  • Then his companion might say, with perfect justice, "I will do this
  • additional work for you; but if I do it, you must promise to do as
  • much for me at another time. I will count how many hours I spend on
  • your ground, and you shall give me a written promise to work for the
  • same number of hours on mine, whenever I need your help, and you are
  • able to give it."
  • Suppose the disabled man's sickness to continue, and that under
  • various circumstances, for several years, requiring the help of the
  • other, he on each occasion gave a written pledge to work, as soon as
  • he was able, at his companion's orders, for the same number of hours
  • which the other had given up to him. What will the positions of the
  • two men be when the invalid is able to resume work?
  • Considered as a "Polis," or state, they will be poorer than they would
  • have been otherwise: poorer by the withdrawal of what the sick man's
  • labour would have produced in the interval. His friend may perhaps
  • have toiled with an energy quickened by the enlarged need, but in the
  • end his own land and property must have suffered by the withdrawal of
  • so much of his time and thought from them; and the united property of
  • the two men will be certainly less than it would have been if both had
  • remained in health and activity.
  • But the relations in which they stand to each other are also widely
  • altered. The sick man has not only pledged his labour for some years,
  • but will probably have exhausted his own share of the accumulated
  • stores, and will be in consequence for some time dependent on the
  • other for food, which he can only "pay" or reward him for by yet more
  • deeply pledging his own labour.
  • Supposing the written promises to be held entirely valid (among
  • civilized nations their validity is secured by legal measures[33]),
  • the person who had hitherto worked for both might now, if he chose,
  • rest altogether, and pass his time in idleness, not only forcing his
  • companion to redeem all the engagements he had already entered into,
  • but exacting from him pledges for further labour, to an arbitrary
  • amount, for what food he had to advance to him.
  • [33] The disputes which exist respecting the real nature of money
  • arise more from the disputants examining its functions on
  • different sides, than from any real dissent in their
  • opinions. All money, properly so called, is an
  • acknowledgment of debt; but as such, it may either be
  • considered to represent the labour and property of the
  • creditor, or the idleness and penury of the debtor. The
  • intricacy of the question has been much increased by the
  • (hitherto necessary) use of marketable commodities, such as
  • gold, silver, salt, shells, etc., to give intrinsic value or
  • security to currency; but the final and best definition of
  • money is that it is a documentary promise ratified and
  • guaranteed by the nation to give or find a certain quantity
  • of labour on demand. A man's labour for a day is a better
  • standard of value than a measure of any produce, because no
  • produce ever maintains a consistent rate of productibility.
  • There might not, from first to last, be the least illegality (in the
  • ordinary sense of the word) in the arrangement; but if a stranger
  • arrived on the coast at this advanced epoch of their political
  • economy, he would find one man commercially Rich; the other
  • commercially Poor. He would see, perhaps with no small surprise, one
  • passing his days in idleness; the other labouring for both, and living
  • sparely, in the hope of recovering his independence, at some distant
  • period.
  • This is, of course, an example of one only out of many ways in which
  • inequality of possession may be established between different persons,
  • giving rise to the Mercantile forms of Riches and Poverty. In the
  • instance before us, one of the men might from the first have
  • deliberately chosen to be idle, and to put his life in pawn for
  • present ease; or he might have mismanaged his land, and been compelled
  • to have recourse to his neighbour for food and help, pledging his
  • future labour for it. But what I want the reader to note especially is
  • the fact, common to a large number of typical cases of this kind, that
  • the establishment of the mercantile wealth which consists in a claim
  • upon labour, signifies a political diminution of the real wealth which
  • consists in substantial possessions.
  • Take another example, more consistent with the ordinary course of
  • affairs of trade. Suppose that three men, instead of two, formed the
  • little isolated republic, and found themselves obliged to separate in
  • order to farm different pieces of land at some distance from each
  • other along the coast; each estate furnishing a distinct kind of
  • produce, and each more or less in need of the material raised on the
  • other. Suppose that the third man, in order to save the time of all
  • three, undertakes simply to superintend the transference of
  • commodities from one farm to the other; on condition of receiving some
  • sufficiently remunerative share of every parcel of goods conveyed, or
  • of some other parcel received in exchange for it.
  • If this carrier or messenger always brings to each estate, from the
  • other, what is chiefly wanted, at the right time, the operations of
  • the two farmers will go on prosperously, and the largest possible
  • result in produce, or wealth, will be attained by the little
  • community. But suppose no intercourse between the landowners is
  • possible, except through the travelling agent; and that, after a time,
  • this agent, watching the course of each man's agriculture, keeps back
  • the articles with which he has been entrusted until there comes a
  • period of extreme necessity for them, on one side or other, and then
  • exacts in exchange for them all that the distressed farmer can spare
  • of other kinds of produce; it is easy to see that by ingeniously
  • watching his opportunities, he might possess himself regularly of the
  • greater part of the superfluous produce of the two estates, and at
  • last, in some year of severest trial or scarcity, purchase both for
  • himself, and maintain the former proprietors thenceforward as his
  • labourers or servants.
  • This would be a case of commercial wealth acquired on the exactest
  • principles of modern political economy. But more distinctly even than
  • in the former instance, it is manifest in this that the wealth of the
  • State, or of the three men considered as a society, is collectively
  • less than it would have been had the merchant been content with juster
  • profit. The operations of the two agriculturists have been cramped to
  • the utmost; and the continual limitations of the supply of things they
  • wanted at critical times, together with the failure of courage
  • consequent on the prolongation of a struggle for mere existence,
  • without any sense of permanent gain, must have seriously diminished
  • the effective results of their labour; and the stores finally
  • accumulated in the merchant's hands will not in anywise be of
  • equivalent value to those which, had his dealings been honest, would
  • have filled at once the granaries of the farmers and his own.
  • The whole question, therefore, respecting not only the advantage, but
  • even the quantity, of national wealth, resolves itself finally into
  • one of abstract justice. It is impossible to conclude, of any given
  • mass of acquired wealth, merely by the fact of its existence, whether
  • it signifies good or evil to the nation in the midst of which it
  • exists. Its real value depends on the moral sign attached to it, just
  • as sternly as that of a mathematical quantity depends on the
  • algebraical sign attached to it. Any given accumulation of commercial
  • wealth may be indicative, on the one hand, of faithful industries,
  • progressive energies, and productive ingenuities; or, on the other, it
  • may be indicative of mortal luxury, merciless tyranny, ruinous
  • chicane. Some treasures are heavy with human tears, as an ill-stored
  • harvest with untimely rain; and some gold is brighter in sunshine than
  • it is in substance.
  • And these are not, observe, merely moral or pathetic attributes of
  • riches, which the seeker of riches may, if he chooses, despise; they
  • are, literally and sternly, material attributes of riches,
  • depreciating or exalting, incalculably, the monetary signification of
  • the sum in question. One mass of money is the outcome of action which
  • has created,--another, of action which has annihilated,--ten times as
  • much in the gathering of it; such and such strong hands have been
  • paralysed, as if they had been numbed by nightshade: so many strong
  • men's courage broken, so many productive operations hindered; this and
  • the other false direction given to labour, and lying image of
  • prosperity set up, on Dura plains dug into seven-times-heated
  • furnaces. That which seems to be wealth may in verity be only the
  • gilded index of far-reaching ruin; a wrecker's handful of coin gleaned
  • from the beach to which he has beguiled an argosy; a camp-follower's
  • bundle of rags unwrapped from the breasts of goodly soldiers dead; the
  • purchase-pieces of potter's fields, wherein shall be buried together
  • the citizen and the stranger.
  • And therefore, the idea that directions can be given for the gaining
  • of wealth, irrespectively of the consideration of its moral sources,
  • or that any general and technical law of purchase and gain can be set
  • down for national practice, is perhaps the most insolently futile of
  • all that ever beguiled men through their vices. So far as I know,
  • there is not in history record of anything so disgraceful to the human
  • intellect as the modern idea that the commercial text, "Buy in the
  • cheapest market and sell in the dearest," represents, or under any
  • circumstances could represent, an available principle of national
  • economy. Buy in the cheapest market?--yes; but what made your market
  • cheap? Charcoal may be cheap among your roof timbers after a fire, and
  • bricks may be cheap in your streets after an earthquake; but fire and
  • earthquake may not therefore be national benefits. Sell in the
  • dearest?--yes, truly; but what made your market dear? You sold your
  • bread well to-day; was it to a dying man who gave his last coin for
  • it, and will never need bread more, or to a rich man who to-morrow
  • will buy your farm over your head; or to a soldier on his way to
  • pillage the bank in which you have put your fortune?
  • None of these things you can know. One thing only you can know,
  • namely, whether this dealing of yours is a just and faithful one,
  • which is all you need concern yourself about respecting it; sure thus
  • to have done your own part in bringing about ultimately in the world a
  • state of things which will not issue in pillage or in death. And thus
  • every question concerning these things merges itself ultimately in the
  • great question of justice, which, the ground being thus far cleared
  • for it, I will enter upon in the next paper, leaving only, in this,
  • three final points for the reader's consideration.
  • It has been shown that the chief value and virtue of money consists in
  • its having power over human beings; that, without this power, large
  • material possessions are useless, and, to any person possessing such
  • power, comparatively unnecessary. But power over human beings is
  • attainable by other means than by money. As I said a few pages back,
  • the money power is always imperfect and doubtful; there are many
  • things which cannot be reached with it, others which cannot be
  • retained by it. Many joys may be given to men which cannot be bought
  • for gold, and many fidelities found in them which cannot be rewarded
  • with it.
  • Trite enough,--the reader thinks. Yes: but it is not so trite,--I wish
  • it were,--that in this moral power, quite inscrutable and immeasurable
  • though it be, there is a monetary value just as real as that
  • represented by more ponderous currencies. A man's hand may be full of
  • invisible gold, and the wave of it, or the grasp, shall do more than
  • another's with a shower of bullion. This invisible gold, also, does
  • not necessarily diminish in spending. Political economists will do
  • well some day to take heed of it, though they cannot take measure.
  • But farther. Since the essence of wealth consists in its authority
  • over men, if the apparent or nominal wealth fail in this power, it
  • fails in essence; in fact, ceases to be wealth at all. It does not
  • appear lately in England, that our authority over men is absolute. The
  • servants show some disposition to rush riotously upstairs, under an
  • impression that their wages are not regularly paid. We should augur
  • ill of any gentleman's property to whom this happened every other day
  • in his drawing-room.
  • So also, the power of our wealth seems limited as respects the comfort
  • of the servants, no less than their quietude. The persons in the
  • kitchen appear to be ill-dressed, squalid, half-starved. One cannot
  • help imagining that the riches of the establishment must be of a very
  • theoretical and documentary character.
  • Finally. Since the essence of wealth consists in power over men, will
  • it not follow that the nobler and the more in number the persons are
  • over whom it has power, the greater the wealth? Perhaps it may even
  • appear after some consideration, that the persons themselves _are_ the
  • wealth--that these pieces of gold with which we are in the habit of
  • guiding them, are, in fact, nothing more than a kind of Byzantine
  • harness or trappings, very glittering and beautiful in barbaric sight,
  • wherewith we bridle the creatures; but that if these same living
  • creatures could be guided without the fretting and jingling of the
  • byzants in their mouths and ears, they might themselves be more
  • valuable than their bridles. In fact, it may be discovered that the
  • true veins of wealth are purple--and not in Rock, but in
  • Flesh--perhaps even that the final outcome and consummation of all
  • wealth is in the producing as many as possible full-breathed,
  • bright-eyed, and happy-hearted human creatures. Our modern wealth, I
  • think, has rather a tendency the other way;--most political economists
  • appearing to consider multitudes of human creatures not conducive to
  • wealth, or at best conducive to it only by remaining in a dim-eyed and
  • narrow-chested state of being.
  • Nevertheless, it is open, I repeat, to serious question, which I leave
  • to the reader's pondering, whether, among national manufactures, that
  • of Souls of a good quality may not at last turn out a quite leadingly
  • lucrative one? Nay, in some faraway and yet undreamt-of hour, I can
  • even imagine that England may cast all thoughts of possessive wealth
  • back to the barbaric nations among whom they first arose; and that,
  • while the sands of the Indus and adamant of Golconda may yet stiffen
  • the housings of the charger, and flash from the turban of the slave,
  • she, as a Christian mother, may at last attain to the virtues and the
  • treasures of a Heathen one, and be able to lead forth her Sons,
  • saying--
  • "These are MY Jewels."
  • ESSAY III.
  • "QUI JUDICATIS TERRAM."
  • Some centuries before the Christian era, a Jew merchant, largely
  • engaged in business on the Gold Coast, and reported to have made one
  • of the largest fortunes of his time (held also in repute for much
  • practical sagacity), left among his ledgers some general maxims
  • concerning wealth, which have been preserved, strangely enough, even
  • to our own days. They were held in considerable respect by the most
  • active traders of the middle ages, especially by the Venetians, who
  • even went so far in their admiration as to place a statue of the old
  • Jew on the angle of one of their principal public buildings. Of late
  • years these writings have fallen into disrepute, being opposed in
  • every particular to the spirit of modern commerce. Nevertheless, I
  • shall reproduce a passage or two from them here, partly because they
  • may interest the reader by their novelty; and chiefly because they
  • will show him that it is possible for a very practical and acquisitive
  • tradesman to hold, through a not unsuccessful career, that principle
  • of distinction between well-gotten and ill-gotten wealth, which,
  • partially insisted on in my last paper, it must be our work more
  • completely to examine in this.
  • He says, for instance, in one place: "The getting of treasures by a
  • lying tongue is a vanity tossed to and fro of them that seek death:"
  • adding in another, with the same meaning (he has a curious way of
  • doubling his sayings): "Treasures of wickedness profit nothing: but
  • justice delivers from death." Both these passages are notable for
  • their assertion of death as the only real issue and sum of attainment
  • by any unjust scheme of wealth. If we read, instead of "lying
  • tongue," "lying label, title, pretence, or advertisement," we shall
  • more clearly perceive the bearing of the words on modern business. The
  • seeking of death is a grand expression of the true course of men's
  • toil in such business. We usually speak as if death pursued us, and we
  • fled from him; but that is only so in rare instances. Ordinarily, he
  • masks himself--makes himself beautiful--all-glorious; not like the
  • King's daughter, all-glorious within, but outwardly: his clothing of
  • wrought gold. We pursue him frantically all our days, he flying or
  • hiding from us. Our crowning success at three-score and ten is utterly
  • and perfectly to seize, and hold him in his eternal integrity---robes,
  • ashes, and sting.
  • Again: the merchant says, "He that oppresseth the poor to increase his
  • riches, shall surely come to want." And again, more strongly: "Rob not
  • the poor because he is poor; neither oppress the afflicted in the
  • place of business. For God shall spoil the soul of those that spoiled
  • them."
  • This "robbing the poor because he is poor" is especially the
  • mercantile form of theft, consisting in taking advantage of a man's
  • necessities in order to obtain his labour or property at a reduced
  • price. The ordinary highwayman's opposite form of robbery--of the
  • rich, because he is rich--does not appear to occur so often to the old
  • merchant's mind; probably because, being less profitable and more
  • dangerous than the robbery of the poor, it is rarely practised by
  • persons of discretion.
  • But the two most remarkable passages in their deep general
  • significance are the following:--
  • "The rich and the poor have met. God is their maker."
  • "The rich and the poor have met. God is their light."
  • They "have met:" more literally, have stood in each other's way,
  • (_obviaverunt_). That is to say, as long as the world lasts, the
  • action and counteraction of wealth and poverty, the meeting, face to
  • face, of rich and poor, is just as appointed and necessary a law of
  • that world as the flow of stream to sea, or the interchange of power
  • among the electric clouds:--"God is their maker." But, also, this
  • action may be either gentle and just, or convulsive and destructive:
  • it may be by rage of devouring flood, or by lapse of serviceable
  • wave;--in blackness of thunderstroke, or continual force of vital
  • fire, soft, and shapeable into love-syllables from far away. And
  • which of these it shall be depends on both rich and poor knowing that
  • God is their light; that in the mystery of human life, there is no
  • other light than this by which they can see each other's faces, and
  • live;--light, which is called in another of the books among which the
  • merchant's maxims have been preserved, the "sun of justice,"[34] of
  • which it is promised that it shall rise at last with "healing"
  • (health-giving or helping, making whole or setting at one) in its
  • wings. For truly this healing is only possible by means of justice; no
  • love, no faith, no hope will do it; men will be unwisely fond--vainly
  • faithful, unless primarily they are just; and the mistake of the best
  • men through generation after generation, has been that great one of
  • thinking to help the poor by almsgiving, and by preaching of patience
  • or of hope, and by every other means, emollient or consolatory, except
  • the one thing which God orders for them, justice. But this justice,
  • with its accompanying holiness or helpfulness, being even by the best
  • men denied in its trial time, is by the mass of men hated wherever it
  • appears: so that, when the choice was one day fairly put to them, they
  • denied the Helpful One and the Just;[35] and desired a murderer,
  • sedition-raiser, and robber, to be granted to them;--the murderer
  • instead of the Lord of Life, the sedition-raiser instead of the Prince
  • of Peace, and the robber instead of the Just Judge of all the world.
  • [34] More accurately, Sun of Justness; but, instead of the harsh
  • word "Justness," the old English "Righteousness" being
  • commonly employed, has, by getting confused with
  • "godliness," or attracting about it various vague and broken
  • meanings, prevented most persons from receiving the force of
  • the passages in which it occurs. The word "righteousness"
  • properly refers to the justice of rule, or right, as
  • distinguished from "equity," which refers to the justice of
  • balance. More broadly, Righteousness is King's justice; and
  • Equity, Judge's justice; the King guiding or ruling all, the
  • Judge dividing or discerning between opposites (therefore,
  • the double question, "Man, who made me a ruler--[Greek:
  • dikastês]--or a divider--[Greek: meristês]--over you?")
  • Thus, with respect to the Justice of Choice (selection, the
  • feebler and passive justice), we have from lego,--lex,
  • legal, loi, and loyal; and with respect to the Justice of
  • Rule (direction, the stronger and active justice), we have
  • from rego,--rex, regal, roi, and royal.
  • [35] In another place written with the same meaning, "Just, and
  • having salvation."
  • I have just spoken of the flowing of streams to the sea as a partial
  • image of the action of wealth. In one respect it is not a partial, but
  • a perfect image. The popular economist thinks himself wise in having
  • discovered that wealth, or the forms of property in general, must go
  • where they are required; that where demand is, supply must follow. He
  • farther declares that this course of demand and supply cannot be
  • forbidden by human laws. Precisely in the same sense, and with the
  • same certainty, the waters of the world go where they are required.
  • Where the land falls, the water flows. The course neither of clouds
  • nor rivers can be forbidden by human will. But the disposition and
  • administration of them can be altered by human forethought. Whether
  • the stream shall be a curse or a blessing, depends upon man's labour,
  • and administrating intelligence. For centuries after centuries, great
  • districts of the world, rich in soil, and favoured in climate, have
  • lain desert under the rage of their own rivers; not only desert, but
  • plague-struck. The stream which, rightly directed, would have flowed
  • in soft irrigation from field to field--would have purified the air,
  • given food to man and beast, and carried their burdens for them on its
  • bosom--now overwhelms the plain, and poisons the wind; its breath
  • pestilence, and its work famine. In like manner this wealth "goes
  • where it is required." No human laws can withstand its flow. They can
  • only guide it: but this, the leading trench and limiting mound can do
  • so thoroughly, that it shall become water of life--the riches of the
  • hand of wisdom;[36] or, on the contrary, by leaving it to its own
  • lawless flow, they may make it, what it has been too often, the last
  • and deadliest of national plagues: water of Marah--the water which
  • feeds the roots of all evil.
  • [36] "Length of days in her right hand; in her left, riches
  • and honour."
  • The necessity of these laws of distribution or restraint is curiously
  • overlooked in the ordinary political economist's definition of his own
  • "science." He calls it, shortly, the "science of getting rich." But
  • there are many sciences, as well as many arts, of getting rich.
  • Poisoning people of large estates was one employed largely in the
  • middle ages; adulteration of food of people of small estates is one
  • employed largely now. The ancient and honourable Highland method of
  • black mail; the more modern and less honourable system of obtaining
  • goods on credit, and the other variously improved methods of
  • appropriation--which, in major and minor scales of industry, down to
  • the most artistic pocket-picking, we owe to recent genius,--all come
  • under the general head of sciences, or arts, of getting rich.
  • So that it is clear the popular economist, in calling his science the
  • science _par excellence_ of getting rich, must attach some peculiar
  • ideas of limitation to its character. I hope I do not misrepresent
  • him, by assuming that he means _his_ science to be the science of
  • "getting rich by legal or just means." In this definition, is the word
  • "just," or "legal," finally to stand? For it is possible among certain
  • nations, or under certain rulers, or by help of certain advocates,
  • that proceedings may be legal which are by no means just. If,
  • therefore, we leave at last only the word "just" in that place of our
  • definition, the insertion of this solitary and small word will make a
  • notable difference in the grammar of our science. For then it will
  • follow that, in order to grow rich scientifically we must grow rich
  • justly; and, therefore, know what is just; so that our economy will no
  • longer depend merely on prudence, but on jurisprudence--and that of
  • divine, not human law. Which prudence is indeed of no mean order,
  • holding itself, as it were, high in the air of heaven, and gazing for
  • ever on the light of the sun of justice; hence the souls which have
  • excelled in it are represented by Dante as stars forming in heaven for
  • ever the figure of the eye of an eagle: they having been in life the
  • discerners of light from darkness; or to the whole human race, as the
  • light of the body, which is the eye; while those souls which form the
  • wings of the bird (giving power and dominion to justice, "healing in
  • its wings") trace also in light the inscription in heaven: "DILIGITE
  • JUSTITIAM QUI JUDICATIS TERRAM." "Ye who judge the earth, give" (not,
  • observe, merely love, but) "diligent love to justice:" the love which
  • seeks diligently, that is to say, choosingly, and by preference to all
  • things else. Which judging or doing judgment in the earth is,
  • according to their capacity and position, required not of judges
  • only, nor of rulers only, but of all men:[37] a truth sorrowfully lost
  • sight of even by those who are ready enough to apply to themselves
  • passages in which Christian men are spoken of as called to be "saints"
  • (_i.e._, to helpful or healing functions); and "chosen to be kings"
  • (_i.e._, to knowing or directing functions); the true meaning of these
  • titles having been long lost through the pretences of unhelpful and
  • unable persons to saintly and kingly character; also through the once
  • popular idea that both the sanctity and royalty are to consist in
  • wearing long robes and high crowns, instead of in mercy and judgment;
  • whereas all true sanctity is saving power, as all true royalty is
  • ruling power; and injustice is part and parcel of the denial of such
  • power, which "makes men as the creeping things, as the fishes of the
  • sea, that have no ruler over them."[38]
  • [37] I hear that several of our lawyers have been greatly
  • amused by the statement in the first of these papers that a
  • lawyer's function was to do justice. I did not intend it for
  • a jest; nevertheless it will be seen that in the above
  • passage neither the determination nor doing of justice are
  • contemplated as functions wholly peculiar to the lawyer.
  • Possibly, the more our standing armies, whether of soldiers,
  • pastors, or legislators (the generic term "pastor" including
  • all teachers, and the generic term "lawyer" including makers
  • as well as interpreters of law), can be superseded by the
  • force of national heroism, wisdom, and honesty, the better
  • it may be for the nation.
  • [38] It being the privilege of the fishes, as it is of rats and
  • wolves, to live by the laws of demand and supply; but the
  • distinction of humanity, to live by those of right.
  • Absolute justice is indeed no more attainable than absolute truth; but
  • the righteous man is distinguished from the unrighteous by his desire
  • and hope of justice, as the true man from the false by his desire and
  • hope of truth. And though absolute justice be unattainable, as much
  • justice as we need for all practical use is attainable by all those
  • who make it their aim.
  • We have to examine, then, in the subject before us, what are the laws
  • of justice respecting payment of labour--no small part, these, of the
  • foundations of all jurisprudence.
  • I reduced, in my last paper, the idea of money payment to its simplest
  • or radical terms. In those terms its nature, and the conditions of
  • justice respecting it, can be best ascertained.
  • Money payment, as there stated, consists radically in a promise to
  • some person working for us, that for the time and labour he spends in
  • our service to-day we will give or procure equivalent time and labour
  • in his service at any future time when he may demand it.[39]
  • [39] It might appear at first that the market price of labour
  • expressed such an exchange: but this is a fallacy, for the
  • market price is the momentary price of the kind of labour
  • required, but the just price is its equivalent of the
  • productive labour of mankind. This difference will be
  • analysed in its place. It must be noted also that I speak
  • here only of the exchangeable value of labour, not of that
  • of commodities. The exchangeable value of a commodity is
  • that of the labour required to produce it, multiplied
  • into the force of the demand for it. If the value of the
  • labour = _x_ and the force of demand = _y_, the exchangeable
  • value of the commodity is _xy_, in which if either _x_ = 0,
  • or _y_ = 0, _xy_ = 0.
  • If we promise to give him less labour than he has given us, we
  • under-pay him. If we promise to give him more labour than he has given
  • us, we over-pay him. In practice, according to the laws of demand and
  • supply, when two men are ready to do the work, and only one man wants
  • to have it done, the two men under-bid each other for it; and the one
  • who gets it to do, is under-paid. But when two men want the work done,
  • and there is only one man ready to do it, the two men who want it done
  • over-bid each other, and the workman is over-paid.
  • I will examine these two points of injustice in succession, but first
  • I wish the reader to clearly understand the central principle lying
  • between the two, of right or just payment.
  • When we ask a service of any man, he may either give it us freely, or
  • demand payment for it. Respecting free gift of service, there is no
  • question at present, that being a matter of affection--not of traffic.
  • But if he demand payment for it, and we wish to treat him with
  • absolute equity, it is evident that this equity can only consist in
  • giving time for time, strength for strength, and skill for skill. If a
  • man works an hour for us, and we only promise to work half an hour for
  • him in return, we obtain an unjust advantage. If, on the contrary, we
  • promise to work an hour and a half for him in return, he has an unjust
  • advantage. The justice consists in absolute exchange; or, if there be
  • any respect to the stations of the parties, it will not be in favour
  • of the employer: there is certainly no equitable reason in a man's
  • being poor, that if he give me a pound of bread to-day, I should
  • return him less than a pound of bread to-morrow; or any equitable
  • reason in a man's being uneducated, that if he uses a certain quantity
  • of skill and knowledge in my service, I should use a less quantity of
  • skill and knowledge in his. Perhaps, ultimately, it may appear
  • desirable, or, to say the least, gracious, that I should give in
  • return somewhat more than I received. But at present, we are concerned
  • on the law of justice only, which is that of perfect and accurate
  • exchange;--one circumstance only interfering with the simplicity of
  • this radical idea of just payment--that inasmuch as labour (rightly
  • directed) is fruitful just as seed is, the fruit (or "interest" as it
  • is called) of the labour first given, or "advanced," ought to be taken
  • into account, and balanced by an additional quantity of labour in the
  • subsequent repayment. Supposing the repayment to take place at the end
  • of a year, or of any other given time, this calculation could be
  • approximately made; but as money (that is to say, cash) payment
  • involves no reference to time (it being optional with the person paid
  • to spend what he receives at once or after any number of years), we
  • can only assume, generally, that some slight advantage must in equity
  • be allowed to the person who advances the labour, so that the typical
  • form of bargain will be: If you give me an hour to-day, I will give
  • you an hour and five minutes on demand. If you give me a pound of
  • bread to-day, I will give you seventeen ounces on demand, and so on.
  • All that is necessary for the reader to note is, that the amount
  • returned is at least in equity not to be _less_ than the amount given.
  • The abstract idea, then, of just or due wages, as respects the
  • labourer, is that they will consist in a sum of money which will at
  • any time procure for him at least as much labour as he has given,
  • rather more than less. And this equity or justice of payment is,
  • observe, wholly independent of any reference to the number of men who
  • are willing to do the work. I want a horseshoe for my horse. Twenty
  • smiths, or twenty thousand smiths, may be ready to forge it; their
  • number does not in one atom's weight affect the question of the
  • equitable payment of the one who _does_ forge it. It costs him a
  • quarter of an hour of his life, and so much skill and strength of arm
  • to make that horseshoe for me. Then at some future time I am bound in
  • equity to give a quarter of an hour, and some minutes more, of my life
  • (or of some other person's at my disposal), and also as much strength
  • of arm and skill, and a little more, in making or doing what the smith
  • may have need of.
  • Such being the abstract theory of just remunerative payment, its
  • application is practically modified by the fact that the order for
  • labour, given in payment, is general, while the labour received is
  • special. The current coin or document is practically an order on the
  • nation for so much work of any kind; and this universal applicability
  • to immediate need renders it so much more valuable than special labour
  • can be, that an order for a less quantity of this general toil will
  • always be accepted as a just equivalent for a greater quantity of
  • special toil. Any given craftsman will always be willing to give an
  • hour of his own work in order to receive command over half an hour, or
  • even much less, of national work. This source of uncertainty, together
  • with the difficulty of determining the monetary value of skill,[40]
  • renders the ascertainment (even approximate) of the proper wages of
  • any given labour in terms of currency, matter of considerable
  • complexity. But they do not affect the principle of exchange. The
  • worth of the work may not be easily known; but it _has_ a worth, just
  • as fixed and real as the specific gravity of a substance, though such
  • specific gravity may not be easily ascertainable when the substance is
  • united with many others. Nor is there so much difficulty or chance in
  • determining it as in determining the ordinary maxima and minima of
  • vulgar political economy. There are few bargains in which the buyer
  • can ascertain with anything like precision that the seller would have
  • taken no less;--or the seller acquire more than a comfortable faith
  • that the purchaser would have given no more. This impossibility of
  • precise knowledge prevents neither from striving to attain the desired
  • point of greatest vexation and injury to the other, nor from accepting
  • it for a scientific principle that he is to buy for the least and sell
  • for the most possible, though what the real least or most may be he
  • cannot tell. In like manner, a just person lays it down for a
  • scientific principle that he is to pay a just price, and, without
  • being able precisely to ascertain the limits of such a price, will
  • nevertheless strive to attain the closest possible approximation to
  • them. A practically serviceable approximation he _can_ obtain. It is
  • easier to determine scientifically what a man ought to have for his
  • work, than what his necessities will compel him to take for it. His
  • necessities can only be ascertained by empirical, but his due by
  • analytical, investigation. In the one case, you try your answer to the
  • sum like a puzzled schoolboy--till you find one that fits; in the
  • other, you bring out your result within certain limits, by process of
  • calculation.
  • [40] Under the term "skill" I mean to include the united force of
  • experience, intellect, and passion in their operation on
  • manual labour: and under the term "passion," to include the
  • entire range and agency of the moral feelings; from the
  • simple patience and gentleness of mind which will give
  • continuity and fineness to the touch, or enable one person
  • to work without fatigue, and with good effect, twice as long
  • as another, up to the qualities of character which render
  • science possible--(the retardation of science by envy is one
  • of the most tremendous losses in the economy of the present
  • century)--and to the incommunicable emotion and imagination
  • which are the first and mightiest sources of all value in
  • art.
  • It is highly singular that political economists should not
  • yet have perceived, if not the moral, at least the
  • passionate element, to be an inextricable quantity in every
  • calculation. I cannot conceive, for instance, how it was
  • possible that Mr. Mill should have followed the true clue so
  • far as to write,--"No limit can be set to the
  • importance--even in a purely productive and material point
  • of view--of mere thought," without seeing that it was
  • logically necessary to add also, "and of mere feeling." And
  • this the more, because in his first definition of labour he
  • includes in the idea of it "all feelings of a disagreeable
  • kind connected with the employment of one's thoughts in a
  • particular occupation." True; but why not also, "feelings of
  • an agreeable kind?" It can hardly be supposed that the
  • feelings which retard labour are more essentially a part of
  • the labour than those which accelerate it. The first are
  • paid for as pain, the second as power. The workman is merely
  • indemnified for the first; but the second both produce a
  • part of the exchangeable value of the work, and materially
  • increase its actual quantity.
  • "Fritz is with us. _He_ is worth fifty thousand men." Truly,
  • a large addition to the material force;--consisting,
  • however, be it observed, not more in operations carried on
  • in Fritz's head, than in operations carried on in his
  • armies' heart. "No limit can be set to the importance of
  • _mere_ thought." Perhaps not! Nay, suppose some day it
  • should turn out that "mere" thought was in itself a
  • recommendable object of production, and that all Material
  • production was only a step towards this more precious
  • Immaterial one?
  • Supposing, then, the just wages of any quantity of given labour to
  • have been ascertained, let us examine the first results of just and
  • unjust payment, when in favour of the purchaser or employer; _i.e._,
  • when two men are ready to do the work, and only one wants to have it
  • done.
  • The unjust purchaser forces the two to bid against each other till he
  • has reduced their demand to its lowest terms. Let us assume that the
  • lowest bidder offers to do the work at half its just price.
  • The purchaser employs him, and does not employ the other. The first or
  • _apparent_ result, is, therefore, that one of the two men is left out
  • of employ, or to starvation, just as definitely as by the just
  • procedure of giving fair price to the best workman. The various
  • writers who endeavoured to invalidate the positions of my first paper
  • never saw this, and assumed that the unjust hirer employed _both_. He
  • employs both no more than the just hirer. The only difference (in the
  • outset) is that the just man pays sufficiently, the unjust man
  • insufficiently, for the labour of the single person employed.
  • I say, in "the outset;" for this first or apparent difference is not
  • the actual difference. By the unjust procedure, half the proper price
  • of the work is left in the hands of the employer. This enables him to
  • hire another man at the same unjust rate on some other kind of work;
  • and the final result is that he has two men working for him at
  • half-price, and two are out of employ.
  • By the just procedure, the whole price of the first piece of work goes
  • into the hands of the man who does it. No surplus being left in the
  • employer's hands, _he_ cannot hire another man for another piece of
  • labour. But by precisely so much as his power is diminished, the hired
  • workman's power is increased; that is to say, by the additional half
  • of the price he has received; which additional half _he_ has the power
  • of using to employ another man in _his_ service. I will suppose, for
  • the moment, the least favourable, though quite probable, case--that,
  • though justly treated himself, he yet will act unjustly to his
  • subordinate; and hire at half-price, if he can. The final result will
  • then be, that one man works for the employer, at just price; one for
  • the workman, at half-price; and two, as in the first case, are still
  • out of employ. These two, as I said before, are out of employ in
  • _both_ cases. The difference between the just and unjust procedure
  • does not lie in the number of men hired, but in the price paid to
  • them, and the _persons by whom_ it is paid. The essential difference,
  • that which I want the reader to see clearly, is, that in the unjust
  • case, two men work for one, the first hirer. In the just case, one man
  • works for the first hirer, one for the person hired, and so on, down
  • or up through the various grades of service; the influence being
  • carried forward by justice, and arrested by injustice. The universal
  • and constant action of justice in this matter is therefore to diminish
  • the power of wealth, in the hands of one individual, over masses of
  • men, and to distribute it through a chain of men. The actual power
  • exerted by the wealth is the same in both cases; but by injustice it
  • is put all into one man's hands, so that he directs at once and with
  • equal force the labour of a circle of men about him; by the just
  • procedure, he is permitted to touch the nearest only, through whom,
  • with diminished force, modified by new minds, the energy of the wealth
  • passes on to others, and so till it exhausts itself.
  • The immediate operation of justice in this respect is, therefore, to
  • diminish the power of wealth, first in acquisition of luxury, and,
  • secondly, in exercise of moral influence. The employer cannot
  • concentrate so multitudinous labour on his own interests, nor can he
  • subdue so multitudinous mind to his own will. But the secondary
  • operation of justice is not less important. The insufficient payment
  • of the group of men working for one, places each under a maximum of
  • difficulty in rising above his position. The tendency of the system is
  • to check advancement. But the sufficient or just payment, distributed
  • through a descending series of offices or grades of labour,[41] gives
  • each subordinated person fair and sufficient means of rising in the
  • social scale, if he chooses to use them; and thus not only diminishes
  • the immediate power of wealth, but removes the worst disabilities of
  • poverty.
  • [41] I am sorry to lose time by answering, however curtly, the
  • equivocations of the writers who sought to obscure the
  • instances given of regulated labour in the first of these
  • papers, by confusing kinds, ranks, and quantities of labour
  • with its qualities. I never said that a colonel should have
  • the same pay as a private, nor a bishop the same pay as a
  • curate. Neither did I say that more work ought to be paid as
  • less work (so that the curate of a parish of two thousand
  • souls should have no more than the curate of a parish of
  • five hundred). But I said that, so far as you employ it at
  • all, bad work should be paid no less than good work; as a
  • bad clergyman yet takes his tithes, a bad physician takes
  • his fee, and a bad lawyer his costs. And this, as will be
  • farther shown in the conclusion, I said, and say, partly
  • because the best work never was, nor ever will be, done for
  • money at all; but chiefly because, the moment people know
  • they have to pay the bad and good alike, they will try to
  • discern the one from the other, and not use the bad. A
  • sagacious writer in the _Scotsman_ asks me if I should like
  • any common scribbler to be paid by Messrs. Smith, Elder and
  • Co. [the original publishers of this work] as their good
  • authors are. I should, if they employed him--but would
  • seriously recommend them, for the scribbler's sake, as well
  • as their own, _not_ to employ him. The quantity of its money
  • which the country at present invests in scribbling is not,
  • in the outcome of it, economically spent; and even the
  • highly ingenious person to whom this question occurred,
  • might perhaps have been more beneficially employed than in
  • printing it.
  • It is on this vital problem that the entire destiny of the labourer is
  • ultimately dependent. Many minor interests may sometimes appear to
  • interfere with it, but all branch from it. For instance, considerable
  • agitation is often caused in the minds of the lower classes when they
  • discover the share which they nominally, and to all appearance,
  • actually, pay out of their wages in taxation (I believe thirty-five or
  • forty per cent.). This sounds very grievous; but in reality the
  • labourer does not pay it, but his employer. If the workman had not to
  • pay it, his wages would be less by just that sum: competition would
  • still reduce them to the lowest rate at which life was possible.
  • Similarly the lower orders agitated for the repeal of the corn
  • laws,[42] thinking they would be better off if bread were cheaper;
  • never perceiving that as soon as bread was permanently cheaper, wages
  • would permanently fall in precisely that proportion. The corn laws
  • were rightly repealed; not, however, because they directly oppressed
  • the poor, but because they indirectly oppressed them in causing a
  • large quantity of their labour to be consumed unproductively. So also
  • unnecessary taxation oppresses them, through destruction of capital,
  • but the destiny of the poor depends primarily always on this one
  • question of dueness of wages. Their distress (irrespectively of that
  • caused by sloth, minor error, or crime) arises on the grand scale from
  • the two reacting forces of competition and oppression. There is not
  • yet, nor will yet for ages be, any real over-population in the world;
  • but a local over-population, or, more accurately, a degree of
  • population locally unmanageable under existing circumstances for want
  • of forethought and sufficient machinery, necessarily shows itself by
  • pressure of competition; and the taking advantage of this competition
  • by the purchaser to obtain their labour unjustly cheap, consummates at
  • once their suffering and his own; for in this (as I believe in every
  • other kind of slavery) the oppressor suffers at last more than the
  • oppressed, and those magnificent lines of Pope, even in all their
  • force, fall short of the truth--
  • "Yet, to be just to these poor men of pelf,
  • Each does but HATE HIS NEIGHBOUR AS HIMSELF:
  • Damned to the mines, an equal fate betides
  • The slave that digs it, and the slave that hides."
  • [42] I have to acknowledge an interesting communication on the
  • subject of free trade from Paisley (for a short letter from
  • "A Well-wisher" at ----, my thanks are yet more due). But
  • the Scottish writer will, I fear, be disagreeably surprised
  • to hear, that I am, and always have been, an utterly
  • fearless and unscrupulous free trader. Seven years ago,
  • speaking of the various signs of infancy in the European
  • mind (_Stones of Venice_, vol. iii. p. 168), I wrote: "The
  • first principles of commerce were acknowledged by the
  • English parliament only a few months ago, in its free trade
  • measures, and are still so little understood by the million,
  • that _no nation dares to abolish its custom-houses_."
  • It will be observed that I do not admit even the idea of
  • reciprocity. Let other nations, if they like, keep their
  • ports shut; every wise nation will throw its own open. It is
  • not the opening them, but a sudden, inconsiderate, and
  • blunderingly experimental manner of opening them, which does
  • harm. If you have been protecting a manufacture for a long
  • series of years, you must not take the protection off in a
  • moment, so as to throw every one of its operatives at once
  • out of employ, any more than you must take all its wrappings
  • off a feeble child at once in cold weather, though the
  • cumber of them may have been radically injuring its health.
  • Little by little, you must restore it to freedom and to air.
  • Most people's minds are in curious confusion on the subject
  • of free trade, because they suppose it to imply enlarged
  • competition. On the contrary, free trade puts an end to all
  • competition. "Protection" (among various other mischievous
  • functions) endeavours to enable one country to compete with
  • another in the production of an article at a disadvantage.
  • When trade is entirely free, no country can be competed with
  • in the articles for the production of which it is naturally
  • calculated; nor can it compete with any other, in the
  • production of articles for which it is not naturally
  • calculated. Tuscany, for instance, cannot compete with
  • England in steel, nor England with Tuscany in oil. They must
  • exchange their steel and oil. Which exchange should be as
  • frank and free as honesty and the sea-winds can make it.
  • Competition, indeed, arises at first, and sharply, in order
  • to prove which is strongest in any given manufacture
  • possible to both: this point once ascertained, competition
  • is at an end.
  • The collateral and reversionary operations of justice in this matter I
  • shall examine hereafter (it being needful first to define the nature
  • of value); proceeding then to consider within what practical terms a
  • juster system may be established; and ultimately the vexed question of
  • the destinies of the unemployed workmen.[43] Lest, however, the reader
  • should be alarmed at some of the issues to which our investigations
  • seem to be tending, as if in their bearing against the power of wealth
  • they had something in common with those of socialism, I wish him to
  • know, in accurate terms, one or two of the main points which I have in
  • view.
  • [43] I should be glad if the reader would first clear the ground
  • for himself so far as to determine whether the difficulty
  • lies in getting the work or getting the pay for it. Does he
  • consider occupation itself to be an expensive luxury,
  • difficult of attainment, of which too little is to be found
  • in the world? or is it rather that, while in the enjoyment
  • even of the most athletic delight, men must nevertheless be
  • maintained, and this maintenance is not always forthcoming?
  • We must be clear on this head before going farther, as most
  • people are loosely in the habit of talking of the difficulty
  • of "finding employment." Is it employment that we want to
  • find, or support during employment? Is it idleness we wish
  • to put an end to, or hunger? We have to take up both
  • questions in succession, only not both at the same time. No
  • doubt that work _is_ a luxury, and a very great one. It is,
  • indeed, at once a luxury and a necessity; no man can retain
  • either health of mind or body without it. So profoundly do I
  • feel this, that, as will be seen in the sequel, one of the
  • principal objects I would recommend to benevolent and
  • practical persons, is to induce rich people to seek for a
  • larger quantity of this luxury than they at present possess.
  • Nevertheless, it appears by experience that even this
  • healthiest of pleasures may be indulged in to excess, and
  • that human beings are just as liable to surfeit of labour as
  • to surfeit of meat; so that, as on the one hand, it may be
  • charitable to provide, for some people, lighter dinner, and
  • more work,--for others, it may be equally expedient to
  • provide lighter work, and more dinner.
  • Whether socialism has made more progress among the army and navy
  • (where payment is made on my principles), or among the manufacturing
  • operatives (who are paid on my opponents' principles), I leave it to
  • those opponents to ascertain and declare. Whatever their conclusions
  • may be, I think it necessary to answer for myself only this: that if
  • there be any one point insisted on throughout my works more frequently
  • than another, that one point is the impossibility of Equality. My
  • continual aim has been to show the eternal superiority of some men to
  • others, sometimes even of one man to all others; and to show also the
  • advisability of appointing such persons or person to guide, to lead,
  • or on occasion even to compel and subdue, their inferiors, according
  • to their own better knowledge and wiser will. My principles of
  • Political Economy were all involved in a single phrase spoken three
  • years ago at Manchester: "Soldiers of the Ploughshare as well as
  • Soldiers of the Sword:" and they were all summed in a single sentence
  • in the last volume of _Modern Painters_--"Government and co-operation
  • are in all things the Laws of Life; Anarchy and competition the Laws
  • of Death."
  • And with respect to the mode in which these general principles affect
  • the secure possession of property, so far am I from invalidating such
  • security, that the whole gist of these papers will be found ultimately
  • to aim at an extension in its range; and whereas it has long been
  • known and declared that the poor have no right to the property of the
  • rich, I wish it also to be known and declared that the rich have no
  • right to the property of the poor.
  • But that the working of the system which I have undertaken to develop
  • would in many ways shorten the apparent and direct, though not the
  • unseen and collateral, power, both of wealth, as the Lady of Pleasure,
  • and of capital, as the Lord of Toil, I do not deny: on the contrary, I
  • affirm it in all joyfulness; knowing that the attraction of riches is
  • already too strong, as their authority is already too weighty, for the
  • reason of mankind. I said in my last paper that nothing in history had
  • ever been so disgraceful to human intellect as the acceptance among us
  • of the common doctrines of political economy as a science. I have many
  • grounds for saying this, but one of the chief may be given in few
  • words. I know no previous instance in history of a nation's
  • establishing a systematic disobedience to the first principles of its
  • professed religion. The writings which we (verbally) esteem as divine,
  • not only denounce the love of money as the source of all evil, and as
  • an idolatry abhorred of the Deity, but declare mammon service to be
  • the accurate and irreconcileable opposite of God's service; and,
  • whenever they speak of riches absolute, and poverty absolute, declare
  • woe to the rich, and blessing to the poor. Whereupon we forthwith
  • investigate a science of becoming rich, as the shortest road to
  • national prosperity.
  • "Tai Cristian dannerà l'Etiòpe,
  • Quando si partiranno i due collegi,
  • L'UNO IN ETERNO RICCO, E L'ALTRO INÃ’PE."
  • ESSAY IV.
  • AD VALOREM.
  • In the last paper we saw that just payment of labour consisted in a
  • sum of money which would approximately obtain equivalent labour at a
  • future time: we have now to examine the means of obtaining such
  • equivalence. Which question involves the definition of Value, Wealth,
  • Price, and Produce.
  • None of these terms are yet defined so as to be understood by the
  • public. But the last, Produce, which one might have thought the
  • clearest of all, is, in use, the most ambiguous; and the examination
  • of the kind of ambiguity attendant on its present employment will best
  • open the way to our work.
  • In his Chapter on Capital,[44] Mr. J. S. Mill instances, as a
  • capitalist, a hardware manufacturer, who, having intended to spend a
  • certain portion of the proceeds of his business in buying plate and
  • jewels, changes his mind, and "pays it as wages to additional
  • workpeople." The effect is stated by Mr. Mill to be that "more food is
  • appropriated to the consumption of productive labourers."
  • [44] Book I. chap. iv. s. 1. To save space, my future references
  • to Mr. Mill's work will be by numerals only, as in this
  • instance, I. iv. 1. Ed. in 2 vols. 8vo, Parker, 1848.
  • Now I do not ask, though, had I written this paragraph, it would
  • surely have been asked of me, What is to become of the silversmiths?
  • If they are truly unproductive persons, we will acquiesce in their
  • extinction. And though in another part of the same passage, the
  • hardware merchant is supposed also to dispense with a number of
  • servants, whose "food is thus set free for productive purposes," I do
  • not inquire what will be the effect, painful or otherwise, upon the
  • servants, of this emancipation of their food. But I very seriously
  • inquire why ironware is produce, and silverware is not? That the
  • merchant consumes the one, and sells the other, certainly does not
  • constitute the difference, unless it can be shown (which, indeed, I
  • perceive it to be becoming daily more and more the aim of tradesmen to
  • show) that commodities are made to be sold, and not to be consumed.
  • The merchant is an agent of conveyance to the consumer in one case,
  • and is himself the consumer in the other:[45] but the labourers are in
  • either case equally productive, since they have produced goods to the
  • same value, if the hardware and the plate are both goods.
  • [45] If Mr. Mill had wished to show the difference in result
  • between consumption and sale, he should have represented the
  • hardware merchant as consuming his own goods instead of
  • selling them; similarly, the silver merchant as consuming
  • his own goods instead of selling them. Had he done this, he
  • would have made his position clearer, though less tenable;
  • and perhaps this was the position he really intended to
  • take, tacitly involving his theory, elsewhere stated, and
  • shown in the sequel of this paper to be false, that demand
  • for commodities is not demand for labour. But by the most
  • diligent scrutiny of the paragraph now under examination, I
  • cannot determine whether it is a fallacy pure and simple, or
  • the half of one fallacy supported by the whole of a greater
  • one; so that I treat it here on the kinder assumption that
  • it is one fallacy only.
  • And what distinction separates them? It is indeed possible that in the
  • "comparative estimate of the moralist," with which Mr. Mill says
  • political economy has nothing to do (III. i. 2), a steel fork might
  • appear a more substantial production than a silver one: we may grant
  • also that knives, no less than forks, are good produce; and scythes
  • and ploughshares serviceable articles. But, how of bayonets? Supposing
  • the hardware merchant to effect large sales of _these_, by help of the
  • "setting free" of the food of his servants and his silversmith,--is
  • he still employing productive labourers, or, in Mr. Mill's words,
  • labourers who increase "the stock of permanent means of enjoyment"
  • (I. iii. 4)? Or if, instead of bayonets, he supply bombs, will not the
  • absolute and final "enjoyment" of even these energetically productive
  • articles (each of which costs ten pounds[46]) be dependent on a proper
  • choice of time and place for their _enfantement_; choice, that is to
  • say, depending on those philosophical considerations with which
  • political economy has nothing to do?[47]
  • [46] I take Mr. [afterwards Sir A.] Helps' estimate in his essay
  • on War.
  • [47] Also when the wrought silver vases of Spain were dashed to
  • fragments by our custom-house officers, because bullion
  • might be imported free of duty, but not brains, was the axe
  • that broke them productive?--the artist who wrought them
  • unproductive? Or again. If the woodman's axe is productive,
  • is the executioner's? as also, if the hemp of a cable be
  • productive, does not the productiveness of hemp in a halter
  • depend on its moral more than on its material application?
  • I should have regretted the need of pointing out inconsistency in any
  • portion of Mr. Mill's work, had not the value of his work proceeded
  • from its inconsistencies. He deserves honour among economists by
  • inadvertently disclaiming the principles which he states, and tacitly
  • introducing the moral considerations with which he declares his
  • science has no connection. Many of his chapters, are, therefore, true
  • and valuable; and the only conclusions of his which I have to dispute
  • are those which follow from his premises.
  • Thus, the idea which lies at the root of the passage we have just been
  • examining, namely, that labour applied to produce luxuries will not
  • support so many persons as labour applied to produce useful articles,
  • is entirely true; but the instance given fails--and in four directions
  • of failure at once--because Mr. Mill has not defined the real meaning
  • of usefulness. The definition which he has given--"capacity to satisfy
  • a desire, or serve a purpose" (III. i. 2)--applies equally to the iron
  • and silver; while the true definition,--which he has not given, but
  • which nevertheless underlies the false verbal definition in his mind,
  • and comes out once or twice by accident (as in the words "any support
  • to life or strength" in I. i. 5)--applies to some articles of iron,
  • but not to others, and to some articles of silver, but not to others.
  • It applies to ploughs, but not to bayonets; and to forks, but not to
  • filigree.[48]
  • [48] Filigree: that is to say, generally, ornament dependent
  • on complexity, not on art.
  • The eliciting of the true definition will give us the reply to our
  • first question, "What is value?" respecting which, however, we must
  • first hear the popular statements.
  • "The word 'value,' when used without adjunct, always means, in
  • political economy, value in exchange" (Mill, III. i. 3). So that,
  • if two ships cannot exchange their rudders, their rudders are, in
  • politico-economic language, of no value to either.
  • But "the subject of political economy is wealth."--(Preliminary
  • remarks, page 1.)
  • And wealth "consists of all useful and agreeable objects which possess
  • exchangeable value."--(Preliminary remarks, page 10.)
  • It appears then, according to Mr. Mill, that usefulness and
  • agreeableness underlie the exchange value, and must be ascertained to
  • exist in the thing, before we can esteem it an object of wealth.
  • Now, the economical usefulness of a thing depends not merely on its
  • own nature, but on the number of people who can and will use it. A
  • horse is useless, and therefore unsaleable, if no one can ride,--a
  • sword if no one can strike, and meat, if no one can eat. Thus every
  • material utility depends on its relative human capacity.
  • Similarly: The agreeableness of a thing depends not merely on its own
  • likeableness, but on the number of people who can be got to like it.
  • The relative agreeableness, and therefore saleableness, of "a pot of
  • the smallest ale," and of "Adonis painted by a running brook," depends
  • virtually on the opinion of Demos, in the shape of Christopher Sly.
  • That is to say, the agreeableness of a thing depends on its relative
  • human disposition.[49] Therefore, political economy, being a science
  • of wealth, must be a science respecting human capacities and
  • dispositions. But moral considerations have nothing to do with
  • political economy (III. i. 2). Therefore, moral considerations have
  • nothing to do with human capacities and dispositions.
  • [49] These statements sound crude in their brevity; but will
  • be found of the utmost importance when they are developed.
  • Thus, in the above instance, economists have never perceived
  • that disposition to buy is a wholly _moral_ element in
  • demand: that is to say, when you give a man half-a-crown, it
  • depends on his disposition whether he is rich or poor with
  • it--whether he will buy disease, ruin, and hatred, or buy
  • health, advancement, and domestic love. And thus the
  • agreeableness or exchange value of every offered commodity
  • depends on production, not merely of the commodity, but of
  • buyers of it; therefore on the education of buyers, and on
  • all the moral elements by which their disposition to buy
  • this, or that, is formed. I will illustrate and expand into
  • final consequences every one of these definitions in its
  • place: at present they can only be given with extremest
  • brevity; for in order to put the subject at once in a
  • connected form before the reader, I have thrown into one,
  • the opening definitions of four chapters; namely, of that on
  • Value ("Ad Valorem"); on Price ("Thirty Pieces"); on
  • Production ("Demeter"); and on Economy ("The Law of the
  • House").
  • I do not wholly like the look of this conclusion from Mr. Mill's
  • statements:--let us try Mr. Ricardo's.
  • "Utility is not the measure of exchangeable value, though it is
  • absolutely essential to it."--(Chap. 1. sect. i.) Essential to what
  • degree, Mr. Ricardo? There may be greater and less degrees of utility.
  • Meat, for instance, may be so good as to be fit for any one to eat, or
  • so bad as to be fit for no one to eat. What is the exact degree of
  • goodness which is "essential" to its exchangeable value, but not "the
  • measure" of it? How good must the meat be, in order to possess any
  • exchangeable value; and how bad must it be--(I wish this were a
  • settled question in London markets)--in order to possess none?
  • There appears to be some hitch, I think, in the working even of Mr.
  • Ricardo's principles; but let him take his own example. "Suppose that
  • in the early stages of society the bows and arrows of the hunter were
  • of equal value with the implements of the fisherman. Under such
  • circumstances the value of the deer, the produce of the hunter's day's
  • labour, would be _exactly_" (italics mine) "equal to the value of the
  • fish, the product of the fisherman's day's labour. The comparative
  • value of the fish and game would be _entirely_ regulated by the
  • quantity of labour realized in each." (Ricardo, chap. iii. On Value.)
  • Indeed! Therefore, if the fisherman catches one sprat, and the
  • huntsman one deer, one sprat will be equal in value to one deer; but
  • if the fisherman catches no sprat, and the huntsman two deer, no sprat
  • will be equal in value to two deer?
  • Nay; but--Mr. Ricardo's supporters may say--he means, on an
  • average;--if the average product of a day's work of fisher and hunter
  • be one fish and one deer, the one fish will always be equal in value
  • to the one deer.
  • Might I inquire the species of fish. Whale? or whitebait?[50]
  • [50] Perhaps it may be said, in farther support of Mr. Ricardo,
  • that he meant, "when the utility is constant or given, the
  • price varies as the quantity of labour." If he meant this,
  • he should have said it; but, had he meant it, he could have
  • hardly missed the necessary result, that utility would be
  • one measure of price (which he expressly denies it to be);
  • and that, to prove saleableness, he had to prove a given
  • quantity of utility, as well as a given quantity of labour:
  • to wit, in his own instance, that the deer and fish would
  • each feed the same number of men, for the same number of
  • days, with equal pleasure to their palates. The fact is, he
  • did not know what he meant himself. The general idea which
  • he had derived from commercial experience, without being
  • able to analyse it, was, that when the demand is constant,
  • the price varies as the quantity of labour required for
  • production; or,--using the formula I gave in last
  • paper--when _y_ is constant, _xy_ varies as _x_. But demand
  • never is, nor can be, ultimately constant, if _x_ varies
  • distinctly; for, as price rises, consumers fall away; and as
  • soon as there is a monopoly (and all scarcity is a form of
  • monopoly; so that every commodity is affected occasionally
  • by some colour of monopoly), _y_ becomes the most
  • influential condition of the price. Thus the price of a
  • painting depends less on its merit than on the interest
  • taken in it by the public; the price of singing less on the
  • labour of the singer than the number of persons who desire
  • to hear him; and the price of gold less on the scarcity
  • which affects it in common with cerium or iridium, than on
  • the sun-light colour and unalterable purity by which it
  • attracts the admiration and answers the trust of mankind.
  • It must be kept in mind, however, that I use the word
  • "demand" in a somewhat different sense from economists
  • usually. They mean by it "the quantity of a thing sold." I
  • mean by it "the force of the buyer's capable intention to
  • buy." In good English, a person's "demand" signifies, not
  • what he gets, but what he asks for.
  • Economists also do not notice that objects are not valued by
  • absolute bulk or weight, but by such bulk and weight as is
  • necessary to bring them into use. They say, for instance,
  • that water bears no price in the market. It is true that a
  • cupful does not, but a lake does; just as a handful of dust
  • does not, but an acre does. And were it possible to make
  • even the possession of the cupful or handful permanent
  • (_i.e._, to find a place for them), the earth and sea would
  • be bought up by handfuls and cupfuls.
  • It would be waste of time to pursue these fallacies farther; we will
  • seek for a true definition.
  • Much store has been set for centuries upon the use of our English
  • classical education. It were to be wished that our well-educated
  • merchants recalled to mind always this much of their Latin
  • schooling,--that the nominative of _valorem_ (a word already
  • sufficiently familiar to them) is _valor_; a word which, therefore,
  • ought to be familiar to them. _Valor_, from _valere_, to be well, or
  • strong ([Greek: hugiainô]);--strong, _in_ life (if a man), or valiant;
  • strong, _for_ life (if a thing), or valuable. To be "valuable,"
  • therefore, is to "avail towards life." A truly valuable or availing
  • thing is that which leads to life with its whole strength. In
  • proportion as it does not lead to life, or as its strength is broken,
  • it is less valuable; in proportion as it leads away from life, it is
  • unvaluable or malignant.
  • The value of a thing, therefore, is independent of opinion, and of
  • quantity. Think what you will of it, gain how much you may of it, the
  • value of the thing itself is neither greater nor less. For ever it
  • avails, or avails not; no estimate can raise, no disdain depress, the
  • power which it holds from the Maker of things and of men.
  • The real science of political economy, which has yet to be
  • distinguished from the bastard science, as medicine from witchcraft,
  • and astronomy from astrology, is that which teaches nations to desire
  • and labour for the things that lead to life; and which teaches them to
  • scorn and destroy the things that lead to destruction. And if, in a
  • state of infancy, they suppose indifferent things, such as
  • excrescences of shellfish, and pieces of blue and red stone, to be
  • valuable, and spend large measure of the labour which ought to be
  • employed for the extension and ennobling of life, in diving or digging
  • for them, and cutting them into various shapes,--or if, in the same
  • state of infancy, they imagine precious and beneficent things, such as
  • air, light, and cleanliness, to be valueless,--or if, finally, they
  • imagine the conditions of their own existence, by which alone they can
  • truly possess or use anything, such, for instance, as peace, trust,
  • and love, to be prudently exchangeable, when the market offers, for
  • gold, iron, or excrescences of shells--the great and only science of
  • Political Economy teaches them, in all these cases, what is vanity,
  • and what substance; and how the service of Death, the Lord of Waste,
  • and of eternal emptiness, differs from the service of Wisdom, the Lady
  • of Saving, and of eternal fulness; she who has said, "I will cause
  • those that love me to inherit SUBSTANCE; and I will FILL their
  • treasures."
  • The "Lady of Saving," in a profounder sense than that of the savings'
  • bank, though that is a good one: Madonna della Salute,--Lady of
  • Health--which, though commonly spoken of as if separate from wealth,
  • is indeed a part of wealth. This word, "wealth," it will be
  • remembered, is the next we have to define.
  • "To be wealthy," says Mr. Mill, is "to have a large stock of useful
  • articles."
  • I accept this definition. Only let us perfectly understand it. My
  • opponents often lament my not giving them enough logic: I fear I must
  • at present use a little more than they will like; but this business of
  • Political Economy is no light one, and we must allow no loose terms in
  • it.
  • We have, therefore, to ascertain in the above definition, first, what
  • is the meaning of "having," or the nature of Possession. Then, what is
  • the meaning of "useful," or the nature of Utility.
  • And first of possession. At the crossing of the transepts of Milan
  • Cathedral has lain, for three hundred years, the embalmed body of St.
  • Carlo Borromeo. It holds a golden crosier, and has a cross of emeralds
  • on its breast. Admitting the crosier and emeralds to be useful
  • articles, is the body to be considered as "having" them? Do they, in
  • the politico-economical sense of property, belong to it? If not, and
  • if we may, therefore, conclude generally that a dead body cannot
  • possess property, what degree and period of animation in the body will
  • render possession possible?
  • As thus: lately in a wreck of a Californian ship, one of the
  • passengers fastened a belt about him with two hundred pounds of gold
  • in it, with which he was found afterwards at the bottom. Now, as he
  • was sinking--had he the gold? or had the gold him?[51]
  • [51] Compare George Herbert, _The Church Porch_, Stanza 28.
  • And if, instead of sinking him in the sea by its weight, the gold had
  • struck him on the forehead, and thereby caused incurable
  • disease--suppose palsy or insanity,--would the gold in that case have
  • been more a "possession" than in the first? Without pressing the
  • inquiry up through instances of gradually increasing vital power over
  • the gold (which I will, however, give, if they are asked for), I
  • presume the reader will see that possession, or "having," is not an
  • absolute, but a gradated, power; and consists not only in the quantity
  • or nature of the thing possessed, but also (and in a greater degree)
  • in its suitableness to the person possessing it, and in his vital
  • power to use it.
  • And our definition of Wealth, expanded, becomes: "The possession of
  • useful articles, _which we can use_." This is a very serious change.
  • For wealth, instead of depending merely on a "have," is thus seen to
  • depend on a "can." Gladiator's death, on a "habet"; but soldier's
  • victory, and state's salvation, on a "quo plurimum posset." (Liv. VII.
  • 6.) And what we reasoned of only as accumulation of material, is seen
  • to demand also accumulation of capacity.
  • So much for our verb. Next for our adjective. What is the meaning of
  • "useful?"
  • The inquiry is closely connected with the last. For what is capable of
  • use in the hands of some persons, is capable, in the hands of others,
  • of the opposite of use, called commonly, "from-use," or "ab-use." And
  • it depends on the person, much more than on the article, whether its
  • usefulness or ab-usefulness will be the quality developed in it. Thus,
  • wine, which the Greeks, in their Bacchus, made, rightly, the type of
  • all passion, and which, when used, "cheereth god and man" (that is to
  • say, strengthens both the divine life, or reasoning power, and the
  • earthly, or carnal power, of man); yet, when abused, becomes
  • "Dionusos," hurtful especially to the divine part of man, or reason.
  • And again, the body itself, being equally liable to use and to abuse,
  • and, when rightly disciplined, serviceable to the State, both for war
  • and labour;--but when not disciplined, or abused, valueless to the
  • State, and capable only of continuing the private or single existence
  • of the individual (and that but feebly)--the Greeks called such a body
  • an "idiotic" or "private" body, from their word signifying a person
  • employed in no way directly useful to the State: whence, finally, our
  • "idiot," meaning a person entirely occupied with his own concerns.
  • Hence, it follows, that if a thing is to be useful, it must be not
  • only of an availing nature, but in availing hands. Or, in accurate
  • terms, usefulness is value in the hands of the valiant; so that this
  • science of wealth being, as we have just seen, when regarded as the
  • science of Accumulation, accumulative of capacity as well as of
  • material,--when regarded as the science of Distribution, is
  • distribution not absolute, but discriminate; not of every thing to
  • every man, but of the right thing to the right man. A difficult
  • science, dependent on more than arithmetic.
  • Wealth, therefore, is "THE POSSESSION OF THE VALUABLE BY THE VALIANT;"
  • and in considering it as a power existing in a nation, the two
  • elements, the value of the thing, and the valour of its possessor,
  • must be estimated together. Whence it appears that many of the persons
  • commonly considered wealthy, are in reality no more wealthy than the
  • locks of their own strong boxes are; they being inherently and
  • eternally incapable of wealth; and operating for the nation, in an
  • economical point of view, either as pools of dead water, and eddies in
  • a stream (which, so long as the stream flows, are useless, or serve
  • only to drown people, but may become of importance in a state of
  • stagnation, should the stream dry); or else, as dams in a river, of
  • which the ultimate service depends not on the dam, but the miller; or
  • else, as mere accidental stays and impediments, acting, not as wealth,
  • but (for we ought to have a correspondent term) as "illth," causing
  • various devastation and trouble around them in all directions; or
  • lastly, act not at all, but are merely animated conditions of delay
  • (no use being possible of anything they have until they are dead), in
  • which last condition they are nevertheless often useful _as_ delays,
  • and "impedimenta," if a nation is apt to move too fast.
  • This being so, the difficulty of the true science of Political Economy
  • lies not merely in the need of developing manly character to deal with
  • material value, but in the fact, that while the manly character and
  • material value only form wealth by their conjunction, they have
  • nevertheless a mutually destructive operation on each other. For the
  • manly character is apt to ignore, or even cast away, the material
  • value:--whence that of Pope:--
  • "Sure, of qualities demanding praise
  • More go to ruin fortunes, than to raise."
  • And on the other hand, the material value is apt to undermine the
  • manly character; so that it must be our work, in the issue, to examine
  • what evidence there is of the effect of wealth on the minds of its
  • possessors; also, what kind of person it is who usually sets himself
  • to obtain wealth, and succeeds in doing so; and whether the world owes
  • more gratitude to rich or to poor men, either for their moral
  • influence upon it, or for chief goods, discoveries, and practical
  • advancements. I may, however, anticipate future conclusions so far as
  • to state that in a community regulated only by laws of demand and
  • supply, but protected from open violence, the persons who become rich
  • are, generally speaking, industrious, resolute, proud, covetous,
  • prompt, methodical, sensible, unimaginative, insensitive, and
  • ignorant. The persons who remain poor are the entirely foolish, the
  • entirely wise,[52] the idle, the reckless, the humble, the thoughtful,
  • the dull, the imaginative, the sensitive, the well-informed, the
  • improvident, the irregularly and impulsively wicked, the clumsy knave,
  • the open thief, and the entirely merciful, just, and godly person.
  • [52] "[Greek: ho Zeus dêpou penetai.]"--_Arist. Plut._ 582. It
  • would but weaken the grand words to lean on the preceding
  • ones:--"[Greek: hoti tou Ploutou parecho beltionas andras,
  • kai ten gnomen, kai ten idean.]"
  • Thus far then of wealth. Next, we have to ascertain the nature of
  • PRICE; that is to say, of exchange value, and its expression by
  • currencies.
  • Note first, of exchange, there can be no _profit_ in it. It is only in
  • labour there can be profit--that is to say a "making in advance," or
  • "making in favour of" (from proficio). In exchange, there is only
  • advantage, _i.e._, a bringing of vantage or power to the exchanging
  • persons. Thus, one man, by sowing and reaping, turns one measure of
  • corn into two measures. That is Profit. Another by digging and
  • forging, turns one spade into two spades. That is Profit. But the man
  • who has two measures of corn wants sometimes to dig; and the man who
  • has two spades wants sometimes to eat:--They exchange the gained grain
  • for the gained tool; and both are the better for the exchange; but
  • though there is much advantage in the transaction, there is no profit.
  • Nothing is constructed or produced. Only that which had been before
  • constructed is given to the person by whom it can be used. If labour
  • is necessary to effect the exchange, that labour is in reality
  • involved in the production, and, like all other labour, bears profit.
  • Whatever number of men are concerned in the manufacture, or in the
  • conveyance, have share in the profit; but neither the manufacture nor
  • the conveyance are the exchange, and in the exchange itself there is
  • no profit.
  • There may, however, be acquisition, which is a very different thing.
  • If, in the exchange, one man is able to give what cost him little
  • labour for what has cost the other much, he "acquires" a certain
  • quantity of the produce of the other's labour. And precisely what he
  • acquires, the other loses. In mercantile language, the person who thus
  • acquires is commonly said to have "made a profit;" and I believe that
  • many of our merchants are seriously under the impression that it is
  • possible for everybody, somehow, to make a profit in this manner.
  • Whereas, by the unfortunate constitution of the world we live in, the
  • laws both of matter and motion have quite rigorously forbidden
  • universal acquisition of this kind. Profit, or material gain, is
  • attainable only by construction or by discovery; not by exchange.
  • Whenever material gain follows exchange, for every _plus_ there is a
  • precisely equal _minus_.
  • Unhappily for the progress of the science of Political Economy, the
  • plus quantities, or--if I may be allowed to coin an awkward
  • plural--the pluses, make a very positive and venerable appearance in
  • the world, so that every one is eager to learn the science which
  • produces results so magnificent; whereas the minuses have, on the
  • other hand, a tendency to retire into back streets, and other places
  • of shade,--or even to get themselves wholly and finally put out of
  • sight in graves: which renders the algebra of this science peculiar,
  • and difficultly legible; a large number of its negative signs being
  • written by the account-keeper in a kind of red ink, which starvation
  • thins, and makes strangely pale, or even quite invisible ink, for the
  • present.
  • The science of Exchange, or, as I hear it has been proposed to call
  • it, of "Catallactics," considered as one of gain, is, therefore,
  • simply nugatory; but considered as one of acquisition, it is a very
  • curious science, differing in its data and basis from every other
  • science known. Thus:--If I can exchange a needle with a savage for a
  • diamond, my power of doing so depends either on the savage's ignorance
  • of social arrangements in Europe, or on his want of power to take
  • advantage of them, by selling the diamond to any one else for more
  • needles. If, farther, I make the bargain as completely advantageous to
  • myself as possible, by giving to the savage a needle with no eye in it
  • (reaching, thus, a sufficiently satisfactory type of the perfect
  • operation of catallactic science), the advantage to me in the entire
  • transaction depends wholly upon the ignorance, powerlessness, or
  • heedlessness of the person dealt with. Do away with these, and
  • catallactic advantage becomes impossible. So far, therefore as the
  • science of exchange relates to the advantage of one of the exchanging
  • persons only, it is founded on the ignorance or incapacity of the
  • opposite person. Where these vanish, it also vanishes. It is therefore
  • a science founded on nescience, and an art founded on artlessness. But
  • all other sciences and arts, except this, have for their object the
  • doing away with their opposite nescience and artlessness. _This_
  • science, alone of sciences, must, by all available means, promulgate
  • and prolong its opposite nescience; otherwise the science itself is
  • impossible. It is, therefore, peculiarly and alone, the science of
  • darkness; probably a bastard science--not by any means a _divina
  • scientia_, but one begotten of another father, that father who,
  • advising his children to turn stones into bread, is himself employed
  • in turning bread into stones, and who, if you ask a fish of him (fish
  • not being producible on his estate), can but give you a serpent.
  • The general law, then, respecting just or economical exchange, is
  • simply this:--There must be advantage on both sides (or if only
  • advantage on one, at least no disadvantage on the other) to the
  • persons exchanging; and just payment for his time, intelligence, and
  • labour, to any intermediate person effecting the transaction (commonly
  • called a merchant): and whatever advantage there is on either side,
  • and whatever pay is given to the intermediate person, should be
  • thoroughly known to all concerned. All attempt at concealment implies
  • some practice of the opposite, or undivine science, founded on
  • nescience. Whence another saying of the Jew merchant's--"As a nail
  • between the stone joints, so doth sin stick fast between buying and
  • selling." Which peculiar riveting of stone and timber, in men's
  • dealing with each other, is again set forth in the house which was to
  • be destroyed--timber and stones together--when Zechariah's roll (more
  • probably "curved sword") flew over it: "the curse that goeth forth
  • over all the earth upon every one that stealeth and holdeth himself
  • guiltless," instantly followed by the vision of the Great
  • Measure;--the measure "of the injustice of them in all the earth"
  • ([Greek: autê hê adikia autôn en pasê tê gê]), with the weight of
  • lead for its lid, and the woman, the spirit of wickedness, within
  • it;--that is to say, Wickedness hidden by Dulness, and formalized,
  • outwardly, into ponderously established cruelty. "It shall be set upon
  • its own base in the land on Babel."[53]
  • [53] Zech. v. 11. See note on the passage, at pp. 191-2.
  • I have hitherto carefully restricted myself, in speaking of exchange,
  • to the use of the term "advantage;" but that term includes two ideas:
  • the advantage, namely, of getting what we _need_, and that of getting
  • what we _wish for_. Three-fourths of the demands existing in the world
  • are romantic; founded on visions, idealisms, hopes, and affections;
  • and the regulation of the purse is, in its essence, regulation of the
  • imagination and the heart. Hence, the right discussion of the nature
  • of price is a very high metaphysical and psychical problem; sometimes
  • to be solved only in a passionate manner, as by David in his counting
  • the price of the water of the well by the gate of Bethlehem; but its
  • first conditions are the following:--The price of anything is the
  • quantity of labour given by the person desiring it, in order to obtain
  • possession of it. This price depends on four variable quantities. _A_.
  • The quantity of wish the purchaser has for the thing; opposed to
  • [Greek: a], the quantity of wish the seller has to keep it. _B_. The
  • quantity of labour the purchaser can afford, to obtain the thing;
  • opposed to [Greek: b], the quantity of labour the seller can afford, to
  • keep it. These quantities are operative only in excess; _i.e._, the
  • quantity of wish (_A_) means the quantity of wish for this thing, above
  • wish for other things; and the quantity of work (_B_) means the quantity
  • which can be spared to get this thing from the quantity needed to get
  • other things.
  • Phenomena of price, therefore, are intensely complex, curious, and
  • interesting--too complex, however, to be examined yet; every one of
  • them, when traced far enough, showing itself at last as a part of the
  • bargain of the Poor of the Flock (or "flock of slaughter"), "If ye
  • think good, give ME my price, and if not, forbear"--Zech. xi. 12; but
  • as the price of everything is to be calculated finally in labour, it
  • is necessary to define the nature of that standard.
  • Labour is the contest of the life of man with an opposite:--the term
  • "life" including his intellect, soul, and physical power, contending
  • with question, difficulty, trial, or material force.
  • Labour is of a higher or lower order, as it includes more or fewer of
  • the elements of life: and labour of good quality, in any kind,
  • includes always as much intellect and feeling as will fully and
  • harmoniously regulate the physical force.
  • In speaking of the value and price of labour, it is necessary always
  • to understand labour of a given rank and quality, as we should speak
  • of gold or silver of a given standard. Bad (that is, heartless,
  • inexperienced, or senseless) labour cannot be valued; it is like gold
  • of uncertain alloy, or flawed iron.[54]
  • [54] Labour which is entirely good of its kind, that is to say,
  • effective, or efficient, the Greeks called "weighable,"
  • or [Greek: axios], translated usually "worthy," and
  • because thus substantial and true, they called its price
  • [Greek: timê], the "honourable estimate" of it (honorarium):
  • this word being founded on their conception of true labour
  • as a divine thing, to be honoured with the kind of honour
  • given to the gods; whereas the price of false labour, or of
  • that which led away from life, was to be, not honour, but
  • vengeance; for which they reserved another word, attributing
  • the exaction of such price to a peculiar goddess called
  • Tisiphone, the "requiter (or quittance-taker) of death;"
  • a person versed in the highest branches of arithmetic, and
  • punctual in her habits; with whom accounts current have been
  • opened also in modern days.
  • The quality and kind of labour being given, its value, like that of
  • all other valuable things, is invariable. But the quantity of it which
  • must be given for other things is variable: and in estimating this
  • variation, the price of other things must always be counted by the
  • quantity of labour; not the price of labour by the quantity of other
  • things.
  • Thus, if we want to plant an apple sapling in rocky ground, it may
  • take two hours' work; in soft ground, perhaps only half an hour. Grant
  • the soil equally good for the tree in each case. Then the value of the
  • sapling planted by two hours' work is nowise greater than that of the
  • sapling planted in half an hour. One will bear no more fruit than the
  • other. Also, one half-hour of work is as valuable as another
  • half-hour; nevertheless the one sapling has cost four such pieces of
  • work, the other only one. Now the proper statement of this fact is,
  • not that the labour on the hard ground is cheaper than on the soft;
  • but that the tree is dearer. The exchange value may, or may not,
  • afterwards depend on this fact. If other people have plenty of soft
  • ground to plant in, they will take no cognizance of our two hours'
  • labour, in the price they will offer for the plant on the rock. And
  • if, through want of sufficient botanical science, we have planted an
  • upas-tree instead of an apple, the exchange value will be a negative
  • quantity; still less proportionate to the labour expended.
  • What is commonly called cheapness of labour, signifies, therefore, in
  • reality, that many obstacles have to be overcome by it; so that much
  • labour is required to produce a small result. But this should never be
  • spoken of as cheapness of labour, but as dearness of the object
  • wrought for. It would be just as rational to say that walking was
  • cheap, because we had ten miles to walk home to our dinner, as that
  • labour was cheap, because we had to work ten hours to earn it.
  • The last word which we have to define is "Production."
  • I have hitherto spoken of all labour as profitable; because it is
  • impossible to consider under one head the quality or value of labour,
  • and its aim. But labour of the best quality may be various in aim. It
  • may be either constructive ("gathering," from con and struo), as
  • agriculture; nugatory, as jewel-cutting; or destructive ("scattering,"
  • from de and struo), as war. It is not, however, always easy to prove
  • labour, apparently nugatory, to be actually so;[55] generally, the
  • formula holds good, "he that gathereth not, scattereth;" thus, the
  • jeweller's art is probably very harmful in its ministering to a clumsy
  • and inelegant pride. So that, finally, I believe nearly all labour may
  • be shortly divided into positive and negative labour: positive, that
  • which produces life; negative, that which produces death; the most
  • directly negative labour being murder, and the most directly positive,
  • the bearing and rearing of children: so that in the precise degree in
  • which murder is hateful, on the negative side of idleness, in that
  • exact degree child-rearing is admirable, on the positive side of
  • idleness. For which reason, and because of the honour that there is in
  • rearing[56] children, while the wife is said to be as the vine (for
  • cheering), the children are as the olive-branch, for praise; nor for
  • praise only, but for peace (because large families can only be reared
  • in times of peace): though since, in their spreading and voyaging in
  • various directions, they distribute strength, they are, to the home
  • strength, as arrows in the hand of the giant--striking here and there,
  • far away.
  • [55] The most accurately nugatory labour is, perhaps, that of
  • which not enough is given to answer a purpose effectually,
  • and which, therefore, has all to be done over again. Also,
  • labour which fails of effect through non-cooperation. The
  • curé of a little village near Bellinzona, to whom I had
  • expressed wonder that the peasants allowed the Ticino to
  • flood their fields, told me that they would not join to
  • build an effectual embankment high up the valley, because
  • everybody said "that would help his neighbours as much as
  • himself." So every proprietor built a bit of low embankment
  • about his own field; and the Ticino, as soon as it had a
  • mind, swept away and swallowed all up together.
  • [56] Observe, I say, "rearing," not "begetting." The praise is
  • in the seventh season, not in [Greek: sporêtos], nor in
  • [Greek: phytalia], but in [Greek: opôra]. It is strange
  • that men always praise enthusiastically any person who,
  • by a momentary exertion, saves a life; but praise very
  • hesitatingly a person who, by exertion and self-denial
  • prolonged through years, creates one. We give the crown "ob
  • civem servatum,"--why not "ob civem natum"? Born, I mean, to
  • the full, in soul as well as body. England has oak enough, I
  • think, for both chaplets.
  • Labour being thus various in its result, the prosperity of any nation
  • is in exact proportion to the quantity of labour which it spends in
  • obtaining and employing means of life. Observe,--I say, obtaining and
  • employing; that is to say, not merely wisely producing, but wisely
  • distributing and consuming. Economists usually speak as if there were
  • no good in consumption absolute.[57] So far from this being so,
  • consumption absolute is the end, crown, and perfection of production;
  • and wise consumption is a far more difficult art than wise production.
  • Twenty people can gain money for one who can use it; and the vital
  • question, for individual and for nation, is, never "how much do they
  • make?" but "to what purpose do they spend?"
  • [57] When Mr. Mill speaks of productive consumption, he only
  • means consumption which results in increase of capital, or
  • material wealth. See I. iii. 4, and I. iii. 5.
  • The reader may, perhaps, have been surprised at the slight reference
  • I have hitherto made to "capital," and its functions. It is here the
  • place to define them.
  • Capital signifies "head, or source, or root material"--it is material
  • by which some derivative or secondary good is produced. It is only
  • capital proper (caput vivum, not caput mortuum) when it is thus
  • producing something different from itself. It is a root, which does
  • not enter into vital function till it produces something else than a
  • root; namely, fruit. That fruit will in time again produce roots; and
  • so all living capital issues in reproduction of capital; but capital
  • which produces nothing but capital is only root producing root; bulb
  • issuing in bulb, never in tulip; seed issuing in seed, never in bread.
  • The Political Economy of Europe has hitherto devoted itself wholly to
  • the multiplication, or (less even) the aggregation, of bulbs. It never
  • saw, nor conceived such a thing as a tulip. Nay, boiled bulbs they
  • might have been--glass bulbs--Prince Rupert's drops, consummated in
  • powder (well, if it were glass-powder and not gunpowder), for any end
  • or meaning the economists had in defining the laws of aggregation. We
  • will try and get a clearer notion of them.
  • The best and simplest general type of capital is a well-made
  • ploughshare. Now, if that ploughshare did nothing but beget other
  • ploughshares, in a polypous manner,--however the great cluster of
  • polypous plough might glitter in the sun, it would have lost its
  • function of capital. It becomes true capital only by another kind of
  • splendour,--when it is seen "splendescere sulco," to grow bright in
  • the furrow; rather with diminution of its substance, than addition, by
  • the noble friction. And the true home question, to every capitalist
  • and to every nation, is not, "how many ploughs have you?" but, "where
  • are your furrows?" not--"how quickly will this capital reproduce
  • itself?"--but, "what will it do during reproduction?" What substance
  • will it furnish, good for life? what work construct, protective of
  • life? if none, its own reproduction is useless--if worse than none
  • (for capital may destroy life as well as support it), its own
  • reproduction is worse than useless; it is merely an advance from
  • Tisiphone, on mortgage--not a profit by any means.
  • Not a profit, as the ancients truly saw, and showed in the type of
  • Ixion;--for capital is the head, or fountain head, of wealth--the
  • "well-head" of wealth, as the clouds are the well-heads of rain: but
  • when clouds are without water, and only beget clouds, they issue in
  • wrath at last, instead of rain, and in lightning instead of harvest;
  • whence Ixion is said first to have invited his guests to a banquet,
  • and then made them fall into a pit filled with fire; which is the type
  • of the temptation of riches issuing in imprisoned torment,--torment in
  • a pit (as also Demas' silver mine), after which, to show the rage of
  • riches passing from lust of pleasure to lust of power, yet power not
  • truly understood, Ixion is said to have desired Juno, and instead,
  • embracing a cloud (or phantasm), to have begotten the Centaurs; the
  • power of mere wealth being, in itself, as the embrace of a
  • shadow,--comfortless (so also "Ephraim feedeth on wind and followeth
  • after the east wind"; or "that which is not"--Prov. xxiii. 5; and
  • again Dante's Geryon, the type of avaricious fraud, as he flies,
  • gathers the _air_ up with retractile claws,--"l'aer a se
  • raccolse"[58]), but in its offspring, a mingling of the brutal with
  • the human nature: human in sagacity--using both intellect and arrow;
  • but brutal in its body and hoof, for consuming, and trampling down.
  • For which sin Ixion is at last bound upon a wheel--fiery and toothed,
  • and rolling perpetually in the air;--the type of human labour when
  • selfish and fruitless (kept far into the middle ages in their wheel of
  • fortune); the wheel which has in it no breath or spirit, but is
  • whirled by chance only; whereas of all true work the Ezekiel vision is
  • true, that the Spirit of the living creature is in the wheels, and
  • where the angels go, the wheels go by them; but move no otherwise.
  • [58] So also in the vision of the women bearing the ephah, before
  • quoted, "the wind was in their wings," not wings "of a
  • stork," as in our version; but "_milvi_," of a kite, in the
  • Vulgate, or perhaps more accurately still in the Septuagint,
  • "hoopoe," a bird connected typically with the power of
  • riches by many traditions, of which that of its petition for
  • a crest of gold is perhaps the most interesting. The "Birds"
  • of Aristophanes, in which its part is principal, is full of
  • them; note especially the "fortification of the air with
  • baked bricks, like Babylon," l. 550; and, again, compare the
  • Plutus of Dante, who (to show the influence of riches in
  • destroying the reason) is the only one of the powers of the
  • Inferno who cannot speak intelligibly; and also the
  • cowardliest; he is not merely quelled or restrained, but
  • literally "collapses" at a word; the sudden and helpless
  • operation of mercantile panic being all told in the brief
  • metaphor, "as the sails, swollen with the wind, fall, when
  • the mast breaks."
  • This being the real nature of capital, it follows that there are two
  • kinds of true production, always going on in an active State; one of
  • seed, and one of food; or production for the Ground, and for the
  • Mouth; both of which are by covetous persons thought to be production
  • only for the granary; whereas the function of the granary is but
  • intermediate and conservative, fulfilled in distribution; else it ends
  • in nothing but mildew, and nourishment of rats and worms. And since
  • production for the Ground is only useful with future hope of harvest,
  • all _essential_ production is for the Mouth; and is finally measured
  • by the mouth; hence, as I said above, consumption is the crown of
  • production; and the wealth of a nation is only to be estimated by what
  • it consumes.
  • The want of any clear sight of this fact is the capital error, issuing
  • in rich interest and revenue of error among the political economists.
  • Their minds are continually set on money-gain, not on mouth-gain; and
  • they fall into every sort of net and snare, dazzled by the
  • coin-glitter as birds by the fowler's glass; or rather (for there is
  • not much else like birds in them) they are like children trying to
  • jump on the heads of their own shadows; the money-gain being only the
  • shadow of the true gain, which is humanity.
  • The final object of political economy, therefore, is to get good
  • method of consumption, and great quantity of consumption: in other
  • words, to use everything, and to use it nobly; whether it be
  • substance, service, or service perfecting substance. The most curious
  • error in Mr. Mill's entire work (provided for him originally by
  • Ricardo) is his endeavour to distinguish between direct and indirect
  • service, and consequent assertion that a demand for commodities is not
  • demand for labour (I. v. 9, _et seq._). He distinguishes between
  • labourers employed to lay out pleasure grounds, and to manufacture
  • velvet; declaring that it makes material difference to the labouring
  • classes in which of these two ways a capitalist spends his money;
  • because the employment of the gardeners is a demand for labour, but
  • the purchase of velvet is not.[59] Error colossal as well as strange.
  • It will, indeed, make a difference to the labourer whether we bid him
  • swing his scythe in the spring winds, or drive the loom in
  • pestilential air; but, so far as his pocket is concerned, it makes to
  • him absolutely no difference whether we order him to make green
  • velvet, with seed and a scythe, or red velvet, with silk and scissors.
  • Neither does it anywise concern him whether, when the velvet is made,
  • we consume it by walking on it, or wearing it, so long as our
  • consumption of it is wholly selfish. But if our consumption is to be
  • in any wise unselfish, not only our mode of consuming the articles we
  • require interests him, but also the _kind_ of article we require with
  • a view to consumption. As thus (returning for a moment to Mr. Mill's
  • great hardware theory[60]): it matters, so far as the labourer's
  • immediate profit is concerned, not an iron filing whether I employ him
  • in growing a peach, or forging a bombshell; but my probable mode of
  • consumption of those articles matters seriously. Admit that it is to
  • be in both cases "unselfish," and the difference, to him, is final,
  • whether when his child is ill, I walk into his cottage and give it the
  • peach, or drop the shell down his chimney, and blow his roof off.
  • [59] The value of raw material, which has, indeed, to be deducted
  • from the price of the labour, is not contemplated in the
  • passages referred to, Mr. Mill having fallen into the
  • mistake solely by pursuing the collateral results of the
  • payment of wages to middlemen. He says:--"The consumer does
  • not, with his own funds, pay the weaver for his day's work."
  • Pardon me; the consumer of the velvet pays the weaver with
  • his own funds as much as he pays the gardener. He pays,
  • probably, an intermediate ship-owner, velvet merchant, and
  • shopman; pays carriage money, shop rent, damage money, time
  • money, and care money; all these are above and beside the
  • velvet price (just as the wages of a head gardener would be
  • above the grass price); but the velvet is as much produced
  • by the consumer's capital, though he does not pay for it
  • till six months after production, as the grass is produced
  • by his capital, though he does not pay the man who mowed and
  • rolled it on Monday, till Saturday afternoon. I do not know
  • if Mr. Mill's conclusion--"the capital cannot be dispensed
  • with, the purchasers can"--has yet been reduced to practice
  • in the City on any large scale.
  • [60] Which, observe, is the precise opposite of the one
  • under examination. The hardware theory required us to
  • discharge our gardeners and engage manufacturers; the velvet
  • theory requires us to discharge our manufacturers and engage
  • gardeners.
  • The worst of it, for the peasant, is, that the capitalist's
  • consumption of the peach is apt to be selfish, and of the shell,
  • distributive;[61] but, in all cases, this is the broad and general
  • fact, that on due catallactic commercial principles, _somebody's_ roof
  • must go off in fulfilment of the bomb's destiny. You may grow for
  • your neighbour, at your liking, grapes or grapeshot; he will also,
  • catallactically, grow grapes or grapeshot for you, and you will each
  • reap what you have sown.
  • [61] It is one very awful form of the operation of wealth in
  • Europe that it is entirely capitalists' wealth which
  • supports unjust wars. Just wars do not need so much money to
  • support them; for most of the men who wage such, wage them
  • gratis; but for an unjust war, men's bodies and souls have
  • both to be bought; and the best tools of war for them
  • besides; which makes such war costly to the maximum; not to
  • speak of the cost of base fear, and angry suspicion, between
  • nations which have not grace nor honesty enough in all their
  • multitudes to buy an hour's peace of mind with: as, at
  • present, France and England, purchasing of each other ten
  • millions sterling worth of consternation annually (a
  • remarkably light crop, half thorns and half aspen
  • leaves,--sown, reaped, and granaried by "the science" of the
  • modern political economist, teaching covetousness instead of
  • truth). And all unjust war being supportable, if not by
  • pillage of the enemy, only by loans from capitalists, these
  • loans are repaid by subsequent taxation of the people, who
  • appear to have no will in the matter, the capitalists' will
  • being the primary root of the war; but its real root is the
  • covetousness of the whole nation, rendering it incapable of
  • faith, frankness, or justice, and bringing about, therefore,
  • in due time, his own separate loss and punishment to each
  • person.
  • It is, therefore, the manner and issue of consumption which are the
  • real tests of production. Production does not consist in things
  • laboriously made, but in things serviceably consumable; and the
  • question for the nation is not how much labour it employs, but how
  • much life it produces. For as consumption is the end and aim of
  • production, so life is the end and aim of consumption.
  • I left this question to the reader's thought two months ago, choosing
  • rather that he should work it out for himself than have it sharply
  • stated to him. But now, the ground being sufficiently broken (and the
  • details into which the several questions, here opened, must lead us,
  • being too complex for discussion in the pages of a periodical, so that
  • I must pursue them elsewhere), I desire, in closing the series of
  • introductory papers, to leave this one great fact clearly stated.
  • THERE IS NO WEALTH BUT LIFE. Life, including all its powers of love,
  • of joy, and of admiration. That country is the richest which nourishes
  • the greatest number of noble and happy human beings; that man is
  • richest who, having perfected the functions of his own life to the
  • utmost, has also the widest helpful influence, both personal and by
  • means of his possessions, over the lives of others.
  • A strange political economy; the only one, nevertheless, that ever was
  • or can be: all political economy founded on self-interest[62] being
  • but the fulfilment of that which once brought schism into the Policy
  • of angels, and ruin into the Economy of Heaven.
  • [62] "In all reasoning about prices, the proviso must be
  • understood, 'supposing all parties to take care of their
  • own interest.'"--Mill, III. i. 5.
  • "The greatest number of human beings noble and happy." But is the
  • nobleness consistent with the number? Yes, not only consistent with
  • it, but essential to it. The maximum of life can only be reached by
  • the maximum of virtue. In this respect the law of human population
  • differs wholly from that of animal life. The multiplication of animals
  • is checked only by want of food, and by the hostility of races; the
  • population of the gnat is restrained by the hunger of the swallow, and
  • that of the swallow by the scarcity of gnats. Man, considered as an
  • animal, is indeed limited by the same laws: hunger, or plague, or war,
  • are the necessary and only restraints upon his increase,--effectual
  • restraints hitherto,--his principal study having been how most swiftly
  • to destroy himself, or ravage his dwelling-places, and his highest
  • skill directed to give range to the famine, seed to the plague, and
  • sway to the sword. But, considered as other than an animal, his
  • increase is not limited by these laws. It is limited only by the
  • limits of his courage and his love. Both of these _have_ their bounds;
  • and ought to have: his race has its bounds also; but these have not
  • yet been reached, nor will be reached for ages.
  • In all the ranges of human thought I know none so melancholy as the
  • speculations of political economists on the population question. It is
  • proposed to better the condition of the labourer by giving him higher
  • wages. "Nay," says the economist, "if you raise his wages, he will
  • either drag people down to the same point of misery at which you found
  • him, or drink your wages away." He will. I know it. Who gave him this
  • will? Suppose it were your own son of whom you spoke, declaring to me
  • that you dared not take him into your firm, nor even give him his just
  • labourer's wages, because if you did, he would die of drunkenness, and
  • leave half a score of children to the parish. "Who gave your son these
  • dispositions?"--I should inquire. Has he them by inheritance or by
  • education? By one or other they _must_ come; and as in him, so also in
  • the poor. Either these poor are of a race essentially different from
  • ours, and unredeemable (which, however often implied, I have heard
  • none yet openly say), or else by such care as we have ourselves
  • received, we may make them continent and sober as ourselves--wise and
  • dispassionate as we are--models arduous of imitation. "But," it is
  • answered, "they cannot receive education." Why not? That is precisely
  • the point at issue. Charitable persons suppose the worst fault of the
  • rich is to refuse the people meat; and the people cry for their meat,
  • kept back by fraud, to the Lord of Multitudes.[63] Alas! it is not
  • meat of which the refusal is cruelest, or to which the claim is
  • validest. The life is more than the meat. The rich not only refuse
  • food to the poor; they refuse wisdom; they refuse virtue; they refuse
  • salvation. Ye sheep without shepherd, it is not the pasture that has
  • been shut from you, but the presence. Meat! perhaps your right to that
  • may be pleadable; but other rights have to be pleaded first. Claim
  • your crumbs from the table, if you will; but claim them as children,
  • not as dogs; claim your right to be fed, but claim more loudly your
  • right to be holy, perfect, and pure.
  • [63] James v. 4. Observe, in these statements I am not taking
  • up, nor countenancing one whit, the common socialist idea of
  • division of property; division of property is its
  • destruction; and with it the destruction of all hope, all
  • industry, and all justice: it is simply chaos--a chaos
  • towards which the believers in modern political economy are
  • fast tending, and from which I am striving to save them. The
  • rich man does not keep back meat from the poor by retaining
  • his riches; but by basely using them. Riches are a form of
  • strength; and a strong man does not injure others by keeping
  • his strength, but by using it injuriously. The socialist,
  • seeing a strong man oppress a weak one, cries out--"Break
  • the strong man's arms"; but I say, "Teach him to use them to
  • better purpose." The fortitude and intelligence which
  • acquire riches are intended, by the Giver of both, not to
  • scatter, nor to give away, but to employ those riches in the
  • service of mankind; in other words, in the redemption of the
  • erring and aid of the weak--that is to say, there is first
  • to be the work to gain money; then the Sabbath of use for
  • it--the Sabbath, whose law is, not to lose life, but to
  • save. It is continually the fault or the folly of the poor
  • that they are poor, as it is usually a child's fault if it
  • falls into a pond, and a cripple's weakness that slips at a
  • crossing; nevertheless, most passers-by would pull the child
  • out, or help up the cripple. Put it at the worst, that all
  • the poor of the world are but disobedient children, or
  • careless cripples, and that all rich people are wise and
  • strong, and you will see at once that neither is the
  • socialist right in desiring to make everybody poor,
  • powerless, and foolish as he is himself, nor the rich man
  • right in leaving the children in the mire.
  • Strange words to be used of working people: "What! holy; without any
  • long robes nor anointing oils; these rough-jacketed, rough-worded
  • persons set to nameless and dishonoured service? Perfect!--these, with
  • dim eyes and cramped limbs, and slowly wakening minds? Pure!--these,
  • with sensual desire and grovelling thought; foul of body, and coarse
  • of soul?" It may be so; nevertheless, such as they are, they are the
  • holiest, perfectest, purest persons the earth can at present show.
  • They may be what you have said; but if so, they yet are holier than
  • we, who have left them thus.
  • But what can be done for them? Who can clothe--who teach--who restrain
  • their multitudes? What end can there be for them at last, but to
  • consume one another?
  • I hope for another end, though not, indeed, from any of the three
  • remedies for over-population commonly suggested by economists.
  • These three are, in brief--Colonization; Bringing in of waste lands;
  • or Discouragement of Marriage.
  • The first and second of these expedients merely evade or delay the
  • question. It will, indeed, be long before the world has been all
  • colonized, and its deserts all brought under cultivation. But the
  • radical question is not how much habitable land is in the world, but
  • how many human beings ought to be maintained on a given space of
  • habitable land.
  • Observe, I say, _ought_ to be, not how many _can_ be. Ricardo, with
  • his usual inaccuracy, defines what he calls the "natural rate of
  • wages" as "that which will maintain the labourer." Maintain him! yes;
  • but how?--the question was instantly thus asked of me by a working
  • girl, to whom I read the passage. I will amplify her question for her.
  • "Maintain him, how?" As, first, to what length of life? Out of a given
  • number of fed persons how many are to be old--how many young; that is
  • to say, will you arrange their maintenance so as to kill them
  • early--say at thirty or thirty-five on the average, including deaths
  • of weakly or ill-fed children?--or so as to enable them to live out a
  • natural life? You will feed a greater number, in the first case,[64]
  • by rapidity of succession; probably a happier number in the second:
  • which does Mr. Ricardo mean to be their natural state, and to which
  • state belongs the natural rate of wages?
  • [64] The quantity of life is the same in both cases; but it
  • is differently allotted.
  • Again: A piece of land which will only support ten idle, ignorant, and
  • improvident persons, will support thirty or forty intelligent and
  • industrious ones. Which of these is their natural state, and to which
  • of them belongs the natural rate of wages?
  • Again: If a piece of land support forty persons in industrious
  • ignorance; and if, tired of this ignorance, they set apart ten of
  • their number to study the properties of cones, and the sizes of stars;
  • the labour of these ten, being withdrawn from the ground, must either
  • tend to the increase of food in some transitional manner, or the
  • persons set apart for sidereal and conic purposes must starve, or some
  • one else starve instead of them. What is, therefore, the natural rate
  • of wages of the scientific persons, and how does this rate relate to,
  • or measure, their reverted or transitional productiveness?
  • Again: If the ground maintains, at first, forty labourers in a
  • peaceable and pious state of mind, but they become in a few years so
  • quarrelsome and impious that they have to set apart five, to meditate
  • upon and settle their disputes; ten, armed to the teeth with costly
  • instruments, to enforce the decisions; and five to remind everybody in
  • an eloquent manner of the existence of a God;--what will be the result
  • upon the general power of production, and what is the "natural rate of
  • wages" of the meditative, muscular, and oracular labourers?
  • Leaving these questions to be discussed, or waived, at their pleasure,
  • by Mr. Ricardo's followers, I proceed to state the main facts bearing
  • on that probable future of the labouring classes which has been
  • partially glanced at by Mr. Mill. That chapter and the preceding one
  • differ from the common writing of political economists in admitting
  • some value in the aspect of nature, and expressing regret at the
  • probability of the destruction of natural scenery. But we may spare
  • our anxieties, on this head. Men can neither drink steam, nor eat
  • stone. The maximum of population on a given space of land implies also
  • the relative maximum of edible vegetable, whether for men or cattle;
  • it implies a maximum of pure air; and of pure water. Therefore: a
  • maximum of wood, to transmute the air, and of sloping ground,
  • protected by herbage from the extreme heat of the sun, to feed the
  • streams. All England may, if it so chooses, become one manufacturing
  • town; and Englishmen, sacrificing themselves to the good of general
  • humanity, may live diminished lives in the midst of noise, of
  • darkness, and of deadly exhalation. But the world cannot become a
  • factory, nor a mine. No amount of ingenuity will ever make iron
  • digestible by the million, nor substitute hydrogen for wine. Neither
  • the avarice nor the rage of men will ever feed them, and however the
  • apple of Sodom and the grape of Gomorrah may spread their table for a
  • time with dainties of ashes, and nectar of asps,--so long as men live
  • by bread, the far away valleys must laugh as they are covered with the
  • gold of God, and the shouts of His happy multitudes ring round the
  • winepress and the well.
  • Nor need our more sentimental economists fear the too wide spread of
  • the formalities of a mechanical agriculture. The presence of a wise
  • population implies the search for felicity as well as for food; nor
  • can any population reach its maximum but through that wisdom which
  • "rejoices" in the habitable parts of the earth. The desert has its
  • appointed place and work; the eternal engine, whose beam is the
  • earth's axle, whose beat is its year, and whose breath is its ocean,
  • will still divide imperiously to their desert kingdoms, bound with
  • unfurrowable rock, and swept by unarrested sand, their powers of frost
  • and fire: but the zones and lands between, habitable, will be
  • loveliest in habitation. The desire of the heart is also the light of
  • the eyes. No scene is continually and untiringly loved, but one rich
  • by joyful human labour; smooth in field; fair in garden; full in
  • orchard; trim, sweet, and frequent in homestead; ringing with voices
  • of vivid existence. No air is sweet that is silent; it is only sweet
  • when full of low currents of under sound--triplets of birds, and
  • murmur and chirp of insects, and deep-toned words of men, and wayward
  • trebles of childhood. As the art of life is learned, it will be found
  • at last that all lovely things are also necessary:--the wild flower by
  • the wayside, as well as the tended corn; and the wild birds and
  • creatures of the forest, as well as the tended cattle; because man
  • doth not live by bread only, but also by the desert manna; by every
  • wondrous word and unknowable work of God. Happy, in that he knew them
  • not, nor did his fathers know; and that round about him reaches yet
  • into the infinite, the amazement of his existence.
  • Note, finally, that all effectual advancement towards this true
  • felicity of the human race must be by individual, not public effort.
  • Certain general measures may aid, certain revised laws guide, such
  • advancement; but the measure and law which have first to be determined
  • are those of each man's home. We continually hear it recommended by
  • sagacious people to complaining neighbours (usually less well placed
  • in the world than themselves), that they should "remain content in the
  • station in which Providence has placed them." There are perhaps some
  • circumstances of life in which Providence has no intention that people
  • _should_ be content. Nevertheless, the maxim is on the whole a good
  • one; but it is peculiarly for home use. That your neighbour should, or
  • should not, remain content with _his_ position, is not your business;
  • but it is very much your business to remain content with your own.
  • What is chiefly needed in England at the present day is to show the
  • quantity of pleasure that may be obtained by a consistent,
  • well-administered competence, modest, confessed, and laborious. We
  • need examples of people who, leaving Heaven to decide whether they are
  • to rise in the world, decide for themselves that they will be happy in
  • it, and have resolved to seek--not greater wealth, but simpler
  • pleasure; not higher fortune, but deeper felicity; making the first of
  • possessions, self-possession; and honouring themselves in the harmless
  • pride and calm pursuits of peace.
  • Of which lowly peace it is written that "justice and peace have
  • kissed each other;" and that the fruit of justice is "sown in
  • peace of them that make peace"; not "peace-makers" in the common
  • understanding--reconcilers of quarrels; (though that function also
  • follows on the greater one;) but peace-Creators; Givers of Calm. Which
  • you cannot give, unless you first gain; nor is this gain one which
  • will follow assuredly on any course of business, commonly so called.
  • No form of gain is less probable, business being (as is shown in
  • the language of all nations--[Greek: pôlein] from [Greek: pelô],
  • [Greek: prasis] from [Greek: peraô], venire, vendre, and venal, from
  • venio, etc.) essentially restless--and probably contentious;--having a
  • raven-like mind to the motion to and fro, as to the carrion food;
  • whereas the olive-feeding and bearing birds look for rest for their
  • feet: thus it is said of Wisdom that she "hath builded her house, and
  • hewn out her seven pillars;" and even when, though apt to wait long at
  • the doorposts, she has to leave her house and go abroad, her paths are
  • peace also.
  • For us, at all events, her work must begin at the entry of the doors:
  • all true economy is "Law of the house." Strive to make that law
  • strict, simple, generous: waste nothing, and grudge nothing. Care in
  • nowise to make more of money, but care to make much of it; remembering
  • always the great, palpable, inevitable fact--the rule and root of all
  • economy--that what one person has, another cannot have; and that every
  • atom of substance, of whatever kind, used or consumed, is so much
  • human life spent; which, if it issue in the saving present life, or
  • gaining more, is well spent, but if not, is either so much life
  • prevented, or so much slain. In all buying, consider, first, what
  • condition of existence you cause in the producers of what you buy;
  • secondly, whether the sum you have paid is just to the producer, and
  • in due proportion lodged in his hands;[65] thirdly, to how much clear
  • use, for food, knowledge, or joy, this that you have bought can be
  • put; and fourthly, to whom and in what way it can be most speedily and
  • serviceably distributed: in all dealings whatsoever insisting on
  • entire openness and stern fulfilment; and in all doings, on perfection
  • and loveliness of accomplishment; especially on fineness and purity of
  • all marketable commodity: watching at the same time for all ways of
  • gaining, or teaching, powers of simple pleasure; and of showing "hoson
  • en asphodelph geg honeiar"--the sum of enjoyment depending not on the
  • quantity of things tasted, but on the vivacity and patience of taste.
  • [65] The proper offices of middlemen, namely, overseers (or
  • authoritative workmen), conveyancers (merchants, sailors,
  • retail dealers, etc.), and order-takers (persons employed to
  • receive directions from the consumer), must, of course, be
  • examined before I can enter farther into the question of
  • just payment of the first producer. But I have not spoken
  • of them in these introductory papers, because the evils
  • attendant on the abuse of such intermediate functions result
  • not from any alleged principle of modern political economy,
  • but from private carelessness or iniquity.
  • And if, on due and honest thought over these things, it seems that the
  • kind of existence to which men are now summoned by every plea of pity
  • and claim of right, may, for some time at least, not be a luxurious
  • one:--consider whether, even, supposing it guiltless, luxury would be
  • desired by any of us, if we saw clearly at our sides the suffering
  • which accompanies it in the world. Luxury is indeed possible in the
  • future--innocent and exquisite: luxury for all, and by the help of
  • all; but luxury at present can only be enjoyed by the ignorant; the
  • cruelest man living could not sit at his feast, unless he sat
  • blindfold. Raise the veil boldly; face the light; and if, as yet, the
  • light of the eye can only be through tears, and the light of the body
  • through sackcloth, go thou forth weeping, bearing precious seed, until
  • the time come, and the kingdom, when Christ's gift of bread, and
  • bequest of peace shall be Unto this last as unto thee; and when, for
  • earth's severed multitudes of the wicked and the weary, there shall be
  • holier reconciliation than that of the narrow home, and calm economy,
  • where the Wicked cease--not from trouble, but from troubling--and the
  • Weary are at rest.
  • ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY:
  • CONTRIBUTED TO "FRASER'S MAGAZINE" IN 1862 AND 1863, BEING A SEQUEL TO
  • PAPERS WHICH APPEARED IN THE "CORNHILL MAGAZINE," UNDER THE TITLE OF
  • "UNTO THIS LAST."
  • I.
  • MAINTENANCE OF LIFE; WEALTH, MONEY, AND RICHES.
  • As domestic economy regulates the acts and habits of a household,
  • political economy regulates those of a society or State, with
  • reference to its maintenance.
  • Political economy is neither an art nor a science,[66] but a system of
  • conduct and legislature, founded on the sciences, directing the arts,
  • and impossible, except under certain conditions of moral culture.
  • By the "maintenance" of a State is to be understood the support of its
  • population in healthy and happy life; and the increase of their
  • numbers, so far as that increase is consistent with their happiness.
  • It is not the object of political economy to increase the numbers of a
  • nation at the cost of common health or comfort; nor to increase
  • indefinitely the comfort of individuals, by sacrifice of surrounding
  • lives, or possibilities of life.
  • [66] The science which in modern days had been called Political
  • Economy is in reality nothing more than the investigation of
  • the phenomena of commercial operations. It has no connexion
  • with political economy, as understood and treated of by the
  • great thinkers of past ages; and as long as it is allowed
  • to pass under the same name, every word written by those
  • thinkers--and chiefly the words of Plato, Xenophon, Cicero,
  • and Bacon--must be either misunderstood or misapplied. The
  • reader must not, therefore, be surprised at the care and
  • insistence with which I have retained the literal and earliest
  • sense of all important terms used in these papers; for a word
  • is usually well made at the time it is first wanted; its
  • youngest meaning has in it the full strength of its youth;
  • subsequent senses are commonly warped or weakened; and as a
  • misused word always is liable to involve an obscured thought,
  • and all careful thinkers, either on this or any other subject,
  • are sure to have used their words accurately, the first
  • condition, in order to be able to avail ourselves of their
  • sayings at all, is a firm definition of terms.
  • The assumption which lies at the root of nearly all erroneous
  • reasoning on political economy--namely, that its object is to
  • accumulate money or exchangeable property--may be shown in few words
  • to be without foundation. For no economist would admit national
  • economy to be legitimate which proposed to itself only the building of
  • a pyramid of gold. He would declare the gold to be wasted, were it to
  • remain in the monumental form, and would say it ought to be employed.
  • But to what end? Either it must be used only to gain more gold, and
  • build a larger pyramid, or to some purpose other than the gaining of
  • gold. And this other purpose, however at first apprehended, will be
  • found to resolve itself finally into the service of man--that is to
  • say, the extension, defence, or comfort of his life. The golden
  • pyramid may perhaps be providently built, perhaps improvidently; but,
  • at all events, the wisdom or folly of the accumulation can only be
  • determined by our having first clearly stated the aim of all economy,
  • namely, the extension of life.
  • If the accumulation of money, or of exchangeable property, were a
  • certain means of extending existence, it would be useless, in
  • discussing economical questions, to fix our attention upon the more
  • distant object--life--instead of the immediate one--money. But it is
  • not so. Money may sometimes be accumulated at the cost of life, or by
  • limitations of it; that is to say, either by hastening the deaths of
  • men, or preventing their births. It is therefore necessary to keep
  • clearly in view the ultimate object of economy, and to determine the
  • expediency of minor operations with reference to that ulterior end. It
  • has been just stated that the object of political economy is the
  • continuance not only of life, but of healthy and happy life. But all
  • true happiness is both a consequence and cause of life; it is a sign
  • of its vigour, and means of its continuance. All true suffering is in
  • like manner a consequence and cause of death. I shall therefore, in
  • future, use the word "Life" singly: but let it be understood to
  • include in its signification the happiness and power of the entire
  • human nature, body and soul.
  • That human nature, as its Creator made it, and maintains it wherever
  • His laws are observed, is entirely harmonious. No physical error can
  • be more profound, no moral error more dangerous than that involved in
  • the monkish doctrine of the opposition of body to soul. No soul can be
  • perfect in an imperfect body; no body perfect without perfect soul.
  • Every right action and true thought sets the seal of its beauty on
  • person and face; every wrong action and foul thought its seal of
  • distortion; and the various aspects of humanity might be read as
  • plainly as a printed history, were it not that the impressions are so
  • complex that it must always in some cases--and, in the present state
  • of our knowledge, in all cases--be impossible to decipher them
  • completely. Nevertheless, the face of a consistently just, and of a
  • consistently unjust person, may always be rightly discerned at a
  • glance; and if the qualities are continued by descent through a
  • generation or two, there arises a complete distinction of race. Both
  • moral and physical qualities are communicated by descent, far more
  • than they can be developed by education (though both may be destroyed
  • for want of education), and there is as yet no ascertained limit to
  • the nobleness of person and mind which the human creature may attain,
  • by persevering observance of the laws of God respecting its birth and
  • training. We must therefore yet farther define the aim of political
  • economy to be "the multiplication of human life at the highest
  • standard." It might at first seem questionable whether we should
  • endeavour to maintain a small number of persons of the highest type of
  • beauty and intelligence, or a larger number of an inferior class. But
  • I shall be able to show in the sequel, that the way to maintain the
  • largest number is first to aim at the highest standard. Determine the
  • noblest type of man, and aim simply at maintaining the largest
  • possible number of persons of that class, and it will be found that
  • the largest possible number of every healthy subordinate class must
  • necessarily be produced also.
  • The perfect type of manhood, as just stated, involves the perfections
  • (whatever we may hereafter determine these to be) of his body,
  • affections, and intelligence. The material things, therefore,
  • which it is the object of political economy to produce and use
  • (or accumulate for use), are things which serve either to sustain
  • and comfort the body, or exercise rightly the affections and form the
  • intelligence.[67] Whatever truly serves either of these purposes is
  • "useful" to man, wholesome, healthful, helpful, or holy. By seeking
  • such things, man prolongs and increases his life upon the earth.
  • [67] It may be observed, in anticipation of some of our future
  • results, that while some conditions of the affections are
  • aimed at by the economist as final, others are necessary to
  • him as his own instruments: as he obtains them in greater or
  • less degree his own farther work becomes more or less
  • possible. Such, for instance, are the fortifying virtues,
  • which the wisest men of all time have, with more or less
  • distinctness, arranged under the general heads of Prudence,
  • or Discretion (the spirit which discerns and adopts
  • rightly); Justice (the spirit which rules and divides
  • rightly); Fortitude (the spirit which persists and endures
  • rightly); and Temperance (the spirit which stops and refuses
  • rightly); or in shorter terms still, the virtues which teach
  • how to consist, assist, persist, and desist. These outermost
  • virtues are not only the means of protecting and prolonging
  • life itself, but they are the chief guards or sources of the
  • material means of life, and are the visible governing powers
  • and princes of economy. Thus (reserving detailed statements
  • for the sequel) precisely according to the number of just
  • men in a nation, is their power of avoiding either intestine
  • or foreign war. All disputes may be peaceably settled, if a
  • sufficient number of persons have been trained to submit to
  • the principles of justice. The necessity for war is in
  • direct ratio to the number of unjust persons who are
  • incapable of determining a quarrel but by violence. Whether
  • the injustice take the form of the desire of dominion, or of
  • refusal to submit to it, or of lust of territory, or lust of
  • money, or of mere irregular passion and wanton will, the
  • result is economically the same;--loss of the quantity of
  • power and life consumed in repressing the injustice, as well
  • as of that requiring to be repressed, added to the material
  • and moral destruction caused by the fact of war. The early
  • civil wars of England, and the existing war in America, are
  • curious examples--these under monarchical, this under
  • republican institutions--of the results of the want of
  • education of large masses of nations in principles of
  • justice. This latter war, especially, may perhaps at least
  • serve for some visible, or if that be impossible (for the
  • Greeks told us that Plutus was blind, as Dante that he was
  • speechless), some feelable proof that true political economy
  • is an ethical, and by no means a commercial business. The
  • Americans imagined themselves to know somewhat of
  • money-making; bowed low before their Dollar, expecting
  • Divine help from it; more than potent--even omnipotent. Yet
  • all the while this apparently tangible, was indeed an
  • imaginary Deity;--and had they shown the substance of him to
  • any true economist, or even true mineralogist, they would
  • have been told, long years ago,--"Alas, gentlemen, this that
  • you are gaining is not gold,--not a particle of it. It is
  • yellow, and glittering, and like enough to the real
  • metal,--but see--it is brittle, cat-gold, 'iron firestone.'
  • Out of this, heap it as high as you will, you will get so
  • much steel and brimstone--nothing else; and in a year or
  • two, when (had you known a little of right economy) you
  • might have had quiet roof-trees over your heads, and a fair
  • account at your banker's, you shall instead have to sleep
  • a-field, under red tapestries, costliest, yet comfortless;
  • and at your banker's find deficit at compound interest." But
  • the mere dread or distrust resulting from the want of inner
  • virtues of Faith and Charity among nations, is often no less
  • costly than war itself. The fear which France and England
  • have of each other costs each nation about fifteen millions
  • sterling annually, besides various paralyses of commerce;
  • that sum being spent in the manufacture of means of
  • destruction instead of means of production. There is no more
  • reason in the nature of things that France and England
  • should be hostile to each other than that England and
  • Scotland should be, or Lancashire and Yorkshire; and the
  • reciprocal terrors of the opposite sides of the English
  • Channel are neither more necessary, more economical, nor
  • more virtuous than the old riding and reiving on opposite
  • flanks of the Cheviots, or than England's own weaving for
  • herself of crowns of thorn from the stems of her Red and
  • White Roses.
  • On the other hand, whatever does not serve either of these
  • purposes,--much more whatever counteracts them,--is in like manner
  • useless to man, unwholesome, unhelpful, or unholy; and by seeking such
  • things man shortens and diminishes his life upon the earth. And
  • neither with respect to things useful or useless can man's estimate of
  • them alter their nature. Certain substances being good for his food,
  • and others noxious to him, what he thinks or wishes respecting them
  • can neither change their nature, nor prevent their power. If he eats
  • corn, he will live; if nightshade, he will die. If he produce or make
  • good and beautiful things, they will "recreate" him (note the
  • solemnity and weight of the word); if bad and ugly things, they will
  • "corrupt" or break in pieces--that is, in the exact degree of their
  • power, kill him. For every hour of labour, however enthusiastic or
  • well intended, which he spends for that which is not bread, so much
  • possibility of life is lost to him. His fancies, likings, beliefs,
  • however brilliant, eager, or obstinate, are of no avail if they are
  • set on a false object. Of all that he has laboured for, the eternal
  • law of heaven and earth measures out to him for reward, to the utmost
  • atom, that part which he ought to have laboured for, and withdraws
  • from him (or enforces on him, it may be) inexorably that part which he
  • ought not to have laboured for. The dust and chaff are all, to the
  • last speck, winnowed away, and on his summer threshing-floor stands
  • his heap of corn; little or much, not according to his labour, but to
  • his discretion. No "commercial arrangements," no painting of surfaces
  • nor alloying of substances, will avail him a pennyweight. Nature asks
  • of him calmly and inevitably, What have you found, or formed--the
  • right thing or the wrong? By the right thing you shall live; by the
  • wrong you shall die.
  • To thoughtless persons it seems otherwise. The world looks to them as
  • if they could cozen it out of some ways and means of life. But they
  • cannot cozen IT; they can only cozen their neighbours. The world is
  • not to be cheated of a grain; not so much as a breath of its air can
  • be drawn surreptitiously. For every piece of wise work done, so much
  • life is granted; for every piece of foolish work, nothing; for every
  • piece of wicked work, so much death. This is as sure as the courses of
  • day and night. But when the means of life are once produced, men, by
  • their various struggles and industries of accumulation or exchange,
  • may variously gather, waste, restrain, or distribute them;
  • necessitating, in proportion to the waste or restraint, accurately so
  • much more death. The rate and range of additional death is measured by
  • the rate and range of waste, and is inevitable;--the only question
  • (determined mostly by fraud in peace, and force in war) is, Who is to
  • die, and how?
  • Such being the everlasting law of human existence, the essential work
  • of the political economist is to determine what are in reality useful
  • and life-giving things, and by what degrees and kinds of labour they
  • are attainable and distributable. This investigation divides itself
  • under three great heads--first, of Wealth; secondly, of Money; and
  • thirdly, of Riches.
  • These terms are often used as synonymous, but they signify entirely
  • different things. "Wealth," consists of things in themselves valuable;
  • "Money," of documentary claims to the possession of such things; and
  • "Riches" is a relative term, expressing the magnitude of the
  • possessions of one person or society as compared with those of other
  • persons or societies.
  • The study of Wealth is a province of natural science:--it deals with
  • the essential properties of things.
  • The study of Money is a province of commercial science:--it deals with
  • conditions of engagement and exchange.
  • The study of Riches is a province of moral science:--it deals with the
  • due relations of men to each other in regard of material possessions;
  • and with the just laws of their association for purposes of labour.
  • I shall in this paper shortly sketch out the range of subjects which
  • will come before us as we follow these three branches of inquiry.
  • SECTION I.--WEALTH.
  • Wealth, it has been said, consists of things essentially valuable. We
  • now, therefore, need a definition of "value."
  • Value signifies the strength or "availing" of anything towards the
  • sustaining of life, and is always twofold; that is to say, primarily,
  • INTRINSIC, and, secondarily, EFFECTUAL.
  • The reader must, by anticipation, be warned against confusing value
  • with cost, or with price. Value is the life-giving power of anything;
  • cost, the quantity of labour required to produce it; price, the
  • quantity of labour which its possessor will take in exchange for it.
  • Cost and price are commercial conditions, to be studied under the head
  • of Money.
  • Intrinsic value is the absolute power of anything to support life. A
  • sheaf of wheat of given quality and weight has in it a measurable
  • power of sustaining the substance of the body; a cubic foot of pure
  • air, a fixed power of sustaining its warmth; and a cluster of flowers
  • of given beauty, a fixed power of enlivening or animating the senses
  • and heart.
  • It does not in the least affect the intrinsic value of the wheat, the
  • air, or the flowers, that men refuse or despise them. Used or not,
  • their own power is in them, and that particular power is in nothing
  • else.
  • But in order that this value of theirs may become effectual, a certain
  • state is necessary in the recipient of it. The digesting, the
  • breathing, and perceiving functions must be perfect in the human
  • creature before the food, air, or flowers can become their full value
  • to it. The production of effectual value, therefore, always involves
  • two needs; first, the production of a thing essentially useful; then
  • the production of the capacity to use it. Where the intrinsic value
  • and acceptant capacity come together there is EFFECTUAL value, or
  • wealth. Where there is either no intrinsic value, or no acceptant
  • capacity, there is no effectual value; that is to say, no wealth. A
  • horse is no wealth to us if we cannot ride, nor a picture if we cannot
  • see, nor can any noble thing be wealth, except to a noble person. As
  • the aptness of the user increases, the effectual value of the thing
  • used increases; and in its entirety can co-exist only with perfect
  • skill of use, or harmony of nature. The effectual value of a given
  • quantity of any commodity existing in the world at any moment is
  • therefore a mathematical function of the capacity existing in the
  • human race to enjoy it. Let its intrinsic value be represented by _x_,
  • and the recipient faculty by _y_; its effectual value is _x y_, in
  • which the sum varies as either co-efficient varies, is increased by
  • either's increase,[68] and cancelled by either's absence.
  • [68] With this somewhat strange and ungeometrical limitation,
  • however, which, here expressed for the moment in the
  • briefest terms, we must afterwards trace in detail--that _x
  • y_ may be indefinitely increased by the increase of _y_
  • only; but not by the increase of _x_, unless _y_ increases
  • also in a fixed proportion.
  • Valuable material things may be conveniently referred to five heads:--
  • 1. Land, with an associated air, water, and organisms.
  • 2. Houses, furniture, and instruments.
  • 3. Stored or prepared food and medicine, and articles of bodily
  • luxury, including clothing.
  • 4. Books.
  • 5. Works of art.
  • We shall enter into separate inquiry as to the conditions of value
  • under each of these heads. The following sketch of the entire subject
  • may be useful for future reference:--
  • 1. Land. Its value is twofold--
  • A. As producing food and mechanical power.
  • B. As an object of sight and thought, producing intellectual power.
  • A. Its value, as a means of producing food and mechanical power,
  • varies with its form (as mountain or plain), with its substance (in
  • soil or mineral contents), and with its climate. All these conditions
  • of intrinsic value, in order to give effectual value, must be known
  • and complied with by the men who have to deal with it; but at any
  • given time, or place, the intrinsic value is fixed; such and such a
  • piece of land, with its associated lakes and seas, rightly treated
  • in surface and substance, can produce precisely so much food
  • and power, and no more. Its surface treatment (agriculture) and
  • substance treatment (practical geology and chemistry), are the
  • first roots of economical science. By surface treatment, however, I
  • mean more than agriculture as commonly understood; I mean land
  • and sea culture;--dominion over both the fixed and the flowing
  • fields;--perfect acquaintance with the laws of climate, and of
  • vegetable and animal growth in the given tracts of earth or ocean, and
  • of their relations regulating especially the production of those
  • articles of food which, being in each particular spot producible in
  • the highest perfection, will bring the best price in commercial
  • exchanges.
  • B. The second element of value in land is its beauty, united with such
  • conditions of space and form as are necessary for exercise, or
  • pleasant to the eye, associated with vital organism.
  • Land of the highest value in these respects is that lying in temperate
  • climates, and boldly varied in form; removed from unhealthy or
  • dangerous influences (as of miasm or volcano); and capable of
  • sustaining a rich fauna and flora. Such land, carefully tended by the
  • hand of man, so far as to remove from it unsightlinesses and evidences
  • of decay; guarded from violence, and inhabited, under man's
  • affectionate protection, by every kind of living creature that can
  • occupy it in peace, forms the most precious "property" that human
  • beings can possess.
  • The determination of the degree in which these two elements of value
  • can be united in land, or in which either element must, or should, in
  • particular cases, be sacrificed to the other, forms the most important
  • branch of economical inquiry respecting preferences of things.
  • 2. Buildings, furniture, and instruments.
  • The value of buildings consists--A, in permanent strength, with
  • convenience of form, of size, and of position; so as to render
  • employment peaceful, social intercourse easy, temperature and air
  • healthy. The advisable or possible magnitude of cities and mode of
  • their distribution in squares, streets, courts, etc., the relative
  • value of sites of land, and the modes of structure which are
  • healthiest and most permanent, have to be studied under this head.
  • B. The value of buildings consists, secondarily, in historical
  • association and architectural beauty, of which we have to examine the
  • influence on manners and life.
  • The value of instruments consists--
  • A. In their power of shortening labour, or otherwise accomplishing (as
  • ships) what human strength unaided could not. The kinds of work which
  • are severally best accomplished by hand or by machine;--the effect of
  • machinery in gathering and multiplying population, and its influence
  • on the minds and bodies of such population; together with the
  • conceivable uses of machinery on a colossal scale in accomplishing
  • mighty and useful works, hitherto unthought of, such as the deepening
  • of large river channels;--changing the surface of mountainous
  • districts;--irrigating tracts of desert in the torrid zone;--breaking
  • up, and thus rendering capable of quicker fusion edges of ice in the
  • northern and southern Arctic seas, etc., so rendering parts of the
  • earth habitable which hitherto have not been so, are to be studied
  • under this head.
  • B. The value of instruments is, secondarily, in their aid to abstract
  • sciences. The degree in which the multiplication of such instruments
  • should be encouraged, so as to make them, if large, easy of access to
  • numbers (as costly telescopes), or so cheap as that they might, in a
  • serviceable form, become a common part of the furniture of households,
  • is to be considered under this head.
  • 3. Food, medicine, and articles of luxury. Under this head we shall
  • have to examine the possible methods of obtaining pure and nourishing
  • food in such security and equality of supply as to avoid both waste
  • and famine; then the economy of medicine and just range of sanitary
  • law; finally, the economy of luxury, partly an aesthetic and partly an
  • ethical question.
  • 4. Books. The value of these consists--
  • A. In their power of preserving and communicating the knowledge of
  • facts.
  • B. In their power of exciting vital or noble emotion and intellectual
  • action. They have also their corresponding negative powers of
  • disguising and effacing the memory of facts, and killing the noble
  • emotions, or exciting base ones. Under these two heads we have to
  • consider the economical and educational value, positive and negative,
  • of literature;--the means of producing and educating good authors, and
  • the means and advisability of rendering good books generally
  • accessible, and directing the reader's choice to them.
  • 5. Works of art. The value of these is of the same nature as that of
  • books, but the laws of their production and possible modes of
  • distribution are very different, and require separate examination.
  • SECTION II.--MONEY.
  • Under this head, we shall have to examine the laws of currency and
  • exchange; of which I will note here the first principles.
  • Money has been inaccurately spoken of as merely a means of
  • circulation. It is, on the contrary, an expression of right. It is not
  • wealth, being the sign[69] of the relative quantities of it, to which,
  • at a given time, persons or societies are entitled.
  • [69] Always, and necessarily, an imperfect sign; but capable
  • of approximate accuracy if rightly ordered.
  • If all the money in the world, notes and gold, were destroyed in an
  • instant, it would leave the world neither richer nor poorer than it
  • was. But it would leave the individual inhabitants of it in different
  • relations.
  • Money is, therefore, correspondent in its nature to the title-deed of
  • an estate. Though the deed be burned, the estate still exists, but the
  • right to it has become disputable.
  • The worth of money remains unchanged, as long as the proportion of the
  • quantity of existing money to the quantity of existing wealth, or
  • available labour which it professes to represent, remains unchanged.
  • If the wealth increases, but not the money, the worth of the money
  • increases; if the money increases, but not the wealth, the worth of
  • the money diminishes.
  • Money, therefore, cannot be arbitrarily multiplied, any more than
  • title-deeds can. So long as the existing wealth or available labour is
  • not fully represented by the currency, the currency may be increased
  • without diminution of the assigned worth of its pieces. But when the
  • existing wealth, or available labour, is once fully represented, every
  • piece of money thrown into circulation diminishes the worth of every
  • other existing piece, in the proportion it bears to the number of
  • them, provided the new piece be received with equal credit; if not,
  • the depreciation of worth takes place exclusively in the new piece,
  • according to the inferiority of its credit.
  • When, however, new money, composed of some substance of supposed
  • intrinsic value (as of gold), is brought into the market, or when new
  • notes are issued which are supposed to be deserving of credit, the
  • desire to obtain money will, under certain circumstances, stimulate
  • industry; an additional quantity of wealth is immediately produced,
  • and if this be in proportion to the new claims advanced, the value of
  • the existing currency is undepreciated. If the stimulus given be so
  • great as to produce more goods than are proportioned to the additional
  • coinage, the worth of the existing currency will be raised.
  • Arbitrary control and issues of currency affect the production of
  • wealth, by acting on the hopes and fears of men; and are, under
  • certain circumstances, wise. But the issue of additional currency to
  • meet the exigencies of immediate expense, is merely one of the
  • disguised forms of borrowing or taxing.
  • It is, however, in the present low state of economical knowledge,
  • often possible for Governments to venture on an issue of currency,
  • when they could not venture on an additional loan or tax, because the
  • real operation of such issue is not understood by the people, and the
  • pressure of it is irregularly distributed, and with an unperceived
  • gradation. Finally, the use of substances of intrinsic value as the
  • materials of a currency, is a barbarism;--a remnant of the conditions
  • of barter, which alone can render commerce possible among savage
  • nations. It is, however, still necessary, partly as a mechanical check
  • on arbitrary issues; partly as a means of exchanges with foreign
  • nations. In proportion to the extension of civilization, and increase
  • of trustworthiness in Governments, it will cease. So long as it
  • exists, the phenomena of the cost and price of the articles used for
  • currency, are mingled with those of currency itself, in an almost
  • inextricable manner; and the worth of money in the market is affected
  • by multitudinous accidental circumstances, which have been traced,
  • with more or less success, by writers on commercial operations; but
  • with these variations the true political economist has no more to do
  • than an engineer fortifying a harbour of refuge against Atlantic tide,
  • has to concern himself with the cries or quarrels of children who dig
  • pools with their fingers for its ebbing currents among the sand.
  • SECTION III.--RICHES.
  • According to the various industry, capacity, good fortune, and desires
  • of men, they obtain greater or smaller share of, and claim upon, the
  • wealth of the world.
  • The inequalities between these shares, always in some degree just and
  • necessary, may be either restrained by law (or circumstance) within
  • certain limits; or may increase indefinitely.
  • Where no moral or legal restraint is put upon the exercise of the will
  • and intellect of the stronger, shrewder, or more covetous men, these
  • differences become ultimately enormous. But as soon as they become so
  • distinct in their extremes as that, on one side, there shall be
  • manifest redundance of possession, and on the other manifest pressure
  • of need,--the terms "riches" and "poverty" are used to express the
  • opposite states; being contrary only in the manner of the terms
  • "warmth" and "cold"; which neither of them imply an actual degree, but
  • only a relation to other degrees, of temperature.
  • Respecting riches, the economist has to inquire, first, into the
  • advisable modes of their collection; secondly, into the advisable
  • modes of their administration. Respecting the collection of national
  • riches, he has to inquire, first, whether he is justified in calling
  • the nation rich; if the quantity of money it possesses relatively to
  • that possessed by other nations be large, irrespectively of the manner
  • of its distribution. Or does the mode of distribution in any wise
  • affect the nature of the riches? Thus, if the king alone be
  • rich--suppose Croesus or Mausolus--are the Lydians and Carians
  • therefore a rich nation? Or if one or two slave-masters be rich, and
  • the nation be otherwise composed of slaves, is it to be called a rich
  • nation? For if not, and the ideas of a certain mode of distribution
  • or operation in the riches, and of a certain degree of freedom in the
  • people, enter into our idea of riches as attributed to a people, we
  • shall have to define the degree of fluency or circulative character
  • which is essential to their vitality; and the degree of independence
  • of action required in their possessors. Questions which look as if
  • they would take time in answering. And farther. Since there are two
  • modes in which the inequality, which is indeed the condition and
  • constituent of riches, may be established--namely, by increase of
  • possession on the one side, and by decrease of it on the other--we
  • have to inquire, with respect to any given state of riches, precisely
  • in what manner the correlative poverty was produced; that is to say,
  • whether by being surpassed only, or being depressed, what are the
  • advantages, or the contrary, conceivable in the depression. For
  • instance, it being one of the commonest advantages of being rich to
  • entertain a number of servants, we have to inquire, on the one side,
  • what economical process produced the poverty of the persons who serve
  • him; and what advantage each (on his own side) derives from the
  • result.
  • These being the main questions touching the collection of riches, the
  • next, or last, part of the inquiry is into their administration.
  • They have in the main three great economical powers which require
  • separate examination: namely, the powers of selection, direction, and
  • provision.
  • A. Their power of SELECTION relates to things of which the supply is
  • limited (as the supply of best things is always). When it becomes
  • matter of question to whom such things are to belong, the richest
  • person has necessarily the first choice, unless some arbitrary mode of
  • distribution be otherwise determined upon. The business of the
  • economist is to show how this choice may be a Wise one.
  • B. Their power of DIRECTION arises out of the necessary relation of
  • rich men to poor, which ultimately, in one way or another, involves
  • the direction of, or authority over, the labour of the poor; and this
  • nearly as much over their mental as their bodily labour. The business
  • of the economist is to show how this direction may be a Just one.
  • C. Their power of PROVISION or "preparatory sight" (for pro-accumulation
  • is by no means necessarily pro-vision), is dependent upon their
  • redundance; which may of course by active persons be made available
  • in preparation for future work or future profit; in which function
  • riches have generally received the name of capital; that is to say, of
  • head- or source-material. The business of the economist is to show how
  • this provision may be a Distant one.
  • The examination of these three functions of riches will embrace every
  • final problem of political economy;--and, above, or before all, this
  • curious and vital problem,--whether, since the wholesome action of
  • riches in these three functions will depend (it appears) on the
  • Wisdom, Justice, and Far-sightedness of the holders; and it is by no
  • means to be assumed that persons primarily rich, must therefore be
  • just and wise,--it may not be ultimately possible so, or somewhat so,
  • to arrange matters, as that persons primarily just and wise, should
  • therefore be rich.
  • Such being the general plan of the inquiry before us, I shall not
  • limit myself to any consecutive following of it, having hardly any
  • good hope of being able to complete so laborious a work as it must
  • prove to me; but from time to time, as I have leisure, shall endeavour
  • to carry forward this part or that, as may be immediately possible;
  • indicating always with accuracy the place which the particular essay
  • will or should take in the completed system.
  • II.
  • NATURE OF WEALTH, VARIATIONS OF VALUE, THE NATIONAL STORE, NATURE OF
  • LABOUR, VALUE AND PRICE, THE CURRENCY.
  • The last paper having consisted of little more than definition of
  • terms, I purpose, in this, to expand and illustrate the given
  • definitions, so as to avoid confusion in their use when we enter into
  • the detail of our subject.
  • The view which has been taken of the nature of wealth, namely, that it
  • consists in an intrinsic value developed by a vital power, is directly
  • opposed to two nearly universal conceptions of wealth. In the
  • assertion that value is primarily intrinsic, it opposes the idea that
  • anything which is an object of desire to numbers, and is limited in
  • quantity, may be called, or virtually become, wealth. And in the
  • assertion that value is secondarily dependent upon power in the
  • possessor, it opposes the idea that wealth consists of things
  • exchangeable at rated prices. Before going farther, we will make these
  • two positions clearer.
  • First. All wealth is intrinsic, and is not constituted by the judgment
  • of men. This is easily seen in the case of things affecting the body;
  • we know that no force of fantasy will make stones nourishing, or
  • poison innocent; but it is less apparent in things affecting the mind.
  • We are easily--perhaps willingly--misled by the appearance of
  • beneficial results obtained by industries addressed wholly to the
  • gratification of fanciful desire; and apt to suppose that whatever is
  • widely coveted, dearly bought, and pleasurable in possession, must be
  • included in our definition of wealth. It is the more difficult to quit
  • ourselves of this error because many things which are true wealth in
  • moderate use, yet become false wealth in immoderate; and many things
  • are mixed of good and evil,--as, mostly, books and works of art,--out
  • of which one person will get the good, and another the evil; so that
  • it seems as if there were no fixed good or evil in the things
  • themselves, but only in the view taken, and use made of them. But that
  • is not so. The evil and good are fixed in essence and in proportion.
  • They are separable by instinct and judgment, but not interchangeable;
  • and in things in which evil depends upon excess, the point of excess,
  • though indefinable, is fixed; and the power of the thing is on the
  • hither side for good, and on the farther side for evil. And in all
  • cases this power is inherent, not dependent on opinion or choice. Our
  • thoughts of things neither make, nor mar their eternal force;
  • nor--which is the most serious point for future consideration--can
  • they prevent the effect of it upon ourselves.
  • Therefore, the object of special analysis of wealth into which we have
  • presently to enter will be not so much to enumerate what is
  • serviceable, as to distinguish what is destructive; and to show that
  • it is inevitably destructive; that to receive pleasure from an evil
  • thing is not to escape from, or alter the evil of it, but to be
  • altered by it; that is, to suffer from it to the utmost, having our
  • own nature, in that degree, made evil also. And it will be shown
  • farther that, through whatever length of time or subtleties of
  • connexion the harm is accomplished (being also less or more according
  • to the fineness and worth of the humanity on which it is wrought),
  • still, nothing but harm ever comes of a bad thing.
  • So that, finally, wealth is not the accidental object of a morbid
  • desire, but the constant object of a legitimate one.[70] By the fury
  • of ignorance, and fitfulness of caprice, large interests may be
  • continually attached to things unserviceable or hurtful; if their
  • nature could be altered by our passions, the science of Political
  • Economy would be but as the weighing of clouds, and the portioning out
  • of shadows. But of ignorance there is no science; and of caprice no
  • law. Their disturbing forces interfere with the operations of economy,
  • but have nothing in common with them; the calm arbiter of national
  • destiny regards only essential power for good in all it accumulates,
  • and alike disdains the wanderings of imagination and the thirsts of
  • disease.
  • [70] Few passages of the Book which at least some part of the
  • nations at present most advanced in civilization accept as
  • an expression of final truth, have been more distorted than
  • those bearing on Idolatry. For the idolatry there denounced
  • is neither sculpture, nor veneration of sculpture. It is
  • simply the substitution of an "Eidolon," phantasm, or
  • imagination of Good, for that which is real and enduring;
  • from the Highest Living Good, which gives life, to the
  • lowest material good which ministers to it. The Creator, and
  • the things created, which He is said to have "seen good" in
  • creating, are in this their eternal goodness always called
  • Helpful or Holy: and the sweep and range of idolatry extend
  • to the rejection of all or any of these, "calling evil good,
  • or good evil,--putting bitter for sweet, and sweet for
  • bitter," so betraying the first of all Loyalties, to the
  • fixed Law of life, and with resolute opposite loyalty
  • serving our own imagination of good, which is the law, not
  • of the dwelling, but of the Grave (otherwise called the law
  • of error; or "mark missing," which we translate law of
  • "Sin"), these "two masters," between whose services we have
  • to choose, being otherwise distinguished as God and
  • "Mammon," which Mammon, though we narrowly take it as the
  • power of money only, is in truth the great evil spirit of
  • false and fond desire, or "Covetousness, which is Idolatry."
  • So that Iconoclasm--image or likeness-breaking--is easy; but
  • an idol cannot be broken--it must be forsaken, and this is
  • not so easy, either in resolution or persuasion. For men may
  • readily be convinced of the weakness of an image, but not of
  • the emptiness of a phantasm.
  • Secondly. The assertion that wealth is not only intrinsic, but
  • dependent, in order to become effectual, on a given degree of vital
  • power in its possessor, is opposed to another popular view of
  • wealth;--namely, that though it may always be constituted by caprice,
  • it is, when so constituted, a substantial thing, of which given
  • quantities may be counted as existing here, or there, and exchangeable
  • at rated prices.
  • In this view there are three errors. The first and chief is the
  • overlooking the fact that all exchangeableness of commodity, or
  • effective demand for it, depends on the sum of capacity for its use
  • existing, here or elsewhere. The book we cannot read, or picture we
  • take no delight in, may indeed be called part of our wealth, in so far
  • as we have power of exchanging either for something we like better.
  • But our power of effecting such exchange, and yet more, of effecting
  • it to advantage, depends absolutely on the number of accessible
  • persons who can understand the book, or enjoy the painting, and who
  • will dispute the possession of them. Thus the actual worth of either,
  • even to us, depends no less on their essential goodness than on the
  • capacity consisting somewhere for the perception of it; and it is vain
  • in any completed system of production to think of obtaining one
  • without the other. So that, though the great political economist knows
  • that co-existence of capacity for use with temporary possession cannot
  • be always secured, the final fact, on which he bases all action and
  • administration, is that, in the whole nation, or group of nations, he
  • has to deal with, for every grain of intrinsic value produced he must
  • with exactest chemistry produce its twin grain of governing capacity,
  • or in the degrees of his failure he has no wealth. Nature's challenge
  • to us is in earnest, as the Assyrian's mock, "I will give you two
  • thousand horses, if thou be able on thy part to set riders upon them."
  • Bavieca's paces are brave, if the Cid backs him; but woe to us, if we
  • take the dust of capacity, wearing the armour of it, for capacity
  • itself, for so all procession, however goodly in the show of it, is to
  • the tomb.
  • The second error in this popular view of wealth is that, in estimating
  • property which we cannot use as wealth, because it is exchangeable, we
  • in reality confuse wealth with money. The land we have no skill to
  • cultivate, the book which is sealed to us, or dress which is
  • superfluous, may indeed be exchangeable, but as such are nothing more
  • than a cumbrous form of bank-note, of doubtful and slow
  • convertibility. As long as we retain possession of them, we merely
  • keep our bank-notes in the shape of gravel or clay, of book leaves, or
  • of embroidered tissue. Circumstances may perhaps render such forms the
  • safest, or a certain complacency may attach to the exhibition of
  • them;--into both these advantages we shall inquire afterwards; I wish
  • the reader only to observe here, that exchangeable property which we
  • cannot use is, to us personally, merely one of the forms of money, not
  • of wealth.
  • The third error in the popular view is the confusion of guardianship
  • with possession; the real state of men of property being, too commonly
  • that of curators, not possessors of wealth. For a man's power of Use,
  • Administration, Ostentation, Destruction, or Bequest; and possession
  • is in use only, which for each man is sternly limited; so that such
  • things, and so much of them, are well for him, or Wealth; and more of
  • them, or any other things, are ill for him, or Illth. Plunged to the
  • lips in Orinoco, he shall drink to his thirst measure,--more, at his
  • peril; with a thousand oxen on his lands, he shall eat to his hunger
  • measure,--more, at his peril. He cannot live in two houses at once; a
  • few bales of silk or wool will suffice for the fabric of all the
  • clothes he can ever wear, and a few books will probably hold all the
  • furniture good for his brain.[71] Beyond these, in the best of us but
  • narrow, capacities, we have but the power of administering, or if for
  • harm, mal-administering, wealth (that is to say, distributing,
  • lending, or increasing it);--of exhibiting it (as in magnificence of
  • retinue or furniture), of destroying, or, finally, of bequeathing it.
  • And with multitudes of rich men, administration degenerates into
  • curatorship; they merely hold their property in charge, as Trustees,
  • for the benefit of some person or persons to whom it is to be
  • delivered upon their death; and the position, explained in clear
  • terms, would hardly seem a covetable one. What would be the probable
  • decision of a youth on his entrance into life, to whom the career
  • hoped for him was proposed in terms such as these: "You must work
  • unremittingly, and with your utmost intelligence, during all your
  • available years; you will thus accumulate wealth to a large amount;
  • but you must touch none of it, beyond what is needful for your
  • support. Whatever sums you may gain beyond those required for your
  • decent and moderate maintenance shall be properly taken care of, and
  • on your death-bed you shall have the power of determining to whom they
  • shall belong, or to what purposes be applied?"
  • [71] I reserve, until the completion and collection of these
  • papers, any support by the authority of other writers of the
  • statements made in them; were, indeed, such authorities
  • wisely sought for and shown, there would be no occasion for
  • my writing at all. Even in the scattered passages referring
  • to this subject in three books of Carlyle's:--"Sartor
  • Resartus"; "Past and Present"; and the "Latter-Day
  • Pamphlets"; all has been said that needs to be said, and far
  • better than I shall ever say it again. But the habit of the
  • public mind at the present is to require everything to be
  • uttered diffusely, loudly, and seven times over, before it
  • will listen; and it has exclaimed against these papers of
  • mine, as if they contained things daring and new, when there
  • is not one assertion in them of which the truth has not been
  • for ages known to the wisest, and proclaimed by the most
  • eloquent of men. It will be a far greater pleasure to me
  • hereafter, to collect their words than add to mine; Horace's
  • clear rendering of the substance of the preceding passages
  • in the text may be found room for at once:--
  • Si quis emat citharas, emptas comportet in unum,
  • Nec studio citharae, nec Musae deditus ulli;
  • Si scalpra et formas, non sutor; nautica vela,
  • Aversus mercaturis: delirus et amens
  • Undique dicatur merito. Quî discrepat istis,
  • Qui nummos aurumque recondit, nescius uti
  • Compositis, metuensque velut contingere sacrum?
  • With which it is perhaps desirable also to give Xenophon's
  • statement, it being clearer than any English one can be,
  • owing to the power of the general Greek term for wealth,
  • "useable things":--
  • [Greek: Tauta ara onta, tô men epistamenô chrêsthai
  • autôn hekastois chrêmata esti, tô de mê epistamenô,
  • ou chrêmata; hôsper ge auloi tô men epistamenô axiôs
  • logou aulein chrêmata eisi, tô de mê epistamenô ouden
  • mallon ê achrêstoi lithoi, ei mê apsdidoito ge autous.
  • * * * Mê pôloumenoi men gar ou chrêmata eisin hoi auloi;
  • (ouden gar chrêsimoi eisi) pôloumenoi de chrêmata;
  • Pros tauta d' ho Sôkratês eipen, ên epistêtai ge pôlein.
  • Ei de pôloin hau pros touton hos mê epistêtai chrêsthai,
  • oude pôloumenoi eisi chrêmata.]
  • The labour of life, under such conditions, would probably be neither
  • zealous nor cheerful; yet the only difference between this position
  • and that of the ordinary capitalist is the power which the latter
  • delights in supposing himself to possess, and which is attributed to
  • him by others, of spending his money at any moment. This pleasure,
  • taken in the imagination of power to part with that which we have no
  • intention of parting with, is one of the most curious though commonest
  • forms of Eidolon, or Phantasm of Wealth. But the political economist
  • has nothing to do with this idealism, and looks only to the practical
  • issue of it,--namely, that the holder of wealth, in such temper,
  • may be regarded simply as a mechanical means of collection;
  • or as a money-chest with a slit in it,[72] set in the public
  • thoroughfare;--chest of which only Death has the key, and probably
  • Chance the distribution of contents. In his function of lender (which,
  • however, is one of administration, not use, as far as he is himself
  • concerned), the capitalist takes, indeed, a more interesting aspect;
  • but even in that function, his relations with the state are apt to
  • degenerate into a mechanism for the convenient contraction of debt;--a
  • function the more mischievous, because a nation invariably appeases
  • its conscience with respect to an unjustifiable expense by meeting it
  • with borrowed funds,--expresses its repentance of a foolish piece of
  • business by letting its tradesmen wait for their money,--and always
  • leaves its descendants to pay for the work which will be of the least
  • service to them.[73]
  • [72] The orifice being not merely of a receptant, but of a
  • suctional character. Among the types of human virtue and
  • vice presented grotesquely by the lower animals, perhaps
  • none is more curiously definite that that of avarice in the
  • Cephalopod, a creature which has a purse for a body; a
  • hawk's beak for a mouth; suckers for feet and hands; and
  • whose house is its own skeleton.
  • [73] It would be well if a somewhat dogged conviction could
  • be enforced on nations as on individuals, that, with few
  • exceptions, what they cannot at present pay for, they should
  • not at present have.
  • Quit of these three sources of misconception, the reader will have
  • little farther difficulty in apprehending the real nature of Effectual
  • value. He may, however, at first not without surprise, perceive the
  • consequences involved in the acceptance of our definition. For if the
  • actual existence of wealth be dependent on the power of its possessor,
  • it follows that the sum of wealth held by the nation, instead of being
  • constant or calculable, varies hourly, nay, momentarily, with the
  • number and character of its holders; and that in changing hands, it
  • changes in quantity. And farther, since the worth of the currency is
  • proportioned to the sum of material wealth which it represents, if the
  • sum of the wealth changes, the worth of the currency changes. And thus
  • both the sum of the property, and power of the currency, of the State,
  • vary momentarily, as the character and number of the holders. And not
  • only so, but a different rate and manner of variation is caused by the
  • character of the holders of different kinds of wealth. The transitions
  • of value caused by the character of the holders of land differ in mode
  • from those caused by character in holders of works of art; and these
  • again from those caused by character in holders of machinery or other
  • working capital. But we cannot examine these special phenomena of any
  • kind of wealth until we have a clear idea of the way in which true
  • currency expresses them; and of the resulting modes in which the cost
  • and price of any article are related to its value. To obtain this we
  • must approach the subject in its first elements.
  • Let us suppose a national store of wealth, real or imaginary (that is
  • to say, composed of material things either useful, or believed to be
  • so), presided over by a Government,[74] and that every workman, having
  • produced any article involving labour in its production, and for which
  • he has no immediate use, brings it to add to this store, receiving,
  • from the Government, in exchange an order either for the return of the
  • thing itself, or of its equivalent in other things,[75] such as he may
  • choose out of the store at any time when he needs them. Now, supposing
  • that the labourer speedily uses this general order, or, in common
  • language, "spends the money," he has neither changed the circumstances
  • of the nation nor his own, except in so far as he may have produced
  • useful and consumed useless articles, or vice versa. But if he does
  • not use, or uses in part only, the order he receives, and lays aside
  • some portion of it; and thus every day bringing his contribution to
  • the national store, lays by some percentage of the order received in
  • exchange for it, he increases the national wealth daily by as much as
  • he does not use of the received order, and to the same amount
  • accumulates a monetary claim on the Government. It is of course always
  • in his power, as it is his legal right, to bring forward this
  • accumulation of claim, and at once to consume, to destroy, or
  • distribute, the sum of his wealth. Supposing he never does so, but
  • dies, leaving his claim to others, he has enriched the State during
  • his life by the quantity of wealth over which that claim extends, or
  • has, in other words, rendered so much additional life possible in the
  • State, of which additional life he bequeaths the immediate possibility
  • to those whom he invests with his claim, he would distribute this
  • possibility of life among the nation at large.
  • [74] The reader is to include here in the idea of "Government,"
  • any branch of the Executive, or even any body of private
  • persons, entrusted with the practical management of public
  • interests unconnected directly with their own personal ones.
  • In theoretical discussions of legislative interference
  • with political economy, it is usually and of course
  • unnecessarily, assumed that Government must be always of
  • that form and force in which we have been accustomed to see
  • it;--that its abuses can never be less, nor its wisdom
  • greater, nor its powers more numerous. But, practically, the
  • custom in most civilized countries is, for every man to
  • deprecate the interference of Government as long as things
  • tell for his personal advantage, and to call for it when
  • they cease to do so. The request of the Manchester
  • Economists to be supplied with cotton by the Government (the
  • system of supply and demand having, for the time, fallen
  • sorrowfully short of the expectations of scientific persons
  • from it), is an interesting case in point. It were to be
  • wished that less wide and bitter suffering (suffering, too,
  • of the innocent) had been needed to force the nation, or
  • some part of it, to ask itself why a body of men, already
  • confessedly capable of managing matters both military and
  • divine, should not be permitted, or even requested at need
  • to provide in some wise for sustenance as well as for
  • defence, and secure, if it might be (and it might, I think,
  • even the rather be), purity of bodily ailment, as well as of
  • religious conviction? Why, having made many roads for the
  • passage of armies, they may not make a few for the
  • conveyance of food; and after organizing, with applause,
  • various schemes of spiritual instruction for the Public,
  • organize, moreover, some methods of bodily nourishment for
  • them? Or is the soul so much less trustworthy in its
  • instincts than the stomach, that legislation is necessary
  • for the one, but inconvenient to the other?
  • There is a strange fallacy running at this time through all
  • talk about free trade. It is continually assumed that every
  • kind of Government interference takes away liberty of trade.
  • Whereas liberty is lost only when interference hinders, not
  • when it helps. You do not take away a man's freedom by
  • showing him his road--nor by making it smoother for him (not
  • that it is always desirable to do so, but it may be); nor
  • even by fencing it for him, if there is an open ditch at the
  • side of it. The real mode in which protection interferes
  • with liberty, and the real evil of it, is not in its
  • "protecting" one person, but in its hindering another; a
  • form of interference which invariably does most mischief to
  • the person it is intended to serve, which the Northern
  • Americans are about discomfortably to discover, unless they
  • think better of it. There is also a ludicrous confusion in
  • many persons' minds between protection and encouragement;
  • they differ materially. "Protection" is saying to
  • the commercial schoolboy, "Nobody shall hit you."
  • "Encouragement," is saying to him, "That's the way to
  • hit."
  • [75] The question of equivalence (namely, how much wine a man
  • is to receive in return for so much corn, or how much coal
  • in return for so much iron) is a quite separate one, which
  • we will examine presently. For the time let it be assumed
  • that this equivalence has been determined, and that the
  • Government order in exchange for a fixed weight of any
  • article (called, suppose, _a_), is either for the return of
  • that weight of the article itself, or of another fixed
  • weight of the article _b_, or another of the article _c_,
  • and so on.
  • We hitherto consider the Government itself as simply a conservative
  • power, taking charge of the wealth entrusted to it.
  • But a Government may be far other than a conservative power. It may be
  • on the one hand constructive, on the other destructive.
  • If a constructive, or improving power, using all the wealth entrusted
  • to it to the best advantage, the nation is enriched in root and branch
  • at once, and the Government is enabled for every order presented, to
  • return a quantity of wealth greater than the order was written for,
  • according to the fructification obtained in the interim.[76]
  • [76] The reader must be warned in advance that the conditions
  • here supposed have nothing to do with the "interest" of
  • money commonly so called.
  • This ability may be either concealed, in which case the currency does
  • not completely represent the wealth of the country, or it may be
  • manifested by the continual payment of the excess of value on each
  • order, in which case there is (irrespectively, observe, of collateral
  • results afterwards to be examined) a perpetual rise in the worth of
  • the currency, that is to say, a fall in the price of all articles
  • represented by it.
  • But if the Government be destructive, or a consuming power, it becomes
  • unable to return the value received on the presentation of the order.
  • This inability may either (A), be concealed by meeting demands to the
  • full, until it issue in bankruptcy, or in some form of national
  • debt;--or (B), it may be concealed during oscillatory movements
  • between destructiveness and productiveness, which result on the whole
  • in stability;--or (C), it may be manifested by the consistent return
  • of less than value received on each presented order, in which case
  • there is a consistent fall in the worth of the currency, or rise in
  • the price of the things represented by it.
  • Now, if for this conception of a central Government, we substitute
  • that of another body of persons occupied in industrial pursuits, of
  • whom each adds in his private capacity to the common store: so that
  • the store itself, instead of remaining a public property of
  • ascertainable quantity, for the guardianship of which a body of public
  • men are responsible, becomes disseminated private property, each man
  • giving in exchange for any article received from another, a general
  • order for its equivalent in whatever other article the claimant may
  • desire (such general order being payable by any member of the society
  • in whose possession the demanded article may be found), we at once
  • obtain an approximation to the actual condition of a civilized
  • mercantile community from which approximation we might easily proceed
  • into still completer analysis. I purpose, however, to arrive at every
  • result by the gradual expansion of the simpler conception; but I wish
  • the reader to observe, in the meantime, that both the social
  • conditions thus supposed (and I will by anticipation say also all
  • possible social conditions) agree in two great points; namely, in the
  • primal importance of the supposed national store or stock, and in its
  • destructibility or improvability by the holders of it.
  • I. Observe that in both conditions, that of central
  • Government-holding, and diffused private-holding, the quantity of
  • stock is of the same national moment. In the one case, indeed, its
  • amount may be known by examination of the persons to whom it is
  • confided; in the other it cannot be known but by exposing the private
  • affairs of every individual. But, known or unknown, its significance
  • is the same under each condition. The riches of the nation consist in
  • the abundance, and their wealth depends on the nature of this store.
  • II. In the second place, both conditions (and all other possible ones)
  • agree in the destructibility or improvability of the store by its
  • holders. Whether in private hands, or under Government charge, the
  • national store may be daily consumed, or daily enlarged, by its
  • possessors; and while the currency remains apparently unaltered, the
  • property it represents may diminish or increase.
  • The first question, then, which we have to put under our simple
  • conception of central Government, namely, "What store has it?" is one
  • of equal importance, whatever may be the constitution of the State;
  • while the second question--namely, "Who are the holders of the
  • store?"--involves the discussion of the constitution of the State
  • itself.
  • The first inquiry resolves itself into three heads:
  • 1. What is the nature of the store?
  • 2. What is its quantity in relation to the population?
  • 3. What is its quantity in relation to the currency?
  • The second inquiry, into two:
  • 1. Who are the Holders of the store, and in what proportions?
  • 2. Who are the Claimants of the store (that is to say, the holders
  • of the currency), and in what proportions?
  • We will examine the range of the first three questions in the present
  • paper; of the two following, in the sequel.
  • Question First. What is the nature of the store? Has the nation
  • hitherto worked for and gathered the right thing or the wrong? On that
  • issue rest the possibilities of its life.
  • For example, let us imagine a society, of no great extent, occupied in
  • procuring and laying up store of corn, wine, wool, silk, and other
  • such preservable materials of food and clothing; and that it has a
  • currency representing them. Imagine farther, that on days of
  • festivity, the society, discovering itself to derive satisfaction from
  • pyrotechnics, gradually turns its attention more and more to the
  • manufacture of gunpowder; so that an increasing number of labourers,
  • giving what time they can spare to this branch of industry, bring
  • increasing quantities of combustibles into the store, and use the
  • general orders received in exchange to obtain such wine, wool, or corn
  • as they may have need of. The currency remains the same, and
  • represents precisely the same amount of material in the store, and of
  • labour spent in producing it. But the corn and wine gradually vanish,
  • and in their place, as gradually, appear sulphur and saltpetre; till
  • at last, the labourers who have consumed corn and supplied nitre,
  • presenting on a festal morning some of their currency to obtain
  • materials for the feast, discover that no amount of currency will
  • command anything Festive, except Fire. The supply of rockets is
  • unlimited, but that of food limited in a quite final manner; and the
  • whole currency in the hands of the society represents an infinite
  • power of detonation, but none of existence.
  • The statement, caricatured as it may seem, is only exaggerated in
  • assuming the persistence of the folly to extremity, unchecked, as in
  • reality it would be, by the gradual rise in price of food. But it
  • falls short of the actual facts of human life in expression of the
  • depth and intensity of the folly itself. For a great part (the reader
  • would not believe how great until he saw the statistics in detail) of
  • the most earnest and ingenious industry of the world is spent in
  • producing munitions of war; gathering that is to say the materials,
  • not of festive, but of consuming fire; filling its stores with all
  • power of the instruments of pain, and all affluence of the ministries
  • of death. It was no true Trionfo della Morte which men have seen and
  • feared (sometimes scarcely feared) so long;--wherein he brought them
  • rest from their labours. We see and share another and higher form of
  • his triumph now. Task-master instead of Releaser, he rules the dust of
  • the arena no less than of the tomb; and, content once in the grave
  • whither man went, to make his works cease and his devices to
  • vanish,--now, in the busy city and on the serviceable sea, makes his
  • work to increase, and his devices to multiply.
  • To this doubled loss, or negative power of labour, spent in producing
  • means of destruction, we have to add in our estimate of the
  • consequences of human folly, whatever more insidious waste of toil
  • there is in the production of unnecessary luxury. Such and such an
  • occupation (it is said) supports so many labourers, because so many
  • obtain wages in following it; but it is never considered that unless
  • there be a supporting power in the product of the occupation, the
  • wages given to one man are merely withdrawn from another. We cannot
  • say of any trade that it maintains such and such a number of persons,
  • unless we know how and where the money, now spent in the purchase of
  • its produce, would have been spent, if that produce had not been
  • manufactured. The purchasing funds truly support a number of people in
  • making This; but (probably) leave unsupported an equal number who are
  • making, or could have made That. The manufacturers of small watches
  • thrive in Geneva;--it is well;--but where would the money spent on
  • small watches have gone, had there been no small watches to buy?
  • If the so frequently uttered aphorism of mercantile economy--"labour
  • is limited by capital"--were true, this question would be a definite
  • one. But it is untrue; and that widely. Out of a given quantity of
  • wages, more or less labour is to be had, according to the quantity of
  • will with which we can inspire the workman; and the true limit of
  • labour is only in the limit of this moral stimulus of the will, and
  • the bodily power. In an ultimate, but entirely practical sense, labour
  • is limited by capital, as it is by matter--that is to say, where there
  • is no material, there can be no work--but in the practical sense,
  • labour is limited only by the great original capital[77] of Head,
  • Heart, and Hand. Even in the most artificial relations of commerce, it
  • is to capital as fire to fuel: out of so much fuel you shall have so
  • much fire--not in proportion to the mass of combustibles, but to the
  • force of wind that fans and water that quenches; and the appliance of
  • both. And labour is furthered, as conflagration is, not so much by
  • added fuel, as by admitted air.
  • [77] The aphorism, being hurried English for "labour is limited
  • by want of capital," involves also awkward English in its
  • denial, which cannot be helped.
  • For which reasons, I had to insert, above, the qualifying "probably";
  • for it can never be said positively that the purchase money, or wages
  • fund of any trade is withdrawn from some other trade. The object
  • itself may be the stimulus of the production of the money which buys
  • it; that is to say, the work by which the purchaser obtained the means
  • of buying it would not have been done by him, unless he had wanted
  • that particular thing. And the production of any article not
  • intrinsically (nor in the process of manufacture) injurious, is
  • useful, if the desire of it causes productive labour in other
  • directions.
  • In the national store, therefore, the presence of things intrinsically
  • valueless does not imply an entirely correlative absence of things
  • valuable. We cannot be certain that all the labour spent on vanity has
  • been diverted from reality, and that for every bad thing produced, a
  • precious thing has been lost. In great measure, the vain things
  • represent the results of roused indolence; they have been carved, as
  • toys, in extra time; and, if they had not been made, nothing else
  • would have been made. Even to munitions of war this principle applies;
  • they partly represent the work of men who, if they had not made
  • spears, would never have made pruning-hooks, and who are incapable of
  • any activities but those of contest.
  • Thus, then, finally, the nature of the store has to be considered
  • under two main lights, the one, that of its immediate and actual
  • utility; the other, that of the past national character which it
  • signifies by its production, and future character which it must
  • develop by its uses. And the issue of this investigation will be to
  • show us that Economy does not depend merely on principles of "demand
  • and supply," but primarily on what is demanded, and what is supplied.
  • Question Second. What is the quantity of the store in relation to the
  • population? It follows from what has been already stated that the
  • accurate form in which this question has to be put is--"What quantity
  • of each article composing the store exists in proportion to the real
  • need for it by the population?" But we shall for the time assume, in
  • order to keep all our terms at the simplest, that the store is wholly
  • composed of useful articles, and accurately proportioned to the
  • several needs of them.
  • Now it does not follow, because the store is large in proportion to
  • the number of people, that the people must be in comfort, nor because
  • it is small, that they must be in distress. An active and economical
  • race always produces more than it requires, and lives (if it is
  • permitted to do so) in competence on the produce of its daily labour.
  • The quantity of its store, great or small, is therefore in many
  • respects indifferent to it, and cannot be inferred by its aspect.
  • Similarly an inactive and wasteful population, which cannot live by
  • its daily labour, but is dependent, partly or wholly, on consumption
  • of its store, may be (by various difficulties hereafter to be
  • examined, in realization of getting at such store) retained in a state
  • of abject distress, though its possessions may be immense. But the
  • results always involved in the magnitude of store are, the commercial
  • power of the nation, its security, and its mental character. Its
  • commercial power, in that according to the quantity of its store, may
  • be the extent of its dealings; its security, in that according to the
  • quantity of its store are its means of sudden exertion or sustained
  • endurance; and its character, in that certain conditions of
  • civilization cannot be attained without permanent and continually
  • accumulating store, of great intrinsic value, and of peculiar nature.
  • Now, seeing that these three advantages arise from largeness of store
  • in proportion to population, the question arises immediately, "Given
  • the store--is the nation enriched by diminution of its numbers? Are a
  • successful national speculation and a pestilence, economically the
  • same thing?"
  • This is in part a sophistical question; such as it would be to ask
  • whether a man was richer when struck by disease which must limit his
  • life within a predicable period than he was when in health. He is
  • enabled to enlarge his current expenses, and has for all purposes a
  • larger sum at his immediate disposal (for, given the fortune, the
  • shorter the life the larger the annuity); yet no man considers himself
  • richer because he is condemned by his physician. The logical reply is
  • that, since Wealth is by definition only the means of life, a nation
  • cannot be enriched by its own mortality. Or in shorter words, the life
  • is more than the meat; and existence itself more wealth than the means
  • of existence. Whence, of two nations who have equal store, the more
  • numerous is to be considered the richer, provided the type of the
  • inhabitant be as high (for, though the relative bulk of their store be
  • less, its relative efficiency, or the amount of effectual wealth,
  • must be greater). But if the type of the population be deteriorated by
  • increase of its numbers, we have evidence of poverty in its worst
  • influence; and then, to determine whether the nation in its total may
  • still be justifiably esteemed rich, we must set or weigh the number of
  • the poor against that of the rich.
  • To effect which piece of scalework, it is of course necessary to
  • determine, first, who are poor and who are rich; nor this only, but
  • also how poor and how rich they are! Which will prove a curious
  • thermometrical investigation; for we shall have to do for gold and for
  • silver what we have done for quicksilver--determine, namely, their
  • freezing-point, their zero, their temperate and fever-heat points;
  • finally, their vaporescent point, at which riches, sometimes
  • explosively, as lately in America, "make to themselves wings";--and
  • correspondently the number of degrees below zero at which poverty,
  • ceasing to brace with any wholesome cold, burns to the bone.
  • For the performance of these operations, in the strictest sense
  • scientific, we will first look to the existing so-called "science" of
  • Political Economy; we will ask it to define for us the comparatively
  • and superlatively rich, and the comparatively and superlatively poor;
  • and on its own terms--if any terms it can pronounce--examine, in our
  • prosperous England, how many rich and how many poor people there are;
  • and whether the quantity and intensity of the poverty is indeed so
  • overbalanced by the quantity and intensity of wealth, that we may
  • permit ourselves a luxurious blindness to it, and call ourselves,
  • complacently, a rich country. And if we find no clear definition in
  • the existing science, we will endeavour for ourselves to fix the true
  • degrees of the Plutonic scale, and to apply them.
  • Question Third. What is the quantity of the store in relation to the
  • Currency? We have seen that the real worth of the currency, so far as
  • dependent on its relation to the magnitude of the store, may vary
  • within certain limits, without affecting its worth in exchange. The
  • diminution or increase of the represented wealth may be unperceived,
  • and the currency may be taken either for more or less than it is
  • truly worth. Usually, it is taken for more; and its power in exchange,
  • or credit-power, is thus increased (or retained) up to a given strain
  • upon its relation to existing wealth. This credit-power is of chief
  • importance in the thoughts, because most sharply present to the
  • experience, of a mercantile community; but the conditions of its
  • stability[78] and all other relations of the currency to the material
  • store are entirely simple in principle, if not in action. Far other
  • than simple are the relations of the currency to that "available
  • labour" which by our definition (p. 219) it also represents. For this
  • relation is involved not only with that of the magnitude of the store
  • to the number, but with that of the magnitude of the store to the
  • mind, of the population. Its proportion to their number, and the
  • resulting worth of currency, are calculable; but its proportion to
  • their will for labour is not. The worth of the piece of money which
  • claims a given quantity of the store, is, in exchange, less or greater
  • according to the facility of obtaining the same quantity of the same
  • thing without having recourse to the store. In other words, it depends
  • on the immediate Cost and Price of the thing. We must now, therefore,
  • complete the definition of these terms.
  • [78] These are nearly all briefly represented by the image used
  • for the force of money by Dante, of mast and sail,--
  • "Quali dal vento be gonfiate vele
  • Caggiono avvolte, poi chè l'alber fiacca
  • Tal cadde a terra la fiera crudele."
  • The image may be followed out, like all of Dante's, into as
  • close detail as the reader chooses. Thus the stress of the
  • sail must be proportioned to the strength of mast, and it is
  • only in unforeseen danger that a skilful seaman ever carries
  • all the canvas his spars will bear: states of mercantile
  • languor are like the flap of the sail in a calm,--of
  • mercantile precaution, like taking in reefs; and the
  • mercantile ruin is instant on the breaking of the mast.
  • All cost and price are counted in Labour. We must know first,
  • therefore, what is to be counted as Labour.
  • I have already defined labour to be the Contest of the life of man
  • with an opposite.[79] Literally, it is the quantity of "Lapse," loss,
  • or failure of human life caused by any effort. It is usually confused
  • with effort itself, or the application of power (opera); but there is
  • much effort which is merely a mode of recreation, or of pleasure. The
  • most beautiful actions of the human body and the highest results of
  • the human intelligence, are conditions, or achievements, of quite
  • unlaborious, nay, of recreative, effort. But labour is the suffering
  • in effort. It is the negative quantity, or quantity of de-feat which
  • has to be counted against every Feat, and of de-fect which has to be
  • counted against every Fact, or Deed of men. In brief, it is "that
  • quantity of our toils which we die in."
  • [79] That is to say, its only price is its return. Compare
  • "Unto This Last," p. 162 and what follows.
  • We might, therefore, à priori, conjecture (as we shall ultimately
  • find) that it cannot be bought, nor sold. Everything else is bought
  • and sold for Labour, but labour itself cannot be bought nor sold for
  • anything, being priceless.[80] The idea that it is a commodity to be
  • bought or sold, is the alpha and omega of Politico-Economic fallacy.
  • [80] The object of Political Economy is not to buy, nor to sell
  • labour,--but to spare it. Every attempt to buy or sell it
  • is, in the outcome, ineffectual;--so far as successful, it
  • is not sale, but Betrayal; and the purchase money is a part
  • of that typical thirty pieces which bought, first the
  • greatest of labours, and afterwards the burial field of the
  • Stranger; for this purchase-money, being in its very
  • smallness or vileness the exactly measured opposite of
  • "vilis annona amicorum," makes all men strangers to each
  • other.
  • This being the nature of labour, the "Cost" of anything is the
  • quantity of labour necessary to obtain it;--the quantity for which, or
  • at which, it "stands" (constat). It is literally the "Constancy" of
  • the thing;--you shall win it--move it--come at it--for no less than
  • this.
  • Cost is measured and measurable only in "labor," not in "opera."[81]
  • It does not matter how much power a thing needs to produce it; it
  • matters only how much distress. Generally the more power it requires,
  • the less the distress; so that the noblest works of man cost less than
  • the meanest.
  • [81] Cicero's distinction, "sordidi quæstus, quorum operæ, non
  • quorum artes emuntur," admirable in principle, is inaccurate
  • in expression, because Cicero did not practically know how
  • much operative dexterity is necessary in all the higher
  • arts; but the cost of this dexterity is incalculable. Be
  • it great or small, the "cost" of the mere authority and
  • perfectness of touch in a hammerstroke of Donatello's, or a
  • pencil touch of Correggio's, is inestimable by any ordinary
  • arithmetic. (The best masters themselves usually estimate it
  • at sums varying from two to three or four shillings a day,
  • with wine or soup extra.)
  • True labour, or spending of life, is either of the body, in fatigue
  • or pain, of the temper or heart (as in perseverance of search for
  • things,--patience in waiting for them,--fortitude or degradation in
  • suffering for them, and the like), or of the intellect. All these
  • kinds of labour are supposed to be included in the general term, and
  • the quantity of labour is then expressed by the time it lasts. So that
  • a unit of labour is "an hour's work" or a day's work, as we may
  • determine.[82]
  • [82] Only observe, as some labour is more destructive of life
  • than other labour, the hour or day of the more destructive
  • toil is supposed to include proportionate rest. Though men
  • do not, or cannot, usually take such rest, except in death.
  • Cost, like value, is both intrinsic and effectual. Intrinsic cost is
  • that of getting the thing in the right way; effectual cost is that of
  • getting the thing in the way we set about it. But intrinsic cannot be
  • made a subject of analytical investigation, being only partially
  • discoverable, and that by long experience. Effectual cost is all that
  • the political economist can deal with; that is to say, the cost of the
  • thing under existing circumstances and by known processes.
  • Cost (irrespectively of any question of demand or supply) varies with
  • the quantity of the thing wanted, and with the number of persons who
  • work for it. It is easy to get a little of some things, but difficult
  • to get much; it is impossible to get some things with few hands, but
  • easy to get them with many.
  • The cost and value of things, however difficult to determine
  • accurately, are thus both dependent on ascertainable physical
  • circumstances.[83]
  • [83] There is, therefore, observe, no such thing as cheapness
  • (in the common use of that term), without some error or
  • injustice. A thing is said to be cheap, not because it is
  • common, but because it is supposed to be sold under its
  • worth. Everything has its proper and true worth at any given
  • time, in relation to everything else; and at that worth
  • should be bought and sold. If sold under it, it is cheap to
  • the buyer by exactly so much as the seller loses, and no
  • more. Putrid meat, at twopence a pound, is not "cheaper"
  • than wholesome meat at sevenpence a pound; it is probably
  • much dearer; but if, by watching your opportunity, you can
  • get the wholesome meat for sixpence a pound, it is cheaper
  • to you by a penny, which you have gained, and the seller has
  • lost. The present rage for cheapness is either, therefore,
  • simply and literally, a rage for badness of all commodities,
  • or it is an attempt to find persons whose necessities will
  • force them to let you have more than you should for your
  • money. It is quite easy to produce such persons, and in
  • large numbers; for the more distress there is in a nation,
  • the more cheapness of this sort you can obtain, and your
  • boasted cheapness is thus merely a measure of the extent of
  • your national distress.
  • There is, indeed, a condition of apparent cheapness, which
  • we confuse, in practice and in reasoning, with the other;
  • namely, the real reduction in cost of articles by right
  • application of labour. But in this case the article is only
  • cheap with reference to its former price, the so-called
  • cheapness is only our expression for the sensation of
  • contrast between its former and existing prices. So soon as
  • the new methods of producing the article are established, it
  • ceases to be esteemed either cheap or dear, at the new
  • price, as at the old one, and is felt to be cheap only when
  • accident enables it to be purchased beneath this new value.
  • And it is to no advantage to produce the article more
  • easily, except as it enables you to multiply your
  • population. Cheapness of this kind is merely the discovery
  • that more men can be maintained on the same ground; and the
  • question, how many you will maintain in proportion to your
  • means, remains exactly in the same terms that it did before.
  • A form of immediate cheapness results, however, in many
  • cases, without distress, from the labour of a population
  • where food is redundant, or where the labour by which the
  • food is produced leaves much idle time on their hands, which
  • may be applied to the production of "cheap" articles.
  • All such phenomena indicate to the political economist
  • places where the labour is unbalanced. In the first case,
  • the just balance is to be effected by taking labourers from
  • the spot where the pressure exists, and sending them to that
  • where food is redundant. In the second, the cheapness is a
  • local accident, advantageous to the local purchaser,
  • disadvantageous to the local producer. It is one of the
  • first duties of commerce to extend the market and thus give
  • the local producer his full advantage.
  • Cheapness caused by natural accidents of harvest, weather,
  • etc., is always counterbalanced, in due time, by natural
  • scarcity similarly caused. It is the part of wise
  • Government, and healthy commerce, so to provide in times and
  • places of plenty for times and places of dearth, as that
  • there shall never be waste, nor famine.
  • Cheapness caused by gluts of the market is merely a disease
  • of clumsy and wanton commerce.
  • But their price is dependent on the human will.
  • Such and such a thing is demonstrably good for so much. And it may
  • demonstrably be bad for so much.
  • But it remains questionable, and in all manner of ways questionable,
  • whether I choose to give so much.[84]
  • [84] Price has already been defined (pp. 214, 215) to be the
  • quantity of labour which the possessor of a thing is willing
  • to take for it. It is best to consider the price to be that
  • fixed by the possessor, because the possessor has absolute
  • power of refusing sale, while the purchaser has no absolute
  • power of compelling it; but the effectual or market price is
  • that at which their estimates coincide.
  • This choice is always a relative one. It is a choice to give a price
  • for this, rather than for that;--a resolution to have the thing, if
  • getting it does not involve the loss of a better thing. Price depends,
  • therefore, not only on the cost of the commodity itself, but on its
  • relation to the cost of every other attainable thing.
  • Farther. The power of choice is also a relative one. It depends not
  • merely on our own estimate of the thing, but on everybody else's
  • estimate; therefore on the number and force of the will of the
  • concurrent buyers, and on the existing quantity of the thing in
  • proportion to that number and force.
  • Hence the price of anything depends on four variables.[85]
  • 1. Its cost.
  • 2. Its attainable quantity at that cost.
  • 3. The number and power of the persons who want it.
  • 4. The estimate they have formed of its desirableness.
  • (Its value only affects its price so far as it is contemplated in this
  • estimate; perhaps, therefore, not at all.)
  • [85] The two first of these variables are included in the _x_,
  • and the two last in the _y_, of the formula given at p. 162
  • of "Unto This Last," and the four are the radical conditions
  • which regulate the price of things on first production; in
  • their price in exchange, the third and fourth of these
  • divide each into two others, forming the Four which are
  • stated at p. 186 of "Unto This Last."
  • Now, in order to show the manner in which price is expressed in terms
  • of a currency, we must assume these four quantities to be known, and
  • the "estimate of desirableness," commonly called the Demand, to be
  • certain. We will take the number of persons at the lowest. Let A and B
  • be two labourers who "demand," that is to say, have resolved to labour
  • for, two articles, _a_ and _b_. Their demand for these articles (if
  • the reader likes better, he may say their need) is to be absolute,
  • existence depending on the getting these two things. Suppose, for
  • instance, that they are bread and fuel in a cold country, and let _a_
  • represent the least quantity of bread, and _b_ the least quantity of
  • fuel, which will support a man's life for a day. Let _a_ be producible
  • by an hour's labour but _b_ only by two hours' labour; then the cost
  • of _a_ is one hour, and of _b_ two (cost, by our definition, being
  • expressible in terms of time). If, therefore, each man worked both for
  • his corn and fuel, each would have to work three hours a day. But they
  • divide the labour for its greater ease.[86] Then if A works three
  • hours, he produces 3_a_, which is one _a_ more than both the men want.
  • And if B works three hours, he produces only 1-1/2_b_, or half of _b_
  • less than both want. But if A works three hours and B six, A has 3_a_,
  • and B has 3_b_, a maintenance in the right proportion for both for a
  • day and a half; so that each might take a half a day's rest. But as B
  • has worked double time, the whole of this day's rest belongs in equity
  • to him. Therefore, the just exchange should be, A, giving two _a_ for
  • one _b_, has one _a_ and one _b_;--maintenance for a day. B, giving
  • one _b_ for two _a_, has two _a_ and two _b_;--maintenance for two
  • days.
  • [86] This "greater ease" ought to be allowed for by a diminution
  • in the times of the divided work; but as the proportion of
  • times would remain the same, I do not introduce this
  • unnecessary complexity into the calculation.
  • But B cannot rest on the second day, or A would be left without the
  • article which B produces. Nor is there any means of making the
  • exchange just, unless a third labourer is called in. Then one workman,
  • A, produces _a_, and two, B and C, produce _b_;--A, working three
  • hours, has three _a_;--B, three hours, 1-1/2_b_;--C, three hours,
  • 1-1/2_b_. B and C each give half of _b_ for _a_, and all have their
  • equal daily maintenance for equal daily work.
  • To carry the example a single step farther, let three articles, _a_,
  • _b_, and _c_, be needed.
  • Let _a_ need one hour's work, _b_ two, and _c_ four; then the day's
  • work must be seven hours, and one man in a day's work can make 7_a_,
  • or 3-1/2_b_, or 1-3/4_c_. Therefore one A works for _a_, producing
  • 7_a_; two B's work for _b_, producing 7_b_; four C's work for _c_,
  • producing 7_c_.
  • A has six _a_ to spare, and gives two _a_ for one _b_, and four _a_
  • for one _c_. Each B has 2-1/2_b_ to spare, and gives 1/2_b_ for one
  • _a_, and two _b_ for one _c_. Each C has 3/4 of _c_ to spare, and
  • gives 1/2_c_ for one _b_, and 1/4 of _c_ for one _a_. And all have
  • their day's maintenance.
  • Generally, therefore, it follows that, if the demand is constant,[87]
  • the relative prices of things are as their costs, or as the quantities
  • of labour involved in production.
  • [87] Compare "Unto This Last," p. 177, et seq.
  • Then, in order to express their prices in terms of a currency, we
  • have only to put the currency into the form of orders for a certain
  • quantity of any given article (with us it is in the form of orders for
  • gold), and all quantities of other articles are priced by the relation
  • they bear to the article which the currency claims.
  • But the worth of the currency itself is not in the slightest degree
  • founded more on the worth of the article for which the gold is
  • exchangeable. It is just as accurate to say, "So many pounds are worth
  • an acre of land," as "An acre of land is worth so many pounds." The
  • worth of gold, of land, of houses, and of food, and of all other
  • things, depends at any moment on the existing quantities and relative
  • demands for all and each; and a change in the worth of, or demand for,
  • any one, involves an instantaneously correspondent change in the
  • worth, and demand for, all the rest--a change as inevitable and as
  • accurately balanced (though often in its process as untraceable) as
  • the change in volume of the outflowing river from some vast lake,
  • caused by change in the volume of the inflowing streams, though no eye
  • can trace, no instrument detect motion either on its surface, or in
  • the depth.
  • Thus, then, the real working power or worth of the currency is founded
  • on the entire sum of the relative estimates formed by the population
  • of its possessions; a change in this estimate in any direction (and
  • therefore every change in the national character), instantly alters
  • the value of money, in its second great function of commanding labour.
  • But we must always carefully and sternly distinguish between this
  • worth of currency, dependent on the conceived or appreciated value of
  • what it represents, and the worth of it, dependent on the existence of
  • what it represents. A currency is true or false, in proportion to the
  • security with which it gives claim to the possession of land, house,
  • horse, or picture; but a currency is strong or weak, worth much or
  • worth little, in proportion to the degree of estimate in which the
  • nation holds the house, horse, or picture which is claimed. Thus the
  • power of the English currency has been, till of late, largely based on
  • the national estimate of horses and of wine: so that a man might
  • always give any price to furnish choicely his stable, or his cellar,
  • and receive public approval therefor: but if he gave the same sum to
  • furnish his library, he was called mad, or a Bibliomaniac. And
  • although he might lose his fortune by his horses, and his health or
  • life by his cellar, and rarely lost either by his books, he was yet
  • never called a Hippomaniac nor an Oinomaniac; but only Bibliomaniac,
  • because the current worth of money was understood to be legitimately
  • founded on cattle and wine, but not on literature. The prices lately
  • given at sales for pictures and MSS. indicate some tendency to change
  • in the national character in this respect, so that the worth of the
  • currency may even come in time to rest, in an acknowledged manner,
  • somewhat on the state and keeping of the Bedford missal, as well as on
  • the health of Caractacus or Blink Bonny; and old pictures be
  • considered property, no less than old port. They might have been so
  • before now, but it is more difficult to choose the one than the other.
  • Now, observe, all these sources of variation in the power of the
  • currency exist wholly irrespective of the influences of vice,
  • indolence, and improvidence. We have hitherto supposed, throughout the
  • analysis, every professing labourer to labour honestly, heartily, and
  • in harmony with his fellows. We have now to bring farther into the
  • calculation the effects of relative industry, honour, and forethought,
  • and thus to follow out the bearings of our second inquiry: Who are the
  • holders of the Store and Currency, and in what proportions?
  • This, however, we must reserve for our next paper,--noticing here
  • only that, however distinct the several branches of the subject are,
  • radically, they are so interwoven in their issues that we cannot
  • rightly treat any one, till we have taken cognisance of all. Thus the
  • quantity of the currency in proportion to number of population is
  • materially influenced by the number of the holders in proportion to
  • the non-holders; and this again by the number of holders of goods. For
  • as, by definition, the currency is a claim to goods which are not
  • possessed, its quantity indicates the number of claimants in
  • proportion to the number of holders; and the force and complexity of
  • claim. For if the claims be not complex, currency as a means of
  • exchange may be very small in quantity. A sells some corn to B,
  • receiving a promise from B to pay in cattle, which A then hands over
  • to C, to get some wine. C in due time claims the cattle from B; and B
  • takes back his promise. These exchanges have, or might have been, all
  • effected with a single coin or promise; and the proportion of the
  • currency to the store would in such circumstances indicate only the
  • circulating vitality of it--that is to say, the quantity and
  • convenient divisibility of that part of the store which the habits of
  • the nation keep in circulation. If a cattle-breeder is content to
  • live with his household chiefly on meat and milk, and does not want
  • rich furniture, or jewels, or books,--if a wine- and corn-grower
  • maintains himself and his men chiefly on grapes and bread;--if the
  • wives and daughters of families weave and spin the clothing of the
  • household, and the nation, as a whole, remains content with the
  • produce of its own soil and the work of its own hands, it has little
  • occasion for circulating media. It pledges and promises little and
  • seldom; exchanges only so far as exchange is necessary for life. The
  • store belongs to the people in whose hands it is found, and money is
  • little needed either as an expression of right, or practical means of
  • division and exchange.
  • But in proportion as the habits of the nation become complex and
  • fantastic (and they may be both, without therefore being civilized),
  • its circulating medium must increase in proportion to its store. If
  • everyone wants a little of everything,--if food must be of many kinds,
  • and dress of many fashions,--if multitudes live by work which,
  • ministering to fancy, has its pay measured by fancy, so that large
  • prices will be given by one person for what is valueless to
  • another,--if there are great inequalities of knowledge, causing great
  • inequalities of estimate,--and finally, and worst of all, if the
  • currency itself, from its largeness, and the power which the
  • possession of it implies, becomes the sole object of desire with large
  • numbers of the nation, so that the holding of it is disputed among
  • them as the main object of life:--in each and all these cases, the
  • currency enlarges in proportion to the store, and, as a means of
  • exchange and division, as a bond of right, and as an expression of
  • passion, plays a more and more important part in the nation's
  • dealings, character, and life.
  • Against which part, when, as a bond of Right, it becomes too
  • conspicuous and too burdensome, the popular voice is apt to be raised
  • in a violent and irrational manner, leading to revolution instead of
  • remedy. Whereas all possibility of Economy depends on the clear
  • assertion and maintenance of this bond of right, however burdensome.
  • The first necessity of all economical government is to secure the
  • unquestioned and unquestionable working of the great law of
  • Property--that a man who works for a thing shall be allowed to get it,
  • keep it, and consume it, in peace; and that he who does not eat his
  • cake to-day, shall be seen, without grudging, to have his cake
  • to-morrow. This, I say, is the first point to be secured by social
  • law; without this, no political advance, nay, no political existence,
  • is in any sort possible. Whatever evil, luxury, iniquity, may seem to
  • result from it, this is nevertheless the first of all Equities; and to
  • the enforcement of this, by law and by police-truncheon, the nation
  • must always primarily set its mind--that the cupboard door may have a
  • firm lock to it, and no man's dinner be carried off by the mob, on its
  • way home from the baker's. Which, thus fearlessly asserting, we shall
  • endeavour in the next paper to consider how far it may be practicable
  • for the mob itself, also, in due breadth of dish, to have dinners to
  • carry home.
  • III.
  • THE CURRENCY-HOLDERS AND STORE-HOLDERS. THE DISEASE OF DESIRE.
  • It will be seen by reference to the last paper that our present task
  • is to examine the relation of holders of store to holders of currency;
  • and of both to those who hold neither. In order to do this, we must
  • determine on which side we are to place substances such as gold,
  • commonly known as bases of currency. By aid of previous definitions
  • the reader will now be able to understand closer statements than have
  • yet been possible.
  • The currency of any country consists of every document acknowledging
  • debt which is transferable in the country.
  • This transferableness depends upon its intelligibility and credit. Its
  • intelligibility depends chiefly on the difficulty of forging anything
  • like it;--its credit much on national character, but ultimately always
  • on the existence of substantial means of meeting its demand.
  • As the degrees of transferableness are variable (some documents
  • passing only in certain places, and others passing, if at all, for
  • less than their inscribed value), both the mass and, so to speak,
  • fluidity, of the currency, are variable. True or perfect currency
  • flows freely, like a pure stream; it becomes sluggish or stagnant in
  • proportion to the quantity of less transferable matter which mixes
  • with it, adding to its bulk, but diminishing its purity. Substances of
  • intrinsic value, such as gold, mingle also with the currency, and
  • increase, while they modify, its power; these are carried by it as
  • stones are carried by a torrent, sometimes momentarily impeding,
  • sometimes concentrating its force, but not affecting its purity.
  • These substances of intrinsic value may be also stamped or signed so
  • as to become acknowledgments of debt, and then become, so far as they
  • operate independently of their intrinsic value, part of the real
  • currency.
  • Deferring consideration of minor forms of currency, consisting of
  • documents bearing private signature, we will examine the principle of
  • legally authorized or national currency.
  • This, in its perfect condition, is a form of public acknowledgment of
  • debt, so regulated and divided that any person presenting a commodity
  • of tried worth in the public market, shall, if he please, receive in
  • exchange for it a document giving him claim for the return of its
  • equivalent, (1) in any place, (2) at any time, and (3) in any kind.
  • When currency is quite healthy and vital, the persons entrusted with
  • its management are always able to give on demand either--
  • A. The assigning document for the assigned quantity of goods. Or,
  • B. The assigned quantity of goods for the assigning document.
  • If they cannot give document for goods, the national exchange is at
  • fault.
  • If they cannot give goods for document, the national credit is at
  • fault.
  • The nature and power of the document are therefore to be examined
  • under the three relations which it bears to Place, Time, and Kind.
  • 1. It gives claim to the return of equivalent wealth in any Place. Its
  • use in this function is to save carriage, so that parting with a
  • bushel of corn in London, we may receive an order for a bushel of corn
  • for the Antipodes, or elsewhere. To be perfect in this use, the
  • substance of currency must be to the maximum portable, credible, and
  • intelligible. Its non-acceptance or discredit results always from some
  • form of ignorance or dishonour: so far as such interruptions rise out
  • of differences in denomination, there is no ground for their
  • continuance among civilized nations. It may be convenient in one
  • country to use chiefly copper for coinage, in another silver, and in
  • another gold,--reckoning accordingly in centimes, francs, or sequins;
  • but that a French franc should be different in weight from an English
  • shilling, and an Austrian zwanziger vary in weight and alloy from
  • both, is wanton loss of commercial power.
  • 2. It gives claim to the return of equivalent wealth at any Time. In
  • this second use, currency is the exponent of accumulation: it renders
  • the laying up of store at the command of individuals unlimitedly
  • possible;--whereas, but for its intervention, all gathering would be
  • confined within certain limits by the bulk of poverty, or by its
  • decay, or the difficulty of its guardianship. "I will pull down my
  • barns and build greater" cannot be a daily saying; and all material
  • investment is enlargement of care. The national currency transfers the
  • guardianship of the store to many; and preserves to the original
  • producer the right of re-entering on its possession at any future
  • period.
  • 3. It gives claim (practical, though not legal) to the return of
  • equivalent wealth in any Kind. It is a transferable right, not merely
  • to this or that, but to anything; and its power in this function is
  • proportioned to the range of choice. If you give a child an apple or a
  • toy, you give him a determinate pleasure, but if you give him a penny,
  • an indeterminate one, proportioned to the range of selection offered
  • by the shops in the village. The power of the world's currency is
  • similarly in proportion to the openness of the world's fair, and
  • commonly enhanced by the brilliancy of external aspect, rather than
  • solidity of its wares.
  • We have said that the currency consists of orders for equivalent
  • goods. If equivalent, their quality must be guaranteed. The kinds of
  • goods chosen for specific claim must, therefore, be capable of test,
  • while, also, that a store may be kept in hand to meet the call of the
  • currency, smallness of bulk, with great relative value, is desirable;
  • and indestructibility, over at least a certain period, essential.
  • Such indestructibility and facility of being tested are united in
  • gold; its intrinsic value is great, and its imaginary value is
  • greater; so that, partly through indolence, partly through necessity
  • and want of organization, most nations have agreed to take gold for
  • the only basis of their currencies;--with this grave disadvantage,
  • that its portability enabling the metal to become an active part of
  • the medium of exchange, the stream of the currency itself becomes
  • opaque with gold--half currency and half commodity, in unison of
  • functions which partly neutralize, partly enhance each other's force.
  • They partly neutralize, since in so far as the gold is commodity, it
  • is bad currency, because liable to sale; and in so far as it is
  • currency, it is bad commodity, because its exchange value interferes
  • with its practical use. Especially its employment in the higher
  • branches of the arts becomes unsafe on account of its liability to be
  • melted down for exchange.
  • Again. They partly enhance, since in so far as the gold has
  • acknowledged intrinsic value, it is good currency, because everywhere
  • acceptable; and in so far as it has legal exchangeable value, its
  • worth as a commodity is increased. We want no gold in the form of dust
  • or crystal; but we seek for it coined because in that form it will pay
  • baker and butcher. And this worth in exchange not only absorbs a large
  • quantity in that use,[88] but greatly increases the effect on the
  • imagination of the quantity used in the arts. Thus, in brief, the
  • force of the functions is increased, but their precision blunted, by
  • their unison.
  • [88] The waste of labour in obtaining the gold, though it cannot
  • be estimated by help of any existing data, may be understood
  • in its bearing on entire economy by supposing it limited to
  • transactions between two persons. If two farmers in
  • Australia have been exchanging corn and cattle with each
  • other for years, keeping their accounts of reciprocal debt
  • in any simple way, the sum of the possessions of either
  • would not be diminished, though the part of it which was
  • lent or borrowed were only reckoned by marks on a stone, or
  • notches on a tree; and the one counted himself accordingly,
  • so many scratches, or so many notches, better than the
  • other. But it would soon be seriously diminished if,
  • discovering gold in their fields, each resolved only to
  • accept golden counters for a reckoning; and accordingly,
  • whenever he wanted a sack of corn or a cow, was obliged to
  • go and wash sand for a week before he could get the means of
  • giving a receipt for them.
  • These inconveniences, however, attach to gold as a basis of currency
  • on account of its portability and preciousness. But a far greater
  • inconvenience attaches to it as the only legal basis of currency.
  • Imagine gold to be only attainable in masses weighing several pounds
  • each, and its value, like that of a malachite or marble, proportioned
  • to its largeness of bulk;--it could not then get itself confused with
  • the currency in daily use, but it might still remain as its basis; and
  • this second inconvenience would still affect it, namely, that its
  • significance as an expression of debt, varies, as that of every other
  • article would, with the popular estimate of its desirableness, and
  • with the quantity offered in the market. My power of obtaining other
  • goods for gold depends always on the strength of public passion for
  • gold, and on the limitation of its quantity, so that when either of
  • two things happen--that the world esteems gold less, or finds it more
  • easily,--my right of claim is in that degree effaced; and it has been
  • even gravely maintained that a discovery of a mountain of gold would
  • cancel the National Debt; in other words, that men may be paid for
  • what costs much in what costs nothing. Now, if it is true that there
  • is little chance of sudden convulsion in this respect, the world will
  • not rapidly increase in wisdom so as to despise gold, and perhaps may
  • even desire it more eagerly the more easily it is obtained;
  • nevertheless the right of debt ought not to rest on a basis of
  • imagination; nor should the frame of a national currency vibrate with
  • every miser's panic and every merchant's imprudence.
  • There are two methods of avoiding this insecurity, which would have
  • been fallen upon long ago if, instead of calculating the conditions of
  • the supply of gold, men had only considered how the world might live
  • and manage its affairs without gold at all.[89] One is to base the
  • currency on substances of truer intrinsic value; the other, to base it
  • on several substances instead of one. If I can only claim gold, the
  • discovery of a continent of cornfields need not trouble me. If,
  • however, I wish to exchange my bread for other things, a good harvest
  • will for the time limit my power in this respect; but if I can claim
  • either bread, iron, or silk at pleasure, the standard of value has
  • three feet instead of one, and will be proportionally firm. Thus,
  • ultimately the steadiness of currency depends upon the breadth of its
  • base; but the difficulty of organization increasing with this breadth,
  • the discovery of the condition at once safest and most convenient[90]
  • can only be by long analysis which must for the present be deferred.
  • Gold or silver[91] may always be retained in limited use, as a luxury
  • of coinage and questionless standard, of one weight and alloy among
  • nations, varying only in the die. The purity of coinage when metallic,
  • is closely indicative of the honesty of the system of revenue, and
  • even of the general dignity of the State.[92]
  • [89] It is difficult to estimate the curious futility of
  • discussions such as that which lately occupied a section of
  • the British Association, on the absorption of gold, while no
  • one can produce even the simplest of the data necessary for
  • the inquiry. To take the first occurring one,--What means
  • have we of ascertaining the weight of gold employed this
  • year in the toilettes of the women of Europe (not to
  • speak of Asia); and, supposing it known, what means of
  • conjecturing the weight by which, next year, their fancies,
  • and the changes of style among their jewellers, will
  • diminish or increase it?
  • [90] See, in Pope's epistle to Lord Bathurst, his sketch of the
  • difficulties and uses of a currency literally "pecuniary"--
  • "His Grace will game--to White's a bull he led," etc.
  • [91] Perhaps both; perhaps silver only. It may be found
  • expedient ultimately to leave gold free for use in the arts.
  • As a means of reckoning, the standard might be, and in some
  • cases has already been, entirely ideal.--See Mill's
  • "Political Economy," book iii., chap. 7, at beginning.
  • [92] The purity of the drachma and sequin were not without
  • significance of the state of intellect, art, and policy,
  • both in Athens and Venice;--a fact first impressed upon
  • me ten years ago, when, in daguerreotypes of Venetian
  • architecture, I found no purchasable gold pure enough
  • to gild them with, but that of the old Venetian sequin.
  • Whatever the article or articles may be which the national currency
  • promises to pay, a premium on that article indicates bankruptcy of the
  • Government in that proportion, the division of the assets being
  • restrained only by the remaining confidence of the holders of notes in
  • the return of prosperity to the firm. Incontrovertible currencies,
  • those of forced acceptance, or of unlimited issue, are merely various
  • modes of disguising taxation, and delaying its pressure, until it is
  • too late to interfere with its causes. To do away with the possibility
  • of such disguise would have been among the first results of a true
  • economical science, had any such existed; but there have been too many
  • motives for the concealment, so long as it could by any artifices be
  • maintained, to permit hitherto even the founding of such a science.
  • And, indeed, it is only through evil conduct, wilfully persisted in,
  • that there is any embarrassment either in the theory or the working of
  • currency. No exchequer is ever embarrassed, nor is any financial
  • question difficult of solution, when people keep their practice
  • honest, and their heads cool. But when Governments lose all office of
  • pilotage, protection, scrutiny, and witness; and live only in
  • magnificence of proclaimed larceny, effulgent mendacity, and polished
  • mendicity; or when the people choosing Speculation (the S usual
  • redundant in the spelling) instead of Toil, pursue no dishonesty with
  • chastisement, that each may with impunity take his dishonest turn; and
  • enlarge their lust of wealth through ignorance of its use, making
  • their harlot of the dust, and setting Earth, the Mother, at the mercy
  • of Earth, the Destroyer, so that she has to seek in hell the children
  • she left playing in the meadows,--there are no tricks of financial
  • terminology that will save them; all signature and mintage do but
  • magnify the ruin they retard; and even the riches that remain,
  • stagnant or current, change only from the slime of Avernus to the sand
  • of Phlegethon;--quicksand at the embouchure;--land fluently
  • recommended by recent auctioneers as "eligible for building leases."
  • Finally, then, the power of true currency is fourfold.
  • 1. Credit power. Its worth in exchange, dependent on public opinion of
  • the stability and honesty of the issuer.
  • 2. Real worth. Supposing the gold, or whatever else the currency
  • expressly promises, to be required from the issuer, for all his notes;
  • and that the call cannot be met in full. Then the actual worth of the
  • document (whatever its credit power) would be, and its actual worth at
  • any moment is to be defined as being, what the division of the assets
  • of the issuer, and his subsequent will work, would produce for it.
  • 3. The exchange power of its base. Granting that we can get five
  • pounds in gold for our note, it remains a question how much of other
  • things we can get for five pounds in gold. The more of other things
  • exist, and the less gold, the greater this power.
  • 4. The power over labour, exercised by the given quantity of the base,
  • or of the things to be got for it. The question in this case is, how
  • much work, and (question of questions) whose work, is to be had for
  • the food which five pounds will buy. This depends on the number of the
  • population; on their gifts, and on their dispositions, with which,
  • down to their slightest humours and up to their strongest impulses,
  • the power of the currency varies; and in this last of its ranges,--the
  • range of passion, price, or praise (converso in pretium Deo), is at
  • once least, and greatest.
  • Such being the main conditions of national currency, we proceed to
  • examine those of the total currency, under the broad definition,
  • "transferable acknowledgment of debt";[93] among the many forms of
  • which there are in effect only two, distinctly opposed; namely, the
  • acknowledgments of debts which will be paid, and of debts which will
  • not. Documents, whether in whole or part, of bad debt, being to those
  • of good debt as bad money to bullion, we put for the present these
  • forms of imposture aside (as in analysing a metal we should wash it
  • clear of dross), and then range, in their exact quantities, the true
  • currency of the country on one side, and the store or property of the
  • country on the other. We place gold, and all such substances, on the
  • side of documents, as far as they operate by signature;--on the side
  • of store as far as they operate by value. Then the currency represents
  • the quantity of debt in the country, and the store the quantity of its
  • possession. The ownership of all the property is divided between the
  • holders of currency and holders of store, and whatever the claiming
  • value of the currency is at any moment, that value is to be deducted
  • from the riches of the store-holders, the deduction being practically
  • made in the payment of rent for houses and lands, of interest on
  • stock, and in other ways to be hereafter examined.
  • [93] Under which term, observe, we include all documents of debt
  • which, being honest, might be transferable, though they
  • practically are not transferred; while we exclude all
  • documents which are in reality worthless, though in fact
  • transferred temporarily as bad money is. The document of
  • honest debt, not transferred, is merely to paper currency as
  • gold withdrawn from circulation is to that of bullion. Much
  • confusion has crept into the reasoning on this subject from
  • the idea that withdrawal from circulation is a definable
  • state, whereas it is a gradated state, and indefinable. The
  • sovereign in my pocket is withdrawn from circulation as long
  • as I choose to keep it there. It is no otherwise withdrawn
  • if I bury it, nor even if I choose to make it, and others,
  • into a golden cup, and drink out of them; since a rise in
  • the price of the wine, or of other things, may at any time
  • cause me to melt the cup and throw it back into currency;
  • and the bullion operates on the prices of the things in the
  • market as directly, though not as forcibly, while it is in
  • the form of a cup, as it does in the form of a sovereign. No
  • calculation can be founded on my humour in any ease. If I
  • like to handle rouleaus, and therefore keep a quantity of
  • gold, to play with, in the form of jointed basaltic columns,
  • it is all one in its effect on the market as if I kept it in
  • the form of twisted filigree, or steadily amicus lamnæ, beat
  • the narrow gold pieces into broad ones, and dined off them.
  • The probability is greater that I break the rouleau than
  • that I melt the plate; but the increased probability is not
  • calculable. Thus, documents are only withdrawn from the
  • currency when cancelled, and bullion when it is so
  • effectually lost as that the probability of finding it is no
  • greater than that of finding new gold in the mine.
  • At present I wish only to note the broad relations of the two great
  • classes--the currency-holders and store-holders.[94] Of course they
  • are partly united, most monied men having possessions of land or other
  • goods; but they are separate in their nature and functions. The
  • currency-holders as a class regulate the demand for labour, and the
  • store-holders the laws of it; the currency-holders determine what
  • shall be produced, and the store-holders the conditions of its
  • production. Farther, as true currency represents by definition debts
  • which will be paid, it represents either the debtor's wealth, or his
  • ability and willingness; that is to say, either wealth existing in his
  • hands transferred to him by the creditor, or wealth which, as he is at
  • some time surely to return it, he is either increasing, or, if
  • diminishing, has the will and strength to reproduce. A sound currency,
  • therefore, as by its increase it represents enlarging debt, represents
  • also enlarging means; but in this curious way, that a certain quantity
  • of it marks the deficiency of the wealth of the country from what it
  • would have been if that currency had not existed.[95] In this respect
  • it is like the detritus of a mountain; assume that it lies at a fixed
  • angle, and the more the detritus, the larger must be the mountain; but
  • it would have been larger still, had there been none.
  • [94] They are (up to the amount of the currency) simply creditors
  • and debtors--the commercial types of the two great sects of
  • humanity which those words describe; for debt and credit are
  • of course merely the mercantile forms of the words "duty"
  • and "creed," which give the central ideas: only it is more
  • accurate to say "faith" than "creed," because creed has been
  • applied carelessly to mere forms of words. Duty properly
  • signifies whatever in substance or act one person owes to
  • another, and faith the other's trust in his rendering it.
  • The French "devoir" and "foi" are fuller and clearer words
  • than ours; for, faith being the passive of fact, foi comes
  • straight through fides from fio; and the French keep the
  • group of words formed from the infinitive--fieri, "se fier,"
  • "se défier," "défiance," and the grand following "défi." Our
  • English "affiance," "defiance," "confidence," "diffidence,"
  • retain accurate meanings; but our "faithful" has become
  • obscure, from being used for "faithworthy," as well as "full
  • of faith." "His name that sat on him was called Faithful and
  • True."
  • Trust is the passive of true saying, as faith is the passive
  • of due doing; and the right learning of these etymologies,
  • which are in the strictest sense only to be learned "by
  • heart," is of considerably more importance to the youth of a
  • nation than its reading and ciphering.
  • [95] For example, suppose an active peasant, having got his
  • ground into good order and built himself a comfortable
  • house, finding still time on his hands, sees one of his
  • neighbours little able to work, and ill lodged, and offers
  • to build him also a house, and to put his land in order, on
  • condition of receiving for a given period rent for the
  • building and tithe of the fruits. The offer is accepted, and
  • a document given promissory of rent and tithe. This note is
  • money. It can only be good money if the man who has incurred
  • the debt so far recovers his strength as to be able to take
  • advantage of the help he has received, and meet the demand
  • of the note; if he lets his house fall to ruin, and his
  • field to waste, his promissory note will soon be valueless:
  • but the existence of the note at all is a consequence of his
  • not having worked so stoutly as the other. Let him gain as
  • much as to be able to pay back the entire debt; the note is
  • cancelled and we have two rich store-holders and no
  • currency.
  • Finally, though, as above stated, every man possessing money has
  • usually also some property beyond what is necessary for his immediate
  • wants, and men possessing property usually also hold currency beyond
  • what is necessary for their immediate exchanges, it mainly determines
  • the class to which they belong, whether in their eyes the money is an
  • adjunct of the property, or the property of the money. In the first
  • case, the holder's pleasure is in his possessions, and in his money
  • subordinately, as the means of bettering or adding to them. In the
  • second, his pleasure is in his money, and in his possessions only as
  • representing it. In the first case, the money is as an atmosphere
  • surrounding the wealth, rising from it and raining back upon it; but
  • in the second, it is a deluge, with the wealth floating, and for the
  • most part perishing in it. The shortest distinction between the men is
  • that the one wishes always to buy and the other to sell.
  • Such being the great relations of the classes, their several
  • characters are of the highest importance to the nation; for on the
  • character of the store-holders depends the preservation, display, and
  • serviceableness of its wealth;--on that of the currency-holders its
  • nature, and in great part its distribution; and on both its
  • production.
  • The store-holders are either constructive, or neutral, or destructive;
  • and in subsequent papers we shall, with respect to every kind of
  • wealth, examine the relative power of the store-holder for its
  • improvement or destruction; and we shall then find it to be of
  • incomparably greater importance to the nation in whose hands the thing
  • is put, than how much of it is got; and that the character of the
  • holders may be conjectured by the quality of the store, for such and
  • such a thing; nor only asks for it, but if to be bettered, betters it:
  • so that possession and possessor reciprocally act on each other
  • through the entire sum of national possession. The base nation asking
  • for base things sinks daily to deeper vileness of nature and of use;
  • while the noble nation, asking for noble things, rises daily into
  • diviner eminence in both; the tendency to degradation being surely
  • marked by [Greek: ataxia], carelessness as to the hands in which
  • things are put, competition for the acquisition of them,
  • disorderliness in accumulation, inaccuracy in reckoning, and bluntness
  • in conception as to the entire nature of possession.
  • Now, the currency-holders always increase in number and influence in
  • proportion to the bluntness of nature and clumsiness of the
  • store-holders; for the less use people can make of things the more
  • they tire of them, and want to change them for something else, and
  • all frequency of change increases the quantity and power of currency;
  • while the large currency-holder himself is essentially a person who
  • never has been able to make up his mind as to what he will have, and
  • proceeds, therefore, in vague collection and aggregation, with more
  • and more infuriate passion, urged by complacency in progress, and
  • pride in conquest.
  • While, however, there is this obscurity in the nature of possession of
  • currency, there is a charm in the absoluteness of it, which is to some
  • people very enticing. In the enjoyment of real property others must
  • partly share. The groom has some enjoyment of the stud, and the
  • gardener of the garden; but the money is, or seems shut up; it is
  • wholly enviable. No one else can have part in any complacencies
  • arising from it.
  • The power of arithmetical comparison is also a great thing to
  • unimaginative people. They know always they are so much better than
  • they were, in money; so much better than others, in money; wit cannot
  • be so compared, nor character. My neighbour cannot be convinced I am
  • wiser than he is, but he can that I am worth so much more; and the
  • universality of the conviction is no less flattering than its
  • clearness. Only a few can understand, none measure, superiorities in
  • other things; but everybody can understand money, and count it.
  • Now, these various temptations to accumulation would be politically
  • harmless, if what was vainly accumulated had any fair chance of being
  • wisely spent. For as accumulation cannot go on for ever, but must some
  • day end in its reverse--if this reverse were indeed a beneficial
  • distribution and use, as irrigation from reservoir, the fever of
  • gathering, though perilous to the gatherer, might be serviceable to
  • the community. But it constantly happens (so constantly, that it may
  • be stated as a political law having few exceptions), that what is
  • unreasonably gathered is also unreasonably spent by the persons into
  • whose hands it finally falls. Very frequently it is spent in war, or
  • else in stupefying luxury, twice hurtful, both in being indulged by
  • the rich and witnessed by the poor. So that the _mal tener_ and _mal
  • dare_ are as correlative as complementary colours; and the circulation
  • of wealth, which ought to be soft, steady, strong, far-sweeping, and
  • full of warmth, like the Gulf Stream, being narrowed into an eddy, and
  • concentrated on a point, changes into the alternate suction and
  • surrender of Charybdis. Which is, indeed, I doubt not, the true
  • meaning of that marvellous fable, "infinite," as Bacon said of it,
  • "in matter of meditation."[96]
  • [96] It is a strange habit of wise humanity to speak in enigmas
  • only, so that the highest truths and usefullest laws must be
  • hunted for through whole picture-galleries of dreams, which
  • to the vulgar seem dreams only. Thus Homer, the Greek
  • tragedians, Plato, Dante, Chaucer, Shakespeare, and Goethe,
  • have hidden all that is chiefly serviceable in their work,
  • and in all the various literature they absorbed and
  • re-embodied, under types which have rendered it quite
  • useless to the multitude. What is worse, the two primal
  • declarers of moral discovery, Homer and Plato, are partly at
  • issue; for Plato's logical power quenched his imagination,
  • and he became incapable of understanding the purely
  • imaginative element either in poetry or painting; he
  • therefore somewhat overrates the pure discipline of
  • passionate art in song and music, and misses that of
  • meditative art. There is, however, a deeper reason for his
  • distrust of Homer. His love of justice, and reverently
  • religious nature made him dread as death, every form of
  • fallacy; but chiefly, fallacy respecting the world to come
  • (his own myths being only symbolic exponents of a rational
  • hope). We shall perhaps now every day discover more clearly
  • how right Plato was in this, and feel ourselves more and
  • more wonderstruck that men such as Homer and Dante (and, in
  • an inferior sphere, Milton), not to speak of the great
  • sculptors and painters of every age, have permitted
  • themselves, though full of all nobleness and wisdom, to coin
  • idle imaginations of the mysteries of eternity, and mould
  • the faiths of the families of the earth by the courses of
  • their own vague and visionary arts: while the indisputable
  • truths respecting human life and duty, respecting which they
  • all have but one voice, lie hidden behind these veils of
  • phantasy, unsought and often unsuspected. I will gather
  • carefully, out of Dante and Homer, what of this kind bears
  • on our subject, in its due place; the first broad intention
  • of their symbols may be sketched at once. The rewards of a
  • worthy use of riches, subordinate to other ends, are shown
  • by Dante in the fifth and sixth orbs of Paradise; for the
  • punishment of their unworthy use, three places are assigned;
  • one for the avaricious and prodigal whose souls are lost
  • ("Hell": Canto 7); one for the avaricious and prodigal whose
  • souls are capable of purification ("Purgatory": Canto 19);
  • and one for the usurers, of whom none can be redeemed
  • ("Hell": Canto 17). The first group, the largest in all hell
  • (gente piu che altrove troppa), meet in contrary currents,
  • as the waves of Charybdis, casting weights at each other
  • from opposite sides. This weariness of contention is the
  • chief element of their torture; so marked by the beautiful
  • lines, beginning, Or puoi, figliuol, etc. (but the usurers,
  • who made their money inactively, sit on the sand, equally
  • without rest, however, "Di qua, di la soccorrien," etc.).
  • For it is not avarice but contention for riches, leading to
  • this double misuse of them, which, in Dante's sight, is the
  • unredeemable sin. The place of its punishment is guarded by
  • Plutus, "the great enemy," and "la fièra crudele," a spirit
  • quite different from the Greek Plutus, who, though old and
  • blind, is not cruel, and is curable, so as to become
  • far-sighted ([Greek: hou typhlos all' oxy blepôn]--Plato's
  • epithets in first book of the Laws). Still more does this
  • Dantesque type differ from the resplendent Plutus of Goethe
  • in the second part of "Faust," who is the personified power
  • of wealth for good or evil; not the passion for wealth; and
  • again from the Plutus of Spenser, who is the passion of mere
  • aggregation. Dante's Plutus is specially and definitely the
  • spirit of Contention and Competition, or Evil Commerce; and
  • because, as I showed in my last paper, this kind of commerce
  • "makes all men strangers," his speech is unintelligible, and
  • no single soul of all those ruined by him has recognizable
  • features.
  • (La sconescente vita--
  • Ad ogni conoscenza or li fa bruni).
  • On the other hand, the redeemable sins of avarice and
  • prodigality are, in Dante's sight, those which are without
  • deliberate or calculated operation. The lust, or lavishness,
  • of riches can be purged, so long as there has been no
  • servile consistency of dispute and competition for them. The
  • sin is spoken of as that of degradation by the love of
  • earth; it is purified by deeper humiliation--the souls crawl
  • on their bellies; their chant, "my soul cleaveth unto the
  • dust." But the spirits here condemned are all recognizable,
  • and even the worst examples of the thirst for gold, which
  • they are compelled to tell the histories of during the
  • night, are of men swept by the passion of avarice into
  • violent crime, but not sold to its steady work. The precept
  • given to each of these spirits for its deliverance is--Turn
  • thine eyes to the lucre (lure) which the Eternal King rolls
  • with the mighty wheels: otherwise, the wheels of the
  • "Greater Fortune," of which the constellation is ascending
  • when Dante's dream begins. Compare George Herbert,--
  • "Lift up thy head;
  • Take stars for money; stars, not to be told
  • By any art, yet to be purchased."
  • And Plato's notable sentence in the third book of
  • "Polity":--"Tell them they have divine gold and silver in
  • their souls for ever; that they need no money stamped of
  • men--neither may they otherwise than impiously mingle the
  • gathering of the divine with the mortal treasure, for
  • through that which the law of the multitude has coined,
  • endless crimes have been done and suffered; but in theirs is
  • neither pollution nor sorrow." At the entrance of this place
  • of punishment an evil spirit is seen by Dante, quite other
  • than the "Gran Nemico." The great enemy is obeyed knowingly
  • and willingly; but this spirit--feminine--and called a
  • Siren--is the "Deceitfulness of riches," [Greek: apatê
  • ploutou] of the gospels, winning obedience by guile. This is
  • the Idol of Riches, made doubly phantasmal by Dante's seeing
  • her in a dream. She is lovely to look upon, and enchants by
  • her sweet singing, but her womb is loathsome. Now, Dante
  • does not call her one of the Sirens carelessly, any more
  • than he speaks of Charybdis carelessly, and though he had
  • only got at the meaning of the Homeric fable through
  • Virgil's obscure tradition of it, the clue he has given us
  • is quite enough. Bacon's interpretation, "the Sirens, or
  • pleasures," which has become universal since his time, is
  • opposed alike to Plato's meaning and Homer's. The Sirens are
  • not pleasures, but Desires: in the Odyssey they are the
  • phantoms of vain desire; but in Plato's vision of Destiny,
  • phantoms of constant Desire; singing each a different note
  • on the circles of the distaff of Necessity, but forming one
  • harmony, to which the three great Fates put words. Dante,
  • however, adopted the Homeric conception of them, which was
  • that they were demons of the Imagination, not carnal (desire
  • of the eyes; not lust of the flesh); therefore said to be
  • daughters of the Muses. Yet not of the muses, heavenly or
  • historical, but of the muse of pleasure; and they are at
  • first winged, because even vain hope excites and helps when
  • first formed; but afterwards, contending for the possession
  • of the imagination with the muses themselves, they are
  • deprived of their wings, and thus we are to distinguish the
  • Siren power from the Power of Circe, who is no daughter of
  • the muses, but of the strong elements, Sun and Sea; her
  • power is that of frank and full vital pleasure, which, if
  • governed and watched, nourishes men; but, unwatched, and
  • having no "moly," bitterness or delay mixed with it, turns
  • men into beasts, but does not slay them, leaves them, on the
  • contrary, power of revival. She is herself indeed an
  • Enchantress;--pure Animal life; transforming--or
  • degrading--but always wonderful (she puts the stores on
  • board the ship invisibly, and is gone again, like a ghost);
  • even the wild beasts rejoice and are softened around her
  • cave; to men, she gives no rich feast, nothing but pure and
  • right nourishment,--Pramnian wine, cheese and flour; that is
  • corn, milk, and wine, the three great sustainers of life--it
  • is their own fault if these make swine of them; and swine
  • are chosen merely as the type of consumption; as Plato's
  • [Greek: huôn polis] in the second book of the "Polity," and
  • perhaps chosen by Homer with a deeper knowledge of the
  • likeness of nourishment, and internal form of body. "Et quel
  • est, s'il vous plaît, cet audacieux animal qui se permet
  • d'être bâti au dedans comme une jolie petite fille?"
  • "Hélas! chère enfant, j'ai honte de le nommer, et il ne
  • foudra pas m'en vouloir. C'est ... c'est le cochon. Ce n'est
  • pas précisément flatteur pour vous; mais nous en sommes tous
  • là, et si cela vous contrarie par trop, il faut aller vous
  • plaindre au bon Dieu qui a voulu que les choses fussent
  • arrangées ainsï: seulement le cochon, qui ne pense qu' à
  • manger, a l'estomac bien plus vaste que nous, et c'est
  • toujours une consolation." ("Histoire d'une Bouchée de
  • Pain," Lettre ix.) But the deadly Sirens are all things
  • opposed to the Circean power. They promise pleasure, but
  • never give it. They nourish in no wise; but slay by slow
  • death. And whereas they corrupt the heart and the head,
  • instead of merely betraying the senses, there is no recovery
  • from their power; they do not tear nor snatch, like Scylla,
  • but the men who have listened to them are poisoned, and
  • waste away. Note that the Sirens' field is covered, not
  • merely with the bones, but with the skins of those who have
  • been consumed there. They address themselves, in the part of
  • the song which Homer gives, not to the passions of Ulysses,
  • but to his vanity, and the only man who ever came within
  • hearing of them, and escaped untempted, was Orpheus, who
  • silenced the vain imaginations by singing the praises of the
  • gods.
  • It is, then, one of these Sirens whom Dante takes as the
  • phantasm or deceitfulness of riches; but note further, that
  • she says it was her song that deceived Ulysses. Look back to
  • Dante's account of Ulysses' death, and we find it was not
  • the love of money, but pride of knowledge, that betrayed
  • him; whence we get the clue to Dante's complete meaning:
  • that the souls whose love of wealth is pardonable have been
  • first deceived into pursuit of it by a dream of its higher
  • uses, or by ambition. His Siren is therefore the Philotimé
  • of Spenser, daughter of Mammon--
  • "Whom all that folk with such contention
  • Do flock about, my deare, my daughter is--
  • Honour and dignitie from her alone
  • Derived are."
  • By comparing Spenser's entire account of this Philotimé with
  • Dante's of the Wealth-Siren, we shall get at the full
  • meaning of both poets; but that of Homer lies hidden much
  • more deeply. For his Sirens are indefinite, and they are
  • desires of any evil thing; power of wealth is not specially
  • indicated by him, until, escaping the harmonious danger of
  • imagination, Ulysses has to choose between two practical
  • ways of life, indicated by the two rocks of Scylla and
  • Charybdis. The monsters that haunt them are quite distinct
  • from the rocks themselves, which, having many other
  • subordinate significations, are in the main Labour and
  • Idleness, or getting and spending; each with its attendant
  • monster, or betraying demon. The rock of gaining has its
  • summit in the clouds, invisible and not to be climbed; that
  • of spending is low, but marked by the cursed fig-tree, which
  • has leaves but no fruit. We know the type elsewhere; and
  • there is a curious lateral allusion to it by Dante when
  • Jacopo di Sant' Andrea, who had ruined himself by profusion
  • and committed suicide, scatters the leaves of the bush of
  • Lotto degli Agli, endeavouring to hide himself among them.
  • We shall hereafter examine the type completely; here I will
  • only give an approximate rendering of Homer's words, which
  • have been obscured more by translation than even by
  • tradition--
  • "They are overhanging rocks. The great waves of blue water
  • break round them; and the blessed Gods call them the
  • Wanderers.
  • "By one of them no winged thing can pass--not even the wild
  • doves that bring ambrosia to their father Jove--but the
  • smooth rock seizes its sacrifice of them." (Not even
  • ambrosia to be had without Labour. The word is peculiar--as
  • a part of anything offered for sacrifice; especially used of
  • heave-offering.) "It reaches the wide heaven with its top,
  • and a dark-blue cloud rests on it, and never passes; neither
  • does the clear sky hold it in summer nor in harvest. Nor can
  • any man climb it--not if he had twenty feet and hands, for
  • it is smooth as though it were hewn.
  • "And in the midst of it is a cave which is turned the way of
  • hell. And therein dwells Scylla, whining for prey: her cry,
  • indeed, is no louder than that of a newly-born whelp: but
  • she herself is an awful thing--nor can any creature see her
  • face and be glad; no, though it were a god that rose against
  • her. For she has twelve feet, all fore-feet, and six necks,
  • and terrible heads on them; and each has three rows of
  • teeth, full of black death.
  • "But the opposite rock is lower than this, though but a
  • bow-shot distant; and upon it there is a great fig-tree,
  • full of leaves; and under it the terrible Charybdis sucks it
  • down, and thrice casts it up again; be not thou there when
  • she sucks down, for Neptune himself could not save thee."
  • The reader will find the meaning of these types gradually
  • elicited as we proceed.
  • This disease of desire having especial relation to the great art of
  • Exchange, or Commerce, we must, in order to complete our code of first
  • principles, shortly state the nature and limits of that art.
  • As the currency conveys right of choice out of many things in exchange
  • for one, so Commerce is the agency by which the power of choice is
  • obtained; and countries producing only timber can obtain for their
  • timber silk and gold; or, naturally producing only jewels and
  • frankincense, can obtain for them cattle and corn. In this function
  • commerce is of more importance to a country in proportion to the
  • limitations of its products and the restlessness of its
  • fancy;--generally of greater importance towards Northern latitudes.
  • Commerce is necessary, however, not only to exchange local products,
  • but local skill. Labour requiring the agency of fire can only be given
  • abundantly in cold countries; labour requiring suppleness of body and
  • sensitiveness of touch only in warm ones; labour involving accurate
  • vivacity of thought only in temperate ones; while peculiar imaginative
  • actions are produced by extremes of heat and cold, and of light and
  • darkness. The production of great art is limited to climates warm
  • enough to admit of repose in the open air, and cool enough to render
  • such repose delightful. Minor variations in modes of skill distinguish
  • every locality. The labour which at any place is easiest, is in that
  • place cheapest; and it becomes often desirable that products raised in
  • one country should be wrought in another. Hence have arisen
  • discussions on "International values," which will be one day
  • remembered as highly curious exercises of the human mind. For it will
  • be discovered, in due course of tide and time, that international
  • value is regulated just as inter-provincial or inter-parishional value
  • is. Coals and hops are exchanged between Northumberland and Kent on
  • absolutely the same principles as iron and wine between Lancashire and
  • Spain. The greater breadth of an arm of the sea increases the cost,
  • but does not modify the principle of exchange; and a bargain written
  • in two languages will have no other economical results than a bargain
  • written in one. The distances of nations are measured not by seas, but
  • by ignorances; and their divisions determined, not by dialects, but by
  • enmities.
  • Of course, a system of international values may always be constructed
  • if we assume a relation of moral law to physical geography; as, for
  • instance, that it is right to cheat across a river, though not across
  • a road; or across a lake, though not across a river; or over a
  • mountain, though not across a lake, etc.:--again, a system of such
  • values may be constructed by assuming similar relations of taxation to
  • physical geography; as, for instance, that an article should be taxed
  • in crossing a river, but not in crossing a road; or in being carried
  • over a mountain, but not over a ferry, etc.: such positions are indeed
  • not easily maintained when once put in logical form; but one law of
  • international value is maintainable in any form; namely, that the
  • farther your neighbour lives from you, and the less he understands
  • you, the more you are bound to be true in your dealings with him;
  • because your power over him is greater in proportion to his ignorance,
  • and his remedy more difficult in proportion to his distance.
  • I have just said the breadth of sea increases the cost of exchange.
  • Exchange or commerce, as such, is always costly; the sum of the value
  • of the goods being diminished by the cost of their conveyance, and by
  • the maintenance of the persons employed in it. So that it is only when
  • there is advantage to both producers (in getting the one thing for the
  • other), greater than the loss in conveyance, that the exchange is
  • expedient. And it is only justly conducted when the porters kept by
  • the producers (commonly called merchants) look only for pay, and not
  • for profit. For in just commerce there are but three parties--the two
  • persons or societies exchanging and the agent or agents of exchange:
  • the value of the things to be exchanged is known by both the
  • exchangers, and each receives equivalent value, neither gaining nor
  • losing (for whatever one gains the other loses). The intermediate
  • agent is paid an equal and known percentage by both, partly for labour
  • in conveyance, partly for care, knowledge, and risk; every attempt at
  • concealment of the amount of the pay indicates either effort on the
  • part of the agent to obtain exorbitant percentage, or effort on the
  • part of the exchangers to refuse him a just one. But for the most part
  • it is the first, namely, the effort on the part of the merchant to
  • obtain larger profit (so called) by buying cheap and selling dear.
  • Some part, indeed, of this larger gain is deserved, and might be
  • openly demanded, because it is the reward of the merchant's knowledge,
  • and foresight of probable necessity; but the greater part of such gain
  • is unjust; and unjust in this most fatal way, that it depends first on
  • keeping the exchangers ignorant of the exchange value of the articles,
  • and secondly, on taking advantage of the buyer's need and the seller's
  • poverty. It is, therefore, one of the essential, and quite the most
  • fatal, forms of usury; for usury means merely taking an exorbitant sum
  • for the use of anything, and it is no matter whether the exorbitance
  • is on loan or exchange, in rent or in price--the essence of the usury
  • being that it is obtained by advantage of opportunity or necessity,
  • and not as due reward for labour. All the great thinkers, therefore,
  • have held it to be unnatural and impious, in so far as it feeds on
  • the distress of others, or their folly.[97] Nevertheless attempts to
  • repress it by law (in other words, to regulate prices by law so far as
  • their variations depend on iniquity, and not on nature) must for ever
  • be ineffective; though Plato, Bacon, and the First Napoleon--all three
  • of them men who knew somewhat more of humanity than the "British
  • merchant" usually does--tried their hands at it, and have left some
  • (probably) good moderative forms of law, which we will examine in
  • their place. But the only final check upon it must be radical
  • purifying of the national character, for being, as Bacon calls it,
  • "concessum propter duritiem cordis," it is to be done away with by
  • touching the heart only; not, however, without medicinal law--as in
  • the case of the other permission, "propter duritiem." But in this,
  • more than in anything (though much in all, and though in this he would
  • not himself allow of their application, for his own laws against usury
  • are sharp enough), Plato's words are true in the fourth book of the
  • "Polity," that neither drugs, nor charms, nor burnings, will touch a
  • deep-lying political sore, any more than a deep bodily one; but only
  • right and utter change of constitution; and that "they do but lose
  • their labour who think that by any tricks of law they can get the
  • better of these mischiefs of intercourse, and see not that they hew at
  • a Hydra."
  • [97] Hence Dante's companionship of Cahors, Inf., canto xi.,
  • supported by the view taken of the matter throughout the
  • middle ages, in common with the Greeks.
  • And indeed this Hydra seems so unslayable, and sin sticks so fast
  • between the joinings of the stones of buying and selling, that "to
  • trade" in things, or literally "cross-give" them, has warped itself,
  • by the instinct of nations, into their worst word for fraud; for,
  • because in trade there cannot but be trust, and it seems also that
  • there cannot but also be injury in answer to it, what is merely fraud
  • between enemies becomes treachery among friends: and "trader,"
  • "traditor," and "traitor" are but the same word. For which simplicity
  • of language there is more reason than at first appears; for as in true
  • commerce there is no "profit," so in true commerce there is no "sale."
  • The idea of sale is that of an interchange between enemies
  • respectively endeavouring to get the better of one another; but
  • commerce is an exchange between friends; and there is no desire but
  • that it should be just, any more than there would be between members
  • of the same family. The moment there is a bargain over the pottage,
  • the family relation is dissolved;--typically "the days of mourning for
  • my father are at hand." Whereupon follows the resolve "then will I
  • slay my brother."
  • This inhumanity of mercenary commerce is the more notable because it
  • is a fulfilment of the law that the corruption of the best is the
  • worst. For as, taking the body natural for symbol of the body politic,
  • the governing and forming powers may be likened to the brain and the
  • labouring to the limbs, the mercantile, presiding over circulation and
  • communication of things in changed utilities is symbolized by the
  • heart; which, if it harden, all is lost. And this is the ultimate
  • lesson which the leader of English intellect meant for us (a lesson,
  • indeed, not all his own, but part of the old wisdom of humanity), in
  • the tale of the "Merchant of Venice"; in which the true and incorrupt
  • merchant,--kind and free, beyond every other Shakespearian conception
  • of men,--is opposed to the corrupted merchant, or usurer; the lesson
  • being deepened by the expression of the strange hatred which the
  • corrupted merchant bears to the pure one, mixed with intense scorn--
  • "This is the fool that lent out money gratis; look to him, jailor,"
  • (as to lunatic no less than criminal); the enmity, observe, having its
  • symbolism literally carried out by being aimed straight at the heart,
  • and finally foiled by a literal appeal to the great moral law that
  • flesh and blood cannot be weighed, enforced by "Portia" ("Portion"),
  • the type of divine Fortune,[98] found, not in gold, nor in silver, but
  • in lead, that is to say, in endurance and patience, not in splendour;
  • and finally taught by her lips also, declaring, instead of the law and
  • quality of "merces," the greater law and quality of mercy, which is
  • not strained, but drops as the rain, blessing him that gives and him
  • that takes. And observe that this "mercy" is not the mean
  • "Misericordia," but the mighty "Gratia," answered by Gratitude
  • (observe Shylock's leaning on the, to him detestable, word gratis, and
  • compare the relation of Grace to Equity given in the second chapter of
  • the second book of the "Memorabilia"); that is to say, it is the
  • gracious or loving, instead of the strained, or competing manner, of
  • doing things, answered, not only with "merces" or pay, but with
  • "merci," or thanks. And this is indeed the meaning of the great
  • benediction, "Grace, mercy, and peace," for there can be no peace
  • without grace (not even by help of rifled cannon),[99] nor even
  • without triplicity of graciousness, for the Greeks, who began with but
  • one Grace, had to open their scheme into three before they had done.
  • [98] Shakespeare would certainly never have chosen this name had
  • he been forced to retain the Roman spelling. Like Perdita,
  • "lost lady," or "Cordelia," "heart-lady," Portia is
  • "fortune-lady." The two great relative groups of words,
  • Fortune, fero, and fors--Portio, porto, and pars (with the
  • lateral branch, op-portune, im-portune, opportunity, etc.),
  • are of deep and intrinsic significance; their various senses
  • of bringing, abstracting, and sustaining, being all
  • centralized by the wheel (which bears and moves at once), or
  • still better, the ball (spera) of Fortune,--"Volve sua
  • spera, e beata si gode:" the motive power of this wheel
  • distinguishing its goddess from the fixed majesty of
  • Necessitas with her iron nails; or [Greek: anankê], with
  • her pillar of fire and iridescent orbits, fixed at the
  • centre. Portus and porta, and gate in its connexion with
  • gain, form another interesting branch group; and Mors, the
  • concentration of delaying, is always to be remembered with
  • Fors, the concentration of bringing and bearing, passing on
  • into Fortis and Fortitude.
  • [99] Out of whose mouths, indeed, no peace was ever promulgated,
  • but only equipoise of panic, highly tremulous on the edge in
  • changes in the wind.
  • With the usual tendency of long-repeated thought to take the surface
  • for the deep, we have conceived their goddesses as if they only gave
  • loveliness to gesture; whereas their true function is to give
  • graciousness to deed, the other loveliness arising naturally out of
  • that. In which function Charis becomes Charitas[100] and has a name and
  • praise even greater than that of Faith or truth, for these may be
  • maintained sullenly and proudly; but Charis[101] is in her countenance
  • always gladdening (Aglaia), and in her service instant and humble; and
  • the true wife of Vulcan, or Labour. And it is not until her sincerity
  • of function is lost, and her mere beauty contemplated, instead of her
  • patience, that she is born again of the foam flake, and becomes
  • Aphrodité; then only capable of joining herself to War and to the
  • enmities of men, instead of to Labour and their services. Therefore
  • the fable of Mars and Venus is, chosen by Homer, picturing himself as
  • Demodocus, to sing at the games in the Court of Alcinous. Phæacia is
  • the Homeric island of Atlantis; an image of noble and wise government,
  • concealed, how slightly! merely by the change of a short vowel for a
  • long one in the name of its queen; yet misunderstood by all later
  • writers, even by Horace in his "pinguis, Phæaxque," etc. That fable
  • expresses the perpetual error of men, thinking that grace and dignity
  • can only be reached by the soldier, and never by the artizan; so that
  • commerce and the useful arts have had the honour and beauty taken
  • away, and only the Fraud[102] and Pain left to them, with the lucre.
  • Which is, indeed, one great reason of the continual blundering about
  • the offices of government with respect to commerce. The higher classes
  • are ashamed to deal with it; and though ready enough to fight for (or
  • occasionally against) the people,--to preach to them,--or judge them,
  • will not break bread for them; the refined upper servant who has
  • willingly looked after the burnishing of the armoury and ordering of
  • the library, not liking to set foot into the larder.
  • [100] The reader must not think that any care can be misspent
  • in tracing the connexion and power of the words which we
  • have to use in the sequel. Not only does all soundness of
  • reasoning depend on the work thus done in the outset, but
  • we may sometimes gain more by insistence on the expression
  • of a truth, than by much wordless thinking about it; for
  • to strive to express it clearly is often to detect it
  • thoroughly; and education, even as regards thought, nearly
  • sums itself in making men economise their words, and
  • understand them. Nor is it possible to estimate the harm
  • that has been done, in matters of higher speculation and
  • conduct, by loose verbiage, though we may guess at it by
  • observing the dislike which people show to having anything
  • about their religion said to them in simple words, because
  • then they understand it. Thus congregations meet weekly to
  • invoke the influence of a Spirit of Life and Truth; yet if
  • any part of that character were intelligibly expressed to
  • them by the formulas of the service, they would be offended.
  • Suppose, for instance, in the closing benediction, the
  • clergyman were to give its vital significance to the word
  • "Holy," and were to say, "the Fellowship of the Helpful and
  • Honest Ghost be with you, and remain with you always," what
  • would be the horror of many, first, at the irreverence of so
  • intelligible an expression, and, secondly, at the
  • discomfortable entry of the suspicion that (while throughout
  • the commercial dealings of the week they had denied the
  • propriety of Help, and possibility of Honesty) the Person
  • whose company they had been asking to be blessed with could
  • have no fellowship with knaves.
  • [101] As Charis becomes Charitas [see next page], the word "Cher,"
  • or "Dear," passes from Shylock's sense of it (to buy cheap
  • and sell dear) into Antonio's sense of it: emphasized with
  • the final i in tender "Cheri," and hushed to English
  • calmness in our noble "Cherish."
  • [102] While I have traced the finer and higher laws of this matter
  • for those whom they concern, I have also to note the
  • material law--vulgarly expressed in the proverb, "Honesty is
  • the best policy." That proverb is indeed wholly inapplicable
  • to matters of private interest. It is not true that honesty,
  • as far as material gain is concerned, profits individuals. A
  • clever and cruel knave will, in a mixed society, always be
  • richer than an honest person can be. But Honesty is the best
  • "policy," if policy means practice of State. For fraud gains
  • nothing in a State. It only enables the knaves in it to live
  • at the expense of honest people; while there is for every
  • act of fraud, however small, a loss of wealth to the
  • community. Whatever the fraudulent person gains, some other
  • person loses, as fraud produces nothing; and there is,
  • besides, the loss of the time and thought spent in
  • accomplishing the fraud; and of the strength otherwise
  • obtainable by mutual help (not to speak of the fevers of
  • anxiety and jealousy in the blood, which are a heavy
  • physical loss, as I will show in due time). Practically,
  • when the nation is deeply corrupt, cheat answers to cheat,
  • every one is in turn imposed upon, and there is to the body
  • politic the dead loss of ingenuity, together with the
  • incalculable mischief of the injury to each defrauded
  • person, producing collateral effect unexpectedly. My
  • neighbour sells me bad meat: I sell him in return flawed
  • iron. We neither of us get one atom of pecuniary advantage
  • on the whole transaction, but we both suffer unexpected
  • inconvenience;--my men get scurvy, and his cattle-truck runs
  • off the rails.
  • Farther still. As Charis becomes Charitas on the one side, she
  • becomes--better still--Chara, Joy, on the other; or rather this is her
  • very mother's milk and the beauty of her childhood; for God brings no
  • enduring Love, nor any other good, out of pain, nor out of contention;
  • but out of joy and harmony.[103] And in this sense, human and divine,
  • music and gladness, and the measures of both, come into her name; and
  • Cher becomes full-vowelled Cheer, and Cheerful; and Chara,
  • companioned, opens into Choir and Choral.
  • [103] "[Greek: ta men houn alla zôa ouk echein aisthêsin tôn
  • en tais kinêsesi taxeôn oude ataxiôn, hoi dê rhuthmos
  • onoma kai harmonia hêmin de ous eipomen tous theous]
  • [Apollo, the Muses, and Bacchus--the grave Bacchus, that
  • is---ruling the choir of age; or Bacchus restraining;
  • 'sæva _tene_, cum Berecyntio cornu, tympana,' etc.]
  • [Greek: sunchoreutas dedosthai, toutous einai kai tous
  • dedôkotas tên enruthmon te kai henarmonion aisthêsin
  • meth' êdonês ... chorous te ônomakenai para tês charas
  • emphyton unoma.]"--"Laws," book ii.
  • And lastly. As Grace passes into Freedom of action, Charis becomes
  • Eleutheria, or liberality; a form of liberty quite curiously and
  • intensely different from the thing usually understood by "Liberty"
  • in modern language; indeed, much more like what some people would
  • call slavery; for a Greek always understood, primarily, by liberty,
  • deliverance from the law of his own passions (or from what the
  • Christian writers call bondage of corruption), and this a complete
  • liberty: not having to resist the passion, but making it fawn upon,
  • and follow him--(this may be again partly the meaning of the fawning
  • beasts about the Circean cave; so, again, George Herbert--
  • Correct thy passion's spite;
  • Then may the beasts draw thee to happy light)--
  • not being merely safe from the Siren, but also unbound from the mast.
  • And it is only in such generosity that any man becomes capable of so
  • governing others as to take true part in any system of national
  • economy. Nor is there any other eternal distinction between the upper
  • and lower classes than this form of liberty, Eleutheria, or benignity,
  • in the one, and its opposite of slavery, Douleia, or malignity, in the
  • other; the separation of these two orders of men, and the firm
  • government of the lower by the higher, being the first conditions of
  • possible wealth and economy in any state,--the Gods giving it no
  • greater gift than the power to discern its freemen, and "malignum
  • spernere vulgus."
  • The examination of this form of Charis must, therefore, lead us into
  • the discussion of the principles of government in general, and
  • especially of that of the poor by the rich, discovering how the
  • Graciousness joined with the Greatness, or Love with Majestas, is the
  • true Dei Gratia, or Divine Right, of every form and manner of King;
  • _i.e._, specifically, of the thrones, dominations, princedoms,
  • virtues, and powers of the earth;--of the thrones, stable, or
  • "ruling," literally right-doing powers ("rex eris, recte si facies:")
  • of the dominations, lordly, edifying, dominant, and harmonious powers;
  • chiefly domestic, over the "built thing," domus, or house; and
  • inherently twofold, Dominus and Domina; Lord and Lady: of the
  • Princedoms, pre-eminent, incipient, creative, and demonstrative
  • powers; thus poetic and mercantile, in the "princeps carmen deduxisse"
  • and the merchant-prince: of the Virtues or Courages; militant,
  • guiding, or Ducal powers; and finally of the Strengths and Forces
  • pure; magistral powers, of the more over the less, and the forceful
  • and free over the weak and servile elements of life.
  • Subject enough for the next paper involving "economical" principles of
  • some importance, of which, for theme, here is a sentence, which I do
  • not care to translate, for it would sound harsh in English, though,
  • truly, it is one of the tenderest ever uttered by man; which may be
  • meditated over, or rather through, in the meanwhile, by any one who
  • will take the pains:--
  • [Greek: Arh oun, hôsper hippos tô anepistêmoni men encheirounti
  • de chrêsthai zêmia estin, houtô kai adelphos hotan tis autô mê
  • epistamenos encheirê chrêsthai, zêmia esti?]
  • IV.
  • LAWS AND GOVERNMENTS: LABOUR AND RICHES.
  • It remains, in order to complete the series of our definitions, that
  • we examine the general conditions of government, and fix the sense in
  • which we are to use, in future, the terms applied to them.
  • The government of a state consists in its customs, laws, and councils,
  • and their enforcements.
  • I.--CUSTOMS.
  • As one person primarily differs from another by fineness of nature,
  • and secondarily, by fineness of training, so also, a polite nation
  • differs from a savage one, first by the refinement of its nature, and
  • secondly by the delicacy of its customs.
  • In the completeness, or accomplishment of custom, which is the
  • nation's self-government, there are three stages--first, fineness in
  • method of doing or of being;--called the manner or moral of acts:
  • secondly, firmness in holding such method after adoption, so that
  • it shall become a habit in the character: _i.e._, a constant "having"
  • or "behaving"; and, lastly, practice, or ethical power in performance
  • and endurance, which is the skill following on habit, and the ease
  • reached by frequency of right doing.
  • The sensibility of the nation is indicated by the fineness of its
  • customs; its courage, patience, and temperance by its persistence in
  • them.
  • By sensibility I mean its natural perception of beauty, fitness, and
  • rightness; or of what is lovely, decent, and just: faculties
  • dependent much on race, and the primal signs of fine breeding in man;
  • but cultivable also by education, and necessary perishing without it.
  • True education has, indeed, no other function than the development of
  • these faculties, and of the relative will. It has been the great error
  • of modern intelligence to mistake science for education. You do not
  • educate a man by telling him what he knew not, but by making him what
  • he was not.
  • And making him what he will remain for ever: for no wash of weeds will
  • bring back the faded purple. And in that dyeing there are two
  • processes--first, the cleansing and wringing out, which is the baptism
  • with water; and then the infusing of the blue and scarlet colours,
  • gentleness and justice, which is the baptism with fire.
  • The customs and manners of a sensitive and highly-trained race are
  • always vital: that is to say, they are orderly manifestations of
  • intense life (like the habitual action of the fingers of a musician).
  • The customs and manners of a vile and rude race, on the contrary,
  • are conditions of decay: they are not, properly speaking, habits,
  • but incrustations; not restraints, or forms, of life; but
  • gangrenes;--noisome, and the beginnings of death. And generally, so
  • far as custom attaches itself to indolence instead of action, and to
  • prejudice instead of perception, it takes this deadly character, so
  • that thus
  • "Custom hangs upon us with a weight
  • Heavy as frost, and deep almost as life."
  • This power and depth are, however, just what give value to custom,
  • when it works with life, instead of against it.
  • The high ethical training, of a nation being threefold, of body,
  • heart, and practice (compare the statement in the preface to "Unto
  • This Last"), involves exquisiteness in all its perceptions of
  • circumstance,--all its occupations of thought. It implies perfect
  • Grace, Pitifulness, and Peace; it is irreconcilably inconsistent with
  • filthy or mechanical employments,--with the desire of money,--and with
  • mental states of anxiety, jealousy, and indifference to pain. The
  • present insensibility of the upper classes of Europe to the aspects of
  • suffering, uncleanness, and crime, binds them not only into one
  • responsibility with the sin, but into one dishonour with the foulness,
  • which rot at their thresholds. The crimes daily recorded in the police
  • courts of London and Paris (and much more those which are unrecorded)
  • are a disgrace to the whole body politic;[104] they are, as in the
  • body natural, stains of disease on a face of delicate skin, making the
  • delicacy itself frightful. Similarly, the filth and poverty permitted
  • or ignored in the midst of us are as dishonourable to the whole social
  • body, as in the body natural it is to wash the face, but leave the
  • hands and feet foul. Christ's way is the only true one: begin at the
  • feet; the face will take care of itself. Yet, since necessarily, in
  • the frame of a nation, nothing but the head can be of gold, and the
  • feet, for the work they have to do, must be part of iron, part of
  • clay;--foul or mechanical work is always reduced by a noble race to
  • the minimum in quantity; and, even then, performed and endured, not
  • without sense of degradation, as a fine temper is wounded by the sight
  • of the lower offices of the body. The highest conditions of human
  • society reached hitherto, have cast such work to slaves;--supposing
  • slavery of a politically defined kind to be done away with, mechanical
  • and foul employment must in all highly-organized states take the
  • aspect either of punishment or probation. All criminals should at once
  • be set to the most dangerous and painful forms of it, especially to
  • work in mines and at furnaces,[105] so as to relieve the innocent
  • population as far as possible: of merely rough (not mechanical) manual
  • labour, especially agricultural, a large portion should be done by the
  • upper classes;--bodily health, and sufficient contrast and repose for
  • the mental functions, being unattainable without it; what necessarily
  • inferior labour remains to be done, as especially in manufactures,
  • should, and always will, when the relations of society are reverent
  • and harmonious, fall to the lot of those who, for the time, are fit
  • for nothing better. For as, whatever the perfectness of the
  • educational system, there must remain infinite differences between the
  • natures and capacities of men; and these differing natures are
  • generally rangeable under the two qualities of lordly (or tending
  • towards rule, construction, and harmony) and servile (or tending
  • towards misrule, destruction, and discord); and, since the lordly part
  • is only in a state of profitableness while ruling, and the servile
  • only in a state of redeemableness while serving, the whole health of
  • the state depends on the manifest separation of these two elements of
  • its mind: for, if the servile part be not separated and rendered
  • visible in service, it mixes with and corrupts the entire body of the
  • state; and if the lordly part be not distinguished, and set to rule,
  • it is crushed and lost, being turned to no account, so that the rarest
  • qualities of the nation are all given to it in vain.[106] The
  • effecting of which distinction is the first object, as we shall see
  • presently, of national councils.
  • [104] "The ordinary brute, who flourishes in the very centre
  • of ornate life, tells us of unknown depths on the verge of
  • which we totter, being bound to thank our stars every day we
  • live that there is not a general outbreak and a revolt from
  • the yoke of civilization."--_Times_ leader, Dec. 25th, 1862.
  • Admitting that our stars are to be thanked for our safety,
  • whom are we to thank for the danger?
  • [105] Our politicians, even the best of them, regard only the
  • distress caused by the failure of mechanical labour. The
  • degradation caused by its excess is a far more serious
  • subject of thought, and of future fear. I shall examine this
  • part of our subject at length hereafter. There can hardly be
  • any doubt, at present, cast on the truth of the above
  • passages, as all the great thinkers are unanimous on the
  • matter. Plato's words are terrific in their scorn and pity
  • whenever he touches on the mechanical arts. He calls the men
  • employed in them not even human,--but partially and
  • diminutively human, "[Greek: anthrôpiskoi]," and opposes
  • such work to noble occupations, not merely as prison is
  • opposed to freedom, but as a convict's dishonoured prison is
  • to the temple (escape from them being like that of a
  • criminal to the sanctuary), and the destruction caused by
  • them being of soul no less than body.--Rep., vi. 9. Compare
  • "Laws," v. 11. Xenophon dwells on the evil of occupations at
  • the furnace (root of [Greek: banausos]), and especially their
  • "[Greek: ascholia], want of leisure"--Econ. i. 4. (Modern
  • England, with all its pride of education, has lost that
  • first sense of the word "school," and till it recover that
  • it will find no other rightly.) His word for the harm to the
  • soul is to "break" it, as we say of the heart.--Econ. i. 6.
  • And herein also is the root of the scorn, otherwise
  • apparently most strange and cruel, with which Homer, Dante,
  • and Shakespeare always speak of the populace; for it is
  • entirely true that in great states the lower orders are low
  • by nature as well as by task, being precisely that part of
  • the commonwealth which has been thrust down for its
  • coarseness or unworthiness (by coarseness I mean especially
  • insensibility and irreverence; the "profane" of Horace); and
  • when this ceases to be so, and the corruption and the
  • profanity are in the higher instead of the lower orders,
  • there arises, first, helpless confusion; then, if the lower
  • classes deserve power, ensues swift revolution, and they get
  • it: but if neither the populace nor their rulers deserve it,
  • there follows mere darkness and dissolution, till, out of
  • the putrid elements, some new capacity of order rises, like
  • grass on a grave; if not, there is no more hope, nor shadow
  • of turning, for that nation. Atropos has her way with it.
  • So that the law of national health is like that of a great
  • lake or sea, in perfect but slow circulation, letting the
  • dregs fall continually to the lowest place, and the clear
  • water rise; yet so as that there shall be no neglect of the
  • lower orders, but perfect supervision and sympathy, so that
  • if one member suffer, all members shall suffer with it.
  • [106] "[Greek: oligês, kai allôs gignomenês.]" The bitter
  • sentence never was so true as at this day.
  • II.--LAWS.
  • These are the definitions and bonds of custom, or, of what the nation
  • desires should become custom.
  • Law is either archic[107] (of direction), meristic (of division), or
  • critic (of judgment). Archic law is that of appointment and precept:
  • it defines what is and is not to be done. Meristic law is that of
  • balance and distribution: it defines what is and is not to be
  • possessed. Critic law is that of discernment and award: it defines
  • what is and is not to be suffered.
  • [107] Thetic, or Thesmic, would perhaps be a better term than
  • Archic; but liable to be confused with some which we shall
  • want relating to Theoria. The administrators of the three
  • great divisions of law are severally Archons, Merists, and
  • Dicasts. The Archons are the true princes, or beginners of
  • things; or leaders (as of an orchestra); the Merists are
  • properly the Domini, or Lords (law-words) of houses and
  • nations; the Dicasts properly the judges, and that with
  • Olympian justice, which reaches to heaven and hell. The
  • violation of archic law is [Greek: hamartia] (error)
  • [Greek: ponêria] (failure), [Greek: plêmmeleia] (discord).
  • The violation of meristic law is [Greek: anomia] (iniquity).
  • The violation of critic law is [Greek: adikia] (injury).
  • Iniquity is central generic term; for all law is _fatal_; it
  • is the division to men of their fate; as the fold of their
  • pasture, it is [Greek: nomos]; as the assigning of their
  • portion, [Greek: moira].
  • If we choose to class the laws of precept and distribution under the
  • general head of "statutes," all law is simply either of statute or
  • judgment; that is, first, the establishment of ordinance, and,
  • secondly, the assignment of the reward or penalty due to its
  • observance or violation.
  • To some extent these two forms of law must be associated, and, with
  • every ordinance, the penalty of disobedience to it be also determined.
  • But since the degrees and guilt of disobedience vary, the
  • determination of due reward and punishment must be modified by
  • discernment of special fact, which is peculiarly the office of the
  • judge, as distinguished from that of the lawgiver and lawsustainer, or
  • king; not but that the two offices are always theoretically and, in
  • early stages, or limited numbers, of society, are often practically,
  • united in the same person or persons.
  • Also, it is necessary to keep clearly in view the distinction between
  • these two kinds of law, because the possible range of law is wider in
  • proportion to their separation. There are many points of conduct
  • respecting which the nation may wisely express its will by a written
  • precept or resolve; yet not enforce it by penalty; and the expedient
  • degree of penalty is always quite a separate consideration from the
  • expedience of the statute, for the statute may often be better
  • enforced by mercy than severity, and is also easier in bearing, and
  • less likely to be abrogated. Farther, laws of precept have reference
  • especially to youth, and concern themselves with training; but laws of
  • judgment to manhood, and concern themselves with remedy and reward.
  • There is a highly curious feeling in the English mind against
  • educational law; we think no man's liberty should be interfered with
  • till he has done irrevocable wrong; whereas it is then just too late
  • for the only gracious and kingly interference, which is to hinder him
  • from doing it. Make your educational laws strict, and your criminal
  • ones may be gentle; but, leave youth its liberty, and you will have to
  • dig dungeons for age. And it is good for a man that he wear the yoke
  • in his youth; for the yoke of youth, if you know how to hold it, may
  • be of silken thread; and there is sweet chime of silver bells at that
  • bridle rein; but, for the captivity of age, you must forge the iron
  • fetter, and cast the passing bell.
  • Since no law can be in a final or true sense established, but by right
  • (all unjust laws involving the ultimate necessity of their own
  • abrogation), the law-sustaining power in so far as it is Royal, or
  • "right doing";--in so far, that is, as it rules, not mis-rules, and
  • orders, not dis-orders, the things submitted to it. Throned on this
  • rock of justice, the kingly power becomes established and
  • establishing, "[Greek: theios]," or divine, and, therefore, it is
  • literally true that no ruler can err, so long as he is a ruler, or
  • [Greek: archôn oudeis hamartanei tote hotan archôn ê] (perverted by
  • careless thought, which has cost the world somewhat, into "the king
  • can do no wrong"). Which is a divine right of kings indeed, and quite
  • unassailable, so long as the terms of it are "God and my Right," and
  • not "Satan and my Wrong," which is apt, in some coinages, to appear on
  • the reverse of the die, under a good lens.
  • Meristic law, or that of tenure of property, first determines what
  • every individual possesses by right, and secures it to him; and what
  • he possesses by wrong, and deprives him of it. But it has a far higher
  • provisory function: it determines what every man should possess, and
  • puts it within his reach on due conditions; and what he should not
  • possess, and puts this out of his reach conclusively.
  • Every article of human wealth has certain conditions attached to its
  • merited possession, which, when they are unobserved, possession
  • becomes rapine. The object of meristic law is not only to secure every
  • man his rightful share (the share, that is, which he has worked for,
  • produced, or received by gift from a rightful owner), but to enforce
  • the due conditions of possession, as far as law may conveniently
  • reach; for instance, that land shall not be wantonly allowed to run to
  • waste, that streams shall not be poisoned by the persons through whose
  • properties they pass, nor air be rendered unwholesome beyond given
  • limits. Laws of this kind exist already in rudimentary degree, but
  • needing large development; the just laws respecting the possession of
  • works of art have not hitherto been so much as conceived, and the
  • daily loss of national wealth, and of its use, in this respect, is
  • quite incalculable.[108] While, finally, in certain conditions of a
  • nation's progress, laws limiting accumulation of property may be found
  • expedient.
  • [108] These laws need revision quite as much respecting property
  • in national as in private hands. For instance: the public
  • are under a vague impression, that because they have paid
  • for the contents of the British Museum, every one has an
  • equal right to see and to handle them. But the public have
  • similarly paid for the contents of Woolwich Arsenal; yet do
  • not expect free access to it, or handling of its contents.
  • The British Museum is neither a free circulating library,
  • nor a free school; it is a place for the safe preservation,
  • and exhibition on due occasion, of unique books, unique
  • objects of natural history, and unique works of art; its
  • books can no more be used by everybody than its coins can be
  • handled, or its statues cast. Free libraries there ought to
  • be in every quarter of London, with large and complete
  • reading-rooms attached; so also free educational
  • institutions should be open in every quarter of London, all
  • day long and till late at night, well lighted, well
  • catalogued, and rich in contents both of art and natural
  • history. But neither the British Museum nor National Gallery
  • are schools; they are treasuries; and both should be
  • severely restricted in access and in use. Unless some order
  • is taken, and that soon, in the MSS. department of the
  • Museum (Sir Frederic Madden was complaining of this to me
  • only the other day), the best MSS. in the collection will be
  • destroyed, irretrievably, by the careless and continual
  • handling to which they are now subjected.
  • Critic law determines questions of injury, and assigns due rewards and
  • punishments to conduct.[109]
  • [109] Two curious economical questions arise laterally with
  • respect to this branch of law, namely, the cost of crime and
  • the cost of judgment. The cost of crime is endured by
  • nations ignorantly, not being clearly stated in their
  • budgets; the cost of judgment patiently (provided only it
  • can be had pure for the money), because the science, or
  • perhaps we ought rather to say the art, of law, is felt to
  • found a noble profession, and discipline; so that civilized
  • nations are usually glad that a number of persons should be
  • supported by funds devoted to disputation and analysis. But
  • it has not yet been calculated what the practical value
  • might have been, in other directions, of the intelligence
  • now occupied in deciding, through courses of years, what
  • might have been decided as justly, had the date of judgment
  • been fixed, in as many hours. Imagine one half of the funds
  • which any great nation devotes to dispute by law, applied to
  • the determination of physical questions in medicine,
  • agriculture, and theoretic science; and calculate the
  • probable results within the next ten years.
  • I say nothing yet, of the more deadly, more lamentable loss,
  • involved in the use of purchased instead of personal
  • justice,--[Greek: epaktô par' allôn--aporia' oikeiôn].
  • Therefore, in order to true analysis of it, we must understand the
  • real meaning of this word "injury."
  • We commonly understand by it any kind of harm done by one man to
  • another; but we do not define the idea of harm; sometimes we limit it
  • to the harm which the sufferer is conscious of, whereas much the worst
  • injuries are those he is unconscious of; and, at other times, we limit
  • the idea to violence, or restraint, whereas much the worse forms of
  • injury are to be accomplished by carelessness, and the withdrawal of
  • restraint.
  • "Injury" is, then, simply the refusal, or violation of any man's right
  • or claim upon his fellows: which claim, much talked of in modern
  • times, under the term "right," is mainly resolvable into two branches:
  • a man's claim not to be hindered from doing what he should; and his
  • claim to be hindered from doing what he should not; these two forms of
  • hindrance being intensified by reward, or help and fortune, or Fors on
  • one side, and punishment, impediment, and even final arrest, or Mors,
  • on the other.
  • Now, in order to a man's obtaining these two rights, it is clearly
  • needful that the worth of him should be approximately known; as well
  • as the want of worth, which has, unhappily, been usually the principal
  • subject of study for critic law, careful hitherto only to mark degrees
  • of de-merit, instead of merit;--assigning, indeed, to the deficiencies
  • (not always, alas! even to these) just fine, diminution, or (with the
  • broad vowels) damnation; but to the efficiencies, on the other side,
  • which are by much the more interesting, as well as the only profitable
  • part of its subject, assigning in any clear way neither measurement
  • nor aid.
  • Now, it is in this higher and perfect function of critic law, enabling
  • as well as disabling, that it becomes truly kingly or basilican,
  • instead of Draconic (what Providence gave the great, old, wrathful
  • legislator his name?); that is, it becomes the law of man and of life,
  • instead of the law of the worm and of death--both of these laws being
  • set in everlasting poise one against another, and the enforcement of
  • both being the eternal function of the lawgiver, and true claim of
  • every living soul: such claim being indeed as straight and earnest to
  • be mercifully hindered, and even, if need be, abolished, when longer
  • existence means only deeper destruction, as to be mercifully helped
  • and recreated when longer existence and new creation mean nobler life.
  • So that what we vulgarly term reward and punishment will be found to
  • resolve themselves mainly into help and hindrance, and these again
  • will issue naturally from true recognition of deserving, and the just
  • reverence and just wrath which follow instinctively on such
  • recognition.
  • I say "follow," but in reality they are the recognition. Reverence is
  • but the perceiving of the thing in its entire truth: truth reverted is
  • truth revered (vereor and veritas having clearly the same root), so
  • that Goethe is for once, and for a wonder, wrong in that part of the
  • noble scheme of education in "Wilhelm Meister," in which he says that
  • reverence is not innate, and must be taught. Reverence is as
  • instinctive as anger;--both of them instant on true vision: it is
  • sight and understanding that we have to teach, and these are
  • reverence. Make a man perceive worth, and in its reflection he sees
  • his own relative unworth, and worships thereupon inevitably, not with
  • stiff courtesy, but rejoicingly, passionately, and, best of all,
  • restfully: for the inner capacity of awe and love is infinite in man;
  • and when his eyes are once opened to the sight of beauty and honour,
  • it is with him as with a lover, who, falling at his mistress's feet,
  • would cast himself through the earth, if it might be, to fall lower,
  • and find a deeper and humbler place. And the common insolences and
  • petulances of the people, and their talk of equality, are not
  • irreverence in them in the least, but mere blindness, stupefaction,
  • and fog in the brains,[110] which pass away in the degree that they
  • are raised and purified: the first sign of which raising is, that they
  • gain some power of discerning, and some patience in submitting to
  • their true counsellors and governors; the modes of such discernment
  • forming the real "constitution" of the state, and not the titles or
  • offices of the discerned person; for it is no matter, save in degree
  • of mischief, to what office a man is appointed, if he cannot fulfil
  • it. And this brings us to the third division of our subject.
  • [110] Compare Chaucer's "villany" (clownishness).
  • "Full foul and chorlishe seemed she,
  • And eke villanous for to be,
  • And little coulde of norture
  • To worship any creature."
  • III.--GOVERNMENT BY COUNCIL.
  • This is the determination, by living authority, of the national
  • conduct to be observed under existing circumstances; and the
  • modification or enlargement, abrogation or enforcement, of the code of
  • national law according to present needs or purposes. This government
  • is necessarily always by Council, for though the authority of it may
  • be vested in one person, that person cannot form any opinion on a
  • matter of public interest but by (voluntarily or involuntarily)
  • submitting himself to the influence of others.
  • This government is always twofold--visible and invisible.
  • The visible government is that which nominally carries on the national
  • business; determines its foreign relations, raises taxes, levies
  • soldiers, fights battles, or directs that they be fought, and
  • otherwise becomes the exponent of the national fortune. The invisible
  • government is that exercised by all energetic and intelligent men,
  • each in his sphere, regulating the inner will and secret ways of the
  • people, essentially forming its character, and preparing its fate.
  • Visible governments are the toys of some nations, the diseases of
  • others, the harness of some, the burdens of the more, the necessity of
  • all. Sometimes their career is quite distinct from that of the people,
  • and to write it, as the national history, is as if one should number
  • the accidents which befall a man's weapons and wardrobe, and call the
  • list his biography. Nevertheless a truly noble and wise nation
  • necessarily has a noble and wise visible government, for its wisdom
  • issues in that conclusively. "Not out of the oak, nor out of the rock,
  • but out of the temper of man, is his polity:" where the temper
  • inclines, it inclines as Samson by his pillar, and draws all down with
  • it.
  • Visible governments are, in their agencies, capable of three pure
  • forms, and of no more than three.
  • They are either monarchies, where the authority is vested in one
  • person; oligarchies, when it is vested in a minority; or democracies,
  • when vested in a majority.
  • But these three forms are not only, in practice, variously limited and
  • combined, but capable of infinite difference in character and use,
  • receiving specific names according to their variations; which names,
  • being nowise agreed upon, nor consistently used, either in thought or
  • writing, no man can at present tell, in speaking of any kind of
  • government, whether he is understood, nor in hearing whether he
  • understands. Thus we usually call a just government by one person a
  • monarchy, and an unjust or cruel one, a tyranny; this might be
  • reasonable if it had reference to the divinity of true government; but
  • to limit the term "oligarchy" to government by a few rich people, and
  • to call government by a few wise or noble people "aristocracies," is
  • evidently absurd, unless it were proved that rich people never could
  • be wise, or noble people rich; and farther absurd because there are
  • other distinctions in character, as well as riches or wisdom (greater
  • purity of race, or strength of purpose, for instance), which may give
  • the power of government to the few. So that if we had to give names to
  • every group or kind of minority, we should have verbiage enough. But
  • there is one right name--"oligarchy."
  • So also the terms "republic" and "democracy" are confused, especially
  • in modern use; and both of them are liable to every sort of
  • misconception. A republic means, properly, a polity in which the
  • state, with its all, is at every man's service, and every man, with
  • his all, at the state's service (people are apt to lose sight of the
  • last condition); but its government may nevertheless be oligarchic
  • (consular, or decemviral, for instance), or monarchic (dictatorial).
  • But a democracy means a state in which the government rests directly
  • with the majority of the citizens. And both these conditions have been
  • judged only by such accidents and aspects of them as each of us has
  • had experience of; and sometimes both have been confused with anarchy,
  • as it is the fashion at present to talk of the "failure of republican
  • institutions in America," when there has never yet been in America any
  • such thing as an institution; neither any such thing as a res-publica,
  • but only a multitudinous res-privata; every man for himself. It is not
  • republicanism which fails now in America; it is your model science of
  • political economy, brought to its perfect practice. There you may see
  • competition, and the "law of demand and supply" (especially in paper),
  • in beautiful and unhindered operation.[111] Lust of wealth, and trust
  • in it; vulgar faith in magnitude and multitude, instead of nobleness;
  • besides that faith natural to backwoodsmen,--"lucum ligna,"--perpetual
  • self-contemplation, issuing in passionate vanity: total ignorance of
  • the finer and higher arts, and of all that they teach and bestow;[112]
  • and the discontent of energetic minds unoccupied, frantic with hope of
  • uncomprehended change, and progress they know not whither;[113] these
  • are the things that they have "failed" with in America; and yet not
  • altogether failed--it is not collapse, but collision; the greatest
  • railroad accident on record, with fire caught from the furnace, and
  • Catiline's quenching "non aquá, sed ruinâ." But I see not, in any of
  • our talk of them, justice enough done to their erratic strength of
  • purpose, nor any estimate taken of the strength of endurance of
  • domestic sorrow in what their women and children suppose a righteous
  • cause. And out of that endurance and suffering, its own fruit will be
  • born with time; and Carlyle's prophecy of them (June, 1850), as it has
  • now come true in the first clause, will in the last.
  • America too will find that caucuses, division-lists,
  • stump-oratory and speeches to Buncombe will _not_ carry men
  • to the immortal gods; that the Washington Congress, and
  • constitutional battle of Kilkenny cats is, there as here,
  • naught for such objects; quite incompetent for such; and, in
  • fine, that said sublime constitutional arrangement will
  • require to be (with terrible throes, and travail such as few
  • expect yet) remodelled, abridged, extended, suppressed; torn
  • asunder, put together again;--not without heroic labour, and
  • effort quite other than that of the Stump-Orator and the
  • Revival Preacher, one day!
  • [111] "Supply-and-demand,--alas! For what noble work was there
  • ever any audible 'demand' in that poor sense?" ("Past and
  • Present"). Nay, the demand is not loud even for ignoble
  • work. See "Average earnings of Betty Taylor," in _Times_, of
  • 4th February, of this year [1863]: "Worked from Monday
  • morning at 8 a.m., to Friday night at 5.30 p.m., for 1_s._
  • 5-1/2_d._"--Laissez faire.
  • [112] See Bacon's note in the "Advancement of Learning," on
  • "didicisse fideliter artes" (but indeed the accent had need
  • be upon "fideliter"). "It taketh away vain admiration of
  • anything, which is the root of all weakness: for all things
  • are admired either because they are new, or because they are
  • great," etc.
  • [113] Ames, by report of Waldo Emerson, expressed the popular
  • security wisely, saying, "that a monarchy is a merchantman,
  • which sails well, but will sometimes strike on a rock, and
  • go to the bottom; whilst a republic is a raft, which would
  • never sink, but then your feet are always in the water."
  • Yes, and when the four winds (your only pilots) steer
  • competitively from the four corners, [Greek: hôs d' hot'
  • opôrinos Boreês phoreêsin akanthas], perhaps the wiser
  • mariner may wish for keel and wheel again.
  • Understand, then, once for all, that no form of government, provided
  • it be a government at all, is, as such, either to be condemned or
  • praised, or contested for in anywise but by fools. But all forms of
  • government are good just so far as they attain this one vital
  • necessity of policy--that the wise and kind, few or many, shall govern
  • the unwise and unkind; and they are evil so far as they miss of this
  • or reverse it. Nor does the form in any case signify one whit, but its
  • firmness and adaptation to the need; for if there be many foolish
  • persons in a state, and few wise, then it is good that the few govern;
  • and if there be many wise and few foolish, then it is good that many
  • govern; and if many be wise, yet one wiser, then it is good that one
  • should govern; and so on. Thus, we may have "the ants' republic, and
  • the realm of bees," both good in their kind; one for groping, and the
  • other for building; and nobler still, for flying, the Ducal monarchy
  • of those
  • "Intelligent of seasons, that set forth
  • The aery caravan, high over seas."
  • Nor need we want examples, among the inferior creatures, of
  • dissoluteness, as well as resoluteness in, government. I once saw
  • democracy finely illustrated by the beetles of North Switzerland, who,
  • by universal suffrage, and elytric acclamation, one May twilight,
  • carried it that they would fly over the Lake of Zug; and flew short,
  • to the great disfigurement of the Lake of Zug--[Greek: Kantharou
  • limên]--over some leagues square, and to the close of the Cockchafer
  • democracy for that year. The old fable of the frogs and the stork
  • finely touches one form of tyranny; but truth will touch it more
  • nearly than fable, for tyranny is not complete when it is only over
  • the idle, but when it is over the laborious and the blind. This
  • description of pelicans and climbing perch which I find quoted in one
  • of our popular natural histories, out of Sir Emerson Tennent's
  • "Ceylon," comes as near as may be to the true image of the thing:--
  • Heavy rains came on, and as we stood on the high ground, we
  • observed a pelican on the margin of the shallow pool gorging
  • himself; our people went towards him, and raised a cry of
  • "Fish! fish!" We hurried down, and found numbers of fish
  • struggling upward through the grass, in the rills formed by
  • the trickling of the rain. There was scarcely water to cover
  • them, but nevertheless they made rapid progress up the bank,
  • on which our followers collected about two baskets of them.
  • They were forcing their way up the knoll, and had they not
  • been interrupted, first by the pelican, and afterwards by
  • ourselves, they would in a few minutes have gained the
  • highest point, and descended on the other side into a pool
  • which formed another portion of the tank. In going this
  • distance, however, they must have used muscular exertion
  • enough to have taken them half a mile on level ground; for
  • at these places all the cattle and wild animals of the
  • neighbourhood had latterly come to drink, so that the
  • surface was everywhere indented with footmarks, in addition
  • to the cracks in the surrounding baked mud, into which the
  • fish tumbled in their progress. In those holes which were
  • deep, and the sides perpendicular, they remained to die, and
  • were carried off by kites and crows.
  • But whether governments be bad or good, one general disadvantage seems
  • to attach to them in modern times--that they are all costly. This,
  • however, is not essentially the fault of the governments. If nations
  • choose to play at war, they will always find their governments willing
  • to lead the game, and soon coming under that term of Aristophanes,
  • "[Greek: kapêloi aspidôn]," shield-sellers. And when ([Greek: pêm'
  • epipêmati]) the shields take the form of iron ships, with apparatus
  • "for defence against liquid fire"--as I see by latest accounts they
  • are now arranging the decks in English dockyards,--they become costly
  • biers enough for the grey convoy of chief-mourner waves, wreathed with
  • funereal foam, to bear back the dead upon; the massy shoulders of
  • those corpse-bearers being intended for quite other work, and to bear
  • the living, if we would let them.
  • Nor have we the least right to complain of our governments being
  • expensive so long as we set the government to do precisely the work
  • which brings no return. If our present doctrines of political economy
  • be just, let us trust them to the utmost; take that war business out
  • of the government's hands, and test therein the principles of supply
  • and demand. Let our future sieges of Sebastopol be done by
  • contract--no capture, no pay--(I am prepared to admit that things
  • might go better so); and let us sell the commands of our prospective
  • battles, with our vicarages, to the lowest bidder; so may we have
  • cheap victories and divinity. On the other hand, if we have so much
  • suspicion of our science that we dare not trust it on military or
  • spiritual business, it would be but reasonable to try whether some
  • authoritative handling may not prosper in matters utilitarian. If we
  • were to set our governments to do useful things instead of
  • mischievous, possibly even the apparatus might in time come to be less
  • costly! The machine, applied to the building of the house, might
  • perhaps pay, when it seems not to pay, applied to pulling it down. If
  • we made in our dockyards ships to carry timber and coals, instead of
  • cannon, and with provision for brightening of domestic solid culinary
  • fire, instead of for the averting of hostile liquid fire, it might
  • have some effect on the taxes? Or if the iron bottoms were to bring us
  • home nothing better than ivory and peacocks, instead of martial glory,
  • we might at least have gayer suppers, and doors of the right material
  • for dreams after them. Or suppose that we tried the experiment on land
  • instead of water carriage; already the government, not unapproved,
  • carries letters and parcels for us; larger packages may in time
  • follow:--parcels;--even general merchandise? Why not, at last,
  • ourselves? Had the money spent in local mistakes and vain private
  • litigation, on the railroads of England, been laid out, instead, under
  • proper government restraint, on really useful railroad work, and had
  • no absurd expense been incurred in ornamenting stations, we might
  • already have had,--what ultimately will be found we must
  • have,--quadruple rails, two for passengers, and two for traffic, on
  • every great line; and we might have been carried in swift safety, and
  • watched and warded by well-paid pointsmen, for half the present fares.
  • "[Greek: hô Dêmidion, horas ta lagô' ha soi pherô]?" Suppose it should
  • turn out, finally, that a true government set to true work, instead of
  • being a costly engine, was a paying one? that your government, rightly
  • organized, instead of itself subsisting by an income tax, would
  • produce its subjects some subsistence in the shape of an income
  • dividend!--police and judges duly paid besides, only with less work
  • than the state at present provides for them.
  • A true government set to true work!--Not easily imagined, still less
  • obtained, but not beyond human hope or ingenuity. Only you will have
  • to alter your election systems somewhat, first. Not by universal
  • suffrage, nor by votes purchasable with beer, is such government to be
  • had. That is to say, not by universal equal suffrage. Every man
  • upwards of twenty, who had been convicted of no legal crime, should
  • have his say in this matter; but afterwards a louder voice, as he
  • grows older, and approves himself wiser. If he has one vote at twenty,
  • he should have two at thirty, four at forty, and ten at fifty. For
  • every one vote which he has with an income of a hundred a year, he
  • should have ten with an income of a thousand (provided you first see
  • to it that wealth is, as nature intended it to be, the reward of
  • sagacity and industry,--not of good luck in a scramble or a lottery.)
  • For every one vote which he had as subordinate in any business, he
  • should have two when he became a master; and every office and
  • authority nationally bestowed, inferring trustworthiness and
  • intellect, should have its known proportional number of votes attached
  • to it. But into the detail and working of a true system in these
  • matters we cannot now enter; we are concerned as yet with definitions
  • only, and statements of first principles, which will be established
  • now sufficiently for our purposes when we have examined the nature of
  • that form of government last on the list in the previous paper,--the
  • purely "Magistral," exciting at present its full share of public
  • notice, under its ambiguous title of "slavery."
  • I have not, however, been able to ascertain in definite terms, from
  • the declaimers against slavery, what they understand by it. If they
  • mean only the imprisonment or compulsion being in many cases highly
  • expedient, slavery, so defined, would be no evil in itself, but only
  • in its abuse; that is, when men are slaves, who should not be, or
  • masters, who should not be, or under conditions which should not be.
  • It is not, for instance, a necessary condition of slavery, nor a
  • desirable one, that parents should be separated from children, or
  • husbands from wives; but the institution of war, against which people
  • declaim with less violence, effects such separations--not unfrequently
  • in a higher permanent manner. To press a sailor, seize a white youth
  • by conscription for a soldier, or carry off a black one for a
  • labourer, may all be right, or all wrong, according to needs and
  • circumstances. It is wrong to scourge a man unnecessarily. So it is to
  • shoot him. Both must be done on occasion; and it is better and kinder
  • to flog a man to his work, than to leave him idle till he robs, and
  • flog him afterwards. The essential thing for all creatures is to be
  • made to do right; how they are made to do it--by pleasant promises, or
  • hard necessities, pathetic oratory, or the whip, is comparatively
  • immaterial. To be deceived is perhaps as incompatible with human
  • dignity as to be whipped, and I suspect the last instrument to be not
  • the worst, for the help of many individuals. The Jewish nation throve
  • under it, in the hand of a monarch reputed not unwise; it is only the
  • change of whip for scorpion which is expedient, and yet that change is
  • as likely to come to pass on the side of licence as of law; for the
  • true scorpion whips are those of the nation's pleasant vices, which
  • are to it as St. John's locusts--crown on the head, ravin in the
  • mouth, and sting in the tail. If it will not bear the rule of Athena
  • and her brother, who shepherd without smiting ([Greek: ou plêgê
  • nemontes]), Athena at last calls no more in the corners of the
  • streets; and then follows the rule of Tisiphone, who smites without
  • shepherding.
  • If, however, slavery, instead of absolute compulsion, is meant the
  • purchase, by money, of the right of compulsion, such purchase is
  • necessarily made whenever a portion of any territory is transferred,
  • for money, from one monarch to another: which has happened frequently
  • enough in history, without its being supposed that the inhabitants of
  • the districts so transferred became their slaves. In this, as in the
  • former case, the dispute seems about the fashion of the thing rather
  • than the fact of it. There are two rocks in mid-sea, on each of which,
  • neglected equally by instructive and commercial powers, a handful of
  • inhabitants live as they may. Two merchants bid for the two
  • properties, but not in the same terms. One bids for the people, buys
  • them, and sets them to work, under pain of scourge; the other bids for
  • the rock, buys it, and throws the inhabitants into the sea. The former
  • is the American, the latter the English method, of slavery; much is to
  • be said for, and something against, both, which I hope to say in due
  • time and place.
  • If, however, slavery mean not merely the purchase of the right of
  • compulsion, but the purchase of the body and soul of the creature
  • itself for money, it is not, I think, among the black races that
  • purchases of this kind are most extensively made, or that separate
  • souls of a fine make fetch the highest price. This branch of the
  • inquiry we shall have occasion also to follow out at some length; for
  • in the worst instance of the "[Greek: Biôn prasis]" we are apt to get
  • only Pyrrhon's answer--[Greek: ti phês?--epriamên se? Adêlon].
  • The fact is that slavery is not a political institution at all, but an
  • inherent, natural, and eternal inheritance of a large portion of the
  • human race--to whom the more you give of their own will, the more
  • slaves they will make themselves. In common parlance, we idly confuse
  • captivity with slavery, and are always thinking of the difference
  • between pine-trunks and cowslip bells, or between carrying wood and
  • clothes-stealing, instead of noting the far more serious differences
  • between Ariel and Caliban, and the means by which practically that
  • difference may be brought about.[114]
  • [114] The passage of Plato, referred to in note p. 280, in its
  • context, respecting the slave who, well dressed and washed,
  • aspires to the hand of his master's daughter, corresponds
  • curiously to the attack of Caliban on Prospero's cell, and
  • there is an undercurrent of meaning throughout, in the
  • "Tempest" as well as in the "Merchant of Venice"; referring
  • in this case to government, as in that to commerce. Miranda
  • ("the wonderful," so addressed first by Ferdinand, "Oh, you
  • wonder!") corresponds to Homer's Arete: Ariel and Caliban
  • are respectively the spirits of freedom and mechanical
  • labour. Prospero ("for hope"), a true governor, opposed to
  • Sycorax, the mother of slavery, her name, "Swine-raven,"
  • indicating at once brutality and deathfulness; hence the
  • line--"As wicked dew as e'er my mother brushed, with raven's
  • feather,"--etc. For all dreams of Shakespeare, as those of
  • true and strong men must be, are "[Greek: phantasmata theia,
  • kai skiai tôn ontôn]," phantasms of God, and shadows of
  • things that are. We hardly tell our children, willingly, a
  • fable with no purport in it; yet we think God sends His best
  • messengers only to say fairy tales to us, all fondness and
  • emptiness. The "Tempest" is just like a grotesque in a rich
  • missal, "clasped where paynims pray." Ariel is the spirit of
  • true liberty, in early stages of human society oppressed by
  • ignorance and wild tyranny; venting groans as fast as
  • mill-wheels strike; in shipwreck of states, fearful; so that
  • "all but mariners plunge in the brine, and quit the vessel,
  • then all afire with me," yet having in itself the will and
  • sweetness of truest peace, whence that is especially called
  • "Ariel's" song, "Come unto these yellow sands"--(fenceless,
  • and countless--changing with the sweep of the sea--"vaga
  • arena." Compare Horace's opposition of the sea-sand to the
  • dust of the grave: "numero carentis"--"exigui;" and again
  • compare "animo rotundum percurrisse" with "put a girdle
  • round the earth")--"and then take hands: court'sied when you
  • have, and kiss'd,--the wild waves whist:" (mind it is
  • "courtesia," not "curtsey") and read "quiet" for "whist" if
  • you want the full sense. Then may you indeed foot it featly,
  • and sweet spirits bear the burden for you--with watch in the
  • night, and call in early morning. The power of liberty in
  • elemental transformation follows--"Full fathom five thy
  • father lies, of his bones are coral made." Then, giving rest
  • after labour, it "fetches dew from the still-vex'd
  • Bermoothes, and, with a charm joined to their suffered
  • labour, leaves men asleep." Snatching away the feast of the
  • cruel, it seems to them as a harpy, followed by the utterly
  • vile, who cannot see it in any shape, but to whom it is the
  • picture of nobody, it still gives shrill harmony to their
  • false and mocking catch, "Thought is free," but leads them
  • into briars and foul places, and at last hollas the hounds
  • upon them. Minister of fate against the great criminal, it
  • joins itself with the "incensed seas and shores"--the sword
  • that layeth at it cannot hold, and may, "with bemocked-at
  • stabs as soon kill the still-closing waters, as diminish one
  • dowle that's in my plume." As the guide and aid of true
  • love, it is always called by Prospero "fine" (the French
  • "fine"--not the English), or "delicate"--another long note
  • would be needed to explain all the meaning in this word.
  • Lastly, its work done, and war, it resolves itself to the
  • elements. The intense significance of the last song, "Where
  • the bee sucks," I will examine in its due place. The types
  • of slavery in Caliban are more palpable, and need not be
  • dwelt on now: though I will notice them also, severally, in
  • their proper places;--the heart of his slavery is in his
  • worship: "That's a brave god, and bears celestial liquor."
  • But, in illustration of the sense in which the Latin
  • "benignus" and "malignus," are to be coupled with Eleutheria
  • and Douleia, not that Caliban's torment is always the
  • physical reflection of his own nature--"cramps" and
  • "side-stitches that shall pen thy breath up"--"thou shalt be
  • pinched as thick as honeycomb:" the whole nature of slavery
  • being one cramp and cretinous contraction. Fancy this of
  • Ariel! You may fetter him, but yet set no mark on him; you
  • may put him to hard work and far journey, but you cannot
  • give him a cramp.
  • Of Shakespeare's names I will afterwards speak at more
  • length: they are curiously--often barbarously--mixed out of
  • various traditions and languages. Three of the clearest in
  • meaning have been already noticed. Desdemona, "[Greek:
  • dysdaimonia]," "miserable fortune," is also plain enough.
  • Othello is, I believe, "the careful"; all the calamity of
  • the tragedy arising from the single flaw and error in his
  • magnificently collected strength. Ophelia,
  • "serviceableness," the true lost wife of Hamlet, is marked
  • as having a Greek name by that last word of her, where her
  • gentle preciousness is opposed to the uselessness of the
  • churlish clergy--"A ministering angel shall my sister be
  • when thou liest howling." Hamlet is, I believe, connected in
  • some way with "homely," the entire event of the tragedy
  • turning on betrayal of home duty. Hermione ([Greek: herma]),
  • "pillar-like" ([Greek: hê eidos eche chrysês Aphroditês]).
  • Titania ([Greek: titênê]), "the queen;" Benedict and
  • Beatrice, "blessed and blessing;" Valentine and Proteus,
  • enduring (or strong) (valens) and changeful. Iago and
  • Iachimo have evidently the same root--probably the Spanish
  • Iago, Jacob, "the supplanter." Leonatus, and other such
  • names are interpreted, or played with, in the plays
  • themselves. For the interpretation of Sycorax, and reference
  • to her raven's feather, I am indebted to Mr. John R. Wise.
  • I should dwell, even in these prefatory papers, at somewhat more
  • length on this matter, had not all I would say, been said (already in
  • vain) by Carlyle, in the first of the "Latter-Day Pamphlets," which I
  • commend to the reader's gravest reading: together with that as much
  • neglected, and still more immediately needed, on model prisons, and
  • with the great chapter on "Permanence" (fifth of the last section of
  • "Past and Present"), which sums, what is known, and foreshadows,--or
  • rather fore-lights, all that is to be learned, of National Discipline.
  • I have only here farther to examine the nature of one world-wide and
  • everlasting form of slavery, wholesome in use, deadly in abuse--the
  • service of the rich by the poor.
  • As in all previous discussions of our subject, we must study this
  • relation in its simplest elements in order to reach its first
  • principles. The simplest state of it is, then, this:[115] a wise and
  • provident person works much, consumes little, and lays by store; an
  • improvident person works little, consumes all the produce, and lays by
  • no store. Accident interrupts the daily work, or renders it less
  • productive; the idle person must then starve, or be supported by the
  • provident one,--who, having him thus at his mercy, may either refuse
  • to maintain him altogether, or, which will evidently be more to his
  • own interest, say to him, "I will maintain you, indeed, but you shall
  • now work hard, instead of indolently, and instead of being allowed to
  • lay by what you save, as you might have done, had you remained
  • independent, I will take all the surplus. You would not lay it up
  • yourself; it is wholly your own fault that has thrown you into my
  • power, and I will force you to work, or starve; yet you shall have no
  • profit, only your daily bread." This mode of treatment has now become
  • so universal that it is supposed the only natural--nay, the only
  • possible one; and the market wages are calmly defined by economists as
  • "the sum which will maintain the labourer."
  • [115] In the present general examination I concede so much to
  • ordinary economists as to ignore all innocent poverty. I
  • assume poverty to be always criminal; the conceivable
  • exceptions we will examine afterwards.
  • The power of the provident person to do this is only checked by the
  • correlative power of some neighbour of similarly frugal habits, who
  • says to the labourer--"I will give you a little more than my provident
  • friend:--come and work for me." The power of the provident over the
  • improvident depends thus primarily on their relative numbers;
  • secondarily, on the modes of agreement of the adverse parties with
  • each other. The level of wages is a variable function of the number of
  • provident and idle persons in the world, of the enmity between them as
  • classes, and of the agreement between those of the same class. It
  • depends, from beginning to end, on moral conditions.
  • Supposing the rich to be entirely selfish, it is always for their
  • interest that the poor should be as numerous as they can employ and
  • restrain. For, granting the entire population no larger than the
  • ground can easily maintain,--that the classes are stringently
  • divided,--and that there is sense or strength of hand enough with the
  • rich to secure obedience; then, if nine-tenths of a nation are poor,
  • the remaining tenth have the service of nine persons each;[116] but,
  • if eight-tenths are poor, only of four each; if seven-tenths are poor,
  • of two and a third each; but, practically if the rich strive always to
  • obtain more power over the poor, instead of to raise them,--and if, on
  • the other hand, the poor become continually more vicious and numerous,
  • through neglect and oppression--though the range of the power of the
  • rich increases, its tenure becomes less secure; until, at last, the
  • measure of iniquity being full, revolution, civil war, or the
  • subjection of the state to a healthier or stronger one, closes the
  • moral corruption and industrial disease.
  • [116] I say nothing yet of the quality of the servants, which,
  • nevertheless, is the gist of the business. Will you have
  • Paul Veronese to paint your ceiling, or the plumber from
  • over the way? Both will work for the same money; Paul, if
  • anything, a little cheaper of the two, if you keep him in
  • good humour; only you have to discern him first, which will
  • need eyes.
  • It is rare, however, that things come to this extremity. Kind persons
  • among the rich, and wise among the poor, modify the connexion of the
  • classes: the efforts made to raise and relieve on the one side, and
  • the success and honest toil on the other, bind and blend the orders of
  • society into the confused tissue of half-felt obligation,
  • sullenly-rendered obedience, and variously-directed, or mis-directed,
  • toil, which form the warp of daily life. But this great law rules all
  • the wild design of the weaving; that success (while society is guided
  • by laws of competition) signifies always so much victory over your
  • neighbour as to obtain the direction of his work, and to take the
  • profits of it. This is the real source of all great riches. No man can
  • become largely rich by his personal toil.[117] The work of his own
  • hands, wisely directed, will indeed always maintain himself and his
  • family, and make fitting provision for his age. But it is only by the
  • discovery of some method of taxing the labour of others that he can
  • become opulent. Every increase of his capital enables him to extend
  • this taxation more widely; that is, to invest larger funds in the
  • maintenance of his labourers--to direct, accordingly, vaster and yet
  • vaster masses of labour; and to appropriate its profits. There is much
  • confusion of idea on the subject of this appropriation. It is, of
  • course, the interest of the employer to disguise it from the persons
  • employed; and for his own comfort and complacency he often desires no
  • less to disguise it from himself. And it is matter of much doubt with
  • me, how far the foolish arguments used habitually on this subject are
  • indeed the honest expressions of foolish convictions,--or rather (as I
  • am sometimes forced to conclude from the irritation with which they
  • are advanced) are resolutely dishonest, wilful sophisms, arranged so
  • as to mask to the last moment the real state of economy, and future
  • duties of men. By taking a simple example, and working it thoroughly
  • out, the subject may be rescued from all but determined misconception.
  • [117] By his heart he may; but only when its produce, or the
  • sight or hearing of it, becomes a subject of dispute, so as
  • to enable the artist to tax the labour of multitudes highly,
  • in exchange for his own.
  • Let us imagine a society of peasants, living on a river-shore, exposed
  • to destructive inundation at somewhat extended intervals; and that
  • each peasant possesses of this good, but imperilled ground, more than
  • he needs to cultivate for immediate subsistence. We will assume
  • farther (and with too great probability of justice) that the greater
  • part of them indolently keep in tillage just as much land as supplies
  • them with daily food;--that they leave their children idle and
  • untaught; and take no precautions against the rise of the stream. But
  • one of them (we will say only one, for the sake of greater clearness)
  • cultivates carefully all the ground of his estate; makes his children
  • work hard and healthily; uses his spare time and theirs in building a
  • rampart against the river; and at the end of some years has in his
  • storehouses large reserves of food and clothing, and in his stables a
  • well-tended breed of cattle.
  • The torrent rises at last--sweeps away the harvests and many of the
  • cottages of the careless peasantry, and leaves them destitute. They
  • naturally come for help to the provident one, whose fields are
  • unwasted and whose granaries are full. He has the right to refuse it
  • them; no one disputes his right. But he will probably not refuse it;
  • it is not his interest to do so, even were he entirely selfish and
  • cruel. The only question with him will be on what terms his aid is to
  • be granted.
  • Clearly not on terms of mere charity. To maintain his neighbours in
  • idleness would be his ruin and theirs. He will require work from them
  • in exchange for their maintenance; and whether in kindness or cruelty,
  • all the work they can give. Not now the three or four hours they were
  • wont to spend on their own land, but the eight or ten hours they ought
  • to have spent. But how will he apply this labour? The men are now his
  • slaves--nothing less. On pain of starvation, he can force them to work
  • in the manner and to the end he chooses. And it is by his wisdom in
  • this choice that the worthiness of his mastership is proved, or its
  • unworthiness. Evidently he must first set them to bank out the water
  • in some temporary way, and to get their ground cleansed and resown;
  • else, in any case, their continued maintenance will be impossible.
  • That done, and while he has still to feed them, suppose he makes them
  • raise a secure rampart for their own ground against all future flood,
  • and rebuild their houses in safer places, with the best material they
  • can find; being allowed time out of their working hours to fetch such
  • material from a distance. And for the food and clothing advanced, he
  • takes security in land that as much shall be returned at a convenient
  • period.
  • At the end of a few years, we may conceive this security redeemed, and
  • the debt paid. The prudent peasant has sustained no loss; but is no
  • richer than he was, and has had all his trouble for nothing. But he
  • has enriched his neighbours materially; bettered their houses, secured
  • their land, and rendered them, in worldly matters, equal to himself.
  • In all true and final sense, he has been throughout their lord and
  • king.
  • We will next trace his probable line of conduct, presuming his object
  • to be exclusively the increase of his own fortune. After roughly
  • recovering and cleansing the ground, he allows the ruined peasantry
  • only to build huts upon it, such as he thinks protective enough from
  • the weather to keep them in working health. The rest of their time he
  • occupies first in pulling down and rebuilding on a magnificent scale
  • his own house, and in adding large dependencies to it. This done, he
  • follows the example of the first great Hebrew financier, and in
  • exchange for his continued supply of corn, buys as much of his
  • neighbours! land, as he thinks he can superintend the management of;
  • and makes the former owners securely embank and protect the ceded
  • portion. By this arrangement he leaves to a certain number of the
  • peasantry only as much ground as will just maintain them in their
  • existing numbers: as the population increases, he takes the extra
  • hands, who cannot be maintained on the narrow estates, for his own
  • servants; employs some to cultivate the ground he has bought, giving
  • them of its produce merely enough for subsistence; with the surplus,
  • which, under his energetic and careful superintendence, will be large,
  • he supports a train of servants for state, and a body of workmen, whom
  • he educates in ornamental arts. He now can splendidly decorate his
  • house, lay out its grounds magnificently, and richly supply his table,
  • and that of his household and retinue. And thus, without any abuse of
  • right, we should find established all the phenomena of poverty and
  • riches, which (it is supposed necessarily) accompany modern
  • civilization. In one part of the district, we should have unhealthy
  • land, miserable dwellings and half-starved poor; in another, a
  • well-ordered estate, well-fed servants, and refined conditions of
  • highly-educated and luxurious life.
  • I have put the two cases in simplicity, and to some extremity. But
  • though in more complex and qualified operation, all the relations of
  • society are but the expansion of these two typical sequences of
  • conduct and result. I do not say, observe, that the first procedure is
  • entirely right; still less, that the second is wholly wrong. Servants
  • and artists, and splendour of habitation and retinue, have all their
  • use, propriety and office. I only wish the reader to understand
  • clearly what they cost; that the condition of having them is the
  • subjection to you of a certain number of imprudent or unfortunate
  • persons (or, it may be, more fortunate than their master), over whose
  • destinies you exercise a boundless control. "Riches" mean eternally
  • and essentially this; and may heaven send at last a time when those
  • words of our best-reputed economist shall be true, and we shall indeed
  • "all know what it is to be rich;" that is to be slave-master over
  • farthest earth, and over all ways and thoughts of men. Every operative
  • you employ is your true servant: distant or near, subject to your
  • immediate orders, or ministering to your widely-communicated
  • caprice--for the pay he stipulates, or the price he tempts,--all are
  • alike under this great dominion of the gold. The milliner who makes
  • the dress is as much a servant (more so, in that she uses more
  • intelligence in the service) as the maid who puts it on; the carpenter
  • who smoothes the door, as the footman who opens it; the tradesmen who
  • supply the table, as the labourers and sailors who supply the
  • tradesmen. Why speak of these lower services? Painters and singers
  • (whether of note or rhyme), jesters and story-tellers, moralists,
  • historians, priests--so far as these, in any degree, paint, or sing,
  • or tell their tale, or charm their charm, or "perform" their rite, for
  • pay, in so far they are all slaves; abject utterly, if the service be
  • for pay only; abject less and less in proportion to the degrees of
  • love and wisdom which enter into their duty, or can enter into it,
  • according as their function is to do the bidding and the work of a
  • man;--or to amuse, tempt, and deceive a child.
  • There may be thus, and, to a certain extent, there always is, a
  • government of the rich by the poor, as of the poor by the rich; but
  • the latter is the prevailing and necessary one, and it consists,
  • observe, of two distinct functions,--the collection of the profits of
  • labour from those who would have misused them, and the administration
  • of those profits for the service either of the same person in future,
  • or of others; or, as is more frequently the case in modern times, for
  • the service of the collector himself.
  • The examination of these various modes of collection and use of riches
  • will form the third branch of our future inquiries; but the key to the
  • whole subject lies in the clear understanding of the difference
  • between selfish and unselfish expenditure. It is not easy, by any
  • course of reasoning, to enforce this on the generally unwilling
  • hearer; yet the definition of unselfish expenditure is brief and
  • simple. It is expenditure which if you are a capitalist, does not pay
  • you, but pays somebody else; and if you are a consumer, does not
  • please you, but pleases somebody else. Take one special instance, in
  • further illustration of the general type given above. I did not invent
  • that type, but spoke of a real river, and of real peasantry, the
  • languid and sickly race which inhabits, or haunts--for they are often
  • more like spectres than living men--the thorny desolation on the banks
  • of the Arve. Some years ago, a society formed at Geneva offered to
  • embank the river, for the ground which would have been recovered by
  • the operation; but the offer was refused by the (then Sardinian)
  • government. The capitalists saw that this expenditure would have
  • "paid," if the ground saved from the river was to be theirs. But if
  • when the offer that had this aspect of profit was refused, they had
  • nevertheless persisted in the plan and, merely taking security for the
  • return of their outlay, lent the funds for the work, and thus saved a
  • whole race of human souls from perishing in a pestiferous fen (as, I
  • presume, some among them would, at personal risk, have dragged any one
  • drowning creature out of the current of the stream, and not expected
  • payment therefor), such expenditure would have precisely corresponded
  • to the use of his power made, in the first instance, by our supposed
  • richest peasant--it would have been the king's, of grace, instead of
  • the usurer's, for gain.
  • "Impossible, absurd, Utopian!" exclaim nine-tenths of the few readers
  • whom these words may find. No, good reader, this is not Utopian: but I
  • will tell you what would have seemed, if we had not seen it, Utopian
  • on the side of evil instead of good: that ever men should have come to
  • value their money so much more than their lives, that if you call upon
  • them to become soldiers, and take chance of bullet, for their pride's
  • sake, they will do it gaily, without thinking twice; but if you ask
  • them for their country's sake to spend a hundred pounds without
  • security of getting back a hundred-and-five[118] they will laugh in
  • your face.
  • [118] I have not hitherto touched on the subject of interest of
  • money; it is too complex; and must be reserved for its
  • proper place in the body of the work. (I should be glad if a
  • writer, who sent me some valuable notes on this subject, and
  • asked me to return a letter which I still keep at his
  • service, would send me his address.) The definition of
  • interest (apart from compensation for risk) is, "the
  • exponent of the comfort of accomplished labour, separated
  • from its power;" the power being what is lent: and the
  • French economists who have maintained the entire illegality
  • of interest are wrong; yet by no means so curiously or
  • wildly wrong as the English and French ones opposed to them,
  • whose opinions have been collected by Dr. Whewell at page 41
  • of his Lectures; it never seeming to occur to the mind of
  • the compiler any more than to the writers whom he quotes,
  • that it is quite possible, and even (according to Jewish
  • proverb) prudent, for men to hoard, as ants and mice do, for
  • use, not usury; and lay by something for winter nights, in
  • the expectation of rather sharing than lending the
  • scrapings. My Savoyard squirrels would pass a pleasant time
  • of it under the snow-laden pine-branches, if they always
  • declined to economize because no one would pay them interest
  • on nuts.
  • Not but that also this game of life-giving-and-taking is, in the end,
  • somewhat more costly than other forms of play might be. Rifle practice
  • is, indeed, a not unhealthy pastime, and a feather on the top of the
  • head is a pleasing appendage; but while learning the stops and
  • fingering of the sweet instrument, does no one ever calculate the cost
  • of an overture? What melody does Tityrus meditate on his tenderly
  • spiral pipe? The leaden seed of it, broad cast, true conical "Dents de
  • Lion" seed--needing leas allowance for the wind than is usual with
  • that kind of herb--what crop are you likely to have of it? Suppose,
  • instead of this volunteer marching and countermarching, you were to do
  • a little volunteer ploughing and counterploughing? It is more
  • difficult to do it straight: the dust of the earth, so disturbed, is
  • more grateful than for merely rhythmic footsteps. Golden cups, also,
  • given for good ploughing would be more suitable in colour (ruby glass,
  • for the wine which "giveth his colour" on the ground, as well as in
  • the cup, might be fitter for the rifle prize in the ladies' hands);
  • or, conceive a little volunteer exercise with the spade, other than
  • such as is needed for moat and breastwork, or even for the burial of
  • the fruit of the leaden avena-seed, subject to the shrill Lemures'
  • criticism--
  • "Wer hat das Haus so schlecht gebaut?"
  • If you were to embank Lincolnshire now,--more stoutly against the sea?
  • or strip the peat of Solway, or plant Plinlimmon moors with
  • larch--then, in due hour of year, some amateur reaping and threshing?
  • "Nay, we reap and thresh by steam in these advanced days."
  • I know it, my wise and economical friends. The stout arms God gave
  • you to win your bread by, you would fain shoot your neighbours--and
  • God's sweet singers--with;[119] then you invoke the friends to your
  • farm-service, and--
  • "When young and old come forth to play
  • On a sulphurous holiday,
  • Tell how the darling goblin sweat
  • (His feast of cinders duly set),
  • And belching night, where breathed the morn.
  • His shadowy flail hath threshed the corn
  • That ten day-labourers could not end."
  • But we will press the example closer. On a green knoll above that
  • plain of the Arve, between Cluses and Bonneville, there was, in the
  • year 1860, a cottage, inhabited by a well-doing family--man and wife,
  • three children, and the grandmother. I call it a cottage but, in
  • truth, it was a large chimney on the ground, wide at the bottom (so
  • that the family might live round the fire), with one broken window in
  • it, and an unclosing door. The family, I say, was "well-doing," at
  • least, it was hopeful and cheerful; the wife healthy, the children,
  • for Savoyards, pretty and active, but the husband threatened with
  • decline, from exposure under the cliffs of the Mont Vergi by day, and
  • to draughts between every plank of his chimney in the frosty nights.
  • "Why could he not plaster the chinks?" asks the practical reader. For
  • the same reason that your child cannot wash its face and hands till
  • you have washed them many a day for it, and will not wash them when it
  • can, till you force it.
  • [119] Compare Chaucer's feeling respecting birds (from Canace's
  • falcon, to the nightingale, singing "Domine labia "--to the
  • Lord of Love) with the usual modern British sentiments on
  • this subject. Or even Cowley's:--
  • "What prince's choir of music can excel
  • That which within this shade does dwell.
  • To which we nothing pay, or give,
  • They, like all other poets, live
  • Without reward, or thanks for their obliging pains!
  • 'Tis well if they became not prey."
  • Yes; it is better than well; particularly since the seed
  • sown by the wayside has been protected by the peculiar
  • appropriation of part of the church rates in our country
  • parishes. See the remonstrance from a "Country Parson," in
  • the _Times_ of June 4th (or 5th; the letter is dated June
  • 3rd, 1862):--"I have heard at a vestry meeting a good deal
  • of higgling over a few shillings' outlay in cleaning the
  • church; but I have never heard any dissatisfaction expressed
  • on account of the part of the rate which is invested in
  • fifty or 100 dozens of birds' heads."
  • I passed this cottage often in my walks, had its window and door
  • mended, sometimes mended also a little the meal of sour bread and
  • broth, and generally got kind greeting and smile from the face of
  • young or old; which greeting, this year, narrowed itself into the
  • half-recognizing stare of the elder child and the old woman's tears;
  • for the father and mother were both dead,--one of sickness, the other
  • of sorrow. It happened that I passed not alone, but with a companion,
  • a practised English joiner, who, while these people were dying of
  • cold, had been employed from six in the morning to six of the evening
  • for two months, in fitting the panels without nails, of a single door
  • in a large house in London. Three days of his work taken, at the right
  • time, from the oak panels, and applied to the larch timbers, would
  • have saved these Savoyards' lives. He would have been maintained
  • equally (I suppose him equally paid for his work by the owner of the
  • greater house, only the work not consumed selfishly on his own walls;)
  • and the two peasants, and eventually, probably their children, saved.
  • There are, therefore, let me finally enforce and leave with the reader
  • this broad conclusion,--three things to be considered in employing any
  • poor person. It is not enough to give him employment. You must employ
  • him first to produce useful things; secondly, of the several (suppose
  • equally useful) things he can equally well produce, you must set him
  • to make that which will cause him to lead the healthiest life; lastly,
  • of the things produced, it remains a question of wisdom and conscience
  • how much you are to take yourself, and how much to leave to others. A
  • large quantity, remember, unless you destroy it, must always be so
  • left at one time or another; the only questions you have to decide
  • are, not what you will give, and what you will keep, but when, and
  • how, and to whom, you will give. The natural law of human life is, of
  • course, that in youth a man shall labour and lay by store for his old
  • age, and when age comes, should use what he has laid by, gradually
  • slackening his toil, and allowing himself more frank use of his store,
  • taking care always to leave himself as much as will surely suffice for
  • him beyond any possible length of life. What he has gained, or by
  • tranquil and unanxious toil, continues to gain, more than is enough
  • for his own need, he ought so to administer, while he yet lives, as to
  • see the good of it again beginning in other hands; for thus he has
  • himself the greatest sum of pleasure from it, and faithfully uses his
  • sagacity in its control. Whereas most men, it appears, dislike the
  • sight of their fortunes going out into service again, and say to
  • themselves,--"I can indeed nowise prevent this money from falling at
  • last into the hands of others, nor hinder the good of it, such as it
  • is, from becoming theirs, not mine; but at least let a merciful death
  • save me from being a witness of their satisfaction; and may God so far
  • be gracious to me as to let no good come of any of this money of mine
  • before my eyes." Supposing this feeling unconquerable, the safest way
  • of rationally indulging it would be for the capitalist at once to
  • spend all his fortune on himself, which might actually, in many cases,
  • be quite the rightest as well as the pleasantest thing to do, if he
  • had just tastes and worthy passions. But, whether for himself only, or
  • through the hands and for the sake of others also, the law of wise
  • life is, that the maker of the money should also be the spender of it,
  • and spend it, approximately, all, before he dies; so that his true
  • ambition as an economist should be, to die, not as rich, but as poor,
  • as possible, calculating the ebb tide of possession in true and calm
  • proportion to the ebb tide of life. Which law, checking the wing of
  • accumulative desire in the mid-volley,[120] and leading to peace of
  • possession and fulness of fruition in old age, is also wholesome in
  • that by the freedom of gift, together with present help and counsel,
  • it at once endears and dignifies age in the sight of youth, which then
  • no longer strips the bodies of the dead, but receives the grace of the
  • living. Its chief use would (or will be, for men are indeed capable of
  • attaining to this much use for their reason), that some temperance and
  • measure will be put to the acquisitiveness of commerce.[121] For as
  • things stand, a man holds it his duty to be temperate in his food, and
  • of his body, but for no duty to be temperate in his riches, and of his
  • mind. He sees that he ought not to waste his youth and his flesh for
  • luxury; but he will waste his age, and his soul, for money, and think
  • it no wrong, nor the delirium tremens of the intellect any evil. But
  • the law of life is, that a man should fix the sum he desires to make
  • annually, as the food he desires to eat daily; and stay when he has
  • reached the limit, refusing increase of business, and leaving it to
  • others, so obtaining due freedom of time for better thoughts. How the
  • gluttony of business is punished, a bill of health for the principals
  • of the richest city houses, issued annually, would show in a
  • sufficiently impressive manner.
  • [120] [Greek: kai penian hêgoumenous heinai mê to tên ousian
  • elattô poiein, alla to tên aplêstian pleiô.]--"Laws," v. 8.
  • Read the context and compare. "He who spends for all that is
  • noble, and gains by nothing but what is just, will hardly be
  • notably wealthy, or distressfully poor."--"Laws," v. 42.
  • [121] The fury of modern trade arises chiefly out of the
  • possibility of making sudden fortune by largeness of
  • transaction, and accident of discovery or contrivance.
  • I have no doubt that the final interest of every nation
  • is to check the action of these commercial lotteries. But
  • speculation absolute, unconnected with commercial effort, is
  • an unmitigated evil in a state, and the root of countless
  • evils beside.
  • I know, of course, that these statements will be received by the
  • modern merchant, as an active Border rider of the sixteenth century
  • would have heard of its being proper for men of the Marches to get
  • their living by the spade instead of the spur. But my business is only
  • to state veracities and necessities; I neither look for the acceptance
  • of the one, nor promise anything for the nearness of the other. Near
  • or distant, the day will assuredly come when the merchants of a state
  • shall be its true "ministers of exchange," its porters, in the double
  • sense of carriers and gate-keepers, bringing all lands into frank and
  • faithful communication, and knowing for their master of guild, Hermes
  • the herald, instead of Mercury the gain-guarder.
  • And now, finally, for immediate rule to whom it concerns.
  • The distress of any population means that they need food, houseroom,
  • clothes, and fuel. You can never, therefore, be wrong in employing any
  • labourer to produce food, houseroom, clothes, or fuel: but you are
  • always wrong if you employ him to produce nothing (for then some other
  • labourer must be worked double time to feed him); and you are
  • generally wrong, at present, if you employ him (unless he can do
  • nothing else) to produce works of art, or luxuries; because modern art
  • is mostly on a false basis, and modern luxury is criminally great.[122]
  • [122] It is especially necessary that the reader should keep his
  • mind fixed on the methods of consumption and destruction, as
  • the true sources of national poverty. Men are apt to watch
  • rather the exchanges in a state than its damages; but the
  • exchanges are only of importance so far as they bring about
  • these last. A large number of the purchases made by the
  • richer classes are mere forms of interchange of unused
  • property, wholly without effect on national prosperity. It
  • matters nothing to the state, whether if a china pipkin be
  • rated as worth a hundred pounds, A has the pipkin, and B the
  • pounds, or A the pounds and B the pipkin. But if the pipkin
  • is pretty, and A or B breaks it, there is national loss; not
  • otherwise. So again, when the loss has really taken place,
  • no shifting of the shoulders that bear it will do away with
  • the fact of it. There is an intensely ludicrous notion in
  • the public mind respecting the abolishment of debt by
  • denying it. When a debt is denied, the lender loses instead
  • of the borrower, that is all; the loss is precisely,
  • accurately, everlastingly the same. The Americans borrow
  • money to spend in blowing up their own houses. They deny
  • their debt; by one third already, gold being at fifty
  • premium; and will probably deny it wholly. That merely means
  • that the holders of the notes are to be the losers instead
  • of the issuers. The quantity of loss is precisely equal, and
  • irrevocable; it is the quantity of human industry spent in
  • explosion, plus the quantity of goods exploded. Honour only
  • decides who shall pay the sum lost, not whether it is to be
  • paid or not. Paid it must be and to the uttermost farthing.
  • The way to produce more food is mainly to bring in fresh ground, and
  • increase facilities of carriage;--to break rock, exchange earth, drain
  • the moist, and water the dry, to mend roads, and build harbours of
  • refuge. Taxation thus spent will annihilate taxation, but spent in
  • war, it annihilates revenue.
  • The way to produce houseroom is to apply your force first to the
  • humbler dwellings. When your bricklayers are out of employ, do not
  • build splendid new streets, but better the old ones: send your
  • paviours and slaters to the poorest villages, and see that your poor
  • are healthily lodged before you try your hand on stately architecture.
  • You will find its stateliness rise better under the trowel afterwards;
  • and we do not yet build so well as that we need hasten to display our
  • skill to future ages. Had the labour which has decorated the Houses of
  • Parliament filled, instead, rents in walls and roofs throughout the
  • county of Middlesex; and our deputies met to talk within massive walls
  • that would have needed no stucco for five hundred years,--the
  • decoration might have been better afterwards, and the talk now. And
  • touching even our highly conscientious church building, it may be well
  • to remember that in the best days of church plans, their masons called
  • themselves "logeurs du bon Dieu;" and that since, according to the
  • most trusted reports, God spends a good deal of His time in cottages
  • as well as in churches, He might perhaps like to be a little better
  • lodged there also.
  • The way to get more clothes is,--not necessarily, to get more cotton.
  • There were words written twenty years ago which would have saved many
  • of us some shivering had they been minded in time. Shall we read them?
  • "The Continental people, it would seem, are 'importing our machinery,
  • beginning to spin cotton and manufacture for themselves, to cut us out
  • of this market and then out of that!' Sad news indeed; but
  • irremediable;--by no means. The saddest news is, that we should find
  • our National Existence, as I sometimes hear it said, depend on selling
  • manufactured cotton at a farthing an ell cheaper than any other
  • People. A most narrow stand for a great Nation to base itself on! A
  • stand which, with all the Corn-Law Abrogations conceivable, I do not
  • think will be capable of enduring.
  • "My friends, suppose we quitted that stand; suppose we came honestly
  • down from it and said: 'This is our minimum cotton-prices. We care
  • not, for the present, to make cotton any cheaper. Do you, if it seem
  • so blessed to you, make cotton cheaper. Fill your lungs with
  • cotton-fuzz, your hearts with copperas-fumes, with rage and mutiny;
  • become ye the general gnomes of Europe, slaves of the lamp!' I admire
  • a Nation which fancies it will die if it do not undersell all other
  • Nations, to the end of the world. Brothers, we will cease to
  • _under_sell them; we will be content to _equal_-sell them; to be happy
  • selling equally with them! I do not see the use of underselling them.
  • Cotton-cloth is already two-pence a yard or lower; and yet bare backs
  • were never more numerous among us. Let inventive men cease to spend
  • their existence incessantly contriving how cotton can be made cheaper;
  • and try to invent, a little, how cotton at its present cheapness could
  • be somewhat justlier divided among us. Let inventive men consider,
  • Whether the Secret of this Universe, and of Man's Life there, does,
  • after all, as we rashly fancy it, consist in making money?... With a
  • Hell which means--'Failing to make money,' I do not think there is any
  • Heaven possible that would suit one well; nor so much as an Earth that
  • can be habitable long! In brief, all this Mammon-Gospel of
  • Supply-and-demand, Competition, Laissez-faire, and Devil take the
  • hindmost" (foremost, is it not, rather, Mr. Carlyle?) "begins to be
  • one of the shabbiest Gospels ever preached." (In the matter of
  • clothes, decidedly.) The way to produce more fuel is first to make
  • your coal mines safer, by sinking more shafts; then set all your
  • convicts to work in them, and if, as is to be hoped, you succeed in
  • diminishing the supply of that sort of labourer, consider what means
  • there may be, first of growing forest where its growth will improve
  • climate; then of splintering the forests which now make continents of
  • fruitful land pathless and poisonous, into faggots for fire;--so
  • gaining at once dominion sunwards and icewards. Your steam power has
  • been given you (you will find eventually) for work such as that; and
  • not for excursion trains, to give the labourer a moment's breath, at
  • the peril of his breath for ever, from amidst the cities which you
  • have crushed into masses of corruption. When you know how to build
  • cities, and how to rule them, you will be able to breathe in their
  • streets, and the "excursion" will be the afternoon's walk or game in
  • the fields round them. Long ago, Claudian's peasant of Verona knew,
  • and we must yet learn, in his fashion, the difference between via and
  • vita. But nothing of this work will pay.
  • No; no more than it pays to dust your rooms or wash your doorsteps. It
  • will pay; not at first in currency, but in that which is the end and
  • the source of currency,--in life (and in currency richly afterwards).
  • It will pay in that which is more than life,--in "God's first
  • creature, which was light," whose true price has not yet been
  • reckoned in any currency, and yet into the image of which all wealth,
  • one way or other, must be cast. For your riches must either as the
  • lightning, which,
  • "begot but in a cloud,
  • Though shining bright, and speaking loud,
  • Whilst it begins, concludes its violent race,
  • And, where it gilds, it wounds the place;"
  • or else as the lightning of the sacred sign, which shines from one
  • part of the heaven to the other. There is no other choice; you must
  • either take dust for deity, spectre for possession, fettered dream for
  • life, and for epitaph, this reversed verse of the great Hebrew hymn of
  • economy (Psalm cxii.):--"He hath gathered together, he hath stripped
  • the poor, his iniquity remaineth for ever." Or else, having the sun
  • for justice to shine on you, and the sincere substance of good in your
  • possession, and the pure law and liberty of life within you, leave men
  • to write this better legend over your grave: "He hath dispersed
  • abroad. He hath given to the poor. His righteousness remaineth for
  • ever."
  • * * * * *
  • The present paper completes the definitions necessary for
  • future service. The next in order will be the first chapter
  • of the body of the work.
  • These introductory essays are as yet in imperfect form; I
  • suffer them to appear, though they were not intended for
  • immediate publication, for the sake of such chance service
  • as may be found in them.
  • [Here the author indicated certain corrections, which have
  • been carried out in this edition. He then went on to say
  • that the note on Charis (p. 274) required a word or two in
  • further illustration, as follows:--]
  • The derivation of words is like that of rivers: there is one
  • real source, usually small, unlikely, and difficult to find,
  • far up among the hills; then, as the word flows on and comes
  • into service, it takes in the force of other words from
  • other sources, and becomes itself quite another word--even
  • more than one word, after the junction--a word as it were of
  • many waters, sometimes both sweet and bitter. Thus the whole
  • force of our English "charity" depends on the guttural in
  • "Charis" getting confused with the "c" of the Latin "carus;"
  • thenceforward throughout the middle ages, the two ideas
  • ran on together, and both got confused with St. Paul's
  • [Greek: agapê], which expresses a different idea in all
  • sorts of ways; our "charity," having not only brought in the
  • entirely foreign sense of almsgiving, but lost the essential
  • sense of contentment, and lost much more in getting too far
  • away from the "charis," of the final Gospel benedictions.
  • For truly it is fine Christianity we have come to, which
  • professing to expect the perpetual grace of its Founder,
  • has not itself grace enough to save it from overreaching
  • its friends in sixpenny bargains; and which, supplicating
  • evening and morning the forgiveness of its own debts, goes
  • forth in the daytime to take its fellow-servants by the
  • throat, saying--not "Pay me that thou owest," but "Pay me
  • that thou owest me not."
  • Not but that we sometimes wear Ophelia's rue with a
  • difference, and call it, "Herb o' grace o' Sundays," taking
  • consolation out of the offertory with--"Look, what he layeth
  • out, it shall be paid him again." Comfortable words, indeed,
  • and good to set against the old royalty of Largesse--
  • "Whose moste joie was, I wis,
  • When that she gave, and said, 'Have this.'"
  • Again: the first root of the word faith being far away
  • in----(compare my note on this force of it in "Modern
  • Painters," vol. v., p. 255), the Latins, as proved by
  • Cicero's derivation of the word, got their "facio," also
  • involved in the idea; and so the word, and the world with
  • it, gradually lose themselves in an arachnoid web of
  • disputation concerning faith and works, no one ever taking
  • the pains to limit the meaning of the term: which in
  • earliest Scriptural use is as nearly as possible our English
  • "obedience." Then the Latin "fides," a quite different word,
  • alternately active and passive in different uses, runs into
  • "foi;" "facere," through "ficare," into "fier," at the end
  • of words; and "fidere," into "fier" absolute; and out of
  • this endless reticulation of thought and word rise still
  • more finely reticulated theories concerning salvation by
  • faith--the things which the populace expected to be saved
  • from, being indeed carved for them in a very graphic manner
  • in their cathedral porches, but the things they were
  • expected to believe being carved for them not so clearly.
  • Lastly I debated with myself whether to make the note on
  • Homer longer by examining the typical meaning of the
  • shipwreck of Ulysses, and his escape from Charybdis by help
  • of her fig-tree; but as I should have had to go on to the
  • lovely myth of Leucothea's veil, and did not care to spoil
  • this by a hurried account of it, I left it for future
  • examination; and three days after the paper was published,
  • observed that the reviewers, with their usual useful
  • ingenuity, were endeavouring to throw the whole subject back
  • into confusion by dwelling on the single (as they imagined)
  • oversight. I omitted also a note on the sense of the word
  • [Greek: lygron], with respect to the pharmacy of Circe, and
  • herb-fields of Helen (compare its use in Odyssey, xvii. 473,
  • etc.), which would further have illustrated the nature of
  • the Circean power. But, not to be led too far into the
  • subtleness of these myths, respecting them all I have but
  • this to say: Even in very simple parables, it is not always
  • easy to attach indisputable meaning to every part of them. I
  • recollect some years ago, throwing an assembly of learned
  • persons who had met to delight themselves with
  • interpretations of the parable of the prodigal son
  • (interpretations which had up to that moment gone very
  • smoothly) into high indignation, by inadvertently asking who
  • the prodigal son was, and what was to be learned by his
  • example. The leading divine of the company (still one of our
  • great popular preachers) at last explained to me that the
  • unprodigal son was a lay figure, put in for dramatic effect,
  • to make the story prettier, and that no note was to be taken
  • of him. Without, however, admitting that Homer put in the
  • last escape of Ulysses merely to make his story prettier,
  • this is nevertheless true of all Greek myths, that they have
  • many opposite lights and shades: they are as changeful as
  • opal and, like opal, usually have one colour by reflected,
  • and another by transmitted, light. But they are true jewels
  • for all that, and full of noble enchantment for those who
  • can use them; for those who cannot, I am content to repeat
  • the words I wrote four years ago, in the appendix to the
  • "Two Paths"--
  • "The entire purpose of a great thinker may be difficult to
  • fathom, and we may be over and over again more or less
  • mistaken in guessing at his meaning; but the real, profound,
  • nay, quite bottomless and unredeemable mistake, is the
  • fool's thought, that he had no meaning."
  • LONDON: WARD, LOCK & CO., LIMITED.
  • * * * * *
  • Transcriber's note:
  • 1. Text in italics is enclosed by underscores (_italics_).
  • 2. Footnotes have been renumbered and moved from the middle of the
  • paragraph to the closest paragraph break.
  • 3. The original text includes Greek characters. For this text version
  • these letters have been replaced with transliterations. For example,
  • [Greek: b] represents greek letter beta.
  • 4. Certain words use an oe ligature in the original.
  • 5. Mixed fractions are indicated with a hyphen and forward slash. For
  • example, 3-1/2 indicates three and a half.
  • 6. Obvious misprints and punctuation errors have been silently corrected
  • in this text version.
  • 7. Other than the changes listed above, printer's inconsistencies in
  • hyphenation and ligature usage have been retained.
  • ***END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK UNTO THIS LAST AND OTHER ESSAYS ON
  • POLITICAL ECONOMY***
  • ******* This file should be named 36541-8.txt or 36541-8.zip *******
  • This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/3/6/5/4/36541
  • Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
  • will be renamed.
  • Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
  • one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
  • (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
  • permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
  • set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
  • copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
  • protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
  • Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
  • charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
  • do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
  • rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
  • such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
  • research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
  • practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
  • subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
  • redistribution.
  • *** START: FULL LICENSE ***
  • THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  • PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
  • To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
  • distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
  • (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/license).
  • Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works
  • 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
  • and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
  • (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
  • the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
  • all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
  • If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
  • terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
  • entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
  • 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
  • used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
  • agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
  • things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
  • paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
  • and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  • works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  • 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
  • or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
  • collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
  • individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
  • located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
  • copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
  • works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
  • are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
  • freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
  • this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
  • the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
  • keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
  • 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
  • what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
  • a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
  • the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
  • before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
  • creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
  • Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
  • the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
  • States.
  • 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
  • 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
  • access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
  • whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
  • phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
  • copied or distributed:
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
  • almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
  • re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
  • with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
  • 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
  • from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
  • posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
  • and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
  • or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
  • with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
  • work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
  • through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
  • Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
  • 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
  • with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
  • must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
  • terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
  • to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
  • permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
  • 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
  • work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
  • 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
  • electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
  • prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
  • active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License.
  • 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
  • compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
  • word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
  • distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
  • "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
  • posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
  • you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
  • copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
  • request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
  • form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
  • 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
  • performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
  • unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
  • access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
  • that
  • - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
  • the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
  • you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
  • owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
  • has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
  • Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
  • must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
  • prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
  • returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
  • sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
  • address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
  • the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
  • - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
  • you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
  • does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License. You must require such a user to return or
  • destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
  • and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
  • Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  • - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
  • money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
  • electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
  • of receipt of the work.
  • - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
  • distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  • 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
  • forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
  • both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
  • Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
  • Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
  • 1.F.
  • 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
  • effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
  • public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  • works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
  • "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
  • corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
  • property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
  • computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
  • your equipment.
  • 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
  • of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
  • liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
  • fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
  • LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
  • PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
  • TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
  • LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
  • INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
  • DAMAGE.
  • 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
  • defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
  • receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
  • written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
  • received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
  • your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
  • the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
  • refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
  • providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
  • receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
  • is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
  • opportunities to fix the problem.
  • 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
  • in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO OTHER
  • WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
  • WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
  • 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
  • warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
  • If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
  • law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
  • interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
  • the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
  • provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
  • 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
  • trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
  • providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
  • with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
  • promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
  • harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
  • that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
  • or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
  • work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
  • Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
  • Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
  • electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
  • including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
  • because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
  • people in all walks of life.
  • Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
  • assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
  • goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
  • remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
  • and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
  • To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
  • and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
  • and the Foundation web page at http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/pglaf.
  • Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
  • Foundation
  • The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
  • 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
  • state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
  • Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
  • number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
  • permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
  • The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
  • Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
  • throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
  • 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
  • business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact
  • information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
  • page at http://www.gutenberg.org/about/contact
  • For additional contact information:
  • Dr. Gregory B. Newby
  • Chief Executive and Director
  • gbnewby@pglaf.org
  • Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation
  • Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
  • spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
  • increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
  • freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
  • array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
  • ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
  • status with the IRS.
  • The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
  • charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
  • States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
  • considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
  • with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
  • where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
  • SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
  • particular state visit http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/donate
  • While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
  • have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
  • against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
  • approach us with offers to donate.
  • International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
  • any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
  • outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
  • Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
  • methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
  • ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
  • To donate, please visit:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/donate
  • Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  • works.
  • Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
  • with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
  • Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
  • Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
  • editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
  • unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
  • keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
  • Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org
  • This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
  • including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
  • subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.