Quotations.ch
  Directory : Foreword to Lev Shestov's All Things are Possible
GUIDE SUPPORT US BLOG
  • The Project Gutenberg EBook of All Things are Possible, by Lev Shestov
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
  • most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
  • whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms
  • of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you'll
  • have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using
  • this ebook.
  • Title: All Things are Possible
  • Author: Lev Shestov
  • Contributor: D. H. Lawrence
  • Translator: Samuel Solominivitch Koteliansky
  • Release Date: June 21, 2018 [EBook #57369]
  • Language: English
  • Character set encoding: UTF-8
  • *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK ALL THINGS ARE POSSIBLE ***
  • Produced by Marc D'Hooghe at Free Literature (Images
  • generously made available by the Internet Archive.)
  • ALL THINGS ARE POSSIBLE
  • BY LEO SHESTOV
  • AUTHORISED TRANSLATION
  • BY S. S. KOTELIANSKY
  • WITH A FOREWORD BY
  • D. H. LAWRENCE
  • LONDON: MARTIN SECKER
  • 1920
  • NOTE
  • Leo Shestov is one of the living Russians. He is about fifty years old.
  • He was born at Kiev, and studied at the university there. His first
  • book appeared in 1898, since which year he has gradually gained an
  • assured position as one of the best critics and essayists in Russia. A
  • list of his works is as follows:--
  • 1898. Shakespeare and his Critic, Brandes.
  • 1900. Good in the Teaching of Dostoevsky and Nietzsche: Philosophy and
  • Preaching.
  • 1903. Dostoevsky and Nietzsche: The Philosophy of Tragedy.
  • 1905. The Apotheosis of Groundlessness (here translated under the title
  • "All Things are Possible").
  • 1908. Beginnings and Ends.
  • 1912. Great Vigils.
  • FOREWORD
  • _In his paragraph on The Russian Spirit, Shestov gives us the real clue
  • to Russian literature. European culture is a rootless thing in the
  • Russians. With us, it is our very blood and bones, the very nerve and
  • root of our psyche. We think in a certain fashion, we feel in a certain
  • fashion, because our whole substance is of this fashion. Our speech and
  • feeling are organically inevitable to us_.
  • _With the Russians it is different. They have only been inoculated with
  • the virus of European culture and ethic. The virus works in them like a
  • disease. And the inflammation and irritation comes forth as literature.
  • The bubbling and fizzing is almost chemical, not organic. It is an
  • organism seething as it accepts and masters the strange virus. What
  • the Russian is struggling with, crying out against, is not life itself:
  • it is only European culture which has been introduced, into his psyche,
  • and which hurts him. The tragedy is not so much a real soul tragedy,
  • as a surgical one. Russian art, Russian literature after all does not
  • stand on the same footing as European or Greek or Egyptian art. It is
  • not spontaneous utterance. It is not the flowering of a race. It is a
  • surgical outcry, horrifying, or marvellous, lacerating at first; but
  • when we get used to it, not really so profound, not really ultimate, a
  • little extraneous_.
  • _What is valuable, is the evidence against European culture, implied
  • in the novelists, here at last expressed. Since Peter the Great Russia
  • has been accepting Europe, and seething Europe down in a curious
  • process of katabolism. Russia has been expressing nothing inherently
  • Russian. Russia's modern Christianity even was not Russian. Her
  • genuine Christianity, Byzantine and Asiatic, is incomprehensible to
  • us. So with her true philosophy. What she has actually uttered is her
  • own unwilling, fantastic reproduction of European truths. What she
  • has really to utter the coming centuries will hear. For Russia will
  • certainly inherit the future. What I we already call the greatness of
  • Russia is only her pre-natal struggling_.
  • _It seems as if she had at last absorbed and overcome the virus of
  • old Europe. Soon her new, healthy body will begin to act in its own
  • reality, imitative no more, protesting no more, crying no more, but
  • full and sound and lusty in itself. Real Russia is born. She will
  • laugh at us before long. Meanwhile she goes through the last stages of
  • reaction against us, kicking away from the old womb of Europe_.
  • _In Shestov one of the last kicks is given. True, he seems to be only
  • reactionary and destructive. But he can find a little amusement at last
  • in tweaking the European nose, so he is fairly free. European idealism
  • is anathema. But more than this, it is a little comical. We feel the
  • new independence in his new, half-amused indifference_.
  • _He is only tweaking the nose of European idealism. He is preaching
  • nothing: so he protests time and again. He absolutely refutes any
  • imputation of a central idea He is so afraid lest it should turn out to
  • be another hateful hedge-stake of an ideal_.
  • "_Everything is possible"--this is his really central cry. It is not
  • nihilism. It is only a shaking free of the human psyche from old bonds.
  • The positive central idea is that the human psyche, or soul, really
  • believes in itself, and in nothing else_.
  • _Dress this up in a little comely language, and we have a real new
  • ideal, that will last us for a new, long epoch. The human soul itself
  • is the source and well-head of creative activity. In the unconscious
  • human soul the creative prompting issues first into the universe.
  • Open the consciousness to this prompting, away with all your old
  • sluice-gates, locks, dams, channels. No ideal on earth is anything
  • more than an obstruction, in the end, to the creative issue of the
  • spontaneous soul. Away with all ideals. Let each individual act
  • spontaneously from, the forever-incalculable prompting of the creative
  • well-head within him. There is no universal law. Each being is, at his
  • purest, a law unto himself, single, unique, a Godhead, a fountain from
  • the unknown_.
  • _This is the ideal which Shestov refuses positively to state, because
  • he is afraid it may prove in the end a trap to catch his own free
  • spirit. So it may. But it is none the less a real, living ideal for the
  • moment, the very salvation. When it becomes ancient, and like the old
  • lion who lay in his cave and whined, devours all its servants, then it
  • can be despatched. Meanwhile it is a really liberating word_.
  • _Shestov's style is puzzling at first. Having found the "ands" and
  • "buts" and "becauses" and "therefores" hampered him, he clips them all
  • off deliberately and even spitefully, so that his thought is like a man
  • with no buttons on his clothes, ludicrously hitching along all undone.
  • One must be amused, not irritated. Where the armholes were a bit tight,
  • Shestov cuts a slit. It is baffling, but really rather piquant.
  • The real conjunction, the real unification lies in the reader's own
  • amusement, not in the author's unbroken logic_.
  • D. H. LAWRENCE.
  • PART I
  • _Zu fragmentarish ist Welt und Leben_.
  • H. HEINE.
  • 1
  • The obscure streets of life do not offer the conveniences of the
  • central thoroughfares: no electric light, no gas, not even a kerosene
  • lamp-bracket. There are no pavements: the traveller has to fumble his
  • way in the dark. If he needs a light, he must wait for a thunderbolt,
  • or else, primitive-wise, knock a spark out of a stone. In a glimpse
  • will appear unfamiliar outlines; and then, what he has taken in he
  • must try to remember, no matter whether the impression was right or
  • false. For he will not easily get another light, except he run his head
  • against a wall, and see sparks that way. What can a wretched pedestrian
  • gather under such circumstances? How can we expect a clear account from
  • him whose curiosity (let us suppose his curiosity so strong) led him to
  • grope his way among the outskirts of life? Why should we try to compare
  • his records with those of the travellers through brilliant streets?
  • 2
  • The law of sequence in natural phenomena seems so plausible, so
  • obvious, that one is tempted to look for its origin, not in the
  • realities of actual life, but in the promptings of the human mind. This
  • law of sequence is the most mysterious of all the natural laws. Why so
  • much order? Why not chaos and disorderliness? Really, if the hypothesis
  • of sequence had not offered such blatant advantages to the human
  • intelligence, man would never have thought of raising it to the rank of
  • eternal and irrefutable truth. But he saw his opportunity. Thanks to
  • the grand hypothesis, man is forewarned and forearmed. Thanks to this
  • master-key, the future is at his mercy. He knows, in order that he may
  • foreknow: _savoir pour prévoir_. Here, is man, by virtue of one supreme
  • assumption, dictator henceforward of all nature. The philosophers
  • have ever bowed the knee to success. So down they went before the
  • newly-invented law of natural sequence, they hailed it with the title
  • of eternal truth. But even this seemed insufficient. _L'appétit vient
  • en mangeant_. Like the old woman in the fairy-tale about the golden
  • fish, they had it in their minds that the fish should do their
  • errands. But some few people at last could not stand this impudence.
  • Some very few began to object....
  • 3
  • The comfortable settled man says to himself: "How could, one live
  • without being sure of the morrow; how could one sleep without a roof
  • over one's head?" But misfortune turns him out of house and home.
  • He must perforce sleep under a hedge. He cannot rest, he is full of
  • terrors. There may be wild beasts, fellow-tramps. But in the long run
  • he gets used to it. He will trust himself to chance, live like a tramp,
  • and sleep his sleep in a ditch.
  • 4
  • A writer, particularly a young and inexperienced writer, feels himself
  • under an obligation to give his reader the fullest answers to all
  • possible questions. Conscience will not let him shut his eyes to
  • tormenting problems, and so he begins to speak of "first and ultimate
  • things." As he cannot say anything profitable on such subjects--for it
  • is not the business of the young to be profoundly philosophical--he
  • grows excited, he shouts himself to hoarseness. In the end he is
  • silent from exhaustion. And then, if his words have had any success
  • with the public, he is astonished to find that he has become a prophet.
  • Whereupon, if he be an average sort of person, he is filled with an
  • insatiable desire to preserve his influence till the end of his days.
  • But if he be more sensitive or gifted than usual, he begins to despise
  • the crowd for its vulgar credulity, and himself for having posed in the
  • stupid and disgraceful character of a clown of lofty ideas.
  • 5
  • How painful it is to read Plato's account of the last conversations of
  • Socrates! The days, even the hours of the old man are numbered, and
  • yet he talks, talks, talks.... Crito comes to him in the early morning
  • and tells him that the sacred ships will shortly return to Athens. And
  • at once Socrates is ready to talk, to argue.... It is possible, of
  • course, that Plato is not altogether to be trusted. It is said that
  • Socrates observed, of the dialogues already written down by Plato.
  • "How much that youth has belied me!" But then from all sources we have
  • it, that Socrates spent the month following his verdict in incessant
  • conversations with his pupils and friends. That is what it is to be a
  • beloved master, and to have disciples. You can't even die quietly....
  • The best death is really the one which is considered the worst: to die
  • alone, in a foreign land, in a poor-house, or, as they say, like a dog
  • under a hedge. Then at least one may spend one's last moments honestly,
  • without dissembling or ostentation, preparing oneself for the dreadful,
  • or wonderful, event. Pascal, as his sister tells us, also talked a
  • great deal before his death, and de Musset cried like a baby. Perhaps
  • Socrates and Pascal talked so much, for fear they should start crying.
  • It is a false shame!
  • 6
  • The fact that some ideas, or some series of ideas, are materially
  • unprofitable to mankind cannot serve as a justification for their
  • rejection. Once an idea is there, the gates must be opened to it. For
  • if you close the gates, the thought will force a way in, or, like the
  • fly in the fable, will sneak through unawares. Ideas have no regard for
  • our laws of honour or morality. Take for example realism in literature.
  • At its appearance it aroused universal indignation. Why need we know
  • the dirt of life? And honestly, there _is_ no need. Realism could give
  • no straightforward justification for itself. But, as it had to come
  • through, it was ready with a lie; it compared itself to pathology,
  • called itself useful, beneficial, and so obtained a place. We can all
  • see now that realism is _not_ beneficial, but harmful, very harmful,
  • and that it has nothing in common with pathology. Nevertheless, it is
  • no longer easy to drive it from its place. The prohibition evaded,
  • there is now the _justus titulus possessions_.
  • 7
  • Count Tolstoy preached inaction. It seems he had no need. We "inact"
  • remarkably. Idleness, just that idleness Tolstoy dreamed of, a free,
  • conscious idling that despises labour, this is one of the chief
  • characteristics of our time. Of course I speak of the higher, cultured
  • classes, the aristocracy of spirit--"We write books, paint pictures,
  • compose symphonies"--But is that labour? It is only the amusement of
  • idleness. SO that Tolstoy is much more to the point when, forgetting
  • his preaching of inaction, he bids us trudge eight hours a day at the
  • tail of the plough. In this there is some sense. Idleness spoils
  • us. We were returning to the most primitive of all the states of our
  • forefathers. Like paradisal Adam and Eve, having no need to sweat for
  • our bread, we were trying to pilfer the fruit from the forbidden tree.
  • Truly we received a similar punishment. Divine laws are inscrutable.
  • In Paradise everything is permitted, except curiosity. Even labour
  • is allowed, though it is not obligatory, as it is outside. Tolstoy
  • realised the dangers of the paradisal state. He stooped to talk of
  • inaction for a moment--and then he began to work. Since in regular,
  • smooth, constant, rhythmical labour, whether it is efficient or whether
  • it merely appears efficient, like Tolstoy's farming, there is peace
  • of mind. Look at the industrious Germans, who begin and who end their
  • day with a prayer. In Paradise, where there is no labour, and no need
  • for long rest and heavy sleep, all temptations become dangerous. It
  • is a peril to live there.... Perhaps present-day people eschew the
  • paradisal state. They prefer work, for where there is no work there
  • is no smoothness, no regularity, no peacefulness, no satisfaction. In
  • Eden, even the well-informed individuals Cannot tell what will come
  • next, _savoir pour prévoir_ does not answer, and everlasting laws are
  • exposed to ridicule. Amongst ourselves also a few of the work-abjurors,
  • the idlers, are beginning to question our established knowledge. But
  • the majority of men, and particularly Germans, still defend _a priori_
  • judgments, on the ground that without these, perfect knowledge would
  • be impossible, there could be no regulation of the course of natural
  • phenomena, and no looking ahead.
  • 8
  • To escape from the grasp of contemporary ruling ideas, one should study
  • history. The lives of other men in other lands in other ages teach
  • us to realise that our "eternal laws" and infallible ideas are just
  • abortions. Take a step further, imagine mankind living elsewhere than
  • on this earth, and all our terrestial eternalities lose their charm.
  • 9
  • We know nothing of the ultimate realities of our existence, nor shall
  • we ever know anything. Let that be agreed. But it does not follow that
  • therefore we must accept some or other dogmatic theory as a _modus
  • vivendi_, no, not even positivism, which has such a sceptical face
  • on it. It only follows that man is free to change his conception of
  • the universe as often as he changes his boots or his gloves, and that
  • constancy of principle belongs only to one's relationships with other
  • people, in order that they may know where and to what extent they may
  • depend on us. Therefore, on principle man should respect order in the
  • external world and complete chaos in the inner. And for those who find
  • it difficult to bear such a duality, some internal order might also
  • be provided. Only, they should not pride themselves on it, but always
  • remember that it is a sign of their weakness, pettiness, dullness.
  • 10
  • The Pythagoreans assumed that the sun is motionless and that the earth
  • turns round. What a long time the truth had to wait for recognition!
  • 11
  • In spite of Epicurus and his exasperation we are forced to admit that
  • anything whatsoever may result from anything whatsoever. Which does
  • not mean, however, that a stone ever turned into bread, or that our
  • visible universe was ever "naturally" formed from nebulous puffs. But
  • from our own minds and our own experience we can deduce nothing that
  • would serve us as a ground for setting even the smallest limit to
  • nature's own arbitrary behaviour. If whatever happens now had chanced
  • to happen quite differently, it would not, therefore, have seemed any
  • the less _natural_ to us. In other words, although there may be an
  • element of inevitability in our human judgments concerning the natural
  • phenomena, we have never been able and probably never shall be able
  • to separate the grain of inevitable from the chaff of accidental and
  • casual truth. Moreover, we do not even know which is more essential
  • and important, the inevitable or the casual. Hence we are forced to
  • the conclusion that philosophy must give up her attempt at finding the
  • _veritates aeternae_. The business of philosophy is to teach man to
  • live in uncertainty--man who is supremely afraid of uncertainty, and
  • who is forever hiding himself behind this or the other dogma. More
  • briefly, the business of philosophy is not to reassure people, but to
  • upset them.
  • 12
  • When man finds in himself a certain defect, of which he can by no means
  • rid himself, there remains but to accept the so-called failing as a
  • natural quality. The more grave and important the defect, the more
  • urgent is the need to ennoble it. From sublime to ridiculous is only
  • one step, and an ineradicable vice in strong men is always rechristened
  • a virtue.
  • 13
  • On the whole, there is little to choose between metaphysics and
  • positivism. In each there is the same horizon, but the composition and
  • colouring are different. Positivism chooses grey, colourless paint
  • and ordinary composition; metaphysics prefers brilliant colouring
  • and complicated design, and always carries the vision away into the
  • infinite; in which trick it often succeeds, owing to its skill in
  • perspective. But the canvas is impervious, there is no melting through
  • it into "the other world." Nevertheless, skilful perspectives are very
  • alluring, so that metaphysicians will still have something to quarrel
  • about with the positivists.
  • 14
  • The task of a writer: to go forward and share his impressions with his
  • reader. In spite of everything to the contrary, he is not obliged to
  • _prove_ anything. But, because every step of his progress is dogged by
  • those police agents, morality, science, logic, and so forth, he needs
  • always to have ready some sort of argument with which to frustrate
  • them. There is no necessity to trouble too deeply about the quality
  • of the argumentation. Why fret about being "inwardly right." It is
  • quite enough if the reasoning which comes handiest will succeed in
  • occupying those guardians of the verbal highways whose intention it is
  • to obstruct his passage.
  • 15
  • The Secret of Poushkin's "inner harmony."--To Poushkin nothing was
  • hopeless. Nay, he saw hopeful signs in everything. It is agreeable to
  • sin, and it is just as delightful to repent. It is good to doubt, but
  • it is still better to believe. It is jolly "with feet shod in steel"
  • to skate the ice, it is pleasant to wander about with gypsies, to pray
  • in church, to quarrel with a friend, to make peace with an enemy, to
  • swoon on waves of harmony, to weep over a passing fancy, to recall the
  • past, to peep into the future. Poushkin could cry hot tears, and he who
  • can weep can hope. "I want to live, so that I may think and suffer," he
  • says; and it seems as if the word "to suffer," which is so beautiful
  • in the poem, just fell in accidentally, because there was no better
  • rhyme in Russian for "to die." The later verses, which are intended to
  • amplify _to think and to suffer,_ prove this. Poushkin might repeat the
  • words of the ancient hero: "danger is dangerous to others, but not to
  • me." Therein lies the secret of his harmonious moods.
  • 16
  • The well-trodden field of contemporary thought should be dug up.
  • Therefore, on every possible occasion, in season and out, the
  • generally-accepted truths must be ridiculed to death, and paradoxes
  • uttered in their place. Then we shall see....
  • 17
  • What is a Weltanschauung, a world-conception, a philosophy? As we all
  • know, Turgenev was a realist, and from the first he tried to portray
  • life truthfully. Although we had had no precise exponents of realism,
  • yet after Poushkin it was impossible for a Russian writer to depart too
  • far from actuality. Even those who did not know what to do with "real
  • life" had to cope with it as best they could. Hence, in order that
  • the picture of life should not prove too depressing, the writer must
  • provide himself in due season with a philosophy. This philosophy still
  • plays the part of the magic wand in literature, enabling the author to
  • turn anything he likes into anything else.
  • Most of Turgenev's works are curious in respect of philosophy. But most
  • curious is his _Diary of a Superfluous Man_. Turgenev was the first to
  • introduce the term "a superfluous man" into Russian literature. Since
  • then an endless amount has been written about superfluous people,
  • although up till now nothing important has been added to what was
  • already said fifty years ago. There are superfluous people, plenty of
  • them. But what is to be done with them? No one knows. There remains
  • only to invent philosophies on their behalf. In 1850 Turgenev, then
  • a young man, thus solved the problem. He ends the _Diary_--with a
  • humorous postscript, supposed to have been scribbled by an impertinent
  • reader on the last fly-leaf of the MS.
  • _This MS. was ready and contents thereof disapproved_,
  • _by Peter Zudotyeshin. M.M.M.M_.
  • _Dear Sir, Peter Zudotyeshin, My dear Sir_.
  • It is obvious Turgenev felt that after a tragedy must follow a farce,
  • and therein lies the substance of his philosophy. It is also obvious
  • that in this feeling he has the whole of European civilisation behind
  • him. Turgenev was the most educated, the most cultured of all Russian
  • writers. He spent nearly all his life abroad, and absorbed into himself
  • all that European learning could offer. He knew this, although he never
  • directly admitted it, owing to an exaggerated modesty which sometimes
  • irritates us by its obviousness. He believed profoundly that only
  • learning, only European science could open men's eyes to life, and
  • explain all that needed explanation. According to this belief he judges
  • even Tolstoy. "The saddest instance of the lack of real freedom," the
  • sixty-year-old Turgenev writes _of War and Peace_, in his literary
  • memoirs: "the saddest instance of the lack of real freedom, arising
  • from the lack of real knowledge, is revealed to us in Leo Tolstoy's
  • latest work, a work which at the same time, by virtue of its creative,
  • poetic force, ranks almost first among all that has appeared in
  • Russian literature since 1840. No! without culture, without freedom in
  • the widest sense, freedom within oneself, freedom from preconceived
  • ideas, freedom with regard to one's own nation and history, without
  • this, the real artist is unthinkable; without this free air he cannot
  • breathe." Listening to Turgenev one might imagine that he had learned
  • some great secret in the West, a secret which gave him the right to
  • bear himself cheerfully and modestly when other people despaired and
  • lost their heads.... A year after the writing of the literary memoirs
  • above quoted, Turgenev happened to be present at the execution of the
  • notorious murderer, Tropman. His impressions are superbly rendered in a
  • long article called "Tropman's Execution." The description produces a
  • soul-shaking effect upon the reader; for I think I shall not exaggerate
  • if I say that the essay is one of the best, at least one of the most
  • vigorous of Turgenev's writings. It is true that Tolstoy describes
  • scenes of slaughter with no less vigour, and therefore the reader need
  • not yield too much to the artist's power. Yet when Turgenev relates
  • that, at the decisive moment, when the executioners like spiders on
  • a fly threw themselves on Tropman and bore him to the ground--"the
  • earth quietly swam away from under my feet"--we are forced to believe
  • him. Men respond only faintly to the horrors that take place around
  • them, except at moments, when the savage, crying incongruity and
  • ghastliness of our condition suddenly reveals itself vivid before our
  • eyes, and we are forced to know what we are. Then the ground slides
  • away from under our feet. But not for long. The horror of the sensation
  • of groundlessness quickly brings man to himself. He must forget
  • everything, he must only get his feet on earth again. In this sense
  • Turgenev proved himself in as risky a state at sixty as he was when, as
  • a young man, he wrote his _Diary of a Superfluous Man._ The description
  • of Tropman's execution ends with these words: "Who can fail to feel
  • that the question of capital punishment is one of the urgent, immediate
  • problems which modern humanity must settle? I shall be satisfied ...
  • if my story will provide even a few arguments for those who advocate
  • the abolition, or at least the suppression of the publicity of capital
  • punishments." Again the mountain has brought forth a mouse. After
  • a tragedy, a farce. Philosophy enters into her power, and the earth
  • returns under one's feet.
  • I emphasise and repeat: Turgenev is not alone responsible for his
  • attitude. With his lips speaks the whole of European civilisation. On
  • principle all insoluble problems are rejected. During her thousand
  • years of experience, the old civilisation has acquired the skill which
  • allows her children to derive satisfaction and benefit out of anything,
  • even the blood of their neighbour. Even the greatest horrors, even
  • crimes are beneficial, properly construed. Turgenev was, as we know,
  • a soft, "humane" man, an undoubted idealist. In his youth he had been
  • through the Hegelian school. And from Hegel he learned what an enormous
  • value education has, and how supremely important it is for an educated
  • man to have a complete and finished--most certainly a "finished"
  • philosophy.
  • 18
  • To praise oneself is considered improper, immodest; to praise one's
  • own sect, one's own philosophy, is considered the highest duty. Even
  • the best writers have taken at least as much trouble to glorify their
  • philosophy as to found it, and have always had more success in the
  • former case than in the latter. Their ideas, whether proven or not, are
  • the dearest possession in life to them, in sorrow a consolation, in
  • difficulty a source of counsel. Even death is not terrible to ideas;
  • they will follow man beyond the grave, they are the only imperishable
  • riches. All this the philosophers repeat, very eloquently repeat and
  • reiterate concerning their ideas, not less skilfully than advocates
  • plead their cases on behalf of thieves and swindlers. But nobody has
  • ever yet called a philosopher "a hired conscience," though everybody
  • gives the lawyer this nickname. Why this partiality?
  • 19
  • Certain savage tribes believe that their kings need no food, neither
  • to eat nor to drink. As a matter of fact, kings eat and drink, and
  • even relish a good mouthful more than ordinary mortals. So, having
  • no desire, even for the sake of form, to abstain too long, they not
  • infrequently interrupt the long-drawn-out religious ceremonies of
  • their tribes, in order to command refreshment for their frail bodies.
  • But none must witness, or even be aware of this refreshing, and so
  • while he eats the king is hidden within a purple pall. Metaphysicians
  • remind one of these savage kings. They want everyone to believe that
  • empiricism, which means all reality and substantial existence, is
  • nothing to them, they need only pure ideas for their existence. In
  • order to keep up this fiction, they appear before the world invested
  • in a purple veil of fine words. The crowd knows perfectly well that
  • it is all a take-in, but since it likes shows and bright colours, and
  • since also it has no ambition to appear too knowing, it rarely betrays
  • that it has caught the trick of the comedy. On the contrary, it loves
  • to pretend to be fooled, knowing by instinct that actors always do
  • their best when the audience believes implicitly in what happens. Only
  • inexperienced youths and children, unaware of the great importance of
  • the conventional attitude, now and then cry out in indignation and
  • give the lie to the performance: like the child in Andersen's story,
  • who so unexpectedly and inopportunely broke the general, deliberate
  • illusion by calling out--"But the king is naked." Of course everybody
  • knows without telling that the king is naked: that the metaphysicians
  • not only are unable to explain anything, but that hitherto they
  • have not been able to present even a single hypothesis free from
  • contradiction. It is necessary to pretend to believe that kings eat
  • nothing, that philosophers have divined the secrets of the universe,
  • that arbitrary theories are more precious than empirical harvests, and
  • so on. There remains only one difficulty: grownups may be won over to
  • the conventional lie, but what about the children? With them the only
  • remedy is the Pythagorean system of upbringing, so glorified by Hegel.
  • Children must keep silent and not raise their voice until they realise
  • that _some_ things may not be talked about. This is our method. With
  • us pupils remain silent, not only for five years, as the Pythagoreans
  • recommended, but for ten or more--until they have learned to speak like
  • their masters. And then they are granted a freedom which is no longer
  • any good to them. Perhaps they had wings, or might have had them, but
  • they have crawled all their life long in imitation of their masters,
  • so how can they now dream of flight? To a well-informed man, who has
  • studied much, the very thought of the possibility of tearing himself
  • away from the earth, even for a moment, is horrifying: as if he knew
  • beforehand what the result would be.
  • 20
  • The best, the most effective way of convincing a reader is to begin
  • one's argument with inoffensive, commonplace assertions. When suspicion
  • has been sufficiently lulled, and a certainty has been begot that what
  • follows will be a confirmation of the readers own accepted views--then
  • has the moment arrived to speak one's mind openly, but still in the
  • same easy tone, as if there were no break in the flow of truisms. The
  • logical connection is unimportant. Consequence of manner and intonation
  • is much more impressive than consequence of ideas. The thing to do is
  • to go on, in the same suave tone, from uttering a series of banalities
  • to expressing a new and dangerous thought, without any break. If you
  • succeed in this, the business is done. The reader will not forget--the
  • new words will plague and torment him until he has accepted them.
  • 21
  • The habit of logical thinking kills imagination. Man is convinced that
  • the only way to truth is through logic, and that any departure from
  • this way leads to error and absurdity. The nearer we approach the
  • ultimate questions of existence, in our departure from logicality,
  • the more deadly becomes the state of error we fall into. The Ariadne
  • ball has become all unwound long ago, and man is at the end of the
  • tether. But he does not know, he holds the end of the thread firmly,
  • and marks time with energy on the same spot, imagining his progress,
  • and little realising the ridiculous situation into which he has
  • fallen. How should he realise, considering the innumerable precautions
  • he has taken to prevent himself from losing the logical way? He had
  • better have stayed at home. Once he set out, once he decided to be
  • a Theseus and kill the Minotaur, he should have given himself up,
  • forfeited the old attachment, and been ready _never to escape from the
  • labyrinth_. True, he would have risked losing Ariadne: and this is
  • why long journeys should be undertaken only after family connections
  • have become a burden. Such being the case, a man deliberately cuts
  • the thread which binds him to hearth and home, so that he may have a
  • legitimate excuse to his conscience for not going back. Philosophy must
  • have nothing in common with logic; philosophy is an art which aims at
  • breaking the logical continuity of argument and bringing man out on
  • the shoreless sea of imagination, the fantastic tides where everything
  • is equally possible and impossible. Certainly it is difficult, given
  • sedentary habits of life, to be a good philosopher. The fact that the
  • fate of philosophy has ever lain in the hands of professors can only be
  • explained by the reluctance of the envious gods to give omniscience to
  • mortals. Whilst stay-at-home persons are searching for truth, the apple
  • will stay on the tree. The business must be undertaken by homeless
  • adventurers, born nomads, to whom _ubi bene ibi patria_. It seems to me
  • that but for his family and his domesticity, Count Tolstoy, who lives
  • to such a ripe old age, might have told us a great many important and
  • interesting things. Or, perhaps, had he not married, like Nietzsche
  • he would have gone mad. "If you turn to the right, you will marry, if
  • to the left, you will be killed." A true philosopher never chooses
  • the middle course; he needs no riches, he does not know what to do
  • with money. But whether he turns to the right or to the left, nothing
  • pleasant awaits him.
  • 22
  • Scratch a Russian and you will find a Tartar. Culture is an age-long
  • development, and sudden grafting of it upon a race rarely succeeds.
  • To us in Russia, civilisation came suddenly, whilst we were still
  • savages. At once she took upon herself the responsibilities of a tamer
  • of wild animals, first working with decoys and baits, and later, when
  • she felt her power, with threats. We quickly submitted. In a short
  • time we were swallowing in enormous doses those poisons which Europe
  • had been gradually accustoming herself to, gradually assimilating
  • through centuries. Thanks to which, the transplanting of civilisation
  • into Russia turns out to be no mild affair. A Russian had only to
  • catch a whiff of European atmosphere, and his head began to swim. He
  • interpreted in his own way, savage-like, whatever he heard of western
  • success. Hearing about railways, agricultural machines, schools,
  • municipalities, his imagination painted miracles: universal happiness,
  • boundless freedom, paradise, wings, etc. And the more impossible his
  • dreams, the more eager he was to believe them real. How disillusioned
  • with Europe the westerner _Herzen_ became, after living for years on
  • end abroad! Yet, with all his acuteness, it did not occur to him that
  • Europe was not in the least to blame for his disillusionment. Europe
  • had dropped miracles ages ago; she contented herself with ideals. It
  • is we in Russia who will go on confusing miracles with ideals, as if
  • the two were identical, whereas they have nothing to do with each
  • other. As a matter of fact, just because Europe had ceased to believe
  • in miracles, and realised that all human problems resolve down to mere
  • arrangements here on earth, ideas and ideals had been invented. But
  • the Russian bear crept out of his hole and strolled to Europe for the
  • elixir of life, the flying carpet, the seven-leagued shoes, and so on,
  • thinking in all his naïveté that railways and electricity were signs
  • which clearly proved that the old nurse never told a lie in her fairy
  • tales.... All this happened just at the moment when Europe had finally
  • made away with alchemy and astrology, and started on the positive
  • researches resulting in chemistry and astronomy.
  • 23
  • The first assumption of all metaphysics is, that by dialectic
  • development of any concept a whole system can be evolved. Of course the
  • initial concept, the _a priori_, is generally unsound, so there is no
  • need to mention the deductions. But since it is very difficult in the
  • realm of abstract thought to distinguish a lie from truth, metaphysical
  • systems often have a very convincing appearance. The chief defect only
  • appears incidentally, when the taste for dialectic play becomes blunted
  • in man, as it did in Turgenev towards the end of his life, so that he
  • realises the uselessness of philosophical systems. It is related that
  • a famous mathematician, after hearing a musical symphony to the end,
  • inquired, "What does it prove?" Of course, it proves nothing, except
  • that the mathematician had no taste for music. And to him who has no
  • taste for dialectics, metaphysics can prove nothing, either. Therefore,
  • those who are interested in the success of metaphysics must always
  • encourage the opinion that a taste for dialectics is a high distinction
  • in a man, proving the loftiness of his soul.
  • 24
  • Man is used to having convictions, so there we are. We can none of us
  • do without our hangers-on, though we despise them at the bottom of our
  • souls.
  • 25
  • Socrates and Plato tried to determine under the shifting change of
  • appearance the immutable, unchanging reality. In the Platonic "ideas"
  • the attempt was incarnated. The visible reality, never true to itself,
  • assuming numberless varying forms, this is not the genuine reality.
  • That which is real must be constant. Hence the ideas of objects are
  • real, and the objects themselves are fictitious. Thus the root of
  • the Platonic philosophy appears to be a fundamental defect in human
  • reasoning--a defect regarded as the highest merit. It is difficult
  • for the philosopher to get a good grasp of this agitated, capricious
  • life, and so he decides that it is not life at all, but a figment.
  • Dialectics is supreme only over general concepts--and the general
  • concepts are promoted to an ideal. Since Plato and Socrates, only
  • such philosophers have succeeded largely who have taught that the
  • unchangeable is preferable to the changeable, the eternal to the
  • temporal. The ordinary individual, who lives unconsciously, never
  • reckoning his spiritual credit against his spiritual debit, naturally
  • regards the philosopher as his legitimate book-keeper, keeper of
  • the soul's accounts. Already in Greece the Athenian youth watched
  • with passionate interest the dexterity which Socrates displayed in
  • his endeavour to restore by means of dialectics the lost "ultimate
  • foundations" of human conduct. Now in book-keeping, as we are aware,
  • not a single farthing must disappear untraceably. Socrates was trying
  • to come up to expectations. The balance between man's spiritual assets
  • and liabilities was with him ideally established. Perhaps in this
  • lies the secret of that strange attraction he exerted even over such
  • volatile and unsteady natures as that of Alcibiades, drawing the young
  • men to him so that they were attached to him with all their soul.
  • Alcibiades had long since lost all count of his spiritual estate, and
  • therefore from time to time he had need to recourse to Socrates, who
  • by speeches and dissertations could bring order into chaos and harmony
  • into the spiritual confusion of his young friend. Alcibiades turned to
  • Socrates to be relieved. Of course, he sought relief in order that
  • he might begin again his riotous living: rest is so sweet to a tired
  • man. But to conclude that because Alcibiades exhausted himself, and
  • because rest is sweet, therefore all men must rest, this is absurd. Yet
  • Socrates dictated this conclusion, in all his ideas. He wished that
  • all men should rest, rest through eternity, that they should see their
  • highest fulfilment in this resting. It is easier to judge of Socrates
  • since we have Count Tolstoy with us. Probably the physiognomist Topir
  • would say of Tolstoy as he said of Socrates, that there are many evil
  • propensities lurking in him. Topir is not here to speak, but Tolstoy
  • has told us himself how wicked he found his own nature, how he had to
  • struggle with it. Tolstoy is not naturally over-courageous; by long
  • effort he has trained himself to be bold. How afraid of death he was
  • in his youth And how cleverly he could conceal that fear. Later on,
  • in mature age, it was still the fear of death which inspired him to
  • write his confession. He was conquering that fear, and with it all
  • other fears. For he felt that, since fear is very difficult to master
  • in oneself, man must be a much higher being when he has learned not
  • to be afraid any more. Meanwhile, who knows? Perhaps "cowardice,"
  • that miserable, despicable, much-abused weakness of the underworld,
  • is not such a vice after all. Perhaps it is even a virtue. Think of
  • Dostoevsky and his heroes, think of Hamlet. If the underworld man in us
  • were afraid of nothing, if Hamlet was naturally a gladiator, then we
  • should have neither tragic poetry nor philosophy. It is a platitude,
  • that fear of death has been the inspiration of philosophers. Numberless
  • quotations could be drawn from ancient and modern writers, if they
  • were necessary. Maybe the poetic daimon of Socrates, which made him
  • wise, was only fear personified. Or perhaps it was his dark dreams.
  • That which troubled him by day did not quit him by night. Even after
  • the sentence of death Socrates dreamed that he ought to engage in the
  • arts, so in order not to provoke the gods he began to compose verses,
  • at the age of seventy. Tolstoy also at the age of fifty began to
  • perform good deeds, to which performance he had previously given not
  • the slightest attention. If it were our custom nowadays to express
  • ourselves mythologically, we should no doubt hear Tolstoy telling us
  • about his daimon or his dreams. Instead he squares his accounts with
  • science and morality, in place of gods or demons. Many a present-day
  • Alcibiades, who laves all the week in the muddy waters of life, comes
  • on Sundays to cleanse himself in the pure stream of Tolstoyian ideas.
  • Book-keeping is satisfied with this modest success, and assumes that
  • if it commands universal attention one day in the week, then obviously
  • it is the sum and essence of life, beyond which man needs nothing. On
  • the same grounds the keepers of public baths could argue that, since
  • so many people come to them on Saturdays, therefore cleanliness is the
  • highest ambition of man, and during the week no one should stir at all,
  • lest he sweat or soil himself.
  • 26
  • In an old French writer, a contemporary of Pascal, I came across
  • the following remarkable words: "L'homme est si miserable que
  • _l'inconstance avec laquelle il abandonne ses desseins est, en quelque
  • sorte, sa plus grande vertu_; parce qu'il temoigne par là qu'il y a
  • encore en lui quelque reste de grandeur qui le porte à se dégouter de
  • choses qui ne méritent pas son amour et son estime." What a long way
  • modern thought has travelled from even the possibility of such an
  • assumption. To consider inconstancy the finest human virtue! Surely in
  • order to get somewhere in life it is necessary to give the whole self,
  • one's whole energy to the service of some one particular purpose. In
  • order to be a _virtuoso_, a master of one's art and one's instrument,
  • it is necessary with a truly angelic or asinine patience to try over
  • and over again, dozens, hundreds, thousands of times, different ways
  • of expressing one's ideas or moods, sparing neither labour, nor time,
  • nor health. Everything else must take a second place. The first must
  • be occupied by "the Art." Goncharov, in his novel _Obryv_, cleverly
  • relates how a 'cellist struggled all day, like a fish against the ice,
  • sawing and sawing away, so that later on, in the evening, he might play
  • super-excellently well. And that is the general idea. Objectionable,
  • tedious, irritating labour,--this is the condition of genius, which no
  • doubt explains the reason why men so rarely achieve anything. Genius
  • must submit to cultivate an ass within itself--the condition being so
  • humiliating that man will seldom take up the job. The majority prefer
  • talent, that medium which lies between genius and mediocrity. And many
  • a time, towards the end of life, does the genius repent of his choice.
  • "It would be better not to startle the world, but to live at one with
  • it," says Ibsen in his last drama. Genius is a wretched, blind maniac,
  • whose eccentricities are condoned because of what is got from him. And
  • still we all bow to persevering talent, to the only god in whom we
  • moderns believe, and the eulogy of inconstancy will awake very little
  • sympathy in our hearts. Probably we shall not even regard it seriously.
  • 27
  • We very often express in a categorical form a judgment of which we do
  • not feel assured, we even lay stress on its absolute validity. We want
  • to see what opposition it will arouse, and this can be achieved only by
  • stating our assumption not as a tentative suggestion, which no one will
  • consider, but as an irrefutable, all-important truth. The greater the
  • value an assumption has for us, the more carefully do we conceal any
  • suggestion of its improbability.
  • 28
  • Literature deals with the most difficult and important problems of
  • existence, and, therefore, littérateurs consider themselves the most
  • important of people. A bank clerk, who is always handing money out,
  • might just as well consider himself a millionaire. The high estimate
  • placed upon unexplained, unsolved questions ought really to discredit
  • writers in our eyes. And yet these literary men are so clever, so
  • cunning at stating their own case and revealing the high importance of
  • their mission, that in the long run they convince everybody, themselves
  • most of all. This last event is surely owing to their own limited
  • intelligence. The Romans augurs had subtler, more versatile minds. In
  • order to deceive others, they had no need to deceive themselves. In
  • their own set they were not afraid to talk about their secrets, even
  • to make fun of them, being fully confident that they could easily
  • vindicate themselves before outsiders, in case of necessity, and pull
  • a solemn face befitting the occasion. But our writers of to-day,
  • before they can lay their improbable assertions before the public,
  • must inevitably try to be convinced in their own minds. Otherwise they
  • cannot begin.
  • 29
  • "The writer is writing away, the reader is reading away"--the writer
  • doesn't care what the reader is after, the reader doesn't care what the
  • writer is about. Such a state of things hurt Schedrin very much. He
  • would have liked it different; no sooner has the writer said a word,
  • than the reader at once scales the wall. This was his ideal. But the
  • reader is by no means so naive as all that. He prefers to rest easy,
  • and insists that the writer shall climb the wall for him. So those
  • authors succeed with the public who write "with their heart's blood."
  • Conventional tournaments, even the most brilliant, do not attract the
  • masses any more than the connoisseurs. People rush to see a fight of
  • gladiators, where awaits them a scent of real, hot, smoking blood,
  • where they are going to see real, not pretended victims.
  • Thus many writers, like gladiators, shed their blood to gratify that
  • modern Caesar, the mob. "_Salve, Caesar, morituri te salutant_!"
  • 30
  • Anton Tchekhov tells the truth neither out of love or respect for the
  • truth, nor yet because, in the Kantian manner, a high duty bids him
  • never to tell a lie, even to escape death. Neither has he the impulse
  • which so often pushes young and fiery souls into rashness; that desire
  • to stand erect, to keep the head high. On the contrary, Tchekhov always
  • walks with a stoop, his head bent down, never fixing his eyes on the
  • heavens, since he will read no signs there. If he tells the truth, it
  • is because the most reeking lie no longer intoxicates him, even though
  • he swallow it not in the modest doses that idealism offers, but in
  • immoderate quantities, thousand-gallon-barrel gulps. He would taste the
  • bitterness, but it would not make his head turn, as it does Schiller's,
  • or Dostoevsky's, or even Socrates', whose head, as we know, could stand
  • any quantity of wine, but went spinning with the most commonplace lie.
  • 31
  • _Noblesse Oblige_.--The moment of obligation, compulsion, duty, that
  • moment described by Kant as the essential, almost the only predicate
  • of moral concepts, serves chiefly to indicate that Kant was modest in
  • himself and in his attitude towards all whom he addressed, perceiving
  • in all men beings subject to the ennobling effect of morality.
  • _Noblesse oblige_ is a motto not for the aristocracy, which recognises
  • in its privileges its own instant duties, but for the self-made,
  • wealthy _parvenues_ who pant for an illustrious title. They have
  • been accustomed to telling lies, to playing poltroon, swindling, and
  • meanness, and the necessity for speaking the truth impartially, for
  • bravely facing danger, for freely giving of their fortunes scares
  • them beyond measure. Therefore it is necessary that they should
  • repeat it to themselves and to their children, in whose veins the
  • lying, sneaking blood still runs, hourly, lest they forget: "You must
  • not tell lies, you must be open, magnanimous." It is silly, it is
  • incomprehensible--but "_noblesse oblige_."
  • 32
  • _Homo homini lupus_ is one of the most steadfast maxims of eternal
  • morality. In each of our neighbours we fear a wolf. "This fellow is
  • evil-minded, if he is not restrained by law he will ruin us," so we
  • think every time a man gets out of the rut of sanctified tradition.
  • The fear is just. We are so poor, so weak, so easily ruined and
  • destroyed! How can we help being afraid! And yet, behind danger and
  • menace there is usually hidden something significant, which merits
  • our close and sympathetic attention. But fear's eyes are big. We see
  • danger, danger only, we build up a fabric of morality inside which
  • as in a fortress we sit out of danger all our lives. Only poets have
  • undertaken to praise dangerous people--Don Juans, Fausts, Tannhaüsers.
  • But nobody takes the poets seriously. Common-sense values a
  • commercial-traveller or a don much more highly than a Byron, a Goethe,
  • or a Molière.
  • 33
  • The possibilities which open out before mankind are sufficiently
  • limited. It is impossible to see everything, impossible to know
  • everything, impossible to rise too high above the earth, impossible
  • to penetrate too deeply down. What has been is hidden away, what will
  • be we cannot anticipate, and we know for certain that we shall never
  • grow wings. Regularity, immutably regular succession of phenomena puts
  • a term to our efforts, drives us into a regular, narrow, hard-beaten
  • road of everyday life. But even on this road we may not wander from
  • side to side. We must watch our feet, consider each step, since the
  • moment we are off our guard disaster is upon us. Another life is
  • conceivable, however: life in which the word disaster does not exist,
  • where responsibility for one's actions, even if it be not completely
  • abolished, at least has not such a deadly and accidental weight,
  • and where, on the other hand, there is no "regularity," but rather
  • an infinite number of possibilities. In such a life the sense of
  • fear--most disgraceful to us--disappears. There the virtues are not
  • the same as ours. Fearlessness in face of danger, liberality, even
  • lavishness are considered virtues with us, but they are respected
  • without any grounds. Socrates was quite right when he argued that not
  • all courage, but only the courage which measures beforehand the risks
  • and the chances of victory, is fully justifiable. To the same extent
  • those economical, careful people who condemn lavishness are in the
  • right. Fearlessness and lavishness do not suit mortal men, rather it
  • becomes them to tremble and to count every penny, seeing what a state
  • of poverty and impotence they exist in. That is why these two virtues
  • are so rarely met with, and when they are met, why they arouse such
  • superstitious reverence in the crowd. "This man fears nothing and
  • spares nothing: he is probably not a man, but a demi-god, perhaps even
  • a god." Socrates did not believe in gods, so he wanted to justify
  • virtue by reason. Kant also did not believe in God, and therefore he
  • derived his morals from "Law." But if there is God, and all men are the
  • children of God, then we should be afraid of nothing and spare nothing.
  • And then the man who madly dissipates his own life and fortunes, and
  • the lives and fortunes of others, is more right than the calculating
  • philosophers who vainly seek to regulate mankind on earth.
  • 34
  • Moral people are the most revengeful of mankind, they employ their
  • morality as the best and most subtle weapon of vengeance. They are
  • not satisfied with simply despising and condemning their neighbour
  • _themselves_, they want the condemnation to be universal and supreme:
  • that is, that all men should rise as one against the condemned, _and
  • that even the offender's own conscience shall be against him_. Then
  • only are they fully satisfied and reassured. Nothing on earth but
  • morality could lead to such wonderful results.
  • 35
  • _Inveterate wickedness_.--Heretics were often most bitterly persecuted
  • for their least digression from accepted belief. It was just their
  • obstinacy in trifles that irritated the righteous to madness. "Why
  • can they not yield on so trifling a matter? They cannot possibly have
  • serious cause for opposition. They only want to grieve us, to spite
  • us." So the hatred mounted up, piles of faggots and torture machines
  • appeared against obdurate wickedness.
  • 36
  • I do not know where I came across the remark, whether in Tolstoy or
  • Turgenev, that those who have been subjected to trial in the courts
  • of justice always acquire a particularly noble expression of face.
  • Although logic does so earnestly recommend caution in the forming
  • of contradictory conclusions, come what may I shall for once risk a
  • deduction: a noble expression of face is a sign that a man has been
  • under trial--but certainly not a trial for political crime--for theft
  • or bribe-taking.
  • 37
  • The most important and significant revelations come into the world
  • naked, without a wordy garment. To find words for them is a delicate,
  • difficult business, a whole art. Stupidities and banalities, on the
  • contrary, appear at once in ready-made apparel, gaudy even if shabby.
  • So that they are ready straight away to be presented to the public.
  • 38
  • A strange impatience has taken possession of Russian writers lately.
  • They are all running a race after the "ultimate words." They have no
  • doubt that the ultimate words will be attained. The question is, who
  • will lay hold of them first.
  • 39
  • The appearance of Socrates on the philosophic horizon is hailed by
  • historians as the greatest event. Morals were beginning to work
  • loose, Athens was threatened with ruin. Socrates' mission was to put
  • an end to the violent oscillation in moral judgments which extreme
  • individualism on the one hand and the relativism of the sophists on
  • the other had set up. The great teacher did all he could. He gave
  • up his usual occupations and his family life, he took no thought for
  • the morrow, he taught, taught, taught--simple people or eminent, wise
  • or foolish, ignorant or learned. Notwithstanding, he did not save
  • the country. Under Pericles, Athens flourished without wisdom, or at
  • least independently of Socratic wisdom. After Pericles, in spite of
  • the fact that the Socratic teaching found such a genius as Plato to
  • continue it, Athens steadily declined, and Aristotle is already master
  • to the son of Philip of Macedon. Whence it is obvious that the wisdom
  • of Socrates had not saved the country, and as this had been its chief
  • object, it had failed in its object, and therefore was not worthy of
  • the exaggerated respect it received. It is necessary to find some
  • justification for philosophy other than country-saving. This would
  • be the easiest thing in the world. But altogether we must give up
  • the favourite device of the philosophers, of looking to find in the
  • well-being of society the _raison d'être_ of philosophy. At the best,
  • the trick was a risky one. As a rule, wisdom goes one way, society the
  • other. They are artificially connected. It is public orators who have
  • trained both the philosophers and the masses to regard as worthy of
  • attention only those considerations which have absolutely everything on
  • their side: social utility, morality, even metaphysical wisdom.... Why
  • so much? Is it not sufficient if some new project will prove useful?
  • Why try to get the sanction of morality and metaphysics? Nay, once the
  • laws of morality are autonomous, and once ideas are allowed to stand
  • above the empirical needs of mankind, it is impossible to balance ideas
  • and morality with social requirements, or even with the salvation of
  • the Country from ruin. _Pereat mundus, fiat philosophia_. If Athens
  • was ruined because of philosophy, philosophy is not impugned. So the
  • autonomous thinker should hold. But _de facto_ a thinker does not like
  • quarrelling with his country.
  • 40
  • When a writer has to express an idea whose foundation he has not
  • been able to establish, and which yet is dear to his heart, so that
  • he earnestly wishes to secure its general acceptance, as a rule he
  • interrupts his exposition, as if to take breath, and makes a small, or
  • at times a serious digression, during which he proves the invalidity
  • of this or that proposition, often without any reference to his
  • real theme. Having triumphantly exposed one or more absurdities, and
  • thus acquired the aplomb of a solid expert, he returns to his proper
  • task, calculating that now he will inspire his reader with greater
  • confidence. His calculation is perfectly justified. The reader is
  • afraid to attack such a skilled dialectician, and prefers to agree
  • rather than to risk himself in argument. Not even the greatest
  • intellects, particularly in philosophy, disdain such stratagems. The
  • idealists, for example, before expounding their theories, turn and rend
  • materialism. The materialists, we remember, at one time did the same
  • with the idealists, and achieved a vast success.
  • 41
  • Theories of sequence and consequence are binding only upon the
  • disciples, not upon the masters. Fathers of great ideas tend to be
  • very, careless about their progeny, giving very little heed to their
  • future career. The offspring of one and the same philosopher frequently
  • bear such small resemblance to one another, that it is impossible to
  • discern the family connection. Conscientious disciples, wasting away
  • under the arduous effort to discover that which does not exist, are
  • brought to despair of their task. Having got an inkling of the truth
  • concerning their difficulty, they give up the job for ever, they cease
  • their attempt at reconciling glaring contradictions. But then they only
  • insist the harder upon the necessity for studying the philosophers,
  • studying them minutely, circumstantially, historically, philologically
  • even. So the history of philosophy is born, which now is taking the
  • place of philosophy. Certainly the history of philosophy may be an
  • exact science, since by means of historical research it is often
  • possible to decide what exactly a certain philosopher did mean, and in
  • what sense he employed his peculiar terms. And seeing that there have
  • been a fair number of philosophers, the business of clearing them all
  • up is a respectable undertaking, and deserves the name of a science.
  • For a good translation or a commentary on the chief works of Kant a
  • man may be given the degree of doctor of philosophy, and henceforth
  • recognised as one who is initiated in the profundities of the secrets
  • of the universe. Then why ever should anybody think out new systems--or
  • even write them?
  • The raptures of creative activity!--empty words, invented by men who
  • never had an opportunity of judging from their own experience, but who
  • derive their conclusion syllogistically: "if a creation gives us such
  • delight, what must the creator himself experience!" Usually the creator
  • feels only vexations. Every creation is created out of the Void. At the
  • best, the maker finds himself confronted with a formless, meaningless,
  • usually obstinate and stiff matter, which yields reluctantly to
  • form. And he does not know how to begin. Every time a new thought is
  • gendered, so often must that new thought, which for the moment seems
  • so brilliant and fascinating, be thrown aside as worthless. Creative
  • activity is a continual progression from failure to failure, and the
  • condition of the creator is usually one of uncertainty, mistrust, and
  • shattered nerves. The more serious and original the task which a man
  • sets himself, the more tormenting is the self-misgiving. For this
  • reason even men of genius cannot keep up the creative activity to the
  • last. As soon as they have acquired their technique, they begin to
  • repeat themselves, well aware that the public willingly endures the
  • monotony of a favourite, even finds virtue in it. Every connoisseur of
  • art is satisfied if he recognises in a new work the accepted "manner"
  • of the artist. Few realise that the acquiring of a manner is the
  • beginning of the end. Artists realise well enough, and would be glad
  • to be rid of their manner, which seems to them a hackneyed affair. But
  • this requires too great a strain on their powers, new torments, doubts,
  • new groping. He who has once been through the creative raptures is not
  • easily tempted to try again. He prefers to turn out work according
  • to the pattern he has evolved, calmly and securely, assured of his
  • results. Fortunately no one except himself knows that he is not any
  • longer a creator. What a lot of secrets there are in the world, and how
  • easy it is to keep one's secret safe from indiscreet glances!
  • 43
  • A writer works himself up to a pitch of ecstasy, otherwise he does
  • not take up his pen. But ecstasy is not so easily distinguished from
  • other kinds of excitement. And as a writer is always in haste to write,
  • he has rarely the patience to wait, but at the first promptings of
  • animation begins to pour himself forth. So in the name of ecstasy we
  • are offered such quantities of banal, by no means ecstatic effusions.
  • Particularly easy it is to confound with ecstasy that very common
  • sort of spring-time liveliness which in our language is well-named
  • calf-rapture. And calf-rapture is much more acceptable to the public
  • than true inspiration or genuine transport. It is easier, more familiar.
  • 44
  • A school axiom: logical scepticism refutes itself, since the denial
  • of the possibility of positive knowledge is already an affirmation.
  • But, in the first place, scepticism is not bound to be logical, for
  • it has no desire whatever to gratify that dogma which raises logic to
  • the position of law. Secondly, where is the philosophic theory which,
  • if carried to its extreme, would not destroy itself? Therefore, why is
  • more demanded from scepticism than from other systems? especially from
  • scepticism, which honestly avows that it cannot give that which all
  • other theories claim to give.
  • 45
  • The Aristotelian logic, which forms the chief component in modern
  • logic, arose, as we know, as a result of the permanent controversies
  • which were such sport to the Greeks. In order to argue, it is indeed
  • necessary to have a common ground; in other words, to agree about the
  • rules of the game. But in our day dialectic tournaments, like all
  • other bouts of contention, no longer attract people. Thus logic may be
  • relegated to the background.
  • 46
  • In Gogol's _Portrait_, the artist despairs at the thought that he has
  • sacrificed art for the sake of "life." In Ibsen's drama, _When We Dead
  • Awaken_, there is also an artist, who has become world-famous, and who
  • repents that he has sacrificed his life--to art. Now, choose--which of
  • the two ways of repentance do you prefer?
  • 47
  • Man is often quite indifferent to success whilst he has it. But once he
  • loses his power over people, he begins to fret. And--vice versa.
  • 48
  • Turgenev's Insarov strikes the imagination of Elena because he is a
  • man preparing for battle. She prefers him to Shubin the painter, or to
  • Berseniev the savant. Since ancient days women have looked with favour
  • on warriors rather than on peaceful men. Had Turgenev invested that
  • idea with less glamour, he would probably not have become the ideal of
  • the young. Who does not get a thrill from Elena and her elect? Who has
  • not felt the fascination of Turgenev's women! And yet all of them give
  • themselves to the _strong_ male. With such "superior people," as with
  • beasts, the males fight with each other, the woman looks on, and when
  • it is over, she submits herself the slave of the conqueror.
  • 49
  • A caterpillar is transformed into a chrysalis, and for a long
  • time lives in a warm, quiet little world. Perhaps if it had human
  • consciousness it would declare that _that_ world was the best, perhaps
  • the only one possible to live in. But there comes a time when some
  • unknown influence causes the little creature to begin the work of
  • destruction. If other caterpillars could see it how horrified they
  • would be, revolted to the bottom of their soul by the awful work in
  • which the insurgent is engaged. They would call it immoral, godless,
  • they would begin to talk about pessimism, scepticism, and so on. To
  • destroy what has cost such labour to construct! Why, what is wrong
  • with this complete, cosy, comfortable little world? To keep it intact
  • they call to their aid sacred morality and the idealistic theory of
  • knowledge. Nobody cares that the caterpillar has grown wings, that when
  • it has nibbled its old nest away it will fly out into space--nobody
  • gives a thought to this.
  • Wings--that is mysticism; self-nibbling--this is actuality. Those who
  • are engaged in such actuality deserve torture and execution. And there
  • are plenty of prisons and voluntary hangmen on the bright earth. The
  • majority of books are prisons, and great authors are not bad hangmen.
  • 50
  • Nietzsche and Dostoevsky seem to be typical "inverted simulators," if
  • one may use the expression. They imitated spiritual sanity, although
  • they were spiritually insane. They knew their morbidity well enough,
  • but they exhibited their disease only to that extent where freakishness
  • passes for originality. With the sensitiveness peculiar to all who are
  • in constant danger, they never went beyond the limits. The axe of the
  • guillotine of public opinion hung over them: one awkward move, and
  • the execution automatically takes place. But they knew how to avoid
  • unwarrantable moves.
  • 51
  • The so-called ultimate questions troubled mankind in the world's dawn
  • as badly as they trouble us now. Adam and Eve wanted "to know," and
  • they plucked the fruit at their risk. Cain, whose sacrifice did not
  • please God, raised his hand against his brother: and it seemed to him
  • he committed murder in the name of justice, in vindication of his
  • own injured rights. Nobody has ever been able to understand why God
  • preferred Abel's sacrifice to that of Cain. In our own day Sallieri
  • repeats Cain's vengeance and poisons his friend and benefactor Mozzart,
  • according to the poem of Poushkin. "All say, there is no justice on
  • earth; but there is no justice up above: this is as clear to me as a
  • simple scale of music." No man on earth can fail to recognise in these
  • words his own tormenting doubts. The outcome is creative tragedy,
  • which for some mysterious reason has been considered up till now as
  • the highest form of human creation. Everything is being unriddled and
  • explained. If we compare our knowledge with that of the ancients,
  • we appear very wise. But we are no nearer to solving the riddle
  • of eternal justice than Cain was. Progress, civilisation, all the
  • conquests of the human mind have brought us nothing new here. Like our
  • ancestors, we stand still with fright and perplexity before ugliness,
  • disease, misery, senility, death. All that the wise men have been able
  • to do so far is to turn the earthly horrors into problems. We are told
  • that perhaps all that is horrible only _appears_ horrible, that perhaps
  • at the end of the long journey something new awaits us. Perhaps! But
  • the modern educated man, with the wisdom of all the centuries of
  • mankind at his command, knows no more about it than the old singer
  • who solved universal problems at his own risk. We, the children of a
  • moribund civilisation, we, old men from our birth, in this respect are
  • as young as the first man.
  • 52
  • They say it is impossible to set a bound between the "I" and society.
  • _Naïveté_! Crusoes are to be found not only on desert islands. They
  • are there, in populous cities. It is true they are not clad in skins,
  • they have no dark Fridays in attendance, and so nobody recognises them.
  • But surely Friday and a fur jacket do not make a Crusoe. Loneliness,
  • desertion, a boundless, shoreless sea, on which no sail has risen for
  • tens of years,--do not many of our contemporaries live in such a
  • circumstance? And are they not Crusoes, to whom the rest of people have
  • become a vague reminiscence, barely distinguishable from a dream?
  • 53
  • To be irremediably unhappy--this is shameful. An irremediably unhappy
  • person is outside the laws of the earth. Any connection between him
  • and society is severed finally. And since, sooner or later, every
  • individual is doomed to irremediable unhappiness, _the last word, of
  • philosophy is loneliness_.
  • 54
  • "It is better to be an unhappy man, than a happy pig." The utilitarians
  • hoped by this golden bridge to get over the chasm which separates them
  • from the promised land of the ideal. But psychology stepped in and
  • rudely interrupted: _There are no unhappy people, the unhappy ones are
  • all pigs_. Dostoevsky's philosopher of the underworld, Raskolnikov,
  • also Hamlet, and such-like, are not simply unhappy men whose fate
  • might be esteemed, or even preferred before some happy fates; they
  • are simply unhappy swine. And they themselves are principally aware of
  • it.... He that hath ears to hear, let him hear.
  • 55
  • If you want people to envy you your sorrow or your shame, look as if
  • you were proud of it. If you have only enough of the actor in you, rest
  • assured, you will become the hero of the day. Since the parable of the
  • Pharisee and the publican was uttered, what a lot of people who could
  • not fulfil their sacred duties pretended to be publicans and sinners,
  • and so aroused sympathy, even envy.
  • 56
  • Philosophers dearly love to call their utterances "truths," since
  • in that guise they become binding upon us all. But each philosopher
  • invents his own truths. Which means that he asks his pupils to deceive
  • themselves in the way he shows, but that he reserves for himself the
  • option of deceiving himself in his own way. Why? Why not allow everyone
  • to deceive himself just as he likes?
  • 57
  • When Xanthippe poured slops over Socrates, as he returned from his
  • philosophical occupations, tradition says that he observed: "After a
  • storm there is always rain." Would it not be more worthy (not of the
  • philosopher, but of philosophy) to say: After one's philosophical
  • exercise, one feels as if one had had Slops emptied over one's head.
  • And therefore Xanthippe did but give outward expression to what had
  • taken place in Socrates' soul. Symbols are not always beautiful.
  • 58
  • From the notes of an underworld man--"I read little, I write little,
  • and, it seems to me, I think little. He who is ill-disposed towards
  • me will say that this shows a great defect in my character, perhaps
  • he will call me lazy, an Oblomov, and will repeat the copy-book maxim
  • that idleness is the mother of all the vices. A friend, on the other
  • hand, will say it is only a temporary state, that perhaps I am not
  • quite well--in short, he will find random excuses for me, more with the
  • idea of consoling me than of speaking the truth. But for my part, I say
  • let us wait. If it turns out at the end of my life that I have 'done'
  • not less than others--why, then--it will mean that idleness may be a
  • virtue."
  • 59
  • Börne, a contemporary of Heine, was very much offended when his enemies
  • insisted on explaining his misanthropic outpourings as the result of a
  • stomach and liver disease. It seemed to him much nobler and loftier to
  • be indignant and angry because of the triumph of evil on earth, than
  • because of the disorders of his own physical organs. Sentimentality
  • apart--was he right, and is it really nobler?
  • 60
  • A real writer _disdains_ to repeat from hearsay events which he has
  • not witnessed. It seems to him tedious and humiliating to tell "in
  • his own words," like a schoolboy, things which he has fished out of
  • another man's books. But there--how can we expect him to stoop to such
  • insignificance!
  • 61
  • Whilst conscience stands between the educated and the lower classes,
  • as the only possible mediator, there can be no hope for mutual
  • understanding. Conscience demands sacrifices, nothing but sacrifices.
  • It says to the educated man: "You are happy, well-off, learned--the
  • people are poor, unhappy, ignorant; renounce therefore your well-being,
  • or else soothe your conscience with suave speeches." Only he who has
  • nothing to sacrifice, nothing to lose, having lost everything, can hope
  • to approach the people as an equal.
  • This is why Dostoevsky and Nietzsche were not afraid to speak in their
  • own name, and did not feel compelled either to stretch up or to stoop
  • down in order to be on a level with men.
  • 62
  • Not to know what you want is considered a shameful weakness. To confess
  • it is to lose for ever not only the reputation of a writer, but even
  • of a man. None the less, "conscience" demands such a confession. True,
  • in this case as in most others the demands of conscience are satisfied
  • only when they incur no very dire consequences. Leaving aside the fact
  • that people are no longer terrified of the once-so-terrible public
  • opinion (the public has been tamed, it listens with reverence to what
  • is told to it, and never dares judge)--the admission "I do not know
  • myself what I want" seems to offer a guarantee of something important.
  • Those who know what they want generally want trifles, and attain to
  • inglorious ends: riches, fame, or at the best, progress or a philosophy
  • of their own. Even now it is sometimes not a sin to laugh at such
  • wonders, and may-be the time is coming when a rehabilitated Hamlet will
  • announce, not with shame but with pride: "I don't in the least know
  • what I want." And the crowd will applaud him, for the crowd always
  • applauds heroes and proud men.
  • 63
  • Fear of death is explained conclusively by the desire for
  • self-preservation. But at that rate the fear should disappear in old
  • and sick people, who ought by nature to look with indifference on
  • death. Whereas the horror of death is present in all living things.
  • Does not this suggest that there is still some other reason for the
  • dread, and that even where the pangs of horror cannot save a man
  • from his end, still it is a necessary and purposeful anguish? The
  • natural-scientific explanation here, as usual, stops halfway, and
  • fails to lead the human mind to the promised goal.
  • 64
  • Moral indignation is only a refined form of ancient vengeance. Once
  • anger spoke with daggers, now words will do. And happy is the man who,
  • loving and thirsting to chastise his offender, yet is appeased when the
  • offence is punished. On account of the gratification it offers to the
  • passions, morality, which has replaced bloody chastisement, will not
  • easily' lose its charm. But there are offences, deep, unforgettable
  • offences, inflicted not by people, but by "laws of nature." How are we
  • to settle these? Here neither dagger nor indignant word will serve.
  • Therefore, for him who has once run foul of the laws of nature morality
  • sinks, for ever or for a time, into subsidiary importance.
  • 65
  • Fatalism frightens people particularly in that form which holds it just
  • to say, of anything that happens, or has happened, or will happen: be
  • it so! How can one acquiesce in the actuality of life, when it contains
  • so many horrors? But _amor fati_ does not imply eternal acquiescence
  • in actuality. It is only a truce, for a more or less lasting period.
  • Time is needed in which to estimate the forces and intentions of the
  • enemy. Under the mask of friendship the old enmity persists, and an
  • awful revenge is in preparation.
  • 66
  • In the "ultimate questions of life" we are not a bit nearer the truth
  • than our ancestors were. Everybody knows it, and yet so many go on
  • talking about infinity, without any hope of ever saying anything. It
  • is evident that a result--in the usual acceptance of the word--is
  • not necessary. In the very last resort we trust to instinct, even in
  • the field of philosophy, where reason is supposed to reign supreme,
  • uttering its eternal "Why?" "Why?" laughs at all possible "becauses."
  • Instinct, however, does not mock. It simply ignores the whys, and
  • leads us by impossible ways to ends that our divine reason would hold
  • absurd, if it could only see them in time. But reason is a laggard,
  • without much foresight, and, therefore, when we have run up to an
  • unexpected conclusion, nothing remains but for reason to accept: or
  • even to justify, to exalt the new event. And therefore,--"reality is
  • reasonable," say the philosophers: reasonable, not only when they
  • draw their philosophic Salaries, as the socialists, and with them our
  • philosopher Vladimir Soloviov, explain; but still reasonable even
  • when philosophers have their maintenance taken away from them. Nay,
  • in the latter case, particularly in the latter case, in spite of the
  • socialists and VI. Soloviov, reality shows herself most reasonable. A
  • philosopher persecuted, downtrodden, hungry, cold, receiving no salary,
  • is nearly always an extreme fatalist--although this, of course, by no
  • means hinders him from abusing the existing order. Theories of sequence
  • and consequence, as we already know, are binding only upon disciples,
  • whose single virtue lies in their scrupulous, logical developing of the
  • master's idea. But masters themselves _invent_ ideas, and, therefore,
  • have the right to substitute one for another. The sovereign power which
  • proclaims a law has the same power to abolish it. But the duty of the
  • subordinate consists in the praise, in the consequential interpretation
  • and the strict observance of the dictates of the higher will.
  • 67
  • The Pharisee in the parable fulfilled all that religion demanded of
  • him: kept his fasts, paid his tithes, etc. Had he a right to be pleased
  • with his own piety, and to despise the erring publican? Everybody
  • thought so, including the Pharisee himself. _The judgment of Christ
  • came as the greatest surprise to him_. He had a clear conscience.
  • He did not merely pretend before others to be righteous, he himself
  • believed in his own righteousness. And suddenly he turns out guilty,
  • awfully guilty. But if the conscience of a righteous man does not help
  • him to distinguish between good and evil, how is he to avoid sin? What
  • does Kant's moral law mean, that law which was as consoling as the
  • starry sky? Kant lived his life in profound peace of soul, he met his
  • death quietly, in the consciousness of his own purity. But if Christ
  • came again, he might condemn the serene philosopher for his very
  • serenity. For the Pharisee, we repeat, was righteous, if purity of
  • intentions, together with a firm readiness to fulfil everything which
  • appears, to him in the light of duty, be righteousness in a man.
  • 68
  • We jeer and laugh at a man not because he is ridiculous, but because
  • _we_ want to have a laugh out of him. In the same way we are indignant,
  • not because this or the other act is revolting to us, but because we
  • want to let off our steam. But it does not follow from this that we
  • ought always to be calm and smooth. Woe to him who would try to realise
  • the ideal of justice on earth.
  • 69
  • We think with peculiar intensity during the hard moments of our
  • life--we write when we have nothing else to do. So that a writer can
  • only communicate something of importance in reproducing the past. When
  • we are driven to think, we have unfortunately no mind to write, which
  • accounts for the fact that books are never more than a feeble echo of
  • what a man has gone through.
  • 70
  • Tchekhov has a story called _Misfortune_ which well illustrates the
  • difficulty a man finds in adapting himself to a new truth, if this
  • truth threaten the security of his condition. The Merchant Avdeyer
  • does not believe that he is condemned, that he has been brought to
  • trial, and tried, and found guilty, for his irregularities in a public
  • bank. He still thinks the verdict is yet to come--he still waits. In
  • the world of learning something like this is happening. The educated
  • have become so accustomed to think themselves not guilty, perfectly
  • in the right, that they do not admit for a moment even now that they
  • are brought to court. When threatening voices reach them, calling
  • them to give an account of themselves, they only suspiciously shrug
  • their shoulders. "All this will pass away"--they think. Well, when at
  • last they are convinced that misfortune has befallen them, they will
  • probably begin to justify themselves, like Avdeyer, declaring that they
  • cannot even read printed matter sufficiently well. As yet, they pass
  • for respectable, wise, experienced, omniscient men.
  • 71
  • If a man had come to Dostoevsky and said to him, "I am hopelessly
  • unhappy," the great artist in human misery would probably, at the
  • bottom of his soul, have laughed at the naïveté of the poor creature.
  • May one confess such things of oneself? May one go to such lengths of
  • complaint, and still expect consolation from his neighbour?
  • Hopelessness is the most solemn and supreme moment in life. Till that
  • point we have been assisted--now we are left to ourselves. Previously
  • we had to do with men and human laws--now with eternity, and with the
  • complete absence of laws. Is it not obvious?
  • 72
  • Byelinsky, in his famous letter, accuses Gogol, among other things,
  • that in his _Correspondence with Friends_, he, Gogol, succumbs to the
  • fear of death, of devils, and of hell. I find the accusation just:
  • Gogol definitely feared death, demons, and hell. The point is, whether
  • it is not right to fear these things, and whether fearlessness would
  • be a proof of the high development of a man's soul. Schopenhauer
  • asserts that death inspired philosophy. All the best poetry, all the
  • wonderful mythology of the ancients and of modern peoples have for
  • their source the fear of death. Only modern science forbids men to
  • fear, and insists on a tranquil attitude towards death. So we arrive
  • at utilitarianism and the positivist philosophy. If you wish to be rid
  • of both these creeds you must be allowed to think again of death, and
  • without shame to fear hell and its devils. It may be there is really
  • a certain justification for concealing fears of such kind: in the
  • ability to conceal one's agitation at moments of great danger there
  • is a true beauty. But to deaden human sensitiveness and to keep the
  • human intelligence within the bounds of perception, such a task can
  • have charms only for a petty creature. Happily, mankind has no means by
  • which to perform on itself such monstrous castration. Persecuted Eros,
  • it is true, has hidden himself from the eyes of his enemies, but he
  • has never abjured himself; and even the strictest medieval monks could
  • not completely tear out their hearts from their breasts. Similarly
  • with the aspiration towards the infinite: science persecuted it and
  • put a veto on it. But laboratory workers themselves, sooner or later,
  • recover their senses, and thirstily long to get out of the enclosure of
  • positive knowledge, with that same thirsty longing that tortured the
  • monks who wanted to get out of the enclosure of monastery walls.
  • 73
  • If fate--and they say there is such a law--punishes criminals, it has
  • its penalty also for the lovers of good. The former it throttles, the
  • latter it spits upon. The former end in bitter torment, the latter--in
  • ignominy.
  • 74
  • Philosophy has always loved to occupy the position of a servant. In
  • the Middle Ages she was the _ancilla theologiæ_, nowadays she waits on
  • science. At the same time she calls herself the science of sciences.
  • 75
  • I wonder which more effectually makes a man rush forwards without
  • looking back: the knowledge that behind him hovers the head of Medusa,
  • with horrible snakes, ready to turn him into stone; or the certainty
  • that in the rear lies the unchangeable order laid down by the law of
  • causality and by modern science. Judging from what we see, judging
  • from the degree of tension which human thought has reached to-day,
  • it would seem that the head of Medusa is less terrible than the law
  • of causality. In order to escape the latter, man will face anything.
  • Rather than return to the bosom of scientific cause and effect, he
  • embraces madness: not that fine frenzy of madness which spends itself
  • in fiery speeches, but technical madness, for which one is stowed away
  • in a lunatic asylum.
  • 76
  • "To experience a feeling of joy or sorrow, of triumph or despair,
  • _ennui_ or happiness, and so on, without having sufficient cause for
  • such feeling, is an unfailing sign of mental disease...." One of the
  • modern truths which is seeing its last days.
  • 77
  • Count Tolstoy's German biographer regrets the constant misunderstanding
  • and quarrels which took place between Tolstoy and Turgenev. He reminds
  • us of Goethe and Schiller, and thinks that Russian literature would
  • have gained a great deal if the two remarkable Russian writers had
  • been more pacific, had remained on constantly friendly terms with one
  • another, and bequeathed to posterity a couple of volumes of letters
  • dealing with literary and philosophic subjects. It might have been very
  • nice--but I refuse to imagine Tolstoy and Turgenev keeping up a long,
  • peaceful correspondence, particularly on high subjects. Nearly every
  • one of Turgenev's opinions drove Tolstoy to madness, or was capable of
  • so driving him. Dostoevsky's dislike of Turgenev was even stronger than
  • Tolstoy's; he wrote of him very spitefully and offensively, libelling
  • him rather than drawing a caricature. Evidently Dostoevsky, like
  • Tolstoy, detested the "European" in their _confrere._ But here he was
  • mistaken, in spite of his psychological acuteness. To Dostoevsky, it
  • was enough that Turgenev wore European clothes and tried to appear like
  • a westerner. He himself did the opposite: he tried to get rid of every
  • trace of Europeanism from himself, apparently without great success,
  • since he failed to make clear to himself wherein lay the strength of
  • Europe, and where her sting. Nevertheless, the late Mikhailovsky is not
  • wrong in calling Dostoevsky a seeker of buried treasure. Surely, in the
  • second half of his literary activity Dostoevsky no longer sought for
  • the real fruits of life. There awoke in him the Russian, the elemental
  • man, with a thirst for the miraculous. Compared with what he wanted,
  • the fruits of European civilisation seemed to him trivial, flat,
  • insipid. The age-long civilisation of his neighbours told him that
  • there never had been a miracle, and never would be. But all his being,
  • not yet broken-in by civilisation, craved for the stupendous unknown.
  • Therefore, the apparently-satisfied progressivist enraged him. Tolstoy
  • once said of Turgenev: "I hate his democratic backside." Dostoevsky
  • might have repeated these words.... And now, for the gratification
  • of the German critic, please reconcile the Russian writers and make
  • them talk serenely on high-flown matters! Dostoevsky was within a
  • hair's-breath of a quarrel with Tolstoy, with whom, not long before
  • death interrupted him, he began a long controversy concerning "Anna
  • Karenina." Even Tolstoy seemed to him too compliant, too accommodating.
  • 78
  • We rarely make a display of that which is dear to us, near and dear
  • and necessary. On the other hand, we readily exhibit that which is
  • of no importance to us--there is nothing else to be done with it. A
  • man takes his mistress to the theatre and sticks her in full view of
  • everybody; he prefers to remain at home with the woman he loves, or to
  • go about with her quietly, unnoticed. So with our "Virtues." Every time
  • we notice in ourselves some quality we do not prize we haste to make a
  • show of it, thinking perhaps that someone would be glad of it. If it
  • wins us approval, we are pleased--so there is some gain. To an actor,
  • a writer, or an orator, his own antics, without which he can have no
  • success with the public, are often disgusting. And yet his knack of
  • making-such antics he considers a talent, a divine gift, and he would
  • rather die than that it should be lost to the public. Talent, on the
  • whole, is accounted a divine gift, only because it is always on show,
  • because it serves the public in some way or other. All our judgments
  • are permeated through and through with utilitarianism, and were we to
  • attempt to purify them from this adulteration what would remain of
  • modern philosophy? That is why youngish, inexperienced writers usually
  • believe in _harmonia praestabilitata_, even though they have never
  • heard of Leibnitz. They persuade themselves that there is no breach
  • between egoistic and idealistic aspirations; that, for instance, thirst
  • for fame and desire to serve mankind are one and the same thing. Such
  • a persuasion is usually very tenacious of life, and lasts long in men
  • of vigorous and courageous mind. It seems to me that Poushkin would not
  • have lost it, even had he lived to a prolonged old age. It was also
  • part of Turgenev's belief--if a man of his spiritual fibre could have
  • any belief. Tolstoy now believed, and now disbelieved, according to the
  • work he had in hand. When he had other people's ideas to destroy he
  • doubted the identity of egoistic and idealist aspirations; when he had
  • his own to defend, he believed in it. Which is a line of conduct worthy
  • of attention, and supremely worthy of imitation; for human truths are
  • proper exclusively for ancillary purposes....
  • 79
  • Man is such a conservative creature that any change, even a change for
  • the better, scares him, he prefers the bad old way to the new good
  • one. A man who has been all his life a confirmed materialist would
  • not consent to believe that the soul was immortal, not if it were
  • proved to him _more geometrico,_ and not if he were a constitutional
  • coward, fearing death like Shakespeare's Falstaff. Then we must take
  • human conceit into account. Men do not like to admit themselves
  • wrong. It is absurd, but it is so. Men, trivial, wretched creatures,
  • proved by history and by every common event to be bunglers, yet must
  • needs consider themselves infallible, omniscient. What for? Why not
  • admit their ignorance flatly and frankly? True, it is easier said
  • than done. But why should slavish intellect, in spite of our desire
  • to be straightforward, deck us out with would-be truths, of which we
  • cannot divest ourselves even when we know their flimsiness. Socrates
  • wanted to think that he knew nothing--but he could not bring it off.
  • He most absorbedly believed in his own knowledge; nothing could be
  • "truth," except his teaching; he accepted the decree of the oracle,
  • and sincerely esteemed himself the wisest of men. And so it will be,
  • as long as philosophers feel it their duty to teach and to save their
  • neighbours. If a man wants to help people, he is bound to become a
  • liar. We should undertake doubt seriously, not in order to return at
  • length to established beliefs, for that would be a vicious circle.
  • Experience shows us that such a process, certainly in the development
  • of ultimate questions, only leads from error to error; we should doubt
  • _so that doubt becomes a continuous creative force, inspiring the
  • very essence of our life_. For established knowledge argues in us a
  • condition of imperfect receptivity. The weak, flabby spirit cannot
  • bear quick, ceaseless change. It must look round, it must have time
  • to gather its wits, and so it must undergo the same experience time
  • after time. It needs the support and the security of habit, But the
  • well-grown soul despises your crutches. He is tired of crawling on his
  • own cabbage patch, he tears himself away from his own "native" soil,
  • and takes himself off into the far distances, braving the infinitude
  • of space. Surely everybody knows we are not to live in the world for
  • ever. But cowardice prevents one straightforward admitting of it, we
  • keep it close till there is an occasion to air it as a truism. Only
  • when misfortune, disease, old age come upon us, then the dread fear of
  • departure walks with us like our own skeleton. We cannot dismiss him.
  • At length, involuntarily, we begin to examine our gruesome companion
  • with curiosity. And then, strangely enough, we observe that he not only
  • tortures us, but, keeping pace with us, he has begun to gnaw through
  • all the threads that bind us to the old existence. At moments it seems
  • as if, a few more threads gone, nothing, nothing will remain to hold
  • us back, the eternal dream of crawling man will be fulfilled, we shall
  • be released from the bonds, we shall betake ourselves in liberty to
  • regions far from this damned vale of earth....
  • 80
  • Moralists are abused because they offer us "moral consolations."
  • This is not quite fair. Moralists would joyfully substitute palpable
  • blessings for their abstract gifts, _if they could_. When he was young,
  • Tolstoy wanted to make men happy; when he was old, and knew he could
  • not make them happy, he began to preach renunciation, resignation, and
  • so forth. And how angry he got when people wouldn't have his teaching!
  • But if, instead of foisting his doctrines off on us as the solution
  • of the ultimate problems, and as optimism, he had only spoken of the
  • impossibility of finding satisfactory answers, and have offered himself
  • as a pessimist, he would probably have obtained a much more willing
  • hearing. Now he is annoying, because, finding himself unable to relieve
  • his neighbours, he turns to them and insists that they shall consider
  • themselves relieved by him, nay, even made happy by him. To which many
  • will not agree: for why should they voluntarily renounce their rights?
  • Since although, God knows, the right of quarrelling with one's fate,
  • and cursing it, is not a very grand right, still, it _is_ a right ...
  • 81
  • Ivanov, in Tchekhov's drama of that name, compares himself to an
  • overstrained labourer. The labourer dies, so that all that remains to
  • Ivanov is to die. But logic, as you know, recommends great caution in
  • coming to conclusions by analogy. Behold Tchekhov himself, who, as far
  • as we can judge, had endured in his own soul all the tragedy, just as
  • Ivanov had, did not die or think of dying, or even turn out a wasted
  • man. He is doing something, he struggles, he seeks, his work seems
  • important and considerable to us, just like other human works. Ivanov
  • shot himself because the drama _must_ end, while Tchekhov had not yet
  • finished his own struggle. Our aesthetics demand that the drama must
  • have a climax and a finale: though we have abandoned the Aristotelian
  • unities. Given a little more time, however, dramatic writers will have
  • got rid of this restriction also. They will frankly confess that they
  • do not know how, or with what event to end their dramas. Stories have
  • already learnt to dispense with an ending.
  • 82
  • More of the same.--Ivanov says: "Now, where is my salvation? In what?
  • If an intelligent, educated, healthy man for no discoverable reason
  • sets up a Lazarus lament and starts to roll down an inclined plane,
  • then he is rolling without resisting, and there is no salvation for
  • him." One way out would be to accept the inclined plane and the
  • gathering impetus as normal. Even further, one might find in the
  • rolling descent a proof of one's spiritual superiority to other men.
  • Of course in such a case one should go apart from the rest, not court
  • young girls or fraternise with those who are living the ordinary life,
  • but be alone. "Love is nonsense, caresses maudlin, work is meaningless,
  • and song and fiery speeches are banal, played-out," continued
  • Ivanov. To young Sasha these words are horrible,--but Ivanov will be
  • responsible for them. He is already responsible for them. That he is
  • tottering is nothing: it is still full early for him to shoot himself.
  • He will live whilst his creator, Tchekhov, lives. And we shall listen
  • to the shaky, vacillating philosophy. We are so sick of symmetry and
  • harmony and finality, sick as we are of bourgeois self-complacency.
  • 83
  • It will be seen from the above that already in _Ivanov_, one of his
  • early works, Tchekhov has assumed the rôle of _advocatus diaboli_.
  • Wherever Ivanov appears he brings ruin and destruction. It is true,
  • Tchekhov hesitates to take his side openly, and evidently does not know
  • what to do with his hero, so that in the end he shakes him off, so
  • to speak, he washes his hands of him in the accepted fashion: Ivanov
  • shoots himself in the sight of everybody, has not even time to go
  • discreetly into a corner. The only justification of _Ivanov_ is that
  • caricature of honesty, Doctor Lvov. Lvov is not a living figure--that
  • is obvious. But this is why he is remarkable. It is remarkable that
  • Tchekhov should deem it necessary to resurrect the forgotten Starodoum,
  • that utterer of truisms in Fon-Visin's comedy; and to resurrect him
  • no longer that people may bow their heads before the incarnation of
  • virtue, but so that they shall jeer at him. Look at Doctor Lvov! Is he
  • not Starodoum alive again? He is honesty personified. From force of
  • old habit, honesty sticks his chest out, and speaks in a loud voice,
  • with imperious tone, and yet not one of this old loyal subjects gives
  • a brass farthing for him. They don't even trouble to gibe at him,
  • but spit on him and shove him through the door, as a disgusting and
  • impudent toady. Poor honesty! What has he sunk to! Evidently virtues,
  • like everything else, should not live too long on earth.
  • Tchekhov's "Uncle Vanya" is waiting to throw himself on the neck of
  • his friend and rival, the doctor, throw himself on his neck and sob
  • there like a little child, But he finds that the doctor himself has
  • an unquenchable thirst for consolation and encouragement, whilst poor
  • Sonia can bear her maiden sorrows no longer. They all go wandering
  • round with big, lost eyes, looking for someone to relieve them from
  • _part_ of their woes, at least. And lo, everybody is in the same street
  • as themselves. All are over-heavy-laden, not one can carry his own
  • burden, let alone give a lift to another's. The last consolation is
  • taken away. It is no use complaining: there is no sympathetic response.
  • On all faces the same expression of hopelessness and despair. Each must
  • bear his cross in silence. None may weep nor utter pitiful cries--it
  • would be uncalled-for and indecent. When Uncle Vanya, who has not
  • realised at once the extremity of his situation, begins to cry out:
  • "My life's a waste!" nobody wants to listen to him. "Waste, waste!
  • Everybody knows it's a waste! Shut your mouth, howling won't help you:
  • neither will pistol-shots solve anything. Everyone of us might start
  • your cry--but we don't, neither do we shout:
  • _--You think I'll weep_;
  • _No, I'll not weep: I have full cause of weeping,_
  • _But this heart shall break into a hundred thousand flaws_,
  • _Or ere I'll weep; O Fool, I shall go mad_."
  • Gradually there settles down a dreadful, eternal silence of the
  • cemetery. All go mad, without words, they realise what is happening
  • within them, and make up their minds for the last shift: to hide
  • their grief for ever from men, and to speak in commonplace, trivial
  • words which will be accepted as sensible, serious, and even lofty
  • expressions. No longer will anyone cry: "Life is a waste," and intrude
  • his feelings on his neighbours. Everybody knows that it is shameful for
  • one's life to be a waste, and that this shame should be hidden from
  • every eye. The last law on earth is--loneliness.
  • _Résigne-toi, mon cœur, dors ton sommeil de brute_!
  • 85
  • _Groundless assumptions_.--"Based on nothing," because they seem to
  • derive from common assumption of the reasonableness of human existence,
  • which assumption surely is the child of our desires, and probably a
  • bastard at that..... In his _Miserly Knight_ Poushkin represented a
  • miser as a romantic figure. Gogol, with his Plyushkin, creates on the
  • contrary a repulsive figure of a miser. Gogol was nearer to reality. A
  • miser is ugly, whatever view you take of him--inward or outward. Yet
  • Gogol ought not to teach people to preserve in their age the ideals of
  • their youth. Once old age is upon us--it must not be improved upon,
  • much less apologised for. It must be accepted, and its essence brought
  • to light. Plyushkin, the vulgar, dirty maniac is disgusting--but who
  • knows? perhaps he is fulfilling the serious mission of his own being.
  • He is possessed by one desire--to everything else, to all happenings in
  • the outer world he is indifferent. It is the same to him whether he is
  • hungry or full, warm or cold, clean or dirty. Practically no event can
  • distract his attention from his single purpose. He is disinterestedly
  • mean, if one may say so. He has no need for his riches. He lets them
  • rot in a disgusting heap, and does not dream, like Poushkin's knight,
  • of palaces and power, or of sportive nymphs. Upon what end is he
  • concentrated? No one has the time to think it out. At the sight of
  • Plyushkin everyone recalls the damage the miser has done. Everyone
  • of course is right: Plyushkins, who heap up fortunes to let them rot,
  • are very harmful. The social judgment is nearly always to the point.
  • But not quite always. It won't hurt morals and social considerations
  • if at times they have to hold their tongue--and at such times we might
  • succeed in guessing the riddle of meanness, sordidness, old age.
  • 86
  • We have sufficient grounds for taking life mistrustfully: it has
  • defrauded us so often of our cherished expectations. But we have still
  • stronger grounds for mistrusting reason: since if life deceived us, it
  • was only because futile reason let herself be deceived. Perhaps reason
  • herself invented the deception, and then to serve her own ambitious
  • ends, threw the blame on life, so that life shall appear sick-headed.
  • But if we have to choose between life and reason, we choose life, and
  • then we no longer need try to foresee and to explain, we can wait, and
  • accept all that is unalterable as part of the game. And thus Nietzsche,
  • having realised that all his hopes had gradually crumbled, and that
  • he could never get back to his former strength, but must grow worse
  • and worse every day, wrote in a private letter of May 28, 1883: "_Ich
  • will es so schwer haben, wie nur irgend ein Mensch es hat; erst writer
  • diesem Drucke gewinne ich das gute Gewissen dafür, etwas zu besitzen,
  • das wenige Menschen haben und gehabt haben: Flügel, um im Gleichnisse
  • zu reden_." In these few simple words lies the key to the philosophy of
  • Nietzsche.
  • 87
  • "So long as Apollo calls him not to the sacred offering, of all the
  • trifling children of men the most trifling perhaps is the poet." Put
  • Poushkin's expression into plain language, and you will get a page
  • on neuropathology. All neurasthenic individuals sink from a state of
  • extreme excitation to one of complete prostration. Poets too: and they
  • are proud of it.
  • 88
  • Shy people usually receive their impressions post-dated. During those
  • moments when an event is taking place before their eyes, they can see
  • nothing, only later on, having evoked from their memory a fragment of
  • what happened, they make for themselves an impression of the whole
  • scene. And then, retrospectively arise in their soul feelings of pity,
  • offence, surprise, so vivid, as if they were the flames of the instant
  • moment, not rekindlings from the past. Thus shy people always think a
  • great deal, and are always too late for their work. It is never too
  • late for thought. Timid before others, they reach great heights of
  • daring when alone. They are bad speakers--but often excellent writers.
  • Their life is insignificant and tedious, they are not noticed,--until
  • they become famous. And by the time fame comes, they do not need
  • popular attention any more.
  • 89
  • If Tchekhov's Layevsky, in _The Duel_, had been a writer with a
  • literary talent, people would have said of him that he was original,
  • and that he was engaged in the study of the "mysticism of sex," like
  • Gabriele D'Annunzio for example; whereas, as he stands, he is only
  • banal. His idleness is a reproach to him: people would prefer that at
  • least he should copy out extracts from documents.
  • 90
  • _From observations on children_.--Egoism in a man strikes us
  • unpleasantly because it betrays our poverty. "I cannot dole out my
  • abundance to my neighbour, for if I do I myself shall be left with
  • little." We should like to be able to scatter riches with a royal hand;
  • and, therefore, when we see someone else clutching his rags with the
  • phrase, "property is sacred," we are hurt. What is sacred comes from
  • the gods, and the gods have plenty of everything, they do not count and
  • skimp, like mortals.
  • 91
  • We see a man repent for his actions, and conclude that such actions
  • should be avoided: an instance of false, but apparently irreproachable
  • reasoning. Time passes, and we see the same man repenting again of the
  • self-same acts. If we love logic, this will confirm us in our first
  • conclusion. But if we do not care for logic, we shall say: man is
  • under an equal necessity to commit these acts, and to repent of them.
  • Sometimes, however, the first conclusion is corrected differently.
  • Having decided that repentance proves that a certain course of action
  • should be avoided, man avoids it all his life; only to realise in the
  • end, suddenly, with extraordinary clarity, how bitter is his regret
  • that he has not trodden the forbidden course. But by this time a new
  • conclusion is already useless. Life is over, and the newly-enlightened
  • mind no longer knows how to rid itself of the Superfluous light.
  • 92
  • A version of one of the scenes of Tolstoy's _Power of Darkness_ reminds
  • us exactly of a one-act piece of Maeterlinck. There can be no question
  • of imitation. When the _Power of Darkness_ was written nobody had
  • heard of Maeterlinck. Tolstoy evidently wanted to try a new method
  • of creating, and to get rid of his own manner, which he had evolved
  • through tens of years of dogged labour. But the risk was too great. He
  • preferred to cure himself of his doubts by the common expedient, manual
  • toil and an outdoor life. So he took up the plough.
  • 93
  • Every woodcock praises its own fen; Lermontov saw the sign of spiritual
  • pre-eminence in dazzling white linen, and therefore his heroes always
  • dressed with taste. Dostoevsky, on the other hand, despised show:
  • Dmitri Karamazov wears dirty linen--and this is assigned to him as a
  • merit, or almost a merit.
  • 94
  • While he was yet young, when he wrote his story, _Enough_, Turgenev
  • saw that something terrible hung over his life. He saw, but did not
  • get frightened, although he understood that in time he ought to become
  • frightened, because life without a continual inner disturbance would
  • have no meaning for him.
  • 95
  • Napoleon is reputed to have had a profound insight into the human soul;
  • Shakespeare also. And their vision has nothing in common.
  • 96
  • What we call imagination, which we value so highly in great poets--is,
  • essentially, unbridled, loose, or if you will, even perverted
  • mentality. In ordinary mortals we call it vice; but to the poets
  • everything is forgiven on account of the benefit and pleasure we derive
  • from their works. In spite of our high-flown theories we have always
  • been extremely practical, great utilitarians. Two-and-a-half-thousand
  • years went by before Tolstoy got up, and, in his turn, offered the
  • poets their choice: either to be virtuous, or to stop creating and
  • forfeit the fame of teachers. If Tolstoy did not make a laughing-stock
  • of himself, he has to thank his grey hairs and the respect which was
  • felt for his past. Anyhow, nobody took him seriously. Far from it;
  • for never yet did poets feel so free from the shackles of morality
  • as they do now. If Schiller were writing his dramas and philosophic
  • essays to-day, he would scarcely find a reader. In Tolstoy himself it
  • is not so much his virtues as his vices which we find interesting.
  • We begin to understand his works, not so much in the light of his
  • striving after ideals, but from the standpoint of that incongruity
  • which existed between the ideas he artificially imposed upon himself,
  • and the demands of his own non-virtu ous soul, which struggled ever
  • for liberty. Nicolenka Irtenyev, in _Childhood, and Youth_, would sit
  • for hours on the terrace, turning over in his mind his elder brother
  • Volodya's love-making with the chambermaids. But, although he desired
  • it "_more than anything on earth_" he could never bring himself to
  • be like Volodya. The maid said to the elder brother, "Why doesn't
  • Nicolai Fetrovitch ever come here and have a lark?" She did not know
  • that Nicolai Petrovitch was sitting at that moment under the stairs,
  • ready to give _anything on earth_ to take the place of the scamp
  • Volodya. "_Everything on earth_" is twice repeated. Tolstoy gives a
  • psychological explanation of his little hero's conduct. "I was timid
  • by nature," Nicolenka tells us, "but my shyness was increased by the
  • conviction of my ugliness." Ugliness, the consciousness of one's
  • ugliness, leads to shyness! What good can there be in virtue which
  • has such a suspicious origin? And how can the morality of Tolstoy's
  • heroes be trusted i Consciousness of one's ugliness begets shyness,
  • shyness drives the passions inwards and allows them no natural outlet.
  • Little by little there develops a monstrous discrepancy between the
  • imagination and its desires, on the one hand, and the power to satisfy
  • these desires, on the other. Permanent hunger, and a contracted
  • alimentary canal, which does not pass the food through. Hence the
  • hatred of the imagination, with its unrealised and unrealisable
  • cravings.... In our day no one has scourged love so cruelly as Tolstoy
  • in _Power of Darkness_. But the feats of the village Don Juan need not
  • necessarily end in tragedy. "More than anything on earth," however,
  • Tolstoy hates the Don Juans, the handsome, brave, successful, the
  • self-confident, who spontaneously act upon suggestion, the conquerors
  • of women, who stretch out their hands to living statues cold as stone.
  • As far as ever he can he has his revenge on them in his writing.
  • 97
  • In the drama of the future the whole presentation will be different.
  • First of all, the difficulties of the dénouement will be set aside.
  • The new hero has a past-reminiscent--but no present; neither wife,
  • nor sweetheart, nor friends, nor occupation. He is alone, he communes
  • only with himself or with imaginary listeners. He lives a life apart.
  • So that the stage will represent either a desert island or a room in
  • a large densely-populated city, where among millions of inhabitants
  • one can live alone as on a desert island. The hero must not return
  • to people and to social ideals. He must go forward to loneliness, to
  • absolute loneliness. Even now nobody, looking at Gogol's Plyushkin,
  • will feel any more the slightest response to the pathetic appeal for
  • men to preserve the ideals of youth on into old age. Modern youths go
  • to see Plyushkin, not for the sake of laughing at him or of benefiting
  • from the warning which his terrible miserly figure offers them, but in
  • order to see if there may not be some few little pearls there where
  • they could be least expected, in the midst of his heap of dirt.
  • ... Lycurgus succeeded in fixing the Spartans like cement for some
  • centuries--but after that came the thaw, and all their hardness
  • melted. The last remains of the petrified Doric art are now removed to
  • museums.... Is something happening----?
  • 98
  • If I sow not in the spring, in autumn I shall eat no bread. Every
  • day brings troubles and worries enough for poor, weak man. He had
  • to forget his work for a moment, and now he is lost: he will die of
  • hunger or cold. In order merely to preserve our existence we have to
  • strain mind and body to the utmost: nay more, we have to think of the
  • surrounding world exclusively with a view to gaining a livelihood from
  • it. There is no time to think about truth! This is why positivism was
  • invented, with its theory of natural development. Really, everything
  • we see is mysterious and incomprehensible. A tiny midge and a huge
  • elephant, a caressing breeze and a blizzard, a young tree and a
  • rocky mountain--what are all these? What are they, why are they? we
  • incessantly ask ourselves, but we may not speak out. For philosophy is
  • ever pushed aside to make room for the daily needs. Only those think
  • who are unable to trouble about self-preservation, or who will not
  • trouble, or who are too careless: that is, sick, desperate, or lazy
  • people. These return to the riddle which workaday men, confirmed in the
  • certainty that they are right, have construed into "naturalness."
  • 99
  • Kant, and after him Schopenhauer, was exceedingly fond of the epithet
  • "disinterested," and used it on every occasion when the supply of
  • laudatory terms he had at his disposal was exhausted. "Disinterested
  • thinking," which does not pursue any practical aim, is, according to
  • Schopenhauer, the highest ideal towards which man can strive. This
  • truth he considered universal, an _a priori_. But had he chanced to
  • be brought amongst Russian peasants he would have had to change his
  • opinion. With them thoughts about destiny and the why and wherefore of
  • the universe and infinity and so on, would by no means be considered
  • disinterested, particularly if the man who devoted himself to such
  • thoughts were at the same time to announce, as becomes a philosopher,
  • that he claimed complete freedom from physical labour. There the
  • philosopher, were he even Plato, would be stigmatised with the
  • disgraceful nickname, "Idle-jack." There the highest activity is
  • interested activity, directed towards strictly practical purposes; and
  • if the peasants could speak learnedly, they would certainly call the
  • principle upon which their judgment is founded an _a priori_. Tolstoy,
  • who draws his wisdom from the folk-sources, attacks the learned for
  • the very fact that they do not want to work, but are disinterestedly
  • occupied in the search for truth.
  • 100
  • It is clear to any impartial observer that practically every man
  • changes his opinion ten times a day. Much has been said on this
  • subject, it has served for innumerable satires and humorous sketches.
  • Nobody has ever doubted that it was a vice to be unstable is one's
  • opinions. Three-fourths of our education goes to teaching us most
  • carefully to conceal within ourselves the changeableness of our moods
  • and judgments. A man who cannot keep his word is the last of men:
  • never to be trusted. Likewise, a man with no firm convictions: it is
  • impossible to work together with him. Morality, here as always making
  • towards utilitarian ends, issues the "eternal" principle: thou shalt
  • remain true to thy convictions. In cultured circles this commandment
  • is considered so unimpeachable that men are terrified even to appear
  • inconstant in their own eyes. They become petrified in their beliefs,
  • and no greater shame can happen to them than that they should be
  • forced to admit that they have altered in their convictions. When a
  • straightforward man like Montaigne plainly speaks of the inconstancy of
  • his mind and his views, he is regarded as a libeller of himself. One
  • need neither see, nor hear, nor understand what is taking place around
  • one: once your mind is made up, you have lost your right to grow, you
  • must remain a stock, a statue, the qualities and defects of which are
  • known to everybody.
  • 101
  • Every philosophic world-conception starts from some or other solution
  • of the general problem of human existence, and proceeds from this to
  • direct the course of human life in some particular direction or other.
  • We have neither the power nor the data for the solution of general
  • problems, and consequently all our moral deductions are arbitrary,
  • they only witness to our prejudices if we are naturally timid, or to
  • our propensities and tastes if we are self-confident. But to keep up
  • prejudices is a miserable, unworthy business: nobody will dispute that.
  • Therefore let us cease to grieve about our differences in opinion,
  • let us wish that in the future there should be many more differences,
  • and much less unanimity. There is no arbitrary truth: it remains to
  • suppose that truth lies in changeable human tastes and desires. In so
  • far as our common social existence demands it--let us try to come to
  • an understanding, to agree: but not one jot more. Any agreement which
  • does not arise out of common necessity will be a crime against the Holy
  • Spirit.
  • 102
  • Tchekhov was very good at expounding a system of philosophy--even
  • several systems. We have examples in more than one of his stories,
  • particularly in _The Duel,_ where Fon-Koren speaks _ex cathedra_.
  • But Tchekhov had no use for such systems, save for purely literary
  • purposes. When you write a story, and your hero must speak clearly
  • and consistently, a system has its value. But when you are left to
  • yourself, can you seriously trouble your soul about philosophy? Even
  • a German cannot, it seems, go so far in his "idealism." Vladimir
  • Semionovitch, the young author in Tchekhov's _Nice People_, sincerely
  • and deeply believes in his own ideas, but even of him, notwithstanding
  • his blatantly comical limitations, we cannot say more than that
  • his ideas were constant little views or pictures to him, which had
  • gradually become a second natural setting to everything he saw.
  • Certainly he did not live by ideas. Tchekhov is right when he says that
  • the singing of _Gaudeamus igitur_ and the writing of a humanitarian
  • appeal were equally important to Vladimir Semionovitch. As soon as
  • Vladimir's sister begins to think for herself, her brother's highest
  • ideas, which she has formerly revered, become banal and objectionable
  • to her. Her brother cannot understand her, neither her hostility
  • to progress and humanitarianism, nor to the university spree and
  • _Gaudeamus igitur._ But Tchekhov _does_ understand. Only, let us
  • admit, the word "understand" does not carry its ordinary meaning
  • here. So long as the child was fed on its mother's milk, everything
  • seemed to it smooth and easy. But when it had to give up milk and take
  • to vodka,--and this is the inevitable law of human development--the
  • childish suckling dreams receded into the realm of the irretrievable
  • past.
  • 103
  • The summit of human existence, say the philosophers, is spiritual
  • serenity, _aequanimitas_: But in that case the animals should be our
  • ideal, for in the matter of imperturbability they leave nothing to be
  • desired. Look at a grazing sheep, or a cow. They do not look before
  • and after, and sigh for what is not. Given a good pasture, the present
  • suffices them perfectly.
  • 104
  • A hungry man was given a piece of bread, and a kind word. The kindness
  • seemed more to him than the bread. But had he been given only the kind
  • word and no bread, he would perhaps have hated nice phrases. Therefore,
  • caution is always to be recommended in the drawing of conclusions:
  • and in none more than in the conclusion that truth is more urgently
  • required than a consoling lie. The connections of isolated phenomena
  • can very rarely be discerned. As a rule, several causes at once produce
  • one effect. Owing to our propensity for idealising, we always make
  • prominent that cause which seems to us loftiest.
  • 105
  • A strange anomaly! we see thousands of human beings perish around us,
  • yet we walk warily lest we crush a worm. The sense of compassion is
  • strong in us, but it is adapted to the conditions of our existence. It
  • can relieve an odd case here and there--and it raises a terrific outcry
  • over a trifling injustice. Yet Schopenhauer wanted to make compassion
  • the metaphysical basis of morality.
  • 106
  • To discard logic as an instrument, a means or aid for acquiring
  • knowledge, would be extravagant. Why should we? For the sake of
  • consequentialism? _i.e._ for logic's very self? But logic, as an aim
  • in itself, or even as the _only_ means to knowledge, is a different
  • matter. Against this one must fight even if he has against him all the
  • authorities of thought--beginning with Aristotle.
  • 107
  • "When the yellowing corn-fields sway and are moved, and the fresh
  • forest utters sound to the breeze ... then I see happiness on earth,
  • and God in heaven." It may be so, to the poet; but it may be quite
  • different. Sometimes the corn-field waves, the woods make noise in
  • the wind, the stream whispers its best tales: and still man cannot
  • perceive happiness, nor forget the lesson taught in childhood, that
  • the blue heavens are only an optical illusion. But if the sky and the
  • boundless fields do not convince, is it possible that the arguments of
  • Kant and the commentations of his dozens of talentless followers can do
  • anything?
  • 108
  • _The greatest temptation_.--In Dostoevsky's _Grand Inquisitor_
  • lurks a dreadful idea. Who can be sure, he says--metaphorically, of
  • course--that when the crucified Christ uttered His cry: "Lord, why hast
  • thou forsaken me?" He did not call to mind the temptation of Satan, who
  • for one word had offered Him dominion over the world? And, if Jesus
  • recollected this offer, how can we be sure that He did not repent not
  • having taken it?... One had better not be told about such temptations.
  • 109
  • From the "_Future Opinions concerning contemporary Europe_."--"Europe
  • of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries presented a strange
  • picture. After Luther, Christianity degenerated into morality, and
  • all the threads connecting man with God were cut. Together with
  • the rationalisation of religion, all life took on a fiat, rational
  • character. Knights were replaced by a standing army, recruited on the
  • principle of compulsory military service for all, and existing chiefly
  • for the purpose of parades and official needs. Alchemy, which had been
  • trying to find the philosopher's stone, was replaced by chemistry,
  • which tried to discover the best means for cheap preparation of cheap
  • commodities. Astrology, which had sought in the stars the destinies
  • of men, was replaced by astronomy, which foretold the eclipses of the
  • sun and the appearing of comets. Even the dress of the people became
  • strangely colourless; not only men, but women also wore uniform,
  • monochromatic clothes. Most remarkable of all, that epoch did not
  • notice its own insignificance, but was even proud of itself. It seemed
  • to the man of that day that never before had the common treasury of
  • spiritual riches been so well replenished. We, of course, may smile at
  • their naïveté, but if one of their own number had allowed himself to
  • express an opinion disdainful of the bases of the contemporary culture
  • he would have been declared immoral, or put away in a mad-house: a
  • terrible punishment, very common in that coarse period, though now
  • it is very difficult even to imagine what such a proceeding implied.
  • But in those days, to be known as immoral, or to find oneself in a
  • mad-house, was worse than to die. One of the famous poets of the
  • nineteenth century, Alexander Poushkin, said: 'God forbid that I should
  • go mad. Rather let me be a starving beggar.' In those times people,
  • on the whole, were compelled to tell lies and play the hypocrite, so
  • that not infrequently the brightest minds, who saw through the shams of
  • their epoch, yet pretended to believe in science and morality, only in
  • order to escape the persecution of public opinion."
  • 110
  • _Writers of tragedies on Shakespeare's model._--To obtain a spark,
  • one must strike with all one's might with an iron upon a stone.
  • Whereupon there is a loud noise, which many are inclined to believe
  • more important than the little spark. Similarly, writers having shouted
  • very loudly, are deeply assured that they have fulfilled their sacred
  • mission, and are amazed that all do not share their raptures, that some
  • even stop their ears and run away.
  • 111
  • _Metamorphoses_.--Sense and folly are not at all native qualities
  • in a man. In a crisis, a stupid man becomes clever. We need not go
  • far for an example. What a gaping simpleton Dostoevsky looks in his
  • _Injured and Insulted_, not to mention _Poor Folk_. But in _Letters
  • from the Underworld_ and the rest of his books he is the shrewdest and
  • cleverest of writers. The same may be said of Nietzsche, Tolstoy, or
  • Shakespeare. In his _Birth of Tragedy_ Nietzsche seems just like the
  • ordinary honest, rather simple, blue-eyed provincial German student,
  • and in _Zarathustra_ he reminds one of Machiavelli. Poor Shakespeare
  • got himself into a row for his Brutus--but no man could deny the great
  • mind in _Hamlet._ The best instance of all, however, is Tolstoy. Right
  • up to to-day, whenever he likes he can be cleverer than the cleverest.
  • Yet at times he is a schoolboy. This is the most interesting and
  • enviable trait in him.
  • 112
  • In _Troilus and Cressida_ Thersites says: "Shall the elephant Ajax
  • carry it thus? He beats me, and I rail at him: O worthy satisfaction!
  • would it were otherwise; that I could beat him, whilst he railed at
  • me." Dostoevsky might have said the same of his opponents. He pursued
  • them with stings, sarcasm, abuse, and they drove him to a white heat
  • by their quiet assurance and composure.... The present-day admirers of
  • Dostoevsky _quietly believe_ in the teachings of their master. Does it
  • not mean that _de facto_ they have betrayed him and gone over to the
  • side of his enemies.
  • 113
  • The opinion has gained ground that Turgenev's ideal women--Natalie,
  • Elena, Marianna--are created in the image and likeness of Poushkin's
  • Tatyana. The critics have been misled by external appearances. To
  • Poushkin his Tatyana appears as a vestal guarding the sacred flame
  • of high morality--because such a job is not fitting for a male. The
  • Pretender in _Boris Godunov_ says to the old monk Pimen, who preaches
  • meekness and submission: "But you fought under the walls of Kazan,
  • etc." That is a man's work. But in the hours of peace and leisure the
  • fighter needs his own hearth-side, he must feel assured that at home
  • his rights are safely guarded. This is the point of Tatyana's last
  • words: "I belong to another, and shall remain forever true to him." But
  • in Turgenev woman appears as the judge and the reward, sometimes even
  • the inspirer of victorious man. There is a great difference.
  • 114
  • From a German _Introduction to Philosophy_.--"We shall maintain the
  • opinion that metaphysics, as the crown of the particular sciences, is
  • possible and desirable, and that to it falls the task intermediate
  • between theory and practice, experiment and anticipation, mind and
  • feeling, the task of weighing probabilities, balancing arguments,
  • and reconciling difficulties." Thus metaphysics is a weighing of
  • probabilities. _Ergo_--further than probable conclusions it cannot
  • go. Thus why do metaphysicians pretend to universal and obligatory,
  • established and eternal judgments? They go beyond themselves. In the
  • domain of metaphysics there cannot and must not be any established
  • beliefs. The word established loses all its sense in the connection. It
  • is reasonable to speak of eternal hesitation and temporality of thought.
  • 115
  • From another _Introduction to Philosophy,_ also German. "Compared
  • with the delusion of the materialists ... the wretchedest worshipper
  • of idols seems to us a being capable of apprehending to a certain
  • degree the great meaning and essence of things," Perhaps this thought
  • strayed in accidentally among the huge herd of the other thoughts of
  • the professor, so little does it resemble the rest. But even so, it
  • loses none of its interest. If the materialists here spoken of, those
  • of the nineteenth century, Buchner, Vogt, Moleschot, all of them men
  • who stood on the pinnacle of natural science, were capable of proving
  • in the realm of philosophy more uninformed than the nakedest savage,
  • then it follows, not only that science has nothing in common with
  • philosophy, but that the two are even hostile. Therefore we ought to
  • go to the savages, not to civilise them, but even to learn philosophy
  • from them. A Papuan or a Tierra del Fuegan delivering a lecture in
  • philosophy to the professors of the Berlin University--Friedrich
  • Paulsen, for example--is a curious sight. I say to Friedrich Paulsen,
  • and not to Buchner or Moleschot, because Paulsen is also an educated
  • person, and therefore his _philosophic_ sensibility may have suffered
  • from contact with science, even if not so badly as that of the
  • materialists. He needs the assistance of a red-skinned master. Why
  • have German professors so little daring or enterprise? Why should not
  • Paulsen, on his own initiative, go to Patagonia to perfect himself in
  • philosophy?--or at least send his pupils there, and preach broadcast
  • the new pilgrimage. And now lo and behold he has hatched an original
  • and fertile idea, so he will stick in a corner with it, so that even if
  • you wanted you could not get a good look at it. The idea is important
  • and weighty: our philosophers would lose nothing by sitting at the feet
  • of the savages.
  • 116
  • From a _History of Ethics_.--"Doubts concerning the existence or
  • the possibility of discovering a moral norm have, _of course_ (I
  • underline it), proved a stimulus to a new speculative establishing
  • of ethics, just as the denial of the possibility of knowledge led to
  • the discovery of the condition of knowledge." With this proposition
  • the author does not play hide-and-seek, as Paulsen with his. He places
  • it in a conspicuous position, in a conspicuous section of his book,
  • and accompanies it with the trumpeting herald "of course." But only
  • one thing is clear: namely, that the majority share the opinion of
  • Professor Yodl, to whom the quoted words belong. So that the first
  • assumption of ethics has as its foundation the _consensus sapientium_.
  • It is enough.
  • 117
  • "The normative theory," which has taken such hold in Germany and
  • Russia, bears the stamp of that free and easy self-assurance which
  • characterises the state of contentment, and which does not desire, even
  • for the sake of theoretical perfection, to take into consideration the
  • divided state of soul which usually accompanies discontent. Windelband
  • (_Praeludien_, p. 313) is evidence of this. He exposes himself with
  • the naive frankness almost of an irrational creature, and is not only
  • unashamed, but even proud of his part. "Philosophic research," he says,
  • "is possible only to those who are convinced that the norm of the
  • universal imperative is supreme above individual activities, and that
  • such a norm is discoverable." Not every witness will give evidence so
  • honestly. It amounts to this: that philosophic research is not a search
  • after truth, but a conspiracy amongst people who _dethrone truth_ and
  • exalt instead the all-binding norm. The task is truly ethical: morality
  • always was and always will be utilitarian and bullying. Its active
  • principle is: He who is not with us, is against us.
  • 118
  • "If, besides the reality which is evident to us, we were susceptible to
  • another form of reality, chaotic, lawless, then this latter could not
  • be the subject of thought." (Riehl--_Philosophie der Gegenwart_.) This
  • is one of the _a priori_ of critical philosophy--one of the unproved
  • first assumptions, evidently. It is only an expression in other
  • words of Windelband's assertion quoted above, concerning the ethical
  • basis of the law of causation. Thus, the _a priori_ of contemporary
  • thought convince us more and more that Nietzsche's instinct was not
  • at fault. The root of all our philosophies lies, not in our objective
  • observations, but in the demands of our own heart, in the subjective,
  • moral _will_, and therefore science cannot be uprooted except we first
  • destroy morality.
  • 119
  • One of the lofty truisms--"The philosopher conquers passion by
  • perceiving it, the artist by bodying it forth." In German it sounds
  • still more lofty: but does not for that reason approach any nearer
  • to the truth. "_Der Philosoph überwindet die Leidenschaft, indem er
  • sie begreift--der Künstler, indem er sie darstellt_." (Windelband,
  • _Praeludien_, p. 198.)
  • 120
  • The Germans always try to get at _Allgemeingültigkeit_. Well, if the
  • problem of knowledge is to fathom all the depths of actual life, then
  • experience, in so far as it repeats itself, is uninteresting, or at
  • least has a limit of interest. It is necessary, however, to know what
  • nobody yet knows, and therefore we must walk, not on the common road
  • of _Allgemeingültigkeit_, but on new tracks, which have never yet seen
  • human feet. Thus morality, which lays down definite rules and thereby
  • guards life for a time from any surprise, exists only by convention,
  • and in the end collapses before the non-moral surging-up of individual
  • human aspirations. Laws--all of them--have only a regulating value, and
  • are necessary only to those who want rest and security. But the first
  • and essential condition of life is lawlessness. Laws are a refreshing
  • sleep--lawlessness is creative activity.
  • 121
  • A = A.--They say that logic does not need this postulate, and could
  • easily develop it by deduction. I think not. On the contrary, in my
  • opinion, logic could not exist without this premiss. Meanwhile it has
  • a purely empirical origin. In the realm of fact, A is always more or
  • less equal to A. But it might be otherwise. The universe might be so
  • constituted as to admit of the most fantastic metamorphoses. That which
  • now equals A would successively equal B and then C, and so on. At
  • present a stone remains long enough a stone, a plant a plant, an animal
  • an animal. But it might be that a stone changed into a plant before our
  • eyes, and the plant into an animal. That _there is nothing unthinkable_
  • in such a supposition is proved by the theory of evolution. This
  • theory only puts centuries in place of seconds. So that, in spite of
  • the risk to which I expose myself from the admirers of the famous
  • Epicurean system, I am compelled to repeat once more that anything
  • you please may come from anything you please, that A may not equal A,
  • and that consequently logic is dependent, for its soundness, on the
  • empirically-derived law of the unchangeableness of the external world.
  • Admit the possibility of supernatural interference--and logic will lose
  • that certitude and inevitability of its conclusions which at present is
  • so attractive to us.
  • 122
  • The effort to _understand_ people, life, the universe prevents us from
  • getting to know them at all. Since "to know" and "to understand" are
  • two concepts which are not only non-identical, but just the opposite
  • of one another in meaning; in spite of their being in constant use
  • as synonyms. We think we have understood a phenomenon if we have
  • included it in a list of others, previously known to us. And, since all
  • our mental aspiration reduces itself to understanding the universe,
  • we refuse to know a great deal which will not adapt itself to the
  • plane surface of the contemporary world-conceptions. For instance
  • the Leibnitz question, put by Kant into the basis of the critique of
  • reason: "How can we know a thing outside us, if it does not enter into
  • us?" It is non-understandable; that is, it does not agree with our
  • notion of understanding. Hence it follows that it must be squeezed out
  • of the field of view--which is exactly what Kant attempted to do. To
  • us it seems, on the contrary, that in the interests of _knowing_ we
  • should sacrifice, and gladly, understanding, since understanding in any
  • case is a secondary affair.-_Zu fragmentarish ist Welt und Leben_!...
  • PART II
  • _Nur für Schwindelfreie_.
  • (From _Alpine Recollections_.)
  • 1
  • Light reveals to us beauty--but also ugliness. Throw vitriol in the
  • face of a beautiful woman, and the beauty is gone, no power on earth
  • will enable us to look upon her with the same rapture as before. Could
  • even the sincerest, deepest love endure the change? True, the idealists
  • will hasten to say that love overcomes all things. But idealism needs
  • be prompt, for if she leaves us one single moment in which to _see_,
  • we shall see such things as are not easily explained away. That is why
  • idealists stick so tight so logic. In the twinkling of an eye logic
  • will convey us to the remotest conclusions and forecasts. Reality could
  • never overtake her. Love is eternal, and consequently a disfigured face
  • will seem as lovely to us as a fresh one. This is, of course, a lie,
  • but it helps to preserve old tastes and obscures danger. Real danger,
  • however, was never dispelled by words. In spite of Schiller and eternal
  • love, in the long run vitriol triumphs, and the agreeable young man is
  • forced to abandon his beloved and acknowledge himself a fraud. Light,
  • the source of his life and hope, has now destroyed hope and life for
  • him. He will not return to idealism, and he will hate logic: light,
  • that seemed to him so beautiful, will have become hideous. He will turn
  • to darkness, where logic and its binding conclusions have no power, but
  • where the fancy is free for all her vagaries. Without light we should
  • never have known that vitriol ruins beauty. No science, nor any art can
  • give us what darkness gives. It is true, in our young days when all
  • was new, light brought us great happiness and joy. Let us, therefore,
  • remember it with gratitude, as a benefactor we no longer need. Do after
  • all let us dispense with gratitude, for it belongs to the calculating,
  • bourgeois virtues. _Do ut des_. Let us forget light, and gratitude, and
  • the qualms of self-important idealism, let us go bravely to meet the
  • coming night. She promises us great power over reality. Is it worth
  • while to give up our old tastes and lofty convictions? Love and light
  • have not availed against vitriol. What a horror would have seized us
  • at the thought, once upon a time! That short phrase can annul all
  • Schiller. We have shut our eyes and stopped our ears, we have built
  • huge philosophic systems to shield us from this tiny thought. And
  • now--now it seems we have no more feeling for Schiller and the great
  • systems, we have no pity on our past beliefs. We now are seeking for
  • words with which to sing the praises of our former enemy. Night, the
  • dark, deaf, impenetrable night, peopled with horrors--does she not
  • now loom before us, infinitely beautiful? Does she not draw us with
  • her still, mysterious, fathomless beauty, far more powerfully than
  • noisy, narrow day? It seems as if, in a short while, man will feel that
  • the same incomprehensible, cherishing power which threw us out into
  • the universe and set us, like plants, to reach to the light, is now
  • gradually transferring us to a new direction, where a new life awaits
  • us with all its stores. _Fata volentem ducunt, nolentem trahunt._ And
  • perhaps the time is near when the impassioned poet, casting a last look
  • to his past, will boldly and gladly cry:
  • _Hide thyself, sun! O darkness, be welcome_!
  • 2
  • Psychology at last leads us to conclude that the most generous
  • human impulses spring from a root of egoism. Tolstoy's "love to
  • one's neighbour," for example, proves to be a branch of the old
  • self-love. The same may be said of Kant's idealism, and even of
  • Plato's. Though they glorify the service of the idea, in practice
  • they succeed in getting out of the vicious circle of egoism no better
  • than the ordinary mortal, who is neither a genius nor a flower of
  • culture. In my eyes this is "almost" an absolute truth. (It is never
  • wrong to add the retractive "almost"; truth is too much inclined to
  • exaggerate its own importance, and one must guard oneself against
  • its despotic authority.) Thus--all men are egoists. Hence follows
  • a great deal. I even think this proposition might provide better
  • grounds for metaphysical conclusions than the doubtful capacity for
  • compassion and love for one's neighbour which has been so tempting
  • to dogma. For some reason men have imagined that love for oneself
  • is more natural and comprehensible than love for another. Why? Love
  • for others is only a little-rarer, less widely diffused than love
  • to oneself. But then hippopotami and rhinoceros, even in their own
  • tropical regions, are less frequent than horses and mules. Does it
  • follow that they are less natural and transcendental? Positivism is
  • not incumbent upon blood-thirsty savages. Nay, as we know, many of
  • them are less positive-minded than our learned men. For instance, a
  • future life is to them such an infallible reality that they even enter
  • into contracts, part of which is to be fulfilled in the next world. A
  • German metaphysician won't go as far as that. Hence it follows that
  • the way to know the other world is not by any means through love,
  • sympathy, and self-denial, as Schopenhauer taught. On the contrary, it
  • appears as if love for others were only an impediment to metaphysical
  • flights. Love and sympathy chain the eye to the misery of this earth,
  • where such a wide field for active charity opens out. The materialists
  • were mostly very good men--a fact which bothered the historians of
  • philosophy. They preached Matter, believed in nothing, and were
  • ready to perform all kinds of sacrifices for their neighbours. How
  • is this? It is a case of clearest logical consequence: man loves his
  • neighbour, he sees that heaven is indifferent to misery, therefore
  • he takes upon himself the rôle of Providence. Were he indifferent
  • to the sufferings of others, he would easily become an idealist and
  • leave his neighbours to their fate. Love and compassion kill belief,
  • and make a man a positivist and a materialist in his philosophical
  • outlook. If he feels the misery of others, he leaves off meditating
  • and wants to act. Man only thinks properly when he realises he has
  • nothing to do, his hands are tied. That is why any profound thought
  • must arise from despair. Optimism, on the other hand, the readiness
  • to jump hastily from one conclusion to another, may be regarded as an
  • inevitable sign of narrow self-sufficiency, which dreads doubt and
  • is consequently always superficial. If a man offers you a solution
  • of eternal questions, it shows he has not even begun to think about
  • them. He has only "acted." Perhaps it is not necessary to think--who
  • can say how we ought or ought not to live? And how could we be brought
  • to live "as we ought," when our own nature is and always will be an
  • incalculable mystery. There is no mistake about it, nobody _wants_
  • to think, I do not speak here of logical thinking. That, like any
  • other natural function, gives man great pleasure. For this reason
  • philosophical systems, however complicated, arouse real and permanent
  • interest in the public provided they only require from man the logical
  • exercise of the mind, and nothing else. But to think---really to
  • think--surely this means a relinquishing of logic. It means living a
  • new life. It means a permanent sacrifice of the dearest habits, tastes,
  • attachments, without even the assurance that the sacrifice will bring
  • any compensation. Artists and philosophers like to imagine the thinker
  • with a stern face, a profound look which penetrates into the unseen,
  • and a noble bearing--an eagle preparing for flight. Not at all. A
  • thinking man is one who has lost his balance, in the vulgar, not in
  • the tragic sense. Hands raking the air, feet flying, face scared and
  • bewildered, he is a caricature of helplessness and pitiable perplexity.
  • Look at the aged Turgenev, his Poems in Prose and his letter to
  • Tolstoy. Maupassant thus tells of his meeting with Turgenev: " There
  • entered a giant with a silvery head." Quite so! The majestic patriarch
  • and master, of course! The myth of giants with silver locks is firmly
  • established in the heart of man. Then suddenly enters Turgenev in his
  • Prose Poems--pale, pitiful, fluttering like a bird that has been
  • "winged." Turgenev, who has taught us everything--how can he be so
  • fluttered and bewildered? How could he write his letter to Tolstoy?
  • Did he not know that Tolstoy was finished, the source of his creative
  • activity dried up, that he must seek other activities. Of course he
  • knew--and still he wrote that letter. But it was not for Tolstoy, nor
  • even for Russian literature, which, of course, is not kept going by the
  • death-bed letters and covenants of its giants. In the dreadful moments
  • of the end, Turgenev, in spite of his noble size and silver locks, did
  • not know what to say or where to look for support and consolation. So
  • he turned to literature, to which he had given his life.... He yearned
  • that she, whom he had served so long and loyally, should just once
  • help him, save him from the horrible and thrice senseless nightmare.
  • He stretched out his withered, numbing hands to the printed sheets
  • which still preserve the traces of the Soul of a living, suffering
  • man. He addressed his late enemy Tolstoy with the most flattering
  • name: "Great writer of the Russian land"; recollected that he was his
  • contemporary, that he himself was a great writer of the Russian land.
  • But this he did not express aloud. He only said, "I can no longer----"
  • He praised a strict school of literary and general education. To the
  • last he tried to preserve his bearing of a giant with silvery locks.
  • And we were gratified. The same persons who are indignant at Gogol's
  • correspondence, quote Turgenev's letter with reverence. The attitude
  • is everything. Turgenev knew how to pose passably well, and this is
  • ascribed to him as his greatest merit. _Mundus vult decipi, ergo
  • decipiatur_. But Gogol and Turgenev felt substantially the same. Had
  • Turgenev burnt his own manuscripts and talked of himself instead of
  • Tolstoy, before death, he would have been accounted mad. Moralists
  • would have reproached him for his display of extreme egoism.... And
  • Philosophy? Philosophy seems to be getting rid of certain prejudices.
  • At the moment when men are least likely to play the hypocrite and lie
  • to themselves Turgenev and Gogol placed their personal fate higher
  • than the destinies of Russian literature. Does not this betray a
  • "secret" to us? Ought we not to see in absolute egoism an inalienable
  • and great, yes, very great quality of human nature? Psychology,
  • ignoring the threats of morality, has led us to a new knowledge. Yet
  • still, in spite of the instances we have given, the mass of people
  • will, as usual, see nothing but malice in every attempt to reveal
  • the human impulses that underlie "lofty" motives. To be merely men
  • seems humiliating to men. So now malice will also be detected in my
  • interpretation of Turgenev's letter, no matter what assurance I offer
  • to the contrary.
  • 3
  • _On Method_.--A certain naturalist made the following experiment:
  • A glass jar was divided into two halves by a perfectly transparent
  • glass partition. On the one side of the partition he placed a pike,
  • on the other a number of small fishes such as form the prey of the
  • pike. The pike did not notice the partition, and hurled itself on its
  • prey, with, of course, the result only of a bruised nose. The same
  • happened many times, and always the same result. At last, seeing all
  • its efforts ended so painfully, the pike abandoned the hunt, so that
  • in a few days, when the partition had been removed it continued to
  • swim about among the small fry without daring to attack them.... Does
  • not the same happen with us? Perhaps the limits between "this world"
  • and "the other world" are also essentially of an experimental origin,
  • neither rooted in the nature of things, as was thought before Kant, or
  • in the nature of our reason, as was thought after Kant. Perhaps indeed
  • a partition does exist, and make vain all attempts to cross over.. But
  • perhaps there comes a moment when the partition is removed. In our
  • minds, however, the conviction is firmly rooted that it is impossible
  • to pass certain limits, and painful to try: a conviction founded on
  • experience. But in this case we should recall the old scepticism of
  • Hume, which idealist philosophy has regarded as mere subtle mind-play,
  • valueless after Kant's critique. The most lasting and varied experience
  • cannot lead to any binding and universal conclusion. Nay, all our
  • _a priori_, which are so useful for a certain time, become sooner
  • or later extremely harmful. A philosopher should not be afraid of
  • scepticism, but should go on bruising his jaw. Perhaps the failure
  • of metaphysics lies in the caution and timidity of metaphysicians,
  • who seem ostensibly so brave. They have sought for rest--which they
  • describe as the highest boon. Whereas they should have valued more than
  • anything restlessness, aimlessness, even purposelessness. How can you
  • tell when the partition will be removed? Perhaps at the very moment
  • when man ceased his painful pursuit, settled all his questions and
  • rested on his laurels, inert, he could with one strong push have swept
  • through the pernicious fence which separated him from the unknowable.
  • There is no need for man to move according to a carefully-considered
  • plan. This is a purely aesthetic demand which need not bind us. Let
  • man senselessly and deliriously knock his head against the wall--if
  • the wall go down at last, will he value his triumph any the less?
  • Unfortunately for us the illusion has been established in us that plan
  • and purpose are the best guarantee of success. What a delusion it is!
  • The opposite is true. The best of all that genius has revealed to us
  • has been revealed as the result of fantastic, erratic, apparently
  • ridiculous and useless, but relentlessly stubborn seeking. Columbus,
  • tired of sitting on the same spot, sailed west to look for India. And
  • genius, in spite of vulgar conception, is a condition of chaos and
  • unutterable restlessness. Not for nothing has genius been counted kin
  • to madness. Genius flings itself hither and thither because it has not
  • the _Sitzfleisch_ necessary for industrious success in mediocrity.
  • We may be sure that earth has seen much more genius than history
  • has recorded; since genius is acknowledged only when it has been
  • serviceable. When the tossing-about has led to no useful issue--which
  • is the case in the majority of instances--it arouses only a feeling
  • of disgust and abomination in all witnesses. "He can't rest and he
  • can't let others rest." If Lermontov and Dostoevsky had lived in times
  • when there was no demand for books, nobody would have noticed them.
  • Lermontov's early death would have passed unregretted. Perhaps some
  • settled and virtuous citizen would have remarked, weary of the young
  • man's eternal and dangerous freaks: "For a dog a dog's death." The same
  • of Gogol, Tolstoy, Poushkin. Now they are praised because they left
  • interesting books.... And so we need pay no attention to the cry about
  • the futility and worthlessness of scepticism, even scepticism pure and
  • unadulterated, scepticism which has no ulterior motive of clearing
  • the way for a new creed. To knock one's head against the wall out of
  • hatred for the wall: to beat against established and obstructive ideas,
  • because one detests them: is it not an attractive proposition? And
  • then, to see ahead uncertainly and limitless possibilities, instead of
  • up-to-date "ideals," is not this too fascinating? The highest good is
  • rest! I shall not argue: _de gustibus aut nihil aut bene_.... By the
  • way, isn't it a superb principle? And this superb principle has been
  • arrived at perfectly by chance, unfortunately not by me, but by one of
  • the comical characters in Tchekhov's _Seagull_. He mixed up two Latin
  • proverbs, and the result was a splendid maxim which, in order to become
  • an _a priori_, awaits only universal acceptance.
  • 4
  • Metaphysicians praise the transcendental, and carefully avoid it.
  • Nietzsche hated metaphysics, he praised the earth--_bleib nur der
  • Erde treu, O meine Bruder_--and always lived in the realm of the
  • transcendental. Of course the metaphysicians behave better: this is
  • indisputable. He who would be a teacher must proclaim the metaphysical
  • point of view, and he may become a hero without ever smelling powder.
  • In these anxious days, when positivism seems to fall short, one cannot
  • do better than turn to metaphysics. Then the young man need not any
  • more envy Alexander the Macedonian. With the assistance of a few
  • books not only earthly states are conquered, but the whole mysterious
  • universe. Metaphysics is the great art of swerving round dangerous
  • experience. So metaphysicians should be called the positivists _par
  • excellence_. They do not despise all experience, as they assert, but
  • _only the dangerous experiences_. They adapt the safest of all methods
  • of selfdefence, what the English call protective mimicry. Let us repeat
  • to all students--professors know it already: he who would be a sincere
  • metaphysician must avoid risky experience. Schiller once asked: How can
  • tragedy give delight? The answer--to put it in our own words--was: If
  • we are to obtain delight from tragedy, it must be seen only upon the
  • stage.--In order to love the transcendental it also should be known
  • only from the stage, or from books of the philosophers. This is called
  • idealism, the nicest word ever invented by philosophising men.
  • 5
  • _Poetae nascuntur_.--Wonderful is man. Knowing nothing about it, he
  • asserts the existence of an objective impossibility. Even a little
  • while ago, before the invention of the telephone and telegraph, men
  • would have declared it impossible for Europe to converse with America.
  • Now it is possible. We cannot produce poets, therefore we say they are
  • born. Certainly we cannot make a child a poet by forcing him to study
  • literary models, from the most ancient to the most modern. Neither will
  • anybody hear us in America no matter how loud we shout here. To make a
  • poet of a man, he must not be developed along ordinary lines. Perhaps
  • books should be kept from him. Perhaps it is necessary to perform some
  • apparently dangerous operation on him: fracture his skull or throw
  • him out of a fourth-storey window. I will refrain from recommending
  • these methods as a substitute for paedagogy. But that is not the
  • point. Look at the great men, and the poets. Except John Stuart Mill
  • and a couple of other positivist thinkers, who had learned fathers
  • and virtuous mothers, none of the great men can boast of, or better,
  • complain of, a proper upbringing. In their lives nearly always the
  • decisive part was played by accident, accident which reason would dub
  • meaninglessness, if reason ever dared raise its voice against obvious
  • success. Something like a broken skull or a fall from the fourth
  • floor--not metaphorically, but often absolutely literally--has proved
  • the commencement, usually concealed but occasionally avowed, of the
  • activity of genius. But we repeat automatically: _poetae nascuntur_,
  • and are deeply convinced that this extraordinary truth is so lofty it
  • needs no verification.
  • 6
  • "Until Apollo calls him to the sacrifice, ignobly the poet is plunged
  • in the cares of this shoddy world; silent is his lyre, cold sleeps his
  • soul, of all the petty children of earth most petty it seems is he."
  • Pisaryev, the critic, was exasperated by these verses. Presumably, if
  • they had not belonged to Poushkin, all the critics along with Pisaryev
  • would have condemned them and their author to oblivion. Suspicious
  • verse! Before Apollo calls to him--the poet is the most insignificant
  • of mortals! In his free hours, the ordinary man finds some more or less
  • distinguished distraction fox himself: he hunts, attends exhibitions
  • of pictures, or the theatre, and finally rests in the bosom of his
  • family. But the poet is incapable of normal existence. Immediately he
  • has finished with Apollo, forgetting all about altars and sacrifices,
  • he proceeds to occupy himself with unworthy objects. Or he abandons
  • himself to the _dolce far niente_, the customary pastime of all
  • favourites of the Muses. Let us here remark that not only all poets,
  • but all writers and artists in general are inclined to lead bad lives.
  • Think what Tolstoy tells us, in _Confession_ and elsewhere, of the best
  • representatives of literature in the fifties. On the whole it is just
  • as Poushkin says in his verses. Whilst he is engaged in composition,
  • an author is a creature of some consequence: apart from this, he is
  • nothing. Why are Apollo and the Muses so remiss? Why do they draw to
  • themselves wayward or vicious votaries, instead of rewarding virtue?
  • We dare not suspect the gods, even the dethroned, of bad intentions.
  • Apollo loved virtuous persons--and yet virtuous persons are evidently
  • mediocre and unfit for the sacred offices. If any man is overcome with
  • a great desire to serve the god of song, let him get rid of his virtues
  • at once. Curious that this truth is so completely unknown to men. They
  • think that through virtue they can truly deserve the favour and choice
  • of Apollo. And since industry is the first virtue, they peg away,
  • morning, noon, and night. Of course, the more they work the less they
  • do. Which really puzzles and annoys them. They even fling aside the
  • sacred arts, and all the labours of a devotee; they give themselves up
  • to idleness and other bad habits. And sometimes it so happens, that
  • just as a man decides that it is all no good, the Muses suddenly visit
  • him. So it was with Dostoevsky and others; Schiller alone managed
  • to get round Apollo. But perhaps it was only his biographers he got
  • round. Germans are so trustful, so easy to deceive. The biographers
  • saw nothing unusual in Schiller's habit of keeping his feet in cold
  • water whilst he worked. No doubt they felt that if the divine poet had
  • lived in the Sahara, where water is precious as gold, and the inspired
  • cannot take a footbath every day, then the speeches of the Marquis of
  • Pola would have lacked half their nobleness, at least. And apparently
  • Schiller was not so wonderfully chaste, if he needed such artificial
  • resources in the composition of his fine speeches. In a word, we must
  • believe Poushkin. A poet is, on the one hand, among the elect; on the
  • other hand, he is one of the most insignificant of mortals. Hence we
  • can draw a very consoling conclusion: the most insignificant of men
  • are not altogether so worthless as we imagine. They may not be fit to
  • occupy government positions or professorial chairs, but they are often
  • extremely at home on Parnassus and such high places. Apollo rewards
  • vice, and virtue, as everybody knows, is so satisfied with herself she
  • needs no reward. Then why do the pessimists lament? Leibnitz was quite
  • right: we live in the best possible of worlds. I would even suggest
  • that we leave out the modification "possible."
  • 7
  • It is _Das Ewig Weibliche_, with Russian writers. Poushkin and
  • Lermontov loved women and were not afraid of them; Poushkin, who
  • trusted his own nature, was often in love, and always sang his love of
  • the moment. When infatuated with a bacchante, he glorified bacchantes.
  • When he married, he warbled of a modest, nun-like beauty, his wife.
  • A synthesising mind would probably not know what to do with all
  • Poushkin's sorts of love. Nor is Lermontov any better. He abused women,
  • but, as Byelinsky observed after meeting him, he loved women more than
  • anything in the world. And again, not women of one mould only: any and
  • all attractive females: the wild Bella, the lovely Mary, Thamar; one
  • and all, no matter of what race or condition. Every time Lermontov is
  • in love, he assures us his love is so deep and ardent and even moral,
  • that we cannot judge him without conpunction. Vladimir Soloviov alone
  • was not afraid to condemn him. He brought Poushkin as well as Lermontov
  • to account for their moral irregularities, and he even went so far as
  • to say that it was not he himself who judged them, but Fate, in whose
  • service he acted as public denouncer. Lermontov and Poushkin, both
  • dying young, had deserved death for their frivolities. But there was
  • nobody else besides Vladimir Soloviov to darken the memories of the two
  • poets. It is true Tolstoy cannot forgive Poushkin's dissolute life, but
  • he does not apply to Fate for a verdict. According to Tolstoy morality
  • can cope even with a Titan like Poushkin. In Tolstoy's view morality
  • grows stronger the harder the job it has to tackle. It pardons the
  • weak offenders without waste of words, but it never forgives pride and
  • self-confidence. If Tolstoy's edicts had been executed, all memorials
  • to Poushkin would have disappeared; chiefly because of the poet's
  • addiction to the eternal female. In such a case Tolstoy is implacable.
  • He admits the the kind of love whose object is the establishing of
  • a family, but no more. Don Juan is a hateful transgressor. Think of
  • Levin, and his attitude to prostitutes. He is exasperated, indignant,
  • even forgets the need for compassion, and calls them "beasts." In the
  • eternal female Tolstoy sees temptation, seduction, sin, _great danger_.
  • Therefore it is necessary to keep quite away from the danger. But
  • surely danger is the dragon which guards every treasure on earth. And
  • again, no matter what his precautions, a man will meet his fate sooner
  • or later, and come into conflict with the dragon. Surely this is an
  • axiom. Poushkin and Lermontov loved danger, and therefore sought women.
  • They paid a heavy price, but while they lived they lived freely and
  • lightly. If they had cared to peep in the book of destinies, they might
  • have averted or avoided their sad end. But they preferred to trust
  • their star--lucky or unlucky. Tolstoy was the first among us--we cannot
  • speak of Gogol--who began to fear life. He was the first to start open
  • moralising. In so far as public opinion and personal dignity demand
  • it, he did go to meet his dangers: but not a step further. So he
  • avoided women, art, and philosophy. Love _per se_, that is, love which
  • does not lead to a family, like wisdom _per se_, which is wisdom that
  • has no utilitarian motive, and like art for art's sake, seemed to him
  • the worst of temptations, leading to the destruction of the soul. When
  • he plunged too deep in thinking, he was seized with panic. "It seemed
  • to me I was going mad, so I went away to the Bashkirs for koumiss."
  • Such confessions are common in his works. And surely there is no other
  • way with temptations, than to cut short, at once, before it is too
  • late. Tolstoy preserved himself on account of his inborn instinct for
  • departing betimes from a dangerous situation. Save for this cautious
  • prompting he would probably have ended like Lermontov or Poushkin.
  • True, he might have gone deeper into nature, and revealed us rare
  • secrets, instead of preaching at us abstinence, humility, simplicity
  • and so on. But such luck fell to the fate of Dostoevsky. Dostoevsky
  • had very muddled relations with morality. He was too racked by disease
  • and circumstance to get much profit out of the rules of morality. The
  • hygiene of the soul, like that of the body, is beneficial only to
  • healthy men. To the sick it is simply harmful. The more Dostoevsky
  • engaged himself with high morality, the more inextricably entangled
  • he became. He wanted to respect the personality in a woman, and only
  • the personality, and so he came to the point where he could not look
  • on any woman, however ugly, with indifference. The elder Karamazov and
  • his affair with Elizabeth Smerdyascha (Stinking Lizzie)--in what other
  • imagination could such a union have been contemplated? Dostoevsky, of
  • course, reprimands Karamazov, and thanks to the standards of modern
  • criticism, such a reprimand is accounted sufficient to exonerate our
  • author. But there are other standards. If a writer sets out to tell you
  • that no drab could be so loathsome that her ugliness would make you
  • forget she was woman; and if for illustration of this novel idea we
  • are told the history of Fiodov Karamazov with the deformed, repulsive
  • idiot, Stinking Lizzie; then, in face of such "imaginative art" it is
  • surely out of place to preserve the usual confidence in that writer.
  • We do not speak of the interest and _appreciation_ of Dostoevsky's
  • tastes and ideas. Not for one moment will I assert that those who
  • with Poushkin and Lermontov can see the Eternal Female only in young
  • and charming women, have any advantage over Dostoevsky. Of course,
  • we are not forbidden to live according to our tastes, and we may,
  • like Tolstoy, call certain women "beasts." But who has given us the
  • right to assert that we are higher or better than Dostoevsky? Judging
  • "objectively," all the points go to show that Dostoevsky is better--at
  • any rate he saw further, deeper. He could find an original interest,
  • he could discover _das ewig Weibliche_ where we should see nothing of
  • attraction at all, where Goethe would avert his face. Stinking Lizzie
  • is not a beast, as Levin would say, but a woman who is able, if even
  • for a moment, to arouse a feeling of love in a man. And we thought she
  • was worse than nothing, since she roused in us only disgust. Dostoevsky
  • made a discovery, we with our refined feelings missed it. His
  • distorted, abnormal sense showed a greater sensitiveness, in which our
  • high morality was deficient.... And the road to the great truth this
  • time, as ever, is through deformity. Idealists will not agree. They are
  • quite justly afraid that one may not reach the truth, but may get stuck
  • in the mud. Idealists are careful men, and not nearly so stupid as
  • their ideals would lead us to suppose.
  • 8
  • New ideas, even our own, do not quickly conquer our sympathies. We must
  • first get accustomed to them.
  • 9
  • _A point of view_.--Every writer, thinker--even every educated person
  • thinks it necessary to have a permanent point of view. He climbs up
  • some elevation and never climbs down again all his days. Whatever
  • he sees from this point of view, he believes to be reality, truth,
  • justice, good--and what he does not see he excludes from existence.
  • Man is not much to blame for this. Surely there is no very great joy
  • in moving from point of view to point of view, shifting one's camp
  • from peak to peak. We have no wings, and "a winged thought" is only
  • a nice metaphor--unless, of course, it refers to logical thinking.
  • There to be sure great volatility is usual, a lightness which comes
  • from perfect naïveté, if not ignorance. He who really wishes to know
  • something, and not merely to have a philosophy, does not rely on logic
  • and is not allured by reason. He must clamber from summit to summit,
  • and, if necessary, hibernate in the dales. For a wide horizon leads
  • to illusions, and in order to familiarise oneself with any object,
  • it is essential to go close up to it, touch it, feel it, examine it
  • from top to bottom and on every side. One must be ready, should this
  • be impossible otherwise, to sacrifice the customary position of the
  • body: to wriggle, to lie flat, to stand on one's head, in a word, to
  • assume the most unnatural of attitudes. Can there be any question of a
  • permanent point of view? The more mobility and elasticity a man has,
  • the less he values the ordinary equilibrium of his body; the oftener
  • he changes his outlook, the more he will take in. If, on the other
  • hand, he imagines that from this or the other pinnacle he has the most
  • comfortable survey of the world and life, leave him alone; he will
  • never know anything. Nay, he does not want to know, he cares more about
  • his personal convenience than about the quality of his work. No doubt
  • he will attain to fame and success, and thus brilliantly justify his
  • "point of view."
  • 10
  • _Fame_.--"A thread from everyone, and the naked will have a shirt."
  • There is no beggar but has his thread of cotton, and he will not
  • grudge it to a naked man--no, nor even to a fully dressed one; but
  • will bestow it on the first comer. The poor, who want to forget their
  • poverty, are very ready with their threads. Moreover, they prefer to
  • give them to the rich, rather than to a fellow-tramp. To load the rich
  • with benefits, must not one be very rich indeed? That is why fame is
  • so easily got. An ambitious person asks admiration and respect from
  • the crowd, and is rarely denied. The mob feel that their throats are
  • their own, and their arms are strong. Why not vociferate and clap,
  • seeing that you can turn the head not only of a beggar like yourself,
  • but of a future hero, God knows how almighty a person. The humiliated
  • citizen who has hitherto been hauled off to the police station if he
  • shouted, suddenly feels that his throat has acquired a new value. Never
  • before has anyone given a rap for his worthless opinion, and now seven
  • cities are ready to quarrel for it, as for the right to claim Homer.
  • The citizen is delighted, he shouts at the top of his voice, and is
  • ready to throw all his possessions after his shouts. So the hero is
  • satisfied. The greater the shout, the deeper his belief in himself
  • and his mission. What will a hero not believe! For he forgets so soon
  • the elements of which his fame and riches are made. Heroes usually
  • are convinced that they set out on their noble career, not to beg
  • shouts from beggars, but to heap blessings on mankind. If they could
  • only call to mind with what beating hearts they awaited their first
  • applause, their first alms, how timidly they curried favour with ragged
  • beggars, perhaps they would speak less assuredly of their own merits.
  • But our memory is fully acquainted with Herbert Spencer and his law of
  • adaptability, and thus many a worthy man goes gaily on in full belief
  • in his own stupendous virtue.
  • 11
  • _In defence of righteousness_.--Inexperienced and ingenuous people see
  • in righteousness merely a burden which lofty people have assumed out
  • of respect for law or for some other high and inexplicable reason. But
  • a righteous man has not only duties but rights. True, sometimes, when
  • the law is against him, he has to compromise. Yet how rarely does the
  • law desert him! No cruelty matters in him, so long as he does not
  • infringe the statutes. Nay, he will ascribe his cruelty as a merit to
  • himself, since he acts out of no personal considerations, but in the
  • name of sacred justice. No matter what he may do, once he is sanctioned
  • he sees in his actions only merit, merit, merit. Modesty forbids him to
  • say too much--but if he were to let go, what a luxurious panegyric he
  • might deliver to himself! Remembering his works, he praises himself at
  • all times; not aloud, but inwardly. The nature of virtue demands it:
  • man must rejoice in his morality and ever keep it in mind. And after
  • that, people declare that it is hard to be righteous. Whatever the
  • other virtues may be, certainly righteousness has its selfish side. As
  • a rule it is decidedly worth while to make considerable sacrifices in
  • order later on to enjoy in calm confidence all that surety and those
  • rights bestowed on a man by morality and public approval. Look at a
  • German who has paid his contribution to a society for the assistance of
  • the indigent. Not one stray farthing will he give, not to a poor wretch
  • who is starving before his eyes. And in this he feels right. This is
  • righteousness out and out: pay your tax and enjoy the privileges of a
  • high-principled man. So righteousness is much in vogue with cultured,
  • commercial nations. Russians have not quite got there. They are
  • afraid of the exactions of righteousness, not guessing the enormous
  • advantages derived. A Russian has a permanent relationship with his
  • conscience, which costs him far more than the most moral German, or
  • even Englishman, has to pay for his righteousness.
  • 12
  • The best way of getting rid of tedious, played-out truths is to stop
  • paying them the tribute of respect and to treat them with a touch of
  • easy familiarity and derision. To put into brackets, as Dostoevsky did,
  • such words as good, self-sacrifice, progress, and so on, will alone
  • achieve you much more than many brilliant arguments would do. Whilst
  • you still contest a certain truth, you still believe in it, and this
  • even the least penetrating individual will perceive. But if you favour
  • it with no serious attention, and only throw out a scornful remark now
  • and then, the result is different. It is evident you have ceased to be
  • afraid of the old truth, you no longer respect it. And this sets people
  • thinking.
  • 13
  • _Four walls_.--Arm-chair philosophy is being condemned--rightly.
  • An arm-chair thinker is busy deciding on everything that is taking
  • place in the world: the state of the world market, the existence of
  • a world-soul, wireless telegraphy and the life after death, the cave
  • dweller and the perfectibility of man, and so on and so on. His chief
  • business is so to select his statements that there shall be no internal
  • contradiction; and this will give an appearance of truth. Such work,
  • which is quite amusing and even interesting, leads at last to very
  • poor results. Surely verisimilitudes of truth are not truth: nor have
  • necessarily anything in common with truth. Again, a man who undertakes
  • to talk of everything probably knows nothing. Thus a swan can fly, and
  • walk, and swim. But it flies indifferently, walks badly, and swims
  • poorly. An arm-chair philosopher, enclosed by four walls, sees nothing
  • but those four walls, and yet of these precisely he does not choose
  • to speak. If by accident he suddenly realised them and spoke of them
  • his philosophy might acquire an enormous value. This may happen when a
  • study is converted into a prison: the same four walls, but impossible
  • not to think of them! Whatever the prisoner turns his mind to--Homer,
  • the Greek-Persian wars, the future world-peace, the bygone geological
  • cataclysms--still the four walls enclose it all. The calm of the study
  • supplanted by the pathos of imprisonment. The prisoner has no more
  • contact with the world, and no less. But now he no longer slumbers
  • and has grayish dreams called world-conceptions. He is wide awake and
  • strenuously living. His philosophy is worth hearing. But man is not
  • distinguished for his powers of discrimination. He sees solitude and
  • four walls, and says: a study. He dreams of the market-place, where
  • there is noise and jostling, physical bustle, and decides that there
  • alone life is to be met. He is wrong as usual. In the market-place,
  • among the crowd, do not men sleep their deadest sleep? And is not the
  • keenest spiritual activity taking place in seclusion?
  • 14
  • The Spartans made their helots drunk as an example and warning to their
  • noble youths. A good method, no doubt, but what are we of the twentieth
  • century to do? Whom shall we make drunk? We have no slaves, so we have
  • instituted a higher literature. Novels and stories describe drunken,
  • dissolute men, and paint them in such horrid colours that every reader
  • feels all his desire for vice depart from him. Unfortunately only our
  • Russians are either too conscientious or not sufficiently rectilinear
  • in their minds. Instead of showing the drunken helot as an object of
  • repugnance, as the Spartans did, they try to describe vice truthfully.
  • Realism has taken hold. Indeed, why make a fuss? What does it matter if
  • the writer's description is a little more or less ugly than the event?
  • Was justice invented that everything, _even evil,_ should be kept
  • intact? Surely evil must be simply rooted out, banned, placed outside
  • the pale. The Spartans did not stand on ceremony with living men, and
  • yet our novelists are afraid of being unjust to imaginary drunken
  • helots. And, so to speak, out of humane feeling too.... How naive one
  • must be to accept such a justification! Yet everybody accepts it.
  • Tolstoy alone, towards the end, guessed that humanitarianism is only
  • a pretext in this case, and that we Russians have described vice not
  • only for the purpose of scaring our readers. In modern masters the word
  • vice arouses not disgust, but insatiable curiosity. Perhaps the wicked
  • thing has been persecuted in vain, like so many other good things.
  • Perhaps it should have been studied, perhaps it held mysteries.... On
  • the strength of this "perhaps" morality was gradually abandoned, and
  • Tolstoy remained almost alone in his indignation. Realism reigns, and
  • a drunken helot arouses envy in timid readers who do not know where to
  • put their trust, whether in the traditional rules or in the appeal of
  • the master. A drunken helot an ideal! What have we come to? Were it not
  • better to have stuck to Lycurgus? Have we not paid too dearly for our
  • progress?
  • Many people think we have paid too dearly--not to mention Tolstoy,
  • who is now no longer taken quite seriously, though still accounted
  • a great man. Any mediocre journalist enjoys greater influence than
  • this master-writer of the Russian land. It is inevitable. Tolstoy
  • insists on thinking about things which are nobody's concern. He has
  • long since abandoned this world--and does he continue to exist in
  • any other? Difficult question! "Tolstoy writes books and letters,
  • therefore he exists." This inference, once so convincing, now has
  • hardly any effect on us: particularly if we take into account what it
  • is that Tolstoy writes. In several of his last letters he expresses
  • opinions which surely have no meaning for an ordinary man. They can
  • be summed up in a few words. Tolstoy professes an extreme egoism,
  • sollipsism, solus-ipse-ism. That is, in his old age, after infinite
  • attempts to love his neighbour, he comes to the conclusion that not
  • only is it impossible to love one's neighbour, but that there _is_ no
  • neighbour, that in all the world Tolstoy alone exists, that there is
  • even no world, but only Tolstoy: a view so obviously absurd, that it
  • is not worth refuting. By the way, there is also no possibility of
  • refuting it, unless you admit that logical inferences are non-binding.
  • Sollipsism dogged Tolstoy already in early youth, but at that time
  • he did not know what to do with the impertinent, oppressive idea,
  • so he ignored it. Finally, he came to it. The older a man becomes,
  • the more he learns how to make use of impertinent ideas. Fairly
  • recently Tolstoy could pronounce such a dictum: "Christ taught men
  • not to do stupid things." Who but Tolstoy could have ventured on such
  • an interpretation of the gospels? Why have we all held--all of us
  • but Tolstoy--that these words contained the greatest blasphemy on
  • Christ and His teaching? But it was Tolstoy's last desperate attempt
  • to save himself from sollipsism, without at the same time flying in
  • the face of logic: even Christ appeared among men only to teach them
  • common sense. Whence follows that "mad" thoughts may be rejected
  • with an easy conscience, and the advantage, as usual, remains with
  • the wholesome, reasonable, sensible thoughts. There is room for good
  • and for reason. Good is self-understood; it need not be explained.
  • If only good existed in the world, there would exist no questions,
  • neither simple nor ultimate. This is why youth never questions. What
  • indeed should it question: the song of the nightingale, the morning
  • of May, happy laughter, all the predicates of youth? Do these need
  • interpretation? On the contrary, any explanation is reduced to these
  • The proper questions arise only on contact with evil. A hawk struck
  • a nightingale, flowers withered, Boreas froze laughing youth--and in
  • terror our questions arose. "That is evil. The ancients were right.
  • Not in vain is our earth called a vale of tears and sorrow." And
  • once questions are started, it is impossible and unseemly to hurry
  • the answers, still less anticipate the questions. The nightingale
  • is dead and will sing no longer, the listener is frozen to death and
  • can hear no more songs. The situation is so palpably absurd that only
  • with the intention of getting rid of the question at any cost will
  • one strive for a sensible answer. The answer must be absurd--if you
  • don't want it, don't question. But if you must question, then be ready
  • beforehand to reconcile yourself with something like sollipsism or
  • modern realism. Thought is in a dilemma, and dare not take the leap to
  • get out. We laugh at philosophy, and, as long as possible, avoid evil.
  • But nearly all men feel the intolerable cramp of such a situation, and
  • each at his risk ventures to swim to shore on some more or less witty
  • theory. A few courageous ones speak the truth--but they are neither
  • understood nor respected. When a man's words show the depth of the
  • pain through which he has passed, he is not, indeed, condemned, but
  • the world begins to talk of his tragic state of soul, and to take
  • on a mournful look fitting to the occasion. Others more scrupulous
  • feel that phrases and mournful looks are unfitting, yet they cannot
  • dwell at length on the tragedies of outsiders, so they take on an
  • exaggeratedly stern bearing, as if to say, "We feel deeply, but we do
  • not wish to show our feeling." They really feel nothing, only want
  • to make others believe how sensitive and modest they are. At times
  • this leads to curious results, even in writers of the first order
  • of renown. Thus Anatole France, the inventor of that most charming
  • smile which is intended to convince men that he feels everything and
  • understands everything, but does not cry out, because that would not
  • be fitting, in one of his novels takes upon himself the noble rôle of
  • advocate of the victims of a crime, against the criminal. "Our time,"
  • he says, "out of _pity_ to the criminal forgets the sufferings of his
  • victim." This, I repeat, is one of the most curious misrepresentations
  • of modern endeavour. It is true we in Russia talk a good deal about
  • compassion, particularly to criminals, and Anatole France is by no
  • means the only man who thinks that our distinguishing characteristic is
  • extreme sensitiveness and tender-heartedness. But as a matter of fact
  • the modern man who thinks for himself is not drawn to the criminal by
  • a sense of compassion, which would incontestably be better applied to
  • the victim, but by curiosity, or if you like, inquisitiveness. For
  • thousands of years man has sought to solve the great mystery of life
  • through a God-conception--with theodicy and metaphysical theories as
  • a result, both of which deny the possibility of a mystery. Theodicy
  • has long ago wearied us. The mechanistic theories, which contend that
  • there is nothing special in life, that its appearance and disappearance
  • depend on the same laws as those of the conservation of energy and
  • the indestructibility of matter, these look more plausible at first
  • sight, but people do not take to them. And no theory can survive men's
  • reluctance to believe in it. In a word, good has not justified the
  • expectations placed on it. Reason has done no better. So overwrought
  • mankind has turned from its old idols and enthroned madness and evil.
  • The smiling Anatole argues, and proves--proves excellently. But who
  • does not know what his proofs amount to?--and who wants them? It may be
  • our children will take fright at the task we have undertaken, will call
  • us "squandering parents," and will set themselves again to heaping up
  • treasures, spiritual and material. Again they will believe in ideals,
  • progress, and such like. For my own part, I have hardly any doubt of
  • it. Sollipsism and the cult of groundlessness are not lasting, and,
  • most of all, they are not to be handed down. The final triumph, in life
  • as in old comedies, rests with goodness and common sense. History has
  • known many epochs like ours, and gone through with them. Degeneration
  • follows on the heels of immoderate curiosity, and sweeps away all
  • refined and exaggerately well-informed individuals. Men of genius have
  • no posterity--or their children are idiots. Not for nothing is nature
  • so majestically serene: she has hidden her secrets well enough. Which
  • is not surprising, considering how unscrupulous she is. No despot, not
  • the greatest villain on earth, has ever wielded power with the cruelty
  • and heartlessness of nature. The least violation of her laws--and
  • the severest punishment follows. Disease, deformity, madness, death
  • --what has not our common mother contrived to keep us in subjection?
  • True, certain optimists think that nature does not punish us, but
  • educates us. So Tolstoy sees it. "Death and sufferings, like animated
  • scarecrows, boo at man and drive him into the one way of life open to
  • him: for life is subject to its own law of reason." Not a bad method
  • of upbringing. Exactly like using wolves and bears. Unfortunate man,
  • bolting from one booing monster, is not always able in time to dodge
  • into the one correct way, and dashes straight into the maw of another
  • beast of prey. Then what? And this often happens. Without disparagement
  • of the optimists, we may say that sooner or later it happens to every
  • man. After which no more running. You won't tear yourself out of the
  • claws of madness or disease. Only one thing is left: in spite of
  • traditions, theodicy, wiseacres, and most of all in spite of oneself,
  • to go on praising mother nature and her great goodness. Let future
  • generations reject us, let history stigmatise our names, as the names
  • of traitors to the human cause--still we will compose hymns to
  • deformity, destruction, madness, chaos, darkness. And after that--let
  • the grass grow.
  • 15
  • Astrology and alchemy lived their day and died a natural death.
  • But they left a posterity--chemistry inventing dyes, and astronomy
  • accumulating formulae. So it is. Geniuses beget idiots: especially when
  • the mothers are very virtuous, as in this case, when their virtue
  • is extraordinary. For the mothers are public utility and morality.
  • The alchemists wasted their time seeking the philosopher's stone; the
  • astrologers, swindled people telling fortunes by the stars. Wedded to
  • utility these two fathers have begotten the chemists and astronomers.
  • ... Nobody will dispute the genealogy. Perhaps even none will dispute
  • that, from idiotic children one may, with a measure of probability,
  • infer genius in the parents. There are certain indications that this is
  • so--though of course one may not go beyond supposition. But supposition
  • is enough. There are more arguments in store. For instance--our day is
  • so convinced of the absolute nonsense and uselessness of alchemy and
  • astrology that no one dreams of verifying the conviction. We know there
  • were many charlatans and liars amongst alchemists and astrologers. But
  • what does this prove? In every department there are the same mediocre
  • creatures who speculate on human credulity. However positive our
  • science of medicine is, there are many fraudulent doctors who rob their
  • patients. The alchemists and astrologers were, in all probability,
  • the most remarkable men of their time. I will go further: in spite
  • of dye-stuffs and formulae, even in our nineteenth century, which
  • was so famous for its inventions and discoveries, the most eminent,
  • talented men still sought the philosopher's stone and forecast the
  • destinies of man. And those among them who were possessed of a poetic
  • gift won universal attention. In the old days, _consensu sapientium_,
  • a poet was allowed all kinds of liberties: he might speak of fate,
  • miracles, spirits, the life beyond--indeed of anything, provided he was
  • interesting. That was enough. The nineteenth century paid its tribute
  • to restlessness. Never were there so many disturbing, throbbing writers
  • as during the epoch of telephones and telegraphs. It was held indecent
  • to speak in plain language of the vexed and troubled aspirations of
  • the human spirit. Those guilty of the indecency were even dosed with
  • bromides and treated with shower-baths and concentrated foods. But all
  • this is external, it belongs to a history of "fashions" and cannot
  • interest us here. The point is that alchemy and astrology did not die,
  • they only shammed death and left the stage for a time. Now, apparently,
  • they are tired of seclusion and are coming forward again, having pushed
  • their unsuccessful children into the background. Well, so be it. _A la
  • bonne heure_!...
  • 16
  • Man comes to the pass where all experience seems exhausted. Wherever he
  • go, whatever he see, all is old and wearyingly familiar. Most people
  • explain this by saying that they really know everything, and that from
  • what they have experienced they can infer all experience. This phase
  • of the exhaustion of life usually comes to a man between thirty-five
  • and forty--the best period, according to Karamzin. Not seeing anything
  • new, the individual assumes he is completely matured and has the right
  • to judge of everything. Knowing what has been he can forecast what will
  • be. But Karamzin was mistaken about the best period, and the "mature"
  • people are mistaken about the "nothing new can happen." The fact of
  • spiritual stagnation should not be made the ground for judging all
  • life's possibilities from known possibilities. On the contrary, such
  • stagnation should prove that however rich and multifarious the past may
  • have been, it has not exhausted a tittle of the whole possibilities.
  • From that which has been it is impossible to infer what will be.
  • Moreover, it is unnecessary--except, perhaps, to give us a sense of
  • our full maturity and let us enjoy all the charms of the best period
  • of life, so eloquently described by Karamzin. The temptation is not
  • overwhelming. So that, if man is under the necessity of enduring a
  • period of arrest and stagnation, and until such time as life re-starts
  • is doomed to meditation, would it not be better to use this meditating
  • _interregnum_ for a directly opposite purpose from the one indicated:
  • that is to say, for the purpose of finding in our past signs which tell
  • us that the future has every right to be anything whatsoever, like or
  • utterly unlike the past. Such signs, given a good will to find them,
  • may be seen in plenty. At times one comes to the conclusion that the
  • natural connection of phenomena, as hitherto observed, is not at all
  • inevitable for the future, and that miracles which so far have seemed
  • impossible, may come to seem possible, even natural, far more natural
  • than that loathsome law of sequence, the law of the regularity of
  • phenomena. We are bored stiff with regularity and sequence--confess
  • it, you also, you men of science. At the mere thought that, however we
  • may think, we can get no further than the acknowledgment of the old
  • regularity, an invincible disgust to any kind of mental work overcomes
  • us. To discover another law--still another--when already we have far
  • more than we can do with! Surely if there is any will-to-think left
  • in us, it is established in the supposition that the mind cannot and
  • must not have any bounds, any limits; and that the theory of knowledge,
  • which is based on the _history_ of knowledge and on a few very doubtful
  • assumptions, is only a piece of property belonging to a certain caste,
  • and has nothing to do with us others_--und die Natur zuletzt sich doch
  • ergründe._ What a mad impatience seizes us at times when we realise
  • that we shall never fathom the great mystery! Every individual in
  • the world must have felt at one time the mad desire to unriddle the
  • universe. Even the stodgy philosophers who invented the theory of
  • knowledge have at times made surreptitious sorties, hoping to open a
  • path to the unknown, in spite of their own fat, senseless books that
  • demonstrate the advantages of scientific knowledge. Man either lives in
  • continuous experience, or he frees himself from conclusions imposed by
  • limited experience. All the rest is the devil. From the devil come the
  • blandishments with which Karamzin charmed himself and his readers....
  • Or is it the contrary? Who will answer! Once again, as usual, at the
  • end of a pathetic speech one is left with a conjecture. Let every man
  • please himself. But what about those who would like to live according
  • to Karamzin, but cannot? I cannot speak for them. Schiller recommended
  • hope. Will it do? To be frank, hardly. He who has once lost his peace
  • of mind will never find it again.
  • 17
  • Ever since Kant succeeded in convincing
  • the learned that the world of phenomena is quite other than the world
  • of true reality, and that even our own existence is not our real
  • existence, but only the visible manifestation of a mysterious, unknown
  • substance (substantia)--philosophy has been stuck in a new rut, and
  • cannot move a single millimetre out of the track laid out by the
  • great Königsbergian. Backward or forward it can go, but necessarily
  • in the Kantian rut. For how can you get out of the counterposing
  • of the phenomenon against the thing-in-itself? This proposition,
  • this counterposing seems inalterable, so there is nothing left but
  • to stick your head in the heavy draught-collar of the theory of
  • knowledge. Which most philosophers do, even with a glad smile, which
  • inevitably rouses a suspicion that they have got what they wanted,
  • and their "metaphysical need" was nothing more than a need for a
  • harness. Otherwise they would have kicked at the sight of the collar.
  • Surely the contraposition between the world of phenomena and the
  • thing-in-itself is an invention of the reasoning mind, as is the
  • theory of knowledge deduced from this contraposing. Therefore the
  • freedom-loving spirit could reject it in the very beginning--and
  • _basta!_ With the devil one must be very cautious. We know quite well
  • that if he only gets hold of the tip of your ear he will carry off
  • your whole body. So it is with Reason. Grant it one single assumption,
  • admit but one proposition--and _finita la commedia_. You are in the
  • toils. Metaphysics cannot exist side-by-side with reason. Everything
  • metaphysical is absurd, everything reasonable is--positive. So we come
  • upon a dilemma. The fundamental predicate of metaphysics is absurdity:
  • and yet surely many positive assertions can lay legitimate claim to
  • that self-same, highly-respectable predicate. What then? Is there means
  • of distinguishing a metaphysical absurdity from a perfectly ordinary
  • one? May one have recourse to criteria? Will not the very criterion
  • prove a pitfall wherein cunning reason will catch the poor man who was
  • rushing out to freedom? There can be no two answers to this question.
  • All services rendered by reason must be paid for sooner or later at
  • the exorbitant price of self-renunciation. Whether you accept the
  • assistance in the noble form of the theory of knowledge, or merely as
  • a humble criterion, at last you will be driven forth into the streets
  • of positivism. This happens all the time to young, inexperienced minds.
  • They break the bridle and dash forward into space, to find themselves
  • rushing into the same old Rome, whither, as we know, all roads lead:
  • or, to use more lofty language, rushing into the stable whither also
  • all roads lead. The only way to guard against positivism--granting,
  • of course, that positivism no longer attracts your sympathies--is to
  • cease to fear any absurdities, whether rational or metaphysical, and
  • systematically to reject all the services of reason. Such behaviour has
  • been known in philosophy; and I make bold to recommend it. _Credo, quia
  • absurdum_ comes from the Middle Ages. Modern instances are Nietzsche
  • and Schopenhauer. Both present noble examples of indifference to logic
  • and common-sense: particularly Schopenhauer, who, a Kantian, even in
  • the name of Kant made such daring sallies against reason, driving her
  • into confusion and shame. That astounding Kantian even went so far, in
  • the master's name still, as to attempt the overthrow of the space and
  • time notions. He admitted clairvoyance--and to this day the learned are
  • bothered whether to class that admission among the metaphysical or the
  • ordinary absurdities. Really, I can't advise them. A very clever man
  • insists on an enormous absurdity, so I am satisfied. Schopenhauer's
  • whole campaign against intellect is very comforting. It is evident
  • that, though he set out from the Kantian stable, he soon got sick
  • of hauling along down the cart-ruts, and having broken the shafts,
  • he trotted jauntily into a jungle of irreconcilable contradictions,
  • without reflecting in the least where he was making for. The primate
  • of will over reason; and music as the expression of our deepest
  • essence; are not these assertions sufficient to show us how dexterously
  • he wriggled out from the harness of synthetic judgments _a priori_
  • which Kant had placed upon every thinker. There is indeed much more
  • music than logic in the philosophy of Schopenhauer; Not for nothing
  • is he excluded from the universities. But of course one may speak of
  • him in the open; not of his ideas, naturally, but of his music. The
  • European market is glutted with ideas. How neat and nicely-finished and
  • logically well-turned-out those ideas are. Schopenhauer had no such
  • goods. But what lively and splendid contradictions he boldly spreads
  • on his stall, often even without suspicion that he ought to hide them
  • from the police. Schopenhauer cries and laughs and gets furious or
  • glad, without ever realising that this is forbidden to a philosopher.
  • "Do not speak, but sing," said Zarathustra, and Schopenhauer ready
  • fulfilled the command in great measure. Philosophy may be music--though
  • it doesn't follow that music may be called philosophy. When a man
  • has done his work, and gives himself up to looking and listening and
  • pleasantly accepting everything, hiding nothing from himself, then he
  • begins to "philosophise." What good are abstract formulae to him? Why
  • should he ask himself, before he begins to think: "What can I think
  • about, what are the limits of thought?" He will think, and those who
  • like can do the summing up and the building of theories of knowledge.
  • What is the earthly use of talking about beauty? Beautiful things must
  • be created. Not one single aesthetic theory has so far been able to
  • guess what direction the artists' mind will next take, or what are the
  • limits to his creative activity. The same with the theory of knowledge.
  • It may arrest the work of a man of learning, if he be himself afraid
  • that he is going too far, but it is powerless to pre-determine human
  • thought. Even Kant's counterposing of things-in-themselves to the world
  • of phenomena cannot finally clip the wings of human curiosity. There
  • will come a time when this unshakeable foundation of positivism will
  • be shaken. All gnosiological disputes as to what thought can or cannot
  • achieve will seem to our posterity just as amusing as the disputes
  • of the schoolmen seem to us. "Why did they argue about the nature of
  • truth, when they might have gone out and looked for truth itself?" the
  • future historians will ask. Let us have an answer ready for them. Our
  • contemporaries do not want to go out and seek, so they make a great
  • deal of talk about a theory of knowledge.
  • "Trust not thyself, young dreamer."--However sincerely you may long
  • for truth, whatever sufferings and horrors you may have surpassed, do
  • not believe your own self, young dreamer. What you are looking for,
  • you won't find. At the utmost, if you have a gift for writing you will
  • bring out a nice original book. Even--do not be offended--you may
  • be satisfied with such a result. In Nietzsche's letters relating to
  • the year 1888, the year when Brandes discovered him, you will find a
  • sad confirmation of the above. Had not Nietzsche struggled, sought,
  • suffered?--and behold, towards the end of his life, when it would
  • have seemed that all mundane rewards had become trivial to him, he
  • threw himself with rapture on the tidings of first fame, and rushed
  • to share his joy with all his friends, far and near. He does not tire
  • of telling in dozens of letters and in varying forms the story of how
  • Brandes first began his lectures on him, Nietzsche, how the audience
  • consisted of three hundred people, and he even quotes Brandes' placard
  • announcement in the original Danish. Fame just threw him a smile,
  • and forgotten are all the horrible experiences of former days. The
  • loneliness, the desertedness, the cave in the mountain, the man into
  • whose mouth the serpent climbed--all forgotten, every thought turned to
  • the ordinary, easily-comprehensible good. Such is man.
  • _Mit gier'ger Hand nach Schätzen gräbt_
  • _Und froh ist wenn er Regenwürmer findet_.
  • 19
  • When a man is young he writes because it seems to him he has discovered
  • a new almighty truth which he must make haste to impart to forlorn
  • mankind. Later, becoming more modest, he begins to doubt his truths:
  • and then he writes to convince himself. A few more years go by, and
  • he knows he was mistaken all round, so there is no need to convince
  • himself. Nevertheless he continues to write, because he is not fit for
  • any other work, and to be accounted a "superfluous" man is so horrible.
  • 20
  • A very original man is often a banal writer, and vice versa. We tend
  • so often to write not about what is going on in us, but of our _pia
  • desideria_. Thus restless, sleepless men sing the glory of sleep
  • and rest, which have long been sung to death. And those who sleep
  • ten hours on end and are always up to the mark must perforce dream
  • about adventures and storms and dangers, and even extol everything
  • problematical.
  • 21
  • When one reads the books of long-dead men, a strange sensation comes
  • over one. These men who lived two hundred, three hundred, three
  • thousand years ago are so far off now from this writing which they have
  • left on earth. Yet we look for eternal truths in their works.
  • 22
  • The truth which I have the right to announce so solemnly to-day, even
  • to the first among men, will probably be a stale old lie on my lips
  • to-morrow. So I will deprive myself of the right of calling such a
  • truth my own. Probably I shall deprive no one but myself: others will
  • go on loving and praising the self-same truth, living with it.
  • 23
  • A writer who cannot lie with inspiration--and that is a great art,
  • which few may accomplish--loves to make an exhibition of honesty and
  • frankness. Nothing else is left him to do.
  • 24
  • _The source of originality_.--A man who has lost all hope of rooting
  • out of himself a certain radical defect of character, or even of hiding
  • the flaw from others, turns round and tries to find in his defect a
  • pertain merit. If he succeeds in convincing his acquaintances, he
  • achieves a double gain: first, he quiets his conscience, and then he
  • acquires a reputation for being original.
  • 25
  • Men begin to strive towards great ends when they feel they cannot cope
  • with the little tasks of life. They often have their measure of success.
  • 26
  • A belch interrupts the loftiest meditation. You may draw a conclusion
  • if you like: if you don't like, you needn't.
  • 27
  • _A woman of conviction_.--We forgive a man his "convictions," however
  • unwillingly. It goes without saying that we balk at any individual who
  • believes in his own infallibility, but one must reconcile oneself
  • with necessity. It is ugly and preposterous to have corns on one's
  • hands, but still, they can't be avoided in this unparadisal earth of
  • sweat and labour. But why see an ideal in callosities? In practical
  • life, particularly in the social political life to which we are
  • doomed, convictions are a necessity. Unity is strength, and unity is
  • possible only among people who think alike. Again, a deep conviction
  • is in itself a strong force, far more powerful than the most logical
  • argumentation. Sometimes one has only to pronounce in a full, round,
  • vibrating chest voice, such as is peculiar to people of conviction,
  • some trifling sentence, and an audience hitherto unconvinced is carried
  • away. Truth is often dumb, particularly a new truth, which is most
  • shy of people, and which has a feeble, hoarse voice. But in certain
  • situations that which will influence the crowd is more important than
  • that which is genuine truth. Convictions are necessary to a public
  • man; but he who is too clever to believe in himself entirely, and is
  • not enough of an actor to look as if he believed, he had best give up
  • public work altogether. At the same time he will realise that lack
  • of convictions is not profitable, and will look with more indulgence
  • on such as are bound to keep themselves well supplied. Yet all the
  • more will he dislike those men who without any necessity disfigure
  • themselves with the coarse tattoo marks. And particularly he will
  • object to such women. What can be more intolerable than a woman of
  • conviction. She lives in a family, without having to grind for her
  • daily bread--why disfigure herself? Why wilfully rub her hands into
  • corns, when she might keep them clean and pretty! Women, moreover,
  • usually pick up their convictions ready-made from the man who interests
  • them most at the moment. And never do they do this so vigorously as
  • when the man himself seems incapable of paving the way to his ideas!
  • They are full of feeling for him; they rush to the last extremities
  • of resource. Will not their feeble little fists help him? It may be
  • touching, but in the end it is intolerable. So it is much pleasanter
  • to meet a woman who believes in her husband and does not consider it
  • necessary to help him. She can then dispense with convictions.
  • 28
  • _Emancipation of women_.--The one and only way of mastering an enemy
  • is to learn the use of his weapons. Starting from this, modern woman,
  • weary of being the slave of man, tries to learn all his tricks. Hard
  • is slavery, wonderful is freedom! Slavery at last is so unendurable
  • that a human being will sacrifice, everything for freedom. Of what use
  • are his virtues to a prisoner languishing in prison? He has one aim,
  • one object--to get out of prison, and he values only such qualities
  • in himself as will assist his escape. If it is necessary to break
  • an iron grating by physical force, then strong muscles will seem to
  • the prisoner the most desirable of all things. If cunning will help
  • him, cunning is the finest thing on earth. Something the same happens
  • with woman. She became convinced that man owed his priority chiefly
  • to education and a trained mind, so she threw herself on books and
  • universities. Learning that promises freedom is light, everything else
  • darkness. Of course, it is a delusion, but you could never convince her
  • of it, for that would mean the collapse of her best hopes of freedom.
  • So that in the end woman will be as well-informed as man, she will
  • furnish herself with broad views and unshakeable convictions, with a
  • philosophy also--and in the end she may even learn to think logically.
  • Then, probably, the many misunderstandings between the sexes will
  • cease. But heavens, how tedious it will be! Men will argue, women will
  • argue, children will probably be born fully instructed, understanding
  • everything. With what pain will the men of the future view our women,
  • capricious, frivolous, uninformed creatures, understanding nothing and
  • desiring to understand nothing. A whole half of the human race neither
  • would nor could have any understanding! But the hope lies there. Maybe
  • we can do without understanding. Perhaps a logical mind is not an
  • attribute, but a curse. In the struggle for existence, however, and the
  • survival of the fittest, not a few of the best human qualities have
  • perished. Obviously woman's illogicality is also destined to disappear.
  • It is a thousand pities.
  • 29
  • All kinds of literature are good, except the tedious, said Voltaire.
  • We may enlarge the idea. All men and all activities are good, except
  • the tedious. Whatever your failings and your vices, if you are only
  • amusing or interesting all is forgiven you. Accordingly, frankness and
  • naturalness are quite rightly considered doubtful virtues. If people
  • say that frankness and naturalness are virtues, always take it _cum
  • grano salis_. Sometimes it is permissible and even opportune to fire
  • off truth of all sorts. Sometimes one may stretch oneself like a log
  • across the road. But God forbid that such sincere practices should be
  • raised into a principle. To out with the truth at all times, always to
  • reveal oneself entirely, besides being impossible to accomplish, never
  • having been accomplished even in the confessions of the greatest men,
  • is moreover a far more risky business than it seems. I can confidently
  • assert that if any man tried to tell the whole truth about himself, not
  • metaphorically, for every metaphor is a covering ornament, but in plain
  • bare words, that man would ruin himself for ever, for he would lose
  • all interest in the eyes of his neighbours, and even in his own eyes.
  • Each of us bears in his soul a heavy wound, and knows it, yet carries
  • himself, _must_ carry himself as if he were aware of nothing, while all
  • around keep up the pretence. Remember Lermontov:
  • _Look! around you, playfully_
  • _The crowd moves on the usual road_.
  • _Scarce a mark of trouble on the festive faces_,
  • _Not one indecent tear_!
  • _And yet is barely one amongst them_
  • _But is crushed by heavy torture_,
  • _Or has gathered the wrinkles of young age_
  • _Save from crime or loss_.
  • These words are horribly true--and the really horrible should be
  • concealed, it frightens one off. I admit, Byron and Lermontov could
  • make it alluring. But all that is alluring depends on vagueness,
  • remoteness. Any monster may be beautiful in the distance. And no
  • man can be interesting unless he keep a certain distance between
  • himself and people. Women do not understand this. If they like a
  • man, they try to come utterly near to him, and are surprised that he
  • does not meet their frankness with frankness, and admit them to his
  • holy of holies. But in the innermost sanctuary the only beauty is
  • inaccessibility. As a rule it is not a sanctuary but a lair where the
  • wounded beast in man has run to lick his wounds. And shall this be
  • done in public? People generally, and women particularly, ought to be
  • given something positive. In books one may still sing the praise of
  • wounds, hopelessness, and despair--whatever you like, for books are
  • still literature, a conventionality. But to strip one's anguish in the
  • open market, to confess an incurable disease to others, this is to
  • kill one's soul, not to relieve it. All, even the best men, have some
  • aversion for you. Perhaps in the interest of order and decorum they
  • will grant you a not-too-important place in their philosophy of life.
  • For in a philosophy of life, as in a cemetery, a place is prepared for
  • each and all, and everyone is welcome. There also are enclosures where
  • rubbish is dumped to rot. But for those who have as yet no desire to
  • be fitted into a world-philosophy, I would advise them to keep their
  • tongue between their teeth, or like Nietzsche and Dostoevsky, take to
  • literature. To a writer, in books and only in books, all is permitted
  • provided he has talent. But in actual living even a writer must not
  • let loose too much, lest people should guess that in his books he is
  • telling the truth.
  • 30
  • Poushkin asserts that the poet himself can and must be the judge of
  • his own work. "Are you content, exacting artist? Content, then let
  • the mob revile." It is needless to argue against this, for how could
  • you prove that the supreme verdict belongs not to the poet himself,
  • but to public opinion? Nor, for that matter, can we prove Poushkin
  • right. We must agree or disagree, as we like. But we cannot reject the
  • evidence. Whether you like it or not, Poushkin was evidently satisfied
  • with his own work, and did not need his reader's sanction. Happy man!
  • And it seems to me he owed his happiness exclusively to his inability
  • to pass beyond certain limits. I doubt-if all poets would agree to
  • repeat Poushkin's verse quoted above. I decidedly refuse to believe
  • that Shakespeare, for instance, after finishing _Hamlet_ or _King
  • Lear_ could have said to himself: "I, who judge my work more strictly
  • than any other can judge, am satisfied." I do not think he can even
  • have thought for a moment of the merits of his works, _Hamlet_ or
  • _King Lear_. To Shakespeare, after Hamlet, the word "satisfied" must
  • have lost all its meaning, and if he used it, it was only by force of
  • habit, as we sometimes call to a dead person. His own works must have
  • seemed to him imperfect, mean, pitiful, like the sob of a child or the
  • moaning of a sick man. He gave them to the theatre, and most probably
  • was surprised that they had any success. Perhaps he was glad that his
  • tears were of some use, if only for amusing and instructing people. And
  • probably in this sense the verdict of the crowd was dearer to him than
  • his own verdict. He could not help accusing his own offspring--thank
  • heaven, other people acquitted it. True, they acquitted it because
  • they did not understand, or understood imperfectly, but this did not
  • matter. "Use every man after his desert, and who should 'scape a
  • whipping?" asked Hamlet. Shakespeare knew that a strict tribunal would
  • reject his works: for they contain so many terrible questions, and not
  • one perfect answer. Could anyone be "satisfied" at that rate? Perhaps
  • with _Comedy of Errors, Twelfth Night_, or even _Richard III_.--but
  • after _Hamlet_ a man may find rest only in his grave. To speak the
  • whole truth, I doubt if Poushkin himself maintained the view we have
  • quoted till the end of his days, or even if he spoke all he felt when
  • he wrote the poem in 1830. Possibly he felt how little a poet can be
  • satisfied with his work, but pride prevented his admitting it, and he
  • tried to console himself with his superiority over the crowd. Which
  • is undeniably a right thing to do. Insults--and Poushkin had to endure
  • many--are answered with contempt; and woe to the poor wretch who feels
  • impelled to justify his contempt by his own merits, according to the
  • stern voice of conscience. Such niceness is dangerous and unnecessary.
  • If a man would preserve his strength and his confidence he must give
  • up magnanimity, he must learn to despise people, and even if he cannot
  • despise them he must have the air of one who would not give a pin's
  • head for anybody. He must appear always content. ... Poushkin was a
  • clever man and a deep nature.
  • 31
  • _Metaphysics against their will_.--It often occurs to us that evil is
  • not altogether so, unnecessary, after all. Diseases, humiliations,
  • miseries, deformity, failure, and all the rest of those plants which
  • flourish with such truly tropical luxuriance on our planet, are
  • probably essential to man. Poets sing plentifully of sorrow.
  • "_Nous sommes les apprentis, la douleur est notre maître_," said
  • de Musset. On this subject everybody can bring forth a quotation,
  • not only from the philosophers, who are a cold, heartless tribe,
  • but from tender, gentle, or sentimental poets. Doubtless one knows
  • many instances where suffering has profited a man. True also, one
  • knows many cases of the direct opposite. And these are all cases of
  • profound, earnest, outrageous, incredibly outrageous suffering. Look
  • at Tchekhov's men and women--plainly drawn from life, or at any rate,
  • exceedingly life-' like. Uncle Vanya, an old man of fifty, cries beside
  • himself all over the stage, "My life is done for, my life is done for,"
  • and senselessly shoots at a harmless professor. The hero in _A Tedious
  • Story_ was a quiet, happy man engaged in work of real importance, when
  • suddenly a horrible disease stole upon him, not killing him, but taking
  • him between its loathsome jaws. But what for? Then Tchekhov's girls and
  • women! They are mostly young, innocent, fascinating. And always there
  • lies in wait for them round every corner a meaningless, rude, ugly
  • misery which murders even the most modest hopes. They sob bitterly, but
  • fate takes no notice. How explain such horrors? Tchekhov is silent.
  • He does not weep himself--he left off long ago, and besides it is a
  • humiliating thing for a grown-up person to do. Setting one's teeth, it
  • is necessary either to keep silent or--to explain. Well, metaphysics
  • under takes the explanation. Where common sense stops, metaphysics must
  • take another stride. "We have seen," it says, "many instances where
  • at first glance suffering seemed absurd and needless, but where later
  • on a profound significance was revealed. Thus it may be that what we
  • cannot explain may find its explanation in time. 'Life is lost,' cries
  • Uncle Vanya, 'Life is done for,' repeat the voices of girls innocently
  • perishing--yet nothing is lost. The very horror which a drowning man
  • experiences goes to show that the drowning is nothing final. It is
  • only the beginning of greater events. The less a man has fulfilled in
  • experience, the more in him remains of unsatisfied passion and desire,
  • the greater are the grounds for thinking that his essence cannot be
  • destroyed, but must manifest itself somehow or other in the universe.
  • Voluntary asceticism and self-denial, such common human phenomena,
  • help to solve the riddle. Nobody compels a man, he imposes suffering
  • and abstinence on himself. It is an incomprehensible instinct, but
  • still an instinct which, rooted in the depths of our nature, prompts
  • us to a decision repugnant to reason: renounce life, save yourself. The
  • majority of men do not hear or do not heed the prompting. And then
  • nature, which cannot rely on our sensibility, has recourse to violence.
  • She shows glimpses of Paradise to us in our youth, awakens hopes and
  • impossible desires, and at the moment of our supreme expectation she
  • shows us the hollowness of our hope. Nearly every life can be summed
  • up in a few words: man was shown heaven--and thrown into the mud. We
  • are all ascetics--voluntary or involuntary. Here on earth dreams and
  • hopes are only awakened, not fulfilled. And he who has endured most
  • suffering, most privation, will awaken in the afterwards most keenly
  • alive." Such long speeches metaphysics whispers to us. And we repeat
  • them, often leaving out the "it may be." Sometimes we believe them,
  • and forge our philosophies from them. Even we go so far as to assert
  • that had we the power we would change nothing, absolutely nothing in
  • the world. And yet, if by some miracle such power came into our hands,
  • how triumphantly we would send to the devil all philosophies and lofty
  • world-conceptions, all ideals and metaphysics, and plainly and simply,
  • without reflection, abolish sufferings, deformities, failures, all
  • those things to which we attach such a high educational value, abolish
  • them from the face of the earth. We are fed up, oh, how fed up we are
  • with carrying on our studies. But it can't be helped. _Faute de mieux,_
  • let us keep on inventing systems, thinking them out. But let us agree
  • not to be cross with those who don't want to have anything to do with
  • our systems. Really, they have a perfect right.
  • 32
  • Old age must be respected--so all say, even the old. And the young
  • willingly meet the demand. But in such spontaneous, even often emphatic
  • respect, is there not something insulting to old age. Every young man,
  • by his voluntary deference, seems to say: "And still the rising star
  • shines brighter than the setting." And the old, accepting the respect,
  • are well aware that they can count on nothing more. The young are
  • attentive and respectful to the old only upon the express condition
  • that the latter shall behave like old people, and stand aside from
  • life. Let a real man try to follow Faust's example, and what a shindy
  • there will be! The old, being as a rule helpless, are compelled to
  • bow to public opinion and behave as if their only interests were
  • the interests of righteousness, good name, and such-like Platonic
  • attributes. Only a few go against the convention, and these are
  • monsters and degenerates. We do not wish old men to have desires, so
  • that life is arranged as if old men desired nothing. This, of course,
  • is no great matter: even the young are compelled to be satisfied
  • with less than nothing, in our system. We are not out to meddle with
  • human rights. Our point is that science and philosophy take enforced
  • appearances for reality. Grey hair is supposed to be a sure sign of
  • victory over the passions. Hence, seeing that we must all come to
  • grey hairs, therefore the ultimate business of man is to overcome the
  • passions.... On this granite foundation whole systems of philosophy are
  • built. It is not worth while quarrelling with a custom--let us continue
  • to pay respect to old age. But let us look in other directions for
  • philosophic bases. It is time to open a free road to the passions even
  • in the province of metaphysics.
  • 33
  • _Dostoevsky_--_advocatus diaboli_.--Dostoevsky, like Nietzsche,
  • disliked Protestantism, and tried every means of degrading it in
  • the eyes of the world. As normally he was not over scrupulous, it is
  • probable he never took the trouble to acquaint himself with Luther's
  • teaching. His flair did not deceive him: the Protestant religion and
  • morality was most unsuitable to him and his kind. But does this mean
  • that it was to be calumniated, and judged, as Dostoevsky judged it,
  • merely by the etymological meaning of a word? Protestant--a protester,
  • one who only protests and has no positive content. A child's text-book
  • of history will show the absurdity of the definition. Protestantism
  • is, on the whole, the most positive, _assertive_ creed of all the
  • Christian religions. It certainly protested against Catholicism, but
  • against the destructive tendencies in the latter, and in the name of
  • positive ideals. Catholicism relied too much on its power and its
  • spell, and most of all on the infallibility of its dogmas to which it
  • offered millions of victims. To maim and mutilate a man _ad majorem
  • gloriam Dei_ was considered a perfectly proper thing in the Middle
  • Ages, the period of bloom for Catholicism. At the risk of appearing
  • paradoxical, I venture to assert that ideas have been invented only for
  • the purpose of giving the right to mutilate people. The Middle Ages
  • nourished a mysterious, incomprehensible hatred for everything normal,
  • self-satisfied, complete. A young, healthy, handsome man, at peace
  • with himself, aroused suspicion and hostility in a believing Catholic.
  • His very appearance offended religion and confuted dogma. It was not
  • necessary to examine him. Even though he went to church, and gave no
  • sign of doubt, either in deed or word, yet he must be a heretic, to
  • be converted at all cost. And we know the Catholic cost: privation,
  • asceticism, mortification of the flesh. The most normal person, kept
  • on a monastic regime, will lose his spiritual balance, and all those
  • virtues which belong to a healthy spirit and a healthy body. This was
  • all Catholicism needed. It tried to obtain from people the _extreme
  • endeavour_ of their whole being. Ordinary, natural love, which found
  • its satisfaction--this was sinful. Monks and priests were condemned
  • to celibacy--hence monstrous and abnormal passions developed. Poverty
  • was preached, and the most unheard-of greed appeared in the world,
  • the more secret the stronger it became. Humility was essential--and
  • out of bare-footed monks sprang despots who had no limits to their
  • ambitions. Luther was the last man to understand the meaning and
  • value of the tasks which Catholicism had set itself. What he saw in
  • Rome was not the accidental outcome of this or the other historical
  • circumstance, but a result of the age-long effort of generations that
  • had striven to attribute to life as alarming and dangerous a nature as
  • possible. The sincere, direct, rustic German monk was too simple-minded
  • to make out what was going on in Rome. He thought there existed one
  • truth, and that the essence of Catholicism lay in what seemed to him
  • an exemplary, virtuous life. He went direct to his aim? What meaning
  • can monasticism have? Why deprive a priest of family happiness? How
  • accept the licentiousness of the pope's capital? The common sense of
  • the normal German revolted against the absurdity of such a state of
  • things--and Luther neither could nor _would_ see any good where common
  • sense was utterly forgotten. The violent oscillation of life resulting
  • from the continuous quick passage from asceticism and blind faith to
  • unbelief and freedom of the passions aroused a mystic horror in the
  • honest monk and released the enormous powers in him necessary to start
  • the great struggle. How could he help protesting? And who was the
  • denier, Luther, or the Rome which passed on from the keeping of the
  • Divine Word to the arbitrary ordaining of all the mysteries of life?
  • Luther might have forgiven the monks had they confined themselves
  • to sophistries. But mediaeval monks had nothing in common with our
  • philosophers. They did not look for world-conceptions in books, and
  • logical tournaments amused them only moderately. They threw themselves
  • into the deeps of life, they experimented on themselves and their
  • neighbours. They passed from mortification to licentious bacchanalia.
  • They feared nothing, spared nothing. In a word, the Rome against which
  • Luther arose had undertaken to build Babylon again, not with stones,
  • but with human souls. Luther, horrified, withdrew, and with him half
  • Europe was withdrawn. That is his positive merit. And Dostoevsky
  • attacked Lutheranism, and pitied the old Catholicism and the breathless
  • heights to which its "spiritual" children had risen. Wholesome
  • morality and its support is not enough for Dostoevsky. All this is not
  • "positive," it is only "protest." Whether I am believed or not, I will
  • repeat that Vladimir Soloviov, who held that Dostoevsky was a prophet,
  • is wrong, and that N. K. Mikhailovsky, who calls him a cruel talent
  • and a grubber after buried treasure, is right. Dostoevsky grubs after
  • buried treasure--no doubt about that. And, therefore, it would be more
  • becoming in the younger generation that still marches under the flag
  • of pious idealism if, instead of choosing him as a spiritual leader,
  • they avoided the old sorcerer, in whom only those gifted with great
  • shortsightedness or lack of experience in life could fail to see the
  • dangerous man.
  • 34
  • It is boring and difficult to convince people, and after all, not
  • necessary. It would be much better if every individual kept his own
  • opinions. Unfortunately, it cannot be. Whether you like it or not, you
  • have to admit the law of gravitation. Some people find it necessary
  • to admit the origin of man from the monkey. In the empirical realm,
  • however humiliating it may be, there are certain real, binding,
  • universal truths against which no rebellion will avail. With what
  • pleasure would we declare to a representative of science that fire does
  • not burn, that rattlesnakes are not poisonous, that a fall from a high
  • tower is perfectly agreeable, etc., etc., supposing he were obliged
  • to prove to us the contrary. Unluckily the scientific person is free
  • from the burden of proof: nature proves, and thoroughly. If nature,
  • like metaphysics, set out to compel us through syllogisms or sermons
  • to believe in her, how little she would get out of us. She is much
  • more sagacious. Morality and logic she has left to Hegel and Spinoza,
  • for herself she has taken a cudgel. Now then, try to argue against
  • _this_! You will give in against your will. The cleverest of all the
  • metaphysicians, Catholic inquisitors, imitated nature. They rarely
  • tried the word, and trusted to the fire of faggots rather than of the
  • heart. Had they only had more power, it would not be possible to find
  • two people in the whole world disbelieving in the infallibility of the
  • Pope. Metaphysical ideas, dreamily expecting to conquer the world by
  • reasoned exposition, will never attain dominion. If they are bent on
  • success, let them try more effective methods of convincing.
  • 35
  • _Evolution_.--In recent years we see more and more change in the
  • philosophies of writers and even of non-literary people. The old men
  • are beside themselves--such shiftiness seems indecent. After all,
  • convictions are not gloves. But the young carelessly pass on from
  • one idea to another. Irresolute men are somewhat timid, and although
  • they abandon their former convictions they do not declare the change
  • openly. Others, however, plainly announce, as if it were nothing, how
  • far they now are from the beliefs they held six months ago. One even
  • publishes whole volumes relating how he passed on from one philosophy
  • to another, and then to a third. People see nothing alarming in that
  • kind of "evolution." They believe it is in the ordering of things.
  • But not so at all! The readiness to leave off one set of convictions
  • in order to assume another set shows complete indifference to
  • convictions altogether. Not for nothing do the old sound the alarm.
  • But to us who have fought so long against all kinds of constancy, the
  • levity of the young is a pleasant sight. They will don materialism,
  • positivism, Kantianism, spiritualism, and so on, one after the other,
  • till they realise that all theories, ideas and ideals are as of little
  • consequence as the hoop-skirts and crinolines of our grandmothers. Then
  • they will begin to live without ideals and pre-arranged purposes,
  • without foresight, relying on chance and their own ready wit. This way,
  • too, must be tried. Perhaps we shall do better by it.... Anyhow, it
  • will be more fun.
  • 36
  • _Strength of will_.--Weakness and paralysis of the will, a very
  • dangerous disease in our times, and in most other times, consists
  • not in the absolute loss of desire, such as takes place in the very
  • old, but in the loss of the capacity to translate desire into deed. A
  • diseased will is often met in violently passionate men, so that the
  • proverb--"Say I will not, not I cannot"--does not always hold good. Man
  • often would, but cannot. And then the force of desire instead of moving
  • to outward creation, works inwardly. This is justly considered the
  • most dangerous effect of the weakening of the will. For inward working
  • is destructive working. Man does not only, to put it scientifically,
  • fail to adapt nature to his needs, but he loses his own power of
  • adaptability to outward circumstances. The most ordinary doctor, or
  • even anybody, decides that he has before him a pathological case which
  • must be treated with care. The patient is of the same opinion, whilst
  • he still hopes. But when the treatment has had no results, the doctor
  • draws back and speaks of the inadequacy of his science. Then what is
  • the patient to retire upon? It is disgusting to speak of an incurable
  • disease. So he begins to think, think, think--all the time about things
  • of which nobody thinks. He is gradually forgotten, and gradually he
  • forgets everything--but first of all, that widespread truth which
  • asserts that no judgments are valid save those that are accepted
  • and universal. Not that he disputes the truth: he _forgets it_, and
  • there is none to remind him. To him all his judgments seem valid and
  • important. Of course he cannot advance the principle: let all men turn
  • from the external world into themselves. But why advance a principle
  • at all? One can simply say: I am indifferent to the destinies of the
  • external world. I do not want to move mountains or turn rivers aside or
  • rearrange the map of Europe. I don't even want to go to the tobacconist
  • to buy cigarettes. I don't want _to do_ anything. I want to think that
  • my inaction is the most important thing on earth, that any "disease" is
  • better than health, and so on and so on without end. To what thought's
  • will not a man abandoned by medicine and doctors sink down! His
  • judgments are not binding on us, that is as clear as day. But are they
  • uninteresting? And is that paralysis, that weakness of will, a disease
  • only?
  • 37
  • _Death and metaphysics_.--A superficial observer knows that the best
  • things in life are hard to attain. Some psychologists even consider
  • that the chief beauty of the highest things consists in their
  • unattainability. This is surely not true--yet there is a grain in it.
  • The roads to good things are dangerous to travel. Is it because nature
  • is so much poorer than we imagine, so she must lock up her blessings,
  • or is there some greater meaning in it, that we have not guessed? For
  • the fact is, the more alluring an end we have in view, the more risks
  • and horrors we must undertake to get there. May we not also make a
  • contrary suggestion: that behind every danger something good is hidden,
  • and that therefore danger serves as an indication, a mark to guide us
  • onwards, not as a warning, as we are taught to believe. To decide this
  • would be to decide that behind death, the greatest of dangers, must
  • lie the most promising things. It is as well not to speculate further.
  • We had best stop lest we quarrel even with metaphysics. Traditional
  • metaphysics has always been able to illumine our temporal existence
  • with the reflected beams of eternity. Let us follow the example. Let
  • us make no attempt to know the absolute. If you have discovered a
  • comforting hypothesis, even in the upper transcendental air, drag it
  • quickly to earth where labouring men forever await even an imaginary
  • relief from their lot. We must make use of everything, even of death,
  • to serve the ends of this life of ours.
  • 38
  • _The future_.--A clever, reasonable boy, accustomed to trust his
  • common sense, read in a book for children a description of a shipwreck
  • which occurred just as the passengers were eating their sweets at
  • dessert. He was astonished to learn that everyone, women and children
  • as well, who could give no assistance-whatever in saving the ship,
  • left their dessert and rushed on deck with wailing and tears. Why
  • wail, why rush about, why be stupidly agitated? The crew knew their
  • business and would do all that could be done. If you are going to
  • perish, perish you will, no matter how you scream. It seemed to
  • the boy that if he had been on the ship he would just have gone on
  • eating his sweets to the last moment. Justice should be done to this
  • judicious and irreproachable opinion. There remained only a few minutes
  • to live--would it not have been better to enjoy them? The logic is
  • perfect, worthy of Aristotle. And it was found impossible to prove to
  • the boy that he would have left his sweets, even his favourite sweets,
  • under the same circumstances, and rushed, and screamed with the rest.
  • Hence a moral--do not decide about the future. To-day common sense is
  • uppermost, and sweets are your highest law. But to-morrow you will
  • get rid of normality and sense, you will link on with nonsense and
  • absurdity, and probably you will even get a taste for bitters. What do
  • you think?
  • 39
  • A priori _synthetic judgments_.--Kant, as we know, found in mathematics
  • and the natural sciences _a priori_ synthetic judgments. Was he right
  • or wrong? Are the judgments he indicated _a priori_ or _a posteriori_?
  • Anyhow, one thing is certain: they are not accepted as absolutely,
  • but only as relatively indisputable. In metaphysics, where the only
  • curious and important truths are hidden, the case is different. Kant
  • was compelled to admit that just where metaphysics begin the capacity
  • of our human reason to judge _a priori_ ends. But since we cannot
  • dispense with metaphysical judgments, he proposed to substitute
  • for them postulates. At the same time he admitted the optimistic
  • presupposition that in the domain of the transcendental we shall find
  • all that we miss in the world of phenomena. So that, because he could
  • not invent a truly scientific metaphysics, he contrived to present us
  • with a non-scientific sort. Which is to say, after many round-about
  • journeys he brings his readers along the opposite way right back to the
  • very spot from which he led them off. Surely non-scientific metaphysics
  • existed before Kant: the mediaeval philosophers had plenty of
  • phantasies and speculations, all supported by "moral" proofs. If Kant
  • wanted to reform metaphysics, he should have got rid of its favourite
  • method of obtaining truths through inferential "conclusions." Men are
  • greedy, they want to learn much, and get their knowledge cheap. So
  • they think that every truth they have paid for with experience and loss
  • of energy entitles them to a few more truths gratis: or, in philosophic
  • language, _a priori_, by deduction. They are not ashamed to speculate
  • with a gift that has been given them. Instead of looking, listening,
  • touching, _seeking_, they want to infer and conclude. Certainly if they
  • could wring any secret out of nature, no matter by what means, cunning,
  • impudence, fraud, we would forgive them--conquerors are not judged.
  • But nothing comes of their "conclusions" save metaphysical systems and
  • empty prattle. It is surely time to give up conclusions, and get truth
  • _a posteriori_, as did Shakspeare, Goethe, Dostoevsky; that is, every
  • time you want to know anything, go and look and find out. And if one is
  • lazy, or horrified at a new experiment, let him train himself to look
  • on ultimate questions with indifference, as the positivists do. But
  • moral, ontological and such like arguments!--really, it is disgusting
  • to talk about them. Every new experiment is interesting; but our
  • conclusions, _i.e._, synthetic judgments _a priori,_ are mostly pompous
  • lies, not worth the scrap of paper on which they are recorded.
  • 40
  • _General rules_.--People go to philosophers for general principles.
  • And since philosophers are human, they are kept busy supplying the
  • market with general principles. But what sense is there in them? None
  • at all. Nature demands individual creative activity from us. Men won't
  • understand this, so they wait forever for the ultimate truths from
  • philosophy, which they will never get. Why should not every grown-up
  • person be a creator, live in his own way at his own risk and have his
  • own experience? Children and raw youths must go in leading strings. But
  • adult people who want to feel the reins should be despised. They are
  • cowards, and slothful: afraid to try, they eternally go to the wise for
  • advice. And the wise do not hesitate to take the responsibility for the
  • lives of others. They invent general rules, as if they had access to
  • the sources of knowledge. What foolery! The wise are no wiser than the
  • stupid--they have only more conceit and effrontery. Every intelligent
  • man laughs in his soul at "bookish" views. And are not books the work
  • of the wise? They are often extremely interesting--but only in so far
  • as they do not contain general rules. Woe to him, who would build
  • up his life according to Hegel, Schopenhauer, Tolstoy, Schiller, or
  • Dostoevsky. He must read them, but he must have sense, a mind of his
  • own to live with. Those who have tried to live according to theories
  • from books have found this out. At the best, their efforts produced
  • banality. There is no alternative. Whether man likes or not he will
  • at last have to realise that cliches are worthless, and that he must
  • live from himself. There are no all-binding, universal judgments--let
  • us manage with non-binding, non-universal ones. Only professors will
  • suffer for it....
  • 41
  • _Metaphysical consolations_.--Metaphysics mercilessly persecutes all
  • eudaemonistic doctrines, seeing in them a sort of _laesio majestatis_
  • of human dignity. Our dignity forbids us to place human happiness in
  • the highest goal. Suppose it is so? But why then invent consolations,
  • even metaphysical ones? Why give to such a "pure" ideal concept as
  • metaphysics such a coarse "sensual" partner as consolation?--sensual
  • in the Kantian meaning of the word. Metaphysics had much better
  • associate herself with proud disconsolation. Consolation brings
  • calm and ease, even quiet gratification to the soul. But surely, if
  • metaphysics condescend to accept any assistance whatever, she must
  • scorn all earthly gratifications, leave them to wingless positivism
  • and materialism. What are joys and pains to metaphysics?--she is one
  • thing, they another. Yet all of a sudden metaphysicians begin to shout
  • about consolations. Evidently there is a misunderstanding here, and a
  • big one. The more you pierce to the ultimate ends of the "infinite"
  • metaphysical problems, the more finite they reveal themselves.
  • Metaphysicians only look out for some new boon--I nearly said pleasure.
  • Voltaire said that if there was no God, then He should be invented. We
  • explain these words by the great Frenchman's extreme positivism. But
  • the form only is positive, the content is purely metaphysical. All that
  • a metaphysician wants to do is to convince himself that God exists. No
  • matter whether he is mistaken or not, he has found a consolation. It
  • is impossible for him to see that his belief in a certain fact does
  • not make that fact veritable. The whole question is whether there
  • does exist a supreme, conscious First Cause, or whether we are slaves
  • to the laws of dead necessity. But what does the metaphysician care
  • about this real question! Having declared himself the avowed enemy
  • of eudaemonism, he next seeks consolation, nothing but consolation.
  • To doubt his right to be consoled drives him to fury and madness. He
  • is prepared to support his convictions by every means--ranging from
  • righteous indignation to fists. It is obviously futile to try to
  • enlighten such a creature. Once a man cares nothing for God, and seeks
  • only to make the best of his life, you will not tear away his attention
  • from the immediate moment. But perhaps there is a God, and neither
  • Voltaire nor the metaphysicians have any need to invent Him. The
  • metaphysicians never saw that an avowed disbelief in God does not prove
  • the non-existence of God, but just the opposite; it is a surer sign of
  • faith than ever belief is. Unfortunate metaphysicians! They might have
  • found their greatest consolation here, and fists and moral indignation
  • and other forms of chastisement to which they have been driven might
  • have been spared us.
  • 42
  • _Practical advice_.--People who read much must always keep it in mind
  • that life is one thing, literature another. Not that authors invariably
  • lie. I declare that there are writers who rarely and most reluctantly
  • lie. But one must know how to read, and that isn't easy. Out of a
  • hundred book-readers ninety-nine have no idea what they are reading
  • about. It is a common belief, for example, that any writer who sings of
  • suffering must be ready at all times to open his arms to the weary and
  • heavy-laden. This is what his readers feel when they read his books.
  • Then when they approach him with their woes, and find that he runs away
  • without looking back at them, they are filled with indignation and talk
  • of the discrepancy between word and deed. Whereas the fact is, the
  • singer has more than enough woes of his own, and he sings them because
  • he can't get rid of them. _L'uccello canto, nella gabbia, non di gioia
  • ma di rabbia_, says the Italian proverb: "The bird sings in the cage,
  • not from joy but from rage." It is impossible to love sufferers,
  • particularly hopeless sufferers, and whoever says otherwise is a
  • deliberate liar. "Come unto Me all ye that labour and are heavy laden,
  • and I will give you rest." But you remember what the Jews said about
  • Him: "He speaks as one having authority!" And if Jesus had been unable,
  • or _had not possessed the right_, to answer this sceptical taunt, He
  • would have had to renounce His words. We common mortals have neither
  • divine powers nor divine rights, we can only love our neighbours whilst
  • they still have hope, and any pretence of going beyond this is empty
  • swagger. Ask him who sings of suffering for nothing but his songs.
  • Rather think of alleviating his burden than of requiring alleviation
  • from him. Surely not for ever should we ask any poet to sob and look
  • upon tears. I will end with another Italian saying: _Non e un si triste
  • cane che non meni la coda_. ... "No dog so wretched but he wags his
  • tail sometimes."
  • 43
  • If a patient fulfils all the orders of a sensible doctor, we say
  • he behaves wisely. If he wantonly neglects his treatment, we say
  • he acts stupidly. If a healthy person wished to inoculate himself
  • with some dangerous disease--say phthisis--we should say he was mad,
  • and forcibly restrain him. To such an extent are we convinced that
  • disease is evil, health good. Well--on what is our conviction based?
  • At a glance the question seems absurd. But then at a glance people
  • would absolutely refuse to doubt the fixity of the earth, at a glance
  • an ordinary person would giggle if he was shown the problem of the
  • relation between the real world and the ideal. Who knows what would
  • seem amenable to discussion to the ordinary person? The philosopher
  • has no right to appeal to the ordinary person. The philosopher must
  • doubt and doubt and doubt, and question when nobody questions, and
  • risk making a laughing-stock of himself. If common sense were enough
  • to settle all problems, we should have known everything long age. So
  • that--why do we value health more than sickness? Or even further--which
  • is better, health or sickness. If we will drop the utilitarian point
  • of view--and all are agreed that this has no place in philosophy--then
  • we shall see at once that we have no grounds whatever for preferring
  • health and sickness. We have invented neither the one nor the other.
  • We found them both in the world along with us. Why then do we, who
  • know so little about it, take upon ourselves to judge which are
  • nature's successes, which her failures? Health is agreeable--sickness
  • disagreeable. But this consideration is unworthy of a philosopher:
  • otherwise why be a philosopher, why distinguish oneself from the herd?
  • The philosopher invented morality, which has at its disposal various
  • pure ideas that have no relation to empirical life. Then let us go
  • further. Reason should have a supply of pure ideas also. Let Reason
  • judge in her own independent way, without conforming to conventional
  • ideas. When she has no other resort, let her proceed by the method of
  • negation: everything that common sense asserts, I, Reason, declare
  • to be false. So--common sense Says sickness is bad, reason therefore
  • asserts that sickness is the highest boon. Such Reason we should call
  • autonomous, law-unto-itself. Like a real monarch, it is guided only by
  • its own will. Let all considerations point in favour of health, Reason
  • must remain inexorable and keep her stand till we are all brought to
  • obedience. She must praise suffering, deformity, failure, hopelessness.
  • At every step she must fight common-sense and utilitarianism, until
  • mankind is brought under. Is she afraid of rebellion? Must she in the
  • last issue, like morality, adapt herself to the inclinations of the
  • mob?
  • 44
  • _Experience and Science_.--As we are well aware, science does not,
  • nay cannot, admit experience in all its extent. She throws overboard
  • an enormous quantity of individual facts, regarding them as the
  • ballast of our human vessel. She takes note only of such phenomena as
  • alternate constantly and with a certain regularity. Best of all she
  • likes those phenomena which can be artificially provoked, when, so
  • to speak, experiment is possible. She explains the rotation of the
  • earth and succession of the seasons since a regular recurrence is
  • observable, and she demonstrates thunder and lightning with a spark
  • from an electric machine. In a word, in so far as a regular alternation
  • of phenomena is observable, so far extends the realm of science. But
  • what about those individual phenomena which do not recur, and which
  • cannot be artificially provoked? If all men were blind, and one for a
  • moment recovered his sight and opened his eyes on God's world, science
  • would reject his evidence. Yet the evidence of one seeing man is worth
  • that of a million blind. Sudden enlightenments are possible in our
  • life--even if they endure only for a few seconds. Must they be passed
  • over in silence because they are not normal and cannot be provoked?--or
  • treated poetically, as beautiful fictions? Science insists on it. She
  • declares that no judgments are true except such as can be verified by
  • all and everyone. She exceeds her bounds. Experience is wider than
  • scientific experiment, and individual phenomena mean much more to us
  • than the constantly recurrent.
  • Science is useful--but she need not pretend to truth. She cannot know
  • what truth is, she can only accumulate universal laws. Whereas there
  • are, and always have been, non-scientific ways of searching for truth,
  • ways which lead, if not to the innermost secrets, yet to the threshold.
  • These roads, however, we have let fall into ruin whilst we followed
  • our modern methodologies, so now we dare not even think of them. What
  • gives us the right to assert that astrologers, alchemists, diviners,
  • and sorcerers who passed the long nights alone with their thoughts,
  • wasted their time in vain? As for the philosopher's stone, that was
  • merely a plausible excuse invented to satisfy the uninitiated. Could
  • an alchemist dare to confess openly that all his efforts were towards
  • no useful or utilitarian end? He had to guard against importunate
  • curiosity and impertinent authority in outsiders. So he lied, now
  • frightening, now alluring the mob through its cupidity. But certainly
  • he had his own important work to do: and it had only one fault, that
  • it was purely personal to him. And about personal matters it is
  • considered correct to keep silent.... Astonishing fact! As a rule a
  • man hesitates over trifles. But it does sometimes occur that a moment
  • arrives when he is filled with unheard-of courage and resolution in his
  • judgments. He is ready to stand up for his opinions against all the
  • world, dead or living. Whence such sudden surety, what does it mean?
  • Rationally we can discover no foundation for it. If a lover has got
  • into his head that his beloved is the fairest woman on earth, worth
  • the whole of life to him; if one who has been insulted feels that
  • his offender is the basest wretch, deserving torture and death; if a
  • would-be Columbus persuades himself that America is the only goal for
  • his ambition--who will convince such men that their opinions, shared
  • by none but themselves, are false or unjustifiable? And for whose
  • sake will they renounce their tenets? For the sake of objective truth?
  • that is, for the pleasure of the assurance that all men after them
  • will repeat their judgment for truth? They don't care. Let Don Quixote
  • run broadcast with drawn sword, proving the beauty of Dulcinea or the
  • impending horror of windmills. As a matter of fact, he and the German
  • philosophers with him have a vague idea, a kind of presentiment, that
  • their giants are but mill-sails, and that their ideal on the whole is
  • but a common girl driving swine to pasture. To defy such deadly doubt
  • they take to the sword or to argument, and do not rest until they have
  • succeeded in stopping the mouth of everybody. When from all lips they
  • hear the praise of Dulcinea they say: yes, she is beautiful, and she
  • never drove pigs. When the world beholds their windmilling exploits
  • with amazement they are filled with triumph; sheep are not sheep, mills
  • are not mills, as you might imagine; they are knights and cyclops. This
  • is called a proven, all-binding, universal truth. The support of the
  • mob is a necessary condition of the existence of modern philosophy and
  • its knights of the woful countenance. Scientific philosophy wearies
  • for a new Cervantes who will put a stop to its paving the way to truth
  • by dint of argument. All opinions have a right to exist, and if we
  • speak of privilege, then preference should be given to such as are most
  • run down to-day; namely, to such opinions as cannot be verified and
  • which are, for that self-same reason, universal. Once, long ago "man
  • invented speech in order to express his real relation to the universe."
  • So he may be heard, even though the relation he wishes to express be
  • unique, not to verified by any other individual. To attempt to verify
  • it by observations and experiments is strictly forbidden. If the habit
  • of "objective verification" has destroyed your native receptivity to
  • such an extent that your eyes and ears are gone, and you must rely only
  • on the evidence of instruments or objects not subject to your will,
  • then, of course, nothing is left you but to stick to the belief that
  • science is perfect knowledge. But if your eyes live and your ear is
  • sensitive--throw away instruments and apparatuses, forget methodology
  • and scientific Don-Quixotism, and try to trust yourself. What harm is
  • there in not having universal judgments or truths? How will it hurt
  • you to see sheep as sheep? It is a step forward. You will learn not
  • to see with everybody's eyes, but to see as none other sees. You will
  • learn not to meditate, but to conjure up and call forth with words
  • alien to all but yourself an unknown beauty and an unheard-of power.
  • Not for nothing, I repeat, did astrologers and alchemists scorn the
  • experimental method--which, by the way, far from being anything new or
  • particularly modern, is as old as the hills. Animals experiment, though
  • they do not compose treatises on inductive logic or pride themselves
  • on their reasoning powers. A cow who has burnt her mouth in her
  • trough will come up cautiously next time to feed. Every experimenter
  • is the same--only he systematises. But animals can often trust to
  • instinct when experience is lacking. And have we humans got sufficient
  • experience? Can experience give us what we want most? If so, let
  • science and craftsmanship serve our everyday need, let even philosophy,
  • also eager to serve, go on finding universal truths. But beyond craft,
  • science, and philosophy there is another region of knowledge. Through
  • all the ages men, each one at his own risk, have sought to penetrate
  • into this region. Shall we, men of the twentieth century, voluntarily
  • renounce our supreme powers and rights, and because public opinion
  • demands it, occupy ourselves exclusively with discovering useful
  • information? Or, in order not to appear mean or poverty-stricken in
  • our own eyes, shall we accept in place of the philosopher's stone our
  • modern metaphysics, which muffles her dread of actuality in postulates,
  • absolutes, and such-like apparently transcendental paraphernalia?
  • 45
  • _The Russian Spirit_.--It will easily be admitted that the
  • distinguishing qualities of Russian literature, and of Russian art in
  • general, are simplicity, truthfulness, and complete lack of rhetorical
  • ornament. Whether it be to our credit or to our discredit is not for
  • me to judge, but one thing seems certain: that our simplicity and
  • truthfulness are due to our relatively scanty culture. Whilst European
  • thinkers have for centuries been beating their brains over insoluble
  • problems, we have only just begun to try our powers. We have no
  • failures behind us. The fathers of the profoundest Russian writers were
  • either landowners, dividing their time between extravagant amusement
  • and State service, or peasants whose drudgery left them no time for
  • idle curiosity. Such being the case, how can we know whether human
  • knowledge has any limits? And if we don't know, it seems to us it is
  • only because we haven't tried to find out. Other people's experience
  • is not ours. We are not bound by their conclusions. Indeed, what do we
  • know of the experience of others, save what we gather, very vaguely
  • and fragmentarily and unreliably, from books? It is natural for us to
  • believe the best, till the contrary is proved to us. Any attempt to
  • deprive us of our belief meets with the most energetic resistance.
  • The most sceptical Russian hides a hope at the bottom of his soul.
  • Hence our fearlessness of the truth, realistic truth which so stunned
  • European critics. Realism was invented in the West, established
  • there as a theory. But in the West, to counteract it, were invented
  • numberless other palliating theories whose business it was to soften
  • down the disconsolate conclusions of Realism. There in Europe they
  • have the _l'être suprême_, the _deus sive natura_, Hegel's absolute,
  • Kant's postulates, English utilitarianism, progress, humanitarianism,
  • hundreds of philosophic and sociological theories in which even extreme
  • realists can so cleverly dish up what they call life, that life, or
  • realism, ceases to be life or reality altogether.
  • The Westerner is self-reliant. He knows that if he doesn't help himself
  • nobody will help him. So he directs all his thoughts to making the
  • best of his opportunities. A limited time is granted him. If he can't
  • get to the end of his song within the time-limit, the song must remain
  • unsung. Fate will not give him one minute's grace for the unbeaten
  • bars. Therefore as an experienced musician he adapts himself superbly.
  • Not a second is wasted. The _tempo_ must not drag for an instant,
  • or he is lost. The _tempo_ is everything, and it exacts facility
  • and quickness of movement. During a few short beats the artist must
  • produce many notes, and produce them so as to leave the impression
  • that he was not hurried, that he had all the time in the world at his
  • disposal. Moreover, each note must be complete, accomplished, have its
  • fulness and its value. Native talent alone will not suffice for this.
  • Experience is necessary, tradition, training, and inherited instinct.
  • _Carpe diem_--the European has been living up to the motto for two
  • thousand years. But if we Russians are convinced of anything, it is
  • that we have time enough and to spare. To count days, much less hours
  • and minutes--find me the Russian who could demean himself to such a
  • bourgeois occupation. We look round, we stretch ourselves, we rub our
  • eyes, we want first of all to decide what we shall do, and how we
  • shall do it, before we can begin to live in earnest. We don't choose
  • to decide anyhow, nor at second-hand, from fragments of other people's
  • information. It must be from our own experience, with our own brains,
  • that we judge. We admit no traditions. In no literature has there been
  • such a-determined struggle with tradition as in ours. We have wanted
  • to re-examine everything, re-state everything. I won't deny that our
  • courage is drawn from our quite uncultured confidence in our own
  • powers. Byelinsky, a half-baked undergraduate, deriving his knowledge
  • of European philosophy at third hand, began a quarrel with the universe
  • over the long-forgotten victims of Philip II. and the Inquisition.
  • In that quarrel is the sense and essence of all creative Russian
  • literature. Dostoevsky, towards his end, raised the same storm and the
  • same question over the little tear of an unfortunate child.
  • A Russian believes he can do anything, hence he is afraid of nothing.
  • He paints life in the gloomiest colours--and were you to ask him: How
  • can you accept such a life? how can you reconcile yourself with such
  • horrors of reality as have been described by all your writers, from
  • Poushkin to Tchekhov? he would answer in the words of Dmitri Karamazov:
  • _I do not accept life._ This answer seems at first sight absurd. Since
  • life is here, impossible not to accept it. But there is a sub-meaning
  • in the reply, a lingering belief in the possibility of a final triumph
  • over "evil." In the strength of this belief the Russian goes forth to
  • meet his enemy--he does not hide from him. Our sectarians immolate
  • themselves. Tolstoyans and votaries of the various sects that crop up
  • so plentifully in Russia go in among the people, they go, God knows
  • to what lengths, destroying their own lives and the lives of others.
  • Writers do not lag behind sectarians. They, too, refuse to be prudent,
  • to count the cost or the hours. Minutes, seconds, time-beats, all this
  • is so insignificant as to be invisible to the naked eye. We wish to
  • draw with a generous hand from fathomless eternity, and all that is
  • limited we leave to European bourgeoisie. With few exceptions Russian
  • writers really despise the pettiness of the West. Even those who have
  • admired Europe most have done so because they failed most completely
  • to understand her. They did not want to understand her. That is why we
  • have always taken over European ideas in such fantastic forms. Take
  • the sixties for example. With its loud ideas of sobriety and modest
  • outlook, it was a most drunken period. Those who awaited the New
  • Messiah and the Second Advent read Darwin and dissected frogs. It is
  • the same to-day. We allow ourselves the greatest luxury that man can
  • dream of--sincerity, truthfulness--as if we were spiritual Croesuses,
  • as if we had plenty of everything, could afford to let everything be
  • seen, ashamed of nothing. But even Croesuses, the greatest sovereigns
  • of the world, did not consider they had the right to tell the truth at
  • all times. Even kings have to pretend--think of diplomacy. Whereas,
  • we think we may speak the truth, and the truth only, that any lie
  • which obscures our true substance is a crime; since our true substance
  • is the world's finest treasure, its finest reality.... Tell this
  • to a European, and it will seem a joke to him, even if he can grasp
  • it at all. A European uses all his powers of intellect and talent,
  • all his knowledge and his art for the purpose of concealing his
  • real self and all that really affects him:--for that the natural is
  • ugly and repulsive, no one in Europe will dispute for a moment. Not
  • only the fine arts, but science and philosophy in Europe tell lies
  • instinctively, by lying they justify their existence. First and last,
  • a European student presents you with a finished theory. Well, and what
  • does all the "finish" and the completeness signify? It merely means
  • that none of our western neighbours will end his speech before the
  • last reassuring word is said; he will never let nature have the last
  • word; so he rounds off his synthesis. With him, ornament and rhetoric
  • is a _sine qua non_ of creative utterance, the only remedy against all
  • ills. In philosophy reigns theodicy, in science, the law of sequence.
  • Even Kant could not avoid declamation, even with him the last word is
  • "moral necessity." Thus there lies before us the choice between the
  • artistic and accomplished lie of old, cultured Europe, a lie which is
  • the outcome of a thousand years of hard and bitter effort, and the
  • artless, sincere simplicity of young, uncultured Russia.
  • They are nearer the end, we are nearer the beginning. And which is
  • nearer the truth? And can there be a question of voluntary, free
  • choice? Probably neither the old age of Europe nor the youth of Russia
  • can give us the truth we seek. But does such a thing as ultimate truth
  • exist? Is not the very conception of truth, the very assumption of the
  • possibility of truth, merely an outcome of our limited experience,
  • a fruit of limitation? We decide _a priori_ that one thing must be
  • possible, another impossible, and from our arbitrary assumptions we
  • proceed to deduce the body of truth. Each one judges in his own way,
  • according to his powers and the conditions of his existence. The timid,
  • scared man worries after _order,_ that will give him a day of peace
  • and quiet, youth dreams of beauty and brilliance, old age doesn't want
  • to think of anything, having lost the faculty for hope. And so it goes
  • on, _ad infinitum_. And this is called truth, truths! Every man thinks
  • that his own experience covers the whole range of life. And, therefore,
  • the only men who turn out to be at all in the right are empiricists and
  • positivists. There can be no question of truth once we tear ourselves
  • away from the actual conditions of life.
  • Our confident truthfulness, like European rhetoric, turns out to be
  • "beyond truth and falsehood." The young East and the old West alike
  • suffer from the restrictions imposed by truth--but the former ignores
  • the restrictions, whilst the latter adapts itself to them. After all,
  • it comes to pretty much the same in the end. Is not clever rhetoric
  • as delightful as truthfulness? Each is equally _life_. Only we find
  • unendurable a rhetoric which poses as truth, and a truthfulness
  • which would appear cultured. Such a masquerade would try to make us
  • believe that truth, which is only _limitedness_, has a real objective
  • existence. Which is offensive. Until the contrary is proved, we need to
  • think that only one assertion has or can have any objective reality:
  • _that nothing on earth is impossible_. Every time somebody wants to
  • force us to admit that there are other, more limited and limiting
  • truths, we must resist with every means we can lay hands on. We do not
  • hesitate even to make use of morality and logic, both of which we have
  • abused so often. But why not use them!
  • When a man is at his last resources, he does not care what weapons he
  • picks up.
  • 46
  • _Nur für Schwindelfreie_.--To be proper, I ought to finish with a
  • moral. I ought to say to the reader that in spite of all I have said,
  • or perhaps _because of_ all I have said--for in conclusions, as you
  • are aware, "in spite of" is always interchangeable with "because of,"
  • particularly if the conclusion be drawn from many scattered data--well
  • then, because of all I have said, hope is not lost. Every destruction
  • leads to construction, sweet rest follows labour, dawn follows the
  • darkest hour, and so on and so on and so on--all the banalities with
  • which a writer reconciles his reader. But it is never too late for
  • reconciliation, and it is often too early. So why not postpone the
  • moral for a few years--even a few dozen years, God granting us the
  • length of life? Why make the inevitable "conclusion" at the end of
  • every book? I am almost certain that sooner or later I can promise the
  • reader all his heart desires. But not yet. He may, of course, dispense
  • with my consolations. What do promises matter, anyhow? especially when
  • neither reader nor writer can fulfil them. But if there is no escape,
  • if a writer is finally obliged to admit in everybody's hearing that the
  • secret desires of poor mankind may yet be realised, let "us at least
  • give the wretched writer a respite, let him postpone his confession
  • till old age_--usque ad infinitum_,... Meanwhile our motto "_Nur für
  • Schwindelfreie._" There are in the Alps narrow, precipitous paths where
  • only mountaineers may go, who feel no giddiness. Giddy-free! "Only
  • for the giddy-free," it says on the notice-board. He who is subject
  • to giddiness takes a broad, safe road, or sits away below and admires
  • the snowy summits. Is it inevitably necessary to mount up? Beyond the
  • snow-line are no fat pastures nor goldfields. They say that up there
  • is to be found the clue to the eternal mystery--but they say so many
  • things. We can't believe everything. He who is tired of the valleys,
  • loves climbing, and is not afraid to look down a precipice, and, most
  • of all, has nothing left in life but the "metaphysical craving," he
  • will certainly climb to the summits without asking what awaits him
  • there. He does not fear, he longs for giddiness. But he will hardly
  • call people after him: he doesn't want just anybody for a companion.
  • In such a case companions are not wanted at all, much less those
  • tender-footed ones who are used to every convenience, roads, street
  • lamps, guide-posts, careful maps which mark every change in the road
  • ahead. They will not help, only hinder. They will prove superfluous,
  • heavy ballast, which may not be thrown overboard. Fuss over them,
  • console them, promise them! Who would be bothered? Is it not better to
  • go one's way alone, and not only to refrain from enticing others to
  • follow, but frighten them off as much as possible, exaggerate every
  • danger and difficulty? In order that conscience may not prick too
  • hard--we who love high altitudes love a quiet conscience--let us find
  • a justification for their inactivity. Let us tell them they are the
  • best, the worthiest of people, really the salt of the earth. Let us
  • pay them every possible mark of respect. But since they are subject to
  • giddiness, they had better stay down. The upper Alpine ways, as any
  • guide will tell you, are _nur für Schwindelfreie_.
  • End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of All Things are Possible, by Lev Shestov
  • *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK ALL THINGS ARE POSSIBLE ***
  • ***** This file should be named 57369-0.txt or 57369-0.zip *****
  • This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/5/7/3/6/57369/
  • Produced by Marc D'Hooghe at Free Literature (Images
  • generously made available by the Internet Archive.)
  • Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will
  • be renamed.
  • Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
  • law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
  • so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
  • States without permission and without paying copyright
  • royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
  • of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm
  • concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
  • and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive
  • specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this
  • eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook
  • for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports,
  • performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given
  • away--you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks
  • not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the
  • trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
  • START: FULL LICENSE
  • THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  • PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
  • To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
  • distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
  • (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
  • Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org/license.
  • Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
  • and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
  • (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
  • the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
  • destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your
  • possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
  • Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
  • by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the
  • person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph
  • 1.E.8.
  • 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
  • used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
  • agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
  • things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
  • paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this
  • agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  • 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the
  • Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
  • of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual
  • works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
  • States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
  • United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
  • claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
  • displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
  • all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
  • that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting
  • free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
  • Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily
  • comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
  • same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when
  • you share it without charge with others.
  • 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
  • what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
  • in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
  • check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
  • agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
  • distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
  • other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no
  • representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
  • country outside the United States.
  • 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
  • 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
  • immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear
  • prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work
  • on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the
  • phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed,
  • performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
  • most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no
  • restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it
  • under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this
  • eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the
  • United States, you'll have to check the laws of the country where you
  • are located before using this ebook.
  • 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is
  • derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
  • contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
  • copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
  • the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
  • redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
  • either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
  • obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
  • with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
  • must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
  • additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
  • will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works
  • posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
  • beginning of this work.
  • 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
  • work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
  • 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
  • electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
  • prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
  • active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License.
  • 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
  • compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
  • any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
  • to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format
  • other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official
  • version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site
  • (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
  • to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
  • of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain
  • Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the
  • full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
  • 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
  • performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
  • unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
  • access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • provided that
  • * You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
  • the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
  • you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
  • to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has
  • agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
  • within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
  • legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
  • payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
  • Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation."
  • * You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
  • you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
  • does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
  • copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
  • all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works.
  • * You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
  • any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
  • electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
  • receipt of the work.
  • * You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
  • distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  • 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than
  • are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
  • from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and The
  • Project Gutenberg Trademark LLC, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
  • 1.F.
  • 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
  • effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
  • works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
  • contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
  • or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
  • intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
  • other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
  • cannot be read by your equipment.
  • 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
  • of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
  • liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
  • fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
  • LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
  • PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
  • TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
  • LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
  • INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
  • DAMAGE.
  • 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
  • defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
  • receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
  • written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
  • received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
  • with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
  • with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
  • lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
  • or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
  • opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
  • the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
  • without further opportunities to fix the problem.
  • 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
  • in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO
  • OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
  • LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
  • 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
  • warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
  • damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
  • violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
  • agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
  • limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
  • unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
  • remaining provisions.
  • 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
  • trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
  • providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in
  • accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
  • production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
  • including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
  • the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
  • or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or
  • additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any
  • Defect you cause.
  • Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
  • electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
  • computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
  • exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
  • from people in all walks of life.
  • Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
  • assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
  • goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
  • remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
  • and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future
  • generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
  • Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
  • www.gutenberg.org Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation
  • The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
  • 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
  • state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
  • Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
  • number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
  • U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
  • The Foundation's principal office is in Fairbanks, Alaska, with the
  • mailing address: PO Box 750175, Fairbanks, AK 99775, but its
  • volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous
  • locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt
  • Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to
  • date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and
  • official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact
  • For additional contact information:
  • Dr. Gregory B. Newby
  • Chief Executive and Director
  • gbnewby@pglaf.org
  • Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation
  • Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
  • spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
  • increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
  • freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
  • array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
  • ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
  • status with the IRS.
  • The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
  • charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
  • States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
  • considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
  • with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
  • where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
  • DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular
  • state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
  • have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
  • against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
  • approach us with offers to donate.
  • International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
  • any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
  • outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
  • Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
  • methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
  • ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
  • donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works.
  • Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be
  • freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
  • distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of
  • volunteer support.
  • Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
  • editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
  • the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
  • necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
  • edition.
  • Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search
  • facility: www.gutenberg.org
  • This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
  • including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
  • subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.