- The Project Gutenberg EBook of Supply and Demand, by Hubert D. Henderson
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
- almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
- re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
- with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
- Title: Supply and Demand
- Author: Hubert D. Henderson
- Release Date: January 6, 2004 [EBook #10612]
- Language: English
- *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK SUPPLY AND DEMAND ***
- Produced by Josh Cogliati and PG Distributed Proofreaders
- SUPPLY AND DEMAND
- By Hubert D. Henderson M.A.
- With an Introduction by J.M. Keynes M.A., C.B.
- 1922.
- INTRODUCTION
- The Theory of Economics does not furnish a body of settled conclusions
- immediately applicable to policy. It is a method rather than a
- doctrine, an apparatus of the mind, a technique of thinking, which
- helps its possessor to draw correct conclusions. It is not difficult
- in the sense in which mathematical and scientific techniques are
- difficult; but the fact that its modes of expression are much less
- precise than these, renders decidedly difficult the task of conveying
- it correctly to the minds of learners.
- Before Adam Smith this apparatus of thought scarcely existed. Between
- his time and this it has been steadily enlarged and improved. Nor is
- there any branch of knowledge in the formation of which Englishmen can
- claim a more predominant part. It is not complete yet, but important
- improvements in its elements are becoming rare. The main task of the
- professional economist now consists, either in obtaining a wide
- knowledge of _relevant_ facts and exercising skill in the application
- of economic principles to them, or in expounding the elements of his
- method in a lucid, accurate and illuminating way, so that, through his
- instruction, the number of those who can think for themselves may be
- increased.
- This Series is directed towards the latter aim. It is intended to
- convey to the ordinary reader and to the uninitiated student some
- conception of the general principles of thought which economists now
- apply to economic problems. The writers are not concerned to make
- original contributions to knowledge, or even to attempt a complete
- summary of all the principles of the subject. They have been more
- anxious to avoid obscure forms of expression than difficult ideas; and
- their object has been to expound to intelligent readers, previously
- unfamiliar with the subject, the most significant elements of economic
- method. Most of the omissions of matter often treated in textbooks are
- intentional; for as a subject develops, it is important, especially in
- books meant to be introductory, to discard the marks of the chrysalid
- stage before thought had wings.
- Even on matters of principle there is not yet a complete unanimity of
- opinion amongst professors. Generally speaking, the writers of these
- volumes believe themselves to be orthodox members of the Cambridge
- School of Economics. At any rate, most of their ideas about the
- subject, and even their prejudices, are traceable to the contact they
- have enjoyed with the writings and lectures of the two economists who
- have chiefly influenced Cambridge thought for the past fifty years,
- Dr. Marshall and Professor Pigou.
- J.M. Keynes.
- CONTENTS
- CHAPTER I
- THE ECONOMIC WORLD
- §1. THEORY AND FACT
- §2. THE DIVISION OF LABOR
- §3. THE EXISTENCE OF ORDER
- §4. SOME REFLECTIONS UPON JOINT PRODUCTS
- §5. SOME REFLECTIONS UPON CAPITAL
- §6. THE FUNDAMENTAL CHARACTER OF MANY ECONOMIC LAWS
- CHAPTER II
- THE GENERAL LAWS OF SUPPLY AND DEMAND
- §1. PRELIMINARY STATEMENT OF THREE LAWS
- §2. DIAGRAMS AND THEIR USES
- §3. AMBIGUITIES OF THE EXPRESSIONS, "INCREASE IN DEMAND," ETC.
- §4. REACTIONS OF CHANGES IN DEMAND AND SUPPLY ON PRICE
- §5. SOME PARADOXICAL REACTIONS OF PRICE CHANGES ON SUPPLY
- §6. THE DISTURBANCES OF MONETARY CHANGES
- §7. THE TRADE CYCLE
- CHAPTER III
- UTILITY AND THE MARGIN OF CONSUMPTION
- §1. THE FORCES BEHIND SUPPLY AND DEMAND
- §2. THE LAW OF DIMINISHING UTILITY
- §3. THE RELATION BETWEEN PRICE AND MARGINAL UTILITY
- §4. THE MARGINAL PURCHASER
- §5. THE BUSINESS MAN AS PURCHASER
- §6. THE DIMINISHING UTILITY OF MONEY
- CHAPTER IV
- COST AND THE MARGIN OF PRODUCTION
- §1. AN ILLUSTRATION FROM COAL
- §2. THE VARIOUS ASPECTS OF MARGINAL COST
- §3. THE DANGERS OF IGNORING THE MARGIN
- §4. A MISINTERPRETATION
- §5. SOME CONSEQUENCES OF A HIGHER PRICE LEVEL
- §6. GENERAL RELATION BETWEEN PRICE, UTILITY AND COST
- CHAPTER V
- JOINT DEMAND AND SUPPLY
- §1. MARGINAL COST UNDER JOINT SUPPLY
- §2. MARGINAL UTILITY UNDER JOINT DEMAND
- §3. A CONTRAST BETWEEN COTTON AND COTTON-SEED, AND WOOL AND MUTTON
- §4. THE IMPORTANCE OF BEING UNIMPORTANT
- §5. CAPITAL AND LABOR
- §6. CONCLUSIONS AS TO JOINT SUPPLY AND JOINT DEMAND
- §7. COMPOSITE SUPPLY AND COMPOSITE DEMAND
- §8. ULTIMATE REAL COSTS
- CHAPTER VI
- LAND
- §1. THE SPECIAL CHARACTERISTICS OF LAND
- §2. THE SCARCITY ASPECT
- §3. THE DIFFERENTIAL ASPECT
- §4. THE MARGIN OF TRANSFERENCE
- §5. THE NECESSITY OF RENT
- §6. THE QUESTION OF REAL COSTS
- §7. RENT AND SELLING PRICE
- CHAPTER VII
- RISK-BEARING AND ENTERPRISE
- §1. PROFITS AND EARNINGS OF MANAGEMENT
- §2. THE PAYMENT FOR RISK-BEARING
- §3. MONTE CARLO AND INSURANCE
- §4. RISK UNDER LARGE SCALE ORGANIZATION
- §5. THE ENTREPRENEUR
- §6. RISK-TAKING AND CONTROL
- §7. GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROFITS
- CHAPTER VIII
- CAPITAL
- §1. A REFERENCE TO MARX
- §2. WAITING FOR PRODUCTION
- §3. WAITING FOR CONSUMPTION
- §4. CAPITAL NOT A STOCK OF CONSUMABLE GOODS
- §5. THE ESSENCE OF WAITING
- §6. INDIVIDUAL AND SOCIAL SAVING
- §7. THE NECESSITY OF INTEREST
- §8. THE SUPPLY OF CAPITAL
- §9. INVOLUNTARY SAVING
- §10. INTEREST AND DISTRIBUTION
- CHAPTER IX
- LABOR
- §1. A RETROSPECT ON LAISSEZ-FAIRE
- §2. IDEAS AND INSTITUTIONS
- §3. THE GENERAL WAGE-LEVEL
- §4. THE SUPPLY OF LABOR IN GENERAL
- §5. THE APPORTIONMENT OF LABOR AMONG PLACES
- §6. THE APPORTIONMENT OF LABOR AMONG SOCIAL GRADES
- §7. THE APPORTIONMENT OF LABOR AMONG OCCUPATIONS
- §8. WOMEN'S WAGES
- CHAPTER X
- THE REAL COSTS OF PRODUCTION
- §1. COMPARATIVE COSTS
- §2. THE ALLOCATION OF RESOURCES
- §3. UTILITY AND WEALTH
- §4. CRITERIA OF POLICY
- SUPPLY AND DEMAND
- CHAPTER I
- THE ECONOMIC WORLD
- §1. _Theory and Fact_. The controversy between the "Theorist" and the
- "Practical Man" is common to all branches of human affairs, but it is
- more than usually prevalent, and perhaps more than usually acrid in
- the economic sphere. It is always a rather foolish controversy, and I
- have no intention of entering into it, but its prevalence makes it
- desirable to emphasize a platitude. Economic theory must be based
- upon actual fact: indeed, it must be essentially an attempt, like all
- theory, to _describe_ the actual facts in proper sequence, and in true
- perspective; and if it does not do this it is an imposture. Moreover,
- the facts which economic theory seeks to describe are primarily
- economic facts, facts, that is to say, which emerge in, and are
- concerned with, the ordinary business world; and it is, therefore,
- mainly upon such facts that the theory must be based. People
- sometimes speak as though they supposed the economist to start from a
- few psychological assumptions (e. g. that a man is actuated mainly by
- his own self-interest) and to build up his theories upon such
- foundations by a process of pure reasoning. When, therefore, some
- advance in the study of psychology throws into apparent disrepute such
- ancient maxims about human nature, these people are disposed to
- conclude that the old economic theory is exploded, since its
- psychological premises have been shown to be untrue. Such an attitude
- involves a complete misunderstanding not merely of economics, but of
- the processes of human thought. It is quite true that the various
- branches of knowledge are interrelated very intimately, and that an
- advance in one will often suggest a development in another. By all
- means let the economist and psychologist avoid a pedantic specialism
- and let each stray into the other's province whenever he thinks
- fit. But the fact remains that they are primarily concerned with
- different things: and that each is most to be trusted when he is upon
- his own ground. When, therefore, the economist indulges in a
- generalization about psychology, even when he gives it as a reason for
- an economic proposition, in nine cases out of ten the economics will
- not depend upon the psychology; the psychology will rather be an
- inference (and very possibly a crude and hasty one) from the economic
- facts of which he is tolerably sure.
- But the purpose of economic theory is not merely to describe the facts
- of the economic world; it is to describe them in their proper sequence
- and true perspective. It must begin with those facts which are most
- general and which have the widest possible significance. Those are not
- likely to be the facts which our practical experience forces most
- insistently upon our notice. For it is the particular and not the
- general, the differences between things rather than their
- resemblances, that concern us most in daily life. Nor are we likely to
- find the universal facts which we require in the sphere of public
- controversy. We must rather look for them in the dark recesses of our
- consciousness, where are stored those truths which are so obvious that
- we hardly notice them, which are so indisputable that we seldom
- examine them, which seem so trite that we are apt to miss their full
- significance.
- §2. _The Division of Labor_. There is one such truth in the economic
- sphere which it is essential to appreciate vividly and fully, with the
- widest sweep of the imagination and the sharpest clarity of
- thought. Man lives by cooperating with his fellow-men. In the modern
- world, that cooperation is of a boundless range and an indescribable
- complexity. Yet it is essentially undesigned and uncontrolled by
- man. The humblest inhabitant of the United States or Great Britain
- depends for the satisfaction of his simplest needs upon the activities
- of innumerable people, in every walk of life and in every corner of
- the globe. The ordinary commodities which appear upon his dinner table
- represent the final product of the labors of a medley of merchants,
- farmers, seamen, engineers, workers of almost every craft. But there
- is no human authority presiding over this great complex of labor,
- organizing the various units, and directing them towards the common
- ends which they subserve. Wheel upon wheel, in a ceaseless succession
- of interdependent processes, the business world revolves: but no one
- has planned and no one guides the intricate mechanism whose smooth
- working is so vital to us all. Man, indeed, can organize and has
- organized much. Within a large factory the efforts of thousands of
- work-people, each engaged on the repetition of a single small process,
- are fitted together so as to form an ordered whole by the conscious
- direction of the management. Sometimes factory is joined with factory,
- with farms, fisheries, mines, with transport and distributing
- agencies, as one gigantic business unit, controlled by a common
- will. These giant businesses are remarkable achievements of man's
- organizing gifts. The individuals who control them wield an immense
- power, which so impresses the public imagination that we dub them
- "kings," "supermen," "Napoleons of industry." But how small a portion
- of man's economic life is dominated by such men! Even as regards the
- affairs of their own businesses, how narrow, after all, are the limits
- of their influence! The prices at which they can buy their materials
- and borrow their capital, the quantities of their products which the
- public will consume, are factors at once vital to their prosperity and
- outside their own control.
- A great business, like a nation, may cherish visions of
- self-sufficiency, may stretch its tentacles forward to the consumer
- and backwards to its supplies of raw material; but each fresh
- extension of its activities serves only to multiply its points of
- contact with the outside world. When those points are reached, the
- largest business, like the smallest, is out on the open sea of an
- economic system immeasurably larger and more powerful than
- itself. There it must meet--the better perhaps for its inherent
- strength and accumulated knowledge--the impact of rude forces, which
- it is powerless to control. Beneath the blasts of a trade depression,
- or some other tendency of world-wide scope, the authority of the
- mightiest industrial magnate, and equally of any Government, assumes
- the same essential insignificance as the pride of a man humbled by
- contact with the elemental powers of nature.
- §3. _The Existence of Order_. The parallel can be pursued further with
- advantage. Just as in the world of natural phenomena, which for long
- seemed to man so wayward and inexplicable, we have come gradually to
- perceive an all-pervading uniformity and order; so there is manifest
- in the economic world, uniformity, order, of a similar if less
- majestic kind. Upon the cooperation of his fellowmen, man depends for
- the very means of life: yet he takes this cooperation for granted,
- with a complacent confidence and often with a naive unconsciousness,
- as he takes the rising of to-morrow's sun. The reliability of this
- unorganized cooperation has powerfully impressed the imagination of
- many observers.
- "On entering Paris which I had come to visit," exclaimed Bastiat some
- seventy years ago, "I said to myself--Here are a million of human
- beings who would all die in a short time if provisions of every kind
- ceased to flow towards this great metropolis. Imagination is baffled
- when it tries to appreciate the vast multiplicity of commodities which
- must enter to-morrow through the barriers in order to preserve the
- inhabitants from falling a prey to the convulsions of famine,
- rebellion, and pillage. And yet all sleep at this moment, and their
- peaceful slumbers are not disturbed for a single instant by the
- prospect of such a frightful catastrophe. On the other hand, eighty
- departments have been laboring to-day, without concert, without any
- mutual understanding, for the provisioning of Paris."
- The theme may well excite wonder. But wonder should always be watched
- with a wary eye; for he is apt to bring in his train a hanger-on
- called worship, who can do nothing but mischief here. It is a short
- step from a passage like that quoted above to a glorification of the
- existing system of society, to a defence of all manner of indefensible
- things; and a cross-grained attitude towards all projects of
- reform. It is a short step; but it is one which it is quite
- unjustifiable to take. For the evils of our economic system are too
- plain to be ignored; too many people have harsh personal experience of
- the wastefulness of its production, the injustice of its distribution;
- of its sweating, its unemployment and slums. And when the attempt is
- made to plaster over evils, such as these with obsequious rhetoric
- about the majesty of economic law, it is not surprising that the
- spirit of many men should revolt and that they should retort by
- denying the existence of order in the business world, by declaring
- that the spectacle which _they_ see is one of discord, confusion and
- chaos. And then we are engulfed in a controversy as stale, flat and
- unprofitable as that between the "theorist" and the "practical man."
- The truth is that the language of praise and obloquy is quite
- inappropriate. In the first place, it may be well to note that the
- order of which I have spoken manifests itself not merely in those
- economic phenomena which are beneficial to man, but hardly less in
- those which work to his hurt. Even in those alternations of good and
- bad trade, which spell so much unemployment and misery, there is
- discernible a rhythmic regularity like that of the process of the
- seasons, or the ebb and flow of the tide. This is not an elegance to
- be admired. Furthermore, in so far as the order comprises adjustments
- and tendencies which are beneficial (as, indeed, is mainly true),
- there is no warrant for assuming that these are either adequate to
- secure a prosperous community or dependent upon the social
- arrangements which happen to exist. Let us, therefore, refrain from
- premature polemics and examine in a spirit of detachment some further
- aspects of the elaborate, but yet unorganized, cooperation of which so
- much has been already said.
- §4. _Some Reflections upon Joint Products_. A quite inadequate idea of
- the complexity of this coöperation is obtained by dwelling on the
- numbers of people who participate in it, or the immense distances over
- which it extends. The deficiency can be partially supplied by
- referring to some of the more obvious of the many subtle
- interconnections which exist between different commodities and
- different trades.
- There are innumerable groups of commodities (which it is customary to
- term "joint products") such that the production of one commodity
- belonging to the group necessarily implies or very greatly facilitates
- the production of the others. Wool and mutton; beef and hides; cotton
- and cotton-seed are a few familiar illustrations. The important
- feature of these "joint products" is the fairly precise relation which
- must exist between the quantities in which the different products are
- supplied. If you plant a certain crop of cotton, it will yield you so
- much cotton lint and so much cotton-seed. You can, of course, if you
- choose, throw away part of the seed, as indeed at one time planters
- used to do; but unless you do this, you cannot vary the proportions of
- the two things which you will have for sale. Similarly, if you keep a
- flock of sheep, or a herd of cattle, you will obtain wool and mutton
- in the one case, or beef and hides in the other, in proportions, which
- indeed you can vary within certain limits by choosing a different
- breed,[1] but which you cannot radically transform. When, however, we
- turn to the uses to which these products are put, no similar relation
- is to be discovered. Cotton lint is used chiefly for making articles
- of clothing; cotton-seed for crushing into oil, on the one hand, and
- cake for cattle fodder on the other. There is no apparent connection
- of any kind between the demands for these different things, and still
- less is there any obvious reason why these demands should bear to one
- another the particular proportions which characterize their respective
- supplies. It is very much the same with wool and mutton; with beef and
- hides; with all "joint products." Why should we consume mutton on the
- one hand and woolen clothing on the other, in a ratio at all
- commensurate with that in which they are yielded by the sheep?
- [Footnote 1: These possibilities of small variation are of very great
- importance as will be shown in Chapter V, but they do not affect the
- present argument.]
- What, then, might we expect to find if order was nonexistent in the
- economic world? Surely that some things such as wool would be produced
- in quantities many times in excess of the demand for them, quite
- possibly five, ten, or twenty times in excess; while conversely the
- supplies of others such as mutton might fall far short of what was
- required. But in practice we find nothing of the sort. Somehow it
- comes about that an equilibrium is established between the demand for
- and the supply of every commodity; and that this applies to wool and
- mutton, to beef and hides, as surely as to commodities which are
- produced quite independently. It is true that this equilibrium is a
- rough, imperfect one; and it may happen that what is called a "glut"
- of wool may co-exist for a short period with what is called a scarcity
- of mutton. But qualifications of this nature are in the strictest
- sense of the phrase, the exceptions which prove the rule. For the
- departures from equilibrium which gluts and scarcities represent are
- always transient and are usually confined within narrow limits. A
- strong prevailing trend towards an adjustment of demand and supply is
- unmistakably manifest amid all the vagaries of changing circumstance.
- Let me carry the argument a step further for the benefit of any reader
- who is restrained by a repugnance too deep and instinctive to be
- readily overcome, from admitting fairly to his mind that conception of
- order which I am endeavoring to emphasize. He will in all probability
- be one who, cherishing ideals of a better and fairer system of
- society, looks forward to a time when an organized coöperation will be
- substituted for what he regards as the existing chaos. Let us suppose
- that his visions were fulfilled as completely as he could desire; and
- that an immense system of Socialism were in existence, embracing not
- one country only, but the whole world. Suppose all the difficulties of
- human perversity and administrative technique to have been surmounted
- and a wise, disinterested executive to be in supreme control of our
- business life. Let us suppose all this, and ask only the question: How
- would this executive treat the humdrum case of wool and mutton? How
- would it decide the number of sheep it would maintain?
- Shall we suppose that it is inspired by the ideal "to each according
- to his need," and that it resolves accordingly that the commodities
- which people require for a decent standard of life shall be supplied
- to them as a matter of course? How, then, would it proceed? It might
- estimate the amount of woolen clothing which a normal family requires,
- allowing for differences in climate, and possibly indulging somewhat
- the caprices of human taste. On this basis, a certain number of sheep
- would be indicated. It might perform a similar calculation for mutton,
- and again a certain number of sheep would be indicated. But it would
- be an extraordinary coincidence if the numbers which resulted from
- these independent calculations were nearly equal to one another, or
- were even of the same order of magnitude; and, if they differed
- widely, what number would our world executive select? Would it decide
- to waste an immense quantity of either wool or mutton; or would it
- decide that it could not, after all, supply the full human needs for
- one or other of the commodities?
- Of course, if the executive were sensible it could solve the problem
- satisfactorily enough. It could retain the monetary system we know
- to-day and it could supply the commodities to the consumers, not as a
- matter of right, but by selling them to them _at a price_. This price
- it could then move upwards or downwards, raising, say, the price of
- mutton and reducing that of wool, until it found that the consumption
- of the two things was adjusted in the required ratio. But if it acted
- in this manner, what essentially would it be doing? It would be
- seeking by deliberate contrivance to reproduce, in respect of this
- particular problem, the very conditions which occur to-day without aim
- or effort on the part of anyone at all.
- The moral of this illustration must not be misinterpreted. It does
- not show the folly of Socialism or the superiority of
- Laissez-faire. What it does show is the existence in the economic
- world of an order more profound and more permanent than any of our
- social schemes, and equally applicable to them all.
- §5. _Some Reflections upon Capital_. Another aspect of the great
- cooperation is of even greater significance. It embraces not only a
- multitude of living men, but it links the present together with the
- future and the past. The goods and services which we enjoy to-day we
- owe only in part to the labors of the week, the month, or the year,
- only in part even to the efforts of our contemporaries. The men, long
- since dead and forgotten, who built our railways, or sunk our coal
- mines, or engaged in any of a great variety of tasks, are still
- contributing to the satisfaction of our daily wants. The expression is
- not altogether fanciful; for, had it not been reasonable to expect
- that those labors would be of use to us to-day, many of them in all
- probability would never have been undertaken. It was to meet our
- present wants, and even our future wants, that many men toiled on
- monotonous tasks ten, twenty, thirty years ago. And yet, of course, we
- should deceive ourselves if we supposed that this was the motive of
- these men, that our welfare was the centre of their heart's desire. We
- in our turn dedicate to the future, and often to a distant future, an
- immense portion of our energies. Let any reader who doubts this, study
- the statistics of the occupations of the people, and reflect on how
- long a period must elapse before the labors of this trade or that can
- fulfil their ultimate function. How long would the period be in the
- case of a man making bricks, which will later be employed in the
- erection of a factory, where machinery will be made, to equip an
- electrical generating station designed to supply, over a period of
- many years, light, heat, and power to people living in a remote
- Continent? A longer time, it may be hazarded, than he is accustomed
- to look ahead.
- Like the daily cooperation of living men, this cooperation of past,
- present and future is essential to the well-being of mankind, and yet
- it is undesigned and unorganized. As private individuals, men do,
- indeed, deliberately provide for their own future, and for that of
- their kith and kin: as the directors of businesses, they try to
- forecast the trend of demand. But such conscious calculations and
- deliberate acts would avail little if they stood alone. They are
- hardly more than the necessary spokes in the great wheel which
- regulates the relations of past, present and future. The hub of the
- wheel is an elaborate system of borrowing and lending, essentially
- similar to the buying and selling of commodities. The private
- individual in order to provide for his family or for his old age
- "saves" and "invests." But what exactly does this mean? It means that
- he transfers so much purchasing power, which he might have spent on
- his personal pleasures, to some one else in return for the expectation
- of receiving, year by year in the future, he and his heirs after him,
- a certain smaller quantity of purchasing power. The other party to the
- transaction will be, we may suppose, a business man who enters into it
- because he sees the opportunity of a promising industrial development,
- to undertake which he requires more purchasing power than he himself
- possesses. And, because this transaction is entered into, a smaller
- number of us will shortly be engaged in making motorcars, or
- gramaphones, and a larger number of us in making factories and
- machinery, which will later enhance the world's productive power.
- Many transactions of the kind take place daily in modern communities,
- and their multiplicity gives rise to a mass of phenomena with which we
- are all tolerably familiar. We recognize a short-loan market, a stock
- exchange, a number of "markets" where lenders and borrowers are
- brought together by the aid of various intermediaries, such as banks,
- bill brokers, and stock jobbers, who correspond to dealers in
- commodities. Between these different specialized markets, we are
- aware of an interconnection so close and strong that we speak more
- generally of a Capital Market, of which the stock exchange, the
- short-loan market and so forth, are the component parts. Now, "market"
- is a word which was originally used to denote a place where tangible
- commodities were bought and sold; and the more closely we examine the
- phenomena of the Capital Market, the more closely do we perceive the
- profound resemblance between the mechanism of borrowing and lending,
- and that of buying and selling. Corresponding to the price of a
- commodity is the rate of interest (in the short-loan market we
- actually call the rate of Discount "the price of money," and speak of
- money being cheap or dear); and between the rate of interest, the
- demand for and the supply of capital there exist relations precisely
- similar to those between price, demand, and supply in commodity
- markets. Above all there is the same strong prevailing trend towards
- an adjustment of demand and supply.
- This fundamental resemblance between two such apparently
- incommensurable things as the buying of material commodities and the
- borrowing of capital is highly significant; it is another instance of
- that order in the economic world, of which the reader may now be
- growing weary. But so difficult is it to see clearly and fully
- something which one sees, as it were, every day of one's life, that a
- few more moments of reflection on the special case of capital will be
- time well spent. Let us revert then to our fantasy of a world
- socialist commonwealth; and humbly submit another poser to its supreme
- executive. The question this time will be whether some great
- constructional work, such, let us say, as the recently mooted Severn
- barrage scheme, should or should not be undertaken. Let us suppose
- that the costs and future benefits of the undertaking can be estimated
- accurately; and that the problem reduces itself to one of expending
- now a sum, let us say, of $100,000,000, with the prospects of
- obtaining in the future an income of power, or whatever it may be,
- worth $5,000,000 per annum. I have assumed for the sake of simplicity
- that we shall still be reckoning in terms of money, though possibly
- the executive may have substituted Marxian labor units; but it is
- quite immaterial to the present argument what the measuring rod may
- be. The point to be observed is, that it is impossible to tackle the
- problem at all without the conception of a rate of interest. For
- suppose that you tried to do without it, and said, "We shall take a
- long view. The interests of the future are no less our concern than
- those of the present; we shall not discriminate between them. We shall
- regard as an enterprise worthy to be undertaken whatever promises to
- yield in the course of time a return larger than the outlay." Where
- will this lead you? The particular proposal set out above would
- clearly pass the test; for in twenty years the resultant benefits
- would have added up to a figure equivalent to the initial cost. But
- equally clearly, the cost might have been more than $100,000,000; it
- might have been $250,000,000, $500,000,000, whatever figure you care
- to take, and if you extend the period similarly to fifty or one
- hundred years, sooner or later the gains would top the cost. Now there
- is no limit to the enterprises which would pay their way on this
- basis; and it would be quite impossible to undertake them all. For
- they would swallow up all and more than all your labor and your
- materials, and would leave you with no resources with which to meet
- the recurrent daily wants of men. Clearly, then, in some way or other,
- you must pick and choose, you must reject some enterprises as
- _insufficiently_ worth while. But how would you proceed to choose?
- Without a clear principle, a simple criterion to guide you, you would
- be plunged in utter chaos. You could not say, "Let all proposals
- involving capital expenditure be submitted to a central committee, who
- shall compare them with one another in a sort of competitive
- examination and, after deciding the number of applications they can
- pass on the basis of the volume of resources which they can devote to
- the future, award the places to those which head the list." Such a
- prospect is a nightmare of officialism and delay. You would be driven
- to formulate a simple, intelligible rule or measure, and leave that
- rule to be applied by the unfettered judgment of innumerable men to
- individual problems, as and when they arose. And for such a rule or
- measure, you could not do better than a rate of interest; you would
- have to lay it down that only those projects should be approved which
- promised a return of 6 per cent, or whatever it might be. Even in
- deciding what it should be, the limits of your choice would be
- narrowly confined. If, for instance, you fixed on 1 or 2 per cent,
- you would probably discover that you had not achieved your object,
- that the undertakings for distant returns which passed this test,
- still consumed far more resources than you could spare. You would be
- compelled then to raise the rate until it had cut these enterprises
- down within manageable limits. But, once more, what essentially would
- you be doing? You would be using the instrument of the rate of
- interest to adjust the demand for and supply of capital, though indeed
- the interest might not be paid away as now to private individuals. You
- would be reproducing by the method of deliberate trial and error, the
- adjustments which occur automatically as things are, in the actual
- world. Once again the most perfectly contrived Utopia would be
- compelled to pay to the unorganized coöperation of our epoch the
- sincerest flattery of imitation.
- §6. _The Fundamental Character of many Economic Laws_. But again
- perhaps a word of warning may be desirable. There is much controversy
- in these days about something called "Capitalism" or "The capitalist
- system." When these words are used with any precision, they usually
- refer to the arrangement so prevalent at present, whereby the
- ownership and sole ultimate control of a business rests with those who
- hold its stocks and shares. There is much to be said upon the merits
- and demerits of this system; something will perhaps be said upon the
- matter in the fifth volume of this series; but I shall not discuss it
- here. Nothing that I have said so far has any real bearing on it
- whatsoever; to suppose that it has, is indeed to miss the whole point
- of this chapter.
- The order, which I have sought to reveal, pervading and moving the
- most diverse phenomena of the economic world, would be a far less
- noteworthy and impressive thing were it merely the peculiar product of
- capitalism. Merchant adventurers, companies, and trusts; Guilds,
- Governments and Soviets may come and go. But under them all, and, if
- need be, in spite of them all, the profound adjustments of supply and
- demand will work themselves out and work themselves out again for so
- long as the lot of man is darkened by the curse of Adam.
- CHAPTER II
- THE GENERAL LAWS OF SUPPLY AND DEMAND
- §1. _Preliminary Statement of Three Laws_. The recognition of order in
- any branch of natural phenomena is but the prelude to the formulation
- of a set of laws, the simpler as the order is more universal, which
- describe, and as we say, explain it. Thus the perception of the even,
- elliptical courses of the heavenly bodies led to the statement of the
- law of gravitation and the laws of motion.
- In economics, similar laws have long since been enunciated, and have
- proved themselves such valuable instruments for the understanding of
- the daily problems of the workaday world, that they have been woven
- into the texture of our ordinary speech and thought. I have already
- touched upon them in the preceding chapter. But it is now desirable to
- set them out in order, in the most concise and formal manner possible.
- LAW I. When, at the price ruling, demand exceeds supply, the price
- tends to rise. Conversely when supply exceeds demand the price
- tends to fall.
- LAW II. A rise in price tends, sooner or later, to decrease demand and
- to increase supply. Conversely a fall in price tends, sooner or
- later, to increase demand and to decrease supply.
- LAW III. Price tends to the level at which demand is equal to supply.
- These three laws are the cornerstone of economic theory. They are the
- framework into which all analysis of special, detailed problems must
- be fitted. Their scope is very wide. I have purposely refrained from
- introducing into my statement of them any reference to commodities;
- for they extend far beyond commodities. Subject to an important
- qualification, they apply to capital, the price paid for the use of
- capital being what we call the rate of interest. They apply hardly
- less to "services," to the remuneration of labor of every kind and
- grade. People sometimes protest warmly against the idea of treating
- labor "like a commodity." If this indignation expresses no more than
- a belief that in matters concerning conditions of work, and relations
- between employees and the management, the sensibilities of human
- nature should be taken into due account, it is based on elementary
- decency and commonsense. But if, as sometimes appears, it is directed
- against the fact that the remuneration of labor is controlled by the
- laws of supply and demand, it is a mere baying at the moon, with
- singularly little provocation. For these laws are in no way peculiar
- to commodities, and it is no one's fault that they include commodities
- too within their scope.
- But let us go back to the laws themselves, and probe them and dissect
- them, and turn them this way and that, so that we may perceive their
- full content, and grasp it firmly in our minds. The third law implies
- a prevailing tendency for demand to be equal to supply. This
- tendency, as was suggested in Chapter I, can be verified by anyone
- from his experience and observation (provided he is a reasonable
- person, and not the tiresome kind who would dispute the law of
- gravitation because he sees that a feather falls to the ground more
- slowly than a stone). But it can also be deduced as a corollary from
- the two preceding laws; and to regard it in this way will help us to
- appreciate its significance. Start, for instance, by supposing that
- demand is in excess of supply. Then the price will tend to rise. After
- the price has risen, the supply will become larger, while the demand
- will fall away. The excess of demand with which we started will thus
- clearly be diminished. But if there remains any portion of this
- excess, the same reactions will continue; the price will rise further,
- and for the same reason; demand will be further checked and supply
- further stimulated. In other words, these forces must persist until
- the entire excess of demand over supply is eliminated. If we start by
- supposing supply to exceed demand, the converse chain of sequences
- will operate. Now these very simple steps of reasoning illuminate the
- nature of the normal equilibrium of demand and supply. They reveal
- that the equilibrium is established and maintained by the agency of
- _changes in price_, and they enable us to lay it down as perhaps the
- most important thing that can be said about the price of anything that
- it will tend to be such as will equate demand and supply. But that is
- not all that they reveal. They reveal also the extreme dependence of
- both demand and supply upon price.
- Now this is a fact which it is most important to realize vividly. It
- is apt to be obscured by customary modes of speech. In ordinary times
- the prices of most commodities and services do not change by very
- much, unless indeed over a long period of years; the amounts demanded
- and supplied may therefore seem to maintain a fairly constant level;
- and we may be tempted to speak of Great Britain producing so many
- million tons of coal, or America consuming so many millions of
- motor-cars per annum, almost as though these quantities were
- independent of price considerations. But we should never forget that
- there is no service or commodity produced by man, however essential it
- may seem, the demand for or the supply of which might not be reduced
- to nothing, if the price were sufficiently raised on the one hand, or
- lowered on the other. How easy it is sometimes to forget this simple
- truth may be seen from the mistake so commonly made of supposing,
- because the peoples of Central Europe were left, on the cessation of
- the war, starving and destitute of the means of life and the materials
- of work, that they must necessarily become heavy purchasers of
- imported goods; without pausing to consider whether the prices were
- such as they could afford to pay.
- §2. _Diagrams and their Uses_. It will help to prevent mistakes like
- this and more generally to make sharp and clear the fundamental
- relations which exist between demand, supply and price, if we exhibit
- them pictorially in the form of a diagram. Such diagrams are of great
- service in many parts of economic theory, not because they can prove
- anything which could not be proved otherwise, but because, being
- really a simpler medium of expression than words, they enable the mind
- to grasp more readily and to retain more vividly the essential facts
- of complex relations.
- Figure 1:
- Y
- |
- | S'
- | *
- D | **
- |* **
- | ** *
- | ** *
- | * *
- | ** **
- | ** *
- | ** *
- | ** **
- | ** *
- | ** Q **
- _l_|--------------*------------* R
- | |*** **
- | | ** P **
- _m_|--------------------***
- | | *** |***
- _k_|--------------***----+---** _r_
- | _q_*| | ***
- | *** | | ****
- | *** | | ****
- | *** | | ***
- S |**** | | ****
- | | | ** D'
- | | |
- | | |
- | | |
- | | |
- 0+-------------------------------------------------------- X'
- N M.
- Figure 1
- In Fig. 1 the curve DD' represents the conditions of demand. It is
- supposed to be drawn in such a way that if any point, Q, be taken on
- the curve, and the perpendicular QN be drawn to meet the base line, or
- axis OX, then ON will represent the amount that will be demanded at a
- price represented by QN (or O_l_). In other words, distances measured
- along OY represent prices, and distances measured along OX represent
- quantities of the commodity, or service, or whatever it may be.
- Clearly, then, the demand curve, DD', must slope downwards from left
- to right, since the lower the price asked, the greater will be the
- amount demanded. Similarly the curve SS' represents the conditions of
- supply. It is supposed to be so drawn that if any point _q_ be taken
- upon it, and the perpendicular _q_N be drawn to meet OX, then ON will
- represent the amount that will be supplied at a price represented by
- _q_N (or O_k_). Equally clearly this supply curve must slope upwards
- from left to right, since the higher the price obtainable, the greater
- will be the quantity offered. Take the point P where the two curves
- meet, and draw the perpendicular PM to meet OX. Then the third law
- enunciated at the beginning of this chapter corresponds to the
- statement that PM or O_m_ will represent the price at which the
- commodity or service will be exchanged.
- It can readily be seen that no other price could be maintained. For
- suppose the price to be less than O_m_, suppose it to be O_k_, then,
- at this price, ON (or _kq_) will be the amount supplied, and _kr_ the
- amount demanded. The demand will thus exceed the supply, and the
- price will tend to rise, i.e. to move upwards towards O_m_. Similarly
- if we suppose the price to be O_l_, which is larger than O_m_, the
- supply (_l_R) will exceed the demand (_l_Q) and the price will fall
- downwards towards O_m_. Thus, again, we have deduced Law III from Laws
- I and II with the form and precision of a proposition in Euclid. Now,
- when once the eye has become familiar with this diagram, it ought to
- be impossible for the mind to lose even momentarily its grip on the
- fact that demand and supply are both dependent upon price. For these
- curves do not represent any particular amounts; they represent a
- series of _relations_ between amount and price; if the price is QN the
- amount demanded is ON, and so forth. The terms demand and supply in
- the sense, in which I have been using them, of the respective amounts
- demanded and supplied are, indeed, strictly meaningless without
- reference to some particular price. The reference may sometimes be
- implicit; but, whenever there is a chance of ambiguity, it should be
- explicitly made.
- §3. _Ambiguities of the Expressions, "Increase in Demand," etc_. It is
- the more important to be precise upon this point, in that there is a
- further possible confusion which we have now to consider. Demand and
- supply, as we have seen, are dependent upon price; but equally clearly
- they are dependent upon other things as well. Demand depends upon the
- needs, tastes and habits of the people, as well as upon the length of
- their purse; supply depends upon such things as the cost of production
- in the case of commodities. None of these things are constant
- factors, all of them are liable to change, and it may well happen that
- we shall want to consider in some concrete problem the probable
- consequences of such a change. Now the most usual and natural way of
- describing such changes in the medium of words is to use the
- expression "increase" or "decrease in demand," and "increase" or
- "decrease in supply," the same expressions, which we employed before
- to describe the consequences of a change in price. This identity of
- language conceals a fundamental distinction between the phenomena
- described; and to make this distinction plain we cannot do better than
- revert to our diagrammatic presentation of the laws.
- Figure 2:
- Y |
- |
- _d_|
- |.
- | .
- | . _s'_
- | . .
- D | . .
- |** . . * S'
- | ** .. . *
- | ** . . *
- | ** . .. *
- | * .. . **
- | ** . . **
- | ** .. .. **
- | * . . *
- | ** . . *
- | ** .. . **
- | ** .. .. **
- | ** .. .. **
- | ** . .. **
- | ** p' .. **
- | **.. .. **
- | ..|**p **._p_
- | .. | **** | ..
- | ... |**|** | ..
- | .. *| | *| ..
- | ..... *** | | |** .
- _s_|...... *** | | | ** ..
- | *** | | | ** ...
- | ***** | | | ** ...
- S |***** | | | ** ..
- | | | | *** .._d'_
- | | | | ***
- | | | | **
- | | | | **D'
- | | | |
- | | | |
- 0+---------------------------------------------------------
- M' M _m_
- Figure 2
- In Fig. 2 we start as before with our demand curve, and supply curve,
- cutting one another at the point P. We then suppose that some
- alteration takes place in the conditions of demand; there has been a
- growth in the general taste for the commodity or service, and the
- demand, as we say, has increased accordingly. How is this fact to be
- represented in the diagram? Plainly not by taking another point on
- the curve, DD', at a further distance from OY. For this would merely
- indicate the larger amount that would be taken, if the conditions of
- demand had remained unaltered but the sellers had reduced their
- prices. The correct way of representing the change we have supposed is
- to construct a new demand curve (in the figure, the dotted curve
- _dd'_), lying at every point above the old demand curve. For this
- indicates that larger quantities will be purchased at the old prices,
- which is exactly what we want to represent. Similiarly if we wish to
- represent a change in the conditions of supply, such as might result,
- in the case of a commodity, from a tax imposed on its production, we
- must draw a new supply curve, _ss'_, which in the case supposed, must
- lie everywhere above the old supply curve. On the other hand, the
- decrease or increase in demand or supply, _resulting_ from a change in
- price, is represented simply by a shifting of the equilibrium from one
- point to another on the same curve. The striking pictorial contrast
- between a movement from one curve to another, and a movement along the
- same curve should help to make vivid to our minds the fundamental
- distinction between a change in the _conditions_ of demand, arising
- from new tastes, enhanced purchasing power, etc.; and a mere change in
- the amount purchased resulting from an alteration in the price which
- the sellers ask. Words, as this necessarily cumbrous sentence shows,
- are a clumsy instrument for the expression of abstract relations; it
- is not very easy to see which words in a sentence are the significant,
- commanding ones, and which are performing, as it were, ordinary
- routine duties. A diagram is not exposed to similar ambiguities of
- emphasis.
- The particular distinction, to which attention has been called, is
- important. The reader who has grasped it clearly will be able to
- perceive many instances of the confusion arising out of its neglect in
- the ordinary discussions of economic questions which take place in the
- press and on the platform. It is not uncommon, for instance, for an
- argument to run something like this: "The effect of a tax on this
- commodity might seem at first sight to be an advance in price. But an
- advance in price will diminish the demand; and a reduced demand will
- send the price down again. It is not certain, therefore, after all,
- that the tax will really raise the price." A glance at the diagram
- will keep us out of such a bog of sophistry and muddle. For if we
- suppose the amount of the tax per unit of the commodity to be
- represented by S_s_, the curve _ss'_ (drawn, as it is, roughly
- parallel to SS') will represent the new conditions of supply after the
- tax has been imposed. The new position of equilibrium will be given by
- the point P', where _ss'_ cuts DD', the demand curve. Now P' lies to
- the left of P the old point of equilibrium; hence, since DD' _must_
- slope downwards from left to right, it is clear that, if, as it is
- fair here to assume, the _conditions_ of demand have remained
- unaltered, the new price P'M', must be greater than the old.
- §4. _Reactions of Changes in Demand and Supply on Price_. Having now
- made clear the meaning that must be attached to the terms, let us
- consider the question which naturally arises, whether we can lay down
- any general propositions or laws as to the effect upon price, of an
- increase or decrease in demand or supply. Another glance at the
- diagram suggests that we can. An increase in demand is represented in
- Fig. 2 by a movement from DD' to _dd'_, which cuts the supply curve,
- SS', at _p_, to the right of P. Since the supply curve (drawn, as it
- is best to draw it, to represent the amount which will be supplied in
- response to a given price) must always slope upwards from left to
- right, the new price, _pm_, must be greater than the old, PM.
- Conversely a decrease in demand is represented by a movement from
- _dd'_ to DD', and the new price is seen to be less than the old. We
- have already seen that a decrease in supply, which is represented by a
- movement from SS' to _ss'_ results in a higher price; and it is the
- obvious converse that an increase in supply will have the opposite
- effect. It would seem then that we might lay down quite generally that
- an increase in demand or a decrease in supply will raise the price
- while a decrease in demand or an increase in supply will lower it.
- But here it is necessary to be cautious. All conclusions as to the
- effects of causes are necessarily based, implicitly, if not
- explicitly, upon the assumption "other things being equal." This
- method of reasoning, which some people appear to find so irritating in
- the economic sphere, and as they say so "theoretical" and "unreal," is
- one which they adopt readily enough in every other department of
- life. No one, for instance, objects to the statement that the sun,
- when it comes out, makes a room warmer, although it may very well
- happen, if a fire is dying at the same time, that the room grows
- colder in point of fact. For in our general statement we assume
- implicitly that "other things" such as fires, are unchanged. But
- assumptions of this kind are legitimate only when there is no reason
- to suppose that the cause, the effects of which are being studied,
- will itself produce a change in the "other things." If (as I have
- often been told; I really do not know if it is true) the rays of the
- sun help to put a fire out, the statement made above would be the
- better for some qualification.
- Now we can only say that an increase in demand raises price if we
- assume the conditions of supply (as represented by the supply curve)
- to remain unchanged. But in practice, an increase in demand may cause
- a change in the _conditions_ of supply. An increase, for instance, in
- the demand for a commodity may give rise to a revolution in the
- methods of production, to the introduction of labor-saving machinery
- and so forth, which will eventually result in the commodity being
- produced more cheaply. It will certainly take a considerable time
- before reactions of this kind can exert an appreciable influence; and
- we can, therefore, feel reasonably sure that over a short period an
- increase in demand will raise the price. But we cannot be sure what
- the ultimate effect will be. A similar alteration in the condition of
- demand is less likely to result from an increase or decrease in
- supply; but it may conceivably occur. We must, therefore, be careful
- to qualify any general propositions which we lay down in this
- connection, by explicit reference to a short period of time. We can
- add the following to our body of laws:--
- LAW IV. An increase in demand, or a decrease in supply will tend to
- raise the price for a short period at least. Conversely a decrease
- in demand, or an increase in supply will tend to lower the price
- for a short period at least.
- This law, like the others, applies to commodities, services, capital,
- to anything which can be said, literally, or by analogy, to have a
- price. "A short period" is, however, a vague expression and, since
- precision is the hallmark of an important law, we must accord to this
- one a status inferior to that which the preceding three can rightly
- claim.
- §5. _Some paradoxical reactions of price changes on supply_. Let us
- turn, though, once more to these earlier laws, and with a heightened
- critical sense let us submit them to the test of the whole gamut of
- our experience, and see if in any of them we can find the smallest
- flaw. The first of them will pass through the ordeal--let each reader
- prove it for himself--unscathed. The second will emerge with a few
- hairs, as it were, singed. It tells us, for instance, that a rise in
- price will tend to augment the supply. Now there are some things the
- supply of which cannot possibly be augmented; these are the capital
- resources of nature, of which land is the most important for our
- present purpose. Land is bought and sold, it commands a price. In a
- certain sense, it may be said to be possible to increase the supply of
- land, in response to a rise in price, by drainage and reclamation
- schemes; and it will certainly happen that a rise in the price which
- land can command for any particular purpose will increase the amount
- which is devoted to that purpose. But, speaking broadly, the supply
- of land available for purposes of every kind is a fixed unvarying
- factor, with an inertia which the cajolery of price-changes is
- powerless to disturb. This is a most important fact, and it gives rise
- to some peculiar features of the price and rent of land, which we
- shall have to consider later as a separate problem. It constitutes a
- limiting case rather than an exception to the general law. But we have
- not yet done with the reactions of price upon supply. In the case of
- capital, the nature of those reactions has been much discussed as a
- highly controversial question. That a rise in the rate of interest
- will cause some people to save more than before, is generally
- admitted; but it is pointed out that the effect upon others may be the
- exact opposite, because it means that they do not need to save so much
- to acquire the same future annual income. It is unwise to say
- dogmatically that the former tendency outweighs the latter; though
- upon the whole it seems highly probable that it does. We cannot,
- therefore, in this case feel confident that a change in price will
- react upon supply in the manner which our law indicates. Similarly it
- is possible to argue that a rise in the general level of real wages
- may reduce the supply of labor, even, or some might say particularly,
- if the term is used to denote not the number of workpeople, but the
- quantity of work done. For there may be a tendency for workpeople,
- when more comfortably off, to work less regularly or less hard. Here
- again we cannot be sure. In none of these cases, however, including
- that of land, is there any reason to doubt that a rise in price will
- diminish _demand_, or conversely that a fall will increase it. Since,
- therefore, in the reasoning by which we deduced the third law, the
- conclusion will hold good, even if the effects of price-changes on
- supply are of the above paradoxical kind, provided that they do not
- continually outweigh the effects upon demand, there is no reason to
- cast doubt on the solidity of Law III, which, indeed, as we suggested
- before, commends itself directly to experience. But Law II seems now,
- perhaps, somewhat the worse for wear.
- The damage, however, is not considerable. For in each case the
- uncertainty arises only when we are dealing with one of the factors of
- production, land, labor or capital, _regarded as a whole_. If we are
- dealing with the capital available for a particular industry, a rise
- in the rate of profit in that industry will certainly increase the
- supply of capital available there; for it will tend to attract savings
- that might otherwise have been employed elsewhere. We can even be
- fairly sure that an increase in the general rate of interest
- prevailing in any particular country will increase the total supply of
- capital available for the businesses of that country, since capital
- has in modern times acquired a considerable migratory power. In the
- case of labor, we cannot go so far as this; but here, too, there is no
- doubt that an increase in the remuneration offered in any particular
- occupation will attract an increased labor supply (always supposing,
- of course, that "other things are equal"). No similar difficulty
- arises for land, labor or capital, as regards the effect of
- price-changes on demand; while for ordinary commodities there is no
- such difficulty on the side either of demand or of supply. Hence the
- only qualification which the strictest accuracy would require us in
- this connection to attach to our statement of Law II is the
- postscript:--
- "Except that, in the case of land, the aggregate supply is
- unalterable; while in the case of capital or labor we cannot be
- sure how price-changes will affect the aggregate supply."
- Much significance attaches to these exceptions, as later will appear.
- §6. _The Disturbances of Monetary Changes_. But let us still keep a
- critical eye on Law II, and submit it to another flashlight from our
- practical experience. The recent world war made us all acutely aware
- of a remarkable rise in the price of almost everything, which yet did
- not seem to diminish appreciably the demand. The explanation of this
- paradox is not difficult to find. There was an immense increase in the
- volume of nominal purchasing power, due to a complex set of causes, of
- which "currency inflation" may be taken as the symbol. Now perhaps we
- are entitled to assume the absence of such currency changes as part of
- the "other things being equal" which is always understood as
- implied. But it is rash to take this particular assumption for
- granted, more especially in these days. Already people are too apt to
- speak as though the trade depression (which as these pages are written
- holds us in its grip) cannot pass away until pre-war prices are
- restored, ignoring altogether the great and probably permanent
- increase in nominal purchasing power which the war has left behind
- it. It would be safer, therefore, to add explicitly to Law II the
- reservation, "Assuming that there is no change in the general volume
- of purchasing power."
- Monetary and allied questions will form the subject of the second
- volume of this series. It must not be supposed that our general laws
- have no bearing on them. On the contrary, Law I, which all this time
- has remained serene and undisturbed by the occasional discomfitures of
- Law II, is the gateway through which all questions of currency,
- banking and the foreign exchanges should be approached. It is well to
- note, as an inexorable corollary of Law I, that prices can rise _only_
- if demand exceeds supply, and fall _only_ if supply exceeds demand;
- and hence that it is only through the agency of changes in the demand
- for and supply of commodities and services that an inflation or
- deflation of the currency can influence the price level. Further,
- since a condition of things in which supply generally exceeds demand
- spells what we know and fear as a trade depression, it may be well to
- note at once that falling prices and unemployment are inseparable
- bedfellows. For we are far too apt to shut our eyes to these
- unpleasant truths. But we cannot pursue them further here; and in the
- remainder of this volume we shall not be concerned (except, perhaps,
- incidentally) with questions affecting the general level of prices or
- of purchasing power; but rather with the relation which the price of
- one commodity bears to that of another, with the rate of interest
- (which being a rate per cent is not essentially dependent on the price
- level), with "real" wages (as distinct from money wages) and the like.
- §7. _The Trade Cycle_. But our reference to trade depressions suggests
- a final comment on Law II. One small qualification was embodied in our
- original statement of it, namely the words "sooner or later." A rise
- in price may not check the demand immediately (even if the printing
- presses are standing idle in the Treasuries); it may actually
- stimulate it for a time. For people may fear that the price will rise
- further still, and hasten to buy what they _must_ buy before very
- long. Sellers may share the same opinion, and be reluctant on their
- side to part. When prices are falling the roles are reversed, and we
- are likely to see the sellers tumbling over one another in a frantic
- eagerness to sell, the buyers wary and aloof. Sooner or later, indeed,
- these tendencies must dissolve and disappear; but they may persist for
- a longer period than might seem probable at first. For the raw
- material of one trade is, as we say, the finished product of
- another. The demand for one thing gives rise to a demand for other
- things, for the labor with which to make them, and so on in an
- expanding circle. A sympathy, subtle and intense, unites the business
- world, and a wave of depression or animation arising in any quarter
- may spread itself far and wide, heightened by the gusts of human hope
- and fear, and continue long before its influence is spent.
- Here we are upon the threshold of one of the most striking and
- formidable of economic facts, the regular alternation of periods of
- good and bad trade, each very widespread, if not world-wide, in its
- range, each comprising certain regular phases of acceleration and
- decay, and each infallibly yielding sooner or later to the other. The
- details of these phenomena are highly complex, some of them obscure;
- an immense literature has already been devoted to the subject, yet its
- systematic study is hardly more than begun. The account given in the
- preceding paragraph is incomplete and meagre. It is inserted here in
- the hope that it will impress the reader with a sense both of the fact
- of these alternations and of the deeply rooted nature of the causes
- from which they spring. They take a heavy toll of human happiness and
- wealth; and there is no object that more urgently calls for concerted
- human effort than that of mitigating them, and of alleviating the
- misery which they bring in their train. Still better, of eradicating
- them if that is possible; but let none suppose that it can be lightly
- done. Meanwhile, let us always remember that they form the atmosphere
- and medium in which the enduring tendencies of the business world must
- work themselves out. It is often convenient to speak of "normal
- conditions" in this trade or that; but hardly ever can it be truly
- said of a particular moment that conditions are normal. The normal is
- rather a mean level about which oscillations to and fro, round and
- about, are constantly taking place, but which itself is reached only
- by accident, if at all. Whenever we say that some new factor should in
- the long run lower the price of this or that commodity or service, the
- picture which these words should convey to our mind is one of the
- price rising less on times of boom, and falling more in times of
- depression than is the case with other things. And if ever our faith
- in some honored economic law is shaken by the apparent ease with
- which, perhaps, in times of active trade, sellers are able to advance
- their prices to whatever figure (so it almost seems) they choose to
- name, let us rally our sense of economic rhythm, and reserve our
- judgment until the trade cycle has run its course.
- CHAPTER III
- UTILITY AND THE MARGIN OF CONSUMPTION
- §1. _The Forces behind Supply and Demand_. The laws enunciated in the
- preceding chapter constitute the framework and skeleton of all
- economic analysis; but they do not carry us very far. It is only
- through the agency of these laws that any influence can affect the
- price of anything: but what influences may so affect it is a question
- which we have still to consider.
- Let us begin with ordinary commodities and ask ourselves, in the light
- of experience and common sense, upon what factors their price seems
- mainly to depend? Two factors spring to mind at once; their cost of
- production and their usefulness. As regards the former, the case seems
- clear enough. We may indeed sometimes grumble that the price of this
- or that commodity is unconscionably high in comparison with its cost;
- but this only goes to show that we conceive a relation between price
- and cost as the normal, governing rule. If one commodity cost only a
- half as much to produce as another, we should think that something had
- gone very wrong indeed, if the former commodity were sold for the
- higher price. But, when we turn to the usefulness of commodities, the
- case is not so clear. Usefulness has some connection with price, so
- much is certain; for an entirely useless thing, fit only for the
- dust-bin (and known to be such, it may be well to add) will fetch no
- price at all, however costly it may be to produce. But it is not easy
- to express the connection in quantitative terms. It seems reasonable
- enough to say that the prices of commodities are roughly proportionate
- to their costs of production. But directly we contemplate saying a
- similar thing of their usefulness, we are pulled up short. As we look
- round the world, and enumerate the commodities which by common consent
- are the most useful, salt, water, bread, and so forth, the striking
- paradox presents itself that these are among the cheapest of all
- commodities; far cheaper than champagne, motor-cars or ball-dresses,
- which we could very well get on without. As things are, of course, a
- ball-dress, or a motor-car costs more to produce than a loaf of bread
- or a packet of salt; and the common-sense explanation of the paradox
- seems, therefore, to be that the cost of production is a more weighty
- influence than the usefulness, or utility, as we will henceforth call
- it (so as to include the satisfaction we derive from not strictly
- useful things). We are thus tempted to conclude that, provided a
- commodity possesses some utility, its price will be determined by the
- cost of production, the degree of utility being unimportant. This was
- exactly how the position was gummed up for many years in systematic
- treatises upon Political Economy; and it was not until fully half a
- century after the _Wealth of Nations_ that a discovery was made which
- threw a fresh light on the whole matter.
- First of all, let it be clearly observed how very unsatisfactory is
- the above account. In Chapter II where we were treading surely, with a
- sense of solid ground beneath us, we drew no such invidious
- distinction between supply and demand. They seemed then to possess an
- equal status. But cost of production is the chief factor which, in the
- case of commodities, ultimately determines the conditions of
- supply. Utility, similarly, is the chief factor which ultimately
- determines the conditions of demand. Must not then the symmetrical
- relations between demand and supply be reflected in a corresponding
- symmetry between the utility and the costs which underlie them? Demand
- springs obviously from utility; the only motive for buying anything is
- that it will serve some real or fancied use. Can we then accord to
- demand so dignified and to utility so subordinate a place? There is
- here an inconsistency which we must somehow reconcile. It will not
- serve as a solution to distinguish between different periods of time,
- and to say, as economists used to say not very long ago, that price is
- governed over a short period by demand and supply, but in the long run
- by the cost of production. This still leaves our sense of symmetry
- unsatisfied. Moreover, the conception of cost of production, when we
- consider it as ruling over a long period, frequently seems to lose any
- precision, as an independent factor, which it may otherwise
- possess. Motor-cars, we have agreed, are more costly to produce than
- loaves of bread; but, as we know well, the cost of producing
- motor-cars varies enormously, accordingly as they are produced on a
- small or a large scale. By the methods of mass production they can be
- turned out at a relatively low cost per car. But this requires that
- they should be purchased in large numbers and this in turn throws us
- back to the demand for motor-cars, and plainly enough, to people's
- judgment as to their utility. In some cases, the opposite phenomenon
- occurs. In the case of British coal, for instance, the average cost of
- production would be much lower than it is if the output were reduced
- to a fraction of its present volume, and if only the richer seams of
- the more fertile mines were worked. Once again, therefore it is
- difficult to measure the cost of production until we know the
- magnitude of the demand, which in a manner, which we have still to
- elucidate, clearly depends upon the utility.
- If we take the problem of joint products, the conception of cost of
- production fails us still more conspicuously. For what is the cost of
- producing wool, or the cost of producing mutton? We can speak of the
- cost of rearing sheep: but it is hardly possible to allot this cost,
- except quite arbitrarily, between the two products. How, then, can we
- explain the separate prices of these things by reference to cost
- alone? Instances of joint production are becoming so common in the
- modern world, or at least, with the growing attention to the
- utilization of by-products, are assuming so much more heightened a
- significance, that an explanation of price, which does not apply to
- them, is a very feeble one indeed.
- §2. _The Law of Diminishing Utility_. Let us turn back, then, to the
- factor of utility, and see if we cannot put on a more satisfactory
- basis the relation between utility and price. The clue to the puzzle
- is to be found in a brief reflection on the implications of the second
- general law propounded in Chapter II. A rise in price, it was there
- stated, will sooner or later diminish the demand. This was asserted as
- a matter of fact, observed from and confirmed by experience. But what
- does it signify? To what causes is this familiar fact to be
- attributed? The first stage of the answer is very ample. The many
- individuals, whose purchases make up the demand for the commodity,
- will buy smaller quantities now that the price is higher. Possibly
- some of them may cease to buy it altogether; but as a rule it would be
- reasonable to suppose that most people continue to buy a certain
- amount though a smaller amount than hitherto. Let us turn our
- attention, then, to the individual purchaser, and ask ourselves why he
- (or let us say she) acts in the manner indicated. The obvious answer
- is that the more she already has of anything, the less urgently does
- she require a little more of it. If she buys 6 pounds of sugar every
- week when the price is 7 cents a pound, but only 5 pounds when the
- price is 8 cents, she shows by her action that she does not consider
- that the additional utility she will derive from buying 6 pounds a
- week rather then 5 pounds is worth as much as 8 cents. But she shows
- at the same time that she thinks it worth 7 cents. For, when the price
- is 7 cents, no one compels her to buy that sixth pound. She could
- stop, if she chose, at five; and it may serve to make the point quite
- plain if we suppose her actually to hesitate before she buys the
- sixth. She has hitherto, let us say, been buying 5 pounds a week at 8
- cents. To-day she enters the shop and finds the price is down to 7
- cents. She asks for her customary 5 pounds; then she pauses, and a
- minute later turns her order into six. What are the alternatives which
- she has been weighing one against the other in that momentary pause?
- Not the utility of the whole 6 pounds of sugar against the total price
- of 42 cents. For she has already ordered the first 5 pounds; and the
- decision to buy the sixth is taken independently and subsequently. She
- has been sizing up the _increment_ of utility which a sixth pound
- would yield, and she decides that this is worth the expenditure of a
- further 7 cents. Again, when the price was 8 cents she need not have
- bought as many as 5 pounds. She could have stopped at 4 had she
- chosen, and the fact that she did buy 5 pounds shows that the
- increment of utility derived from buying a fifth pound, when she might
- be said already to have 4, was worth at least 8 cents in her judgment.
- This trite illustration enables us to lay down two important laws
- relating to utility. To state them shortly, it is convenient to employ
- one or two technical terms, which, unlike every term employed
- hitherto, are not very commonly used in their present sense in
- everyday life. Their adoption is desirable not merely for the sake of
- convenience, but because they help to stamp clearly on the mind a most
- illuminating conception, that of the "margin," which supplies the clue
- to many complicated problems. The last pound of sugar which the
- housewife purchased, the fifth pound when the price was 8 cents, or
- the sixth pound when the price was 7 cents, we call the "marginal"
- pound of sugar. And the increment of utility which she derives from
- buying this marginal pound we call the "marginal utility" of sugar to
- her. We are thus able to state the fact that the more a person has of
- anything the less urgently does he require a little more of it, in the
- following formal terms:--
- LAW V. The marginal utility of a commodity to anyone diminishes with
- every increase in the amount he has.
- The total utility will, of course, increase with an increase in the
- amount, but at a diminishing rate. This law is usually called The Law
- of Diminishing Utility.
- §3. _Relation between Price and Marginal Utility_ But this is not
- all. We are now in a position to perceive the true relation between
- utility and price. The relation is one which exists not between price
- and total utility, but between price and marginal utility. If we know
- only that a housewife will buy weekly 5 pounds of sugar at 8 cents per
- pound, but 6 pounds at 7 cents, we know nothing of the total utility
- of sugar to her. We do not know how much she might be prepared to pay
- rather than go without 3 pounds, 2 pounds, or any sugar at all. But we
- do know that, when she buys 6 pounds, the marginal utility of sugar is
- in her judgment worth something which does not differ greatly from the
- price. We can, therefore, say in general terms that the price of a
- commodity measures approximately its marginal utility to the
- purchaser.
- This statement is perfectly consistent with the paradox noted above
- that the most useful commodities such as bread, salt and water are
- very cheap. For when we say that these commodities are supremely
- useful, we mean only that their total utility is very great; that,
- rather than do without them altogether, we would offer for them a
- large proportion of our means. But we would not value very highly a
- small addition to the bread, water or salt that we habitually consume;
- nor would most of us feel it as a very serious deprivation if our
- consumption of these things were curtailed by a small percentage. In
- other words, their _marginal_ utilities are small, and it is only the
- _marginal_ utility that has any relation to price.
- §4. _The Marginal Purchaser_. A possible objection to the preceding
- argument deserves to be considered. Some readers may find the picture
- I have drawn of the hesitating housewife entirely unconvincing. They
- may declare that her mind does not work at all in the manner I have
- indicated. She will have formed certain habits in regard to her weekly
- purchases of sugar, which are connected very vaguely, if at all, with
- any conscious processes of thought. She will buy so many pounds of
- sugar weekly without troubling her head over the specific utility of
- the last pound she buys. When the price falls she may, indeed, buy
- more; but it will not be because she separates out and considers by
- itself the extra utility of an additional pound. She may buy more,
- because she has formed the habit of spending so much money on sugar;
- and now that the price has fallen, the same amount of money will
- enable her to buy more pounds. Or, perhaps, she may be moved by
- instinctive and irresistible attraction to buy more of a thing when it
- is cheaper, similar to that which inspires so many people to face with
- ardor the horrors of a bargain sale. In any case the fine calculations
- I have imagined convey a fantastic picture of her state of mind. And
- how much more fantastic, the critic may continue, of the state of mind
- in which things of a different kind are bought by less careful
- people. When, for instance, one of us happy-go-lucky males (more
- liberally supplied, perhaps, than the housewife with the necessary
- cash), decides to buy a motor bicycle, or to replenish his stock of
- collars or ties, does the above analysis bear any resemblance to the
- actual facts? In the case of the motor bicycle, the purchaser may,
- indeed, weigh the price fairly carefully against the pleasure and
- benefit, though contrariwise he may be a rich enough gentleman hardly
- to bother about this. But, one motor bicycle is as much as he is at
- all likely to buy, and what becomes, then, of the distinction between
- total and marginal utility? In the case of the ties and collars, the
- vagueness of many of us about the price will be extreme. We probably
- have been uneasily conscious for some time of an inconvenient shortage
- of these troublesome articles and eventually will go off (or perhaps
- will be sent off with ignominy) to the nearest suitable shop to make
- good the deficiency. How can we speak here with a straight face of the
- relation between marginal utility and price?
- These are very pertinent criticisms; but they do not make nearly as
- much nonsense of the notion of marginal utility as may seem at
- first. The last point, indeed, serves rather to give it a fresh aspect
- of much significance. Those of us who do not bother about the price we
- pay for our ties and collars owe a debt of gratitude, of which we are
- insufficiently conscious, to the more careful people who do; as well
- as to the custom which prevails in shops in Western countries (as
- distinct from the bazaars of the East) of charging as a rule a uniform
- price to all customers. If _we_ were the only people who bought these
- things, an enterprising salesman would be able to charge us very much
- what he chose. He could put up his price, and we would hardly be aware
- of it. And, as by lowering his price he could not tempt us to buy any
- more, price reductions would be few and far between. But fortunately
- there are always some people who do know what the price is, even when
- they are buying collars and ties; and who will adjust the amount they
- buy in accordance with the price. It is these worthy people who make
- the laws of demand work out as we well know they do. It is they who
- will curtail their consumption if the price has fallen and it is they
- who constitute the seller's problem, and help to keep down prices for
- the rest of us. The rest of us--it is well to be quite blunt about
- it--simply do not count in this connection. We have no cause then to
- plume ourselves that we have disproved the truth of economic laws when
- we declare that we seldom weigh the utility of anything against its
- price. All that this shows is that our actions are too insignificant
- to be described by economic laws since they exert no appreciable
- influence on the price of anything. And this in turn shows the extreme
- importance of grasping clearly the conception of the margin. Just as
- it is the marginal purchase, so it is the marginal purchaser who
- matters. It is the man who, before he buys a motor bicycle, weighs the
- matter up very carefully indeed and only just decides to buy it, whose
- demand affects the price of motor bicycles. It is the utility which
- _he_ derives that constitutes the marginal utility, which is roughly
- measured by the price.
- As to the housewife, I am not prepared to concede that my picture is
- in essentials very fanciful. She may be a creature of habits and
- instincts like the rest of us, but most habits and instincts affecting
- household expenditure are based ultimately on _some_ calculation, if
- not one's own, and reason has a way of paying, as it were, periodic
- visits of inspection, and pulling our habits and instincts into line,
- if they have gone far astray. I am not satisfied that the housewife
- does not envisage the utility of a sixth pound of sugar as something
- distinct from the utility of the other five; she may buy it, for
- example, with the definite object of giving the children some sugar on
- their bread, and she may have a very clear idea as to the price which
- sugar must not exceed before she will do any such thing. Possibly I
- may exaggerate. I have the profound respect of the incorrigibly
- wasteful male for the care and skill she displays in laying out her
- money to the best advantage.
- §5. _The Business Man as Purchaser_. But if the reader still finds the
- picture unconvincing, let us shift the scene from domestic economy to
- commerce, and substitute for the careful housewife an enterprising
- business man. Now, as anyone who has a business man for his father
- will have often heard him say, the vagueness and caprice which
- characterize our personal expenditure would be quite intolerable in
- business affairs. There you must weigh and measure with the utmost
- possible precision. You must be for ever watching the several channels
- of your expenditure, careful to see that in none does the stream rise
- higher than the level at which further expenditure ceases to be
- profitable. You will not even engage typists or install a telephone in
- your office without weighing up fairly carefully the number of typists
- or the number of switches that it is worth your while to have. And in
- deciding whether to employ say, five typists, or six, you will not
- vaguely lump the services of the whole six typists together, and
- consider whether as a whole they are worth to you the wages you must
- give them. You will, in the most direct and literal manner, weigh up
- the _additional_ benefit you would derive from a sixth typist, and if
- that does not seem to you equivalent to her wage, you will not engage
- her, however essential it may be to you to have one or two typists in
- your office. If on the other hand, the utility of having a sixth
- typist seems to you worth much more than her pay, the chances are that
- you will be well advised to consider the employment of a seventh. And
- so, where you stop employing further typists, the utility to you of
- the last one, of the "marginal typist" as it were, is unlikely to
- differ greatly from her pay.
- Now this is not a fancy picture of some remote abstraction called an
- "economic man." Allowing for the over-emphasis which is necessary to
- drive home the central point, it is a bald account of the aims and
- methods of the actual man of business. To ascertain the margin of
- profitable expenditure in each direction, to go thus and no further,
- is the very essence of the business spirit, as the business man
- himself conceives it. When he condemns the extravagance of Government
- departments, it is their lack of just this marginal sense that he
- chiefly has in mind. "The lore of nicely calculated less or more" may
- be rejected by High Heaven and Whitehall, but no one can afford to
- despise it in the business world.
- The transition from household to business expenditure involves an
- extended use of the word utility, which is worth noting. Commodities
- like bread, sugar, or privately owned motor-cars are sometimes called
- "consumers' goods" in contrast to "producers' goods," which comprise
- things such as raw materials, machinery, the services of typists and
- so forth, which are bought by business men for business purposes. The
- line of division between the two classes is not a sharp one, and we
- need not trouble with fine-spun questions as to whether a particular
- commodity should in certain circumstances be included under the one
- head or the other. But, broadly speaking, things of the former type
- yield a direct utility; they contribute directly to the satisfaction
- of our pleasures or our wants. Things of the latter type yield rather
- an indirect utility. Their utility to the business man who buys them
- lies in the assistance they give him in making something else from
- which he will derive a profit. The utility of these things is
- therefore said to be _derived_ from that of the consumers' goods or
- services to which they ultimately contribute. This conception of
- derived utility leads to certain complications which we shall have to
- notice later.
- §6. _The Diminishing Utility of Money_. But one important point must
- be emphasized in this chapter. The utility which a business man
- derives from the things which he buys for business purposes is the
- extra receipts which he obtains thereby. Derived utility, in other
- words, is expressed in terms of money, and the idea of its relation to
- price presents no difficulty. But the utility of things which are
- bought for personal consumption means the _satisfaction_ which they
- yield, and this is clearly not a thing which is commensurable with
- money. When, therefore, it is said that the prices measure their
- respective marginal utilities, what exactly is meant? What was it that
- the argument of §3 went to show? That the utility of the marginal
- pound of sugar would seem to the housewife just worth the price that
- she must pay for it; in other words, that it would be roughly equal to
- the utility she could obtain by spending the money in other ways. The
- respective marginal utilities which _she_ obtains from the different
- things she buys will thus be proportionate to their prices. But if she
- were to receive a legacy which gave her a much larger income to spend,
- she might buy larger quantities of practically every commodity; and,
- though she would obtain a greater total utility thereby, the marginal
- utility she would obtain in each direction would be smaller, in
- accordance with the law of diminishing utility. The prices might not
- have changed; the respective marginal utilities to her of the
- different things would again be proportionate to their prices, but
- they would constitute a smaller satisfaction than before.
- Thus we can only say that the prices of commodities will be
- proportionate to their real marginal utilities, when we are
- considering the different purchases of one and the same
- individual. The amounts of money which different people are prepared
- to pay for different consumers' goods are no reliable indication of
- the real utilities, the amounts of human satisfaction which they
- yield. Here we must take account not only of varying needs and
- capacities for enjoyment, but of the very unequal manner in which
- purchasing power is distributed among the people. The cigars which a
- rich man may buy will yield him an immeasurably smaller satisfaction
- than that which a poor family could obtain by spending the same amount
- of money on boots, or clothes or milk. When, therefore, we compare
- commodities which are bought by essentially different consuming
- publics, their respective prices may bear no close relation to their
- _real_ utility, whether marginal or otherwise. Thus the law of
- diminishing utility applies to money or purchasing power, as well as
- to particular commodities. The more money a man has the less is the
- marginal utility which it yields him; and, where the marginal utility
- of money to a man is small, so also will be the real marginal utility
- he derives in each direction of his expenditure. The extreme
- inequality of the distribution of wealth gives immense importance to
- this consideration. Its practical implications will be discussed in
- Chapter V. Meanwhile, we may express the conclusions of the present
- chapter by the statement that the price of a commodity tends to equal
- its marginal utility, _as measured in terms of money_, i.e. relatively
- to the marginal utility of money to its purchaser.
- CHAPTER IV
- COST AND THE MARGIN OF PRODUCTION
- §1. _An Illustration from Coal_. We have already had occasion to note
- the symmetry which characterizes the relations of demand and supply to
- price. This symmetry was apparent throughout the argument of Chapter
- II, and it was a striking feature of the diagrams which we employed to
- illustrate the argument. We shall do well to cultivate a lively sense
- of this symmetry, for it will frequently save us from ignoring factors
- which have a vital bearing on the problems we are considering. We
- should never leave an important feature of demand without turning to
- see whether it has a counterpart on the supply side, though indeed we
- may not always find one. In the last chapter we examined the relation
- between utility and price, and found that the true relation was
- between the price and what we termed the marginal utility.
- Corresponding to utility on the demand side is cost of
- production on the supply side. The question should thus at once
- suggest itself--"Can we speak appropriately of the marginal cost of
- production, and will this serve to make clear the relation between
- cost and price?" To answer these questions, let us take one of the
- instances in which we found that price could not be explained
- satisfactorily by the bare phrase "cost of production."
- An important feature of the coal industry, which recent events have
- brought into sharp prominence, is the great diversity of conditions
- between different coalfields and different collieries. We speak of
- rich seams and poor seams, of fertile and unfertile mines, and we are
- aware that the costs of raising coal to the surface differ very widely
- in accordance with these diverse natural conditions. Nor must we
- confine our attention to the cost price at the pit-head. If we wish to
- speak of cost of production as a factor determining price, we must use
- the term in a broad sense to include the transport and other charges
- necessary to bring the coal to market.
- In this respect also one coalfield differs greatly from another. Some
- are well situated close to a large market, or within easy reach of the
- seaboard; others must incur very heavy transport charges to bring
- their coal to any considerable centre of consumption. These varying
- conditions lead, as we well know, to great variations in the financial
- prosperity of different colliery concerns. In Great Britain, under the
- abnormal conditions which prevailed during the war, and subsequently,
- these variations were so huge as to constitute a most formidable
- embarrassment and to contribute, more perhaps than any other single
- factor, to the unrest and instability by which the industry has been
- afflicted. But they are always with us, if usually upon a more modest
- scale.
- What, then, is the normal relation between price and cost in the case
- of coal? Should we direct our attention to the average costs over the
- whole industry, or the costs incurred by the richer and better
- situated mines, or, lastly, that of the poorer and worse situated?
- Now, as things are, it is clear enough that no concern will continue
- indefinitely producing at a loss. It may do so for a time, rather than
- close down altogether, hoping to recoup itself later when the market
- has taken a more favorable turn. But, in the long run, taking good
- years with bad, it must expect to obtain receipts sufficient not only
- to cover its necessary expenditure, but to provide also a reasonable
- profit on the capital employed. Of course, once the capital has been
- sunk and embodied in plant and buildings, which are of little use for
- any other purpose, a business may continue for many years, with a rate
- of profit far below what it had anticipated. But plant and buildings
- gradually wear out, and need to be replaced; the course of technical
- improvement calls continually for fresh capital outlay, which a
- business in a bad way is reluctant to undertake. The tendency,
- therefore, when profits rule low over a considerable period, is for
- the plant to fall gradually into disrepair and obsolescence, and
- finally for the business to disappear. We can thus include an
- ordinary rate of profit under the head of cost of production, and say
- with substantial accuracy that for no business can this cost for long
- exceed the price if the business is to continue to exist. If then the
- relatively poor and badly situated mines are to be worked, the price
- of coal, taking good years together with bad, must cover the costs at
- which these mines can produce. If the price rules lower than this,
- sooner or later they will close down, and we will be left with a
- smaller number of mines, among which great variations of conditions
- will still prevail. Once more, the price must cover the cost incurred
- by the least profitable of these remaining mines, unless their number
- is still further to be diminished. Thus we can conceive of a "margin
- of production" which will shift backwards to more profitable or
- forwards to include less profitable mines, according as the demand for
- coal contracts or expands. But, wherever this margin may be, there is
- no escaping the conclusion that it is the cost of production of the
- "marginal mines," of those that is to say which it is only just worth
- while to work, to which the price of coal will approximate.
- It follows that there is no real connection between price and cost of
- production throughout the industry as a whole. It follows incidentally
- that those concerns which can market their coal at an appreciably
- lower cost than the marginal concerns, are likely to reap more than an
- ordinary rate of profit, though royalties may absorb part of the
- excess.
- §2. _The Various Aspects of Marginal Cost_. This relation cuts much
- deeper than the particular system under which the mines are at present
- owned and worked. If, for instance, we supposed that the various
- mines were amalgamated together in a few giant concerns, each of which
- comprised some of the richer and some of the poorer mines, the
- preceding argument would need to be recast in form, but its substance
- would be unaffected. For though a great coal trust could in a sense
- _afford_ to sell at a price lower than the marginal cost, setting its
- losses on the poorer against its gains on the better pits, is it
- likely it would do so? Why should it dissipate its profits in this
- way? It is clearly more reasonable to suppose that it would close down
- the poorer pits (unless it could advance the price of coal), and
- thereby maintain its profits at a higher figure. If, indeed, the
- mines were nationalized the deliberate policy might be pursued of
- selling coal at a price which left the industry no more than
- self-supporting as a whole. Some coal might thus be sold at less than
- its cost price, and the selling price would conform roughly to the
- _average_ cost. But such a policy, though in special circumstances it
- might be justified, would represent a very dangerous principle, which
- could not be applied widely without the most serious results. Nothing
- could be more fatal to any enterprise, whether it be in the hands of
- an individual, a joint-stock company, a State department, or a Guild,
- than that the management should content themselves with results which
- in the lump seem satisfactory, and regard losses here or there with an
- indifferent eye. That way lies stagnation, waste, progressive
- inefficiency and ultimate disaster. To inquire searchingly into every
- nook and cranny of the business, to construct, as it were, for each
- part a separate balance-sheet of profit and loss, to expand in those
- directions where further development promises good results, and to
- curtail activity where loss is already evident, is the very essence of
- good management. Here, it will be observed, we are using language very
- similar to that in which we described the principles which govern a
- business man's expenditure. The resemblance is inevitable and
- significant, for we are dealing here with what is essentially another
- aspect of the same thing. The object is to secure that nowhere does
- expenditure fail to yield a commensurate return. This we express, when
- we consider a business in its aspect as a consumer, by saying that its
- consumption of anything will not be carried beyond the point at which
- the marginal utility exceeds the price it will have to pay. When we
- consider it as a producer, we say that its production of anything will
- not be carried beyond the point at which the marginal cost exceeds the
- price it will obtain.
- §3. _The Dangers of Ignoring the Margin_. This at least is the general
- rule. A business may decide deliberately to sell part of its output
- below cost, because, for instance, this will serve as an
- advertisement, bring it connections, and enable it to obtain a larger
- profit at a later date, or immediately on other portions of its
- sales. In so acting, it recognizes that the price obtained for a thing
- may be an inadequate measure of the real return it yields. In the same
- way, though for different reasons, a nationalized coal industry might
- conceivably be justified in selling some coal below cost price,
- because, let us say, it held that the price which the immediate
- purchasers were willing to pay was an inadequate measure of the
- utility of coal to the community as a whole. But in all such cases it
- is essential to be very clear as to what exactly you are doing; so
- that you may be at least moderately clear as to whether the policy is
- well advised. It may be sound enough to lose on the swings and make
- good this loss on the roundabouts, but only if your loss on the swings
- _helps_ you to a larger profit on the roundabouts. If you would get
- the same return on the roundabouts in any case, it would be better to
- cut the swings out altogether. So, if you are directing the policy of
- a nationalized coal industry, and decide to make a loss on a portion
- of your sales, you will need to know that the indirect benefit which
- the community will derive from this particular part of your coal
- output is worth the loss which you incur. You will certainly come to
- grief, if you pursue a vague ideal of lumping all results together,
- and regarding a profit somewhere as a sufficient excuse or a positive
- reason for making a loss elsewhere.
- It is quite true that in big undertakings, where there are large
- standing charges, and where the organization possesses some of the
- characteristics of an integral whole, it is not easy to measure
- accurately the specific costs which should be assigned to any
- particular portion of the output. But this difficulty is one of the
- most serious weaknesses of large undertakings; precise detailed
- measurement is the great prophylactic of business efficiency, and,
- where it is lacking the bacilli of waste will enter in and
- multiply. So clearly is this recognized, that the development of large
- scale business has led to the evolution of new methods of accountancy,
- designed to make detailed mensuration possible. We have most of us
- heard of them vaguely under such names as "comparative costings," but
- too few of us appreciate their full significance. It is hardly too
- much to say that the issue as to whether the size of the typical
- business unit will continue to become larger and larger, or whether it
- has already overshot the point of maximum efficiency will turn largely
- upon the capacity of accountancy to supply large and complex
- undertakings with more accurate instruments of detailed financial
- measurement.
- §4. _A Misinterpretation_. The price, then, of a commodity tends
- roughly to equal its marginal cost of production; and this marginal
- cost (in perfect symmetry with what we observed as regards marginal
- utility), may be conceived as applying either to the marginal producer
- or to the marginal output of any producer. In the former aspect it is
- open to a misinterpretation, against which it will be well to guard.
- Some advocates of socialism have argued, as one of the counts in their
- indictment of the present industrial system, that the price of a
- commodity is determined by the cost at which the least efficient
- concern in the industry can produce. They say, in effect, "Under the
- present competitive regime, you have to pay for everything you buy a
- price which far exceeds the necessary cost to a concern which is
- managed with ordinary ability. For, as economic theory has shown, it
- is the cost of the _marginal_ concern, i.e. the concern managed by the
- most incompetent, and half-witted fellow in the trade; it is the cost
- incurred by him, together with a profit on his capital, that the price
- has got to cover. The producer of no more than average capacity is
- therefore making out of you a surplus profit, which would be quite
- unnecessary in any well-arranged society." Such an argument is a gross
- caricature of the marginal conception. The half-witted incompetent
- will, as we know well enough, speedily disappear under the stress of
- competition, and his place will be taken by more efficient men. There
- is an essential difference between him and the "marginal coal mine" of
- which we spoke above. For the probabilities are that of the coal
- resources, whose existence is clearly known, the more fertile and
- better situated parts will already be in process of exploitation; and
- there is not likely, therefore, to be a supply of substantially better
- seams which can be substituted for the worst of those in actual use.
- There _is_ likely, on the other hand, to be available a supply of
- decent business capacity which can be substituted for the most
- inefficient of existing business men. The marginal concern, in other
- words, must be conceived as that working under the least advantageous
- conditions in respect of the assistance it derives from the strictly
- limited resources of nature, but under average conditions as regards
- managerial capacity and human qualities in general. Thus in
- agriculture we can speak of a marginal farm, which we should conceive
- as the least fertile and worst situated farm which it is just worth
- while to cultivate (of which more will be said when we come to the
- phenomenon of rent), but we must assume it to be cultivated by a
- farmer of average ability.
- §5. _Some Consequences of a Higher Price Level_. The foregoing
- controversy will be of service to us, if it makes clear the manner and
- the spirit in which the marginal conception should be handled. It
- should be regarded not as a rigid formula which we can apply to
- diverse problems without considering the special features they
- present, but rather as a signpost which will enable us to find our
- way, a compass by which we may steer between the shoals of triviality
- and sophistry to the crux of any problem with which we have to deal.
- Let us illustrate its practical uses by an example which is of great
- interest and far-reaching practical importance at the present day. As
- has been already observed, the war has left behind it in all countries
- a great and almost certainly permanent increase in nominal purchasing
- power. Since the armistice prices have moved upwards and downwards
- with unprecedented violence; and it would be very rash to prophesy the
- precise level at which they will ultimately settle (using that word
- with considerable relativity). But, for reasons for which the reader
- is referred to Volume II in this series, it is safe enough to say that
- the general level of post-war will greatly exceed that of pre-war
- prices. Now this will apply not only to consumers' goods like milk and
- clothes, or to raw materials like pig-iron and cotton, but in very
- much the same degree to things like factories and machinery. Things of
- this last type are sometimes called "capital goods," because it is in
- them that a large part of the capital of a business is embodied. Now
- the fact that it will cost much more than it did before the war to
- construct fresh capital goods, has a significance which very few
- people appreciate. An existing factory cost, let us say, $500,000 to
- build and equip with machinery before the war. To construct a similar
- factory to-day would cost, let us assume (it is probably a moderate
- assumption) $1,000,000. Suppose 10 per cent to be the gross profit
- that is necessary to attract capital to the particular industry. Then
- it will not pay to construct this new factory unless the trade
- prospects point to the probability of a profit of about $100,000 per
- annum. But if the old factory is equally well managed, it too should
- be able to earn this $100,000, which upon the capital actually sunk
- would represent a rate of 20 per cent. The particular figures given
- are, of course, purely illustrative; the conclusion to which they
- point is that, if new enterprises are to be undertaken, pre-war
- enterprises are likely to yield a rate of profit, on their fixed
- capital at least, increased in rough proportion to the price-level. Of
- course, in years when trade is bad, the factory which dates from
- pre-war times will not earn a profit of this kind, it may very likely
- make an actual loss. At those times it is very certain that few new
- factories will be erected. But it is difficult to reconcile a
- condition of trade activity, in which the constructional industries
- are busily employed, with a rate of profit to pre-war businesses on
- the fixed part of their capital of a lesser order of magnitude than
- has been indicated. It makes no difference, it should be observed,
- whether we suppose the new enterprises to take the form of starting of
- new concerns or extending old ones; in neither case will they be
- undertaken, unless there is reason to expect an adequate return on the
- capital which they require at post-war constructional prices. High
- profits (taking always good years together with bad) on capital sunk
- before the war in buildings and machinery are thus a likely
- consequence of an increase in the price-level.
- This fact is, indeed, the counterpart or complement of another
- phenomenon with which we are more familiar. While prices are actually
- rising, profits, as we have come to recognize, necessarily rule high,
- because every trader or manufacturer is constantly in the position of
- selling at a higher price-level, stock which he purchased, or goods
- made from materials which he purchased at a lower level. He thus
- acquires an abnormal profit on his circulating capital, which is
- essentially similar to the profit on fixed capital, which we have just
- examined. The difference is that the former profit is crowded into the
- years when prices are actually on the increase, and thus is very
- noticeable indeed; while the latter profit continues to accrue in
- smaller instalments after prices have settled down, as it were, at the
- higher level, and is not exhausted until the buildings and machinery
- have become obsolete. But the two profits are essentially similar,
- and in the long run should be commensurate. In the one case, stock can
- be sold for a large profit, because it cannot be replaced except at a
- higher price; in the other case, plant and buildings yield a higher
- income because _they_ cannot be replaced except at a higher
- price. Indeed, if the owners choose, the plant and building can, like
- the stock, be sold at their appreciated value, as has been widely done
- by the owners of cotton mills in Great Britain since the armistice.
- There is nothing in these considerations that should surprise us, or
- even shock our moral sense. For what they have indicated is an
- increase of money profits in rough proportion to the price-level, so
- that the aggregate profits will represent about as much real income as
- before.[1] The conclusion therefore amounts to no more than this, that
- you cannot alter fundamentally the distribution of wealth between
- labor and capital by merely inflating the currency, or otherwise
- juggling with the price-level. And this is only what we should expect,
- if there are any laws of distribution of sufficient importance and
- permanence to justify the many volumes which have been devoted to
- them.
- [Footnote 1: Assuming that the rate of interest has remained
- unaltered. In fact it has greatly increased since pre-war days, and
- this points to a still further increase of money profits, and an
- increase in the real income which they represent. See Chapter VIII,
- §10]
- But this somewhat tame conclusion does not make it any less important
- to grasp clearly the significance of the appreciation in the value of
- capital goods. A failure to realize it lies at the root of our
- bewildered muddling of many crucial problems of the day. In the matter
- of housing, for instance, we know we cannot build houses at less than
- two or three times their prewar cost, and yet we cannot endure to see
- the owners of pre-war houses obtaining a commensurate increase of
- rent. And so, in Great Britain, we pass Rent Restriction Acts, and
- Housing Acts, and then, in a fit of economy we suspend the latter, and
- let the former stand, while the housing shortage becomes steadily more
- acute. When we hand the railways back from State control to private
- hands, our horror at the idea of the companies receiving larger money
- profits than they did before the war leads us to lay down principles
- for the fixing of fares and freight charges, which take no account of
- post-war construction costs; and then, in alarm lest we may have
- thereby made it unprofitable for the companies to spend a single penny
- of fresh capital upon further development, we seek to provide for
- capital expenditure by cumbrous and dubious expedients. Doubtless we
- shall muddle through somehow with such policies: and, public opinion
- being what it is, they may perhaps have been about the best policies
- that were practicable. But the problems would have been easier to
- handle, if the public generally were a little less disposed to think
- in terms of averages, and a little more in terms of margins, if we all
- of us instinctively realized that the cost that really matters is the
- cost at which additional production is profitable under the conditions
- ruling at the time, or in the immediate future.
- §6. _General Relation between Price, Utility and Cost_. Let us
- conclude this chapter by summing up the conclusions which have emerged
- as to the relations of utility and cost to price.
- The price of a commodity is determined by the conditions of both
- supply and demand; and neither can logically be said to be the
- superior influence, though it may sometimes be convenient to
- concentrate our attention on one or other of them. The chief factor on
- which the conditions of demand depend is the utility (as measured in
- terms of money). The chief factor on which the conditions of supply
- depend is the cost of production (again as measured in terms of
- money). The prevailing trend towards an equilibrium of demand and
- supply can thus be expressed as follows:--
- LAW VI. A commodity tends to be produced on a scale at which its
- marginal cost of production is equal to its marginal utility, as
- measured in terms of money, and both are equal to its price.
- CHAPTER V
- JOINT DEMAND AND SUPPLY
- §1. _Marginal Cost under Joint Supply_. Several references have been
- made above to joint products, a relation which it will be convenient
- now to describe as that of Joint Supply. Our sense of symmetry should
- make us look for a parallel relation on the side of demand; and it is
- not far to seek. There is a "joint demand" for carriages and horses,
- for golf clubs and golf balls, for pens and ink, for the many groups
- of things which we use together in ordinary life. But the most
- important instances of Joint Demand are to be found when we pass from
- consumers' to producers' goods. There, indeed, Joint Demand is the
- universal rule. Iron ore, coal and the services of many grades of
- operatives are all jointly demanded for the production of steel; wool,
- textile machinery and again the services of many operatives are
- jointly demanded for the production of woollen goods (to mention in
- each case only a few things out of a very extensive list). Now we have
- already noted that, when commodities are jointly supplied, there is an
- obvious difficulty in allocating to each of them its proper share of
- the joint cost of production. There is a similar difficulty in
- estimating the utility of a commodity which is demanded jointly with
- others. Thus, the utility of wool is derived from that of the woollen
- goods which it helps to make. But the utility of the factories, the
- machinery and the operatives employed in the woollen and worsted
- industries is derived from precisely the same source. How much, then,
- of the utility of woollen goods should be attributed to the wool and
- how much to the textile machinery? Can we make any sense of the notion
- of utility as applying to one of these things, taken by itself? And,
- if not, how can we explain the price of a thing like wool in terms of
- utility and cost, since we cannot disentangle its cost from that of
- mutton, nor its utility from that of a great variety of other things?
- Here the conception of the margin enables us to grapple with a problem
- which would otherwise be insoluble. For, while it is impossible to
- separate out the total utility and cost of wool, it is not impossible
- to disentangle its marginal utility and its marginal cost. The
- proportion in which wool and mutton are supplied cannot be radically
- transformed; but it can be varied within certain limits, by rearing,
- for instance, a different breed of sheep. Variations of this kind have
- been an important feature of the economic history of Australasia,
- where sheep farming is the leading industry. Before the days of cold
- storage, Australia and New Zealand could not export their mutton to
- European markets, though they could export their wool. Wool was
- accordingly much the most valuable product; the mutton was sold in the
- home markets, where, the supply being very plentiful, the price was
- very low. In the circumstances, the Australasian farmers naturally
- concentrated on breeding a variety of sheep whose wool-yielding were
- superior to their mutton-yielding qualities. The development of the
- arts of refrigeration led in the eighties to an important change. It
- became possible to obtain relatively high prices for frozen mutton in
- overseas markets. There was, therefore, a marked tendency, especially
- in New Zealand, to substitute, for the merino, the crossbred sheep
- which yields a larger quantity of mutton and a smaller quantity of
- wool of poorer quality. Now if we calculate the cost of maintaining
- the number of merino sheep which will yield a given quantity of wool,
- and calculate the cost of maintaining the larger number of crossbred
- sheep which will be required to yield the _same_ quantity of wool
- (allowing for differences of quality) the extra cost which would be
- incurred in the latter case must be attributed entirely to the extra
- mutton that would be obtained. This extra cost we can regard as
- constituting the marginal cost of mutton. So long as this marginal
- cost falls short of the price of mutton, it will be profitable to
- extend further the substitution of crossbred for merino sheep. The
- process of substitution will in fact be continued until we reach the
- point at which the marginal cost is about equal to the price.
- Similarly by starting with the numbers of merino and crossbred
- sheep which would yield the same quantity of mutton, we can calculate
- the marginal cost of wool; and again the tendency will be for this
- marginal cost to be equal to the price.[1]
- [Footnote 1: It may be found difficult to grasp this point when stated
- in general terms. The following arithmetical example may make it
- plainer:--
- Suppose a merino sheep yields 9 units of mutton and 10 units of wool.
- Suppose a crossbred sheep yields 10 units of mutton and 8 units of
- wool.
- Suppose, further, that a merino sheep and a crossbred sheep each cost
- the same sum, say, for convenience, £10, to rear and maintain; and
- that there are no special costs assignable to the wool and the mutton
- respectively, as, of course, in fact there are.
- Then 10 merino sheep, yielding 90 units of mutton + 100 units of wool,
- cost £100; while 9 crossbred sheep, yielding 90 units of mutton + 72
- units of wool, cost £90.
- Hence you could obtain an extra 28 units of wool for an extra cost of
- £10, by maintaining 10 merino sheep rather than 9 crossbred sheep. The
- marginal cost of wool is thus £ 10/28 per unit.
- Similarly 8 merino sheep, yielding 72 units of mutton + 80 units of
- wool, cost £80; while 10 crossbred sheep, yielding 100 units of mutton
- + 80 units of wool, cost £100.
- Hence you could obtain an extra 28 units of mutton for an extra cost
- of £20, by maintaining 10 crossbred sheep in place of 8 merinos. The
- marginal cost of mutton is thus £ 20/28 per unit.
- So long as the price obtainable for wool exceeds £ 10/28, and that
- obtainable for mutton does not exceed £ 20/28 per unit, it will pay to
- substitute merino for crossbred; and conversely. If the price of wool
- exceeds £ 10/28 and the price of mutton also exceeds £ 20/28, it will
- be profitable to expand the supply of both breeds, until as the result
- of the increased supply, one of the above conditions ceases to
- obtain. Conversely, if the prices of both products are less than the
- figures indicated, sheep farming of both kinds will be restricted.
- The resultant of the processes of expansion or restriction, and
- substitution, will be that, unless one of the breeds is eliminated,
- the prices of mutton and wool will equal their respective marginal
- costs. These marginal costs may, of course, alter as the process of
- substitution extends. For the relative cost of maintaining merinos and
- crossbreds will not be the same for every farmer. Here again it is the
- costs at the "margin of substitution" that matter.]
- §2. _Marginal Utility under Joint Demand_. On the side of demand there
- exist as a rule similar possibilities of variation. _Some_ machinery,
- _some_ labor, _some_ materials of various kinds, are all indispensable
- in the production of any manufactured commodity. But the proportions
- in which these factors are combined together can be varied, and are
- frequently varied in practice as the result of the ceaseless pursuit
- of economy by business men. To produce pig-iron, you need both coal
- and iron ore; but, if coal becomes more costly, it is possible to
- economize its use. Machinery and labor must be used together, in some
- cases in proportions which are absolutely fixed. But there is in
- nearly every industry a debated question as to whether the
- introduction of some further labor-saving machine would be worth
- while, or some improved machine which would represent the substitution
- of more capital plus less labor for less capital plus more labor. A
- farmer can cultivate his land, to use a common expression, more
- intensively or less intensively; in other words, he can apply larger
- or smaller quantities of capital and labor (the proportion between
- which he can also vary) to the same amount of land. The problem is
- essentially the same as that of the substitution of the crossbred for
- the merino. We can take the various possible combinations of the
- factors of production, and contrast two cases in which different
- quantities of one factor are employed, together with equal quantities
- of the others. The extra product which will be yielded in the case in
- which the larger quantity of the varying factor is employed can then
- be regarded as the marginal product (or marginal utility) of the extra
- quantity of that factor; and we can say that the employment of this
- factor will be pushed forward to the point where this marginal product
- will be roughly equal to the price that must be paid for it. We can
- thus lay down the most important proposition that the relation between
- marginal utility and price holds good generally of the ultimate agents
- of production; that the rent of land, the wages of labor, and, we can
- even add, the profits of capital tend to equal their (derived)
- marginal utilities, or, as it is sometimes expressed, their marginal
- net products.
- Whenever, therefore, the proportions in which two or more things are
- produced or used together can be varied, the relations of joint supply
- and joint demand are perfectly consistent with a specific marginal
- cost and marginal utility for each commodity.
- §3. _A contrast between Cotton and Cotton-seed, and Wool and
- Mutton_. But it sometimes happens that such variations cannot be
- made. Thus, it has not been found possible (so far as I am aware) to
- alter the proportions in which cotton lint and cotton-seed are yielded
- by the cotton plant. Roughly speaking, you get about 2 pounds of
- cotton-seed for every 1 pound of cotton lint (or raw cotton), and
- though this proportion may vary somewhat from plantation to
- plantation, it is upon the knees of the gods, and not upon the will of
- the planter that the variation depends. We cannot, therefore, speak
- with accuracy of the separate marginal costs of raw cotton and
- cotton-seed. It is true that some plantations are so far distant from
- any seed-crushing mill that it is not worth while to sell the seed as
- a commercial product; and it might seem, therefore, as though we might
- regard the entire costs of cotton growing on _such_ plantations as
- constituting the marginal costs of raw cotton. But planters, so
- situated, derive a considerable value from their cotton-seed by using
- it as fodder for their live stock or as a manure. You can, of course,
- argue that proper allowance is automatically made for this factor, as
- a deduction from the costs of raw cotton, when you add up the expenses
- of the plantation. In the same way you can deduct the price which a
- planter who sells his cotton-seed obtains for it, from the total costs
- of the plantation, and call the remainder the costs of the raw
- cotton. But this is really to reason in a circle. For in either case
- the magnitude of the deduction depends on the marginal utility of the
- cotton-seed. And the notion of the cost of anything becomes blurred
- and blunted if we so use it that it must be deduced from the utility
- of something else, which is not an agent in the production of the
- thing in question.
- This point is not merely an academic one. It means that we cannot
- explain the _relative_ prices of cotton lint and cotton-seed in terms
- of cost at all, whether marginal or otherwise. The influence of cost
- will be confined to the _sum_ of the prices of the two things. Upon
- this sum it will exert precisely the same influence as it exerts upon
- price in general, by affecting the total quantities of the two things
- that will be supplied. But upon the distribution of this sum between
- lint and seed, cost will exert no influence whatever, because it
- cannot affect the proportions in which they are supplied. It may
- assist some readers if I state the matter in more concrete terms. Cost
- of production will be one of the factors which will result in the
- production of an annual cotton crop in the United States of, let us
- say, 10 million tons of seed cotton. This crop will yield roughly
- 6-2/3 million tons of cotton-seed, and 3-1/3 million tons (or rather
- more than 13 million bales) of lint. The combined price received by
- the planter of (let us say) 14.4 cents for 1 pound of lint plus 2
- pounds of seed should correspond roughly to the marginal joint costs
- of production. But the factor of cost has no influence at all in
- determining that this combined price is made up of a price of 12 cents
- per pound for lint, and only 1.2 cents per pound (or $24 per ton) for
- cotton-seed. To account for this we must rely entirely upon demand. We
- can say, shortly, that the respective prices must be such as will
- enable the demand to carry off 6-2/3 million tons of seed, and 3-1/3
- million tons of raw cotton. Or we can go further and say that the
- marginal utility of a pound of raw cotton, when 3-1/3 million tons are
- supplied, is ten times as great as that of a pound of seed when 6-2/3
- million tons are supplied.
- If accordingly the demand for cotton-seed were to expand considerably
- owing, say, to the discovery of some new use for the oil, which is its
- most valuable constituent; the effect would be first a rise in the
- price of cotton-seed, and, subsequently, by stimulating cotton
- growing, a more plentiful supply and a lower price for raw cotton. And
- so far at least as the increased supply is concerned, this must
- necessarily be the effect, "other things being equal"; though, to be
- sure, it might be outweighed and obscured by other influences such as
- the boll-weevil. But it is _not_ the case that an increased demand for
- mutton must necessarily increase the supply or lower the price of
- wool; and it is most unlikely to do so in any similar degree. For,
- here, the separate marginal costs of the two things exert their
- influence. An increased demand for mutton will stimulate sheep
- farming, but it will also stimulate the substitution of crossbred for
- merino breeds; and the resultant of these two opposite tendencies upon
- the supply of wool is logically indeterminate. As a matter of history
- we know that the development of cold storage in the eighties (which we
- may regard for the present purpose as equivalent to an increased
- demand for Australian mutton) caused considerable perturbation in the
- woollen and worsted industries of Yorkshire. They were faced with a
- dwindling supply and a soaring price of merino wool; and the
- adaptability with which they met the situation, and won prestige for
- the crossbred tops, and yarns and fabrics, to which they largely
- turned is a matter of just pride in the trade to-day. The fact,
- however, that this alteration in the supply of wool was a matter not
- only of quantity but of quality, while it takes nothing from the
- substance of the preceding argument, makes it difficult to draw a
- clear moral, bearing on the present issue, from this incursion into
- history.
- §4. _The Importance of being Unimportant_. The above contrast between
- cases in which variation is possible, and those in which it is not
- possible, is reproduced with a heightened significance when we turn
- back to joint demand. The cases are perhaps less common in which it is
- _impossible_ to alter the proportions in which different commodities
- are jointly demanded, but there are many cases in which it is not
- nearly worth while to do so (and this amounts to very much the same
- thing). Cases of this sort are especially likely to occur when we are
- dealing with a commodity which accounts for only a tiny fraction of
- the costs of the industry which is its chief consumer. Sewing cotton,
- for example, is jointly demanded, with many other things, by the
- tailoring and other clothing trades; but the money which these trades
- spend on sewing cotton is so small a part of their total expenditure,
- that no ordinary variation in its price is likely to make it worth
- while to study the ways and means of using it in smaller
- quantities. When sewing cotton is bought by the domestic consumer,
- considerations which are fundamentally the same, though somewhat
- different in form, point to a similar conclusion. It is thus very
- difficult to assign to sewing cotton a specific marginal utility. This
- difficulty is of great importance in connection with the possibilities
- of monopolistic exploitation. For it means that the demand blade of
- the scissors upon which we rely to cut off excrescences of price is
- blunted, and if accordingly the producers constitute a strong enough
- combination to control the supply blade, they will possess an unusual
- power of advancing their selling prices as they choose. I am far from
- suggesting that Messrs. J. & P. Coats are to be condemned as an
- extortionate monopoly. On the contrary, during 1919, when the profits
- in highly competitive industries like the main branches of the cotton
- and woollen trades, soared exuberantly, the record of this concern
- seems to me one of distinct moderation. But the present point is that
- they possess an exceptional _power_ to fix the price of sewing cotton
- as they choose, and that this is attributable in no small degree to
- the fact that sewing cotton constitutes an essential but relatively
- trifling item in the expenses of the processes in which it is
- employed.
- Perhaps the point will be made clearer if we turn from the selling
- prices of commercial products, in regard to which there is a strong
- and not ineffective public sentiment against "profiteering," to the
- remuneration of different classes of labor. With an instinctive
- disposition towards megalomania, it is often claimed in Great Britain
- that the miners, being a very numerous and well-organized body of
- workpeople, were in a stronger strategic position than most workpeople
- for exacting the remuneration they desire. It is quite true that a
- stoppage of work in the coal industry causes us a high degree of
- inconvenience, and temporary concessions may thereby be obtained which
- might otherwise have been refused. But this is a dubious advantage,
- and we grossly exaggerate its real importance. The truth is that the
- strategic position of the miners in regard to wages questions is by no
- means strong. For their wages constitute a very large percentage of
- the cost of coal; and the price of coal in its turn is a most
- important element in the costs of many of the industries which are its
- principal consumers. Great Britain, moreover, is far from possessing
- a monopoly of coal. If, accordingly, the wages of the miners are
- temporarily pushed up to a high point, the result will certainly be a
- diminished demand for British coal, which will lead before long to
- their fighting a losing battle to maintain the concessions they have
- won. Contrast their position with that of the steel smelters, whose
- wages (high though the wage rates are) constitute a very small
- percentage of the costs of steel production, and we must agree I think
- that we have in this distinction the main reason why the steel
- smelters, though they hardly ever go on strike, have as a rule been
- able to do so much better for themselves than the miners.
- When a commodity or service is such that an appreciable alteration in
- its price has only a slight effect upon the quantity demanded, the
- demand is said to be _inelastic_. Conversely, when a small change in
- price greatly alters the quantity demanded, we call the demand
- _elastic_. In the former case, it is worth nothing, a larger aggregate
- sum of money will be spent upon the thing when its price is high than
- when it is low, while the opposite is true in the latter case. This
- distinction is of considerable importance in connection with many
- problems (e.g. of taxation); and the terms, elastic demand and
- inelastic demand, are worth remembering. We may thus express the
- above conclusions by saying that the demand for sewing-cotton is
- highly inelastic, and that the demand for coal miners is more elastic
- than that for steel smelters.
- §5. _Capital and Labor_. Cases in which it is impracticable to make
- any variation in the proportions in which different things are used
- together are, however, the exception rather than the rule. Where
- variation is possible, we are confronted with an uncertainty as to the
- way in which an increased supply of one thing will react on the demand
- for another, similar to our uncertainty as to whether an increased
- demand for mutton would augment or diminish the supply of wool. It is,
- for instance, of the highest importance to give a clear answer, if we
- can, to the question whether an increased supply of capital will
- increase the demand for labor. The chief effect of an increased
- supply of capital is to facilitate the extended use of expensive
- machines: to some extent these machines will increase the demand for
- labor; to some extent they will be substituted for it. Which of these
- two tendencies will outweigh the other we cannot be absolutely
- sure. But fortunately we can be far more nearly sure than was possible
- in the analogous case of wool and mutton. An increase in the supply of
- capital increases the demand for the commodities, from which the
- demand for labor is derived, in both the senses discussed in Chapter
- II. First it makes them cheaper to buy, and thus increases the
- quantity that will be bought. It is this that is parallel to the
- effect of an increased demand for mutton in making it more profitable
- to breed sheep. But it also serves to increase the purchasing power
- with which to buy commodities, because it increases the aggregate real
- wealth of the community, and it thus serves to raise the whole demand
- curve. This last consideration is so important as to make it
- overwhelmingly probable, apart from the evidence of history, that an
- increase in the supply of capital (and the same may be said of an
- increase in the supply of the other agents of production) will on
- balance increase the demand for labor. The evidence of history points
- to the same conclusion. The history of the last hundred years displays
- an unprecedented accumulation of capital, and an unprecedented
- extension of machinery, associated with an unprecedented improvement
- in the standard of living throughout the whole community. This is
- powerful testimony in favor of the view that an increase in the supply
- of capital and the use of machinery will usually enhance on balance
- the demand for labor. Moreover, though this is not conclusive, there
- is little room for doubt that an obstructive attitude towards the
- extension of machinery in a particular country, or a particular
- district, is misguided. For its effect must be to make production
- more costly there than it is elsewhere, and to lead, slowly perhaps,
- but very surely, to the transference of the industry to other regions.
- §6. _Conclusions as to Joint Supply and Joint Demand_. Here, however,
- we are beginning to digress. Let us sum up in a general form our
- conclusions as to the way in which changes in the supply or demand of
- a commodity react upon the demand or supply of the other things with
- which it is jointly demanded or supplied. Everything turns, as we have
- seen, on the possibility of variation in the proportions in which the
- things are used or produced together; and this, it is also clear, is a
- matter of degree. Our conclusions, therefore, had best take the
- following form:--
- LAW VII. When two or more things are jointly demanded, in proportions
- which cannot easily be varied, the tendency will be for an increase
- (or decrease) in the supply of one of them to increase (or
- decrease) the demand for the others. These results will be more
- certain, and more marked, the more difficult it is to vary the
- proportions in which the things are used.
- Similarly, when two or more things are jointly supplied, in
- proportions which cannot easily be varied, the tendency will be for
- an increase (or decrease) in the demand for one of them to increase
- (or decrease) the supply of the others. These results again will be
- more certain and more marked, the more difficult it is to vary the
- proportions in which the things are supplied.
- §7. _Composite Supply and Composite Demand_. Joint Demand and Joint
- Supply do not complete the list of relations between the demand and
- supply of different things. Between tea and coffee, or beef and mutton
- there is a relation of a different kind. These things are in large
- measure what we call "substitutes" for one another. An increased
- supply, and a lower price of mutton, will probably induce us to
- consume less beef. This relation it is convenient to describe as
- Composite Supply. Beef and mutton make up a composite supply of meat;
- tea and coffee a composite supply of a certain type of beverage. For
- any group of things, between which the relation of Composite Supply
- exists, we can say, with complete generality, that an increased supply
- of one of them will tend to diminish the demand for the
- others. Parallel to the relation of Composite Supply is that of
- Composite Demand. There are frequently several alternative uses in
- which a commodity or service can be employed; and these alternative
- uses make up a composite demand for the thing in question. Thus
- railways, gasworks, private households and a great variety of
- industries contribute to a Composite Demand for coal. It is worth
- noting that there is frequently an association in practice between
- Joint Demand and Composite Supply on the one hand; and between Joint
- Supply and Composite Demand on the other. Wool and mutton, for
- instance, we have described as an instance of Joint Supply; but, in so
- far as the proportions of wool and mutton can be varied, we can regard
- these things as constituting a Composite Demand for sheep. And this
- conception may help us to retain a clearer and more orderly picture of
- the problems we have discussed above. We can regard the fact that wool
- and mutton are produced together as their Joint Supply aspect, and the
- fact that these proportions can be varied as their Composite Demand
- aspect; and the question as to whether an increased demand for mutton
- will increase the supply of wool turns upon whether the former aspect
- is more important than the latter. Similarly labor and machinery,
- employed together for the same purpose, form an instance of Joint
- Demand; but in so far as they can be substituted for one another, they
- constitute a Composite Supply of alternative agents of production.
- These four relations of Joint Demand, Joint Supply, Composite Demand
- and Composite Supply are well worth remembering and distinguishing
- from one another. They are of immense importance in every branch of
- economic affairs. There are hardly any economic problems upon which we
- are fitted to express an opinion, unless we have a lively sense of the
- far-reaching ramifications of cause and consequence, of the subtle and
- often unexpected interconnections between different industries and
- different markets. To gape at these complexities in a confused stupor
- is as foolish as it is to ignore them. But confusion and stupor are
- only too likely to represent our final state of mind, if we attempt to
- deal with these complications, one by one as they occur to us, in a
- piecemeal and haphazard fashion. We need a clear method, a systematic
- plan by which we may search them out, and fit them into place. The
- four relations which we have enumerated supply us with such a plan and
- method. For they represent something more than a series of pompous
- names for familiar notions. They constitute a classification of the
- various ways in which the demand and supply of one thing can affect
- the demand and supply of others; a classification which is exhaustive
- when we add the relation of derived demand, and an analogous relation
- on the supply side which we must now notice.
- §8. _Ultimate Real Costs_. Just as the utility of "producers' goods"
- is derived from that of the "consumers' goods" which they help to
- make; so the cost of any commodity is derived from the cost of the
- things which help to make it. Moreover, just as we recognize that the
- utility of "consumers' goods" lies at the back of all demand, and
- constitutes the ultimate end of all production; so we cannot but feel,
- however obscurely, that behind the phenomena of money costs, there
- must lie certain ultimate costs, of which all money costs are but the
- measure. But when we try to explain what the nature of these real
- costs may be, we are plunged in difficulty. Wages, it may indeed seem
- at first sight, present no trouble. There is the effort and the
- fatigue, the unpleasantness of human labor, to represent real
- costs. But can we suppose that these things are measured with any
- approach to accuracy by the wages which are paid in actual fact? Is it
- true, even as a broad general rule, that the services which are most
- arduous and most disagreeable command the highest price? And wages are
- not the only ingredient of money costs. There are profits: to what
- real costs do profits correspond? More difficult still, to what does
- rent correspond? These plainly are not questions upon which he who
- runs may read. It will be necessary to devote the next four chapters
- to their elucidation.
- CHAPTER VI
- LAND
- §1. _The Special Characteristics of Land_. In the great process of
- co-operation by which the wants of mankind are supplied, Nature is an
- indispensable participant. She renders her assistance in an infinite
- variety of ways, of which the properties of the soil which man
- cultivates form only one; but the sunshine and rain which enable the
- farmer to grow his crops; the coal and iron ore beneath the surface of
- the earth, can be regarded for our present purpose as forming part of
- the land with which they are associated. We can thus concentrate upon
- land as the representative of the free gifts of nature, which are of
- economic significance. Land in modern communities is for the most part
- privately owned. It can be bought and sold for a price, and acquired
- by inheritance. Moreover, it is a common practice, particularly in the
- United Kingdom, for an owner who does not wish himself to cultivate or
- otherwise use the land, not to sell it to the man who does, but to
- lease it to him for a term of years for an annual payment which we
- term rent. It is therefore natural and convenient to envisage the
- problems, which we shall consider in this chapter, as problems
- concerning the price and rent of land. But, once again, the laws and
- principles which we shall state and illustrate in terms of the current
- systems of ownership and tenure, possess a much deeper significance
- than this terminology might suggest.
- The fact that land is a free gift of Nature distinguishes it in
- various ways from commodities which are produced by man. The
- peculiarities which are most important from the economic standpoint
- are (1) that the supply of land is, broadly speaking, fixed and
- unalterable, and (2) that its quality and value vary, from piece to
- piece, with a variation which is immense in its range, but fairly
- continuous in its gradation. These are thus two aspects from which
- the phenomena of price and rent can be regarded; aspects which it is
- usual to call, (1) the scarcity aspect, (2) the differential aspect.
- §2. _The Scarcity Aspect_. The fact that the supply of land is fixed
- has the following significance. If the demand for land increases, the
- price will tend to rise. This is also true, for a short period at
- least, of an ordinary commodity. But, in the latter case, there would
- ensue an increase in supply which would serve to check the rise in
- price, and possibly, if production on a larger scale led to improved
- methods of production, bring the price down eventually below its
- original level. In the case of land, no such reaction is
- possible. There is nothing, therefore, to restrain the price (and the
- rent) of land from rising indefinitely, and without limit, if the
- demand for it should continue to increase. Conversely, if the demand
- for land falls off, there is nothing to check the consequent fall in
- price and rent. In the case of ordinary commodities, the supply would
- be diminished, because most things are either consumed by being used,
- or wear out in the course of time, and a regular annual production is
- therefore necessary to sustain their supply at the existing level. But
- land remains, whether it is used or not; and its supply is, broadly
- speaking, just as incapable of being diminished, as it is of being
- increased. Changes in the demand for land in either direction are thus
- likely to affect its price in a much greater degree than that in which
- the price of an ordinary commodity will be affected by a corresponding
- change in its demand.
- For most purposes, however, it is of more interest to compare land
- with other agents of production, especially with capital and labor,
- rather than with ordinary commodities. Now, as we have already noted,
- there is some doubt as to the manner in which the supply of capital or
- labor is likely to be affected by alterations in demand price. But the
- supply of capital and the supply of labor, even if we suppose them to
- be as entirely unresponsive to price changes as is the supply of land,
- are at any rate not fixed. Not only _may_ they vary for many reasons,
- but they are in fact likely to vary in direct proportion to the
- population. An increase in population implies an increase in the
- supply of labor; and it is likely to be accompanied by an increase in
- the supply of capital; in other words, the supply of these agents will
- expand, as the demand for them expands. But the supply of land will
- remain what it was. This fact is enormously important in connection
- with the broad problem of population, which will form the theme of
- Volume VI.
- But it is important also in other connections. It has been the
- dominating factor in many absorbing controversies upon high policy
- regarding the ownership of land, or the taxation of land values, upon
- which we can touch but lightly here. It has seemed to many writers a
- reasonable proposition to lay down, that the ordinary course of the
- progress of society, the increase of population and industry, must
- mean, as a broad general rule, a constant increase in the demand for
- land. And, if that be granted, it seems to follow that the price and
- rent of land will tend constantly to increase. John Stuart Mill,
- accordingly, in the middle of the last century, asserted that "the
- ordinary progress of a society, which increases in wealth, is at all
- times tending to augment the incomes of landlords; to give them both a
- greater amount and a greater proportion of the wealth of the
- community, independently of any trouble or outlay, incurred by
- themselves,"[1] and upon the strength of this assertion, he justified
- the policy of imposing a special tax upon what we have come to call
- the "unearned increment" of land. But how far does actual experience
- bear his assertion out? In Great Britain we have seen in the last
- half-century an undoubted increase in urban rents; but over long
- periods at least, there was a marked fall in both the prices and rents
- of agricultural land, despite the fact that the country was
- "increasing in wealth" as rapidly as ever before. This was due, of
- course, in the main to the increased supplies of wheat and other
- foodstuffs coming from the New World: and if, accordingly, we choose
- to lump together not only our own urban and agricultural land, but the
- land of other countries as well, and to speak vaguely of the demand
- for land as a whole, it might seem as though we could argue that
- Mill's generalization still holds good. But even this is by no means
- certain and in any case such a generalization is of very little
- service: what the illustration should rather suggest to us, is the
- danger of speaking of land vaguely as a whole, and the importance of
- turning our attention to the variations in value between different
- kinds and different pieces.
- [Footnote 1: _Principles of Political Economy_, by John Stuart Mill.]
- §3. _The Differential Aspect_. Most ordinary commodities are not
- produced on a single, uniform pattern. As a rule there are many
- variations of grade and quality, and consequently of price. But these
- variations are usually designed to meet the differences of taste among
- the purchasers, and we do not expect to find that any variety of an
- ordinary commodity will be produced, which is so poor in quality as to
- be entirely valueless. But since it is nature which has produced the
- land, without any assistance or guidance from man, there are many
- pieces of land which are so unfertile, or are otherwise so unsuitable
- for productive purposes, as to be quite valueless from the economic
- standpoint. Even in a densely populated country like Great Britain,
- there are considerable tracts of land which it is unprofitable to
- employ for any economic purpose whatsoever, and which possess no
- further value than what the mere pride of ownership may give
- them. This fact makes it possible to apply the conception of the
- margin to the case of land with particularly illuminating results.
- In the first place, however, it should be observed that the value of
- any piece of land does not depend solely on the intrinsic fertility of
- the soil. The fact that land is an immobile thing makes its
- _situation_ a factor of great importance. In the case of urban land,
- situation is, of course, the only thing that counts. The value of a
- site in Bond Street or the City is entirely unaffected by its capacity
- or incapacity for potato-growing purposes. But even for agricultural
- land, situation is a most important matter. A farm, which is so remote
- that considerable transport charges must be incurred to bring its
- produce to market, will be less sought after, and less valuable, than
- one which is much better situated though somewhat less fertile. In
- what follows, therefore, we must speak of the "quality" of a piece of
- land in a broad sense to include advantages of situation, as well as
- of fertility. Let us now, imagine the different pieces of land in
- Great Britain to be arranged in order of quality, so that we have a
- long series, with land of the best quality at one end, and of the
- poorest quality at the other. At the latter end, we will have such
- land as is found near the top of Snowden or Ben Nevis, which it
- clearly does not pay to cultivate at all. Somewhere, then, between
- these two extremes, we shall come to a point where the land is just,
- but only just, worth cultivating, or where, to revert to a form of
- words we previously employed, it is a matter of _doubt_, whether the
- land is really worth using for a productive purpose. Such land we can
- regard as the "marginal land"; and since the variety of nature is at
- once infinite and fairly minutely graduated we shall probably find
- that on one side of this margin there is much land which is only
- slightly superior, and on the other, much which is only slightly
- inferior, to the marginal land itself. What, then, is likely to be the
- value and the rent of this marginal land, this land which is just on
- the "margin of cultivation"? Some readers may find the answer
- startling. The rent of the marginal land will be nil, because it will
- not pay to cultivate it, if any appreciable rent is charged. A piece
- of land for which it is worth a tenant's while to pay an appreciable
- rent, will not be the marginal land, because there will be land just
- slightly inferior to it which it will also pay to cultivate if a
- somewhat lower rent is charged. And so we can pass to poorer and
- poorer qualities of land, with an ever diminishing rent, until at the
- margin of cultivation the derived utility of the land is negligible
- and the rent vanishes.
- This certainly is a somewhat abstract conception; but it is by no
- means so remote from reality as may at first sight appear. The reader
- may protest that in the course of an extensive and varied acquaintance
- with landowners, he has not yet run across this peculiar marginal
- type, who lets his land for no rent at all. But there, if his
- experience is really extensive, I think he is mistaken. It so happens
- that the ordinary agricultural landowner leases out his land, not by
- itself, but together with a variety of other things such as farm
- buildings, which it costs him a considerable sum of money to
- provide. He will not as a rule be willing to go to this expense,
- unless he sees his way to obtain for the farm an annual payment, which
- represents at least a fair return on this capital outlay, as big a
- return as he could have got, for instance, by investing the same
- amount of money in some gilt-edged security. This annual payment
- will, it is true, be called rent; but the significance of this is that
- what we term rent in ordinary life is usually a complex thing, made up
- of two essentially distinct elements, viz. the normal return on the
- capital goods supplied together with the land, and what we may call
- the "net rent," or the "pure rent" attributable to the land
- itself. Now will any reader make so bold as to say that there is no
- land under cultivation, in respect of which this net rent is either
- nil or negligible? The landowners will not agree with him. It is not
- a question, it should be observed, as to whether the rent obtained
- represents more than a fair return on the purchase price paid for the
- land; that is quite another matter. The question is whether the rent
- obtained exceeds a fair return on the capital sum spent on the
- buildings, etc.; with which every farm must be equipped to let at
- all. In fact there are not a few farms where there is no such excess,
- and where accordingly there is no "net rent" or "pure rent" which can
- be attributed to the land.
- The question whether it would be profitable to cultivate any piece of
- land, turns upon whether the receipts which would be obtained by
- selling the produce would exceed the costs of cultivation: and under
- these costs of cultivation we must include, of course, the
- remuneration of the farmer's services. Farmers, like other people,
- have to live; and they would not take on the troublesome job of
- farming, unless there seemed a prospect of making a living out of
- it. The remuneration of the farmer takes, of course, the form not of a
- salary, but of profits: and these profits vary very much from year to
- year, and from place to place, and from man to man. But they are
- essentially payment for work done, and an ordinary profit must be
- regarded therefore as part of the necessary costs of farming. Thus it
- will not be worth while to cultivate a piece of land, and the land
- will in fact lie unused, upon which a careful farmer might obtain a
- profit in the ordinary sense, of no more than $50 or $100 a year. The
- marginal land will be land which yields a decent profit to a decent
- farmer, as well as a gross rent to the landowner, sufficient to
- compensate him for his capital outlay, but nothing further.
- What, then, will be the rent of a fertile and well-situated farm,
- about which there is no doubt that it is well worth cultivating? Part
- of the gross rent which the landowner receives must again be regarded
- as merely a return for the capital expended in equipping the farm for
- use; but in this case, there will be a residue left over, which
- constitutes the net rent of the land. The net rent will measure the
- derived utility of the land to its occupier, and will in general
- represent (very roughly, of course, in practice) the differential
- advantage of cultivating the land in question rather than land on the
- "margin of cultivation." This differential advantage may take either,
- or both, of the forms, of a larger produce per acre, or a lower cost
- of production and marketing. But, in any case, the extra profit,
- which, if no rent were charged, a decent farmer could obtain by
- cultivating the farm in question, rather than a marginal farm, will be
- roughly equal to the net rent which his landlord can exact from him,
- if his landlord so chooses. The landlord may, of course, not choose to
- exact a rent as high as this; and as a matter of fact, in a country
- like Great Britain landlords often content themselves with less. The
- traditions associated with the ownership of agricultural land, and
- with the relations between landlord and tenant serve to soften the
- edge of economic law, and to subject the rents which are actually
- fixed to the control in no small measure of the general sense of what
- is fair or customary. In such cases the landlord makes the farmer a
- present, for the time being, of part of the economic rent. On the
- other hand, as Irish agrarian history well illustrates, the landlord
- may sometimes expropriate under the name of rent, permanent
- improvements which are due to the labors or the expenditure of the
- tenant. This is, of course, particularly likely to happen, whenever it
- is the custom to leave to the tenant the obligation of providing the
- capital equipment of the farm, which in Great Britain is, for the most
- part, the recognized duty of the owner. Again, in the case of urban
- land in the South of England, expropriations of this kind are an
- essential and well-understood feature of the leasehold system. The
- owner grants a lease for a long period of time, usually ninety-nine
- years, for a ground rent, which is notoriously below the true economic
- rent of the land, subject to the condition that the leaseholder must
- erect upon the land and keep in good repair certain buildings, which
- on expiry of the lease will become the property of the ground
- owner. Here the nominal ground rent is only part of the total rent
- which is really paid; the ultimate transference of the buildings
- representing often the more important part. There is, in fact, a great
- variety of systems of land tenure, some of which are highly complex,
- the respective merits of which vary greatly, and which constitute a
- most important problem for statesmen and legislators. Considerations
- of this kind in no way diminish the importance of the general analysis
- of rent, which we are pursuing in the present chapter. Rather they
- make it the more important, because we cannot properly weigh the
- merits of any system of land tenure, until we have grasped clearly the
- principles governing the rent of land in the purest form. But
- certainly we must never forget that the rent we are discussing may
- differ very greatly from, though it will vitally influence, the money
- payments which are called rent in actual life. It is the pure economic
- rent, the rent which represents the _full_ annual payment which it
- would be worth paying to obtain the use of the land alone, which will
- measure, as we have said, the differential advantage of the land in
- question over land on the margin of cultivation.
- A clear grasp of this relation helps us to perceive that an increase
- in the prosperity of the community may sometimes influence rents in an
- unexpected way. It all depends on the causes which have given rise to
- the increased prosperity. An advance, for instance, in agricultural
- science will facilitate a more abundant supply of foodstuffs; but it
- will not necessarily increase the aggregate rents of agricultural
- land. For if it takes the form, say, of the discovery of some new
- artificial manure, it will very likely facilitate production on the
- less fertile soils far more than it will on the more fertile soils
- where artificial manures are not so necessary. It will thus tend to
- diminish the differential advantages of working on the more fertile
- farms, and their rents will accordingly fall, possibly by much more in
- the aggregate than any increase in the rents of the farms near the
- margin of cultivation. The point may, perhaps, be better understood if
- we pass from agricultural to urban land, and ask what would be the
- effect on site values of a great improvement in the facilities of
- internal transport. Push the case to an extreme, and suppose passenger
- transport to become so cheap and so quick that there ceases to be any
- advantage in living in a town so as to be near your place of work.
- Urban landlords would no longer be able to obtain the high rents they
- now receive for the sites of houses in or near a town. For most people
- would prefer to move out into the country where sites can be obtained
- at little more than an agricultural rent. The country covers so large
- an area relatively to the towns that the supply of rural sites would
- be still very plentiful as compared with the demand. Their rents would
- not, therefore, rise by very much, although the rents of the housing
- sites in towns would fall heavily. Of course, there are other factors
- to be taken into account before we could pronounce upon the effect on
- aggregate rents. Central sites for shops might, for instance, fetch a
- higher rental than before. The purpose of this discussion is not to
- generalize but to show the danger of generalizing about rents in the
- aggregate, or land as a whole.
- §4. _The Margin of Transference_. The last illustration may serve,
- however, to remind us of an obvious fact which we must now take into
- account. The same piece of land may be used for a variety of purposes.
- It may have been used for growing corn, and later it may be devoted to
- the building of houses, or, as at Slough, to a repair depot for motor
- vehicles. It need hardly be said that the land will, as a general
- rule, be put to the use in which its value is greatest; or to speak
- more strictly, in which the biggest rent, or the biggest selling price
- can be obtained. But the notion of the differential advantages which a
- piece of land possesses over the marginal land becomes decidedly more
- complicated when we take account of this variety of uses. Let us turn
- our attention, for instance, to the sites used for shop and office
- purposes, and consider what we can regard as the marginal site in this
- connection. Clearly it will not be the marginal land of which we
- spoke above, which it only just paid to cultivate, and which yielded
- no rent at all. For this will probably be agricultural land in an
- out-of-the-way district, where no one would dream of setting up an
- office or a shop. Any site upon which a sane man would contemplate
- setting up a shop will certainly possess value for other purposes,
- such as house-building. Hence the marginal site for shopkeeping
- purposes will not be like our marginal farm, a site which yields no
- rent.
- As regards many pieces of land, there is no doubt as to the purposes
- for which they can most profitably be used. This piece will command a
- much higher rent as a shop site than in any other capacity; for that
- piece house-building is the obvious employment; for another,
- agriculture. But in quite a number of instances there is considerable
- uncertainty. It is not clear whether upon this site it will be better
- to erect a house or a shop, or if the latter, what kind of a shop. It
- is not clear whether it will pay to use that farm land for a building
- scheme; and, within the domain of agriculture, which of course
- comprises an immense variety of really different industries, it is
- often a very moot point indeed whether a certain field should be left
- under grass, or brought under the plow. Cases of this sort are not
- phantoms of the imagination; they emerge on every side as concrete
- problems with which some one or other is dealing every day, and it is
- these cases which constitute the marginal land for the purposes of a
- particular occupation. The marginal sites for shops are the sites for
- which it is only just worth while to pay rents sufficient to entice
- them away from houses. And the rent for a site in Bond Street, or
- elsewhere, which is so much more suitable for shop purposes that no
- alternative use would be worth considering, will exceed the rent paid
- for one of these marginal sites by, roughly speaking, the extra
- advantage it possesses for shop purposes. Or will fall short of it, it
- may be well to add, to the extent of its comparative disadvantage. For
- there may be many such marginal sites, some of which will fetch low
- rents, and others very high rents indeed; the same site being often of
- great potential utility for a large variety of occupations. Between
- any two occupations there will thus usually be a _margin of
- transference_, which we must conceive not as a point, but as an
- irregular line, upon or near to which there will be many pieces of
- land, differing greatly in the rents which they fetch. These
- variations of rent will correspond to the differences between the
- advantages or derived utilities which the sites possess for _both_ the
- occupations in question. The position of such margins of transference
- will of course alter as industrial conditions change, and, when they
- alter, the rents of sites which are not near any margin of
- transference will be affected also. Thus an increased demand for the
- products of any particular industry will make it profitable for that
- industry to offer higher rents, and thus draw land away from other
- occupations. This will have the effect of raising, though possibly to
- a very slight extent, the rents of sites which still remain in other
- uses; for there will be fewer of them available; and their derived
- utilities will consequently be increased.
- But here, as everywhere, it is upon the margin that our attention
- should be focussed, because it is round about the margin (wherever it
- is found) that the changes are taking place which really matter for
- society. When Mr. Mallaby-Deeley buys an estate in Covent Garden from
- the Duke of Bedford, the transaction hardly deserves the degree of
- public interest it excites. Nothing has happened which is of material
- consequence to anyone except the two gentlemen concerned; the various
- sites are still used for the various purposes for which they were used
- before; nothing has occurred that really matters. But when houses are
- pulled down for the erection of a cinema, or when a field is diverted
- from tillage to pasture, something has happened which affects for good
- or ill the interests of the whole community. Conversion from tillage
- to pasture represents, indeed, a tendency which has been very marked
- in Great Britain during the last generation, and has aroused
- misgivings in many public-spirited observers. Possibly for a variety
- of reasons, these misgivings may be justified; certainly the problem
- is well worthy of attention. But when in this way the issue is raised
- of tillage versus pasture, it is essential, if we are to discuss it
- rationally, that we should envisage it clearly as applying only to a
- limited portion of agricultural land, to the portion which lies
- somewhere near the margin of transference, as things are now, between
- the two forms of agriculture. It might be socially desirable to bring
- under the plow a field which the farmer finds it only _slightly_ more
- profitable to lease under grass; but this would be highly improbable
- in the case of a field where the balance of argument to the farmer in
- favor of pasture is overwhelming. The position of the margin of
- transference between different uses may, in other words, be somewhat
- out of place from the social point of view, and it may be desirable by
- appeals and propaganda, even conceivably by the devices of State
- subsidy and compulsion, to push it forwards or backwards in greater or
- less degree. But it will be necessarily a matter of degree, and
- nothing could be more foolish than to speak as though there was, or
- could be, some ideal method of cultivation equally applicable to all
- lands, without regard to their climatic and other conditions. Needless
- to say, none of the agricultural experts who sometimes deplore the
- decline of arable farming are guilty of such foolishness. But the
- sense of the diversity of nature which is very vivid to them may
- sometimes be lacking in people who live in towns, and a firm grasp of
- the marginal notion may serve best to keep the latter from forgetting
- it.
- §5. _The Necessity of Rent_. Behind all such detailed applications
- there lies a more general consideration which deserves attention. The
- way in which the land of a country is used, the way in which it is
- apportioned between the countless alternative employments that are
- possible, is a most important matter, more important perhaps than any
- questions as to the size of the incomes which particular landowners
- receive by virtue of their rights of ownership. How is this
- apportionment effected as things are now? The answer is clear: mainly
- by the agency of either rent or price. The business which finds it
- worth while to offer the highest rent or the highest price for any
- piece of land will, as a rule, be able to command its use. And, with
- this as the governing principle, an apportionment is secured between
- shops, offices, factories, agriculture, between the immense variety of
- different employments covered by each of these broad headings; not a
- rigid unvarying apportionment, but one which constantly changes as
- economic circumstances change, and as the margin of transference
- between different occupations moves hither and thither. This
- apportionment takes place at present as the result of the independent
- decisions and bargains of many private individuals, who are thinking
- mainly of their own interests, and not of those of the community. But
- this state of affairs might be altered. The land might be nationalized
- and allocated to its various uses by the co-ordinated labors of a
- great State department, or some other agency of the collective
- will. However improbable such a change, it is perfectly conceivable.
- But what is not conceivable is that any State department should handle
- the job with a success even approaching that of the present system,
- unless it continued to use, as its main instrument, the criterion of
- either rent or price. That a piece of land would yield a higher rent
- in one occupation than in any other is not conclusive evidence that it
- is best to devote it to the former purpose, but it is very good
- evidence, and it should be allowed to prevail unless it is
- demonstrably outweighed, as it possibly might often be, by
- considerations of a different kind. That it would not be well for the
- community to employ land in the city of London for corn-growing
- purposes, however desirable might be a revival of home agriculture, is
- so obvious that it may seem to have no bearing on the present issue.
- But it is only an extreme indication of the absurd and wasteful use of
- our natural resources, which would grow up slowly but surely, if we
- dispensed with ideas of rent and price as sordid irrelevancies, and
- allocated our land on the basis of a balancing of the loftiest
- arguments of a vague and sentimental character. If you are prepared
- for the distribution of land to become stereotyped, for each piece to
- continue indefinitely in its present use, then indeed you might
- dispense with rent, as primitive societies very largely do. That would
- mean stagnation and, for an industrial country, decay. But if changes
- are ever to be contemplated, a simple quantitative measure is the only
- safeguard against utter chaos. Thus rent, like interest, will be found
- indispensable as a measure under any efficient system of society, even
- if it might not always represent the payment of sums of money to
- private individuals. And that is why the principles governing rent
- possess, as I indicated at the outset of this chapter, an importance
- more fundamental than our present system of ownership and tenure.
- §6. _The Question of Real Costs_. But we must not forget the
- preliminary question that started us upon our analysis of the agents
- of production. The rent which a manufacturer or farmer has to pay for
- his land he naturally includes in his cost of production. But does
- this money cost to the individual correspond to, and measure, any real
- cost to the community as a whole? Here let us note in the first place
- that if only we could disregard the variety of uses to which land is
- put, if we could suppose that all industry was agriculture, and that
- agriculture was a single industry with a single product, we could
- argue that rent does not enter into marginal costs at all. For we
- could regard the marginal producer as the one working on a marginal
- farm, whereas we have seen there is no pure rent. The rent which other
- producers have to pay would thus represent merely the destination of
- the surplus profits which arise wherever actual costs fall short of
- marginal costs. This way of looking at the matter has proved
- attractive to some thinkers, not in the least because of a desire to
- palliate the effects of landlordism, but because it fits in so well
- with our general sense of rent as a "surplus," and a surplus as
- something distinct from a necessary price. But it is clearly
- illegitimate in an economic theory which professes "to describe the
- facts." The marginal land for many purposes fetches, as we have seen,
- a considerable rent; and this rent is certainly part of the marginal
- costs and of the necessary price of the products of the particular
- industry. The answer to our question is, however, not now very
- difficult to see. Land, greatly as it differs in many respects from
- the other agents of production, resembles them in the very important
- respect that, being used for one purpose, it is not available for
- other purposes, and that the productive powers of the community in
- other directions are thereby diminished. This is the real cost to the
- community, which attaches to the products of any industry, in virtue
- of the land which it occupies; not any human labors or sacrifices
- required to produce the land itself, but the curtailment of the
- natural resources available for productive use elsewhere. This is the
- real cost of which rent is the money measure, and generally speaking
- an accurate measure at the margin of transference between one
- occupation and another. A somewhat fanciful use of the term cost, this
- may seem perhaps, one not quite in accordance with our instinctive
- sense of what real costs should be. But possibly the real costs
- represented by wages and profits may turn out to be not so very
- different, and we had best leave the matter there, until we have
- examined the nature of these other costs.
- §7. _Rent and Selling Price_. In this chapter we have spoken mainly of
- the rent rather than the price of land: the relation between the two
- things is fairly obvious and well understood, but it will be well not
- to close the chapter without a brief account of it. The price of any
- piece of land is affected by all the considerations on which its rent
- depends, but it is also affected by another factor which has no
- influence whatever upon rent. This factor is the rate of
- interest. The higher the rate of interest, the higher the return which
- a man could obtain by buying gilt-edged securities, the lower will be
- the price that he will pay for a piece of land which yields a given
- rent. We can express the relation more precisely by the formula Price
- = (Rent * 100)/(Rate of Interest), though we must be careful, in
- applying this formula in practice to allow for the possible deviations
- between the nominal and the true rent, and similar complications. The
- price, it must be observed, is derived in this way from the rent, not
- the rent from the price.[1] Rent is thus logically the simpler, price
- the more complex thing. It is well, therefore, to analyze in the
- first instance the principles of rent, if we live in a country where
- the practice of leasing land for annual rent is less common than it is
- in Great Britain, even if, for whatever reason, it is the price of
- land with which we are concerned in practice. The problem of price
- contains two distinct elements which it is not easy to handle when
- mixed up together. For the rate of interest represents in itself an
- important branch of economics, which will require a separate chapter
- to itself.
- [Footnote 1: In this the rent of land differs fundamentally from that
- of other things, such as houses. For the price of a house is largely
- influenced by the costs of construction of new houses, and should
- correspond closely to them in the long run. The same relation between
- rent, price and rate of interest will hold good; but the rents will be
- affected by changes in the rate of interest, owing to the reactions of
- such changes on the supply of houses.]
- CHAPTER VII
- RISK-BEARING AND ENTERPRISE
- §1. _Profits and Earnings of Management_. The profits of a business,
- as they are ordinarily reckoned, whether for the purposes of income
- tax or of a balance sheet, comprise several elements which are
- fundamentally distinct. The relative importance of these various
- elements varies greatly from one type of business to another. The
- profits of a private business include, for instance, the remuneration
- of the work of management, which in the case of a Joint Stock Company
- is mostly paid for by salaries or directors' fees. It is to their
- profit that farmers, small shopkeepers, and the partners of a private
- firm look not merely for a return upon their capital, but for the
- reward of their own labors. "Earnings of Management," as they are
- usually termed (though in truth they often cover other and humbler
- forms of labor) are thus frequently one of the ingredients of profits.
- §2. _The Payment for Risk-bearing_. There is another element of great
- importance about which our ordinary ideas are apt to be so vague that
- it will be well to devote a chapter to its examination. This is the
- element of payment for risk, or rather the reward of risk-bearing.
- Risk is inherent in all business, as it is inherent in all life. The
- vagaries of nature and the vagaries of man are alike responsible. The
- farmer may find his harvest ruined by a drought or by a deluge; the
- coal or the gold, for the extraction of which you have perhaps set up
- an extensive mining plant, may come to an end which is unexpectedly
- abrupt. You may put your money into roller-skating rinks and find that
- cinemas have become the rage with the fickle public; sometimes "the
- market" may decline for causes which remain obscure but with
- consequences which are disagreeably plain. But while risk is always
- present in some degree, the degree varies enormously from one industry
- to another. Now, it is obvious enough that in an exceptionally risky
- industry, where there is a considerable possibility that the capital
- invested will yield no return at all, the profits of those concerns
- which succeed are likely to exceed the rate of interest on gilt-edged
- securities. But what is likely to be the magnitude of this excess? Is
- risk-taking rewarded if there is any such excess, however small? Or
- will it suffice that the gains and losses should average out to a fair
- rate of interest over the whole industry? To enable us to think
- closely let us suppose for a moment that we can measure accurately
- what the chances are.
- Suppose, then, that there were a precisely equal chance of success on
- the one hand and failure on the other in any enterprise, failure
- involving a complete loss of all the capital invested. Suppose,
- further, 6 per cent to be at the time a fair return on a perfectly
- secure investment. What would be the return which must be expected
- from the risky enterprise, in the event of its succeeding, before it
- will be undertaken? The reader may be tempted to answer, 12 per cent.
- But 12 per cent would not suffice. An equal chance of 12 per cent or
- nothing, as compared with a certainty of 6 per cent, does not mean
- that the risk in the former case is paid for to the tune of 6 per
- cent. It means that it is not paid for at all. In each case what a
- mathematician would call the _expectation_ is a return of 6 per
- cent. The odds are evenly balanced; in the long run, over a large
- number of cases, if the law of averages works as we assume it does,
- you would get just as much from the one type of investment as the
- other. Now, risky enterprises will not, as a rule, be undertaken on
- terms like these; investors and business men will not take risks with
- the odds precisely equal; they must have them, or believe that they
- have them, in their favor.
- §3. _Monte Carlo and Insurance_. To assert this is not to ignore the
- strength of the appeal which the gambling instinct makes to many, if
- not to most of us. The taste for gambling is, indeed, so deep and
- widespread that it would be foolish to leave it out of account in this
- connection. It is clear enough that at places like Monte Carlo people
- are prepared to have the odds unmistakably against them, apparently
- for the sheer pleasure and exhilaration of taking risks. Moreover,
- though for most people play at Monte Carlo represents a mere holiday
- indulgence, it would be unsafe to assume that what appeals to them
- there will not also appeal to them in their business affairs. But what
- exactly is the secret of the charm of Monte Carlo? It is the great
- attractive force of a small chance of a large gain, as compared with
- the deterrent force of a large chance of a small loss. People will
- readily pay $5 for one chance in a hundred of making no more, perhaps,
- than $400 or $450. And it is very likely that this holds good in the
- world of business. If, for example, we were to suppose that the
- promoters of a new enterprise were confronted with one chance in fifty
- of a profit of 50 per cent per annum on their capital, as against
- forty-nine chances of a profit of 5 per cent, this might well prove a
- more attractive prospect than a certain return of 6 per cent, although
- the strict _expectation_ of profit would be smaller in the former
- case. But the risks of business enterprise are not often of this
- type. They conform more usually to the opposite type of a large chance
- of a relatively small gain, balanced by a small chance of serious loss
- or entire failure. Now for almost everyone the possibility of a great
- loss will count as a deterrent (just as the possibility of a great
- gain may count as an attraction) for much more than its strict
- actuarial value.
- The truth of this proposition is demonstrated by the existence of
- institutions more impressive than Monte Carlo--the Insurance
- Companies, which play so large a part in the economic life of modern
- times. Every year, and upon an ever-growing scale, both private
- individuals and business concerns pay sums of money, which reach in
- the aggregate a colossal sum, as premiums to insure themselves against
- loss by Fire, Shipwreck, Burglary, Death, Death Duties, against every
- risk which Insurance Companies will cover. Now Insurance Companies
- are not, as we say, in business for their health. They find their
- business profitable, and pay good dividends to their shareholders.
- Moreover, they incur a considerable expenditure on offices, on
- clerical staff, on agents, and the like. All these payments must be
- defrayed out of the premiums they receive; so that it is plain that
- the premiums greatly exceed the _expectation_ of the risks insured.
- The odds are heavily in favor of the Insurance Company--of that the
- stupidest person can have no shadow of doubt. Yet we continue to
- insure, as private individuals and as business men, and so far from
- being ashamed of our proceedings as a weak and nerveless folly, which
- somehow we are unable to resist, we blazon them forth in the strong
- accents of conscious pride. We preach insurance to our neighbors as
- the core of self-regarding duty, and, if ever we feel a twinge of
- uneasiness, it is lest we, too, may have omitted in some particular to
- practice what we preach.
- The significance of this is unmistakable. Be our psychology what it
- may, however deep and irrepressible our taste for derring-do, however
- inadequate the scope which the dull routine of modern life affords for
- our adventurous impulses, we are most of us anxious to avoid the risk
- of great financial loss. We are very glad to find someone to take it
- off our shoulders if we can; so glad that we are prepared to pay him
- for the service, to pay him a sum which covers not only the actuarial
- equivalent of the risk, but something substantial over and above. In
- this we are entirely rational. Our conduct is justified by the law of
- the diminishing utility of money, which was noted at the end of
- Chapter III. It would be plainly foolish, for instance, to substitute
- for the certainty of an income of $2500 per annum an even chance of
- $5000 or nothing, since the utility to us of $5000 is not twice as
- great as that of $2500.
- The majority of business risks are not of a kind against which it is
- possible to insure. Insurance companies confine themselves to risks
- which are mainly a matter of what we call objective rather than
- subjective chance, i.e. risks in respect of which knowledge of
- detailed facts peculiar to the individual case is of minor
- importance. But such knowledge is of paramount importance in the case
- of ordinary business risks. If, for example, a new enterprise is to be
- undertaken, the special knowledge and experience which its promoters
- possess is a vital factor in determining their estimate of the risk
- involved. An outsider with no special knowledge would necessarily
- require to estimate the risk far more highly if we were to form a
- rational opinion on the basis of _his_ knowledge. So great, indeed,
- would be the risk to him, that we can lay it down as a sound maxim
- that people are extremely rash who invest their money in risky
- undertakings about which they know very little. This subjective aspect
- of business risk has a significance to which it will be necessary to
- revert.
- But, though most business risks are not and cannot be a matter for
- premiums and policies, the principle, which the practice of insurance
- illustrates, applies none the less. In the light of their knowledge
- and experience, the promoters of a new undertaking must weigh up the
- chances of failure and success, though they will not do so by the
- precise methods of an actuary. They will require that any chances of
- serious loss should be balanced by such chances of exceptional gain,
- as would raise the _expectation_ of profit well above the normal
- return on secure investments. The more risky the project seems the
- greater, generally speaking, must be the _expectation_ of profit
- required to induce people to undertake it.
- If we suppose business men to calculate reasonably, it follows that
- the average profits in any industry over a long period of years,
- reckoning in the losses of the concerns which disappear altogether,
- are likely to be higher, the more risky is the industry. Such a result
- will not, of course, occur in every case. Even when the calculations
- are reasonable, they may be entirely falsified by the event. Moreover,
- business men may not calculate reasonably on the information which
- they have. But, unless we suppose their judgment to be subject to a
- prevailing bias in one direction, i.e. to be unduly optimistic as a
- general rule, _we_ should expect, and in any case _they_ must expect,
- profits above the ordinary in a risky industry.
- This conclusion is sufficiently important. Far too many people, though
- they admit it when it is expressly stated and dismiss it even as a
- tiresome commonplace, are apt to neglect it when the occasion for
- applying it arises. For example, the great importance to any industry
- of good management is generally recognized, and the consequent
- desirability of paying adequate salaries to the managerial staff. The
- importance of securing a supply of capital is very widely recognized,
- and the practical necessity of paying a fair rate of interest is thus,
- however grudgingly, conceded. But the "residuary profits," as they
- are called, which accrue at present to the owners of a business, are
- denounced in some quarters in a sweeping fashion, which seems to
- ignore altogether the all-pervading element of risk. People speak as
- though you might appropriately limit profits in every industry to some
- uniform percentage on the capital employed, without making it clear
- whether you would even be allowed to make up in good years for the
- losses incurred in bad. The effect of introducing any such crude
- device into our present industrial system could only be to paralyze
- enterprises of an unusually risky kind, which, so far from being
- pushed to an excess at present, are more probably curtailed unduly
- from the standpoint of what is socially desirable. Like the fixing of
- a low maximum price for a commodity it would cause the supply to
- wither up and disappear.
- §4. _Risk under Large-scale Organization_. While this is true of the
- present economic system, the question is worth considering whether it
- represents a fundamental necessity, whether, for instance, under our
- world socialist commonwealth the factor of risk-bearing need play so
- important a part as it does in the actual business world. This
- question cannot be answered with a conclusive simplicity; opposing
- considerations present themselves, between which it is not easy to
- strike a balance. On the one hand, in accordance with the law of
- averages gains and losses tend to cancel out over a large series of
- transactions, _when reasonable calculations have been made_. Thus
- Insurance Companies, while they take heavy risks off the shoulders of
- policy-holders, incur relatively trifling risks themselves; they can
- predict the aggregate sums which they will be called upon to pay
- within a small margin of error. In the same way it might seem that
- every enlargement of the scale of business would make for an automatic
- insurance and a consequent economy of risk; and thus that if all
- businesses were comprised in a single financial unit, gains and losses
- would cancel out over so wide a range that the degree of risk
- remaining would be almost negligible.
- This might indeed happen, if business risks were mainly of that
- objective kind in which the insurance companies specialize; for then
- we could assume that the chances of success or failure would be
- estimated reasonably. But, in fact, most business risks, not being of
- this kind, must be estimated by processes of human judgment, which are
- very fallible. And here we must take account of the law of averages in
- another aspect, with a different bearing on the argument. When an
- industry comprises a large number of separate concerns, and the
- decisions accordingly are taken by many men, acting independently of
- one another, the errors of calculation will tend to some extent to
- cancel one another out. The undue optimism of one man will be balanced
- by the undue pessimism of another; and, if there is no prevailing bias
- in either direction, the errors of judgment will not affect the
- results for the industry as a whole. But where the effective decisions
- are taken by very few men, the chances are far greater of a
- preponderating balance of error in one direction. The risks dependent
- on the factor of human judgment tend therefore to increase.
- This truth can be illustrated by a phenomenon which is fairly
- familiar. It is recognized by intelligent persons that the risks of
- speculation in a particular commodity market or stock market increase
- more than proportionately to the scale of operations. A man who sets
- out as a "bull" upon a small scale can buy without sending up the
- price against him in the process, and, if he decides later that his
- judgment is mistaken, he can at any time cut his losses and sell out
- without much difficulty. But a "bull" on a very large scale cannot
- complete his purchases except at a price which has been raised in
- consequence of his own action, and he cannot count on being able to
- "unload" at or near the market price, should he decide to do so. If,
- accordingly, he miscalculates, he cannot save himself from serious
- loss as a smaller man might do by a prompt discovery of his error. His
- difficulties spring from the fundamental fact that the effects of his
- calculations are too great to be offset by those of the different, and
- often opposite, calculations of other men.
- Upon the issue whether a growth in the size of the business unit is
- likely to diminish risk, the law of averages thus cuts both ways. The
- risks arising from the element of pure chance are more likely, those
- arising from miscalculation are less likely, to cancel out. Upon
- these grounds alone, it would be unsafe to conclude that there would
- be on balance an economy of risk under any system of national or world
- socialism.
- §5. _The Entrepreneur_. There remains, however, an aspect of the
- problem which is perhaps more important than those discussed above. It
- is probable that risks would be estimated and undertaken more wisely
- or less wisely under a different system of society or of industrial
- organization? Upon this issue, methods of precise analysis are out of
- place, but we may have something to learn from the emphatic testimony
- of tradition. It has become an axiom of business men that, while
- Governments can manage with more or less competence a safe and routine
- business like a Postal Service, their success would be unlikely to
- prove conspicuous in undertakings where the element of risk is
- great. There, it is said, we owe everything in the past to the
- enterprise of individual men (for even joint-stock companies have not
- been notable as pioneers) adventuring their own fortunes in accordance
- with their own unfettered judgment. This contention, however much we
- may desire to qualify it, has unquestionably a large measure of truth,
- and the explanation is not difficult to discover. For the wise taking
- of risks in industrial development of an experimental character,
- peculiar conditions and special qualities are required. First, it is
- necessary to envisage distinctly the promising though risky
- opportunity, and this calls not infrequently for imagination of a none
- too common order. Then it must be studied with insight and expert
- knowledge and weighed by processes which are as much intuitive as
- intellectual. The reasons for or against taking a particular business
- risk are seldom such as can adequately be expressed in terms of
- arithmetic, or even by clear arguments the soundness of which is
- proportioned to their logical cogency. The mysterious faculty of
- judgment enters in; and from mental processes which defy analysis
- there emerge ultimately conviction and the will to act. But it is
- precisely here that Government Departments are apt to fail. It is here
- that the individual, who need consult no one but himself, has a pull
- over any form of organization, where decisions are reached by the
- method of debate and agreement among a heterogeneous committee. Hence
- it is that we have come to regard exceptional risk-taking as the
- peculiar province of individual enterprise. It is probable that these
- deficiencies of corporate organization are tending to diminish, and it
- is an interesting question how far it may be found possible to
- eliminate them in the future.
- Meanwhile the above considerations have an important bearing on the
- rewards which can often be obtained from risky enterprises. The number
- of individuals who are in a position to envisage a business
- opportunity, and to assess with some confidence the chances of success
- and failure is very limited. Not only must they possess special
- knowledge, ability, imagination, confidence in their own judgment, and
- the capacity to act on it; they must also have at their disposal
- considerable financial resources. To combine all these advantages
- represents a union of circumstances which is distinctly rare. The
- fortunate few, who do combine them, are thus generally able to extract
- in the form of profits a high price for their services, a price which
- covers not only the strict reward of risk-bearing, and the necessary
- remuneration of their own service, but a handsome payment for the
- special qualities and advantages which have been indicated. Profits,
- moreover, may vary between one industry and another, not only in
- accordance with the real risk which is entailed, but with the degree
- to which the supply of special knowledge, etc., is scarce or abundant.
- This consideration goes a long way to explain the large fortunes which
- enterprising business men are often able to amass. It also throws some
- much-needed light upon the functions which such men discharge. They
- perform to a large extent the work of management; they supply capital
- on what may be a considerable scale; but it is the taking of business
- risk which is perhaps their most characteristic function. It is the
- union of these functions which distinguishes them as an essentially
- different type from the salaried manager who has invested his savings
- in rubber or in oil. In other languages there is a specific name for
- the man who combines all these three functions; in French he is called
- an "entrepreneur," in German an "Unternehmer." It is much to be
- regretted that in English we have no clear corresponding word. The
- word "capitalist" is not uncommonly employed to do duty in this
- connection, but this is a source of much confusion. For the word is
- also used, and more appropriately, to include all investors, whether
- or not they are active business men.
- §6. _Risk-taking and Control_. But there is an allied confusion of
- more importance. We commonly suppose it to be a leading feature of our
- present "capitalist system" that the control of industry rests in the
- hands of those who supply the capital. Nor, as a general statement, is
- this untrue. But it conceals the essential point. Strictly speaking,
- it is risk-taking with which control is associated. The mere lending
- of money carries with it no title to control. Governments and
- municipalities concede no such title to the subscribers to their
- loans; nor does a company to its debenture holders. The shareholders'
- ultimate control is based upon the fact that they bear the financial
- risks of the concern. Nor is this a matter of mere legal form. It is
- not uncommon for ordinary shares to carry with them a greater voting
- power than the preference shares of a corresponding value. The
- principle which such arrangements endeavor to express is clear:
- control should rest with him who bears the risk. It is with this
- principle rather than with a mulish insistence on the rights of
- property, that advocates of "workers' control" and the like have got
- to reckon. It is upon this ground that (as they may quite conceivably
- do) they must make good their case.
- §7. _General Analysis of Profits_. Let us conclude this chapter by
- clearing the ground for the next. Earnings of management, payments for
- risk-taking and for the special knowledge and advantages associated
- with it, are ingredients of the gross profits of a business. The chief
- element that remains is that of interest on capital. Frequently,
- indeed, it is not the only one. As we saw in the last chapter, a
- farmer may not be required by his landlord to pay the full economic
- rent for his farm; and he may therefore make profits above the normal
- level, above the ordinary return for his own services, his own capital
- expenditure, and the risks to which he is necessarily exposed. In such
- a case the farmer is really the recipient, as we have already
- suggested, of part of the economic rent of the land; and an element of
- rent accordingly enters into his gross profits. But profits may
- include a surplus element which may arise in a great variety of other
- ways. A business may possess some decided advantage which is not open
- to competitors; and it may reap high profits accordingly. You can,
- for instance, if you choose, regard the high money profits, which, as
- was suggested in Chapter IV, are likely to accrue in future to the
- owners of pre-war factories, as a surplus profit of this kind. But
- while, as this illustration indicates, the phenomenon of surplus
- profits becomes of very great importance when we seek to study the
- distribution of wealth, it need not detain us here. For the surplus
- element arises only in so far as the costs of a business are lower
- than the marginal costs; and it is the marginal costs, which, with
- good reason, we are now endeavoring to analyze. The marginal costs
- must include a normal profit, i.e. a profit which will cover earnings
- of management, the reward of risk and enterprise, interest on capital,
- but nothing further. It remains, then, only to consider this last
- element of interest.
- CHAPTER VIII
- CAPITAL
- §1. _A Reference to Marx_. Interest is the price paid simply for the
- use of capital. But what is capital, and in what does its use consist?
- What claim has it to be regarded as an independent factor of
- production? Our very familiarity with the term, our habit of employing
- it with the rich looseness of every-day life is an obstacle to the
- clearness of thought, which is again essential. We recognize, most of
- us, clearly enough that capital, although we reckon it in terms of
- money, consists, like income, of real things; factories, machinery,
- materials and the like. It is quite obvious that these things are of
- use, are, indeed, indispensable for production; what more natural than
- that capital should command a price? It almost seems as though we
- might pass, without further ado, to a detailed discussion of the
- forces which determine the amount of this price.
- But this account does not bring out the essential point as brief
- reference to a very famous controversy will show. Some ingenious
- writers in the last century, the most notable of whom was Karl Marx,
- set out to prove that, in our modern society, workpeople are
- "exploited," robbed of the "whole produce of their labor," to the full
- extent of the return which accrues to capital. The argument was
- exceedingly complex in detail; but it boils down to this: The
- factories and machinery which are admittedly essential to production
- were themselves produced in exactly the same way as consumable
- goods. They were produced by labor, working with the assistance of
- nature, and, again, if you choose, of capital in the form of further
- factories, machinery, etc. But these further capital goods can in
- their turn be regarded as the product of labor, nature and capital;
- and so we can proceed until it seems as though the element of capital
- must disappear in the last analysis, as though labor and nature were
- the sole ultimate agents of production, and the reward of capital
- represented no more than the exercise of the exploiter's power. In one
- form or another this argument still dominates the minds of a large
- proportion of the so-called "rebels" against the existing social
- order.
- If we are to meet this argument, if, which is perhaps more important,
- we are to understand the true nature of capital, we cannot rest
- content with saying that it consists of factories and machinery, and
- that these are essential to the worker. Just as it was well to get
- behind the money terms, in which we often think of capital, to the
- real goods; so we have now to get behind the real goods to something
- else. What this something else is, the first chapter may have already
- done something to reveal.
- §2. _Waiting for Production_. Between production and consumption there
- is an interval of time. All productive processes take time to
- accomplish. The farmer must plow the soil and sow the seed months
- before he can reap the harvest which will reward him for his
- efforts. Meanwhile, he must live, and in order that he may live he
- must consume. If he employs laborers he must pay them wages, that they
- too may consume and live. For both purposes he requires purchasing
- power, which represents of course command over real things; and if he
- has not sufficient purchasing power of his own, he must borrow from
- someone else who has. In either case it is not enough that the farmer
- and his laborers should work; no less essential is it that someone
- should _wait_. The farmer must wait till he has sold his crops, both
- for the reward of his own labor and for the repayment of the wages he
- advances in the meantime to his laborers. Or, if he cannot afford to
- wait, and borrows in anticipation of the harvest, then the lender must
- wait, until the farmer, having sold his crop, is able to repay
- him. Thus the period of time involved in all production gives rise to
- a demand for _waiting_, which someone or other must supply, if the
- production is to take place. It is this waiting which is the essential
- reality underlying the phenomena of capital and interest. It is really
- this which constitutes an independent factor of production, distinct
- from labor and nature, and equally necessary.
- §3. _Waiting for Consumption_. But let us carry the argument a step
- further. After the farmer has sold his crops, there are many stages
- through which they must pass, at each of which more waiting is
- required, before they reach the ultimate consumer. But then the
- waiting is at an end.
- This, however, is by no means the case with a great number of
- commodities. Let us take the case of a speculative builder. While he
- is building a house he, like the farmer, must wait (or find someone to
- wait on his behalf), for his own reward, and for the repayment of his
- expenditure on wages and materials. But, after the house is built, if
- he lets it to a tenant for an annual rent, his waiting is far from
- over. Not until many years have passed will the rent payments add up
- to a sum which equals or exceeds his outlay. He may, of course, sell
- the house, and thus bring his waiting to an end. But then the
- purchaser must wait, no matter whether or not he is the occupier. For
- no one would consider the use of a house for a day, a month, or a year
- as an adequate return for the price it cost to buy. The occupier-owner
- pays for the prospect of its use for a long and perhaps indefinite
- number of years ahead, and he must wait to enjoy the benefits for
- which he pays now in full. Waiting is as inherent in the consumption
- of durable things as it is in all production.
- Now most industries are consumers of durable things of a very
- expensive kind. Here we come back to the factories and machinery which
- ordinarily spring to our mind at the mention of the word capital. Not
- merely does the construction of these things involve waiting; their
- consumption involves waiting on a vastly larger scale. Just as with a
- house, many years must elapse before their derived utility can even
- approximate to their purchase price. It is mainly to supply the
- waiting involved in the consumption of such durable goods, that a
- typical joint-stock company issues shares for public subscription. The
- waiting required to cover the period of time, which its own productive
- process requires, is largely supplied by means of bank overdrafts or
- other forms of short-period borrowing. More strictly, fixed capital
- represents the waiting involved in the consumption of durable things;
- circulating capital the waiting involved in current production.
- This distinction loses its sharpness when we consider not the affairs
- of a particular business, but the industrial system as a whole. Then
- the period of time involved in the consumption of durable instruments
- falls into place as part of the time required for the production of
- the ultimate consumers' goods. We can even, perhaps, conceive of an
- "average period of production" for industry and commerce as a whole;
- and this conception is not without its uses. For it serves to bring
- out the fact that the period of consumption, and the period of
- production in the narrower sense, are only two aspects of the same
- fundamental thing, the interval of time which elapses between work and
- the utility, which is its ultimate purpose. It serves, moreover, to
- make clear that anything which lengthens this interval of time
- increases the demand for waiting, or in other words, the demand for
- capital; and, conversely, that anything which shortens this interval
- diminishes the demand for capital.
- §4. _Capital not a Stock of Consumable Goods_. But the distinction
- between the two forms of waiting, though not fundamental, is none the
- less worth noting. It enables us to keep our theory in conformity
- with fact, to look at the phenomenon of capital the right way up; and
- it is easy, if we are not careful, to slip into the habit of looking
- at it upside down. People sometimes speak as though the commodities
- which constitute our capital, instead of being mainly, as our plain
- sense tells us that they are, factories, machinery and other durable
- instruments, were rather a _store_ or _stock_ of immediately
- consumable goods. The argument takes the following form. It is
- consumers' goods, things like food and clothes, which the farmer, the
- builder and their workpeople consume while they are working. To enable
- them to work, therefore, it is vital that such things should not in
- the past have been consumed as soon as they were made; part of them
- must have been saved, and carried forward for future use.
- Furthermore, the longer the time that the work on which people are now
- engaged takes to yield its product, the larger must be this store of
- consumers' goods. For these products, when they are completed, will
- serve (taking society as a whole) to replace the store which in the
- meantime is being used up, so that the longer this replacement takes,
- the larger must be the initial store. Conversely, the larger the
- store of consumers' goods available, the more distant is the future
- for which we can afford to work. It is thus the store or stock of
- consumers' goods which represents our real capital; for it is the
- magnitude of this store which determines how far we can devote our
- energies to purposes which are remote in time.
- Now this is pure mysticism. Regarded literally, it is in direct
- conflict with the facts. The processes of industry are fairly regular
- and continuous. At any moment, large quantities of consumers' goods of
- almost every kind are on the point of completion; at the same moment
- equally large quantities are consumed. The things which we buy were
- finished, very likely, only recently; or, if in fact they have lain
- idle for some time in stock, there is nothing essential or at all
- helpful in that fact. It represents rather a defect--a maladjustment
- which should be rectified. Even many kinds of agricultural produce do
- not need to be carried forward from one year to another, for they are
- produced in many parts of the world, where the seasons come at
- different periods of the year. It is conceivable, therefore, that we
- might consume all non-durable things the moment they were ready, and
- the degree to which we approximate to this ideal is a mark of the
- efficiency of our economic system. A large store of consumable goods
- is thus _not_ a fundamental necessity of a prosperous society.
- What _is_ necessary is plainly the power to produce these things in
- large quantities as they are required. And this power is furnished by
- the durable instruments of production, which we thus rightly regard as
- the true representatives of modern capital. If it is argued that this
- power to produce consumable goods may be regarded as being _in effect_
- a store of consumable goods, it must be sternly replied that this is
- the language of symbolism, not of science, and that symbolism is
- highly dangerous in this connection. The false conception of capital
- as essentially a store of consumers' goods has led and still leads to
- many serious fallacies. It was this that gave rise to the notorious
- doctrine of the Wages Fund; the notion that the sum which can at any
- time be paid in wages is equal to the quantity of capital, _alias_
- consumable goods, which happens to exist. To this day it blocks, with
- an undergrowth of obscurantist controversies, the way to a
- straightforward account of the problem of trade cycles.
- §5. _The Essence of Waiting_. But it is with positive conclusions that
- we must here concern ourselves. What is the essence of this waiting,
- as we have called it? What are its results from the point of view of
- the community? The individual, who saves and lends, waits in the
- obvious sense that he postpones consumption. He foregoes his right to
- purchase now a quantity of consumers' goods in consideration of the
- prospect of purchasing a larger quantity of such things in the
- future. From the standpoint of the whole community, there is a similar
- postponement of consumption, though it need not commence so soon. The
- store of consumable goods is what it is: the quantity of goods in
- _process_ of manufacture, which will shortly be coming forward, is
- also what it is. For some time, therefore, a sudden access of saving
- cannot affect the quantity of goods available for consumption; and if,
- in fact, they should be consumed less rapidly, that will represent an
- unfortunate defect, not an essential condition of a smoothly working
- system. The _necessary_ consequence comes later. The increased saving
- will cause labor, materials, land, agents of production generally, to
- be devoted to distant purposes. Men will be set to work producing
- durable goods, largely durable instruments of production like ships or
- railways or factories or plant. If the increased saving is
- considerable, the labor, materials, etc., required for these purposes
- will be withdrawn even under our present system, as under a smoothly
- working system they clearly must be, from the production of other and
- more immediately consumable things. Hence, some time later, the
- supplies of consumable things will be diminished, while at a later
- period still they will be more than correspondingly increased as the
- result of the assistance of the new durable instruments. That is the
- essence of saving from the social standpoint. An early future is
- sacrificed to a more remote future. The aggregate consumable income of
- the present is unaffected; the aggregate consumable income of the near
- future is actually diminished; it is not until at least some years
- later that the aggregate consumable income is increased.
- §6. _Individual and Social Saving_. This conclusion is important: but
- there is an obvious misinterpretation against which it will be well to
- guard. It is customary for social moralists to preach thrift and
- saving as a public duty, and to impart to their appeals a special note
- of urgency in times like the present, when, as the result of the havoc
- of the war, destitution is widespread over Europe. Now obviously these
- advisers do not mean to recommend something which will impoverish the
- world next year and the year after and the benefit of which will
- accrue only in a distant future: it is the immediate urgency of the
- world's needs which is rather the substance of their case. Nor would
- it be right to conclude that these wise men are the victims of a
- delusion, and advocate a course, the consequence of which they do not
- understand. The explanation of the paradox is simple. The more the
- community as a whole saves now, the less in the near future will be
- the aggregate consumable income of the whole community: but not of the
- _remainder_ of the community, exclusive of the savers. It is the saver
- who must wait, whose consumption must be postponed to perhaps a
- distant future; but _at no time_ does his saving result in a smaller
- income of consumable goods for other people. The aggregate consumable
- income of the near future will be diminished, but it may be better
- distributed, and it may consist of things of a different _kind_. For
- consumers' goods, we must remember, comprise champagne and motor cars
- as well as food and clothes; and, if a rich man saves, it may be
- purely articles of luxury, the production of which will shortly be
- diminished. Moreover, if his saving has the effect of transferring
- purchasing power to impoverished people, like those in Central Europe,
- it will not be devoted to a distant future; it will very likely be
- devoted to quite immediate ends. In other words, it may not result in
- any "creation of capital"; it may not represent any saving on the part
- of the community as a whole. A relatively rich man waits, and a
- relatively poor man _anticipates_ his income to a corresponding
- extent; and it is precisely this that is so urgently desirable in a
- time of widespread poverty and chaos.
- This is no matter of hair-splitting, and making plain things
- obscure. While it is always better for the _rest_ of us that an
- individual, who can afford to save, should save rather than spend
- (though it might be better for us still if we could have his money to
- spend ourselves) and while this is the more important the greater is
- the poverty which generally prevails; yet, as a community we cannot
- save so much, we _ought_ not to save so much, when we are impoverished
- as when we are prosperous. It is vital to appreciate this truth,
- because, as we shall see, by no means all the saving of the world is
- done by individuals. There are many forms of "collective saving,"
- which take place in actual fact; still more which we are often urged
- to undertake. And it is of practical importance to realize that the
- very considerations, which call most urgently for individual thrift,
- forbid a great indulgence in such projects. A time of national poverty
- is not a time when it is suitable for the State to embark on large
- schemes of capital development: we require our resources for more
- immediate ends. Faced with such problems, our practical sense may no
- doubt suffice to keep us straight; but it is apt to do so at the
- expense of a complete inversion of the real issues. If, for instance,
- we call for Governmental retrenchment on what we deem extravagant
- policies of housing and education, we usually speak as though they
- represented the profligacy of a spendthrift as contrasted with the
- saving that is indispensable. The truth is rather that these policies
- represent a saving, an investment for future purposes, which may
- conceivably be greater (this must not be taken as representing my
- personal opinion) than the community can properly afford. This is
- another instance of what I mean by looking at the problem of capital
- the right way up.
- §7. _The Necessity of Interest_. It is only now that we are in a
- position to appreciate the true functions of a rate of interest, and
- the nature of its claims to be regarded as a "real cost." Interest, it
- is sometimes said, is necessary to provide for the future. It is far
- more certain that interest is necessary to provide for the present. It
- is a matter of legitimate doubt how far it is necessary to _pay_
- interest to secure a supply of capital; there is no doubt at all that
- it is necessary to _charge_ interest to limit the demand for it. As we
- saw in Chapter I, a world socialist commonwealth would require to
- retain a rate of interest, if only as a matter of bookkeeping, in
- order to choose between the various capital undertakings that were
- technically possible. And this is the primary function which the fate
- of interest fulfils in our present-day society. It separates the sheep
- from the goats. It serves as a screen, by means of which capital
- projects are sifted, and through which only those are allowed to pass
- which will benefit the future in a high degree. For this essential
- purpose it is hard to imagine how a better instrument could be
- devised.
- §8. _The Supply of Capital_. Let us dwell for a moment on this image
- of a screen, or sieve. One condition of a good sieve is that its
- meshes should all be of the same size. This condition the rate of
- interest almost perfectly fulfils. But it is also important that the
- meshes should be of the _right_ size. Whether this is true of the
- actual rate of interest is a far more doubtful matter. It is, indeed,
- plain that it is not altogether devoid of merit in this respect. In
- times of general world poverty, like those which follow upon a great
- war, it is desirable, as has been argued, that more of our productive
- resources should be devoted to immediately useful purposes, and a
- smaller portion dedicated to a distant future. This readjustment the
- rate of interest helps to bring about. For it rises to a higher
- level, and there is accordingly a strong inducement to all
- manufacturers and traders to economize their use of capital, and thus
- to set free productive resources for more urgent needs. But, while the
- meshes of the sieve, as it were, contract in times when it is
- desirable that they should contract, we have no reason for supposing
- that they will contract in just the degree that is desired, neither
- more nor less; or, indeed, that at any time they approximate to the
- right size. We in the twentieth century owe much of the material
- wealth that we enjoy to the fact that over the last century men saved
- as largely as they did. But our natural gratitude should not restrain
- us from doubting whether they were really well advised to do so. If we
- ask the question _how_ they managed to do so, our doubts are
- deepened. For first place among the explanations must be assigned to
- the inequality in the then distribution of wealth. It was because many
- men in England were rich enough to save that our railways were built,
- and the resources of new Continents were opened up. But England, a
- century or even half a century ago, was not really a rich
- community. And if the national income in those days had been
- distributed more evenly among the people, can we doubt that they would
- have spent a far larger proportion of it on immediate needs; can we
- doubt that they would have been right to do so? We may rather doubt,
- in view of the reactions of poverty on physical and mental efficiency,
- on social harmony, even possibly on population, whether we to-day
- would have been really injured as much as might appear. How, then, can
- we suppose that the sum of the amounts which it suits individuals to
- save will bear any close relation to the resources which the community
- can properly devote to future ends? Are we to regard an unjust
- distribution of wealth as a mysterious dispensation of Providence for
- securing perfect harmony between the future and the present? The
- point need not be labored further. There are no grounds for assuming
- that we save, as a community, even roughly what we ought to save. If
- we wish to believe we do, we must turn for support from economics to
- theology.
- It is important to be clear upon this issue in order to distinguish it
- from another, with which it sometimes seems to be confused. This is
- the question, briefly outlined in Chapter II, of the effect of changes
- in the rate of interest on the supply of capital. As was there
- indicated, there are good reasons for supposing that a fall in the
- rate of interest would induce some people to save more, and
- conversely. But the balance of probability is in favor of the
- conclusion that the _net_ effect of changes in the rate of interest,
- though perhaps slight, is usually of the more ordinary kind. The
- decisive argument in this connection is the fact, upon which we have
- just touched, that savings are supplied largely by people who are
- relatively rich, and who become richer when the rate of interest
- rises. For at this point it is necessary to be careful. It is easy to
- slide from the above conclusion into an argument of the following
- kind. A higher rate of interest leads to more saving; it is thus
- necessary to _evoke_ more saving; it is thus required as an
- _incentive_ to induce people to incur the _sacrifice_ of waiting; this
- sacrifice represents the "real cost" for which interest is paid.
- This terminology of incentive, inducement and sacrifice is of very
- dubious validity. A rich man, who is made richer by a rise in the rate
- of interest, will probably save more, but it will be rather because he
- has become richer than because he is tempted by the higher rate: and
- the less we talk about his sacrifice the better. Nor is it clear that
- the attraction of a high rate of interest is an operative factor on
- the mind of a man to whom saving means a real sacrifice of immediate
- comfort or enjoyment. Certainly it is only one among many factors, and
- seldom an important one. A really poor man will think not so much of
- the annual income which will accrue from his savings, as of the
- capital sum upon which he or his family can fall back if a rainy day
- should come. And for this purpose he might save as much as he saves
- now, even if there were no interest to be obtained thereby. He might
- even be prepared to lend what he had saved, at least to banks (a
- deposit with a bank is in effect a loan), for the mere advantage of
- safe custody. The people who save rather for the sake of the capital
- sum that can be realized than for that of the annual interest are very
- numerous, and probably include many men in receipt of quite
- considerable earned incomes. Moreover, those who consider mainly the
- future annual income which their savings will yield them, are usually
- more concerned with its absolute amount than with the ratio it bears
- to the amount they must save in order to acquire it. For this reason,
- as has been often recognized, they may save less when the rate of
- interest rises, since a smaller quantity of savings will insure to
- them the future annual income they desire to obtain. There is no need
- to be dogmatic upon any of these points. The psychology of saving is
- both complex and obscure. Our conclusion must be the negative one that
- we have insufficient evidence to warrant the assertion that the
- particular rate of interest which happens to prevail is a measure of
- the sacrifice involved in saving, even in the case of what we might
- regard as the "marginal saving." And, if we cannot assert this, we
- must be careful not to assume it as the basis of other arguments, or
- as part of a general analysis of price or exchange value.
- It is of some interest to observe that the difficulties which our
- world socialist commonwealth would encounter if it attempted to
- dispense with the rate of interest, would not necessarily include that
- of obtaining a supply of capital. It might, indeed, not find it easy
- to determine the proportions in which it should allocate its
- productive resources between immediate and distant ends. Our present
- system cannot be said to have evolved satisfactory principles for the
- solution of this question; and the socialist commonwealth would have
- to work out its own solution. But when it directed that labor and
- materials should be devoted to purposes of long-period utility, there
- would be an automatic collective saving, of which no one would be
- conscious as an individual sacrifice. Even at the present time, our
- capital is not supplied entirely by the savings of individuals, but to
- an extent, which though quite incalculable is yet certainly
- considerable, by involuntary saving of an essentially similar type to
- the above.
- §9. _Involuntary Saving_. When a municipality embarks on a municipal
- tramways scheme or any other industrial enterprise, and pays off by
- means of a sinking-fund the capital which it borrows in the first
- instance, the proceeding amounts, as the defenders of municipal
- trading have rightly claimed, to a compulsory and unconscious saving
- on the part of the citizens. Their consumption has been postponed
- willy-nilly as the result of the increased rates or the high charges
- which they have had to pay; and, when the subscribers to the original
- loan have been paid off, the capital of the community is enhanced to
- the extent of that loan. Central governments might similarly increase
- the supply of capital by devoting annual revenue to capital purposes;
- though their actual record, as it happens, is mainly of a different
- kind. But what is chiefly a possibility in the case of Governments has
- actually been carried out on an enormous scale by other institutions.
- The development of the joint-stock company system has introduced a new
- factor into the problem of the supply of capital, which is of immense
- though but dimly perceived importance. The directors of a company are
- technically no more than the servants of the shareholders. It is the
- profit of the shareholders that it is the directors' duty to promote
- with a single mind, and the whole capital of the concern, including
- its reserves both open and concealed, is the shareholders' exclusive
- property. But realities have a way of differing from forms, and just
- as in political affairs it is common to regard the State as a very
- different thing to the people who compose it, as a sublime entity with
- a separate existence of its own, so directors are apt to distinguish
- between the company and the shareholders. It is the company to which
- they owe allegiance. To pay away in dividends to shareholders money
- which they could employ in extending the business or strengthening the
- position of the company appears to some directors a necessity hardly
- less unpleasant than an increased wages bill, or an Excess Profits
- Duty. Concessions must indeed be made to the shareholders' rapacity:
- but when something has been done in this direction, dust can easily be
- thrown in their not very observant eyes. Reserves, which within
- limits are a necessity of sound finance, can be accumulated beyond
- those limits, and, when the further limits of an extreme but just
- arguable conservatism have been passed, there remain the innumerable
- devices, known to every resourceful Board, of hidden reserves, the
- secret of which is unmenaced by the meager information of a
- balance-sheet. In all this the shareholder, as the directors
- occasionally assure themselves, has no real grievance, for he will
- gain in the long run, from the appreciation in the capital value of
- his shares, all and perhaps more than all that he foregoes in the
- meantime in the way of dividends.
- In the long run the shareholder is not injured; but in the meantime he
- is in effect compelled, without any consciousness of the proceeding,
- to save and to reinvest in the company a portion of the dividends,
- which he might otherwise have spent. The reserves which are
- accumulated are not allowed to lie idle: they are employed either in
- what are really capital extensions of the business, or in the purchase
- of outside securities, and in either case they represent an increase
- in the total supply of capital. The principal which these proceedings
- represent is capable of indefinite extension.
- But however possible it might be to secure a supply of capital without
- the inducement of a rate of interest, that rate is indispensable for
- dealing with the demand. It is no good saying, "Three per cent seems
- a fair rate of interest; let us try and limit it to that." Given the
- amount of savings which are supplied, the rate of interest must be
- allowed to reach whatever figure is necessary to confine the demand to
- that amount. Given the quantity of resources which you have available
- for future needs, the meshes of the sieve must be made as narrow as is
- necessary to confine the projects that pass through within those
- limits. And so, indeed, it becomes necessary for any particular
- business to pay for its capital interest at the market rate, not so
- much to secure the saving of it as to secure its allocation from the
- common pool.
- §10. _Interest and Distribution_. It is unavoidable that this interest
- should accrue to whoever it is that supplies the capital. If the
- capital were supplied, as it might conceivably be, collectively by the
- community, the interest would accrue to the community, and all would
- be well. But as things are, the capital is supplied mainly by the
- savings of individuals, and largely by individuals confined to a
- relatively narrow class. The profits of Capital have thus a vital
- influence on the very serious matter of the distribution of wealth
- between social classes. Now, as experience shows, there is no element
- in profits which is capable of such radical change in so short a space
- of time, as is the rate of interest. Even before the war it had become
- hard for people in Great Britain to realize that 3 per cent Consols
- had stood at 114 as late as 1896. "How blest," wrote two cynical
- satirists of society in the same period:
- "How blest the prudent man, the maiden pure,
- Whose income is both ample and secure,
- Arising from Consolidated Three
- Per cent Annuities, paid quarterly."[1]
- It is impossible to read those lines now without a sense of irony,
- different from that which they were intended to convey.
- Not only is the rate of interest now double what it was a generation
- ago; we have no good reason to suppose that the present high level
- will quickly be reduced. The havoc of the war, of which the
- widespread poverty of Europe and the huge debts of Governments are but
- two different aspects, makes it almost inevitable that the rate should
- rule high in the present decade. This cannot but exercise a profound
- influence, of a most disquieting character on the general level of
- profits, and to a lesser extent (for here we must allow for the
- effects of high taxation) on the distribution of real wealth between
- social classes. Here we are on the threshold of tremendous issues. We
- almost feel the earth quake beneath our feet. We hear the muffled roar
- of far-reaching social controversy:
- "And 'mid this tumult Kubla heard from far
- Ancestral voices prophesying war."
- [Footnote 1: _Narcissus_, by Samuel Butler and Henry Festing Jones.]
- CHAPTER IX
- LABOR
- §1. _A Retrospect on Laissez-faire_. When, a century and a half ago,
- the foundations were being laid in the Western world of systematic
- economic theory, the public attention was much occupied with a
- subject, which indeed has not ceased to hold it: that of the failings
- of Governments. The general interest in that topic was shared by the
- pioneers of economic thought, of whom, in Great Britain, Adam Smith
- was the most notable. It was indeed their practical concern with the
- concrete economic issues of the day which very naturally gave the
- impetus to their scientific quest. It was hardly less natural that
- they should have expressed their opinions on these concrete issues
- with considerable emphasis.
- Now the keynote of their practical conclusions was that Governments
- were doing immense mischief by meddling with a great many matters,
- which they would have done better to leave alone. In this they were in
- general agreement with one another; incidentally--let there be no
- mistake about it--they were right. But, as invariably happens in
- public controversy, their opinions became crystallized in a compact
- formula, or cry, with unduly sweeping implications. This was the cry
- of "_laissez-faire_." Let Governments preserve law and order; and
- leave the economic sphere alone. The economists picked no quarrel with
- this formula; it served well enough for workaday purposes to indicate
- the lines of policy which they rightly thought essential in their day.
- The history of this cry is the history of every cry which has won a
- wide acceptance from mankind. It did good work for perhaps half a
- century; but then many crimes were committed in its name. The
- instrument which had been forged to clear away a noxious tariff jungle
- and the monstrous laws of Settlement, was turned against Lord
- Shaftesbury and the Factory Acts. Not only was inaction recommended
- to Governments as the highest wisdom; other institutions, like trade
- unions, were warned off the economic grass. An ideal of perfect
- competition became an idol to which much human flesh and blood were
- sacrificed.
- But, what is more to our present purpose, the idea took root of an
- intimate association between the laws of economics and the policy of
- _laissez-faire_. People who opposed some long-overdue measure of State
- regulation believed themselves to be justified by the eternal verities
- of economic law, and this claim even the advocates of the measure
- seldom ventured to dispute. They took refuge rather in a conception of
- economic law as a dangerous monster, whose claws must be clipped in
- the interests of the higher good. This notion that all interference
- with so-called "free competition," is a violation (though very likely
- fully justified) of economic laws has sunk deep into our common
- thought. So that to this day, whenever we see at work the hand of a
- State department, a trust or a trade union, we are apt to say "Demand
- and supply are here in abeyance," and possibly we add "A good thing
- too." Since in the matter of wages, the hand of the trade union is
- very generally evident, it is impossible to discuss the subject-matter
- of this chapter, until we have rid our minds of this quite baseless
- prepossession. To sweep away this cobweb, I urge the reader to recall
- here the general tenor of the analysis of the preceding
- chapters. Whether we were dealing with the price of an ordinary
- commodity, with joint products, land or capital, we came across
- relationships which seemed altogether more fundamental than our
- present industrial system; nor, we may incidentally observe, were we
- ever required to suppose that the present system was one of "perfect
- competition." These relationships were almost invariably such that
- even a world socialist commonwealth would find it necessary to
- maintain them. It was not suggested, and most certainly it must not be
- thought, that a world socialist commonwealth, or even a more modest
- remodeling of the social order would not effect great changes,
- possibly for good, and possibly for ill. The same economic laws might
- be made to bear very different fruits, but they themselves would
- remain unchanged. What is true in all these other fields--this should
- be our predisposition--is not likely to be quite untrue in the field
- of labor.
- §2. _Ideas and Institutions_. Another point is worth noting here. We
- are sometimes advised to distinguish sharply between "What should be"
- and "What is"; often two very different things. The advice is
- pertinent and useful, particularly in the sphere of sociology. But
- our incorrigible habit of confusing the two things together is not
- without justification, or at least excuse. For, in fact, they
- gravitate towards one another with a force which is just as strong as
- the capacity of man for understanding and controlling his
- environment. When we have a system which is clearly bad, _and_ when we
- see our way to make it better, we generally make the change however
- tardily. Our sense of "What should be" thus reacts upon "What is."
- Meanwhile, until we can make the system better, our appreciation of
- "What is" affects our sense of "What should be." And the more so, as
- we are sensible. For "What should be" is pre-eminently an affair of
- relativity. A man may hold very strongly that equal pay to every
- individual is desirable, as he puts it, as an ideal. But this will not
- prevent him, in a world in which managers are paid far more than
- manual workers, from maintaining hotly (at any rate, if he is
- sensible) that to pay the manager of a particular concern a manual
- worker's wage would be monstrously unfair. He would also argue that it
- would be highly inexpedient. Equity and expediency are, in fact,
- intricately intertwined in our sense of "What should be"; and our
- sense of "What should be" in the particular is governed by our
- knowledge of "What is" in the general.
- These may seem unnecessary commonplaces. But they have a vital bearing
- on the _modus operandi_ of economic laws. These laws do not work _in
- vacuo_. They work through the medium of the acts of men. The acts of
- men are greatly influenced by their institutions, and by their ideas
- of right and wrong. Both institutions and ideas may serve to smooth
- rather than obstruct the path of economic laws; because the laws may
- represent either "what should be" in the general, or "what is" in the
- general, and therefore "what should be" in the particular. This may
- hold true even of a trade union or a sense of "fair wages." The
- business of economic theory is not to justify a regime of
- _laissez-faire_, still less to show the folly of bringing morals into
- business. Its value is rather that it may help us, by improving our
- understanding, to shape our institutions, and to adopt our moral
- sentiments so as to promote the public welfare. With these general
- notions in our minds, let us turn to see how stands the case with
- Labor.
- §3. _The General Wage Level_. The term Labor may be used in a broad or
- in a narrow sense. It may be confined to weekly wage-earners: it may
- be extended to include all those who work, as the phrase goes, "with
- either hand or brain." It is with all classes of Labor, in the
- broadest sense of the term, that we must here concern ourselves. It
- will be convenient, however, in the first instance to ignore the
- differences between them, and to consider the forces which determine
- what we may regard as the general wage-level.
- The general laws of supply and demand hold good. The wages of labor
- tend to a level at which the demand is equal to the supply. For, if
- the demand exceeds the supply, if, in other words, labor is scarce,
- wages tend to rise, sooner or later in any case, and the more promptly
- in proportion as the workpeople are organized. Conversely, if the
- supply exceeds the demand, if in other Words there is general
- unemployment, wages tend to fall, and the strongest trade unions
- cannot resist the tendency, though they may delay it. Moreover, the
- higher the wages that must be paid, the smaller, other things being
- equal, is the demand for labor. For, even if we leave foreign
- competition out of account, and consider, as it were, labor throughout
- the world as a whole, the demand for labor is by no means
- inelastic. It is derived along with the demand for the other agents of
- production in the manner described in Chapter V. As was there shown,
- the greater the supply of the other agents of production, the greater
- is likely to be the demand for labor; but these other agents can be
- substituted for labor in a great variety of ways, and an increase in
- wages (unless accompanied by increased efficiency) will make it
- profitable for employers to effect such a substitution, where it was
- not profitable before. Thus, higher wages for the same labor
- efficiency must stimulate the tendency for capital to act as a
- substitute for labor at the expense necessarily (since the aggregate
- supply of capital will not be increased thereby) of its tendency to
- serve as a complement; and this must mean a decrease in the volume of
- employment. Hence the power of labor to secure a general advance of
- wages by concerted or simultaneous trade union action, applied if you
- will, not merely to every industry, but to every country, is
- necessarily very limited. Beyond a certain point, such a policy must
- result in general unemployment; and, if pushed sufficiently far, in
- unemployment so extensive that it would continue even in periods of
- active trade. Such a policy could neither be maintained in practice
- nor would it be a wise policy from the workers' point of view.
- In other words, given on the one hand the conditions of the demand for
- labor (i.e. the supply of capital, natural resources, business
- ability, risk-bearing and knowledge of technical processes, etc.,
- which happens to exist), and given on the other hand the supply of
- labor (i.e. both the numbers of workpeople and their efficiency), the
- wage-level in the long run is fairly rigidly determined. The
- introduction of the phrase "in the long run" in this connection is apt
- to provoke comment which may be pertinent, but may be misconceived.
- The worker, it is pointed out, is deeply concerned with "the short
- run" in which he has to live. It is very true; and it is this that
- supplies one of the many justifications of trade unionism. To secure
- for the workers advances of wages, which economic conditions justify,
- sooner than would otherwise have been obtained, is certainly no
- trivial or contemptible function. But it is none the less an illusion
- to suppose that the general wage-level can be appreciably and
- permanently raised by trade union action, except in so far as it
- increases the efficiency of the workers or incidentally stimulates the
- efficiency of the employers.
- §4. _The Supply of Labor in General_. The efficiency of labor may be
- regarded as affecting either the demand for labor on the one hand or
- the supply of it on the other, according as we look at the matter from
- the worker's or the employer's standpoint. The employer is concerned
- with the labor costs per unit of his output, the worker is concerned
- with the wages he receives. An increase in the efficiency of labor
- may, and usually will, mean both a decrease in labor costs to the
- employer and an increase in the earnings of the worker. It is thus
- wholly to the good. But the effects of an increase in the supply of
- labor in the sense of a growth in the numbers of the population are
- far more dubious. Unaccompanied by an increase in the _demand_ for
- labor, it _must_ result in a diminished remuneration for the
- individual worker. To some extent indeed the demand for labor would
- almost certainly be increased. The supply of Capital may expand,
- perhaps proportionately, perhaps more than proportionately to the
- increase in population. But one factor of production, as we have seen,
- is not capable of such expansion. This is the factor of Land, or
- Natural Resources. It is the limitation of this factor which gives
- rise to what we have most of us heard of as The Law of Diminishing
- Returns. It is this that is the essence of the problem of Population,
- portrayed in somber hues more than a hundred years ago by Malthus.
- This problem will form the subject of the sixth volume of the present
- series. In the meantime it may be suggested that we are easily
- credulous if we suppose that the problem has been finally disposed of
- by the peculiar progress of an abnormal century. But that experience
- has at least destroyed the view that there _need be_, or even is in
- fact in Western countries, a relation between real wages and the
- numbers of the people so close and direct that an improved standard of
- living must be temporary only, doomed to destroy itself by the
- increased population it engenders. One may perhaps go further and say
- that it is doubtful even in what direction changes in remuneration
- will influence the aggregate supply of labor. When we pass to "what
- should be," it is plain that there is nothing whatever to be said for
- the sort of relation indicated above. The view once widely held that
- the principle of population must inevitably keep the mass of people
- close to the verge of the bare means of subsistence was no statement
- of a desirable ideal. It was a nightmare; a nightmare none the less
- though it may haunt us yet. It is far from fanciful to suggest that it
- is because this relation is so obviously _not_ "what should be" that
- it may be ceasing to hold true in fact. But it would be very fanciful
- indeed to maintain that as yet "what should be" is represented by the
- actual population. Thus, just as with capital, so with labor, there is
- no reason to suppose that the aggregate supply is determined by any
- fundamental economic law, or corresponds in practice to what is
- socially desirable.
- §5. _The Apportionment of Labor among Places_. Again, as with capital,
- it is when we turn to the _apportionment_ of labor between different
- employments that both economic law and social ideal make their
- appearance. It will be well, however, to consider briefly in the
- first instance the different question of its apportionment between
- places. This was hardly necessary in the case of capital, because the
- possibilities of foreign investment are very numerous and easy: the
- mobility of capital is thus sufficiently strong (once again it is only
- _marginal_ adjustment that is necessary) to establish over at least a
- large part of the world something near to a uniform rate of
- interest. But this is not the case with labor. People do indeed move
- from place to place within a country, and from one country to another,
- in response to economic opportunities. That even the latter movement
- may be a considerable thing, the present population of the United
- States is a striking testimony. But obviously the mobility is very
- incomplete. Here, then, we have what we might _loosely_ call an
- economic law that labor tends to "flow" (as it is sometimes unhappily
- phrased) to those places where it can command the highest reward; we
- have this tendency in evidence, but it is far too weak to enable us to
- lay down what would deserve more strictly the title of an economic
- law, that in the long run the reward of the same kind of labor is
- roughly equal in all places. Perhaps we can say this for many
- districts in a single country; but for few countries is this true as
- between all their districts. As between countries, it is not remotely
- true.
- Here, however, the imperfection of economic law is balanced by an
- extreme uncertainty as to the ideal. Perfect mobility of labor may be
- _economically_ desirable in a very narrow sense of the term; but it
- opens out a vista of racial, national and cultural problems, into
- which it will be better for us not to enter here. We must take for
- granted the population of a country, like that of the world, as a
- given fact.
- When we do this, the question of its remuneration is on all fours with
- the more general question discussed above. That the remuneration of
- the labor of a country is mainly governed by the relations between
- demand and supply is an inexorable fact. In view of the international
- mobility of capital, the main distinctive factor in the demand for the
- labor of a particular country is the supply of natural resources,
- which it knows how to use. Where the natural resources are great
- relatively to the population, there wages will rule high; where the
- converse is true, wages will rule low. This result of economic
- analysis is abundantly confirmed by experience. The relatively high
- wages in the new world, the low standard of living in the densely
- populated East; the economic history of Ireland are so many
- object-lessons of its truth.
- §6. _The Apportionment of Labor among Social Grades_. The question of
- the apportionment of the labor of a country among different
- employments falls under two heads. Some differences of occupation are
- associated particularly in Great Britain with differences of what we
- know as class. The movement of labor between different social grades
- is clearly a very different thing from its movement between different
- occupations in the same grade. The grades themselves are not easy to
- define: not a little ingenuity has been expended on the attempt, and
- perhaps the best brief classification that has been put forward is one
- which divides labor into the following four grades:--
- (1) Automatic manual labor.
- (2) Responsible manual labor.
- (3) Automatic brain workers.
- (4) Responsible brain workers.
- But the matter is one perhaps for the satirist of manners rather than
- the economist. It suffices for our purpose that the distinctions,
- however vague, are very real.
- It is obvious the mobility of labor between the occupations of a
- platelayer and a barrister is not very great. It may seem perhaps to
- be even smaller than it is. For here it is important to bear in mind a
- general consideration which is equally applicable to horizontal
- movements within any social grade. There may be a considerable
- movement of labor between different employments without any individual
- worker having to change his occupation. The personnel of any industry
- is constantly changing. At one end, men die, retire, or are pensioned
- off; at the other end, young recruits are taken on. By a diversion of
- the new recruits from one employment to another, a radical change can
- be made in the occupational census in a comparatively short space of
- time. It is in this manner that such movement as takes place is
- largely effected at the present time. Within the ranks of the
- professional classes, a man does not commonly leave the profession to
- which he has been trained. But his _choice_ of profession is
- determined by him or his parents not solely on pecuniary grounds but
- usually with an anxious scanning of the general prospects, which
- include pecuniary advantages together with many other things. The same
- thing is true in no small measure of manual wage-earners. This general
- consideration must be borne in mind throughout the remainder of this
- chapter.
- But even the sons of platelayers do not commonly practise at the
- bar. The obstacles in the way are various and subtle. Many of them are
- ideas, inherited from a bygone epoch, about keeping other people "in
- their proper stations," which the whole drift of circumstance, and the
- spirit of the age are rapidly wearing down. In the new world such
- obstacles are rare. But an obstacle of a more tangible and formidable
- kind arises from the fact that the liberal professions and many
- business careers require a long and expensive education and training,
- which the platelayer is quite unable to afford to give his son.
- Now this expense of training is highly relevant not only to "what is,"
- but to "what should be." It includes, it should be observed, a
- negative as well as a positive element; a long period of waiting
- before income begins, as well as the actual outlay on educational and
- other charges. When the burden both of the waiting and the positive
- costs must be borne either by the individual or the family, there are
- few people who would seriously dispute that this goes to justify, on
- grounds of fairness as well as of expediency, a higher level of annual
- remuneration later on; though many people would doubtless argue that
- the amenities and dignities of the professions should be taken into
- account on the other side. But the same consideration makes it a
- matter of legitimate doubt whether it would be desirable, even as an
- ideal, that the community should provide so completely the costs of
- training and of maintenance in the waiting period, as to make it no
- longer "fair" that the individual should be remunerated more highly
- than workers in less expensive occupations. For this would mean that
- more labor would be absorbed in the former employments than in
- principle would be socially desirable, for reasons which the argument
- of the next chapter will make plain. But the most desirable number of
- doctors, barristers, teachers, etc., is not a thing which can be
- settled on purely economic grounds, and it is unprofitable to carry
- further this particular line of thought. Few people would advocate, as
- an ultimate ideal, that the remuneration of the professional grades of
- labor should exceed that of lower grades by _more_ than the extra
- expense of training and waiting they involve. That the excess is
- usually greater than this at the present time seems very probable:
- though it is a matter on which it is very hard to generalize. But it
- would certainly be far greater than it is if the principle of
- _laissez-faire_ ruled supreme in these affairs. Fortunately it does
- not, and has never done so. Even before the days of free elementary
- education, the endowment of education was not unknown. The ancient
- public schools and universities, which have come down to us from the
- Middle Ages, are a standing witness to what in this field a far poorer
- community thought fit to do. Their systems of scholarships and
- exhibitions, no less than their courts and towers, deserve our
- notice. For these were designed to form what we now call "a ladder" by
- which talent could climb from the humblest origins to the callings
- which then seemed the summit either of spiritual or of worldly
- ambition.
- This reference to "talent" makes it well to consider here a factor
- which necessarily complicates, though it does not substantially
- affect, the whole argument of the present chapter. There are
- differences of natural ability, which no education or training can
- obliterate, which it should rather be their business to excite. These
- differences are associated to a great extent with differences of
- occupation; they _should be_ so associated far more closely than in
- fact they are. They are also associated with differences of
- remuneration even within the same occupation; "what should be" here is
- a question which we may excuse ourselves from discussing. The
- principle which, however vague, is sufficient for our present purpose
- is that the same _natural ability_ should command the same reward in
- all occupations, subject to differences which should not exceed the
- differences of educational cost and initial waiting they involve. We
- cannot assert, as an economic law, that this is generally true in
- fact. If ever it becomes true, it will be due not to
- "_laissez-faire_," or "free competition," but to social arrangements,
- which express a sense of what is right.
- §7. _The Apportionment of Labor among Occupations_. When we pass to
- the apportionment of labor among different occupations in the same
- social grade, the same principle as to "what should be" applies in a
- simpler form. Equal natural ability should command an equal reward in
- all occupations; assuming that differences in cost of training can be
- ignored. The reward must, of course, be interpreted not in terms of
- money only but of "real wages," with allowance for the varying
- amenities of different tasks. Now it was here that the extreme
- advocates of _laissez-faire_ made one of their cardinal mistakes. They
- assumed that this ideal would be best secured by "perfect
- competition." The employer would choose the worker who would come for
- the lowest wage; the worker would choose the employer who would pay
- him the highest wage; and so, by a process similar to the higgling of
- a commodity market, the desirable uniform wage-level would become
- established. But in fact the conditions of the labor market differ
- greatly from those of a commodity market. People are ignorant, do not
- look ahead, cannot afford to risk the loss of a job, however wretched,
- which they happen to have got. For reasons such as these, a
- considerable departure from _laissez-faire_ is necessary in order to
- realize the theoretical results of _laissez-faire_. To prevent the
- putting of boys in large numbers into "blind alley" occupations, you
- must supplement the foresight of parents with Juvenile Employment
- Exchanges and After-Care Committees. To secure a proper uniformity of
- wages within the same occupation, you must have trade unions. To
- secure a proper uniformity between different occupations, you must
- have again trade unions, or, failing them, Trade Boards.
- That the actions of trade unions are very largely of this type is a
- fact insufficiently appreciated by the middle-class public. The
- elaborate system of piece-rate lists which has been evolved in the
- Lancashire cotton industry is primarily designed to secure the same
- wage for workers of equal efficiency in all mills, irrespective of the
- degree to which the machinery is antiquated or up to date. This result
- is wholly to the good: not only does it secure "fairness" for the
- worker, it stimulates the employer wonderfully to efficiency. The same
- result could never be secured so effectively by the free play of
- competition. But this tendency, which is easily the predominant
- element in the trade union regulations of the cotton trade, is at
- least an important element in the policy of "The Common Rule" of all
- trade unions, though it may often be mixed up with the more
- questionable tendency to eliminate differences of pay for differences
- of natural ability, and the unquestionably bad tendency to discourage
- output. As between different occupations, the insistence of a trade
- union that wages must be leveled up towards the wages obtaining in
- similar trades acts again as a far more powerful force than
- competition.
- But the actions of trade unions are by no means wholly of this
- type. They often serve rather to secure still higher wages for workers
- who, comparatively speaking, are already highly paid. It makes little
- difference whether this effect is secured directly by wage demands, or
- indirectly by restricting the right of the entry to the trade. In
- either case the consequences are the same, and there should be no
- ambiguity as to their nature. They are certainly bad for the
- community, certainly bad for the _other_ workers of the grade, almost
- certainly bad for the workers of the grade regarded as a whole. The
- higher wages must raise the money costs of production, and result,
- sooner or later, in fewer workpeople being employed in that
- occupation; larger numbers must accordingly seek employment elsewhere;
- and this cannot but depress the wage rates of less strongly organized
- trades. Thus the effect is twofold: a larger proportion of workpeople
- will be employed in badly paid occupations; and the wages there will
- be lessened.
- The power of a strong trade union to secure wage advances of this type
- is considerable, but it must not be exaggerated. Trade unions employ
- as a matter of course devices which, in the case of trusts, we regard
- as the extremest weapons of monopoly. To say, "If you buy from anyone
- except us, you must not buy at a lower price than ours," which
- Messrs. J. & P. Coats are represented as having done, is analogous to
- insisting that if non-unionists are employed, it shall be at the trade
- union rate, as every trade union very properly insists. To say, "You
- must buy _only_ from us," the method of the boycott, as it is called,
- is analogous to the very common refusal to work with non-unionists at
- all. But in one important respect the tactical position of a trade
- union is weaker than that of an ordinary combination. It has usually
- got a buyers' combination up against it, in the shape of an
- association of employers. The latter will be governed in their
- attitude towards the workpeople's demands, not only by immediate
- expediency, but also by their own sense of "what should be"; and they
- will usually resist demands for wages greatly in excess of those
- obtaining in comparable trades. In this way, the tendency for workers
- of the same efficiency to receive the same real wages in all
- employments is far stronger than might at first sight appear.
- If we had to rely for this result upon trade unions alone, it would be
- highly problematical. For here a psychological curiosity emerges,
- which, familiar and intelligible as it is, is none the less a
- curiosity. So far from still higher wages for well-paid workpeople
- being regarded in the world of manual labor as detrimental to the
- interests of other workpeople, it has become almost a point of honor
- to believe the contrary. A wage dispute in a particular trade is
- conceived as an engagement in a far-flung battle between Capital and
- Labor, in which success at any part of the line will facilitate the
- victory of the whole army. This conception contains a measure of
- truth, as regards immediate and purely temporary effects; though, even
- here, it is made to seem unduly plausible by the recurrence of trade
- cycles, which cause wages at any time to move in the same direction
- all along the line. But, if the foregoing analysis has been
- appreciated, the essential falsity of this notion should be evident.
- It is an illusion, which should receive no endorsement, either tacit
- or express, in any work on economics. The general wage level of a
- country cannot be regarded (except temporarily, and within narrow
- limits) as a function of the efficiency of labor organization; it
- depends on the far deeper economic facts set out in §3 above.
- Let us now try to summarize the conclusions of this section. There
- _is_ a tendency towards a uniformity of real wages for workers of the
- same grade and of the same efficiency. This tendency is not due to
- competition alone. It is helped by many acts of a collective kind,
- arising from a sense of "what should be"; it is obstructed by other
- acts of a like kind, where the sense of "what should be" is based on
- imperfect understanding. The more people act in accordance with "what
- should be," and the better their understanding, the more will this
- tendency approximate to an accurate economic law.
- §8. _Women's Wages_. The wages of women represent a problem of great
- public interest, upon which the principles laid down in this chapter
- have a most important bearing, and which in its turn serves to
- illustrate these principles further. It has been suggested that male
- and female labor can be regarded as a strong case of Joint Supply, and
- the suggestion is not merely facetious. The essential point, that the
- proportions of available male and female labor are fairly constant
- (not that they may not alter with time and circumstances, but that
- they are essentially independent of the conditions of demand) holds
- true not only of a country as a whole, but hardly less of a particular
- district. If men and women are to be regarded as separate grades, they
- are grades between which immobility is complete. Now men and women
- differ in many ways which affect both the demand for and the supply of
- their services. On the one hand, far fewer women wish to enter
- business employments of any kind, as women have plenty of work that
- must be done at home. On the other hand, though women can do many
- kinds of work as well as or better than men, it so happens that for
- much the greater number of services, which are in large demand in the
- business world, men are the more efficient. Incidentally, it happens
- that many occupations which women _might_ do as well as men are closed
- to them by exclusive regulations. The resultant of these forces is
- that men and women are for the most part employed in different
- occupations, and the scale of payment in women's occupations is far
- lower than that in men's. Of this last fact singularly small
- complaint is made.
- It is otherwise, however, when we come to occupations where men are
- either wholly or partially employed, where women are at least
- approximately as efficient as men, and where the barriers to their
- entry are at least formally removed. There a ferocious controversy
- rages over what is known as the principle of "equal pay for equal
- work." It is easy to understand why the male trade unionists in, let
- us say, the engineering trades, should support this claim. It is also,
- indeed, _intelligible_ why the enthusiasts for Women's Rights should
- urge it; but it is much more doubtful whether they are wise. Possibly
- they are wise enough in their generation, since it might not serve
- them on this matter to get across the men. But it is clearly not
- prudential considerations of this kind by which they are mainly
- actuated. They make the demand, with extreme intensity of feeling, as
- a demand for fundamental justice. They are also very obviously
- inspired with the belief (similar to the illusion which is a point of
- honor with the male trade unionist) that high wages for women in
- well-paid occupations will help to raise the wages of sweated women
- workers in other trades.
- Now, here again, any lack of candor would be inexcusable. The effect
- of this policy on the wages in women's trades is certainly to reduce
- them. The policy serves, as powerfully as any trade union custom, to
- restrict the entry of women into the men's employments, and often
- spells virtual exclusion. For the "equal efficiency" may be
- approximate only, and there may be advantages in male labor from the
- employer's standpoint which are none the less important, because they
- are not easy to define. Moreover, from the employer's standpoint, the
- efficacy of female labor will be largely a matter for _experiment_,
- and "equal pay" will give him no inducement to experiment at all. The
- diminished number of women in these occupations (as compared with what
- might have been) increases the number who must fall back on the purely
- women's trades; and it _must_ serve to reduce the wages there, where
- organization is by no means strong. I am far from asserting that this
- consideration is conclusive against the principle of "equal pay for
- equal work" (though I think it conclusive against a rigid
- interpretation of it); for other matters, such as the standpoint of
- the male trade unionist must be taken into account. But the reactions
- on the wages in women's trades permit of no ambiguity.
- In occupations of another type, the issue takes a somewhat different
- form. In the teaching profession, "equal pay" would not exclude the
- women; it would be far more likely to exclude the men. For, though the
- advocates of the principle would declare that their intention is that
- the salaries of women should be leveled up to those of men, it is more
- probable that the ultimate outcome would be a leveling down.
- Educational authorities have the ratepayer and the taxpayer to
- consider; and, apart from this, they have their own interpretation of
- "what should be." To pay a woman less than a man for the same work may
- seem glaringly unfair; but it is not very clear why a woman, who is an
- elementary school teacher, should be paid much more than, say, a
- hospital nurse, merely because in the former case a number of men
- happen also to be employed. In fact, there is a clashing of equities
- in this connection; and there is little doubt which of them the
- educational authorities would prefer. A leveling down of the men's
- salaries would make it all but impossible to attract men of the
- desired type into the profession, and would thus lead to the virtual
- extinction of the male elementary school teacher. This might seem in a
- narrow sense to be economically desirable. Why should not men take
- their services to the tasks for which they can command a higher
- reward, and which women cannot do as well? But whether this would be
- desirable in the true interests of education is a far more doubtful
- matter. And this is the real problem of "equal pay for equal work" for
- male and female school teachers. The reader will notice that I have
- refrained from alluding to the controversy as to whether men should
- receive more on the grounds that they have wives and families to
- maintain. That, although a most absorbing issue, is not the real issue
- in practice at the present time. The real issue is a clashing between
- a sense of "what should be" on obvious general grounds and a sense of
- "what should be" in the particular, derived from the very patent and
- general "what is" that men receive as a rule far higher pay than
- women.
- CHAPTER X
- THE REAL COSTS OF PRODUCTION
- §1. _Comparative Costs_. Beneath the great diversity of the
- considerations which are applicable to the different agents of
- production, certain general conclusions emerge from the analysis of
- the last four chapters. In no case did we find that the aggregate
- supply of the agent was determined by clear and certain economic laws,
- possessing any fundamental significance. The supply of natural
- resources is a fixed thing, quite independent of the efforts or the
- desires of man. However the supply of capital and the supply of labor
- may react under present conditions towards economic stimuli, these
- reactions possess no quality of inevitability and bear no clear
- relation to "what should be." The supply of risk-bearing responds
- perhaps more decidedly to the prospects of increased reward; but it is
- so intimately associated with special knowledge and the qualities of
- business enterprise, as to leave some uncertainty attaching even to
- this conclusion. When, on the other hand, we turn to the
- apportionment of these factors among different uses, we find relations
- which are both clear and fundamental. Laws emerge which state at once
- not only "what is" or at least "what tends to be," but also "what
- should be"; and it is the fact that they taste "what should be" that
- gives them their fundamental character.
- These conclusions enable us to give a general answer to the question
- which was raised at the end of Chapter V: What are the ultimate real
- costs to which the money cost of production correspond? The attempt
- has often been made to relate money costs to such things as the effort
- of working and the sacrifice of waiting. The existence of such costs
- is beyond dispute. Much saving does mean a sacrifice of immediate
- enjoyment to the man who saves. Most labor is irksome and disagreeable
- in itself, and involves strain and wear and tear; while all labor
- means a deprivation of the utility of leisure. Workpeople, moreover,
- do not grow on gooseberry bushes, but must be fed and clothed from the
- cradle; and their rearing and maintenance represents a real cost which
- someone must incur.
- But the existence (or the importance) of such costs is one thing,
- their relation to money costs is another. In Chapter VIII we saw how
- difficult it was to establish any clear relation between the rate of
- interest and the sacrifice of saving. The costs of labor present
- similar difficulties. The relative irksomeness of two occupations may
- affect the relative wages which will rule in the two cases; so,
- certainly, will the differences in the cost of education and training
- which they require. But these are matters which concern the
- _apportionment_ of labor between different employments. There is no
- good reason to suppose that the general wage-level would be reduced,
- merely because work as a whole became less irksome, or involved a
- smaller physical or mental strain. The supply of people is not
- determined by the same kind of influences as is the supply of a
- commodity. Parents do not produce children for the sake of the wages
- which the children will receive when they go out to work; or, if this
- happens, we rightly regard it as a horrible anomaly. In so far as
- parents are affected by economic conditions it is by their own
- economic conditions; the question is rather one of how many children
- they can afford to have, than of a balancing of the cost to them
- against the incomes which their children may subsequently acquire. But
- other considerations enter in; and, in fact, it is doubtful how the
- aggregate supply of labor will react to changes in prosperity.
- Finally, the supply of land involves neither effort nor sacrifice;
- and, among our money costs, we have to account for the item
- of the rent of land. To dispose of this difficulty by arguing that
- rent does not enter into marginal costs (in any sense which is not
- equally true of wages and profits) is to lose contact with
- reality. Thus the attempt to explain money costs in terms of the costs
- of producing the ultimate agents of production leads us into a
- quagmire of unreality and dubious hypothesis. For a systematic theory,
- which will rest on firm foundations, we must interpret money costs in
- very different terms.
- The real costs which the price of a commodity measures are not
- absolute, but comparative. Marginal money costs reduce themselves in
- the last analysis to the payments which must be made to secure the use
- of the requisite agents of productions. These payments _tend_ to equal
- the payments which the same agents could have commanded in alternative
- employments. The payments which they could have commanded in
- alternative employments, tend in their turn to equal the derived
- marginal utilities of their services in those employments. It is thus
- the loss of _Utility_ which arises from the fact that these agents of
- production are not available for alternative employments that is
- measured by the money costs of a commodity at the margin of
- production.
- This conception of ultimate costs encounters an instinctive
- repugnance, arising from a mistaken sense of logical symmetry, which
- it will be well to examine. Cost, it is objected, so interpreted
- loses its character as an independent entity. It is merely something
- derived from utility. Now in the earlier chapters of this volume, we
- found reason to be impressed with the general symmetry which pervades
- the relations of demand and supply. Moreover, when we considered the
- case of ordinary commodities we found that at the back of demand and
- giving rise to it was utility; at the back of supply, and limiting it,
- was cost. The general symmetry between demand and supply thus seemed
- almost to imply a fundamental symmetry between utility and cost. If,
- then, cost in the last analysis is derived from utility, does not this
- make nonsense of the symmetry between demand and supply, or, if we
- cling to this last symmetry as a demonstrable truth, must we not
- refuse to admit that cost can be derived from utility?
- This is one of those false dilemmas which supply the wiseacres of the
- world with a plausible case for distrusting the logical faculty. If we
- have good reason for believing that both of two apparently
- inconsistent things are true, the explanation is seldom that one of
- them is really false; it is more usually that they are not really
- inconsistent. So it is here. The symmetry between demand and supply is
- very great, and we should always look to see if it holds good, but it
- is by no means perfect, and it is in the last analysis that it most
- notably fails. It is most important to distinguish clearly between the
- utility and the cost of a commodity as two separate and independent
- things. In Chapter V, it will be remembered, we did not permit
- ourselves to derive the costs of producing cotton lint from the
- utility of cotton-seed. The refusal to do so was essential to clear
- thought; it led to some very useful practical corollaries. But to
- derive the cost of a commodity from the utility of something which is
- produced _with_ it, as part of the same productive process; and to
- derive the cost from the utilities which the agents, which help to
- produce it, possess for other purposes, are two entirely different
- things. In works on International Trade, the reader will discover that
- the comparative nature of real costs is so unmistakable that a
- Doctrine of Comparative Costs is expounded with much formality at the
- outset. This doctrine is apt to prove somewhat puzzling, when we have
- to deal with it as an apparent exception to the general tenor of
- economic theory. Its difficulties disappear when we realize clearly
- that the real cost of _anything_ is the curtailment of the supply of
- other useful things, which the production of that particular thing
- entails.
- §2. _The Allocation of Resources_. However strange the above
- conception may seem, there should be no doubt that this cost is very
- "real." Here the irregularities and maladjustments of the economic
- world, the recurrence of trade depressions and the like, do much to
- obscure a clear vision of the essential realities. At a time when
- there is much unemployment, and much machinery standing idle, it is so
- clear to common sense that we _could_ produce more of some particular
- thing without diminishing the supply of other things, that any
- apparent statement to the contrary may perhaps seem the height of
- academic pedantry. But let me ask the reader to consider with an open
- mind a familiar parallel. During the recent war there was inevitably
- much waste and muddle in the utilization of the military resources of
- the Allies. Some regiments would be kept inactive for long periods,
- not for purposes of rest or training, but owing to some defect of
- organization. In the manufacture of munitions, an insufficient
- appreciation of the principles of joint demand led to the piling up of
- excessive stores of certain materials, which were useless until
- commensurate supplies of the complementary factors could be
- obtained. It is unnecessary to multiply examples. The waste of both
- man-power and material was immense. But the allocation of these
- resources between, for instance, the various theaters of war was none
- the less a very real problem, which gave rise to much engrossing
- controversy. It was an axiom that the more resources you employed in
- Mesopotamia or in Palestine, the less resources remained available for
- France. No one thought of maintaining that, as long as there was any
- waste of these resources, so long as there remained any men to be
- "combed out" of unessential industries, you could pour troops and
- munitions into Salonika without stopping to consider the needs of
- other theaters of war. Such a notion would have been clearly imbecile,
- for the sufficient reason that the sending of armies to Salonika would
- do nothing in itself to secure (however much it might incidentally
- stimulate) the more efficient use of the resources which remained.
- Now this is precisely analogous to the problem of the allocation of
- our resources for the purpose of peace. Notwithstanding all the
- wastes and maladjustments of the economic system, the use of resources
- to produce one commodity _does_ in general curtail the production of
- others. The mere launching of a new business enterprise does no more
- than the sending of an army to Salonika, to eliminate waste in the
- remainder of the economic organism. Unemployment, broadly speaking, is
- a function not of the magnitude of the normal demand for labor (which
- affects rather the wage-level), but of fluctuations in the demand for
- labor; fluctuations from one day to another as at the docks, from one
- season to another as in the building trades, above all from one period
- of years to another as in the cycles of general trade boom and
- depression. Nothing will diminish unemployment which does not serve to
- diminish these fluctuations. A new business will not, as a rule, have
- any such effect. If it is launched during a trade depression (a most
- unusual proceeding), it may temporarily absorb unemployed labor and
- idle materials. But when the next boom comes, it will be using, though
- presumably to greater advantage, labor and materials which, but for
- it, would have been employed for other purposes. Meanwhile the causes
- making for unemployment will be unaffected. Miscalculations will
- still be made, the building trades will still become slack in the
- winter, the casual methods of engaging dock laborers will still
- continue, trade cycles will still recur, while beneath them, and
- concealed by them, some industries will expand and others will decay.
- Thus, like the armies at Salonika, the new business would in effect
- divert resources from elsewhere.
- This truth needs to be firmly grasped in mind. It is this that makes
- it in general unsound policy to subsidize industries, either directly
- or indirectly, by means of a protective tariff. It is this, indeed,
- that supplies the answer to half the economic fallacies that are
- always current.
- The allocation of resources so as to yield the maximum effect was
- rightly recognized as one of the most vital and difficult of our
- war-time problems. To cope with it, the Allied peoples devised one
- instrument after another, and finally evolved the Supreme Allied
- Council. The analogous problem in the economic world of peace time is
- no less important and far more difficult; but there is nothing to
- correspond to the Supreme Allied Council. There we rely upon a
- co-operation which, as was stressed in Chapter I, is unco-ordinated.
- That co-operation has been evolved by the mutual competition
- of innumerable business concerns, controlled by men largely
- animated by the motive of pecuniary profit. But it has not
- been evolved wholly by such means: and how far that competition or
- that motive of profit is essential to its efficiency are questions
- with which this volume has not been in any way concerned. The economic
- laws, the relations between utility, and price and cost, with which it
- has been occupied, are an entirely different matter; and these _are_
- essential to the efficiency of any system of society. For if the
- marginal utility of a commodity is equal to its marginal cost, and if
- this marginal cost is composed of payments to the various agents of
- production at least as great as they could have obtained if they had
- been used otherwise, this amounts to saying that the agents of
- production are so utilized as to yield the maximum utility; and this
- is the same thing as saying that they are so utilized as to produce
- the maximum wealth.
- §3. _Utility and Wealth_. Upon this last point it is important to be
- quite clear. An increase in wealth seems a solid, tangible reality;
- something, which, however much we may scorn it in our more precious
- moods, we recognize, for a rather poor community, to be an important
- object of endeavor. But an increase in utility seems a vague,
- impalpable notion, hardly deserving the same practical concern. None
- the less the two things are identical. We greatly deceive ourselves if
- we suppose wealth to be an objective reality. It is true that, when
- we get behind the money in which it is measured, we come upon
- commodities, like food and clothes and houses and factories, which
- seem comfortably solid and objective things; but we also come upon
- many services, like those of gardeners and doctors and hospital
- nurses, which we are bound to reckon as part of our wealth, although
- they are not embodied in any tangible commodities. Moreover, although
- material commodities are objective realities in themselves, and in
- many of their properties, they are _not_ objective realities in their
- property as wealth. A pair of boots is an objective fact; so is the
- number of pairs in existence at any time, so is their size, their
- weight, the quantity of leather or of paper which they happen to
- contain. But the wealth which those boots represent is not an
- objective fact. It depends upon the opinion which men and women
- entertain as to their utility; and these opinions take us into the
- subjective regions of human psychology. Let us suppose, for instance,
- that we calculated, on the basis of present prices, that the boots in
- existence at the present time represented 1/1000 part of our total
- wealth. Suppose, then, that a miracle were to happen; that the skies
- opened and rained boots upon us, of every size and shape and pattern,
- until we had 1000 times as many boots as we had before. Could we say
- that our total real wealth had been doubled? Clearly we could not. To
- obtain boots for nothing, and to wear a new pair every week, would
- make us somewhat better off, but not twice as well off as we were
- previously. In other words, the real wealth of a thousand times as
- many boots as we have now, is not a thousand times as great as the
- wealth of the present number of boots. We are, indeed, practically
- restating the Law of Diminishing Utility; and this perhaps is enough
- to show that wealth is fundamentally the same thing as utility.
- Another point, however, is worth noting. Our real wealth would be
- somewhat increased in the case supposed; but if we were to turn to the
- money measure of wealth, the opposite result would be far more likely,
- For the price of boots would most likely fall to nothing, and the
- total value of boots, in the commercial sense, would accordingly be
- nothing also. This shows that money values may be a most imperfect
- measure of aggregate wealth; for what money values represent is the
- product of the quantity of the commodity and its _marginal_ utility,
- while aggregate wealth is _total_ utility, which is a very different
- thing. This, it may be observed, makes all attempts to compare the
- wealth of different countries or different times, and no less to
- construct Index Numbers of Prices, imperfect of necessity, and
- arbitrary in their foundations.
- §4. _Criteria of Policy_. The point has now been reached at which we
- must take into account the very important fact which was mentioned at
- the close of Chapter III. The maximum utility which the laws of
- supply and demand tend to bring about is a maximum _total_ utility
- indeed, but one still measured in terms of money. An unequal
- distribution of wealth destroys any necessary correspondence between
- that and the maximum _real_ utility. This consideration, however, does
- not affect the general validity of the conclusion that the laws of
- supply and demand represent what is socially desirable now or under
- any system. For what is at fault here is the distribution of wealth;
- and it is that which should be changed, in so far as it is possible to
- do so. Now it is important to realize that whenever it is possible to
- supply a commodity to poor people below cost price, it is possible to
- alter the distribution of wealth, for that in effect is what is
- done. Purchasing power, which may be taken from richer people by
- taxation, or which may be obtained from "collective" profits on other
- trading, is in effect transferred to the poor people in question,
- though the transference is coupled with the condition that the
- purchasing power must be expended in a particular way. It is _in
- general_ desirable that the transference should be made without this
- condition being attached. To this general statement, exceptions indeed
- exist so numerous and important as possibly to justify a great
- extension of social expenditure of this type. Education should
- certainly be provided free of charge, there are strong arguments for
- subsidizing housing; the provision of milk to expectant mothers, the
- feeding of school children, such instances can be multiplied into a
- very extensive list. But it is important to observe that in each case
- the justification of the policy rests in the presumption that the
- service supplied is one which it is particularly important that the
- beneficiaries should have, _as compared with_ the other things upon
- which they might have preferred to expend the equivalent purchasing
- power, had it been transferred to them without conditions. Where there
- is no such presumption, as surely there is none in the case of the
- great bulk of commodities, the relation between price and marginal
- cost should be rigidly maintained; it is the distribution of
- purchasing power which we should rather seek to alter. How far is it
- possible to alter that?
- I suppose that it is inevitable that many readers will have concluded
- that the preceding chapters must be taken to mean that the
- distribution of wealth is not susceptible of any appreciable change. I
- would remind those readers of an important distinction upon which
- impatient people have sometimes based a complaint against
- economists. The economist, it is said, analyses with great pomp and
- ceremony the laws governing the distribution of wealth among the
- agents of production, but says practically nothing about the
- distribution between individuals and classes, which is the only thing
- of any real interest to practical people. Now the economist
- concentrates on the agents of production for the very good reason that
- it is only with respect to them that any clear and certain laws as to
- distribution can be laid down. Into the distribution between
- individuals and classes there enter other and variable factors,
- governed by no fundamental economic law; and _here_, the conclusion
- should at once suggest itself, is the field for action designed to
- alter the distribution of wealth. What is possible or desirable in
- this field, it is again not the purpose of this volume to discuss. It
- is an obvious, even if not a very helpful conclusion that an increase
- in the habit of saving among weekly wage-earners might, without
- appreciably affecting the distribution between Capital and Labor,
- greatly modify the resulting distribution between social classes. But
- questions as to how far it might be possible or justifiable to achieve
- a similar result by the use of the weapon of taxation, by changes in
- inheritance laws, or by the public ownership of industry take us into
- a far more uncertain and controversial sphere. The difficulties and
- objections which present themselves are familiar and formidable; but
- they are of quite a different order from the economic laws which we
- have been examining. The laws themselves do not entitle us to make any
- dogmatic pronouncement upon these large issues of social policy.
- But this is not to deprive these laws of practical importance. They
- represent essential criteria of sound policy in the sphere of social
- reorganization no less than in ordinary business. In our days a
- curious obsession has led many people to disparage these criteria, as
- though they were the sordid prejudices of a stupid tradesman. Because
- it has been found a matter of obvious practical convenience to
- maintain the roads out of taxation or of rates, and to dispense with
- charges for their use, it is suggested that the same principle should
- be applied to the railways. Or, more commonly, because it has been
- found convenient to make the same charge for the carrying of letters
- between Land's End and John o' Groats as between Hampstead and
- Highgate, it is suggested that _this_ principle should be applied to
- railway rates and fares. It may be well, therefore, to point out that
- the justification of uniform postal charges rests upon the facts: (1)
- that the costs of collection, sorting, etc., are so large a part of
- the costs of carrying a letter, that the real cost between John o'
- Groats and Land's End does not differ from that between Hampstead and
- Highgate by as much as might at first sight appear, (2) that the
- charges in any case are very small; so that (3) the avoidance of the
- small degree of taxes and bounties which the present system implies is
- not worth the book-keeping expenses which differential charges would
- involve. It should be obvious that these considerations apply to the
- railways with a greatly diminished force. They might possibly justify
- what is known as the "zone" system of charges, i.e. uniform rates
- within certain narrow areas. But the notion of uniform rates
- throughout Great Britain conjures up a vision of trains taking coal
- from South Wales to Scotland, and others taking coal from Scotland to
- South Wales, in accordance with the slightest preferences of the
- consumers, and without regard to the extra real cost involved, on a
- scale to which the "wastes of competition" afford no parallel. It
- would in fact achieve the essential folly of "sending coals to
- Newcastle." These considerations, however, are not what interest the
- advocates of the postal principle. They seem to recommend the
- obliteration or the confusion of the relations between price and cost
- as a superior ideal. It is important to be clear what exactly this
- ideal involves.
- It involves, in the first place, as the whole argument of this volume
- has gone to show, a less economical employment of our productive
- resources; they would be diverted to ends of less utility, and so
- produce less real wealth. But this is not the worst. There is plenty
- of waste and maladjustment in our economic system at the present
- time. The desirable relation of price to marginal cost is but
- imperfectly attained. The further departures from this relation, which
- would follow from any likely applications of the postal principle,
- might not matter in themselves so very much. What is far more serious
- is that the criteria of efficiency would become blunted, and the clear
- aims of management would be confused in fog. It is essential that
- every manager should be on the alert to eliminate waste and to improve
- efficiency, that he should be always trying to secure the best
- results; but how can he do this if he has no simple means of
- _measuring_ what results are good and what are bad? The measure which
- he has at present is that of price, cost and the resultant profit, and
- it would be fatal to take that away, unless an equally simple and more
- accurate measure could be substituted for it.
- This is not a question, it should be observed, of motive or
- incentive. Very likely we much exaggerate the importance of the profit
- motive. It may be true that men would work, perhaps that they already
- work in fact, as zealously for a fixed salary, as for personal
- gain. But aim and motive are two somewhat different things, and the
- _aim_ of profit, is, and will remain, essential to the efficient
- conduct of business. In a game the players are not animated by the
- motive of scoring runs or points, but they aim at them; and the zest
- disappears very speedily from the game, if that aim ceases to be of
- interest. Moreover, while a scoring system is always a somewhat
- arbitrary thing, measuring imperfectly the true merits of the play, if
- it measures them with the roughest accuracy, we prefer the issue of
- our games to be decided so, rather than by the decisions of an
- impartial judge, who can take into account the finest points of
- skill. So it is in the world of business. The scoring-board of profits
- may be an imperfect one; let us, by all means, where we can, alter the
- rules of the game so as to make it better. But let us not imagine that
- it displays a finer insight or a superior intellect to speak as though
- the scoring-board could be dispensed with, and the test of profit and
- loss treated as irrelevant. Quantitative measurement is essential to
- efficiency. Let us be careful to remember all that this implies.
- INDEX
- Ability
- Accountancy
- Allocation of resources
- Ambiguities
- Australasia
- Bastiat, Frederic
- Beef and hides
- Borrowing and lending, system of
- Business efficiency
- Business man as a purchaser
- Business risk
- Capital;
- as representing a period of waiting;
- distribution;
- distribution and rate of interest;
- effect on labor of an increased supply;
- not a stock of consumable goods;
- reaction of price charges on;
- reflections upon;
- supply;
- supply as affected by charges in interest rate
- Capital goods
- Capital market
- Capitalism
- Capitalist
- Chance
- Coal industry, cost of production and price;
- miners' wages
- Coats, J. & P.
- Collective saving
- Commodities;
- labor as a commodity
- Competition
- Composite demand
- Composite supply
- Consumable goods
- Consumers' goods and producers' goods
- Consumption, margin of;
- waiting for
- Control and risk-taking
- Controversy
- Coöperation;
- unorganized
- Cost, general relation of price, utility and cost;
- price relation to;
- rent as factor in real costs;
- ultimate;
- utility and
- Cotton and cotton-seed;
- contrast to wool and mutton
- Cotton industry
- Criteria of policy
- Currency inflation
- Cycles
- Demand, ambiguity of expression "increase in demand,";
- derived;
- elastic and inelastic;
- _see also_ Composite demand; Joint demand; Supply and demand
- Derived demand
- Derived utility
- Diagrams, use of
- Diminishing utility;
- money and
- Directors
- Distribution of wealth;
- interest rate and
- Dividends
- Division of labor
- Economic laws;
- fundamental character
- Economic theory;
- fact and
- Economic world, orderly nature
- Education
- Efficiency
- Elastic demand
- Employers' associations
- Enterprise
- Entrepreneur
- "Equal pay for equal work,"
- Expectation
- Fact and theory
- Farmers
- Fortunes
- Gambling
- Government, enterprises;
- failings
- Hides and beef
- Houses
- Housewife as purchaser
- Housing
- Ideas and institutions
- Incompetents
- Increase in demand, ambiguity
- Index numbers
- Inelastic demand
- Inflation
- Institutions and ideas
- Insurance companies;
- significance
- Interest;
- necessity of
- Interest rate;
- changes and their effect on supply of capital;
- distribution and;
- price of land and
- Intuition
- Joint demand;
- importance of the unimportant;
- marginal utility under;
- summary of considerations
- Joint products;
- cost of production
- Joint-stock company
- Joint supply, marginal cost under;
- summary of considerations
- Keynes, J. M.
- Labor;
- apportionment among occupations;
- apportionment among places;
- apportionment among social grades;
- as a commodity;
- cost, difficulty of estimating;
- division;
- effect of increased supply of capital;
- four grades;
- mobility;
- product of;
- reaction of price changes on;
- supply in general
- _Laissez-faire_;
- retrospect on
- Land, characteristics;
- differential aspect;
- margin of transference;
- marginal;
- price and rent, relation;
- question of real costs;
- scarcity aspect;
- supply;
- tenure;
- urban;
- _see also_ Rent
- Landlords
- Large scale business
- Laws, fundamental
- Malthus, T.R.
- Management
- Margin, danger of ignoring
- Margin of consumption
- Margin of production
- Margin of transference
- Marginal cost, aspects;
- misinterpretation;
- under joint supply
- Marginal land
- Marginal purchaser
- Marginal utility;
- price relation to;
- under joint demand
- Market
- Marshall, Alfred
- Marx, Karl
- Mill, J. S.
- Miners
- Monetary changes, disturbances of
- Money, diminishing utility
- Monte Carlo
- Mutton. _See_ Wool and Mutton
- Natural ability
- Normal conditions
- Occupations;
- apportionment of labor among
- Order, economic
- Pasture versus tillage
- Pigou, A. C.
- Policy, criteria
- Population
- Postal charges
- Poverty;
- national
- Price, consequences of higher;
- general relation with utility and cost;
- law of tendency;
- marginal utility and;
- post-war;
- reaction of changes in demand and supply;
- relation of demand and supply to;
- utility and
- Producers' goods
- Production, power of;
- real costs;
- waiting for
- Professions
- Profiteering
- Profits;
- elements;
- general analysis;
- in risky industries
- Protective tariff
- Psychology and economics
- Purchasers, business man;
- housewife;
- marginal
- Purchasing power
- Railway rates
- Railways
- Rate of interest. _See_ Interest rate
- Rent;
- complex character;
- marginal land;
- necessity;
- rate of interest and
- Reserves
- Residuary profits
- Resources, allocation
- Risk, reward for;
- under large-scale organization
- Satisfaction
- Saving;
- individual;
- involuntary;
- psychology;
- social
- School teachers
- Service
- Serving cotton
- Shareholders
- Sinking-fund
- Situation
- Smith, Adam
- Social grades, labor movement among
- Socialism
- Speculation
- Steel smelters
- Subsidies, industrial
- Substitutes
- Supply, reactions of price changes on;
- _see also_ Composite supply; Joint supply
- Supply and demand, changes in, and their reaction on price;
- forces behind;
- general laws;
- relation of price to;
- wages and
- Supreme Allied Council
- Teachers
- Theory, economic
- Thrift
- Tillage versus pasture
- Trade cycles
- Trade depression
- Trade unions;
- actions;
- wage level and
- Ultimate real costs
- Unearned increment
- Unemployment;
- trade union policy and
- Utility;
- cost and;
- derived;
- general relation of price, utility and cost;
- law of diminishing utility;
- law of diminishing utility as applied to money;
- marginal;
- price relation to;
- wealth and
- Wages, general wage level;
- trade unions and;
- women's
- Wages Fund
- Waiting, essence of;
- for consumption;
- for production
- Waste, economic
- Wealth, distribution;
- utility and
- "What should be" and "What is,"
- Women's wages
- Wool and mutton;
- contrast to cotton and cotton-seed
- Workers' control
- End of Project Gutenberg's Supply and Demand, by Hubert D. Henderson
- *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK SUPPLY AND DEMAND ***
- ***** This file should be named 10612-8.txt or 10612-8.zip *****
- This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
- http://www.gutenberg.net/1/0/6/1/10612/
- Produced by Josh Cogliati and PG Distributed Proofreaders
- Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
- will be renamed.
- Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
- one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
- (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
- permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
- set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
- copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
- protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
- Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
- charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
- do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
- rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
- such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
- research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
- practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
- subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
- redistribution.
- *** START: FULL LICENSE ***
- THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
- PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
- To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
- distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
- (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
- Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
- http://gutenberg.net/license).
- Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic works
- 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
- and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
- (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
- the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
- all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
- If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
- terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
- entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
- 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
- used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
- agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
- things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
- even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
- paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
- and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works. See paragraph 1.E below.
- 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
- or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
- collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
- individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
- located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
- copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
- works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
- are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
- Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
- freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
- this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
- the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
- keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
- Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
- 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
- what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
- a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
- the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
- before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
- creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
- Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
- the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
- States.
- 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
- 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
- access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
- whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
- phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
- copied or distributed:
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
- almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
- re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
- with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
- 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
- from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
- posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
- and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
- or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
- with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
- work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
- through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
- Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
- 1.E.9.
- 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
- with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
- must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
- terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
- to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
- permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
- 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
- work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
- 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
- electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
- prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
- active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm License.
- 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
- compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
- word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
- distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
- "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
- posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.net),
- you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
- copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
- request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
- form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
- 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
- performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
- unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
- access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
- that
- - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
- the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
- you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
- owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
- has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
- Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
- must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
- prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
- returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
- sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
- address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
- the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
- - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
- you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
- does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License. You must require such a user to return or
- destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
- and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
- Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
- money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
- electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
- of receipt of the work.
- - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
- distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
- forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
- both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
- Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
- Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
- 1.F.
- 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
- effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
- public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
- collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
- "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
- corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
- property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
- computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
- your equipment.
- 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
- of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
- liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
- fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
- LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
- PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
- TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
- LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
- INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
- DAMAGE.
- 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
- defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
- receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
- written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
- received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
- your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
- the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
- refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
- providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
- receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
- is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
- opportunities to fix the problem.
- 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
- in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS," WITH NO OTHER
- WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
- WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
- 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
- warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
- If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
- law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
- interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
- the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
- provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
- 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
- trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
- providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
- with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
- promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
- harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
- that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
- or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
- work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
- Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
- Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
- Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
- electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
- including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
- because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
- people in all walks of life.
- Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
- assistance they need, is critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
- goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
- remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
- and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
- To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
- and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
- and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.
- Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
- Foundation
- The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
- 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
- state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
- Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
- number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
- http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
- permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
- The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
- Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
- throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
- 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
- business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact
- information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
- page at http://pglaf.org
- For additional contact information:
- Dr. Gregory B. Newby
- Chief Executive and Director
- gbnewby@pglaf.org
- Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation
- Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
- spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
- increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
- freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
- array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
- ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
- status with the IRS.
- The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
- charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
- States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
- considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
- with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
- where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
- SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
- particular state visit http://pglaf.org
- While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
- have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
- against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
- approach us with offers to donate.
- International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
- any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
- outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
- Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
- methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
- ways including including checks, online payments and credit card
- donations. To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate
- Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works.
- Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
- concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
- with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
- Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
- Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
- editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
- unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
- keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
- Each eBook is in a subdirectory of the same number as the eBook's
- eBook number, often in several formats including plain vanilla ASCII,
- compressed (zipped), HTML and others.
- Corrected EDITIONS of our eBooks replace the old file and take over
- the old filename and etext number. The replaced older file is renamed.
- VERSIONS based on separate sources are treated as new eBooks receiving
- new filenames and etext numbers.
- Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
- http://www.gutenberg.net
- This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
- including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
- subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.
- EBooks posted prior to November 2003, with eBook numbers BELOW #10000,
- are filed in directories based on their release date. If you want to
- download any of these eBooks directly, rather than using the regular
- search system you may utilize the following addresses and just
- download by the etext year.
- http://www.gutenberg.net/etext06
- (Or /etext 05, 04, 03, 02, 01, 00, 99,
- 98, 97, 96, 95, 94, 93, 92, 92, 91 or 90)
- EBooks posted since November 2003, with etext numbers OVER #10000, are
- filed in a different way. The year of a release date is no longer part
- of the directory path. The path is based on the etext number (which is
- identical to the filename). The path to the file is made up of single
- digits corresponding to all but the last digit in the filename. For
- example an eBook of filename 10234 would be found at:
- http://www.gutenberg.net/1/0/2/3/10234
- or filename 24689 would be found at:
- http://www.gutenberg.net/2/4/6/8/24689
- An alternative method of locating eBooks:
- http://www.gutenberg.net/GUTINDEX.ALL