Quotations.ch
  Directory : Political Discourses
GUIDE SUPPORT US BLOG
  • The Project Gutenberg eBook, Hume's Political Discourses, by David Hume,
  • Edited by William Bell Robertson
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most
  • other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
  • whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of
  • the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you'll have
  • to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this ebook.
  • Title: Hume's Political Discourses
  • Author: David Hume
  • Editor: William Bell Robertson
  • Release Date: June 22, 2019 [eBook #59792]
  • Language: English
  • Character set encoding: UTF-8
  • ***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HUME'S POLITICAL DISCOURSES***
  • E-text prepared by RichardW and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team
  • (http://www.pgdp.net) from page images generously made available by
  • Internet Archive (https://archive.org)
  • Note: Images of the original pages are available through
  • Internet Archive. See
  • https://archive.org/details/humespolitical00humeuoft
  • Some characters might not display properly in this UTF-8
  • text file (e.g., empty squares). If so, the reader should
  • consult the original page images noted above.
  • Transcriber’s note:
  • Text enclosed by underscores is in italics (_italics_).
  • Original small capitals are now uppercase (but some small
  • capital styling has been discarded).
  • Footnotes have been relabeled 1–117, converted to endnotes,
  • and moved to the ends of the relevant chapters.
  • The Scott Library.
  • HUME’S POLITICAL DISCOURSES.
  • ⁂ For Full List of the Volumes in This Series,
  • See Catalogue at End of Book.
  • HUME’S POLITICAL DISCOURSES.
  • With an Introduction by William Bell Robertson,
  • Author of “Foundations of Political Economy,”
  • “Slavery of Labour,” Etc.
  • The Walter Scott Publishing Co., Ltd.
  • London and Felling-on-Tyne.
  • New York: 3 East 14th Street.
  • CONTENTS.
  • Introduction vii
  • Of Commerce 1
  • Of Refinement in the Arts 15
  • Of Money 27
  • Of Interest 39
  • Of the Balance of Trade 51
  • Of the Jealousy of Trade 67
  • Of the Balance of Power 71
  • Of Taxes 78
  • Of Public Credit 83
  • Of some Remarkable Customs 98
  • Of the Populousness of Ancient Nations 106
  • Of the Original Contract 174
  • Of Passive Obedience 192
  • Of the Coalition of Parties 196
  • Of the Protestant Succession 203
  • Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth 214
  • That Politics may be Reduced to a Science 229
  • Of the First Principles of Government 243
  • Of Political Society 247
  • Alphabetical Arrangement of Authorities cited by Hume 253
  • INTRODUCTION.
  • Regretting the meagre records of the life of Adam Smith, the Right
  • Hon. R. B. Haldane, M.P.,​[1] remarks:—“We think of him, in the main,
  • and we think of him rightly, as the bosom friend of David Hume” (b.
  • 1711, d. 1777). Naturally, incidents in the life of a philosopher are
  • neither numerous nor stirring. It is unreasonable to expect them, and
  • such stories as are handed down regarding great thinkers are best not
  • to be accepted unreservedly. I leave Hume, therefore, to present his
  • own picture as drawn in _My own Life_—the picture he wished posterity
  • to have—which consequently follows this introduction, and is itself
  • followed by Adam Smith’s celebrated letter to Mr. Strahan, Hume’s
  • publisher, giving an account of Hume’s death.
  • It is chiefly as a political economist that Hume concerns us here,
  • as it is in the _Political Discourses_, first published in 1752, his
  • economic principles are set forth. What the reader may expect to find
  • in these _Discourses_ I prefer to let writers of renown tell. Thus Lord
  • Brougham—
  • “Of the _Political Discourses_ it would be difficult to speak in
  • terms of too great commendation. They combine almost every excellence
  • which can belong to such a performance. The reasoning is clear, and
  • unencumbered with more words or more illustrations than are necessary
  • for bringing out the doctrines. The learning is extensive, accurate,
  • and profound, not only as to systems of philosophy, but as to history,
  • whether modern or ancient. . . . The great merit, however, of these
  • _Discourses_ is their originality, and the new system of politics
  • and political economy which they unfold. Mr. Hume is, beyond all
  • doubt, the author of the modern doctrines which now rule the world of
  • science, which are to a great extent the guide of practical statesmen,
  • and are only prevented from being applied in their fullest extent to
  • the affairs of nations by the clashing interests and the ignorant
  • prejudices of certain powerful classes.”
  • Thus, again, J. Hill Burton,​[2] Hume’s biographer—
  • “These _Discourses_ are in truth the cradle of political economy; and
  • much as that science has been investigated and expounded in later
  • times, these earliest, shortest, and simplest developments of its
  • principles are still read with delight even by those who are masters
  • of all the literature of this great subject. But they possess a
  • quality which more elaborate economists have striven after in vain,
  • in being a pleasing object of study not only to the initiated, but to
  • the ordinary popular reader, and of being admitted as just and true
  • by many who cannot or will not understand the views of later writers
  • on political economy. They have thus the rarely conjoined merit that,
  • as they were the first to direct the way to the true sources of this
  • department of knowledge, those who have gone farther, instead of
  • superseding them, have in the general case confirmed their accuracy.”
  • The _Discourses_, in Hume’s own words, was “the only work of mine that
  • was successful on the first publication,” and its success was great.
  • Translated into French immediately, “they conferred,” says Professor
  • Huxley, “a European reputation upon their author; and, what was more
  • to the purpose, influenced the later school of economists of the
  • eighteenth century.” On the same head Burton says—“As no Frenchman
  • had previously approached the subject of political economy with a
  • philosophical pen, this little book was a main instrument, either by
  • causing assent or provoking controversy, in producing the host of
  • French works published between the time of its translation and the
  • publication of Smith’s _Wealth of Nations_ in 1776. The work of the
  • elder Mirabeau in particular—_L’ami des Hommes_—was in a great measure
  • a controversial examination of Hume’s opinions on population.”
  • Professor Knight of St. Andrews, again, echoes similar sentiments.
  • “The merit of the _Discourses_,” he remarks, “is not only great, but
  • they are unrivalled to this day; and it is not too much to affirm that
  • they prepared the way for all the subsequent economic literature of
  • England, including the _Wealth of Nations_, in which Smith laid down
  • the broad and durable foundations of the science. . . . The effect
  • produced by these _Discourses_ was great. Immediately translated into
  • French, they passed through five editions in fourteen years. They
  • were a distinctive addition to English literature, and were strictly
  • scientific, though not technical. They at once floated Hume into
  • fame, bringing him to the front, both as a thinker and as a man of
  • letters; and posterity has ratified this judgment of the hour. . . .
  • They contain many original germs of economic truth. The effect they
  • had on practical statesmen, such as Pitt, must not be overlooked. It
  • was perhaps an advantage that the economic doctrines, both of Hume and
  • Smith, were published at that particular time, as they led naturally
  • and easily to several reforms, without being developed to extremes, as
  • was subsequently the case in France.”
  • All this testimony as to the merits of the _Discourses_—testimony from
  • men of widely divergent views—is sufficient justification for offering
  • them in popular form to the public at a time like the present, when the
  • foundations of political economy are, one might say, being re-laid.​[3]
  • We have already hinted at the friendship that existed between Hume and
  • Adam Smith. Hume was Smith’s senior by twelve years, and seems to have
  • had the latter brought under his notice by Hutcheson, Professor of
  • Moral Philosophy at Glasgow University. In a letter to Hutcheson, dated
  • March 4th, 1740, he says—“My bookseller has sent to Mr. Smith a copy
  • of my book,​[4] which I hope he has received as well as your letter.”
  • “The Smith here mentioned,” Burton says, “we may fairly conclude,
  • notwithstanding the universality of the name, to be Adam Smith, who was
  • then a student in the University of Glasgow, and not quite seventeen
  • years old. It may be inferred that Hutcheson had mentioned Smith as a
  • person on whom it would serve some good purpose to bestow a copy of
  • the _Treatise_; and we have here evidently the first introduction to
  • each other’s notice of two friends, of whom it can be said there was no
  • third person writing the English language during the same period who
  • has had so much influence upon the opinions of mankind as either of
  • these two men.”
  • Hume’s influence upon Adam Smith was great. Even in the ring of the
  • phraseology of the _Wealth of Nations_ I sometimes fancy I can hear
  • Hume. Anyway, the book referred to in the above letter as sent to
  • Smith, Mr. Haldane considers as “in all probability” the determining
  • factor in making Smith abandon his original intention of entering the
  • Church. “Whether Hume could have been but for Smith we cannot now say;
  • but we know that, but for Hume, Smith could never have been.”​[5] While
  • agreeing that “but for Hume Smith could never have been,” I see no
  • reason to question that Hume could have been without Smith. Hume had
  • within him what may here be called the divine light, and it had to come
  • out. That is why, “in poverty and riches, in health and sickness, in
  • laborious obscurity and amidst the blaze of fame,” his ruling passion—a
  • passion for literature—never abated. No man can strike out for himself
  • an original line and stick to it like this, “through thick and thin,”
  • unless he have assurance of the truth of that that is in him. Hume had
  • this assurance. True, he sought fame—and he achieved fame; not for its
  • own sake—that is inconceivable in so great a thinker, a thinker with
  • such a true notion of the relation of things—but for the sake of the
  • truths he had to promulgate; for the higher his eminence the wider and
  • more attentive would be his audience. Of course, he sought fame, and
  • he found gratification in it. It was not the gratification of vanity,
  • however, that writers on Hume usually interpret it as; it was the
  • gratification arising from the knowledge that one has hit the mark—that
  • one has not laboured in vain. The petty vanity ascribed to Hume would
  • not have suffered him as “the parent of the first elucidations of
  • political economy to see his own offspring eclipsed, and to see it with
  • pride”—his attitude, according to Burton, on the successful reception
  • of _The Wealth of Nations_. Vanity, again, would have prevented between
  • these two men that unalloyed friendship so charming to contemplate.
  • In 1776, the year before Hume’s death, _The Wealth of Nations_
  • appeared, and here is how Hume writes to the author:—
  • “_February_ 8, 1776.
  • “DEAR SMITH,—I am as lazy a correspondent as you, yet my anxiety about
  • you makes me write. By all accounts your book has been printed long
  • ago; yet it has never been so much as advertized. What is the reason?
  • If you wait till the fate of America be decided, you may wait long.
  • “By all accounts you intend to settle with us this spring; yet we hear
  • no more of it. What is the reason? Your chamber in my house is always
  • unoccupied. I am always at home. I expect you to land here.
  • “I have been, am, and shall be probably in an indifferent state of
  • health. I weighed myself t’other day, and find I have fallen five
  • complete stones. If you delay much longer I shall probably disappear
  • altogether.
  • “The Duke of Buccleuch tells me that you are very zealous in American
  • affairs. My notion is that the matter is not so important as is
  • commonly imagined. If I be mistaken, I shall probably correct my error
  • when I see you or read you. Our navigation and general commerce may
  • suffer more than our manufactures. Should London fall as much in its
  • size as I have done, it will be the better. It is nothing but a hulk
  • of bad and unclean humours.”
  • At last the book appears, and Hume writes his friend, April 1st, 1776:—
  • “I am much pleased with your performance; and the perusal of it has
  • taken me from a state of great anxiety. It was a work of so much
  • expectation by yourself, by your friends, and by the public, that I
  • trembled for its first appearance, but am now much relieved. Not but
  • that the reading of it necessarily requires so much attention, and
  • the public is disposed to give so little, that I shall still doubt
  • for some time of its being at first very popular. But it has depth
  • and solidity and acuteness, and is so much illustrated by curious
  • facts that it must at last take the public attention. It is probably
  • much improved by your last abode in London. If you were here at my
  • fireside, I should dispute some of your principles. I cannot think
  • that the rent of farms makes any part of the price of produce,​[6]
  • but that the price is determined altogether by the quantity and the
  • demand. . . . But these and a hundred other points are fit only to be
  • discussed in conversation.”
  • Hume, though he “took a particular pleasure in the company of modest
  • women, and had no reason to be displeased with the reception he met
  • with from them,” died unmarried. Adam Smith also died unmarried,
  • “though he was for several years,” according to Dugald Stewart,
  • “attached to a young lady of great beauty and accomplishment.” Hume, in
  • the Essay “Of the Study of History,” speaks of being desired once by “a
  • young beauty _for whom I had some passion_ to send her some novels and
  • romances for her amusement.” David was a “canny” man though. In these
  • circumstances the following playful sally in a letter from Hume to Mrs.
  • Dysart, of Eccles, a relative, may have interest:—“What arithmetic
  • will serve to fix the proportion between good and bad wives, and rate
  • the different classes of each? Sir Isaac Newton himself, who could
  • measure the course of the planets and weigh the earth as in a pair of
  • scales—even he had not algebra enough to reduce that amiable part of
  • our species to a just equation; and they are the only heavenly bodies
  • whose orbits are as yet uncertain.”
  • The foregoing are mere glimpses of this truly great man, and are
  • offered with a view to awakening and stimulating amongst general
  • readers a desire for first-hand knowledge of David Hume.
  • W. B. R.
  • _May_ 1906.
  • MY OWN LIFE.
  • It is difficult for a man to speak long of himself without vanity;
  • therefore, I shall be short. It may be thought an instance of vanity
  • that I pretend at all to write my life; but this narrative shall
  • contain little more than the History of my Writings; as, indeed, almost
  • all my life has been spent in literary pursuits and occupations. The
  • first success of most of my writings was not such as to be an object of
  • vanity.
  • I was born the 26th of April 1711, old style, at Edinburgh. I was of a
  • good family, both by father and mother. My father’s family is a branch
  • of the Earl of Home’s or Hume’s; and my ancestors had been proprietors
  • of the estate, which my brother possesses, for several generations. My
  • mother was daughter of Sir David Falconer, President of the College of
  • Justice; the title of Halkerton came by succession to her brother.
  • My family, however, was not rich; and, being myself a younger brother,
  • my patrimony, according to the mode of my country, was of course very
  • slender. My father, who passed for a man of parts, died when I was
  • an infant, leaving me, with an elder brother and a sister, under the
  • care of our mother, a woman of singular merit, who, though young and
  • handsome, devoted herself entirely to the rearing and educating of
  • her children. I passed through the ordinary course of education with
  • success, and was seized very early with a passion for literature, which
  • has been the ruling passion of my life, and the great source of my
  • enjoyments. My studious disposition, my sobriety, and my industry gave
  • my family a notion that the law was a proper profession for me; but
  • I found an insurmountable aversion to everything but the pursuits of
  • philosophy and general learning; and while they fancied I was poring
  • upon Voet and Vinnius, Cicero and Virgil were the authors which I was
  • secretly devouring.
  • My very slender fortune, however, being unsuitable to this plan of
  • life, and my health being a little broken by my ardent application, I
  • was tempted, or rather forced, to make a very feeble trial for entering
  • into a more active scene of life. In 1734 I went to Bristol, with some
  • recommendations to eminent merchants, but in a few months found that
  • scene totally unsuitable to me. I went over to France, with a view of
  • prosecuting my studies in a country retreat, and I there laid that plan
  • of life which I have steadily and successfully pursued. I resolved
  • to make a very rigid frugality supply my deficiency of fortune, to
  • maintain unimpaired my independency, and to regard every object as
  • contemptible except the improvement of my talents in literature.
  • During my retreat in France, first at Rheims, but chiefly at La Fleche,
  • in Anjou, I composed my _Treatise of Human Nature_. After passing three
  • years very agreeably in that country, I came over to London in 1737.
  • In the end of 1738 I published my Treatise, and immediately went down
  • to my mother and my brother, who lived at his country-house, and was
  • employing himself very judiciously and successfully in the improvement
  • of his fortune.
  • Never literary attempt was more unfortunate than my _Treatise of Human
  • Nature_. It fell _dead-born from the press_, without reaching such
  • distinction as even to excite a murmur among the zealots. But being
  • naturally of a cheerful and sanguine temper, I very soon recovered
  • the blow, and prosecuted with great ardour my studies in the country.
  • In 1742 I printed at Edinburgh the first part of my Essays: the work
  • was favourably received, and soon made me entirely forget my former
  • disappointment. I continued with my mother and brother in the country,
  • and in that time recovered the knowledge of the Greek language, which I
  • had too much neglected in my early youth.
  • In 1745 I received a letter from the Marquis of Annandale, inviting me
  • to come and live with him in England; I found also that the friends
  • and family of that young nobleman were desirous of putting him under
  • my care and direction, for the state of his mind and health required
  • it. I lived with him a twelvemonth. My appointments during that time
  • made a considerable accession to my small fortune. I then received
  • an invitation from General St. Clair to attend him as a secretary to
  • his expedition, which was at first meant against Canada, but ended
  • in an incursion on the coast of France. Next year—to wit, 1747—I
  • received an invitation from the General to attend him in the same
  • station in his military embassy to the courts of Vienna and Turin.
  • I then wore the uniform of an officer, and was introduced at these
  • courts as aide-de-camp to the General, along with Sir Harry Erskine
  • and Captain Grant, now General Grant. These two years were almost the
  • only interruptions which my studies have received during the course
  • of my life. I passed them agreeably, and in good company; and my
  • appointments, with my frugality, had made me reach a fortune, which I
  • called independent, though most of my friends were inclined to smile
  • when I said so; in short, I was now master of near a thousand pounds.
  • I had always entertained a notion that my want of success in publishing
  • the _Treatise of Human Nature_ had proceeded more from the manner than
  • the matter, and that I had been guilty of a very usual indiscretion in
  • going to the press too _early_. I, therefore, cast the first part of
  • that work anew in the _Inquiry concerning Human Understanding_, which
  • was published while I was at Turin. But this piece was at first little
  • more successful than the _Treatise of Human Nature_. On my return
  • from Italy, I had the mortification to find all England in a ferment
  • on account of Dr. Middleton’s _Free Inquiry_, while my performance
  • was entirely overlooked and neglected. A new edition, which had been
  • published at London, of my _Essays, Moral and Political_, met not with
  • a much better reception.
  • Such is the force of natural temper, that these disappointments made
  • little or no impression on me. I went down in 1749 and lived two years
  • with my brother at his country-house, for my mother was now dead. I
  • there composed the second part of my Essays, which I called _Political
  • Discourses_, and also my _Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals_,
  • which is another part of my Treatise that I cast anew. Meanwhile, my
  • bookseller, A. Millar, informed me that my former publications (all
  • but the unfortunate Treatise) were beginning to be the subject of
  • conversation; that the sale of them was gradually increasing, and that
  • new editions were demanded. Answers by Reverends and Right Reverends
  • came out two or three in a year; and I found, by Dr. Warburton’s
  • railing, that the books were beginning to be esteemed in good company.
  • However, I had a fixed resolution, which I inflexibly maintained, never
  • to reply to anybody; and not being very irascible in my temper, I have
  • easily kept myself clear of all literary squabbles. These symptoms of
  • a rising reputation gave me encouragement, as I was ever more disposed
  • to see the favourable than unfavourable side of things; a turn of mind
  • which it is more happy to possess than to be born to an estate of ten
  • thousand a year.
  • In 1751 I removed from the country to the town, the true scene for
  • a man of letters. In 1752 were published at Edinburgh, where I then
  • lived, my _Political Discourses_, the only work of mine that was
  • successful on the first publication. It was well received abroad
  • and at home. In the same year was published at London my _Inquiry
  • concerning the Principles of Morals_; which, in my own opinion (who
  • ought not to judge on that subject), is of all my writings, historical,
  • philosophical, or literary, incomparably the best. It came unnoticed
  • and unobserved into the world.
  • In 1752 the Faculty of Advocates chose me their Librarian, an office
  • from which I received little or no emolument, but which gave me
  • the command of a large library. I then formed the plan of writing
  • the _History of England_; but being frightened with the notion of
  • continuing a narrative through a period of seventeen hundred years, I
  • commenced with the accession of the House of Stuart, an epoch when,
  • I thought, the misrepresentations of faction began chiefly to take
  • place. I was, I own, sanguine in my expectations of the success of
  • this work. I thought that I was the only historian that had at once
  • neglected present power, interest, and authority, and the cry of
  • popular prejudices; and as the subject was suited to every capacity, I
  • expected proportional applause. But miserable was my disappointment:
  • I was assailed by one cry of reproach, disapprobation, and even
  • detestation; English, Scotch, and Irish, Whig and Tory, Churchman and
  • Sectary, Freethinker and Religionist, Patriot and Courtier, united in
  • their rage against the man who had presumed to shed a generous tear for
  • the fate of Charles I. and the Earl of Strafford; and after the first
  • ebullitions of their fury were over, what was still more mortifying,
  • the book seemed to sink into oblivion. Mr. Millar told me that in a
  • twelvemonth, he sold only forty-five copies of it. I scarcely, indeed,
  • heard of one man in the three kingdoms, considerable for rank or
  • letters, that could endure the book. I must only except the Primate
  • of England, Dr. Herring, and the Primate of Ireland, Dr. Stone, which
  • seem two odd exceptions. These dignified prelates separately sent me
  • messages not to be discouraged.
  • I was, however, I confess, discouraged; and had not the war been at
  • that time breaking out between France and England, I had certainly
  • retired to some provincial town of the former kingdom, have changed
  • my name, and never more have returned to my native country. But as
  • this scheme was not now practicable, and the subsequent volume was
  • considerably advanced, I resolved to pick up courage, and to persevere.
  • In this interval I published at London my _Natural History of
  • Religion_, along with some other small pieces. Its public entry was
  • rather obscure, except only that Dr. Hurd wrote a pamphlet against
  • it, with all the illiberal petulance, arrogance, and scurrility which
  • distinguish the Warburtonian school. This pamphlet gave me some
  • consolation for the otherwise indifferent reception of my performance.
  • In 1756, two years after the fall of the first volume, was published
  • the second volume of my _History_, containing the period from the death
  • of Charles I. till the Revolution. This performance happened to give
  • less displeasure to the Whigs, and was better received. It not only
  • rose itself, but helped to buoy up its unfortunate brother.
  • But though I had been taught, by experience, that the Whig party
  • were in possession of bestowing all places, both in the State and
  • in literature, I was so little inclined to yield to their senseless
  • clamour, that in about a hundred alterations which further study,
  • reading, or reflection engaged me to make in the reigns of the two
  • first Stuarts, I have made all of them invariably to the Tory side. It
  • is ridiculous to consider the English constitution before that period
  • as a regular plan of liberty.
  • In 1759 I published my _History of the House of Tudor_. The clamour
  • against this performance was almost equal to that against the history
  • of the two first Stuarts. The reign of Elizabeth was particularly
  • obnoxious. But I was now callous against the impressions of public
  • folly, and continued very peaceably and contentedly in my retreat
  • at Edinburgh, to finish, in two volumes, the more early part of the
  • English History, which I gave to the public in 1761, with tolerable,
  • and but tolerable success.
  • But notwithstanding this variety of winds and seasons, to which my
  • writings had been exposed, they had still been making such advances
  • that the copy-money given me by the booksellers much exceeded anything
  • formerly known in England; I was become not only independent, but
  • opulent. I retired to my native country of Scotland, determined never
  • more to set my foot out of it; and retaining the satisfaction of never
  • having preferred a request to one great man, or even making advances
  • of friendship to any of them. As I was now turned of fifty, I thought
  • of passing all the rest of my life in this philosophical manner, when
  • I received, in 1763, an invitation from the Earl of Hertford, with
  • whom I was not in the least acquainted, to attend him on his embassy
  • to Paris, with a near prospect of being appointed Secretary to the
  • embassy, and, in the meanwhile, of performing the functions of that
  • office. This offer, however inviting, I at first declined, both because
  • I was reluctant to begin connections with the great, and because I was
  • afraid the civilities and gay company of Paris would prove disagreeable
  • to a person of my age and humour; but on his lordship’s repeating the
  • invitation, I accepted of it. I have every reason, both of pleasure and
  • interest, to think myself happy in my connections with that nobleman,
  • as well as afterwards with his brother, General Conway.
  • Those who have not seen the strange effects of Modes, will never
  • imagine the reception I met with at Paris, from men and women of all
  • ranks and stations. The more I resiled from their excessive civilities,
  • the more I was loaded with them. There is, however, a real satisfaction
  • in living in Paris, from the great number of sensible, knowing, and
  • polite company with which that city abounds above all places in the
  • universe. I thought once of settling there for life.
  • I was appointed Secretary to the embassy; and in summer 1765, Lord
  • Hertford left me, being appointed Lord Lieutenant of Ireland. I was
  • _chargé d’affaires_ till the arrival of the Duke of Richmond, towards
  • the end of the year. In the beginning of 1766 I left Paris, and next
  • summer went to Edinburgh, with the same view as formerly, of burying
  • myself in a philosophical retreat. I returned to that place, not
  • richer, but with much more money, and a much larger income, by means
  • of Lord Hertford’s friendship, than I left it; and I was desirous
  • of trying what superfluity could produce, as I had formerly made an
  • experiment of a competency. But in 1767 I received from Mr. Conway
  • an invitation to be Under Secretary; and this invitation, both the
  • character of the person and my connections with Lord Hertford prevented
  • me from declining. I returned to Edinburgh in 1769, very opulent (for
  • I possessed a revenue of £1000 a year), healthy, and, though somewhat
  • stricken in years, with the prospect of enjoying long my ease, and of
  • seeing the increase of my reputation.
  • In spring 1775, I was struck with a disorder in my bowels, which at
  • first gave me no alarm, but has since, as I apprehend it, become
  • mortal and incurable. I now reckon upon a speedy dissolution. I have
  • suffered very little pain from my disorder; and what is more strange,
  • have, notwithstanding the great decline of my person, never suffered
  • a moment’s abatement of my spirits; insomuch, that were I to name the
  • period of my life which I should most choose to pass over again, I
  • might be tempted to point to this later period. I possess the same
  • ardour as ever in study, and the same gaiety in company. I consider,
  • besides, that a man of sixty-five, by dying, cuts off only a few
  • years of infirmities; and though I see many symptoms of my literary
  • reputation’s breaking out at last with additional lustre, I knew that
  • I could have but few years to enjoy it. It is difficult to be more
  • detached from life than I am at present.
  • To conclude historically with my own character. I am, or rather was
  • (for that is the style I must now use in speaking of myself, which
  • emboldens me the more to speak my sentiments)—I was, I say, a man
  • of mild dispositions, of command of temper, of an open, social,
  • and cheerful humour, capable of attachment, but little susceptible
  • of enmity, and of great moderation in all my passions. Even my
  • love of literary fame, my ruling passion, never soured my temper,
  • notwithstanding my frequent disappointments. My company was not
  • unacceptable to the young and careless, as well as to the studious and
  • literary; and as I took a particular pleasure in the company of modest
  • women, I had no reason to be displeased with the reception I met with
  • from them. In a word, though most men anywise eminent have found reason
  • to complain of calumny, I never was touched, or even attacked by her
  • baleful tooth: and though I wantonly exposed myself to the rage of both
  • civil and religious factions, they seemed to be disarmed in my behalf
  • of their wonted fury. My friends never had occasion to vindicate
  • any one circumstance of my character and conduct: not but that the
  • zealots, we may well suppose, would have been glad to invent and
  • propagate any story to my disadvantage, but they never could find any
  • which they thought would wear the face of probability. I cannot say
  • there is no vanity in making this funeral oration of myself, but I hope
  • it is not a misplaced one; and this is a matter of fact which is easily
  • cleared and ascertained.
  • _April_ 18, 1776.
  • ADAM SMITH’S CELEBRATED ACCOUNT OF HUME’S DEATH.
  • “KIRKCALDY, FIFESHIRE, _Nov._ 9, 1776.
  • “DEAR SIR,—It is with a real, though a very melancholy pleasure, that
  • I sit down to give you some account of the behaviour of our excellent
  • friend, Mr. Hume, during his last illness.
  • “Though, in his own judgment, his disease was mortal and incurable,
  • yet he allowed himself to be prevailed upon, by the entreaty of his
  • friends, to try what might be the effects of a long journey. A few days
  • before he set out he wrote that account of his own life which, together
  • with his other papers, he has left to your care. My account, therefore,
  • shall begin where his ends.
  • “He set out for London towards the end of April, and at Morpeth met
  • with Mr. John Home and myself, who had both come down from London to
  • see him, expecting to have found him in Edinburgh. Mr. Home returned
  • with him, and attended him during the whole of his stay in England,
  • with that care and attention which might be expected from a temper so
  • perfectly friendly and affectionate. As I had written to my mother
  • that she might expect me in Scotland, I was under the necessity of
  • continuing my journey. His disease seemed to yield to exercise and
  • change of air, and when he arrived in London he was apparently in much
  • better health than when he left Edinburgh. He was advised to go to
  • Bath to drink the waters, which appeared for some time to have so good
  • an effect upon him that even he himself began to entertain, what he
  • was not apt to do, a better opinion of his own health. His symptoms,
  • however, soon returned with their usual violence, and from that moment
  • he gave up all thoughts of recovery, but submitted with the utmost
  • cheerfulness, and the most perfect complacency and resignation. Upon
  • his return to Edinburgh, though he found himself much weaker, yet his
  • cheerfulness never abated, and he continued to divert himself as usual,
  • with correcting his own works for a new edition, and reading books of
  • amusement, with the conversation of his friends, and, sometimes in the
  • evening, with a party at his favourite game of whist. His cheerfulness
  • was so great, his conversation and amusements ran so much in their
  • usual strain that, notwithstanding all bad symptoms, many people
  • could not believe he was dying. ‘I shall tell your friend, Colonel
  • Edmondstone,’ said Doctor Dundas to him one day, ‘that I left you
  • much better, and in a fair way of recovery.’ ‘Doctor,’ said he, ‘as I
  • believe you would not choose to tell anything but the truth, you had
  • better tell him that I am dying as fast as my enemies, if I have any,
  • could wish, and as easily and as cheerfully as my best friends could
  • desire.’ Colonel Edmondstone soon afterwards came to see him, and took
  • leave of him; and on his way home he could not forbear writing him a
  • letter bidding him once more an eternal adieu, and applying to him, as
  • a dying man, the beautiful French verses in which the Abbé Chaulieu,
  • in expectation of his own death, laments his approaching separation
  • from his friend, the Marquis de la Fare. Mr. Hume’s magnanimity and
  • firmness were such, that his most affectionate friends knew that they
  • hazarded nothing in talking or writing to him as to a dying man,
  • and that, so far from being hurt by this frankness, he was rather
  • pleased and flattered by it. I happened to come into his room while
  • he was reading this letter, which he had just received, and which he
  • immediately showed me. I told him that though I was sensible how very
  • much he was weakened, and that appearances were in many respects very
  • bad yet his cheerfulness was still so great, the spirit of life seemed
  • still to be so very strong in him, that I could not help
  • entertaining some faint hopes. He answered—‘Your hopes are groundless.
  • An habitual diarrhœa of more than a year’s standing would be a very bad
  • disease at any age: at my age it is a mortal one. When I lie down in
  • the evening, I feel myself weaker than when I rose in the morning; and
  • when I rise in the morning, weaker than when I lay down in the evening.
  • I am sensible, besides, that some of my vital parts are affected, so
  • that I must soon die.’ ‘Well,’ said I, ‘if it must be so, you have at
  • least the satisfaction of leaving all your friends, your brother’s
  • family in particular, in great prosperity.’ He said that he felt that
  • satisfaction so sensibly, that when he was reading a few days before,
  • Lucian’s _Dialogues of the Dead_, among all the excuses which are
  • alleged to Charon for not entering readily into his boat, he could not
  • find one that fitted him: he had no house to finish, he had no daughter
  • to provide for, he had no enemies upon whom he wished to revenge
  • himself. ‘I could not well imagine,’ said he, ‘what excuse I could make
  • to Charon in order to obtain a little delay. I have done everything of
  • consequence which I ever meant to do; and I could at no time expect
  • to leave my relations and friends in a better situation than that in
  • which I am now like to leave them; I therefore have all reason to die
  • contented.’ He then diverted himself with inventing several jocular
  • excuses, which he supposed he might make to Charon, and with imagining
  • the very surly answers which it might suit the character of Charon
  • to return to them. ‘Upon further consideration,’ said he, ‘I thought
  • I might say to him, good Charon, I have been correcting my works for
  • a new edition; allow me a little time that I may see how the public
  • receives the alterations.’ But Charon would answer, ‘When you have seen
  • the effect of these, you will be for making other alterations. There
  • will be no end of such excuses; so, honest friend, please step into the
  • boat.’ But I might still urge, ‘Have a little patience, good Charon;
  • I have been endeavouring to open the eyes of the public. If I live a
  • few years longer, I may have the satisfaction of seeing the downfall
  • of some of the prevailing systems of superstition.’ But Charon would
  • then lose all temper and decency. ‘You loitering rogue; that will not
  • happen these many hundred years. Do you fancy I will grant you a lease
  • for so long a term? Get into the boat this instant, you lazy, loitering
  • rogue.’
  • “But though Mr. Hume always talked of his approaching dissolution
  • with great cheerfulness, he never affected to make any parade of his
  • magnanimity. He never mentioned the subject but when the conversation
  • naturally led to it, and never dwelt longer upon it than the course of
  • the conversation happened to require; it was a subject, indeed, which
  • occurred pretty frequently, in consequence of the inquiries which his
  • friends who came to see him naturally made concerning the state of his
  • health. The conversation which I mentioned above, and which passed
  • on Thursday the 8th of August, was the last except one that I ever
  • had with him. He had now become so very weak that the company of his
  • most intimate friends fatigued him; for his cheerfulness was still so
  • great, his complaisance and social disposition were still so entire,
  • that when any friend was with him he could not help talking more, and
  • with greater exertion than suited the weakness of his body. At his own
  • desire, therefore, I agreed to leave Edinburgh, where I was staying
  • partly upon his account, and returned to my mother’s house here, at
  • Kirkcaldy, upon condition that he would send for me whenever he wished
  • to see me; the physician who saw him most frequently, Dr. Black,
  • undertaking in the meantime to write me occasionally an account of the
  • state of his health.
  • “On the 22nd of August the doctor wrote me the following letter:—
  • “‘Since my last Mr. Hume has passed his time pretty easily, but is much
  • weaker. He sits up, goes downstairs once a day, and amuses himself with
  • reading, but seldom sees anybody. He finds that even the conversation
  • of his most intimate friends fatigues and oppresses him; and it is
  • happy that he does not need it, for he is quite free from anxiety,
  • impatience, or low spirits, and passes his time very well with the
  • assistance of amusing books.’
  • “I received the day after a letter from Mr. Hume himself, of which the
  • following is an extract:—
  • “‘EDINBURGH, _August_ 23, 1776.
  • “‘MY DEAREST FRIEND,—I am obliged to make use of my nephew’s hand in
  • writing to you, as I do not rise to-day.
  • · · · · · ·
  • “‘I go very fast to decline, and last night had a small fever, which I
  • hoped might put a quicker period to this tedious illness; but unluckily
  • it has, in a great measure, gone off. I cannot submit to your coming
  • over here on my account, as it is possible for me to see you so small
  • a part of the day, but Dr. Black can better inform you concerning the
  • degree of strength which may from time to time remain with me. Adieu,
  • etc.’
  • “Three days after I received the following letter from Dr. Black:—
  • “‘EDINBURGH, _August_ 26_th_, 1776.
  • “‘DEAR SIR,—Yesterday, about four o’clock afternoon, Mr. Hume expired.
  • The near approach of his death became evident in the night between
  • Thursday and Friday, when his disease became excessive, and soon
  • weakened him so much that he could no longer rise out of his bed. He
  • continued to the last perfectly sensible, and free from much pain
  • or feeling of distress. He never dropped the smallest expression of
  • impatience, but when he had occasion to speak to the people about him
  • always did it with affection and tenderness. I thought it improper to
  • write to bring you over, especially as I heard that he had dictated a
  • letter to you desiring you not to come. When he became very weak it
  • cost him an effort to speak, and he died in such a happy composure of
  • mind that nothing could exceed it!’
  • “Thus died our most excellent and never-to-be-forgotten friend,
  • concerning whose philosophical opinions men will, no doubt, judge
  • variously, every one approving or condemning them according as they
  • happen to coincide or disagree with his own; but concerning whose
  • character and conduct there can scarce be a difference of opinion.
  • His temper, indeed, seemed to be more happily balanced—if I may be
  • allowed such an expression—than that perhaps of any other man I have
  • ever known. Even in the lowest state of his fortune his great and
  • necessary frugality never hindered him from exercising, upon proper
  • occasions, acts both of charity and generosity. It was a frugality
  • founded not upon avarice but upon the love of independency. The extreme
  • gentleness of his nature never weakened either the firmness of his mind
  • or the steadiness of his resolutions. His constant pleasantry was the
  • genuine effusion of good-nature and good-humour tempered with delicacy
  • and modesty, and without even the slightest tincture of malignity—so
  • frequently the disagreeable source of what is called wit in other men.
  • It never was the meaning of his raillery to mortify, and therefore, far
  • from offending, it seldom failed to please and delight even those who
  • were the object of it. To his friends—who were frequently the object of
  • it—there was not perhaps any one of all his great and amiable qualities
  • which contributed more to endear his conversation. And that gaiety of
  • temper, so agreeable in society, but which is so often accompanied with
  • frivolous and superficial qualities, was in him certainly attended
  • with the most severe application, the most extensive learning, the
  • greatest depth of thought, and a capacity in every respect the most
  • comprehensive. Upon the whole, I have always considered him, both in
  • his lifetime and since his death, as approaching as nearly to the idea
  • of a perfectly wise and virtuous man as perhaps the nature of human
  • frailty will permit.
  • “I ever am, dear sir, most affectionately yours,
  • “ADAM SMITH.”
  • ⁂ “It is a usual fallacy,” says Hume in “Of the Populousness of Ancient
  • Nations,” “to consider all the ages of antiquity as one period.” The
  • dates given in the Appendix may serve as a corrective in this regard.
  • NOTES, INTRODUCTION.
  • [1] _Life of Adam Smith_, “Great Writers” series.
  • [2] _Life and Correspondence of David Hume_, 1846.
  • [3] See _Foundations of Political Economy_, The Walter Scott Publishing
  • Company, Limited.
  • [4] His _Treatise of Human Nature_, regarding the publication of which
  • he wrote in 1751 to Sir Gilbert Elliot, of Minto—“I was carried away
  • by the heat of youth and invention to publish too precipitately. So
  • vast an undertaking, planned before I was one-and-twenty, and composed
  • before I was twenty-five, must necessarily be very defective. I have
  • repented my haste a hundred and a hundred times.”
  • [5] Haldane, _Life of Adam Smith_, “Great Writers” series.
  • [6] Hume’s view is the juster here.
  • HUME’S POLITICAL DISCOURSES
  • [Illustration, ornamental]
  • OF COMMERCE.
  • The greatest part of mankind may be divided into two classes: that of
  • shallow thinkers, who fall short of the truth; and that of abstruse
  • thinkers, who go beyond it. The latter class are by far the most
  • uncommon; and I may add, by far the most useful and valuable. They
  • suggest hints, at least, and start difficulties, which they want,
  • perhaps, skill to pursue; but which may produce very fine discoveries,
  • when handled by men who have a more just way of thinking. At worst,
  • what they say is uncommon; and if it should cost some pains to
  • comprehend it, one has, however, the pleasure of hearing something that
  • is new. An author is little to be valued who tells us nothing but what
  • we can learn from every coffee-house conversation.
  • All people of shallow thought are apt to decry even those of solid
  • understanding, as abstruse thinkers, and metaphysicians, and refiners;
  • and never will allow anything to be just which is beyond their own
  • weak conceptions. There are some cases, I own, where an extraordinary
  • refinement affords a strong presumption of falsehood, and where no
  • reasoning is to be trusted but what is natural and easy. When a man
  • deliberates concerning his conduct in any particular affair, and
  • forms schemes in politics, trade, economy, or any business in life,
  • he never ought to draw his arguments too fine, or connect too long
  • a chain of consequences together. Something is sure to happen that
  • will disconcert his reasoning, and produce an event different
  • from what he expected. But when we reason upon general subjects,
  • one may justly affirm that our speculations can scarce ever be too
  • fine, provided they be just; and that the difference between a common
  • man and a man of genius is chiefly seen in the shallowness or depth
  • of the principles upon which they proceed. General reasonings seem
  • intricate, merely because they are general; nor is it easy for the
  • bulk of mankind to distinguish, in a great number of particulars, that
  • common circumstance in which they all agree, or to extract it, pure
  • and unmixed, from the other superfluous circumstances. Every judgment
  • or conclusion, with them, is particular. They cannot enlarge their
  • view to those universal propositions which comprehend under them an
  • infinite number of individuals, and include a whole science in a single
  • theorem. Their eye is confounded with such an extensive prospect; and
  • the conclusions derived from it, even though clearly expressed, seem
  • intricate and obscure. But however intricate they may seem, it is
  • certain that general principles, if just and sound, must always prevail
  • in the general course of things, though they may fail in particular
  • cases; and it is the chief business of philosophers to regard the
  • general course of things. I may add that it is also the chief business
  • of politicians; especially in the domestic government of the state,
  • where the public good, which is, or ought to be, their object, depends
  • on the concurrence of a multitude of cases; not, as in foreign
  • politics, on accidents and chances, and the caprices of a few persons.
  • This therefore makes the difference between particular deliberations
  • and general reasonings, and renders subtlety and refinement much more
  • suitable to the latter than to the former.
  • I thought this introduction necessary before the following discourses
  • on commerce, money, interest, balance of trade, etc., where, perhaps,
  • there will occur some principles which are uncommon, and which may seem
  • too refined and subtle for such vulgar subjects. If false, let them be
  • rejected; but no one ought to entertain a prejudice against them merely
  • because they are out of the common road.
  • The greatness of a state, and the happiness of its subjects, however
  • independent they may be supposed in some respects, are commonly allowed
  • to be inseparable with regard to commerce; and as private men receive
  • greater security in the possession of their trade and riches from the
  • power of the public, so the public becomes powerful in proportion to
  • the riches and extensive commerce of private men. This maxim is true in
  • general, though I cannot forbear thinking that it may possibly admit of
  • some exceptions, and that we often establish it with too little reserve
  • and limitation. There may be some circumstances where the commerce,
  • and riches, and luxury of individuals, instead of adding strength
  • to the public, will serve only to thin its armies, and diminish its
  • authority among the neighbouring nations. Man is a very variable being,
  • and susceptible of many different opinions, principles, and rules of
  • conduct. What may be true while he adheres to one way of thinking will
  • be found false when he has embraced an opposite set of manners and
  • opinions.
  • The bulk of every state may be divided into husbandmen and
  • manufacturers. The former are employed in the culture of the land;
  • the latter work up the materials furnished by the former, into all
  • the commodities which are necessary and ornamental to human life.
  • As soon as men quit their savage state, where they live chiefly by
  • hunting and fishing, they must fall into these two classes; though
  • the arts of agriculture employ at first the most numerous part of the
  • society.​[7] Time and experience improve so much these arts, that the
  • land may easily maintain a much greater number of men than those who
  • are immediately employed in its cultivation, or who furnish the
  • more necessary manufactures to such as are so employed.
  • If these superfluous hands apply themselves to the finer arts, which
  • are commonly denominated the arts of luxury, they add to the happiness
  • of the state, since they afford to many the opportunity of receiving
  • enjoyments with which they would otherwise have been unacquainted.
  • But may not another scheme be proposed for the employment of these
  • superfluous hands? May not the sovereign lay claim to them, and
  • employ them in fleets and armies, to increase the dominions of the
  • state abroad, and spread its fame over distant nations? It is certain
  • that the fewer desires and wants are found in the proprietors and
  • labourers of land, the fewer hands do they employ; and consequently
  • the superfluities of the land, instead of maintaining tradesmen and
  • manufacturers, may support fleets and armies to a much greater extent
  • than where a great many arts are required to minister to the luxury of
  • particular persons. Here therefore seems to be a kind of opposition
  • between the greatness of the state and the happiness of the subjects. A
  • state is never greater than when all its superfluous hands are employed
  • in the service of the public. The ease and convenience of private
  • persons require that these hands should be employed in their service.
  • The one can never be satisfied but at the expense of the other. As the
  • ambition of the sovereign must entrench on the luxury of individuals,
  • so the luxury of individuals must diminish the force and check the
  • ambition of the sovereign.
  • Nor is this reasoning merely chimerical, but is founded on history and
  • experience. The republic of Sparta was certainly more powerful than any
  • state now in the world, consisting of an equal number of people, and
  • this was owing entirely to the want of commerce and luxury. The Helotes
  • were the labourers: the Spartans were the soldiers or gentlemen. It is
  • evident that the labour of the Helotes could not have maintained so
  • great a number of Spartans, had these latter lived in ease and delicacy
  • and given employment to a great variety of trades and manufactures.
  • The like policy may be remarked in Rome. And indeed, through all
  • ancient history, it is observable that the smallest republics raised
  • and maintained greater armies than states consisting of triple the
  • number of inhabitants are able to support at present. It is computed
  • that in all European nations the proportion between soldiers and
  • people does not exceed one to a hundred. But we read that the city of
  • Rome alone, with its small territory, raised and maintained, in early
  • times, ten legions against the Latins. Athens, whose whole dominions
  • were not larger than Yorkshire, sent to the expedition against Sicily
  • near forty thousand men. Dionysius the elder, it is said, maintained
  • a standing army of a hundred thousand foot and ten thousand horse,
  • besides a large fleet of four hundred sail,​[8] though his territories
  • extended no farther than the city of Syracuse, about a third part
  • of the island of Sicily, and some seaport towns or garrisons on the
  • coast of Italy and Illyricum. It is true the ancient armies, in time
  • of war, subsisted much upon plunder; but did not the enemy plunder in
  • their turn? which was a more ruinous way of levying tax than any other
  • that could be devised. In short, no probable reason can be assigned
  • for the great power of the more ancient states above the modern but
  • their want of commerce and luxury. Few artisans were maintained by the
  • labour of the farmers, and therefore more soldiers might live upon it.
  • Titus Livius says that Rome, in his time, would find it difficult to
  • raise as large an army as that which, in her early days, she sent out
  • against the Gauls and Latins. Instead of those soldiers who fought for
  • liberty and empire in Camillus’s time, there were in Augustus’s days
  • musicians, painters, cooks, players, and tailors; and if the land was
  • equally cultivated at both periods, it is evident it could maintain
  • equal numbers in the one profession as in the other. They added nothing
  • to the mere necessaries of life in the latter period more than in the
  • former.
  • It is natural on this occasion to ask whether sovereigns may not return
  • to the maxims of ancient policy, and consult their own interest in
  • this respect more than the happiness of their subjects. I answer that
  • it appears to me almost impossible; and that because ancient policy
  • was violent, and contrary to the more natural and usual course of
  • things. It is well known with what peculiar laws Sparta was governed,
  • and what a prodigy that republic is justly esteemed by every one who
  • has considered human nature, as it has displayed itself in other
  • nations and other ages. Were the testimony of history less positive and
  • circumstantial, such a government would appear a mere philosophical
  • whim or fiction, and impossible ever to be reduced to practice.
  • And though the Roman and other ancient republics were supported on
  • principles somewhat more natural, yet was there a very extraordinary
  • concurrence of circumstances to make them submit to such grievous
  • burdens. They were free states; they were small ones; and the age
  • being martial, all the neighbouring states were continually in arms.
  • Freedom naturally begets public spirit, especially in small states; and
  • this public spirit, this _amor patriæ_, must increase when the public
  • is almost in continual alarm, and men are obliged every moment to
  • expose themselves to the greatest dangers for its defence. A continual
  • succession of wars makes every citizen a soldier: he takes the field
  • in his turn, and during his service is chiefly maintained by himself.
  • And notwithstanding that his service is equivalent to a very severe
  • tax, it is less felt by a people addicted to arms, who fight for honour
  • and revenge more than pay, and are unacquainted with gain and industry
  • as well as pleasure.​[9] Not to mention the great equality of
  • fortunes amongst the inhabitants of the ancient republics, where every
  • field belonging to a different proprietor was able to maintain a
  • family, and rendered the numbers of citizens very considerable, even
  • without trade and manufactures.
  • But though the want of trade and manufactures, amongst a free and very
  • martial people, may sometimes have no other effect than to render the
  • public more powerful, it is certain that, in the common course of human
  • affairs, it will have a quite contrary tendency. Sovereigns must take
  • mankind as they find them, and cannot pretend to introduce any violent
  • change in their principles and ways of thinking. A long course of time,
  • with a variety of accidents and circumstances, is requisite to produce
  • those great revolutions which so much diversify the face of human
  • affairs. And the less natural any set of principles are which support
  • a particular society, the more difficulty will a legislator meet with
  • in raising and cultivating them. It is his best policy to comply with
  • the common bent of mankind, and give it all the improvements of which
  • it is susceptible. Now, according to the most natural course of things,
  • industry, and arts, and trade increase the power of the sovereign as
  • well as the happiness of the subjects; and that policy is violent
  • which aggrandizes the public by the poverty of individuals. This will
  • easily appear from a few considerations, which will present to us the
  • consequences of sloth and barbarity.
  • Where manufactures and mechanic arts are not cultivated, the bulk of
  • the people must apply themselves to agriculture; and if their skill
  • and industry increase, there must arise a great superfluity
  • from their labour beyond what suffices to maintain them. They have no
  • temptation, therefore, to increase their skill and industry; since they
  • cannot exchange that superfluity for any commodities which may serve
  • either to their pleasure or vanity. A habit of indolence naturally
  • prevails. The greater part of the land lies uncultivated. What is
  • cultivated yields not its utmost, for want of skill or assiduity in
  • the farmer. If at any time the public exigencies require that great
  • numbers should be employed in the public service, the labour of the
  • people furnishes now no superfluities by which these numbers can be
  • maintained. The labourers cannot increase their skill and industry on
  • a sudden. Lands uncultivated cannot be brought into tillage for some
  • years. The armies, meanwhile, must either make sudden and violent
  • conquests, or disband for want of subsistence. A regular attack or
  • defence, therefore, is not to be expected from such a people, and
  • their soldiers must be as ignorant and unskilful as their farmers and
  • manufacturers.
  • Everything in the world is purchased by labour, and our passions are
  • the only causes of labour. When a nation abounds in manufactures and
  • mechanic arts, the proprietors of land, as well as the farmers, study
  • agriculture as a science, and redouble their industry and attention.
  • The superfluity which arises from their labour is not lost, but is
  • exchanged with the manufacturers for those commodities which men’s
  • luxury now makes them covet. By this means land furnishes a great
  • deal more of the necessaries of life than what suffices for those who
  • cultivate it. In times of peace and tranquillity this superfluity goes
  • to the maintenance of manufacturers, and the improvers of liberal arts.
  • But it is easy for the public to convert many of these manufacturers
  • into soldiers, and maintain them by that superfluity which arises from
  • the labour of the farmers. Accordingly we find that this is the case
  • in all civilized governments. When the sovereign raises an army, what
  • is the consequence? He imposes a tax. This tax obliges all the people
  • to retrench what is least necessary to their subsistence. Those
  • who labour in such commodities must either enlist in the troops or
  • turn themselves to agriculture, and thereby oblige some labourers to
  • enlist for want of business. And to consider the matter abstractly,
  • manufactures increase the power of the state only as they store up so
  • much labour, and that of a kind to which the public may lay claim,
  • without depriving any one of the necessaries of life. The more labour,
  • therefore, is employed beyond mere necessaries, the more powerful is
  • any state; since the persons engaged in that labour may easily be
  • converted to the public service. In a state without manufactures there
  • may be the same number of hands; but there is not the same quantity of
  • labour, nor of the same kind. All the labour is there bestowed upon
  • necessaries, which can admit of little or no abatement.
  • Thus the greatness of the sovereign and the happiness of the state
  • are, in a great measure, united with regard to trade and manufactures.
  • It is a violent method, and in most cases impracticable, to oblige
  • the labourer to toil in order to raise from the land more than what
  • subsists himself and family. Furnish him with manufactures and
  • commodities, and he will do it of himself. Afterwards you will find it
  • easy to seize some part of his superfluous labour, and employ it in the
  • public service, without giving him his wonted return. Being accustomed
  • to industry, he will think this less grievous than if, at once, you
  • obliged him to an augmentation of labour without any reward. The case
  • is the same with regard to the other members of the state. The greater
  • is the stock of labour of all kinds, the greater quantity may be taken
  • from the heap without making any sensible alteration upon it.
  • A public granary of corn, a storehouse of cloth, a magazine of arms;
  • all these must be allowed real riches and strength in any state. Trade
  • and industry are really nothing but a stock of labour, which, in time
  • of peace and tranquillity, is employed for the ease and satisfaction of
  • individuals; but in the exigencies of state, may, in part, be turned
  • to public advantage. Could we convert a city into a kind of fortified
  • camp, and infuse into each breast so martial a genius, and such
  • a passion for public good, as to make every one willing to undergo the
  • greatest hardships for the sake of the public, these affections might
  • now, as in ancient times, prove alone a sufficient spur to industry,
  • and support the community. It would then be advantageous, as in camps,
  • to banish all arts and luxury; and, by restrictions on equipage and
  • tables, make the provisions and forage last longer than if the army
  • were loaded with a number of superfluous retainers. But as these
  • principles are too disinterested and too difficult to support, it is
  • requisite to govern men by other passions, and animate them with a
  • spirit of avarice and industry, art and luxury. The camp is, in this
  • case, loaded with a superfluous retinue; but the provisions flow in
  • proportionately larger. The harmony of the whole is still supported,
  • and the natural bent of the mind being more complied with, individuals,
  • as well as the public, find their account in the observance of those
  • maxims.
  • The same method of reasoning will let us see the advantage of foreign
  • commerce, in augmenting the power of the state, as well as the riches
  • and happiness of the subjects. It increases the stock of labour in
  • the nation, and the sovereign may convert what share of it he finds
  • necessary to the service of the public. Foreign trade, by its imports,
  • furnishes materials for new manufactures; and by its exports, it
  • produces labour in particular commodities which could not be consumed
  • at home. In short, a kingdom that has a large import and export
  • must abound more with industry, and that employed upon delicacies
  • and luxuries, than a kingdom which rests contented with its native
  • commodities. It is, therefore, more powerful, as well as richer and
  • happier. The individuals reap the benefit of these commodities, so far
  • as they gratify the senses and appetites. And the public is also a
  • gainer, while a greater stock of labour is, by this means, stored up
  • against any public exigency; that is, a greater number of laborious
  • men are maintained, who may be diverted to the public service
  • without robbing any one of the necessaries or even the chief
  • conveniences of life.
  • If we consult history, we shall find that in most nations foreign trade
  • has preceded any refinement in home manufactures, and given birth to
  • domestic luxury. The temptation is stronger to make use of foreign
  • commodities, which are ready for use, and which are entirely new to
  • us, than to make improvements on any domestic commodity, which always
  • advance by slow degrees, and never affect us by their novelty. The
  • profit is also very great in exporting what is superfluous at home,
  • and what bears no price, to foreign nations, whose soil or climate is
  • not favourable to that commodity. Thus men become acquainted with the
  • pleasures of luxury and the profits of commerce; and their delicacy
  • and industry, being once awakened, carry them to farther improvements
  • in every branch of domestic as well as foreign trade. And this perhaps
  • is the chief advantage which arises from a commerce with strangers.
  • It rouses men from their indolence; and presenting the gayer and more
  • opulent part of the nation with objects of luxury, which they never
  • before dreamed of, raises in them a desire of a more splendid way of
  • life than what their ancestors enjoyed; and at the same time the few
  • merchants who possess the secret of this importation and exportation
  • make exorbitant profits, and becoming rivals in wealth to the ancient
  • nobility, tempt other adventurers to become their rivals in commerce.
  • Imitation soon diffuses all those arts; while domestic manufacturers
  • emulate the foreign in their improvements, and work up every home
  • commodity to the utmost perfection of which it is susceptible. Their
  • own steel and iron, in such laborious hands, becomes equal to the gold
  • and rubies of the Indies.
  • When the affairs of the society are once brought to this situation, a
  • nation may lose most of its foreign trade, and yet continue a great and
  • powerful people. If strangers will not take any particular commodity
  • of ours, we must cease to labour in it. The same hands will turn
  • themselves towards some refinement in other commodities which may be
  • wanted at home. And there must always be materials for them to
  • work upon; till every person in the state, who possesses riches, enjoys
  • as great plenty of home commodities, and those in as great perfection,
  • as he desires; which can never possibly happen. China is represented as
  • one of the most flourishing empires in the world, though it has very
  • little commerce beyond its own territories.
  • It will not, I hope, be considered as a superfluous digression, if I
  • here observe, that as the multitude of mechanical arts is advantageous,
  • so is the great number of persons to whose share the productions of
  • these arts fall. A too great disproportion among the citizens weakens
  • any state. Every person, if possible, ought to enjoy the fruits of his
  • labour, in a full possession of all the necessaries, and many of the
  • conveniences of life. No one can doubt but such an equality is most
  • suitable to human nature, and diminishes much less from the happiness
  • of the rich than it adds to that of the poor. It also augments the
  • power of the state, and makes any extraordinary taxes or impositions
  • be paid with much more cheerfulness. Where the riches are engrossed by
  • a few, these must contribute very largely to the supplying the public
  • necessities. But when the riches are dispersed among multitudes, the
  • burden feels light on every shoulder, and the taxes make not a very
  • sensible difference on any one’s way of living.
  • Add to this, that where the riches are in few hands these must enjoy
  • all the power, and will readily conspire to lay the whole burden on
  • the poor, and oppress them still farther, to the discouragement of all
  • industry.
  • In this circumstance consists the great advantage of England above
  • any nation at present in the world, or that appears in the records of
  • story. It is true, the English feel some disadvantages in foreign trade
  • by the high price of labour, which is in part the effect of the riches
  • of their artisans, as well as of the plenty of money; but as foreign
  • trade is not the most material circumstance, it is not to be put in
  • competition with the happiness of so many millions. And if there were
  • no more to endear to them that free government under which they
  • live, this alone were sufficient. The poverty of the common people is
  • a natural, if not an infallible effect of absolute monarchy; though I
  • doubt whether it be always true, on the other hand, that their riches
  • are an infallible result of liberty. Liberty must be attended with
  • particular accidents, and a certain turn of thinking, in order to
  • produce that effect. Lord Bacon, accounting for the great advantages
  • obtained by the English in their wars with France, ascribes them
  • chiefly to the superior ease and plenty of the common people amongst
  • the former; yet the governments of the two kingdoms were, at that time,
  • pretty much alike. Where the labourers and artisans are accustomed to
  • work for low wages, and to retain but a small part of the fruits of
  • their labour, it is difficult for them, even in a free government,
  • to better their condition, or conspire among themselves to heighten
  • their wages. But even where they are accustomed to a more plentiful
  • way of life, it is easy for the rich, in a despotic government, to
  • conspire against them, and throw the whole burden of the taxes on their
  • shoulders.
  • It may seem an odd position, that the poverty of the common people in
  • France, Italy, and Spain is, in some measure, owing to the superior
  • riches of the soil and happiness of the climate; and yet there want
  • not many reasons to justify this paradox. In such a fine mould or soil
  • as that of those more southern regions, agriculture is an easy art;
  • and one man, with a couple of sorry horses, will be able, in a season,
  • to cultivate as much land as will pay a pretty considerable rent to
  • the proprietor. All the art, which the farmer knows, is to leave his
  • ground fallow for a year, so soon as it is exhausted; and the warmth
  • of the sun alone and temperature of the climate enrich it, and restore
  • its fertility. Such poor peasants, therefore, require only a simple
  • maintenance for their labour. They have no stock nor riches, which
  • claim more; and at the same time, they are for ever dependent on their
  • landlord, who gives no leases, nor fears that his land will be spoiled
  • by the ill methods of cultivation. In England, the land is rich, but
  • coarse; must be cultivated at a great expense; and produces
  • slender crops, when not carefully managed, and by a method which
  • gives not the full profit but in a course of several years. A farmer,
  • therefore, in England must have a considerable stock and a long lease;
  • which beget proportional profits. The fine vineyards of Champagne and
  • Burgundy, that oft yield to the landlord above five pounds per acre,
  • are cultivated by peasants who have scarce bread; and the reason is,
  • that such peasants need no stock but their own limbs, with instruments
  • of husbandry which they can buy for twenty shillings. The farmers are
  • commonly in some better circumstances in those countries; but the
  • graziers are most at their ease of all those who cultivate the land.
  • The reason is still the same. Men must have profits proportionable to
  • their expense and hazard. Where so considerable a number of labouring
  • poor as the peasants and farmers are in very low circumstances, all
  • the rest must partake of their poverty whether the government of that
  • nation be monarchical or republican.
  • We may form a similar remark with regard to the general history of
  • mankind. What is the reason why no people living between the tropics
  • could ever yet attain to any art or civility, or reach even any police
  • in their government, and any military discipline; while few nations
  • in the temperate climates have been altogether deprived of these
  • advantages? It is probable that one cause of this phenomenon is the
  • warmth and equality of weather in the torrid zone, which render clothes
  • and houses less requisite for the inhabitants, and thereby remove, in
  • part, that necessity which is the great spur to industry and invention.
  • _Curis acuens mortalia corda._ Not to mention that the fewer goods
  • or possessions of this kind any people enjoy, the fewer quarrels are
  • likely to arise amongst them, and the less necessity will there be for
  • a settled police or regular authority to protect and defend them from
  • foreign enemies, or from each other.
  • NOTES, OF COMMERCE.
  • [7] Monsieur Melon, in his political essay on commerce, asserts that
  • even at present, if you divide France into twenty parts, sixteen are
  • labourers or peasants, two only artisans, one belonging to the law,
  • church, and military, and one merchants, financiers, and bourgeois.
  • This calculation is certainly very erroneous. In France, England, and
  • indeed most parts of Europe, half of the inhabitants live in cities;
  • and even of those who live in the country, a very great number are
  • artisans, perhaps above a third.
  • [8] _Diod. Sic._, lib. 2. This account, I own, is somewhat suspicious,
  • not to say worse, chiefly because this army was not composed of
  • citizens, but of mercenary forces.
  • [9] The more ancient Romans lived in perpetual war with all their
  • neighbours; and in old Latin the term “hostis” expressed both a
  • stranger and an enemy. This is remarked by Cicero; but by him is
  • ascribed to the humanity of his ancestors, who softened, as much as
  • possible, the denomination of an enemy by calling him by the same
  • appellation which signified a stranger. (_De Off._, lib. 2.) It is,
  • however, much more probable, from the manners of the times, that the
  • ferocity of those people was so great as to make them regard all
  • strangers as enemies, and call them by the same name. It is not,
  • besides, consistent with the most common maxims of policy or of nature
  • that any state should regard its public enemies with a friendly eye, or
  • preserve any such sentiments for them as the Roman orator would ascribe
  • to his ancestors. Not to mention that the early Romans really exercised
  • piracy, as we learn from their first treaties with Carthage, preserved
  • by Polybius, lib. 3, and consequently, like the Sallee and Algerine
  • rovers, were actually at war with most nations, and a stranger and an
  • enemy were with them almost synonymous.
  • OF REFINEMENT IN THE ARTS.
  • Luxury is a word of a very uncertain signification, and may be taken
  • in a good as well as in a bad sense. In general, it means great
  • refinement in the gratification of the senses, and any degree of it
  • may be innocent or blameable, according to the age, or country, or
  • condition of the person. The bounds between the virtue and the vice
  • cannot here be fixed exactly, more than in other moral subjects. To
  • imagine that the gratifying any of the senses, or the indulging any
  • delicacy in meats, drinks, or apparel, is in itself a vice, can never
  • enter into a head that is not disordered by the frenzies of enthusiasm.
  • I have, indeed, heard of a monk abroad who, because the windows of
  • his cell opened upon a very noble prospect, made a covenant with his
  • eyes never to turn that way, or receive so sensual a gratification.
  • And such is the crime of drinking champagne or burgundy, preferably to
  • small beer or porter. These indulgences are only vices when they are
  • pursued at the expense of some virtue, as liberality or charity; in
  • like manner as they are follies when for them a man ruins his fortune,
  • and reduces himself to want and beggary. Where they entrench upon no
  • virtue, but leave ample subject whence to provide for friends, family,
  • and every proper object of generosity or compassion, they are entirely
  • innocent, and have in every age been acknowledged such by almost all
  • moralists. To be entirely occupied with the luxury of the table, for
  • instance, without any relish for the pleasures of ambition, study, or
  • conversation, is a mark of gross stupidity, and is incompatible with
  • any vigour of temper or genius. To confine one’s expense entirely
  • to such a gratification, without regard to friends or family, is an
  • indication of a heart entirely devoid of humanity or benevolence. But
  • if a man reserve time sufficient for all laudable pursuits, and money
  • sufficient for all generous purposes, he is free from every
  • shadow of blame or reproach.
  • Since luxury may be considered either as innocent or blameable, one may
  • be surprised at those preposterous opinions which have been entertained
  • concerning it; while men of libertine principles bestow praises even on
  • vicious luxury, and represent it as highly advantageous to society; and
  • on the other hand, men of severe morals blame even the most innocent
  • luxury, and regard it as the source of all the corruptions, disorders,
  • and factions incident to civil government. We shall here endeavour
  • to correct both these extremes, by proving, first, that the ages of
  • refinement are both the happiest and most virtuous; secondly, that
  • wherever luxury ceases to be innocent, it also ceases to be beneficial;
  • and when carried a degree too far, is a quality pernicious, though
  • perhaps not the most pernicious, to political society.
  • To prove the first point, we need but consider the effects of
  • refinement both on private and on public life. Human happiness,
  • according to the most received notions, seems to consist in three
  • ingredients: action, pleasure, and indolence; and though these
  • ingredients ought to be mixed in different proportions, according
  • to the particular dispositions of the person, yet no one ingredient
  • can be entirely wanting without destroying, in some measure, the
  • relish of the whole composition. Indolence or repose, indeed, seems
  • not of itself to contribute much to our enjoyment; but, like sleep,
  • is requisite as an indulgence to the weakness of human nature, which
  • cannot support an uninterrupted course of business or pleasure. That
  • quick march of the spirits which takes a man from himself, and chiefly
  • gives satisfaction, does in the end exhaust the mind, and requires
  • some intervals of repose, which, though agreeable for a moment, yet,
  • if prolonged, beget a languor and lethargy that destroy all enjoyment.
  • Education, custom, and example have a mighty influence in turning the
  • mind to any of these pursuits; and it must be owned, that where they
  • promote a relish for action and pleasure, they are so far favourable
  • to human happiness. In times when industry and arts flourish,
  • men are kept in perpetual occupation, and enjoy, as their reward, the
  • occupation itself, as well as those pleasures which are the fruits of
  • their labour. The mind acquires new vigour; enlarges its powers and
  • faculties; and by an assiduity in honest industry, both satisfies its
  • natural appetites and prevents the growth of unnatural ones, which
  • commonly spring up when nourished with ease and idleness. Banish those
  • arts from society, you deprive men both of action and of pleasure; and
  • leaving nothing but indolence in their place, you even destroy the
  • relish of indolence, which never is agreeable but when it succeeds to
  • labour, and recruits the spirits, exhausted by too much application and
  • fatigue.
  • Another advantage of industry and of refinements in the mechanical arts
  • is that they commonly produce some refinements in the liberal; nor can
  • the one be carried to perfection without being accompanied, in some
  • degree, with the other. The same age which produces great philosophers
  • and politicians, renowned generals and poets, usually abounds with
  • skilful weavers and ship-carpenters. We cannot reasonably expect that a
  • piece of woollen cloth will be wrought to perfection in a nation which
  • is ignorant of astronomy, or where ethics are neglected. The spirit of
  • the age affects all the arts; and the minds of men, being once roused
  • from their lethargy and put into a fermentation, turn themselves on
  • all sides, and carry improvements into every art and science. Profound
  • ignorance is totally banished, and men enjoy the privilege of rational
  • creatures, to think as well as to act, to cultivate the pleasures of
  • the mind as well as those of the body.
  • The more these refined arts advance, the more sociable do men become;
  • nor is it possible that, when enriched with science and possessed of a
  • fund of conversation, they should be contented to remain in solitude,
  • or live with their fellow-citizens in that distant manner which is
  • peculiar to ignorant and barbarous nations. They flock into cities;
  • love to receive and communicate knowledge; to show their wit
  • or their breeding; their taste in conversation or living, in clothes
  • or furniture. Curiosity allures the wise; vanity the foolish; and
  • pleasure both. Particular clubs and societies are everywhere formed,
  • both sexes meet in an easy and sociable manner, and the tempers of
  • men, as well as their behaviour, refine apace. So that, besides the
  • improvements which they receive from knowledge and the liberal arts, it
  • is impossible but they must feel an increase of humanity from the very
  • habit of conversing together and contributing to each other’s pleasure
  • and entertainment. Thus industry, knowledge, and humanity are linked
  • together by an indissoluble chain, and are found, from experience as
  • well as reason, to be peculiar to the more polished, and, what are
  • commonly denominated, the more luxurious ages.
  • Nor are these advantages attended with disadvantages which bear
  • any proportion to them. The more men refine upon pleasure the less
  • will they indulge in excesses of any kind, because nothing is more
  • destructive to true pleasure than such excesses. One may safely affirm
  • that the Tartars are oftener guilty of beastly gluttony when they
  • feast on their dead horses than European courtiers with all their
  • refinements of cookery. And if libertine love, or even infidelity to
  • the marriage-bed, be more frequent in polite ages, when it is often
  • regarded only as a piece of gallantry, drunkenness, on the other hand,
  • is much less common—a vice more odious and more pernicious both to
  • mind and body. And in this matter I would appeal not only to an Ovid
  • or a Petronius, but to a Seneca or a Cato. We know that Cæsar, during
  • Catiline’s conspiracy, being necessitated to put into Cato’s hands a
  • _billet-doux_ which discovered an intrigue with Servilia, Cato’s own
  • sister, that stern philosopher threw it back to him with indignation,
  • and, in the bitterness of his wrath, gave him the appellation of
  • drunkard, as a term more opprobrious than that with which he could more
  • justly have reproached him.
  • But industry, knowledge, and humanity are not advantageous in private
  • life alone; they diffuse their beneficial influence on the public,
  • and render the government as great and flourishing as they make
  • individuals happy and prosperous. The increase and consumption of all
  • the commodities which serve to the ornament and pleasure of life are
  • advantageous to society, because at the same time that they multiply
  • those innocent gratifications to individuals, they are a kind of
  • storehouse of labour, which, in the exigencies of state, may be turned
  • to the public service. In a nation where there is no demand for such
  • superfluities men sink into indolence, lose all the enjoyment of life,
  • and are useless to the public, which cannot maintain nor support its
  • fleets and armies from the industries of such slothful members.
  • The bounds of all the European kingdoms are at present pretty near the
  • same they were two hundred years ago; but what a difference is there
  • in the power and grandeur of those kingdoms! Which can be ascribed to
  • nothing but the increase of art and industry. When Charles VIII. of
  • France invaded Italy, he carried with him about 20,000 men; and yet
  • this armament so exhausted the nation, as we learn from Guicciardin,
  • that for some years it was not able to make so great an effort.
  • The late King of France, in time of war, kept in pay above 400,000
  • men,​[10] though from Mazarin’s death to his own he was engaged in a
  • course of wars that lasted near thirty years.
  • This industry is much promoted by the knowledge inseparable from the
  • ages of art and refinement; as, on the other hand, this knowledge
  • enables the public to make the best advantage of the industry of its
  • subjects. Laws, order, police, discipline—these can never be carried
  • to any degree of perfection before human reason has refined itself by
  • exercise, and by an application to the more vulgar arts, at least, of
  • commerce and manufactures. Can we expect that a government will be
  • well modelled by a people who know not how to make a spinning-wheel,
  • or to employ a loom to advantage? Not to mention that all ignorant
  • ages are infested with superstition, which throws the government
  • off its bias, and disturbs men in the pursuit of their interest and
  • happiness.
  • Knowledge in the arts of government naturally begets mildness and
  • moderation, by instructing men in the advantages of humane maxims above
  • rigour and severity, which drive subjects into rebellion, and render
  • the return to submission impracticable, by cutting off all hopes of
  • pardon. When the tempers of men are softened as well as their knowledge
  • improved, this humanity appears still more conspicuous, and is the
  • chief characteristic which distinguishes a civilized age from times of
  • barbarity and ignorance. Factions are then less inveterate, revolutions
  • less tragical, authority less severe, and seditions less frequent. Even
  • foreign wars abate of their cruelty; and after the field of battle,
  • where honour and interest steel men against compassion as well as fear,
  • the combatants divest themselves of the brute, and resume the man.
  • Nor need we fear that men, by losing their ferocity, will lose their
  • martial spirit, or become less undaunted and vigorous in defence
  • of their country or their liberty. The arts have no such effect in
  • enervating either the mind or body. On the contrary, industry, their
  • inseparable attendant, adds new force to both. And if anger, which is
  • said to be the whetstone of courage, loses somewhat of its asperity
  • by politeness and refinement, a sense of honour, which is a stronger,
  • more constant, and more governable principle, acquires fresh vigour
  • by that elevation of genius which arises from knowledge and a good
  • education. Add to this that courage can neither have any duration nor
  • be of any use when not accompanied with discipline and martial skill,
  • which are seldom found among a barbarous people. The ancients remarked
  • that Datames was the only barbarian that ever knew the art of war.
  • And Pyrrhus, seeing the Romans marshal their army with some art and
  • skill, said with surprise, “These barbarians have nothing barbarous
  • in their discipline!” It is observable that as the old Romans, by
  • applying themselves solely to war, were the only uncivilized
  • people that ever possessed military discipline, so the Italians are the
  • only civilized people among Europeans that ever wanted courage and a
  • martial spirit. Those who would ascribe this effeminacy of the Italians
  • to their luxury or politeness, or application to the arts, need but
  • consider the French and English, whose bravery is as incontestable as
  • their love for luxury and their assiduity in commerce. The Italian
  • historians give us a more satisfactory reason for this degeneracy of
  • their countrymen. They show us how the sword was dropped at once by
  • all the Italian sovereigns; while the Venetian aristocracy was jealous
  • of its subjects, the Florentine democracy applied itself entirely to
  • commerce; Rome was governed by priests, and Naples by women. War then
  • became the business of soldiers of fortune, who spared one another,
  • and, to the astonishment of the world, could engage a whole day in what
  • they called a battle, and return at night to their camp without the
  • least bloodshed.
  • What has chiefly induced severe moralists to declaim against refinement
  • in the arts is the example of ancient Rome, which, joining to its
  • poverty and rusticity, virtue and public spirit, rose to such a
  • surprising height of grandeur and liberty; but having learned from
  • its conquered provinces the Asiatic luxury, fell into every kind of
  • corruption, whence arose sedition and civil wars, attended at last
  • with the total loss of liberty. All the Latin classics, whom we peruse
  • in our infancy, are full of these sentiments, and universally ascribe
  • the ruin of their state to the arts and riches imported from the East:
  • insomuch that Sallust represents a taste for painting as a vice no less
  • than lewdness and drinking. And so popular were these sentiments during
  • the latter ages of the republic, that this author abounds in praises of
  • the old rigid Roman virtue, though himself the most egregious instance
  • of modern luxury and corruption; speaks contemptuously of the Grecian
  • eloquence, though the most eloquent writer in the world; nay, employs
  • preposterous digressions and declamations to this purpose, though a
  • model of taste and correctness.
  • But it would be easy to prove that these writers mistook the cause of
  • the disorders in the Roman state, and ascribed to luxury and the arts
  • what really proceeded from an ill-modelled government and the unlimited
  • extent of conquests. Refinement on the pleasures and conveniences
  • of life has no natural tendency to beget venality and corruption.
  • The value which all men put upon any particular pleasure depends on
  • comparison and experience; nor is a porter less greedy of money, which
  • he spends on bacon and brandy, than a courtier, who purchases champagne
  • and ortolans. Riches are valuable at all times, and to all men, because
  • they always purchase pleasures such as men are accustomed to and
  • desire; nor can anything restrain or regulate the love of money but a
  • sense of honour and virtue, which, if it be not nearly equal at all
  • times, will naturally abound most in ages of knowledge and refinement.
  • Of all European kingdoms, Poland seems the most defective in the arts
  • of war, as well as peace, mechanical as well as liberal; and yet it is
  • there that venality and corruption do most prevail. The nobles seem to
  • have preserved their crown elective for no other purpose but regularly
  • to sell it to the highest bidder; this is almost the only species of
  • commerce with which that people are acquainted.
  • The liberties of England, so far from decaying since the improvements
  • in the arts, have never flourished so much as during that period. And
  • though corruption may seem to increase of late years, this is chiefly
  • to be ascribed to our established liberty, when our princes have found
  • the impossibility of governing without parliaments, or of terrifying
  • parliaments by the phantom of prerogative. Not to mention that this
  • corruption or venality prevails infinitely more among the electors than
  • the elected, and therefore cannot justly be ascribed to any refinements
  • in luxury.
  • If we consider the matter in a proper light, we shall find that
  • improvements in the arts are rather favourable to liberty, and have a
  • natural tendency to preserve, if not produce a free government.
  • In rude, unpolished nations, where the arts are neglected, all the
  • labour is bestowed on the cultivation of the ground; and the whole
  • society is divided into two classes—proprietors of land and their
  • vassals or tenants. The latter are necessarily dependent, and fitted
  • for slavery and subjection; especially where they possess no riches,
  • and are not valued for their knowledge in agriculture, as must always
  • be the case where the arts are neglected. The former naturally erect
  • themselves into petty tyrants, and must either submit to an absolute
  • master for the sake of peace and order, or if they will preserve
  • their independency, like the ancient barons, they must fall into
  • feuds and contests among themselves, and throw the whole society into
  • such confusion as is perhaps worse than the most despotic government.
  • But where luxury nourishes commerce and industry, the peasants, by a
  • proper cultivation of the land, become rich and independent; while
  • the tradesmen and merchants acquire a share of the property, and draw
  • authority and consideration to that middling rank of men, who are the
  • best and firmest basis of public liberty. These submit not to slavery,
  • like the poor peasants, from poverty and meanness of spirit; and having
  • no hopes of tyrannizing over others, like the barons, they are not
  • tempted, for the sake of that gratification, to submit to the tyranny
  • of their sovereign. They covet equal laws, which may secure their
  • property, and preserve them from monarchical as well as aristocratical
  • tyranny.
  • The House of Commons is the support of our popular government, and
  • all the world acknowledges that it owed its chief influence and
  • consideration to the increase of commerce, which threw such a balance
  • of property into the hands of the commons. How inconsistent then is it
  • to blame so violently a refinement in the arts, and to represent it as
  • the bane of liberty and public spirit!
  • To declaim against present times, and magnify the virtue of remote
  • ancestors, is a propensity almost inherent in human nature: and as
  • the sentiments and opinions of civilized ages alone are transmitted
  • to posterity, hence it is that we meet with so many severe judgments
  • pronounced against luxury, and even science; and hence it is that at
  • present we give so ready an assent to them. But the fallacy is easily
  • perceived from comparing different nations that are contemporaries,
  • where we both judge more impartially and can better set in opposition
  • those manners with which we are sufficiently acquainted. Treachery
  • and cruelty, the most pernicious and most odious of all vices, seem
  • peculiar to uncivilized ages; and by the refined Greeks and Romans were
  • ascribed to all the barbarous nations which surrounded them. They might
  • justly, therefore, have presumed that their own ancestors, so highly
  • celebrated, possessed no greater virtue, and were as much inferior to
  • their posterity in honour and humanity as in taste and science. An
  • ancient Frank or Saxon may be highly extolled; but I believe every man
  • would think his life or fortune much less secure in the hands of a Moor
  • or Tartar than in those of a French or English gentleman, the rank of
  • men the most civilized in the most civilized nations.
  • We come now to the second position which we proposed to illustrate—viz.,
  • that as innocent luxury, or a refinement in the arts and conveniences
  • of life, is advantageous to the public, so, wherever luxury ceases to
  • be innocent, it also ceases to be beneficial; and when carried a degree
  • farther, begins to be a quality pernicious, though perhaps not the most
  • pernicious, to political society.
  • Let us consider what we call vicious luxury. No gratification,
  • however sensual, can of itself be esteemed vicious. A gratification
  • is only vicious when it engrosses all a man’s expense, and leaves no
  • ability for such acts of duty and generosity as are required by his
  • situation and fortune. Suppose that he correct the vice, and employ
  • part of his expense in the education of his children, in the support
  • of his friends, and in relieving the poor, would any prejudice result
  • to society? On the contrary, the same consumption would arise, and
  • that labour which at present is employed only in producing a slender
  • gratification to one man, would relieve the necessitous, and bestow
  • satisfaction on hundreds. The same care and toil which raise a dish of
  • peas at Christmas would give bread to a whole family during six months.
  • To say that, without a vicious luxury, the labour would not have been
  • employed at all, is only to say that there is some other defect in
  • human nature, such as indolence, selfishness, inattention to others,
  • for which luxury in some measure provides a remedy, as one poison may
  • be an antidote to another. But virtue, like wholesome food, is better
  • than poisons, however corrected.
  • Suppose the same number of men that are at present in Britain, with
  • the same soil and climate: I ask, is it not possible for them to be
  • happier, by the most perfect way of life which can be imagined, and
  • by the greatest reformation which Omnipotence itself could work in
  • their temper and disposition? To assert that they cannot appears
  • evidently ridiculous. As the land is able to maintain more than all its
  • inhabitants, they could never, in such a Utopian state, feel any other
  • ills than those which arise from bodily sickness; and these are not the
  • half of human miseries. All other ills spring from some vice, either
  • in ourselves or others; and even many of our diseases proceed from the
  • same origin. Remove the vices, and the ills follow. You must only take
  • care to remove all the vices. If you remove part, you may render the
  • matter worse. By banishing vicious luxury, without curing sloth and an
  • indifference to others, you only diminish industry in the state, and
  • add nothing to men’s charity or their generosity. Let us, therefore,
  • rest contented with asserting that two opposite vices in a state may
  • be more advantageous than either of them alone; but let us never
  • pronounce vice in itself advantageous. Is it not very inconsistent for
  • an author to assert in one page that moral distinctions are inventions
  • of politicians for public interest, and in the next page maintain that
  • vice is advantageous to the public?​[11] And indeed it seems, upon any
  • system of morality, little less than a contradiction in terms to talk
  • of a vice which is in general beneficial to society.
  • Prodigality is not to be confounded with a refinement in the arts. It
  • even appears that that vice is much less frequent in the cultivated
  • ages. Industry and gain beget frugality, among the lower and middle
  • ranks of men, and in all the busy professions. Men of high rank,
  • indeed, it may be pretended, are more allured by the pleasures, which
  • become more frequent. But idleness is the great source of prodigality
  • at all times, and there are pleasures and vanities in every age, which
  • allure men equally when they are unacquainted with better enjoyments.
  • Not to mention that the high interest paid in rude times quickly
  • consumes the fortunes of the landed gentry, and multiplies their
  • necessities.
  • I thought this reasoning necessary in order to give some light to a
  • philosophical question which has been much disputed in Britain. I call
  • it a philosophical question, not a political one; for whatever may
  • be the consequence of such a miraculous transformation of mankind as
  • would endow them with every species of virtue and free them from every
  • species of vice, this concerns not the magistrate, who aims only at
  • possibilities. He cannot cure every vice by substituting a virtue in
  • its place. Very often he can only cure one vice by another, and in that
  • case he ought to prefer what is least pernicious to society. Luxury,
  • when excessive, is the source of many ills; but it is in general
  • preferable to sloth and idleness, which would commonly succeed in its
  • place, and are more pernicious both to private persons and to the
  • public. When sloth reigns, a mean, uncultivated way of life prevails
  • amongst individuals, without society, without enjoyment. And if the
  • sovereign, in such a situation, demands the service of his subjects,
  • the labour of the state suffices only to furnish the necessaries of
  • life to the labourers, and can afford nothing to those who are employed
  • in the public service.
  • NOTES, OF REFINEMENT IN THE ARTS.
  • [10] The inscription on the Place de Vendôme says 440,000.
  • [11] _Fable of the Bees._
  • OF MONEY.
  • Money is not, properly speaking, one of the subjects of commerce,
  • but only the instrument which men have agreed upon to facilitate
  • the exchange of one commodity for another. It is none of the wheels
  • of trade; it is the oil which renders the motion of the wheels more
  • smooth and easy. If we consider any one kingdom by itself, it is
  • evident that the greater or less plenty of money is of no consequence,
  • since the prices of commodities are always proportioned to the plenty
  • of money, and a crown in Henry VII.’s time served the same purpose
  • as a pound does at present. It is only the public which draws any
  • advantage from the greater plenty of money, and that only in its wars
  • and negotiations with foreign states. And this is the reason why all
  • rich and trading countries, from Carthage to Britain and Holland,
  • have employed mercenary troops, which they hired from their poorer
  • neighbours. Were they to make use of their native subjects, they would
  • find less advantage from their superior riches, and from their great
  • plenty of gold and silver, since the pay of all their servants must
  • rise in proportion to the public opulence. Our small army in Britain of
  • 20,000 men is maintained at as great expense as a French army thrice
  • as numerous. The English fleet, during the late war, required as much
  • money to support it as all the Roman legions which kept the whole world
  • in subjection during the time of the emperors.​[12]
  • The greater number of people and their greater industry are serviceable
  • in all cases—at home and abroad, in private and in public. But the
  • greater plenty of money is very limited in its use, and may even
  • sometimes be a loss to a nation in its commerce with foreigners.
  • There seems to be a happy concurrence of causes in human affairs which
  • checks the growth of trade and riches, and hinders them from being
  • confined entirely to one people, as might naturally at first be dreaded
  • from the advantages of an established commerce. Where one nation has
  • got the start of another in trade it is very difficult for the latter
  • to regain the ground it has lost, because of the superior industry and
  • skill of the former, and the greater stocks of which its merchants are
  • possessed, and which enable them to trade for so much smaller profits.
  • But these advantages are compensated, in some measure, by the low price
  • of labour in every nation which has not an extensive commerce, and
  • does not very much abound in gold and silver. Manufactures, therefore,
  • gradually shift their places, leaving those countries and provinces
  • which they have already enriched, and flying to others, whither they
  • are allured by the cheapness of provisions and labour, till they have
  • enriched these also and are again banished by the same causes. And, in
  • general, we may observe that the dearness of everything, from plenty
  • of money, is a disadvantage which attends an established commerce, and
  • sets bounds to it in every country by enabling the poorer states to
  • under-sell the richer in all foreign markets.
  • This has made me entertain a great doubt concerning the benefit of
  • banks and paper-credit, which are so generally esteemed advantageous
  • to every nation. That provisions and labour should become dear by the
  • increase of trade and money is, in many respects, an inconvenience;
  • but an inconvenience that is unavoidable, and the effect of that
  • public wealth and prosperity which are the end of all our wishes. It
  • is compensated by the advantages which we reap from the possession of
  • these precious metals, and the weight which they give the nation in
  • all foreign wars and negotiations. But there appears no reason for
  • increasing that inconvenience by a counterfeit money, which foreigners
  • will not accept in any payment, and which any great disorder in the
  • state will reduce to nothing. There are, it is true, many people in
  • every rich state who, having large sums of money, would prefer paper
  • with good security, as being of more easy transport and more safe
  • custody. If the public provide not a bank, private bankers will take
  • advantage of this circumstance; as the goldsmiths formerly did in
  • London, or as the bankers do at present in Dublin; and therefore it
  • is better, it may be thought, that a public company should enjoy the
  • benefit of the paper-credit which always will have place in every
  • opulent kingdom. But to endeavour artificially to increase such a
  • credit can never be the interest of any trading nation; but must lay
  • them under disadvantages, by increasing money beyond its natural
  • proportion to labour and commodities, and thereby heightening their
  • price to the merchant and manufacturer. And in this view, it must be
  • allowed that no bank could be more advantageous than such a one as
  • locked up all the money it received,​[13] and never augmented the
  • circulating coin, as is usual, by returning part of its treasure into
  • commerce. A public bank by this expedient might cut off much of the
  • dealings of private bankers and money-jobbers; and though the state
  • bore the charge of salaries to the directors and tellers of this
  • bank (for, according to the preceding supposition, it would have no
  • profit from its dealings), the national advantage, resulting from the
  • low price of labour and the destruction of paper-credit, would be a
  • sufficient compensation. Not to mention that so large a sum, lying
  • ready at command, would be a great convenience in times of public
  • danger and distress; and what part of it was used might be replaced at
  • leisure, when peace and tranquillity were restored to the nation.
  • But of this subject of paper-credit we shall treat more largely
  • hereafter, and I shall finish this essay on money by proposing and
  • explaining two observations, which may perhaps serve to employ the
  • thoughts of our speculative politicians, for to these only I all along
  • address myself. It is enough that I submit to the ridicule sometimes in
  • this age attached to the character of a philosopher, without adding to
  • it that which belongs to a projector.
  • It was a shrewd observation of Anacharsis the Scythian, who had never
  • seen money in his own country, that gold and silver seemed to him of
  • no use to the Greeks but to assist them in numeration and arithmetic.
  • It is indeed evident that money is nothing but the representation
  • of labour and commodities, and serves only as a method of rating or
  • estimating them. Where coin is in greater plenty, as a greater quantity
  • of it is required to represent the same quantity of goods, it can have
  • no effect, either good or bad, taking a nation within itself; no more
  • than it would make any alteration on a merchant’s books if, instead
  • of the Arabian method of notation, which requires few characters,
  • he should make use of the Roman, which requires a great many. Nay,
  • the greater quantity of money, like the Roman characters, is rather
  • inconvenient, and requires greater trouble both to keep and transport
  • it. But notwithstanding this conclusion, which must be allowed just, it
  • is certain that since the discovery of mines in America industry has
  • increased in all the nations of Europe, except in the possessors of
  • those mines; and this may justly be ascribed, amongst other reasons,
  • to the increase of gold and silver. Accordingly, we find that in every
  • kingdom into which money begins to flow in greater abundance than
  • formerly everything takes a new face; labour and industry gain life,
  • the merchant becomes more enterprising, the manufacturer more diligent
  • and skilful, and even the farmer follows his plough with greater
  • alacrity and attention. This is not easily to be accounted for, if
  • we consider only the influence which a greater abundance of coin has
  • in the kingdom itself, by heightening the price of commodities, and
  • obliging every one to pay a greater number of these little yellow or
  • white pieces for everything he purchases. And as to foreign trade,
  • it appears that great plenty of money is rather disadvantageous, by
  • raising the price of every kind of labour.
  • To account, then, for this phenomenon, we must consider that though the
  • high price of commodities be a necessary consequence of the increase
  • of gold and silver, yet it follows not immediately upon that increase;
  • but some time is required before the money circulates through the
  • whole state, and makes its effects be felt on all ranks of people. At
  • first, no alteration is perceived; by degrees the price rises, first
  • of one commodity then of another, till the whole at last reaches
  • a just proportion with the new quantity of specie which is in the
  • kingdom. In my opinion, it is only in this interval or intermediate
  • situation, between the acquisition of money and rise of prices, that
  • the increasing quantity of gold and silver is favourable to industry.
  • When any quantity of money is imported into a nation, it is not at
  • first dispersed into many hands, but is confined to the coffers of a
  • few persons, who immediately seek to employ it to the best advantage.
  • Here are a set of manufacturers or merchants, we shall suppose, who
  • have received returns of gold and silver for goods which they sent to
  • Cadiz. They are thereby enabled to employ more workmen than formerly,
  • who never dream of demanding higher wages, but are glad of employment
  • from such good paymasters. If workmen become scarce, the manufacturer
  • gives higher wages, but at first requires an increase of labour;
  • and this is willingly submitted to by the artisan, who can now eat
  • and drink better, to compensate his additional toil and fatigue. He
  • carries his money to market, where he finds everything at the same
  • price as formerly, but returns with greater quantity and of better
  • kinds, for the use of his family. The farmer and gardener, finding
  • that all commodities are taken off, apply themselves with alacrity
  • to the raising more; and at the same time can afford to take better
  • and more clothes from their tradesmen, whose price is the same as
  • formerly, and their industry only whetted by so much new gain. It is
  • easy to trace the money in its progress through the whole commonwealth;
  • where we shall find that it must first quicken the diligence of every
  • individual, before it increase the price of labour.
  • And that the specie may increase to a considerable pitch before it have
  • this latter effect appears, amongst other instances, from the frequent
  • operations of the French king on the money; where it was always found
  • that the augmenting the numerary value did not produce a proportional
  • rise of the prices, at least for some time. In the last year of Louis
  • XIV. money was raised three-sevenths, but prices augmented only one.
  • Corn in France is now sold at the same price, or for the same number
  • of livres it was in 1683; though silver was then at thirty livres the
  • mark, and is now at fifty;​[14] not to mention the great addition of
  • gold and silver which may have come into that kingdom since the former
  • period.
  • From the whole of this reasoning we may conclude that it is of no
  • manner of consequence, with regard to the domestic happiness of a
  • state, whether money be in a greater or less quantity. The good
  • policy of the magistrate consists only in keeping it, if possible,
  • still increasing; because, by that means, he keeps alive a spirit of
  • industry in the nation, and increases the stock of labour, in which
  • consists all real power and riches. A nation whose money decreases is
  • actually, at that time, much weaker and more miserable than another
  • nation which possesses no more money but is on the increasing hand.
  • This will be easily accounted for if we consider that the alterations
  • in the quantity of money, either on the one side or the other, are not
  • immediately attended with proportionable alterations in the prices of
  • commodities. There is always an interval before matters be adjusted to
  • their new situation, and this interval is as pernicious to industry
  • when gold and silver are diminishing as it is advantageous when these
  • metals are increasing. The workman has not the same employment from the
  • manufacturer and merchant, though he pays the same price for everything
  • in the market; the farmer cannot dispose of his corn and cattle, though
  • he must pay the same rent to his landlord. The poverty, and beggary,
  • and sloth which must ensue are easily foreseen.
  • The second observation which I proposed to make with regard to money
  • may be explained after the following manner. There are some kingdoms,
  • and many provinces in Europe (and all of them were once in the same
  • condition), where money is so scarce that the landlord can get
  • none at all from his tenants, but is obliged to take his rent in kind,
  • and either to consume it himself, or transport it to places where
  • he may find a market. In those countries the prince can levy few or
  • no taxes but in the same manner; and as he will receive very small
  • benefit from impositions so paid, it is evident that such a kingdom
  • has very little force even at home, and cannot maintain fleets and
  • armies to the same extent as if every part of it abounded in gold and
  • silver.​[15] There is surely a greater disproportion betwixt the force
  • of Germany at present and what it was three centuries ago, than there
  • is in its industry, people, and manufactures. The Austrian dominions
  • in the empire are in general well peopled and well cultivated, and are
  • of great extent, but have not a proportionable weight in the balance
  • of Europe; proceeding, as is commonly supposed, from the scarcity of
  • money. How do all these facts agree with that principle of reason, that
  • the quantity of gold and silver is in itself altogether indifferent?
  • According to that principle, wherever a sovereign has numbers of
  • subjects, and these have plenty of commodities, he should of course be
  • great and powerful, and they rich and happy, independent of the greater
  • or lesser abundance of the precious metals. These admit of divisions
  • and subdivisions to a great extent; and where they would become so
  • small as to be in danger of being lost, it is easy to mix them with a
  • baser metal, as is practised in some countries of Europe, and by that
  • means raise them to a bulk more sensible and convenient. They still
  • serve the same purposes of exchange, whatever their number may be, or
  • whatever colour they may be supposed to have.
  • To these difficulties, I answer that the effect here supposed to flow
  • from scarcity of money really arises from the manners and customs of
  • the inhabitants, and that we mistake, as is too usual, a collateral
  • effect for a cause. The contradiction is only apparent, but it
  • requires some thought and reflection to discover the principles by
  • which we can reconcile reason to experience.
  • It seems a maxim almost self-evident that the prices of everything
  • depend on the proportion between commodities and money, and that any
  • considerable alteration on either of these has the same effect, either
  • of heightening or lowering the prices. Increase the commodities, they
  • become cheaper; increase the money, they rise in their value. As, on
  • the other hand, a diminution of the former and that of the latter have
  • contrary tendencies.
  • It is also evident that the prices do not so much depend on the
  • absolute quantity of commodities and that of money which are in a
  • nation, as in that of the commodities which come or may come to market,
  • and of the money which circulates. If the coin be locked up in chests,
  • it is the same thing with regard to prices as if it were annihilated;
  • if the commodities be hoarded in granaries, a like effect follows. As
  • the money and commodities, in these cases, never meet, they cannot
  • affect each other. Were we, at any time, to form conjectures concerning
  • the price of provisions, the corn which the farmer must reserve for
  • the maintenance of himself and family ought never to enter into the
  • estimation. It is only the overplus, compared to the demand, that
  • determines the value.
  • To apply these principles, we must consider that in the first and more
  • uncultivated ages of any state, ere fancy has confounded her wants
  • with those of nature, men, contented with the productions of their
  • own fields, or with those rude preparations which they themselves can
  • work upon them, have little occasion for exchange, or at least for
  • money, which, by agreement, is the common measure of exchange. The wool
  • of the farmer’s own flock, spun in his own family, and wrought by a
  • neighbouring weaver, who receives his payment in corn or wool, suffices
  • for furniture or clothing. The carpenter, the smith, the mason, the
  • tailor are retained by wages of a like nature; and the landlord
  • himself, dwelling in the neighbourhood, is contented to receive his
  • rent in the commodities raised by the farmer. The greatest part
  • of these he consumes at home, in rustic hospitality; the rest, perhaps,
  • he disposes of for money to the neighbouring town, whence he draws the
  • few materials of his expense and luxury.
  • But after men begin to refine on all these enjoyments, and live not
  • always at home, nor are contented with what can be raised in their
  • neighbourhood, there is more exchange and commerce of all kinds, and
  • more money enters into that exchange. The tradesmen will not be paid in
  • corn, because they want something more than barley to eat. The farmer
  • goes beyond his own parish for the commodities he purchases, and cannot
  • always carry his commodities to the merchant who supplies him. The
  • landlord lives in the capital, or in a foreign country, and demands
  • his rent in gold and silver, which can easily be transported to him.
  • Great undertakers, and manufacturers, and merchants arise in every
  • commodity; and these can conveniently deal in nothing but in specie.
  • And consequently, in this situation of society, the coin enters into
  • many more contracts, and by that means is much more employed than in
  • the former.
  • The necessary effect is, that, provided the money does not increase in
  • the nation, everything must become much cheaper in times of industry
  • and refinement than in rude, uncultivated ages. It is the proportion
  • between the circulating money and the commodities in the market which
  • determines the prices. Goods that are consumed at home, or exchanged
  • with other goods in the neighbourhood, never come to market; they
  • affect not in the least the current specie; with regard to it they
  • are as if totally annihilated; and consequently this method of using
  • them sinks the proportion on the side of the commodities and increases
  • the prices. But after money enters into all contracts and sales, and
  • is everywhere the measure of exchange, the same national cash has a
  • much greater task to perform: all commodities are then in the market;
  • the sphere of circulation is enlarged; it is the same case as if that
  • individual sum were to serve a larger kingdom; and therefore, the
  • proportion being here lessened on the side of the money, everything
  • must become cheaper, and the prices gradually fall.
  • By the most exact computations that have been formed all over Europe,
  • after making allowance for the alteration in the numerary value or
  • the denomination, it is found that the prices of all things have only
  • risen three, or at most, four times, since the discovery of the West
  • Indies. But will any one assert that there is not much more than four
  • times the coin in Europe that was in the fifteenth century and the
  • centuries preceding it? The Spaniards and Portuguese from their mines,
  • the English, French, and Dutch by their African trade, and by their
  • interlopers in the West Indies, bring home six millions a year, of
  • which not above a third part goes to the East Indies. This sum alone
  • in ten years would probably double the ancient stock of money in
  • Europe. And no other satisfactory reason can be given why all prices
  • have not risen to a much more exorbitant height, except that derived
  • from a change of customs and manners. Besides that more commodities
  • are produced by additional industry, the same commodities come more
  • to market after men depart from their ancient simplicity of manners;
  • and though this increase has not been equal to that of money, it has,
  • however, been considerable, and has preserved the proportion between
  • coin and commodities nearer the ancient standard.
  • Were the question proposed, Which of these methods of living in the
  • people, the simple or refined, is most advantageous to the state or
  • public? I should, without much scruple, prefer the latter, in a view to
  • politics at least; and should produce this as an additional reason for
  • the encouragement of trade and manufactures.
  • When men live in the ancient simple manner, and supply all their
  • necessaries from domestic industry or from the neighbourhood, the
  • sovereign can levy no taxes in money from a considerable part of his
  • subjects; and if he will impose on them any burdens, he must take his
  • payment in commodities, with which alone they abound—a method
  • attended with such great and obvious inconveniences, that they need
  • not here be insisted on. All the money he can pretend to raise must be
  • from his principal cities, where alone it circulates; and these, it
  • is evident, cannot afford him so much as the whole state could, did
  • gold and silver circulate through the whole. But besides this obvious
  • diminution of the revenue, there is also another cause of the poverty
  • of the public in such a situation. Not only the sovereign receives less
  • money, but the same money goes not so far as in times of industry and
  • general commerce. Everything is dearer where the gold and silver are
  • supposed equal, and that because fewer commodities come to market, and
  • the whole coin bears a higher proportion to what is to be purchased by
  • it, whence alone the prices of everything are fixed and determined.
  • Here then we may learn the fallacy of the remark, often to be met with
  • in historians, and even in common conversation, that any particular
  • state is weak, though fertile, populous, and well cultivated, merely
  • because it wants money. It appears that the want of money can never
  • injure any state within itself: for men and commodities are the
  • real strength of any community. It is the simple manner of living
  • which here hurts the public, by confining the gold and silver to few
  • hands and preventing its universal diffusion and circulation. On the
  • contrary, industry and refinements of all kinds incorporate it with
  • the whole state, however small its quantity may be; they digest it
  • into every vein, so to speak, and make it enter into every transaction
  • and contract. No hand is entirely empty of it. And as the prices of
  • everything fall by that means, the sovereign has a double advantage: he
  • may draw money by his taxes from every part of the state, and what he
  • receives goes farther in every purchase and payment.
  • We may infer, from a comparison of prices, that money is not more
  • plentiful in China than it was in Europe three centuries ago; but what
  • immense power is that empire possessed of, if we may judge by the civil
  • and military list maintained by it! Polybius tells us that provisions
  • were so cheap in Italy during his time that in some places the
  • stated club​[16] at the inns was a _semis_ a head, little more than a
  • farthing! Yet the Roman power had even then subdued the whole known
  • world. About a century before that period the Carthaginian ambassador
  • said, by way of raillery, that no people lived more sociably amongst
  • themselves than the Romans, for that in every entertainment which, as
  • foreign ministers, they received they still observed the same plate
  • at every table. The absolute quantity of the precious metals is a
  • matter of great indifference. There are only two circumstances of any
  • importance—viz., their gradual increase and their thorough concoction
  • and circulation through the state; and the influence of both these
  • circumstances has been here explained.
  • In the following essay we shall see an instance of a like fallacy as
  • that above mentioned, where a collateral effect is taken for a cause,
  • and where a consequence is ascribed to the plenty of money; though it
  • be really owing to a change in the manners and customs of the people.
  • NOTES, OF MONEY.
  • [12] A private soldier in the Roman infantry had a denarius a day,
  • somewhat less than eightpence. The Roman emperors had commonly 25
  • legions in pay, which, allowing 5000 men to a legion, makes 125,000.
  • (Tacitus, _Ann._ lib. 4.) It is true there were also auxiliaries to
  • the legions, but their numbers are uncertain as well as their pay. To
  • consider only the legionaries, the pay of the private men could not
  • exceed £1,600,000. Now, the Parliament in the last war commonly allowed
  • for the fleet £2,500,000. We have therefore £900,000 over for the
  • officers and other expenses of the Roman legions. There seem to have
  • been but few officers in the Roman armies in comparison of what are
  • employed in all our modern troops, except some Swiss corps. And these
  • officers had very small pay: a centurion, for instance, only double a
  • common soldier. And as the soldiers from their pay (Tacitus, _Ann._
  • lib. 1) bought their own clothes, arms, tents, and baggage, this must
  • also diminish considerably the other charges of the army. So little
  • expensive was that mighty Government, and so easy was its yoke over
  • the world. And, indeed, this is the more natural conclusion from the
  • foregoing calculations; for money, after the conquest of Egypt, seems
  • to have been nearly in as great plenty at Rome as it is at present in
  • the richest of the European kingdoms.
  • [13] This is the case with the bank of Amsterdam.
  • [14] These facts I give upon the authority of Monsieur du Tot in his
  • _Reflexions politiques_, an author of reputation; though I must confess
  • that the facts which he advances on other occasions are often so
  • suspicious as to make his authority less in this matter. However, the
  • general observation that the augmenting the money in France does not at
  • first proportionably augment the prices is certainly just.
  • By the by, this seems to be one of the best reasons which can be given
  • for a gradual and universal augmentation of the money, though it has
  • been entirely overlooked in all those volumes which have been written
  • on that question by Melon, Du Tot, and Paris de Verney. Were all our
  • money, for instance, recoined, and a penny’s worth of silver taken from
  • every shilling, the new shilling would probably purchase everything
  • that could have been bought by the old; the prices of everything
  • would thereby be insensibly diminished; foreign trade enlivened; and
  • domestic industry, by the circulation of a greater number of pounds and
  • shillings, would receive some increase and encouragement. In executing
  • such a project, it would be better to make the new shilling pass for
  • twenty-four half-pence, in order to preserve the illusion, and make it
  • be taken for the same. And as a recoinage of our silver begins to be
  • requisite, by the continual wearing of our shillings and six-pences,
  • it may be doubtful whether we ought to imitate the example in King
  • William’s reign, when the clipped money was raised to the old standard.
  • [15] The Italians gave to the Emperor Maximilian the nickname of
  • Pochi-Danari. None of the enterprises of that prince ever succeeded,
  • for want of money.
  • OF INTEREST.
  • Nothing is esteemed a more certain sign of the flourishing condition
  • of any nation than the lowness of interest; and with reason, though
  • I believe the cause is somewhat different from what is commonly
  • apprehended. The lowness of interest is generally ascribed to the
  • plenty of money; but money, however plentiful, has no other effect, if
  • fixed, than to raise the price of labour. Silver is more common than
  • gold, and therefore you receive a great quantity of it for the same
  • commodities. But do you pay less interest for it? Interest in Batavia
  • and Jamaica is at 10 per cent., in Portugal at 6; though these places,
  • as we may learn from the prices of everything, abound much more
  • in gold and silver than either London or Amsterdam.
  • Were all the gold in England annihilated at once, and one-and-twenty
  • shillings substituted in the place of every guinea, would money be more
  • plentiful and interest lower? No surely; we should only use silver
  • instead of gold. Were gold rendered as common as silver, and silver as
  • common as copper, would money be more plentiful and interest lower?
  • We may assuredly give the same answer. Our shillings would then be
  • yellow, and our halfpence white; and we should have no guineas. No
  • other difference would ever be observed; no alteration on commerce,
  • manufactures, navigation, or interest; unless we imagine that the
  • colour of the metal is of any consequence.
  • Now, what is so visible in these greater variations of scarcity or
  • abundance of the precious metals must hold in all inferior changes.
  • If the multiplying gold and silver fifteen times makes no difference,
  • much less can the doubling or tripling them. All augmentation has no
  • other effect than to heighten the price of labour and commodities; and
  • even this variation is little more than that of a name. In the progress
  • towards these changes the augmentation may have some influence by
  • exciting industry; but after the prices are settled, suitable to the
  • new abundance of gold and silver, it has no manner of influence.
  • An effect always holds proportion with its cause. Prices have risen
  • about four times since the discovery of the Indies, and it is probable
  • that gold and silver have multiplied much more; but interest has not
  • fallen much above a half. The rate of interest, therefore, is not
  • derived from the quantity of the precious metals.
  • Money having merely a fictitious value, arising from the agreement
  • and convention of men, the greater or less plenty of it is of no
  • consequence, if we consider a nation within itself; and the quantity
  • of specie, when once fixed, though never so large, has no other
  • effect than to oblige every one to tell out a greater number of those
  • shining bits of metal for clothes, furniture, or equipage, without
  • increasing any one convenience of life. If a man borrows money
  • to build a house, he then carries home a greater load; because the
  • stone, timber, lead, glass, etc., with the labour of the masons and
  • carpenters, are represented by a greater quantity of gold and silver.
  • But as these metals are considered merely as representations, there
  • can no alteration arise from their bulk or quantity, their weight
  • or colour, either upon their real value or their interest. The same
  • interest, in all cases, bears the same proportion to the sum. And if
  • you lent me so much labour and so many commodities, by receiving 5 per
  • cent. you receive always proportional labour and commodities, however
  • represented, whether by yellow or white coin, whether by a pound or an
  • ounce. It is in vain, therefore, to look for the cause of the fall or
  • rise of interest in the greater or less quantity of gold and silver
  • which is fixed in any nation.
  • High interest arises from three circumstances: A great demand for
  • borrowing; little riches to supply that demand; and great profits
  • arising from commerce. And these circumstances are a clear proof of the
  • small advance of commerce and industry, not of the scarcity of gold
  • and silver. Low interest, on the other hand, proceeds from the three
  • opposite circumstances: A small demand for borrowing; great riches to
  • supply that demand; and small profits arising from commerce. And these
  • circumstances are all connected together, and proceed from the increase
  • of industry and commerce, not of gold and silver. We shall endeavour
  • to prove these points as fully and distinctly as possible, and shall
  • begin with the causes and the effects of a great or small demand for
  • borrowing.
  • When the people have emerged ever so little from a savage state, and
  • their numbers have increased beyond the original multitude, there
  • must immediately arise an inequality of property; and while some
  • possess large tracts of land, others are confined within narrow
  • limits, and some are entirely without any landed property. Those who
  • possess more land than they can labour employ those who possess none,
  • and agree to receive a determinate part of the product. Thus
  • the landed interest is immediately established; nor is there any
  • settled government, however rude, in which affairs are not on this
  • footing. Of these proprietors of land, some must presently discover
  • themselves to be of different tempers from others; and while one would
  • willingly store up the product of his land for futurity, another
  • desires to consume at present what should suffice for many years. But
  • as the spending a settled revenue is a way of life entirely without
  • occupation, men have so much need of somewhat to fix and engage them,
  • that pleasures, such as they are, will be the pursuit of the greatest
  • part of the landholders, and the prodigals amongst them will always
  • be more numerous than the misers. In a state, therefore, where there
  • is nothing but a landed interest, as there is little frugality, the
  • borrowers must be very numerous, and the rate of interest must hold
  • proportion to it. The difference depends not on the quantity of money,
  • but on the habits and manners which prevail. By this alone the demand
  • for borrowing is increased or diminished. Were money so plentiful as
  • to make an egg be sold for sixpence, so long as there are only landed
  • gentry and peasants in the state, the borrowers must be numerous and
  • interest high. The rent for the same farm would be heavier and more
  • bulky, but the same idleness of the landlord, with the higher prices of
  • commodities, would dissipate it in the same time, and produce the same
  • necessity and demand for borrowing.
  • Nor is the case different with regard to the second circumstance which
  • we proposed to consider—viz., the great or little riches to supply
  • this demand. This effect also depends on the habits and ways of living
  • of the people, not on the quantity of gold and silver. In order to
  • have in any state a great number of lenders, it is not sufficient nor
  • requisite that there be great abundance of the precious metals. It is
  • only requisite that the property or command of that quantity which is
  • in the state, whether great or small, should be collected in particular
  • hands, so as to form considerable sums, or compose a great moneyed
  • interest. This begets a number of lenders and sinks the rate of usury;
  • and this, I shall venture to affirm, depends not on the quantity
  • of specie, but on particular manners and customs, which make the specie
  • gather into separate sums or masses of considerable value.
  • For suppose that, by miracle, every man in Britain should have five
  • pounds slipped into his pocket in one night: this would much more than
  • double the whole money that is at present in the kingdom; and yet there
  • would not next day, nor for some time, be any more lenders, nor any
  • variation on the interest. And were there nothing but landlords and
  • peasants in the state, this money, however abundant, could never gather
  • into sums; and would only serve to increase the prices of everything,
  • without any further consequence. The prodigal landlord dissipates it
  • as fast as he receives it; and the beggarly peasant has no means, nor
  • view, nor ambition of obtaining above a bare livelihood. The overplus
  • of borrowers above that of lenders continuing still the same, there
  • will follow no reduction of interest. That depends upon another
  • principle, and must proceed from an increase of industry and frugality,
  • of arts and commerce.
  • Everything useful to the life of man arises from the ground; but few
  • things arise in that condition which is requisite to render them
  • useful. There must, therefore, besides the peasants and the proprietors
  • of land, be another rank of men, who, receiving from the former the
  • rude materials, work them into their proper form, and retain part
  • for their own use and subsistence. In the infancy of society, these
  • contracts betwixt the artisans and the peasants, and betwixt one
  • species of artisans and another, are commonly entered into immediately
  • by the persons themselves, who, being neighbours, are easily acquainted
  • with each other’s necessities, and can lend their mutual assistance
  • to supply them. But when men’s industry increases, and their views
  • enlarge, it is found that the most remote parts of the state can assist
  • each other as well as the more contiguous, and that this intercourse of
  • good offices may be carried on to the greatest extent and intricacy.
  • Hence the origin of merchants, the most useful race of men in the
  • whole society, who serve as agents between those parts of the
  • state that are wholly unacquainted and are ignorant of each other’s
  • necessities. Here are in a city fifty workmen in silk and linen, and a
  • thousand customers; and these two ranks of men, so necessary to each
  • other, can never rightly meet till one man erects a shop, to which all
  • the workmen and all the customers repair. In this province grass rises
  • in abundance: the inhabitants abound in cheese, and butter, and cattle;
  • but want bread and corn, which, in a neighbouring province, are in
  • too great abundance for the use of the inhabitants. One man discovers
  • this. He brings corn from the one province, and returns with cattle;
  • and supplying the wants of both, he is, so far, a common benefactor.
  • As the people increase in numbers and industry, the difficulty of
  • their intercourse increases: the business of the agency or merchandise
  • becomes more intricate, and divides, subdivides, compounds, and mixes
  • to a greater variety. In all these transactions it is necessary, and
  • reasonable, that a considerable part of the commodities and labour
  • should belong to the merchant, to whom, in a great measure, they are
  • owing. And these commodities he will sometimes preserve in kind, or
  • more commonly convert into money, which is their common representation.
  • If gold and silver have increased in the state together with the
  • industry, it will require a great quantity of these metals to represent
  • a great quantity of commodities and labour; if industry alone has
  • increased, the prices of everything must sink, and a very small
  • quantity of specie will serve as a representation.
  • There is no craving or demand of the human mind more constant and
  • insatiable than that for exercise and employment, and this desire
  • seems the foundation of most of our passions and pursuits. Deprive a
  • man of all business and serious occupation, he runs restless from one
  • amusement to another; and the weight and oppression which he feels from
  • idleness is so great that he forgets the ruin which must follow from
  • his immoderate expenses. Give him a more harmless way of employing his
  • mind or body, he is satisfied, and feels no longer that insatiable
  • thirst after pleasure. But if the employment you give him be
  • profitable, especially if the profit be attached to every particular
  • exertion of industry, he has gain so often in his eye that he acquires,
  • by degrees, a passion for it, and knows no such pleasure as that of
  • seeing the daily increase of his fortune. And this is the reason why
  • trade increases frugality, and why, among merchants, there is the same
  • overplus of misers above prodigals as, among the possessors of land,
  • there is the contrary.
  • Commerce increases industry, by conveying it readily from one member
  • of the state to another, and allowing none of it to perish or become
  • useless. It increases frugality, by giving occupation to men, and
  • employing them in the arts of gain, which soon engage their affection
  • and remove all relish for pleasure and expense. It is an infallible
  • consequence of all industrious professions to beget frugality, and make
  • the love of gain prevail over the love of pleasure. Among lawyers and
  • physicians who have any practice there are many more who live within
  • their income than who exceed it, or even live up to it. But lawyers
  • and physicians beget no industry, and it is even at the expense of
  • others they acquire their riches; so that they are sure to diminish the
  • possessions of some of their fellow-citizens as fast as they increase
  • their own. Merchants, on the contrary, beget industry, by serving as
  • canals to convey it through every corner of the state; and at the
  • same time, by their frugality, they acquire great power over that
  • industry, and collect a large property in the labour and commodities
  • which they are the chief instruments in producing. There is no other
  • profession, therefore, except merchandise, which can make the moneyed
  • interest considerable, or, in other words, can increase industry, and,
  • by also increasing frugality, give a great command of that industry to
  • particular members of the society. Without commerce, the state must
  • consist chiefly of landed gentry, whose prodigality and expense make a
  • continual demand for borrowing, and of peasants, who have no sums to
  • supply that demand. The money never gathers into large stocks or sums
  • which can be lent at interest. It is dispersed into numberless
  • hands, who either squander it in idle show and magnificence, or employ
  • it in the purchase of the common necessaries of life. Commerce alone
  • assembles it into considerable sums; and this effect it has merely
  • from the industry which it begets and the frugality which it inspires,
  • independent of that particular quantity of precious metal which may
  • circulate in the state.
  • Thus an increase of commerce, by a necessary consequence, raises a
  • great number of lenders, and by that means produces a lowness of
  • interest. We must now consider how far this increase of commerce
  • diminishes the profits arising from that profession, and gives rise to
  • the third circumstance requisite to produce a lowness of interest.
  • It may be proper to observe on this head that low interest and low
  • profits of merchandise are two events that mutually forward each
  • other, and are both originally derived from that extensive commerce
  • which produces opulent merchants and renders the moneyed interest
  • considerable. Where merchants possess great stocks, whether represented
  • by few or many pieces of metal, it must frequently happen that when
  • they either become tired of business or have heirs unwilling or unfit
  • to engage in commerce, a great deal of these riches will seek an
  • annual and secure revenue. The plenty diminishes the price, and makes
  • the lenders accept of a low interest. This consideration obliges
  • many to keep their stocks in trade, and rather be content with low
  • profits than dispose of their money at an under value. On the other
  • hand, when commerce has become very extensive, and employs very large
  • stocks, there must arise rivalships among the merchants, which diminish
  • the profits of trade, at the same time that they increase the trade
  • itself. The low profits of merchandise induce the merchants to accept
  • more willingly of a low interest, when they leave off business and
  • begin to indulge themselves in ease and indolence. It is needless,
  • therefore, to inquire which of these circumstances—viz., low interest
  • or low profits, is the cause, and which the effect. They both arise
  • from an extensive commerce, and mutually forward each other. No
  • man will accept of low profits where he can have high interest, and
  • no man will accept of low interest where he can have high profits.
  • An extensive commerce, by producing large stocks, diminishes both
  • interest and profits; and is always assisted in its diminution of the
  • one by the proportional sinking of the other. I may add, that as low
  • profits arise from the increase of commerce and industry, they serve
  • in their turn to the further increase of commerce, by rendering the
  • commodities cheaper, encouraging the consumption, and heightening the
  • industry. And thus, if we consider the whole connection of causes and
  • effects, interest is the true barometer of the state, and its lowness
  • is a sign almost infallible of the flourishing of a people. It proves
  • the increase of industry, and its prompt circulation through the whole
  • state, little inferior to a demonstration. And though, perhaps, it may
  • not be impossible but a sudden and a great check to commerce may have
  • a momentary effect of the same kind, by throwing so many stocks out of
  • trade, it must be attended with such misery and want of employment in
  • the poor that, besides its short duration, it will not be possible to
  • mistake the one case for the other.
  • Those who have asserted that the plenty of money was the cause of low
  • interest seem to have taken a collateral effect for a cause, since the
  • same industry which sinks the interest does commonly acquire great
  • abundance of the precious metals. A variety of fine manufactures,
  • with vigilant, enterprising merchants, will soon draw money to a
  • state if it be anywhere to be found in the world. The same cause, by
  • multiplying the conveniences of life and increasing industry, collects
  • great riches into the hands of persons who are not proprietors of
  • land, and produces by that means a lowness of interest. But though
  • both these effects—plenty of money and low interest—naturally arise
  • from commerce and industry, they are altogether independent of each
  • other. For suppose a nation removed into the Pacific Ocean, without
  • any foreign commerce, or any knowledge of navigation: suppose
  • that this nation possesses always the same stock of coin, but is
  • continually increasing in its numbers and industry: it is evident that
  • the price of every commodity must gradually diminish in that kingdom,
  • since it is the proportion between money and any species of goods
  • which fixes their mutual value; and, under the present supposition,
  • the conveniences of life become every day more abundant, without any
  • alteration on the current specie. A less quantity of money, therefore,
  • amongst this people will make a rich man, during the times of industry,
  • than would serve to that purpose in ignorant and slothful ages. Less
  • money will build a house, portion a daughter, buy an estate, support a
  • manufactory, or maintain a family and equipage. These are the uses for
  • which men borrow money, and therefore the greater or less quantity of
  • it in a state has no influence on the interest. But it is evident that
  • the greater or less stock of labour and commodities must have a great
  • influence, since we really and in effect borrow these when we take
  • money upon interest. It is true, when commerce is extended all over the
  • globe the most industrious nations always abound most with the precious
  • metals; so that low interest and plenty of money are in fact almost
  • inseparable. But still it is of consequence to know the principle
  • whence any phenomenon arises, and to distinguish between a cause and
  • a concomitant effect. Besides that the speculation is curious, it
  • may frequently be of use in the conduct of public affairs. At least,
  • it must be owned that nothing can be of more use than to improve, by
  • practice, the method of reasoning on these subjects, which of all
  • others are the most important; though they are commonly treated in the
  • loosest and most careless manner.
  • Another reason of this popular mistake with regard to the cause of
  • low interest seems to be the instance of some nations, where, after a
  • sudden acquisition of money or the precious metals by means of foreign
  • conquest, the interest has fallen not only among them but in all
  • the neighbouring states as soon as that money was dispersed and had
  • insinuated itself into every corner. Thus, interest in Spain
  • fell nearly a half immediately after the discovery of the West Indies,
  • as we are informed by Garcilasso de la Vega; and it has been ever
  • since sinking in every kingdom of Europe. Interest in Rome, after the
  • conquest of Egypt, fell from 6 to 4 per cent., as we learn from Dion.
  • The causes of the sinking of interest upon such an event seem different
  • in the conquering country and in the neighbouring states, but in
  • neither of them can we justly ascribe that effect merely to the
  • increase of gold and silver.
  • In the conquering country it is natural to imagine that this new
  • acquisition of money will fall into a few hands, and be gathered into
  • large sums which seek a secure revenue, either by the purchase of land
  • or by interest; and consequently the same effect follows, for a little
  • time, as if there had been a great accession of industry and commerce.
  • The increase of lenders above the borrowers sinks the interest, and so
  • much the faster if those who have acquired those large sums find no
  • industry or commerce in the state, and no method of employing their
  • money but by lending it at interest. But after this new mass of gold
  • and silver has been digested, and has circulated through the whole
  • state, affairs will soon return to their former situation, while the
  • landlords and new money-holders, living idly, squander above their
  • income, and the former daily contract debt, and the latter encroach on
  • their stock till its final extinction. The whole money may still be in
  • the state, and make itself be felt by the increase of prices, but not
  • being now collected into any large masses or stocks, the disproportion
  • between the borrowers and lenders is the same as formerly, and
  • consequently the high interest returns.
  • Accordingly, we find in Rome that so early as Tiberius’s time interest
  • had again mounted to 6 per cent., though no accident had happened to
  • drain the empire of money. In Trajan’s time money lent on mortgages in
  • Italy bore 6 per cent.; on common securities in Bithynia, 12. And if
  • interest in Spain has not risen to its old pitch, this can be ascribed
  • to nothing but the continuance of the same cause that sunk
  • it—viz., the large fortunes continually made in the Indies, which come
  • over to Spain from time to time and supply the demand of the borrowers.
  • By this accidental and extraneous cause more money is to be lent in
  • Spain—that is, more money is collected into large sums than would
  • otherwise be found in a state where there are so little commerce and
  • industry.
  • As to the reduction of interest which has followed in England, France,
  • and other kingdoms of Europe that have no mines, it has been gradual,
  • and has not proceeded from the increase of money, considered merely in
  • itself, but from the increase of industry, which is the natural effect
  • of the former increase, in that interval, before it raises the price of
  • labour and provisions. For to return to the foregoing supposition, if
  • the industry of England had risen as much from other causes (and that
  • rise might easily have happened though the stock of money had remained
  • the same), must not all the same consequences have followed which we
  • observe at present? The same people would, in that case, be found in
  • the kingdom, the same commodities, the same industry, manufactures, and
  • commerce, and consequently the same merchants with the same stocks—that
  • is, with the same command over labour and commodities, only represented
  • by a smaller number of white or yellow pieces, which, being a
  • circumstance of no moment, would only affect the waggoner, porter, and
  • trunk-maker. Luxury, therefore, manufactures, arts, industry, frugality
  • flourishing equally as at present, it is evident that interest must
  • also have been as low, since that is the necessary result of all these
  • circumstances, so far as they determine the profits of commerce and the
  • proportion between the borrowers and lenders in any state.
  • NOTE, OF INTEREST.
  • [16] Price for a meal.
  • OF THE BALANCE OF TRADE.
  • It is very usual in nations ignorant of the nature of commerce to
  • prohibit the exportation of commodities, and to preserve among
  • themselves whatever they think valuable and useful. They consider not
  • that in this prohibition they act directly contrary to their intention,
  • and that the more is exported of any commodity the more will be raised
  • at home, of which they themselves will always have the first offer.
  • It is well known to the learned that the ancient laws of Athens
  • rendered the exportation of figs criminal, that being supposed a
  • species of fruit so excellent in Attica that the Athenians esteemed it
  • too delicious for the palate of any foreigner; and in this ridiculous
  • prohibition they were so much in earnest that informers were thence
  • called “sycophants” among them, from two Greek words which signify figs
  • and discoverer. There are proofs in many old Acts of Parliament of the
  • same ignorance in the nature of commerce, particularly in the reign
  • of Edward III.; and to this day in France the exportation of corn is
  • almost always prohibited—in order, as they say, to prevent famines,
  • though it is evident that nothing contributes more to the frequent
  • famines which so much distress that fertile country.
  • The same jealous fear with regard to money has also prevailed among
  • several nations, and it required both reason and experience to convince
  • any people that these prohibitions serve to no other purpose than to
  • raise the exchange against them and produce a still greater exportation.
  • These errors, one may say, are gross and palpable; but there still
  • prevails, even in nations well acquainted with commerce, a strong
  • jealousy with regard to the balance of trade, and a fear that all
  • their gold and silver may be leaving them. This seems to me, almost in
  • every case, a very groundless apprehension, and I should as soon
  • dread that all our springs and rivers should be exhausted as that
  • money should abandon a kingdom where there are people and industry. Let
  • us carefully preserve these latter advantages, and we need never be
  • apprehensive of losing the former.
  • It is easy to observe that all calculations concerning the balance
  • of trade are founded on very uncertain facts and suppositions. The
  • custom-house books are allowed to be an insufficient ground of
  • reasoning; nor is the rate of exchange much better, unless we consider
  • it with all nations, and know also the proportion of the several sums
  • remitted, which one may safely pronounce impossible. Every man who has
  • ever reasoned on this subject has always proved his theory, whatever
  • it was, by facts and calculations, and by an enumeration of all the
  • commodities sent to all foreign kingdoms.
  • The writings of Mr. Gee struck the nation with a universal panic when
  • they saw it plainly demonstrated by a detail of particulars that the
  • balance was against them for so considerable a sum as must leave them
  • without a single shilling in five or six years. But luckily twenty
  • years have since elapsed, with an expensive foreign war, and yet it is
  • commonly supposed that money is still more plentiful among us than in
  • any former period.
  • Nothing can be more entertaining on this head than Dr. Swift, an author
  • so quick in discerning the mistakes and absurdities of others. He says,
  • in his _Short View of the State of Ireland_, that the whole cash of
  • that kingdom amounted but to £500,000; that out of this they remitted
  • every year a neat million to England, and had scarce any other source
  • from which they could compensate themselves, and little other foreign
  • trade but the importation of French wines, for which they paid ready
  • money. The consequence of this situation, which must be owned to be
  • disadvantageous, was that in a course of three years the current money
  • of Ireland from £500,000 was reduced to less than two; and at present,
  • I suppose, in a course of thirty years, it is absolutely nothing. Yet I
  • know not how that opinion of the advance of riches in Ireland,
  • which gave the Doctor so much indignation, seems still to continue and
  • gain ground with everybody.
  • In short, this apprehension of the wrong balance of trade appears of
  • such a nature that it discovers itself wherever one is out of humour
  • with the ministry, or is in low spirits; and as it can never be refuted
  • by a particular detail of all the exports which counterbalance the
  • imports, it may here be proper to form a general argument which may
  • prove the impossibility of that event as long as we preserve our people
  • and our industry.
  • Suppose four-fifths of all the money in Britain to be annihilated in
  • one night, and the nation reduced to the same condition, with regard
  • to specie, as in the reigns of the Harrys and Edwards, what would be
  • the consequence? Must not the price of all labour and commodities sink
  • in proportion, and everything be sold as cheap as they were in those
  • ages? What nation could then dispute with us in any foreign market, or
  • pretend to navigate or to sell manufactures at the same price which
  • to us would afford sufficient profit? In how little time, therefore,
  • must this bring back the money which we had lost, and raise us to the
  • level of all the neighbouring nations? where, after we have arrived,
  • we immediately lose the advantage of the cheapness of labour and
  • commodities, and the further flowing in of money is stopped by our
  • fulness and repletion.
  • Again, suppose that all the money of Britain were multiplied fivefold
  • in a night, must not the contrary effect follow? Must not labour and
  • commodities rise to such an exorbitant height that no neighbouring
  • nations could afford to buy from us, while their commodities, on the
  • other hand, became so cheap in comparison that, in spite of all the
  • laws which could be formed, they would be run in upon us, and our money
  • flow out till we come to a level with foreigners, and lose that great
  • superiority of riches which had laid us under such disadvantages?
  • Now, it is evident that the same causes which would correct these
  • exorbitant inequalities, were they to happen miraculously,
  • must prevent their happening in the common course of nature, and must
  • for ever, in all the neighbouring nations, preserve money nearly
  • proportionable to the art and industry of each nation. All water,
  • wherever it communicates, remains always at a level. Ask naturalists
  • the reason: they tell you that were it to be raised in any one place,
  • the superior gravity of that part not being balanced, must depress it
  • till it meets a counterpoise; and that the same cause which redresses
  • the inequality when it happens must for ever prevent it without some
  • violent external operation.​[17]
  • Can one imagine that it had ever been possible, by any laws, or even
  • by any art or industry, to have kept all the money in Spain which the
  • galleons have brought from the Indies? or that all commodities could
  • be sold in France for a tenth of the price which they would yield on
  • the other side of the Pyrenees, without finding their way thither, and
  • draining from that immense treasure? What other reason, indeed, is
  • there why all nations at present gain in their trade with Spain and
  • Portugal, but because it is impossible to heap up money, more than any
  • fluid, beyond its proper level? The sovereigns of these countries have
  • shown that they wanted not inclination to keep their gold and silver to
  • themselves had it been in any degree practicable.
  • But as any body of water may be raised above the level of the
  • surrounding element, if the former has no communication with the
  • latter, so in money, if the communication be cut off by any material
  • or physical impediment (for all laws alone are ineffectual), there
  • may, in such a case, be a very great inequality of money. Thus the
  • immense distance of China, together with the monopolies of our India
  • companies, obstructing the communication, preserve in Europe
  • the gold and silver, especially the latter, in much greater plenty
  • than they are found in that kingdom. But, notwithstanding this great
  • obstruction, the force of the causes above-mentioned is still evident.
  • The skill and ingenuity of Europe in general surpasses perhaps that of
  • China with regard to manual arts and manufactures, yet are we never
  • able to trade thither without great disadvantage; and were it not for
  • the continual recruits which we receive from America, money would very
  • soon sink in Europe and rise in China, till it came nearly to a level
  • in both places. Nor can any reasonable man doubt but that industrious
  • nation, were they as near us as Poland or Barbary, would drain us of
  • the overplus of our specie, and draw to themselves a larger share of
  • the West Indian treasures. We need have no recourse to a physical
  • attraction to explain the necessity of this operation; there is a moral
  • attraction arising from the interests and passions of men which is full
  • as potent and infallible.
  • How is the balance kept in the provinces of every kingdom among
  • themselves but by the force of this principle, which makes it
  • impossible for money to lose its level, and either to rise or sink
  • beyond the proportion of the labour and commodities which is in each
  • province? Did not long experience make people easy on this head, what
  • a fund of gloomy reflections might calculations afford a melancholy
  • Yorkshireman while he computed and magnified the sums drawn to London
  • by taxes, absentees, commodities, and found on comparison the opposite
  • articles so much inferior? And no doubt, had the Heptarchy subsisted in
  • England, the legislature of each state had been continually alarmed by
  • the fear of a wrong balance; and it is probable that the mutual hatred
  • of these states would have been extremely violent on account of their
  • close neighbourhood; they would have loaded and oppressed all commerce
  • by a jealous and superfluous caution. Since the Union has removed the
  • barriers between Scotland and England, which of these nations gains
  • from the other by this free commerce? Or if the former kingdom
  • has received any increase of riches, can it be reasonably accounted for
  • by anything but the increase of its art and industry? It was a common
  • apprehension in England before the Union, as we learn from L’Abbe du
  • Bos, that Scotland would soon drain them of their treasure were an
  • open trade allowed; and on the other side of the Tweed a contrary
  • apprehension prevailed—with what justice in both time has shown.
  • What happens in small portions of mankind must take place in greater.
  • The provinces of the Roman empire no doubt kept their balance with each
  • other, and with Italy, independent of the legislature, as much as the
  • several counties of Britain or the several parishes of each county. And
  • any man who travels over Europe at this day may see by the prices of
  • commodities that money, in spite of the absurd jealousy of princes and
  • states, has brought itself nearly to a level, and that the difference
  • between one kingdom and another is not greater in this respect than it
  • is often between different provinces of the same kingdom. Men naturally
  • flock to capital cities, seaports, and navigable rivers. There we find
  • more men, more industry, more commodities, and consequently more money;
  • but still the latter difference holds proportion with the former, and
  • the level is preserved.​[18]
  • Our jealousy and our hatred of France are without bounds, and the
  • former sentiment at least must be acknowledged very reasonable
  • and well-grounded. These passions have occasioned innumerable barriers
  • and obstructions upon commerce, where we are accused of being commonly
  • the aggressors. But what have we gained by the bargain? We lost the
  • French market for our woollen manufactures, and transferred the
  • commerce of wine to Spain and Portugal, where we buy much worse liquor
  • at a higher price. There are few Englishmen who would not think their
  • country absolutely ruined were French wines sold in England so cheap
  • and in such abundance as to supplant, in some measure, all ale and
  • home-brewed liquors; but would we lay aside prejudice, it would not
  • be difficult to prove that nothing could be more innocent, perhaps
  • advantageous. Each new acre of vineyard planted in France, in order
  • to supply England with wine, would make it requisite for the French
  • to take the produce of an English acre, sown in wheat or barley, in
  • order to subsist themselves; and it is evident that we have thereby got
  • command of the better commodity.
  • There are many edicts of the French King prohibiting the planting of
  • new vineyards, and ordering all those already planted to be grubbed
  • up, so sensible are they in that country of the superior value of corn
  • above every other product.
  • Mareschal Vauban complains often, and with reason, of the absurd duties
  • which load the entry of those wines of Languedoc, Guienne, and other
  • southern provinces that are imported into Brittany and Normandy. He
  • entertained no doubt but these latter provinces could preserve their
  • balance notwithstanding the open commerce which he recommends. And it
  • is evident that a few leagues more navigation to England would make no
  • difference; or if it did, that it must operate alike on the commodities
  • of both kingdoms.
  • There is indeed one expedient by which it is possible to sink, and
  • another by which we may raise, money beyond its natural level in any
  • kingdom; but these cases, when examined, will be found to resolve into
  • our general theory, and to bring additional authority to it.
  • I scarce know any method of sinking money below its level but those
  • institutions of banks, funds, and paper-credit which are so much
  • practised in this kingdom. These render paper equivalent to money,
  • circulate it through the whole state, make it supply the place of gold
  • and silver, raise proportionally the price of labour and commodities,
  • and by that means either banish a great part of those precious metals,
  • or prevent their further increase. What can be more short-sighted than
  • our reasonings on this head? We fancy, because an individual would be
  • much richer were his stock of money doubled, that the same good effect
  • would follow were the money of every one increased, not considering
  • that this would raise as much the price of every commodity, and reduce
  • every man in time to the same condition as before. It is only in our
  • public negotiations and transactions with foreigners that a greater
  • stock of money is advantageous; and as our paper is there absolutely
  • insignificant, we feel, by its means, all the ill effects arising from
  • a great abundance of money without reaping any of the advantages.​[19]
  • Suppose that there are twelve millions of paper which circulate in the
  • kingdom as money (for we are not to imagine that all our enormous funds
  • are employed in that shape), and suppose the real cash of the kingdom
  • to be eighteen millions: here is a state which is found by experience
  • able to hold a stock of thirty millions. I say, if it be able to hold
  • it, it must of necessity have acquired it in gold and silver had we not
  • obstructed the entrance of these metals by this new invention of paper.
  • Whence would it have acquired that sum? From all the kingdoms of the
  • world. But why? Because, if you remove these twelve millions, money in
  • this state is below its level compared with our neighbours; and
  • we must immediately draw from all of them till we be full and saturate,
  • so to speak, and can hold no more. By our present politics we are as
  • careful to stuff the nation with this fine commodity of bank-bills
  • and chequer notes as if we were afraid of being overburdened with the
  • precious metals.
  • It is not to be doubted but the great plenty of bullion in France is,
  • in a great measure, owing to the want of paper-credit. The French have
  • no banks; merchants’ bills do not there circulate as with us; usury or
  • lending on interest is not directly permitted, so that many have large
  • sums in their coffers; great quantities of plate are used in private
  • houses, and all the churches are full of it. By this means provision
  • and labour still remain much cheaper among them than in nations that
  • are not half so rich in gold and silver. The advantages of this
  • situation in point of trade, as well as in great public emergencies,
  • are too evident to be disputed.
  • The same fashion a few years ago prevailed in Genoa which still has
  • place in England and Holland, of using services of china ware instead
  • of plate; but the Senate, wisely foreseeing the consequence, prohibited
  • the use of that brittle commodity beyond a certain extent, while the
  • use of silver plate was left unlimited. And I suppose, in their late
  • distresses, they felt the good effect of this ordinance. Our tax on
  • plate is, perhaps, in this view, somewhat impolitic.
  • Before the introduction of paper-money into our colonies, they had gold
  • and silver sufficient for their circulation. Since the introduction of
  • that commodity, the least inconveniency that has followed is the total
  • banishment of the precious metals. And after the abolition of paper,
  • can it be doubted but money will return, while these colonies possess
  • manufactures and commodities, the only thing valuable in commerce, and
  • for whose sake alone all men desire money?
  • What pity Lycurgus did not think of paper-credit when he wanted to
  • banish gold and silver from Sparta! It would have served his
  • purpose better than the lumps of iron he made use of as money, and
  • would also have prevented more effectually all commerce with strangers,
  • as being of so much less real and intrinsic value.
  • It must, however, be confessed that, as all these questions of trade
  • and money are extremely complicated, there are certain lights in
  • which this subject may be placed so as to represent the advantages of
  • paper-credit and banks to be superior to their disadvantages. That they
  • banish specie and bullion from a state is undoubtedly true, and whoever
  • looks no farther than this circumstance does well to condemn them; but
  • specie and bullion are not of so great consequence as not to admit of
  • a compensation, and even an overbalance from the increase of industry
  • and of credit which may be promoted by the right use of paper-money.
  • It is well known of what advantage it is to a merchant to be able to
  • discount his bills upon occasion; and everything that facilitates this
  • species of traffic is favourable to the general commerce of a state.
  • But private bankers are enabled to give such credit by the credit they
  • receive from the depositing of money in their shops; and the Bank of
  • England in the same manner, from the liberty they have to issue their
  • notes in all payments. There was an invention of this kind which was
  • fallen upon some years ago by the banks of Edinburgh, and which, as it
  • is one of the most ingenious ideas that has been executed in commerce,
  • has also been found very advantageous to Scotland. It is there called
  • a bank-credit, and is of this nature: A man goes to the bank and finds
  • surety to the amount, we shall suppose, of five thousand pounds. This
  • money, or any part of it, he has the liberty of drawing out whenever
  • he pleases, and he pays only the ordinary interest for it while it
  • is in his hands. He may, when he pleases, repay any sum so small as
  • twenty pounds, and the interest is discounted from the very day of the
  • repayment. The advantages resulting from this contrivance are manifold.
  • As a man may find surety nearly to the amount of his substance, and his
  • bank-credit is equivalent to ready money, a merchant does hereby
  • in a manner coin his houses, his household furniture, the goods in his
  • warehouse, the foreign debts due to him, his ships at sea; and can,
  • upon occasion, employ them in all payments as if they were the current
  • money of the country. If a man borrows five thousand pounds from a
  • private hand, besides that it is not always to be found when required,
  • he pays interest for it whether he be using it or not; his bank-credit
  • costs him nothing except during the very moment in which it is of
  • service to him, and this circumstance is of equal advantage as if he
  • had borrowed money at much lower interest. Merchants likewise from this
  • invention acquire a great facility in supporting each other’s credit,
  • which is a considerable security against bankruptcies. A man, when his
  • own bank-credit is exhausted, goes to any of his neighbours who is not
  • in the same condition, and he gets the money, which he replaces at his
  • convenience.
  • After this practice had taken place during some years at Edinburgh,
  • several companies of merchants at Glasgow carried the matter farther.
  • They associated themselves into different banks and issued notes so
  • low as ten shillings, which they used in all payments for goods,
  • manufactures, tradesmen, labour of all kinds; and these notes, from
  • the established credit of the companies, passed as money in all
  • payments throughout the country. By this means a stock of five thousand
  • pounds was able to perform the same operations as if it were ten,
  • and merchants were thereby enabled to trade to a greater extent, and
  • to require less profit in all their transactions. In Newcastle and
  • Bristol, as well as other trading places, the merchants have since
  • instituted banks of a like nature, in imitation of those in Glasgow.
  • But whatever other advantages result from these inventions, it must
  • still be allowed that they banish the precious metals; and nothing
  • can be a more evident proof of it than a comparison of the past and
  • present condition of Scotland in that particular. It was found, upon
  • the recoinage made after the Union, that there was near a million of
  • specie in that country; but notwithstanding the great increase of
  • riches, commerce and manufactures of all kinds, it is thought that,
  • even where there is no extraordinary drain made by England, the current
  • specie will not now amount to a fifth of that sum.
  • But as our projects of paper-credit are almost the only expedient by
  • which we can sink money below its level, so, in my opinion, the only
  • expedient by which we can raise money above its level is a practice
  • which we should all exclaim against as destructive—viz., the gathering
  • large sums into a public treasure, locking them up, and absolutely
  • preventing their circulation. The fluid not communicating with the
  • neighbouring element may, by such an artifice, be raised to what height
  • we please. To prove this we need only return to our first supposition
  • of the annihilating the half or any part of our cash, where we found
  • that the immediate consequence of such an event would be the attraction
  • of an equal sum from all the neighbouring kingdoms. Nor does there seem
  • to be any necessary bounds set by the nature of things to this practice
  • of hoarding. A small city like Geneva, continuing this policy for ages,
  • might engross nine-tenths of the money of Europe. There seems, indeed,
  • in the nature of man an invincible obstacle to that immense growth
  • of riches. A weak state with an enormous treasure will soon become a
  • prey to some of its poorer but more powerful neighbours; a great state
  • would dissipate its wealth in dangerous and ill-concerted projects,
  • and probably destroy with it what is much more valuable—the industry,
  • morals, and number of its people. The fluid in this case, raised to too
  • great a height, bursts and destroys the vessel that contains it, and
  • mixing itself with the surrounding element, soon falls to its proper
  • level.
  • So little are we commonly acquainted with this principle that, though
  • all historians agree in relating uniformly so recent an event as the
  • immense treasure amassed by Harry VII. (which they make amount to
  • £1,700,000), we rather reject their concurring testimony than admit
  • of a fact which agrees so ill with our inveterate prejudices. It is
  • indeed probable that that sum might be three-fourths of all
  • the money in England; but where is the difficulty that such a sum
  • might be amassed in twenty years by a cunning, rapacious, frugal, and
  • almost absolute monarch? Nor is it probable that the diminution of
  • circulating money was ever sensibly felt by the people, or ever did
  • them any prejudice. The sinking of the prices of all commodities would
  • immediately replace it, by giving England the advantage in its commerce
  • with all the neighbouring kingdoms.
  • Have we not an instance in the small republic of Athens with its
  • allies, who in about fifty years between the Median and Peloponnesian
  • Wars amassed a sum greater than that of Harry VII.?​[20] for all the
  • Greek historians and orators agree that the Athenians collected in the
  • citadel more than 10,000 talents, which they afterwards dissipated,
  • to their own ruin, in rash and imprudent enterprises. But when this
  • money was set a-running, and began to communicate with the surrounding
  • fluid, what was the consequence? Did it remain in the state? No; for
  • we find by the memorable census mentioned by Demosthenes and Polybius
  • that, in about fifty years afterwards, the whole value of the republic,
  • comprehending lands, houses, commodities, slaves, and money was less
  • than 6000 talents.
  • What an ambitious, high-spirited people was this, to collect and keep
  • in their treasury, with a view to conquests, a sum which it was every
  • day in the power of the citizens, by a single vote, to distribute among
  • themselves, and which would go near to triple the riches of every
  • individual; for we must observe that the numbers and private riches of
  • the Athenians are said by ancient writers to have been no greater at
  • the beginning of the Peloponnesian War than at the beginning of the
  • Macedonian.
  • Money was little more plentiful in Greece during the age of Philip
  • and Perseus than in England during that of Harry VII., yet these two
  • monarchs in thirty years collected from the small kingdom of
  • Macedon a much larger treasure than that of the English monarch.
  • Paulus Æmilius brought to Rome about £1,700,000 sterling—Pliny says
  • £2,400,000—and that was but a part of the Macedonian treasure; the rest
  • was dissipated by the resistance and flight of Perseus.
  • We may learn from Stanyan that the Canton of Berne had £300,000 lent
  • at interest, and had above six times as much in their treasury. Here,
  • then, is a sum hoarded of £1,800,000 sterling, which is at least
  • quadruple of what should naturally circulate in such a petty state;
  • and yet no one who travels into the Pais de Vaux, or any part of that
  • canton, observes any want of money more than could be supposed in a
  • country of that extent, soil, and situation. On the contrary, there are
  • scarce any inland provinces in the countries of France or Germany where
  • the inhabitants are at this time so opulent, though that canton has
  • vastly increased its treasure since 1714, the time when Stanyan wrote
  • his judicious account of Switzerland.​[21]
  • The account given by Appian of the treasure of the Ptolemies is so
  • prodigious that one cannot admit of it, and so much the less because
  • the historian says the other successors of Alexander were all so
  • frugal, and had many of them treasures not much inferior; for this
  • saving humour of the neighbouring princes must necessarily have checked
  • the frugality of the Egyptian monarchs, according to the foregoing
  • theory. The sum he mentions is 740,000 talents, or £191,166,666 13s.
  • 4d., according to Dr. Arbuthnot’s computation; and yet Appian says that
  • he extracted his account from the public records, and he was himself a
  • native of Alexandria.
  • From these principles we may learn what judgment we ought to form of
  • those numberless bars, obstructions, and imposts which all nations of
  • Europe, and none more than England, have put upon trade, from an
  • exorbitant desire of amassing money, which never will heap up beyond
  • its level while it circulates; or from an ill-grounded apprehension of
  • losing their specie, which never will sink below it. Could anything
  • scatter our riches, it would be such impolitic contrivances. But this
  • general ill effect, however, results from them, that they deprive
  • neighbouring nations of that free communication and exchange which the
  • Author of the world has intended, by giving them soils, climates, and
  • geniuses so different from each other.
  • Our modern politics embrace the only method of banishing money—the
  • using paper-credit; they reject the only method of amassing it, the
  • practice of hoarding; and they adopt a hundred contrivances which
  • serve to no purpose but to check industry, and rob ourselves and our
  • neighbours of the common benefits of art and nature.
  • All taxes, however, upon foreign commodities are not to be regarded
  • as prejudicial or useless, but those only which are founded on the
  • jealousy above mentioned. A tax on German linen encourages home
  • manufactures, and thereby multiplies our people and industry; a tax on
  • brandy increases the sale of rum, and supports our southern colonies.
  • And as it is necessary imposts should be levied for the support of
  • government, it may be thought more convenient to lay them on foreign
  • commodities, which can easily be intercepted at the port and subjected
  • to the impost. We ought, however, always to remember the maxim of Dr.
  • Swift, that, in the arithmetic of the customs, two and two make not
  • four, but often make only one. It can scarcely be doubted but if the
  • duties on wine were lowered to a third, they would yield much more to
  • the Government than at present; our people might thereby afford to
  • drink commonly a better and more wholesome liquor, and no prejudice
  • would ensue to the balance of trade, of which we are so jealous. The
  • manufacture of ale beyond the agriculture is but inconsiderable, and
  • gives employment to few hands. The transport of wine and corn would not
  • be much inferior.
  • But are there not frequent instances, you will say, of states and
  • kingdoms which were formerly rich and opulent, and are now poor
  • and beggarly? Has not the money left them with which they formerly
  • abounded? I answer, if they lose their trade, industry, and people,
  • they cannot expect to keep their gold and silver, for these precious
  • metals will hold proportion to the former advantages. When Lisbon
  • and Amsterdam got the East India trade from Venice and Genoa, they
  • also got the profits and money which arose from it. Where the seat
  • of government is transferred, where expensive armies are maintained
  • at a distance, where great funds are possessed by foreigners, there
  • naturally follows from these causes a diminution of the specie. But
  • these, we may observe, are violent and forcible methods of carrying
  • away money, and are in time commonly attended with the transport of
  • people and industry; but where these remain, and the drain is not
  • continued, the money always finds its way back again, by a hundred
  • canals of which we have no notion or suspicion. What immense treasures
  • have been spent, by so many nations, in Flanders since the revolution,
  • in the course of three long wars! More money perhaps than the half of
  • what is at present in all Europe. But what has now become of it? Is it
  • in the narrow compass of the Austrian provinces? No, surely; it has
  • most of it returned to the several countries whence it came, and has
  • followed that art and industry by which at first it was acquired. For
  • above a thousand years the money of Europe has been flowing to Rome by
  • an open and sensible current; but it has been emptied by many secret
  • and insensible canals, and the want of industry and commerce renders at
  • present the papal dominions the poorest territories in all Italy.
  • In short, a government has great reason to preserve with care its
  • people and its manufactures. Its money it may safely trust to the
  • course of human affairs, without fear or jealousy; or if it ever give
  • attention to this latter circumstance, it ought only to be so far as it
  • affects the former.
  • NOTES, OF THE BALANCE OF TRADE.
  • [17] There is another cause, though more limited in its operation,
  • which checks the wrong balance of trade, to every particular nation to
  • which the kingdom trades. When we import more goods than we export,
  • the exchange turns against us, and this becomes a new encouragement to
  • export, as much as the charge of carriage and insurance of the money
  • which becomes due would amount to. For the exchange can never rise
  • higher than that sum.
  • [18] It must carefully be remarked that throughout this discourse,
  • wherever I speak of the level of money I mean always its proportional
  • level to the commodities, labour, industry, and skill which is in the
  • several states; and I assert that where these advantages are double,
  • treble, quadruple to what they are in the neighbouring states, the
  • money infallibly will also be double, treble, quadruple. The only
  • circumstance that can obstruct the exactness of these proportions is
  • the expense of transporting the commodities from one place to another,
  • and this expense is sometimes unequal. Thus the corn, cattle, cheese,
  • butter of Derbyshire cannot draw the money of London so much as the
  • manufactures of London draw the money of Derbyshire. But this objection
  • is only a seeming one, for so far as the transport of commodities is
  • expensive, so far is the communication between the places obstructed
  • and imperfect.
  • [19] We observed in essay _Of Money_, that money, when increasing,
  • gives encouragement to industry during the interval between the
  • increase of money and the rise of the prices. A good effect of this
  • nature may follow too from paper-credit; but it is dangerous to
  • precipitate matters at the risk of losing all by the failing of that
  • credit, as must happen upon any violent shock in public affairs.
  • [20] There were about eight ounces of silver in a pound sterling in
  • Harry VII.’s time.
  • [21] The poverty which Stanyan speaks of is only to be seen in the most
  • mountainous cantons, where there is no commodity to bring money; and
  • even there the people are not poorer than in the diocese of Saltsburg
  • on the one hand, or Savoy on the other.
  • OF THE JEALOUSY OF TRADE.
  • Having endeavoured to remove one species of ill-founded jealousy which
  • is so prevalent among commercial nations, it may not be amiss to
  • mention another which seems equally groundless. Nothing is more usual,
  • among states which have made some advances in commerce, than to look on
  • the progress of their neighbours with a suspicious eye, to consider all
  • trading states as their rivals, and to suppose that it is impossible
  • for any of them to flourish but at their expense. In opposition to
  • this narrow and malignant opinion, I will venture to assert that the
  • increase of riches and commerce in any one nation, instead of hurting,
  • commonly promotes the riches and commerce of all its neighbours;
  • and that a state can scarcely carry its trade and industry very far
  • where all the surrounding states are buried in ignorance, sloth, and
  • barbarism.
  • It is obvious that the domestic industry of a people cannot be hurt
  • by the greatest prosperity of their neighbours; and as this branch of
  • commerce is undoubtedly the most important in any extensive kingdom,
  • we are so far removed from all reason of jealousy. But I go farther,
  • and observe that where an open communication is preserved among
  • nations, it is impossible but the domestic industry of every one must
  • receive an increase from the improvements of the others. Compare the
  • situation of Great Britain at present with what it was two centuries
  • ago. All the arts, both of agriculture and manufactures, were then
  • extremely rude and imperfect. Every improvement which we have since
  • made has arisen from our imitation of foreigners, and we ought so far
  • to esteem it happy that they had previously made advances in arts and
  • ingenuity. But this intercourse is still upheld to our great advantage.
  • Notwithstanding the advanced state of our manufactures, we daily
  • adopt in every art the inventions and improvements of our neighbours.
  • The commodity is first imported from abroad, to our great
  • discontent, while we imagine that it drains us of our money; afterwards
  • the art itself is gradually imported, to our visible advantage. Yet we
  • continue still to repine that our neighbours should possess any art,
  • industry, and invention, forgetting that had they not first instructed
  • us we should have been at present barbarians, and did they not still
  • continue their instructions, the arts must fall into a state of
  • languor, and lose that emulation and novelty which contribute so much
  • to their advancement.
  • The increase of domestic industry lays the foundation of foreign
  • commerce. Where a great number of commodities are raised and perfected
  • for the home-market there will always be found some which can be
  • exported with advantage. But if our neighbours have no art nor
  • cultivation, they cannot take them, because they will have nothing to
  • give in exchange. In this respect, states are in the same condition
  • as individuals. A single man can scarce be industrious where all his
  • fellow-citizens are idle. The riches of the several members of a
  • community contribute to increase my riches, whatever profession I may
  • follow. They consume the produce of my industry, and afford me the
  • produce of theirs in return.
  • Nor need any state entertain apprehensions that their neighbours will
  • improve to such a degree in every art and manufacture as to have no
  • demand from them. Nature, by giving a diversity of geniuses, climates,
  • and soils to different nations, has secured their mutual intercourse
  • and commerce, as long as they all remain industrious and civilized.
  • Nay, the more the arts increase in any state, the more will be its
  • demands from its industrious neighbours. The inhabitants, having become
  • opulent and skilful, desire to have every commodity in the utmost
  • perfection; and as they have plenty of commodities to give in exchange,
  • they make large importations from every foreign country. The industry
  • of the nations from whom they import receives encouragement; their own
  • is also increased by the sale of the commodities which they give in
  • exchange.
  • But what if a nation has any staple commodity, such as the woollen
  • manufacture is to England? Must not the interfering of their neighbours
  • in that manufacture be a loss to them? I answer that when any commodity
  • is denominated the staple of a kingdom, it is supposed that that
  • kingdom has some peculiar and natural advantages for raising the
  • commodity; and if, notwithstanding these advantages, they lose such a
  • manufactory, they ought to blame their own idleness or bad government,
  • not the industry of their neighbours. It ought also to be considered
  • that by the increase of industry among the neighbouring nations the
  • consumption of every particular species of commodity is also increased;
  • and though foreign manufactures interfere with us in the market, the
  • demand for our product may still continue, or even increase. And even
  • should it diminish, ought the consequence to be esteemed so fatal? If
  • the spirit of industry be preserved, it may easily be diverted from
  • one branch to another, and the manufactures of wool, for instance, be
  • employed in linen, silk, iron, or other commodities for which there
  • appears to be a demand. We need not apprehend that all the objects
  • of industry will be exhausted, or that our manufacturers, while they
  • remain on an equal footing with those of our neighbours, will be in
  • danger of wanting employment; the emulation among rival nations serves
  • rather to keep industry alive in all of them. And any people is happier
  • who possess a variety of manufactures, than if they enjoyed one single
  • great manufacture, in which they are all employed. Their situation is
  • less precarious, and they will feel less sensibly those revolutions and
  • uncertainties to which every particular branch of commerce will always
  • be exposed.
  • The only commercial state which ought to dread the improvements and
  • industry of their neighbours is such a one as Holland, which enjoying
  • no extent of land, nor possessing any native commodity, flourishes
  • only by being the brokers, and factors, and carriers of others. Such a
  • people may naturally apprehend that as soon as the neighbouring
  • states come to know and pursue their interest, they will take into
  • their own hands the management of their affairs, and deprive their
  • brokers of that profit which they formerly reaped from it. But though
  • this consequence may naturally be dreaded, it is very long before it
  • takes place; and by art and industry it may be warded off for many
  • generations, if not wholly eluded. The advantage of superior stocks
  • and correspondence is so great that it is not easily overcome; and
  • as all the transactions increase by the increase of industry in the
  • neighbouring states, even a people whose commerce stands on this
  • precarious basis may at first reap a considerable profit from the
  • flourishing condition of their neighbours. The Dutch, having mortgaged
  • all their revenues, make not such a figure in political transactions
  • as formerly; but their commerce is surely equal to what it was in the
  • middle of the last century, when they were reckoned among the great
  • powers of Europe.
  • Were our narrow and malignant politics to meet with success, we should
  • reduce all our neighbouring nations to the same state of sloth and
  • ignorance that prevails in Morocco and the coast of Barbary. But what
  • would be the consequence? They could send us no commodities, they could
  • take none from us. Our domestic commerce itself would languish for want
  • of emulation, example, and instruction; and we ourselves should soon
  • fall into the same abject condition to which we had reduced them. I
  • shall therefore venture to acknowledge that not only as a man, but as a
  • British subject, I pray for the flourishing commerce of Germany, Spain,
  • Italy, and even France itself. I am at least certain that Great Britain
  • and all these nations would flourish more did their sovereigns and
  • ministers adopt such enlarged and benevolent sentiments towards each
  • other.
  • OF THE BALANCE OF POWER.
  • It is a question whether the _idea_ of the balance of power be owing
  • entirely to modern policy, or whether the _phrase_ only has been
  • invented in these latter ages. It is certain that Xenophon, in his
  • institution of Cyrus, represents the combination of the Asiatic powers
  • to have arisen from a jealousy of the increasing force of the Medes
  • and Persians; and though that elegant composition should be supposed
  • altogether a romance, this sentiment, ascribed by the author to the
  • Eastern princes, is at least a proof of the prevailing notions of
  • ancient times.
  • In all the politics of Greece the anxiety with regard to the balance
  • of power is most apparent, and is expressly pointed out to us even by
  • the ancient historians. Thucydides represents the league which was
  • formed against Athens, and which produced the Peloponnesian war, as
  • entirely owing to this principle. And after the decline of Athens,
  • when the Thebans and Lacedemonians disputed for sovereignty, we find
  • that the Athenians (as well as many other republics) threw themselves
  • always into the lighter scale, and endeavoured to preserve the balance.
  • They supported Thebes against Sparta, till the great victory gained by
  • Epaminondas at Leuctra, after which they immediately went over to the
  • conquered, from generosity as they pretended, but in reality from their
  • jealousy of the conquerors.
  • Whoever will read Demosthenes’ oration for the Megalopolitans may see
  • the utmost refinements on this principle which ever entered into the
  • head of a Venetian or English speculatist; and upon the first rise of
  • the Macedonian power, this orator immediately discovered the danger,
  • sounded the alarm through all Greece, and at last assembled that
  • confederacy under the banners of Athens which fought the great and
  • decisive battle of Chæronea.
  • It is true the Grecian wars are regarded by historians as wars of
  • emulation rather than of politics, and each state seems to have had
  • more in view the honour of leading the rest than any well-grounded
  • hopes of authority and dominion. If we consider, indeed, the small
  • number of inhabitants in any one republic compared to the whole,
  • the great difficulty of forming sieges in those times, and the
  • extraordinary bravery and discipline of every freeman among that noble
  • people, we shall conclude that the balance of power was of itself
  • sufficiently secured in Greece, and needed not to be guarded with that
  • caution which may be requisite in other ages. But whether we ascribe
  • the shifting sides in all the Grecian republics to jealous emulation or
  • cautious politics, the effects were alike, and every prevailing power
  • was sure to meet with a confederacy against it, and that often composed
  • of its former friends and allies.
  • The same principle—call it envy or prudence—which produced the
  • ostracism of Athens and petalism of Syracuse, and expelled every
  • citizen whose fame or power overtopped the rest—the same principle, I
  • say, naturally discovered itself in foreign politics, and soon raised
  • enemies to the leading state, however moderate in the exercise of its
  • authority.
  • The Persian monarch was really, in his force, a petty prince compared
  • to the Grecian republics, and therefore it behoved him, from views of
  • safety more than from emulation, to interest himself in their quarrels,
  • and to support the weaker side in every contest. This was the advice
  • given by Alcibiades to Tissaphernes, and it prolonged near a century
  • the date of the Persian empire; till the neglect of it for a moment,
  • after the first appearance of the aspiring genius of Philip, brought
  • that lofty and frail edifice to the ground with a rapidity of which
  • there are few instances in the history of mankind.
  • The successors of Alexander showed an infinite jealousy of the balance
  • of power, a jealousy founded on true politics and prudence, and which
  • preserved distinct for several ages the partitions made after the death
  • of that famous conqueror. The fortune and ambition of Antigonus
  • threatened them anew with a universal monarchy, but their combination
  • and their victory at Ipsus saved them; and in after times we find that
  • as the Eastern princes considered the Greeks and Macedonians as the
  • only real military force with whom they had any intercourse, they kept
  • always a watchful eye over that part of the world. The Ptolemies, in
  • particular, supported first Aratus and the Achæans, and then Cleomenes
  • King of Sparta, from no other view than as a counterbalance to the
  • Macedonian monarchs; for this is the account which Polybius gives of
  • the Egyptian politics.
  • The reason why it is supposed that the ancients were entirely ignorant
  • of the balance of power seems to be drawn from the Roman history more
  • than the Grecian, and as the transactions of the former are generally
  • the most familiar to us, we have thence formed all our conclusions.
  • It must be owned that the Romans never met with any such general
  • combination or confederacy against them as might naturally be expected
  • from their rapid conquests and declared ambition, but were allowed
  • peaceably to subdue their neighbours, one after another, till they
  • extended their dominion over the whole known world. Not to mention
  • the fabulous history of their Italic wars, there was, upon Hannibal’s
  • invasion of the Roman state, a very remarkable crisis which ought to
  • have called up the attention of all civilized nations. It appeared
  • afterwards (nor was it difficult to be observed at the time​[22]) that
  • this was a contest for universal empire, and yet no prince or state
  • seems to have been in the least alarmed about the event or issue of the
  • quarrel. Philip of Macedon remained neuter till he saw the victories
  • of Hannibal, and then most imprudently formed an alliance with the
  • conqueror, upon terms still more imprudent. He stipulated that he was
  • to assist the Carthaginian state in their conquest of Italy, after
  • which they engaged to send over forces into Greece, to assist him
  • in subduing the Grecian commonwealths.
  • The Rhodean and Achæan republics are much celebrated by ancient
  • historians for their wisdom and sound policy; yet both of them
  • assisted the Romans in their wars against Philip and Antiochus. And
  • what may be esteemed still a stronger proof that this maxim was not
  • familiarly known in those ages, no ancient author has ever remarked the
  • imprudence of these measures, nor has even blamed that absurd treaty
  • above-mentioned made by Philip with the Carthaginians. Princes and
  • statesmen may in all ages be blinded in their reasonings with regard
  • to events beforehand, but it is somewhat extraordinary that historians
  • afterwards should not form a sounder judgment of them.
  • Massinissa, Attalus, Prusias, in satisfying their private passions,
  • were all of them the instruments of the Roman greatness, and never seem
  • to have suspected that they were forging their own chains while they
  • advanced the conquests of their ally. A simple treaty and agreement
  • between Massinissa and the Carthaginians, so much required by mutual
  • interest, barred the Romans from all entrance into Africa, and
  • preserved liberty to mankind.
  • The only prince we meet with in the Roman history who seems to have
  • understood the balance of power is Hiero, King of Syracuse. Though
  • the ally of Rome, he sent assistance to the Carthaginians during the
  • war of the auxiliaries: “Esteeming it requisite,” says Polybius,
  • “both in order to retain his dominions in Sicily and to preserve the
  • Roman friendship, that Carthage should be safe; lest by its fall
  • the remaining power should be able, without contrast or opposition,
  • to execute every purpose and undertaking. And here he acted with
  • great wisdom and prudence; for that is never, on any account, to be
  • overlooked, nor ought such a force ever to be thrown into one hand as
  • to incapacitate the neighbouring states from defending their rights
  • against it.” Here is the aim of modern politics pointed out in express
  • terms.
  • In short, the maxim of preserving the balance of power is
  • founded so much on common sense and obvious reasoning that it is
  • impossible it could altogether have escaped antiquity, where we
  • find, in other particulars, so many marks of deep penetration and
  • discernment. If it was not so generally known and acknowledged as
  • at present, it had at least an influence on all the wiser and more
  • experienced princes and politicians; and indeed, even at present,
  • however generally known and acknowledged among speculative reasoners,
  • it has not, in practice, an authority much more extensive among those
  • who govern the world.
  • After the fall of the Roman Empire the form of government established
  • by the northern conquerors incapacitated them in a great measure
  • from further conquests, and long maintained each state in its proper
  • boundaries; but when vassalage and the feudal militia were abolished
  • mankind were anew alarmed by the danger of universal monarchy, from
  • the union of so many kingdoms and principalities in the person of the
  • Emperor Charles. But the power of the house of Austria, founded on
  • extensive but divided dominions, and their riches, derived chiefly from
  • mines of gold and silver, were more likely to decay, of themselves,
  • from internal defects, than to overthrow all the bulwarks raised
  • against them. In less than a century the force of that violent and
  • haughty race was shattered, their opulence dissipated, their splendour
  • eclipsed. A new power succeeded, more formidable to the liberties of
  • Europe, possessing all the advantages of the former and labouring under
  • none of its defects, except a share of that spirit of bigotry and
  • persecution with which the house of Austria were so long and still are
  • so much infatuated.
  • Europe has now, for above a century, remained on the defensive against
  • the greatest force that ever perhaps was formed by the civil or
  • political combination of mankind. And such is the influence of the
  • maxim here treated of, that though that ambitious nation in the five
  • last general wars has been victorious in four,​[23] and unsuccessful
  • only in one,​[24] they have not much enlarged their dominions,
  • nor acquired a total ascendant over Europe. There remains rather room
  • to hope that by maintaining the resistance some time the natural
  • revolutions of human affairs, together with unforeseen events and
  • accidents, may guard us against universal monarchy, and preserve the
  • world from so great an evil.
  • In the three last of these general wars Britain has stood foremost in
  • the glorious struggle, and she still maintains her station as guardian
  • of the general liberties of Europe, and patron of mankind. Beside her
  • advantages of riches and situation, her people are animated with such a
  • national spirit, and are so fully sensible of the inestimable blessings
  • of their government, that we may hope their vigour never will languish
  • in so necessary and so just a cause. On the contrary, if we may judge
  • by the past, their passionate ardour seems rather to require some
  • moderation, and they have oftener erred from a laudable excess than
  • from a blameable deficiency.
  • In the first place, we seem to have been more possessed with the
  • ancient Greek spirit of jealous emulation than actuated with the
  • prudent views of modern politics. Our wars with France have been begun
  • with justice, and even, perhaps, from necessity; but have always
  • been too far pushed from obstinacy and passion. The same peace which
  • was afterwards made at Ryswick in 1697 was offered so early as the
  • ninety-two; that concluded at Utrecht in 1712 might have been finished
  • on as good conditions at Gertruytenberg in the eight; and we might have
  • given at Frankfort in 1743 the same terms which we were glad to accept
  • of at Aix-la-Chapelle in the forty-eight. Here then we see that above
  • half of our wars with France, and all our public debts, are owing more
  • to our own imprudent vehemence than to the ambition of our neighbours.
  • In the second place, we are so declared in our opposition to French
  • power, and so alert in defence of our allies, that they always
  • reckon upon our force as upon their own, and expecting to carry on war
  • at our expense, refuse all reasonable terms of accommodation. _Habent
  • subjectos, tanquam suos; viles, ut alienos._ All the world knows that
  • the factious vote of the House of Commons in the beginning of the last
  • Parliament, with the professed humour of the nation, made the Queen
  • of Hungary inflexible in her terms, and prevented that agreement with
  • Prussia which would immediately have restored the general tranquillity
  • of Europe.
  • In the third place, we are such true combatants that, when once
  • engaged, we lose all concern for ourselves and our posterity, and
  • consider only how we may best annoy the enemy. To mortgage our revenues
  • at so deep a rate in wars where we are only accessories was surely the
  • most fatal delusion that a nation, who had any pretension to politics
  • and prudence, has ever yet been guilty of. That remedy of funding—if
  • it be a remedy and not rather a poison—ought, in all reason, to be
  • reserved to the last extremity, and no evil but the greatest and most
  • urgent should ever induce us to embrace so dangerous an expedient.
  • These excesses to which we have been carried are prejudicial, and
  • may perhaps in time become still more prejudicial another way, by
  • begetting, as is usual, the opposite extreme, and rendering us totally
  • careless and supine with regard to the fate of Europe. The Athenians,
  • from the most bustling, intriguing, warlike people of Greece, finding
  • their error in thrusting themselves into every quarrel, abandoned all
  • attention to foreign affairs, and in no contest ever took party on
  • either side, except by their flatteries and complaisance to the victor.
  • Enormous monarchies are probably destructive to human nature—in their
  • progress, in their continuance,​[25] and even in their downfall,
  • which never can be very distant from their establishment.
  • The military genius which aggrandized the monarchy soon leaves the
  • court, the capital, and the centre of such a government; while the
  • wars are carried on at a great distance, and interest so small a
  • part of the state. The ancient nobility, whose affections attach
  • them to their sovereign, live all at court; and never will accept of
  • military employments which would carry them to remote and barbarous
  • frontiers, where they are distant both from their pleasures and their
  • fortune. The arms of the state must therefore be trusted to mercenary
  • strangers, without zeal, without attachment, without honour, ready
  • on every occasion to turn them against the prince, and join each
  • desperate malcontent who offers pay and plunder. This is the necessary
  • progress of human affairs; thus human nature checks itself in its
  • airy elevations, thus ambition blindly labours for the destruction of
  • the conqueror, of his family, and of everything near and dear to him.
  • The Bourbons, trusting to the support of their brave, faithful, and
  • affectionate nobility, would push their advantage without reserve or
  • limitation. These, while fired with glory and emulation, can bear the
  • fatigues and dangers of war; but never would submit to languish in the
  • garrisons of Hungary or Lithuania, forgot at court, and sacrificed to
  • the intrigues of every minion or mistress who approaches the prince.
  • The troops are filled with Cravates and Tartars, Hussars and Cossacks,
  • intermingled perhaps with a few soldiers of fortune from the better
  • provinces; and the melancholy fate of the Roman emperors, from the same
  • cause, is renewed over and over again till the final dissolution of the
  • monarchy.
  • NOTES, OF THE BALANCE OF POWER.
  • [22] It was observed by some, as appears from the speech of Agelaus of
  • Naupactum, in the general congress of Greece. See Polyb., lib. 5, cap.
  • 104.
  • [23] Those concluded by the Peace of the Pyrenees, Nimeguen, Ryswick,
  • and Aix-la-Chapelle.
  • [24] That concluded by the Peace of Utrecht.
  • [25] If the Roman Empire was of advantage, it could only proceed from
  • this, that mankind were generally in a very disorderly, uncivilized
  • condition before its establishment.
  • OF TAXES.
  • There is a maxim that prevails among those whom in this country we call
  • “ways and means” men, and who are denominated financiers and maltotiers
  • in France, that every new tax creates a new ability in the subject to
  • bear it, and that each increase of public burdens increases
  • proportionably the industry of the people. This maxim is of such a
  • nature as is most likely to be extremely abused, and is so much the
  • more dangerous, as its truth cannot be altogether denied; but it must
  • be owned, when kept within certain bounds, to have some foundation in
  • reason and experience.
  • When a tax is laid upon commodities which are consumed by the common
  • people, the necessary consequence may seem to be that either the poor
  • must retrench something from their way of living, or raise their wages
  • so as to make the burden of the tax fall entirely upon the rich. But
  • there is a third consequence which very often follows upon taxes—viz.,
  • that the poor increase their industry, perform more work, and live as
  • well as before without demanding more for their labour. Where taxes
  • are moderate, are laid on gradually, and affect not the necessaries of
  • life, this consequence naturally follows; and it is certain that such
  • difficulties often serve to excite the industry of a people, and render
  • them more opulent and laborious than others who enjoy the greatest
  • advantages. For we may observe, as a parallel instance, that the most
  • commercial nations have not always possessed the greatest extent of
  • fertile land; but, on the contrary, that they have laboured under many
  • natural disadvantages. Tyre, Athens, Carthage, Rhodes, Genoa, Venice,
  • Holland are strong examples to this purpose; and in all history we
  • find only three instances of large and fertile countries which have
  • possessed much trade—the Netherlands, England, and France. The two
  • former seem to have been allured by the advantages of their maritime
  • situation, and the necessity they lay under of frequenting foreign
  • ports in order to procure what their own climate refused them; and as
  • to France, trade has come very late into the kingdom, and seems to
  • have been the effect of reflection and observation in an ingenious and
  • enterprising people, who remarked the immense riches acquired by such
  • of the neighbouring nations as cultivated navigation and commerce.
  • The places mentioned by Cicero as possessed of the greatest
  • commerce of his time are Alexandria, Colchos, Tyre, Sidon, Andros,
  • Cyprus, Pamphylia, Lycia, Rhodes, Chios, Byzantium, Lesbos, Smyrna,
  • Miletum, Coos. All these, except Alexandria, were either small islands
  • or narrow territories; and that city owed its trade entirely to the
  • happiness of its situation.
  • Since, therefore, some natural necessities or disadvantages may be
  • thought favourable to industries, why may not artificial burdens have
  • the same effect? Sir William Temple,​[26] we may observe, ascribes the
  • industry of the Dutch entirely to necessity, proceeding from their
  • natural disadvantages; and illustrates his doctrine by a very striking
  • comparison with Ireland, “where,” says he, “by the largeness and plenty
  • of the soil, and scarcity of people, all things necessary to life are
  • so cheap that an industrious man by two days’ labour may gain enough to
  • feed him the rest of the week. Which I take to be a very plain ground
  • of the laziness attributed to the people. For men naturally prefer ease
  • before labour, and will not take pains if they can live idle; though
  • when, by necessity, they have been inured to it, they cannot leave
  • it, being grown a custom necessary to their health, and to their very
  • entertainment. Nor perhaps is the change harder from constant ease
  • to labour than from constant labour to ease.” After which the author
  • proceeds to confirm his doctrine by enumerating as above the places
  • where trade has most flourished in ancient and modern times, and which
  • are commonly observed by such narrow, confined territories as beget a
  • necessity for industry.
  • It is always observed in years of scarcity, if it be not extreme, that
  • the poor labour more and really live better than in years of great
  • plenty, when they indulge themselves in idleness and riot. I have been
  • told by a considerable manufacturer that in the year 1740, when bread
  • and provisions of all kinds were very dear, his workmen not only made
  • a shift to live, but paid debts which they had contracted in
  • former years that were much more favourable and abundant.
  • This doctrine, therefore, with regard to taxes may be admitted to
  • some degree, but beware of the abuse. Exorbitant taxes, like extreme
  • necessity, destroy industry by producing despair; and even before they
  • reach this pitch they raise the wages of the labourer and manufacturer,
  • and heighten the price of all commodities. An attentive, disinterested
  • legislature will observe the point when the emolument ceases and the
  • prejudice begins; but as the contrary character is much more common,
  • it is to be feared that taxes all over Europe are multiplying to
  • such a degree as will entirely crush all art and industry; though
  • perhaps their first increase, together with circumstances, might have
  • contributed to the growth of these advantages.
  • The best taxes are such as are levied upon consumptions, especially
  • those of luxury, because such taxes are less felt by the people. They
  • seem, in some measure, voluntary, since a man may choose how far
  • he will use the commodity which is taxed: they are paid gradually
  • and insensibly, and being confounded with the natural price of the
  • commodity, they are scarcely perceived by the consumers. Their only
  • disadvantage is that they are expensive in the levying.
  • Taxes upon possessions are levied without expense, but have every other
  • disadvantage. Most states, however, are obliged to have recourse to
  • them, in order to supply the deficiencies of the other.
  • But the most pernicious of all taxes are those which are arbitrary.
  • They are commonly converted by their management into punishments on
  • industry; and also by their unavoidable inequality are more grievous
  • than by the real burden which they impose. It is surprising, therefore,
  • to see them have place among any civilized people.
  • In general, all poll-taxes, even when not arbitrary—which they commonly
  • are—may be esteemed dangerous; because it is so easy for the sovereign
  • to add a little more and a little more to the sum demanded, that these
  • taxes are apt to become altogether oppressive and intolerable. On the
  • other hand, a duty upon commodities checks itself, and a prince
  • will soon find that an increase of the impost is no increase of his
  • revenue. It is not easy, therefore, for a people to be altogether
  • ruined by such taxes.
  • Historians inform us that one of the chief causes of the destruction
  • of the Roman state was the alteration which Constantine introduced
  • into the finances, by substituting a universal poll-tax in lieu of
  • almost all the tithes, customs, and excises which formerly composed the
  • revenue of the empire. The people in all the provinces were so grinded
  • and oppressed by the publicans that they were glad to take refuge under
  • the conquering arms of the barbarians, whose dominion, as they had
  • fewer necessities and less art, was found preferable to the refined
  • tyranny of the Romans.
  • There is a prevailing opinion that all taxes, however levied, fall upon
  • the land at last. Such an opinion may be useful in Britain, by checking
  • the landed gentlemen, in whose hands our legislature is chiefly lodged,
  • and making them preserve great regard for trade and industry; but I
  • must confess that this principle, though first advanced by a celebrated
  • writer, has so little appearance of reason that were it not for his
  • authority it had never been received by anybody. Every man, to be sure,
  • is desirous of pushing off from himself the burden of any tax which
  • is imposed, and laying it upon others; but as every man has the same
  • inclination, and is upon the defensive, no set of men can be supposed
  • to prevail altogether in this contest. And why the landed gentleman
  • should be the victim of the whole, and should not be able to defend
  • himself as well as others are, I cannot readily imagine. All tradesmen,
  • indeed, would willingly prey upon him and divide him among them if they
  • could; but this inclination they always have, though no taxes were
  • levied; and the same methods by which he guards against the imposition
  • of tradesmen before taxes will serve him afterwards, and make them
  • share the burden with him. No labour in any commodities that are
  • exported can be very considerably raised in the price without losing
  • the foreign market; and as some part of almost every manufactory
  • is exported, this circumstance keeps the price of most species of
  • labour nearly the same after the imposition of taxes. I may add that it
  • has this effect upon the whole, for were any kind of labour paid beyond
  • its proportion all hands would flock to it, and would soon sink it to a
  • level with the rest.
  • I shall conclude this subject with observing that we have with
  • regard to taxes an instance of what frequently happens in political
  • institutions, that the consequence of things are diametrically opposite
  • to what we should expect on the first appearance. It is regarded as a
  • fundamental maxim of the Turkish Government that the Grand Seignior,
  • though absolute master of the lives and fortunes of each individual,
  • has no authority to impose a new tax; and every Ottoman prince who
  • has made such an attempt either has been obliged to retract, or has
  • found the fatal effects of his perseverance. One would imagine that
  • this prejudice or established opinion were the firmest barrier in the
  • world against oppression, yet it is certain that its effect is quite
  • contrary. The emperor, having no regular method of increasing his
  • revenue, must allow all the pashas and governors to oppress and abuse
  • the subjects, and these he squeezes after their return from their
  • government; whereas, if he could impose a new tax, like our European
  • princes, his interest would so far be united with that of his people
  • that he would immediately feel the bad effects of these disorderly
  • levies of money, and would find that a pound raised by general
  • imposition would have less pernicious effects than a shilling taken in
  • so unequal and arbitrary a manner.
  • NOTE, OF TAXES.
  • [26] _Account of the Netherlands_, chap. vi.
  • OF PUBLIC CREDIT.
  • It appears to have been the common practice of antiquity to make
  • provision in times of peace for the necessities of war, and to hoard
  • up treasures beforehand as the instruments either of conquest or
  • defence, without trusting to extraordinary imposts, much less to
  • borrowing, in times of disorder and confusion. Besides the immense sums
  • above mentioned​[27] which were amassed by Athens, and by the Ptolemies
  • and other successors of Alexander, we learn from Plato that the frugal
  • Lacedemonians had also collected a great treasure; and Arrian and
  • Plutarch​[28] specify the riches which Alexander got possession of on
  • the conquest of Susa and Ecbatana, and which were reserved, some of
  • them, from the time of Cyrus. If I remember right, the Scripture also
  • mentions the treasure of Hezekiah and the Jewish princes, as profane
  • history does that of Philip and Perseus, kings of Macedon. The ancient
  • republics of Gaul had commonly large sums in reserve. Every one knows
  • the treasure seized in Rome by Julius Cæsar during the civil wars,
  • and we find afterwards that the wiser emperors, Augustus, Tiberius,
  • Vespasian, Severus, etc., always discovered the prudent foresight of
  • saving great sums against any public exigency.
  • On the contrary, our modern expedient, which has become very general,
  • is to mortgage the public revenues, and to trust that posterity during
  • peace will pay off the encumbrances contracted during the preceding
  • war; and they, having before their eyes so good an example of their
  • wise fathers, have the same prudent reliance on their posterity, who at
  • last, from necessity more than choice, are obliged to place the same
  • confidence in a new posterity. But not to waste time in declaiming
  • against a practice which appears ruinous beyond the evidence of a
  • hundred demonstrations, it seems pretty apparent that the ancient
  • maxims are in this respect much more prudent than the modern; even
  • though the latter had been confined within some reasonable bounds, and
  • had ever, in any one instance, been attended with such frugality in
  • time of peace as to discharge the debts incurred by an expensive war.
  • For why should the case be so very different between the public and
  • an individual as to make us establish such different maxims of
  • conduct for each? If the funds of the former be greater, its necessary
  • expenses are proportionably larger; if its resources be more numerous,
  • they are not infinite; and as its frame should be calculated for a much
  • longer duration than the date of a single life, or even of a family,
  • it should embrace maxims, large, durable, and generous, agreeable to
  • the supposed extent of its existence. To trust to chances and temporary
  • expedients is indeed what the necessity of human affairs frequently
  • reduces it to, but whoever voluntarily depend on such resources have
  • not necessity but their own folly to accuse for their misfortunes when
  • any such befall them.
  • If the abuses of treasures be dangerous, either by engaging the state
  • in rash enterprises or making it neglect military discipline in
  • confidence of its riches, the abuses of mortgaging are more certain and
  • inevitable—poverty, impotence, and subjection to foreign powers.
  • According to modern policy, war is attended with every destructive
  • circumstance: loss of men, increase of taxes, decay of commerce,
  • dissipation of money, devastation by sea and land. According to ancient
  • maxims, the opening of the public treasure, as it produced an uncommon
  • affluence of gold and silver, served as a temporary encouragement to
  • industry, and atoned in some degree for the inevitable calamities of
  • war.
  • What then shall we say to the new paradox, that public encumbrances
  • are, of themselves, advantageous, independent of the necessity of
  • contracting them; and that any state, even though it were not pressed
  • by a foreign enemy, could not possibly have embraced a wiser expedient
  • for promoting commerce and riches than to create funds, and debts, and
  • taxes without limitation? Discourses such as these might naturally
  • have passed for trials of wit among rhetoricians, like the panegyrics
  • on folly and a fever, on Busiris and Nero, had we not seen such absurd
  • maxims patronized by great ministers and by a whole party among us; and
  • these puzzling arguments (for they deserve not the name of specious),
  • though they could not be the foundation of Lord Orford’s
  • conduct, for he had more sense, served at least to keep his partisans
  • in countenance and perplex the understanding of the nation.
  • Let us examine the consequences of public debts, both in our domestic
  • management by their influence on commerce and industry, and in our
  • foreign transactions by their effect on wars and negotiations.
  • There is a word which is here in the mouth of everybody, and which I
  • find has also got abroad and is much employed by foreign writers​[29]
  • in imitation of the English—and this is “circulation.” This word serves
  • as an account of everything, and though I confess that I have sought
  • for its meaning in the present subject ever since I was a schoolboy,
  • I have never yet been able to discover it. What possible advantage is
  • there which the nation can reap by the easy transference of stock from
  • hand to hand? Or is there any parallel to be drawn from the circulation
  • of other commodities to that of chequer notes and India bonds? Where
  • a manufacturer has a quick sale of his goods to the merchant, the
  • merchant to the shopkeeper, the shopkeeper to his customers, this
  • enlivens industry and gives new encouragement to the first dealer or
  • the manufacturer and all his tradesmen, and makes them produce more
  • and better commodities of the same species. A stagnation is here
  • pernicious, wherever it happens, because it operates backwards, and
  • stops or benumbs the industrious hand in its production of what is
  • useful to human life. But what production we owe to Change-alley, or
  • even what consumption, except that of coffee, and pen, ink, and paper,
  • I have not yet learned; nor can one foresee the loss or decay of any
  • one beneficial commerce or commodity, though that place and all its
  • inhabitants were for ever buried in the ocean.
  • But though this term has never been explained by those who insist
  • so much on the advantages that result from a circulation, there
  • seems, however, to be some benefit of a similar kind arising from our
  • encumbrances—as, indeed, what human evil is there which is not
  • attended with some advantage? This we shall endeavour to explain, that
  • we may estimate the weight which we ought to allow it.
  • Public securities are with us become a kind of money, and pass as
  • readily at the current price as gold or silver. Wherever any profitable
  • undertaking offers itself, however expensive, there are never wanting
  • hands enough to embrace it; nor need a trader who has sums in the
  • public stocks fear to launch out into the most extensive trade, since
  • he is possessed of funds which will answer the most sudden demand
  • that can be made upon him. No merchant thinks it necessary to keep by
  • him any considerable cash. Bank-notes or India bonds, especially the
  • latter, serve all the same purposes; because he can dispose of them or
  • pledge them to a banker in a quarter of an hour; and at the same time
  • they are not idle, even when in his escritoire, but bring him in a
  • constant revenue. In short, our national debts furnish merchants with
  • a species of money that is continually multiplying in their hands, and
  • produces sure gain besides the profits of their commerce. This must
  • enable them to trade upon less profit. The small profit of the merchant
  • renders the commodity cheaper, causes a greater consumption, quickens
  • the labour of the common people, and helps to spread arts and industry
  • through the whole society.
  • There are also, we may observe, in England and in all states which have
  • both commerce and public debts, a set of men who are half merchants,
  • half stock-holders, and may be supposed willing to trade for small
  • profits; because commerce is not their principal or sole support, and
  • their revenues in the funds are a sure resource for themselves and
  • their families. Were there no funds great merchants would have no
  • expedient for realizing or securing any part of their profit but by
  • making purchases of land, and land has many disadvantages in comparison
  • of funds. Requiring more care and inspection, it divides the time and
  • attention of the merchant; upon any tempting offer or extraordinary
  • accident in trade, it is not so easily converted into money; and as it
  • attracts too much, both by the many natural pleasures it affords
  • and the authority it gives, it soon converts the citizen into the
  • country gentleman. More men, therefore, with large stocks and incomes,
  • may naturally be supposed to continue in trade where there are public
  • debts; and this, it must be owned, is of some advantage to commerce
  • by diminishing its profits, promoting circulation, and encouraging
  • industry.
  • But, in opposition to these two favourable circumstances, perhaps of no
  • very great importance, weigh the many disadvantages which attend our
  • public debts in the whole interior economy of the state; you will find
  • no comparison between the ill and the good which result from them.
  • First, it is certain that national debts cause a mighty confluence of
  • people and riches to the capital, by the great sums which are levied in
  • the provinces to pay the interest of those debts; and perhaps, too, by
  • the advantages in trade above mentioned, which they give the merchants
  • in the capital above the rest of the kingdom. The question is, whether,
  • in our case, it be for the public interest that so many privileges
  • should be conferred on London, which has already arrived at such an
  • enormous size and seems still increasing? Some men are apprehensive of
  • the consequences. For my part, I cannot forbear thinking that though
  • the head is undoubtedly too big for the body, yet that great city is so
  • happily situated that its excessive bulk causes less inconvenience than
  • even a smaller capital to a greater kingdom. There is more difference
  • between the prices of all provisions in Paris and Languedoc than
  • between those in London and Yorkshire.
  • Secondly, public stocks, being a kind of paper-credit, have all the
  • disadvantages attending that species of money. They banish gold and
  • silver from the most considerable commerce of the state, reduce them to
  • common circulation, and by that means render all provisions and labour
  • dearer than otherwise they would be.
  • Thirdly, the taxes which are levied to pay the interests of these debts
  • are apt to be a check upon industry, to heighten the price of
  • labour, and to be an oppression on the poorer sort.
  • Fourthly, as foreigners possess a share of our national funds, they
  • render the public in a manner tributary to them, and may in time
  • occasion the transport of our people and our industry.
  • Fifthly, the greatest part of public stock being always in the hands
  • of idle people, who live on their revenue, our funds give great
  • encouragement to a useless and inactive life.
  • But though the injury which arises to commerce and industry from our
  • public funds will appear, upon balancing the whole, very considerable,
  • it is trivial in comparison of the prejudice which results to the
  • state considered as a body politic, which must support itself in the
  • society of nations, and have various transactions with other states,
  • in wars and negotiations. The ill there is pure and unmixed, without
  • any favourable circumstance to atone for it, and it is an ill too of a
  • nature the highest and most important.
  • We have, indeed, been told that the public is no weaker upon account
  • of its debts, since they are mostly due among ourselves, and bring as
  • much property to one as they take from another. It is like transferring
  • money from the right hand to the left, which leaves the person neither
  • richer nor poorer than before. Such loose reasonings and specious
  • comparisons will always pass where we judge not upon principles. I ask,
  • is it possible, in the nature of things, to overburden a nation with
  • taxes, even where the sovereign resides among them? The very doubt
  • seems extravagant, since it is requisite in every commonwealth that
  • there be a certain proportion observed between the laborious and the
  • idle part of it. But if all our present taxes be mortgaged, must we not
  • invent new ones? and may not this matter be carried to a length that is
  • ruinous and destructive?
  • In every nation there are always some methods of levying money more
  • easy than others, agreeable to the way of living of the people and the
  • commodities they make use of. In Britain the excises upon malt and beer
  • afford a very large revenue, because the operations of malting
  • and brewing are very tedious, and are impossible to be concealed; and
  • at the same time, these commodities are not so absolutely necessary to
  • life as that the raising their price would very much affect the poorer
  • sort. These taxes being all mortgaged, what difficulty to find new
  • ones! what vexation and ruin of the poor!
  • Duties upon consumptions are more equal and easy than those upon
  • possessions. What a loss to the public that the former are all
  • exhausted, and that we must have recourse to the more grievous method
  • of levying taxes!
  • Were all the proprietors of land only stewards to the public, must not
  • necessity force them to practise all the arts of oppression used by
  • stewards, where the absence or negligence of the proprietor render them
  • secure against inquiry?
  • It will scarce be asserted that no bounds ought ever to be set to
  • national debts, and that the public would be no weaker were twelve or
  • fifteen shillings in the pound land-tax mortgaged, with the present
  • customs and excises. There is something therefore in the case beside
  • the mere transferring of property from one hand to another. In 500
  • years the posterity of those now in the coaches and of those upon the
  • boxes will probably have changed places, without affecting the public
  • by these revolutions.
  • Suppose the public once fairly brought to that condition to which it
  • is hastening with such amazing rapidity; suppose the land to be taxed
  • eighteen or nineteen shillings in the pound (for it can never bear the
  • whole twenty); suppose all the excises and customs to be screwed up
  • to the outmost which the nation can bear, without entirely losing its
  • commerce and industry; and suppose that all those funds are mortgaged
  • to perpetuity, and that the invention and wit of all our projectors
  • can find no new imposition which may serve as the foundation of a new
  • loan; and let us consider the necessary consequences of this situation.
  • Though the imperfect state of our political knowledge and the narrow
  • capacities of men make it difficult to foretell the effects
  • which will result from any untried measure, the seeds of ruin are here
  • scattered with such profusion as not to escape the eye of the most
  • careless observer.
  • In this unnatural state of society, the only persons who possess
  • any revenue beyond the immediate effects of their industry are the
  • stockholders, who draw almost all the rent of the land and houses,
  • besides the produce of all the customs and excises. These are men who
  • have no connections in the state, who can enjoy their revenue in any
  • part of the world in which they choose to reside, who will naturally
  • bury themselves in the capital, or in great cities, and who will sink
  • into the lethargy of a stupid and pampered luxury, without spirit,
  • ambition, or enjoyment. Adieu to all ideas of nobility, gentry, and
  • family. The stocks can be transferred in an instant, and being in
  • such a fluctuating state, will seldom be transmitted during three
  • generations from father to son. Or were they to remain ever so long
  • in one family, they convey no hereditary authority or credit to the
  • possessors; and by this means, the several ranks of men, which form
  • a kind of independent magistracy in a state, instituted by the hand
  • of nature, are entirely lost, and every man in authority derives his
  • influence from the commission alone of the sovereign. No expedient
  • remains for preventing or suppressing insurrections but mercenary
  • armies; no expedient at all remains for resisting tyranny; elections
  • are swayed by bribery and corruption alone; and the middle power
  • between king and people being totally removed, a horrible despotism
  • must infallibly prevail. The landholders, despised for their poverty
  • and hated for their oppressions, will be utterly unable to make any
  • opposition to it.
  • Though a resolution should be formed by the legislature never to impose
  • any tax which hurts commerce and discourages industry, it will be
  • impossible for men, in subjects of such extreme delicacy, to reason
  • so justly as never to be mistaken, or amidst difficulties so urgent,
  • never to be seduced from their resolution. The continual fluctuations
  • in commerce require continual alterations in the nature of the taxes,
  • which exposes the legislature every moment to the danger both
  • of wilful and involuntary error; and any great blow given to trade,
  • whether by injudicious taxes or by other accidents, throws the whole
  • system of the government into confusion.
  • But what expedient is the public now to fall upon, even supposing trade
  • to continue in the most flourishing condition, to support its foreign
  • wars and enterprises, and to defend its own honour and interests or
  • those of its allies? I do not ask how the public is to exert such a
  • prodigious power as it has maintained during our late wars, where we
  • have so much exceeded, not only our own natural strength, but even that
  • of the greatest empires. This extravagance is the abuse complained of,
  • as the source of all the dangers to which we are at present exposed.
  • But since we must still suppose great commerce and opulence to remain
  • even after every fund is mortgaged, those riches must be defended by
  • proportionable power, and whence is the public to derive the revenue
  • which supports it? It must plainly be from a continual taxation of
  • the annuitants, or, which is the same thing, from mortgaging anew
  • on every exigency a certain part of their annuity, and thus making
  • them contribute to their own defence and to that of the nation; but
  • the difficulties attending this system of policy will easily appear,
  • whether we suppose the king to have become absolute master or to
  • be still controlled by national councils, in which the annuitants
  • themselves must necessarily bear the principal sway.
  • If the prince has become absolute, as may naturally be expected from
  • this situation of affairs, it is so easy for him to increase his
  • exactions upon the annuitants, which amount only to the retaining
  • money in his own hands, that this species of property will soon lose
  • all its credit, and the whole income of every individual in the state
  • must lie entirely at the mercy of the sovereign—a degree of despotism
  • which no oriental monarchy has ever yet attained. If, on the contrary,
  • the consent of the annuitants be requisite for every taxation, they
  • will never be persuaded to contribute sufficiently even to the support
  • of government, as the diminution of their revenue must in that
  • case be very sensible, would not be disguised under the appearance of a
  • branch of excise or customs, and would not be shared by any other order
  • of the state, who are already supposed to be taxed to the utmost. There
  • are instances in some republics of a hundredth penny, and sometimes
  • of the fiftieth, being given to the support of the state; but this is
  • always an extraordinary exertion of power, and can never become the
  • foundation of a constant national defence. We have always found, where
  • a government has mortgaged all its revenues, that it necessarily sinks
  • into a state of languor, inactivity, and impotence.
  • Such are the inconveniences which may reasonably be foreseen of this
  • situation to which Great Britain is visibly tending, not to mention
  • the numberless inconveniences which cannot be foreseen, and which must
  • result from so monstrous a situation as that of making the public
  • the sole proprietor of land, besides investing it with every branch
  • of customs and excise which the fertile imagination of ministers and
  • projectors have been able to invent.
  • I must confess that there is a strange supineness, from long custom,
  • crept into all ranks of men with regard to public debts, not unlike
  • what divines so vehemently complain of with regard to their religious
  • doctrines. We all own that the most sanguine imagination cannot hope
  • either that this or any future ministry will be possessed of such
  • rigid and steady frugality as to make any considerable progress in the
  • payment of our debts, or that the situation of foreign affairs will,
  • for any long time, allow them leisure and tranquillity for such an
  • undertaking.​[30] What then is to become of us? Were we ever so good
  • Christians and ever so resigned to Providence, this, methinks, were
  • a curious question, even considered as a speculative one, and
  • what it might not be altogether impossible to form some conjectural
  • solution of. The events here will depend little upon the contingencies
  • of battles, negotiations, intrigues, and factions. There seems to be a
  • natural progress of things which may guide our reasoning. As it would
  • have required but a moderate share of prudence when we first began this
  • practice of mortgaging to have foretold, from the nature of men and
  • of ministers, that things would necessarily be carried to the length
  • we see, so now that they have at last happily reached it, it may not
  • be difficult to guess at the consequences. It must, indeed, be one
  • of these two events—either the nation must destroy public credit, or
  • public credit will destroy the nation. It is impossible they can both
  • subsist after the manner they have been hitherto managed, in this as
  • well as in some other nations.
  • There was indeed a scheme for the payment of our debts which was
  • proposed by an excellent citizen, Mr. Hutchinson, above thirty years
  • ago, and which was much approved of by some men of sense, but never
  • was likely to take effect. He asserted that there was a fallacy in
  • imagining that the public owed this debt, for that really every
  • individual owed a proportional share of it, and paid, in his taxes,
  • a proportional share of the interest, beside the expenses of levying
  • these taxes. Had we not better, then, says he, make a proportional
  • distribution of the debt among us, and each of us contribute a sum
  • suitable to his property, and by that means discharge at once all our
  • funds and public mortgages? He seems not to have considered that the
  • laborious poor pay a considerable part of the taxes by their annual
  • consumptions, though they could not advance at once a proportional
  • part of the sum required; not to mention that property in money and
  • stock in trade might easily be concealed or disguised, and that
  • visible property in lands and houses would really at last answer for
  • the whole—an inequality and oppression which never would be submitted
  • to. But though this project is never likely to take place, it is not
  • altogether improbable that when the nation become heartily sick of
  • their debts, and are cruelly oppressed by them, some daring projector
  • may arise with visionary schemes for their discharge. And as public
  • credit will begin, by that time, to be a little frail, the least touch
  • will destroy it, as happened in France; and in this manner it will die
  • of the doctor.​[31]
  • But it is more probable that the breach of national faith will be the
  • necessary effect of wars, defeats, misfortunes, and public calamities,
  • or even perhaps of victories and conquests. I must confess, when I
  • see princes and states fighting and quarrelling, amidst their debts,
  • funds, and public mortgages, it always brings to my mind a match of
  • cudgel-playing fought in a china-shop. How can it be expected that
  • sovereigns will spare a species of property which is pernicious to
  • themselves and to the public, when they have so little compassion
  • on lives and properties which are useful to both? Let the time
  • come (and surely it will come) when the new funds created for the
  • exigencies of the year are not subscribed to, and raise not the money
  • projected. Suppose either that the cash of the nation is exhausted,
  • or that our faith, which has hitherto been so ample, begins
  • to fail us; suppose that in this distress the nation is threatened
  • with an invasion; a rebellion is suspected or broken out at home; a
  • squadron cannot be equipped for want of pay, victuals, or repairs;
  • or even a foreign subsidy cannot be advanced—what must a prince or
  • minister do in such an emergence? The right of self-preservation is
  • unalienable in every individual, much more in every community; and
  • the folly of our statesmen must then be greater than the folly of
  • those who first contracted debt, or, what is more, than that of those
  • who trusted, or continue to trust this security, if these statesmen
  • have the means of safety in their hands and do not employ them. The
  • funds, created and mortgaged, will by that time bring in a large
  • yearly revenue, sufficient for the defence and security of the nation.
  • Money is perhaps lying in the exchequer, ready for the discharge of
  • the quarterly interest. Necessity calls, fear urges, reason exhorts,
  • compassion alone exclaims; the money will immediately be seized for
  • the current service—under the most solemn protestations, perhaps, of
  • being immediately replaced. But no more is requisite; the whole fabric,
  • already tottering, falls to the ground, and buries thousands in its
  • ruins. And this, I think, may be called the natural death of public
  • credit; for to this period it tends as naturally as an animal body to
  • its dissolution and destruction.​[32]
  • These two events supposed above are calamitous, but not the most
  • calamitous. Thousands are hereby sacrificed to the safety of millions;
  • but we are not without danger that the contrary event may take place,
  • and that millions may be sacrificed for ever to the temporary safety
  • of thousands.​[33] Our popular government perhaps will render it
  • difficult or dangerous for a minister to venture on so desperate an
  • expedient as that of a voluntary bankruptcy; and though the House of
  • Lords be altogether composed of the proprietors of lands, and the
  • House of Commons chiefly, and consequently neither of them can
  • be supposed to have great property in the funds, yet the connections
  • of the members may be so great with the proprietors as to render them
  • more tenacious of public faith than prudence, policy, or even justice,
  • strictly speaking, requires. And perhaps, too, our foreign enemies,
  • or rather enemy (for we have but one to dread) may be so politic as
  • to discover that our safety lies in despair, and may not therefore
  • show the danger open and barefaced till it be inevitable. The balance
  • of power in Europe, our grandfathers, our fathers, and we, have all
  • justly esteemed too unequal to be preserved without our attention and
  • assistance. But our children, weary with the struggle, and fettered
  • with encumbrances, may sit down secure and see their neighbours
  • oppressed and conquered, till at last they themselves and their
  • creditors lie both at the mercy of the conqueror. And this may properly
  • enough be denominated the violent death of our public credit.
  • These seem to be the events which are not very remote, and which reason
  • foresees as clearly almost as she can do anything that lies in the womb
  • of time. And though the ancients maintained that, in order to reach the
  • gift of prophecy, a certain divine fury or madness was requisite, one
  • may safely affirm that, in order to deliver such prophecies as these,
  • no more is necessary than merely to be in one’s senses, free from the
  • influence of popular madness and delusion.
  • NOTES, OF PUBLIC CREDIT.
  • [27] Essay _Of the Balance of Trade_.
  • [28] Plut. in _Vita Alex_. He makes these treasures amount to 80,000
  • talents, or about 15 millions sterling. Quintus Curtius (lib. 5, cap.
  • 2) says that Alexander found in Susa above 50,000 talents.
  • [29] Melon, Du Tot, Law, in the pamphlets published in France.
  • [30] In times of peace and security, when alone it is possible to pay
  • debt, the moneyed interest are averse to receive partial payments,
  • which they know not how to dispose of to advantage, and the landed
  • interest are averse to continue the taxes requisite for that purpose.
  • Why therefore should a minister persevere in a measure so disagreeable
  • to all parties? For the sake, I suppose, of a posterity which he will
  • never see, or of a few reasonable, reflecting people whose united
  • interest perhaps will not be able to secure him the smallest borough
  • in England. It is not likely we shall ever find any minister so bad a
  • politician. With regard to these narrow, destructive maxims of politics
  • all ministers are expert enough.
  • [31] Some neighbouring states practise an easy expedient, by which they
  • lighten their public debts. The French have a custom (as the Romans
  • formerly had) of augmenting their money, and this the nation has been
  • so much familiarized to that it hurts not public credit, though it be
  • really cutting off at once, by an edict, so much of their debts. The
  • Dutch diminish the interest without the consent of their creditors;
  • or, which is the same thing, they arbitrarily tax the funds as well
  • as other property. Could we practise either of these methods, we need
  • never be oppressed by the national debt; and it is not impossible but
  • one of these, or some other method, may, at all adventures, be tried,
  • on the augmentation of our encumbrances and difficulties. But people
  • in this country are so good reasoners upon whatever regards their
  • interest, that such a practice will deceive nobody, and public credit
  • will probably tumble at once by so dangerous a trial.
  • [32] So great dupes are the generality of mankind, that notwithstanding
  • such a violent shock to public credit as a voluntary bankruptcy in
  • England would occasion, it would not probably be long ere credit would
  • again revive in as flourishing a condition as before. The present
  • King of France, during the late war, borrowed money at lower interest
  • than ever his grandfather did, and as low as the British Parliament,
  • comparing the natural rate of interest in both kingdoms. And though
  • men are commonly more governed by what they have seen than by what
  • they foresee, with whatever certainty, yet promises, protestations,
  • fair appearances, with the allurements of present interest, have such
  • powerful influence as few are able to resist. Mankind are, in all ages,
  • caught by the same baits. The same tricks, played over and over again,
  • still trepan them. The heights of popularity and patriotism are still
  • the beaten road to power and tyranny; flattery to treachery; standing
  • armies to arbitrary government; and the glory of God to the temporal
  • interest of the clergy. The fear of an everlasting destruction of
  • credit, allowing it to be an evil, is a needless bugbear. A prudent
  • man, in reality, would rather lend to the public immediately after
  • they had taken a sponge to their debts, than at present; as much as
  • an opulent knave, even though one could not force him to pay, is a
  • preferable debtor to an honest bankrupt; for the former, in order to
  • carry on business, may find it his interest to discharge his debts,
  • where they are not exorbitant. The latter has it not in his power.
  • The reasoning of Tacitus (_Hist._ lib. 3), as it is eternally true,
  • is very applicable to our present case: “Sed vulgus ad magnitudinem
  • beneficiorum aderat: Stultissimus quisque pecuniis mercabatur: Apud
  • sapientes cassa habebantur, quæ neque dari neque accipi, salva
  • republica, poterant.” The public is a debtor, whom no man can oblige to
  • pay. The only check which the creditors have on it is the interest of
  • preserving credit; an interest which may easily be overbalanced by a
  • very great debt, and by a difficult and extraordinary emergence, even
  • supposing that credit irrecoverable. Not to mention that a present
  • necessity often forces states into measures which are, strictly
  • speaking, against their interest.
  • [33] I have heard it has been computed that all the creditors of the
  • public, natives and foreigners, amount only to 17,000. These make a
  • figure at present on their income; but in case of a public bankruptcy
  • would in an instant become the lowest, as well as the most wretched of
  • the people. The dignity and authority of the landed gentry and nobility
  • is much better rooted, and would render the contention very unequal,
  • if ever we come to that extremity. One would incline to assign to this
  • event a very near period, such as half a century, had not our fathers’
  • prophecies of this kind been already found fallacious by the duration
  • of our public credit so much beyond all reasonable expectation. When
  • the astrologers in France were every year foretelling the death of
  • Henry IV., “These fellows,” says he, “must be right at last.” We shall
  • therefore be more cautious than to assign any precise date, and shall
  • content ourselves with pointing out the event in general.
  • OF SOME REMARKABLE CUSTOMS.
  • I shall observe three remarkable customs in three celebrated
  • governments, and shall conclude from the whole that all general maxims
  • in politics ought to be established with great reserve, and that
  • irregular and extraordinary appearances are frequently discovered
  • in the moral as well as in the physical world. The former
  • perhaps can we better account for after they happen, from springs and
  • principles of which every one has within himself, or from obvious
  • observation, the strongest assurance and conviction; but it is often
  • fully as impossible for human prudence beforehand to foresee and
  • foretell them.
  • I. One would think it essential to every supreme council or assembly
  • which debates, that entire liberty of speech should be granted to
  • every member, and that all motions or reasonings should be received
  • which can any way tend to illustrate the point under deliberation.
  • One would conclude, with still greater assurance, that after a motion
  • was made, which was voted and approved by that assembly in which the
  • legislative power is lodged, the member who made the motion must for
  • ever be exempted from further trial or inquiry. But no political maxim
  • can at first sight appear more undisputable than that he must at least
  • be secured from all inferior jurisdiction, and that nothing less than
  • the same supreme legislative assembly, in their subsequent meetings,
  • could render him accountable for those motions and harangues which they
  • had before approved of. But these axioms, however irrefragable they may
  • appear, have all failed in the Athenian government, from causes, and
  • principles too, which appear almost inevitable.
  • By the γραφη παρανομων, or “indictment of illegality” (though it has
  • not been remarked by antiquaries or commentators), any man was tried
  • and punished by any common court of judicature for any law which
  • had passed upon his motion in the assembly of the people, if that
  • law appeared to the court unjust or prejudicial to the public. Thus
  • Demosthenes, finding that ship-money was levied irregularly, and that
  • the poor bore the same burden as the rich in equipping the galleys,
  • corrected this inequality by a very useful law, which proportioned the
  • expense to the revenue and income of each individual. He moved for
  • this law in the assembly, he proved its advantages,​[34] he
  • convinced the people, the only legislature in Athens, the law passed
  • and was carried into execution; and yet he was tried in a criminal
  • court for that law upon the complaint of the rich, who resented the
  • alteration he had introduced into the finances. He was indeed acquitted
  • upon proving anew the usefulness of his law.
  • Ctesiphon moved in the assembly of the people that particular honours
  • should be conferred on Demosthenes, as on a citizen affectionate and
  • useful to the commonwealth. The people, convinced of this truth, voted
  • those honours; yet was Ctesiphon tried by the γραφη παρανομων. It was
  • asserted, among other topics, that Demosthenes was not a good citizen,
  • nor affectionate to the commonwealth, and the orator was called upon to
  • defend his friend, and consequently himself, which he executed by that
  • sublime piece of eloquence that has ever since been the admiration of
  • mankind.
  • After the battle of Chæronea a law was passed, upon the motion
  • of Hyperides, giving liberty to slaves and enrolling them in the
  • troops.​[35] On account of this law the orator was afterwards tried
  • by the indictment above mentioned, and defended himself, among other
  • topics, by that stroke celebrated by Plutarch and Longinus. “It was not
  • I,” said he, “that moved for this law: it was the necessities of war;
  • it was the battle of Chæronea.” The orations of Demosthenes abound with
  • many instances of trials of this nature, and prove clearly that nothing
  • was more commonly practised.
  • The Athenian Democracy was such a tumultuary government as we can
  • scarce form a notion of in the present age of the world. The whole
  • collective body of the people voted in every law without any limitation
  • of property, without any distinction of rank, without control of any
  • magistracy or senate;​[36] and consequently without regard to
  • order, justice, or prudence. The Athenians soon became sensible of the
  • mischiefs attending this constitution, but being averse to the checking
  • themselves by any rule or restriction, they resolved at least to check
  • their demagogues or counsellors by the fear of future punishment
  • and inquiry. They accordingly instituted this remarkable law, a law
  • esteemed so essential to their government that Æschines insists on
  • it as a known truth, that were it abolished or neglected it were
  • impossible for the Democracy to subsist.​[37]
  • The people feared not any ill consequence to liberty from the authority
  • of the criminal courts, because these were nothing but very numerous
  • juries, chosen by lot from among the people; and they considered
  • themselves justly as in a state of perpetual pupilage, where they had
  • an authority, after they came to the use of reason, not only to retract
  • and control whatever had been determined, but to punish any guardian
  • for measures which they had embraced by his persuasion. The same law
  • had place in Thebes, and for the same reason.
  • It appears to have been a usual practice in Athens, on the
  • establishment of any law esteemed very useful or popular, to prohibit
  • for ever its abrogation and repeal. Thus the demagogue who diverted
  • all the public revenues to the support of shows and spectacles, made
  • it criminal so much as to move for a repeal of this law; thus Leptines
  • moved for a law, not only to recall all the immunities formerly
  • granted, but to deprive the people for the future of the power of
  • granting any more; thus all bills of attainder were forbid, or laws
  • that affected one Athenian without extending to the whole
  • commonwealth. These absurd clauses, by which the legislature vainly
  • attempted to bind itself for ever, proceeded from a universal sense of
  • the levity and inconstancy of the people.
  • II. A wheel within a wheel, such as we observe in the German Empire, is
  • considered by Lord Shaftesbury​[38] as an absurdity in politics; but
  • what must we say to two equal wheels which govern the same political
  • machine without any mutual check, control, or subordination, and yet
  • preserve the greatest harmony and concord? To establish two distinct
  • legislatures, each of which possesses full and absolute authority
  • within itself, and stands in no need of the other’s assistance,
  • in order to give validity to its acts, this may appear beforehand
  • altogether impracticable as long as men are actuated by the passions
  • of ambition, emulation, and avarice, which have been hitherto their
  • chief governing principles. And should I assert that the state I
  • have in my eye was divided into two distinct factions, each of which
  • predominated in a distinct legislature, and yet produced no clashing in
  • these independent powers, the supposition may appear almost incredible;
  • and if, to augment the paradox, I should affirm that this disjointed,
  • irregular government was the most active, triumphant, and illustrious
  • commonwealth that ever yet appeared on the stage of the world, I
  • should certainly be told that such a political chimera was as absurd
  • as any vision of the poets. But there is no need for searching long in
  • order to prove the reality of the foregoing suppositions, for this was
  • actually the case with the Roman republic.
  • The legislative power was there lodged in the _comitia centuriata_
  • and _comitia tributa_. In the former, it is well known, the people
  • voted according to their census; so that when the first class was
  • unanimous, though it contained not perhaps the hundredth part of the
  • commonwealth, it determined the whole, and, with the authority of the
  • senate, established a law. In the latter, every vote was alike; and as
  • the authority of the senate was not there requisite, the lower
  • people entirely prevailed and gave law to the whole state. In all party
  • divisions, at first between the Patricians and Plebeians, afterwards
  • between the nobles and the people, the interest of the aristocracy was
  • predominant in the first legislature, that of the democracy in the
  • second. The one could always destroy what the other had established;
  • nay, the one by a sudden and unforeseen motion might take the start
  • of the other and totally annihilate its rival by a vote, which, from
  • the nature of the constitution, had the full authority of a law. But
  • no such contest or struggle is observed in the history of Rome: no
  • instance of a quarrel between these two legislatures, though many
  • between the parties that governed in each. Whence arose this concord,
  • which may seem so extraordinary?
  • The legislature established at Rome by the authority of Servius Tullius
  • was the _comitia centuriata_, which, after the expulsion of the kings,
  • rendered the government for some time altogether aristocratical.
  • But the people, having numbers and force on their side, and being
  • elated with frequent conquests and victories in their foreign wars,
  • always prevailed when pushed to extremities, and first extorted from
  • the senate the magistracy of the tribunes, and then the legislative
  • power of the _comitia tributa_. It then behoved the nobles to be more
  • careful than ever not to provoke the people, for beside the force
  • which the latter were always possessed of, they had now got possession
  • of legal authority, and could instantly break in pieces any order or
  • institution which directly opposed them. By intrigue, by influence, by
  • money, by combination, and by the respect paid their character, the
  • nobles might often prevail and direct the whole machine of government;
  • but had they openly set their _comitia centuriata_ in opposition to
  • the _tributa_, they had soon lost the advantage of that institution,
  • together with their consuls, prætors, ediles, and all the magistrates
  • elected by it. But the _comitia tributa_, not having the same reason
  • for respecting the _centuriata_, frequently repealed laws favourable
  • to the aristocracy; they limited the authority of the nobles,
  • protected the people from oppression, and controlled the actions of
  • the senate and magistracy. The _centuriata_ found it convenient always
  • to submit; and though equal in authority, yet being inferior in power,
  • durst never directly give any shock to the other legislature, either by
  • repealing its laws or establishing laws, which, it foresaw, would soon
  • be repealed by it.
  • No instance is found of any opposition or struggle between these
  • _comitia_, except one slight attempt of this kind mentioned by Appian
  • in the third book of his Civil Wars. Mark Antony, resolving to deprive
  • Decimus Brutus of the government of Cisalpine Gaul, railed in the
  • forum, and called one of the _comitia_ in order to prevent the meeting
  • of the other which had been ordered by the senate; but affairs were
  • then fallen into such confusion, and the Roman constitution was so near
  • its final dissolution, that no inference can be drawn from such an
  • expedient. This contest, besides, was founded more on form than party.
  • It was the senate who ordered the _comitia tributa_ that they might
  • obstruct the meeting of the _centuriata_, which, by the constitution,
  • or at least forms of the government, could alone dispose of provinces.
  • Cicero was recalled by the _comitia centuriata_, though banished by
  • the _tributa_—that is, by a _plebiscitum_. But his banishment, we may
  • observe, never was considered as a legal deed, arising from the free
  • choice and inclination of the people. It was always ascribed to the
  • violence alone of Clodius, and to the disorders introduced by him into
  • the government.
  • III. The third custom which we proposed to observe regards England, and
  • though it be not so important as those which we have pointed out in
  • Athens and Rome, it is no less singular and remarkable. It is a maxim
  • in politics which we readily admit as undisputed and universal, that
  • a power, however great, when granted by law to an eminent magistrate
  • is not so dangerous to liberty as an authority, however considerable,
  • which he acquires from violence and usurpation; for, besides that
  • the law always limits every power which it bestows, the very
  • receiving it as a concession establishes the authority whence it is
  • derived and preserves the harmony of the constitution. By the same
  • right that one prerogative is assumed without law another may also
  • be claimed, and another with still greater facility; while the first
  • usurpations both serve as precedents to the following, and give force
  • to maintain them. Hence the heroism of Hampden, who sustained the whole
  • violence of royal prosecution rather than pay a tax of twenty shillings
  • not imposed by Parliament; hence the care of all English patriots to
  • guard against the first encroachments of the crown, and hence alone the
  • existence at this day of English liberty.
  • There is, however, one occasion where the Parliament has departed from
  • this maxim, and this is in the pressing of seamen. The exercise of an
  • illegal power is here tacitly permitted in the crown, and though it has
  • frequently been under deliberation how that power might be rendered
  • legal and granted under proper restrictions to the sovereign, no safe
  • expedient could ever be proposed for that purpose, and the danger
  • to liberty always appeared greater from law than from usurpation.
  • While this power is exercised to no other end than to man the Navy
  • men willingly submit to it from a sense of its use and necessity, and
  • the sailors, who are alone affected by it, find nobody to support
  • them in claiming the rights and privileges which the law grants
  • without distinction to all English subjects. But were this power on
  • any occasion made an instrument of faction or ministerial tyranny,
  • the opposite faction, and indeed all lovers of their country, would
  • immediately take the alarm and support the injured party. The liberty
  • of Englishmen would be asserted; juries would be implacable; and the
  • tools of tyranny acting both against law and equity would meet with the
  • severest vengeance. On the other hand, were the Parliament to grant
  • such an authority, they would probably fall into one of these two
  • inconveniences: they would either bestow it under so many restrictions
  • as would make it lose its effects by cramping the authority of the
  • crown, or they would render it so large and comprehensive as might give
  • occasion to great abuses, for which we could in that case have
  • no remedy. The very illegality of the power at present prevents its
  • abuses, by affording so easy a remedy against them.
  • I pretend not by this reasoning to exclude all possibility of
  • contriving a register for seamen, which might man the Navy without
  • being dangerous to liberty. I only observe that no satisfactory scheme
  • of that nature has yet been proposed. Rather than adopt any project
  • hitherto invented, we continue a practice seemingly the most absurd and
  • unaccountable. Authority, in times of full internal peace and concord,
  • is armed against law. A continued and open usurpation of the crown is
  • permitted amidst the greatest jealousy and watchfulness in the people;
  • nay, proceeding from those very principles, liberty, in a country of
  • the highest liberty, is left entirely to its own defence without any
  • countenance or protection; the wild state of nature is renewed in one
  • of the most civilized societies of mankind; and great violences and
  • disorders among the people, the most human and the best-natured, are
  • committed with impunity; while the one party pleads obedience to the
  • supreme magistrate, the other the sanction of fundamental laws.
  • NOTES, OF SOME REMARKABLE CUSTOMS.
  • [34] His harangue for it is still extant: περι Συμμοριας.
  • [35] Plutarchus in _vita decem oratorum_. Demosthenes gives a different
  • account of this law. (_Contra Aristogiton, Orat. II._) He says that its
  • purport was to render the ατιμοι επιτιμοι, or to restore the privilege
  • of bearing offices to those who had been declared incapable. Perhaps
  • these were both clauses of the same law.
  • [36] The senate of the Bean was only a less numerous mob chosen by lot
  • from among the people, and their authority was not great.
  • [37] _In Ctesiphontem._ It is remarkable that the first step after the
  • dissolution of the Democracy by Critias and the Thirty was to annul the
  • γραφη παρανομων, as we learn from Demosthenes κατα Τιμοκ. The orator
  • in this oration gives us the words of the law establishing the γραφη
  • παρανομων, p. 297, _ex edit._ _Aldi_. And he accounts for it from the
  • same principles we here reason upon.
  • [38] Essay on the Freedom of Wit and Humour, part 3, § 2.
  • OF THE POPULOUSNESS OF ANCIENT NATIONS.​[39]
  • There is very little ground, either from reason or experience, to
  • conclude the universe eternal or incorruptible. The continual and
  • rapid motion of matter, the violent revolutions with which every part
  • is agitated, the changes remarked in the heavens, the plain
  • traces as well as tradition of a universal deluge,—all these prove
  • strongly the mortality of this fabric of the world, and its passage,
  • by corruption or dissolution, from one state or order to another. It
  • must therefore, as well as each individual form which it contains,
  • have its infancy, youth, manhood, and old age; and it is probable that
  • in all these variations man, equally with every animal and vegetable,
  • will partake. In the flourishing age of the world it may be expected
  • that the human species should possess greater vigour both of mind
  • and body, more prosperous health, higher spirits, longer life, and
  • a stronger inclination and power of generation. But if the general
  • system of things, and human society of course, have any such gradual
  • revolutions, they are too slow to be discernible in that short period
  • which is comprehended by history and tradition. Stature and force of
  • body, length of life, even courage and extent of genius, seem hitherto
  • to have been naturally in all ages pretty much the same. The arts and
  • sciences, indeed, have flourished in one period and have decayed in
  • another; but we may observe that at the time when they rose to greatest
  • perfection among one people they were perhaps totally unknown to all
  • the neighbouring nations, and though they universally decayed in one
  • age, yet in a succeeding generation they again revived and diffused
  • themselves over the world. As far, therefore, as observation reaches
  • there is no universal difference discernible in the human species,
  • and though it were allowed that the universe, like an animal
  • body, had a natural progress from infancy to old age; yet, as it must
  • still be uncertain whether at present it be advancing to its point of
  • perfection or declining from it, we cannot thence presuppose any decay
  • in human nature.​[40] To prove, therefore, or account for the greater
  • populousness of antiquity by the imaginary youth or vigour of the world
  • will scarcely be admitted by any just reasoner; these general physical
  • causes ought entirely to be excluded from that question.
  • There are indeed some more particular physical causes of great
  • importance. Diseases are mentioned in antiquity which are almost
  • unknown to modern medicine, and new diseases have arisen and propagated
  • themselves of which there are no traces in ancient history. And in
  • this particular we may observe, upon comparison, that the disadvantage
  • is very much on the side of the moderns. Not to mention some others
  • of less importance, the smallpox commits such ravages as would almost
  • alone account for the great superiority ascribed to ancient times.
  • The tenth or the twelfth part of mankind destroyed every generation
  • should make a vast difference, it may be thought, in the numbers of the
  • people; and when joined to venereal distempers, a new plague diffused
  • everywhere, this disease is perhaps equivalent, by its constant
  • operation, to the three great scourges of mankind—war, pestilence,
  • and famine. Were it certain, therefore, that ancient times were more
  • populous than the present, and could no moral causes be assigned for so
  • great a change, these physical causes alone, in the opinion of many,
  • would be sufficient to give us satisfaction on that head.
  • But is it certain that antiquity was so much more populous as is
  • pretended? The extravagancies of Vossius with regard to this subject
  • are well known; but an author of much greater genius and discernment
  • has ventured to affirm that, according to the best computations which
  • these subjects will admit of, there are not now on the face of the
  • earth the fiftieth part of mankind which existed in the time of Julius
  • Cæsar. It may easily be observed that the comparisons in this case
  • must be very imperfect, even though we confine ourselves to the scene
  • of ancient history—Europe and the nations about the Mediterranean. We
  • know not exactly the numbers of any European kingdom, or even city,
  • at present; how can we pretend to calculate those of ancient cities
  • and states where historians have left us such imperfect traces? For
  • my part, the matter appears to me so uncertain that, as I intend to
  • throw together some reflections on that head, I shall intermingle the
  • inquiry concerning causes with that concerning facts, which ought never
  • to be admitted where the facts can be ascertained with any tolerable
  • assurance. We shall first consider whether it be probable, from what
  • we know of the situation of society in both periods, that antiquity
  • must have been more populous; secondly, whether in reality it was so.
  • If I can make it appear that the conclusion is not so certain as is
  • pretended in favour of antiquity, it is all I aspire to.
  • In general we may observe that the question with regard to the
  • comparative populousness of ages or kingdoms implies very important
  • consequences, and commonly determines concerning the preference of
  • their whole police, their manners, and the constitution of their
  • government. For as there is in all men, both male and female, a desire
  • and power of generation more active than is ever universally exerted,
  • the restraints which they lie under must proceed from some difficulties
  • in their situation, which it belongs to a wise legislature carefully
  • to observe and remove. Almost every man who thinks he can maintain a
  • family will have one, and the human species at this rate of propagation
  • would more than double every generation. How fast do mankind
  • multiply in every colony or new settlement, where it is an easy
  • matter to provide for a family, and where men are nowise straightened
  • or confined as in long established governments? History tells us
  • frequently of plagues which have swept away the third or fourth part of
  • a people; yet in a generation or two the destruction was not perceived,
  • and the society had again acquired their former number. The lands which
  • were cultivated, the houses built, the commodities raised, the riches
  • acquired, enabled the people who escaped immediately to marry and to
  • rear families, which supplied the place of those who had perished.​[41]
  • And for a like reason every wise, just, and mild government, by
  • rendering the condition of its subjects easy and secure, will always
  • abound most in people, as well as in commodities and riches. A country,
  • indeed, whose climate and soil are fitted for vines will naturally
  • be more populous than one which is only fitted for pasturage; but if
  • everything else be equal, it seems natural to expect that wherever
  • there are most happiness and virtue and the wisest institutions, there
  • will also be most people.
  • The question, therefore, concerning the populousness of ancient and
  • modern times being allowed of great importance, it will be requisite,
  • if we would bring it to some determination, to compare both the
  • domestic and political situation of these two periods, in order to
  • judge of the facts by their moral causes, which is the first view in
  • which we proposed to consider them.
  • The chief difference between the domestic economy of the ancients
  • and that of the moderns consists in the practice of slavery which
  • prevailed among the former, and which has been abolished for some
  • centuries throughout the greater part of Europe. Some passionate
  • admirers of the ancients and zealous partisans of civil liberty
  • (for these sentiments, as they are both of them in the main extremely
  • just, are found to be almost inseparable) cannot forbear regretting
  • the loss of this institution; and whilst they brand all submission
  • to the government of a single person with the harsh denomination of
  • slavery, they would gladly reduce the greatest part of mankind to
  • real slavery and subjection. But to one who considers coolly on the
  • subject it will appear that human nature in general really enjoys
  • more liberty at present, in the most arbitrary governments of Europe,
  • than it ever did during the most flourishing period of ancient times.
  • As much as submission to a petty prince, whose dominions extend not
  • beyond a single city, is more grievous than obedience to a great
  • monarch, so much is domestic slavery more cruel and oppressive than
  • any civil subjection whatsoever. The more the master is removed from
  • us in place and rank the greater liberty we enjoy, the less are our
  • actions inspected and controlled, and the fainter that cruel comparison
  • becomes between our own subjection and the freedom and even dominion
  • of another. The remains that are found of slavery in the American
  • colonies and among some European nations would never surely create a
  • desire of rendering it more universal. The little humanity commonly
  • observed in persons accustomed from their infancy to exercise so great
  • authority over their fellow-creatures and to trample upon human nature
  • were sufficient alone to disgust us with that authority. Nor can a more
  • probable reason be given for the severe, I might say barbarous manners
  • of ancient times, than the practice of domestic slavery, by which
  • every man of rank was rendered a petty tyrant and educated amidst the
  • flattery, submission, and low debasement of his slaves.
  • According to the ancient practice, all checks were on the inferior, to
  • restrain him to the duty of submission; none on the superior, to engage
  • him to the reciprocal duties of gentleness and humanity. In modern
  • times a bad servant finds not easily a good master, nor a bad master
  • a good servant, and the checks are mutual, suitable to the
  • inviolable and eternal laws of reason and equity.
  • The custom of exposing old, useless, or sick slaves in an island of the
  • Tiber, there to starve, seems to have been pretty common in Rome, and
  • whoever recovered after having been so exposed had his liberty given
  • him by an edict of the Emperor Claudius, where it was likewise forbid
  • to kill any slave merely for old age or sickness. But supposing that
  • this edict was strictly obeyed, would it better the domestic treatment
  • of slaves or render their lives much more comfortable? We may imagine
  • what others would practise when it was the professed maxim of the
  • elder Cato to sell his superannuated slaves for any price rather than
  • maintain what he esteemed a useless burden.
  • The _ergastula_, or dungeons, where slaves in chains were forced to
  • work, were very common all over Italy. Columella advises that they be
  • always built under ground, and recommends it as the duty of a careful
  • overseer to call over every day the names of these slaves, like the
  • mustering of a regiment or ship’s company, in order to know presently
  • when any of them had deserted. A proof of the frequency of these
  • _ergastula_ and of the great number of slaves usually confined in them.
  • A chained slave for a porter was usual in Rome, as appears from Ovid
  • and other authors. Had not these people shaken off all sense of
  • compassion towards that unhappy part of their species, would they have
  • presented all their friends at the first entrance with such an image of
  • the severity of the master and misery of the slave?
  • Nothing so common in all trials, even of civil causes, as to call for
  • the evidence of slaves, which was always extorted by the most exquisite
  • torments. Demosthenes says that where it was possible to produce for
  • the same fact either freemen or slaves as witnesses, the judges always
  • preferred the torturing of slaves as a more certain and infallible
  • evidence.​[42]
  • Seneca draws a picture of that disorderly luxury which changes day
  • into night and night into day, and inverts every stated hour of every
  • office in life. Among other circumstances, such as displacing the meals
  • and times of bathing, he mentions that regularly about the third hour
  • of the night the neighbours of one who indulges this false refinement
  • hear the noise of whips and lashes, and upon inquiry find that he is
  • then taking an account of the conduct of his servants and giving them
  • due correction and discipline. This is not remarked as an instance of
  • cruelty, but only of disorder, which, even in actions the most usual
  • and methodical, changes the fixed hours that an established custom had
  • assigned them.​[43]
  • But our present business is only to consider the influence of slavery
  • on the populousness of a state. It is pretended that in this particular
  • the ancient practice had infinitely the advantage, and was the chief
  • cause of that extreme populousness which is supposed in those times.
  • At present all masters discourage the marrying of their male servants,
  • and admit not by any means the marriage of the female, who are then
  • supposed altogether incapacitated for their service; but where the
  • property of the servants is lodged in the master, their marriage
  • and fertility form his riches, and bring him a succession of slaves
  • that supply the place of those whom age and infirmity have
  • disabled. He encourages, therefore, their propagation as much as that
  • of his cattle, rears the young with the same care, and educates them
  • to some art or calling, which may render them more useful or valuable
  • to him. The opulent are, by this policy, interested in the being at
  • least, though not the well-being of the poor; and enrich themselves by
  • increasing the number and industry of those who are subjected to them.
  • Each man, being a sovereign in his own family, has the same interest
  • with regard to it as the prince with regard to the state; and has not,
  • like the prince, any opposite motive of ambition or vainglory which may
  • lead him to depopulate his little sovereignty. All of it is, at all
  • times, under his eye, and he has leisure to inspect the most minute
  • detail of the marriage and education of his subjects.​[44]
  • Such are the consequences of domestic slavery, according to the
  • first aspect and appearance of things; but if we enter more deeply
  • into the subject, we shall perhaps find reason to retract our hasty
  • determinations. The comparison is shocking between the management
  • of human creatures and that of cattle; but being extremely just
  • when applied to the present subject, it may be proper to trace the
  • consequences of it. At the capital, near all great cities, in all
  • populous, rich, industrious provinces, few cattle are bred. Provisions,
  • lodging, attendance, labour are there dear, and men find better their
  • account in buying the cattle, after they come to a certain age, from
  • the remoter and cheaper countries. These are consequently the only
  • breeding countries for cattle; and by a parity of reason, for men too,
  • when the latter are put on the same footing with the former.
  • To rear a child in London till he could be serviceable would cost much
  • dearer than to buy one of the same age from Scotland or Ireland, where
  • he had been raised in a cottage, covered with rags, and fed on oatmeal
  • or potatoes. Those who had slaves, therefore, in all the richer or more
  • populous countries would discourage the pregnancy of the females, and
  • either prevent or destroy the birth. The human species would perish in
  • those places where it ought to increase the fastest, and a perpetual
  • recruit be needed from all the poorer and more desert provinces. Such a
  • continued drain would tend mightily to depopulate the state, and render
  • great cities ten times more destructive than with us, where every man
  • is master of himself, and provides for his children from the powerful
  • instinct of nature—not the calculations of sordid interest. If London
  • at present, without increasing, needs a yearly recruit from the country
  • of 5000 people, as is commonly computed, what must it require if the
  • greatest part of the tradesmen and common people were slaves, and were
  • hindered from breeding by their avaricious masters?
  • All ancient authors tell us that there was a perpetual flux of slaves
  • to Italy from the remoter provinces, particularly Syria, Cilicia,​[45]
  • Cappadocia, and the Lesser Asia, Thrace, and Egypt; yet the number
  • of people did not increase in Italy, and writers complain of the
  • continual decay of industry and agriculture. Where then is that extreme
  • fertility of the Roman slaves which is commonly supposed? So far from
  • multiplying, they could not, it seems, so much as keep up the stock
  • without immense recruits. And though great numbers were continually
  • manumitted and converted into Roman citizens, the numbers even of these
  • did not increase till the freedom of the city was communicated to
  • foreign provinces.
  • The term for a slave born and bred in the family was _verna_;​[46] and
  • these slaves seem to have been entitled by custom to privileges and
  • indulgences beyond others—a sufficient reason why the masters would
  • not be fond of rearing many of that kind.​[47] Whoever is acquainted
  • with the maxims of our planters will acknowledge the justness of this
  • observation.​[48]
  • Atticus is much praised by his historian for the care which he took
  • in recruiting his family from the slaves born in it.​[49] May we not
  • thence infer that that practice was not then very common?
  • The names of slaves in the Greek comedies—Syrus, Mysus, Geta, Thrax,
  • Davus, Lydus, Phyrx, etc., afford a presumption that at Athens, at
  • least, most of the slaves were imported from foreign nations. The
  • Athenians, says Strabo, gave to their slaves either the names of the
  • nations whence they were bought, as Lydus, Syrus; or the names that
  • were most common among those nations, as Manes or Midas to a Phrygian,
  • Tibias to a Paphlagonian.
  • Demosthenes, after having mentioned a law which forbid any man to
  • strike the slave of another, praises the humanity of this law, and adds
  • that if the barbarians from whom slaves were bought had information
  • that their countrymen met with such gentle treatment, they would
  • entertain a great esteem for the Athenians. Isocrates, too, insinuates
  • that the slaves of the Greeks were generally or very commonly
  • barbarians. Aristotle, in his _Politics_, plainly supposes that a slave
  • is always a foreigner. The ancient comic writers represented the slaves
  • as speaking a barbarous language. This was an imitation of nature.
  • It is well known that Demosthenes, in his nonage, had been defrauded
  • of a large fortune by his tutors, and that afterwards he recovered,
  • by a prosecution of law, the value of his patrimony. His orations on
  • that occasion still remain, and contain a very exact detail of the
  • whole substance left by his father, in money, merchandise, houses,
  • and slaves, together with the value of each particular. Among the
  • rest were 52 slaves, handicraftsmen—viz., 32 sword-cutlers and 20
  • cabinet-makers,​[50] all males; not a word of any wives, children,
  • or family, which they certainly would have had had it been a
  • common custom at Athens to breed from the slaves; and the value of the
  • whole must have depended very much on that circumstance. No female
  • slaves are even so much as mentioned, except some housemaids who
  • belonged to his mother. This argument has great force, if it be not
  • altogether decisive.
  • Consider this passage of Plutarch, speaking of the elder Cato:—“He
  • had a great number of slaves, whom he took care to buy at the sales
  • of prisoners of war; and he chose them young, that they might easily
  • be accustomed to any diet or manner of life, and be instructed in any
  • business or labour, as men teach anything to young dogs or horses. And
  • esteeming love the chief source of all disorders, he allowed the male
  • slaves to have a commerce with the female in his family, upon paying a
  • certain sum for this privilege; but he strictly forbade all intrigues
  • out of his family.” Are there any symptoms in this narration of that
  • care which is supposed in the ancients, of the marriage and propagation
  • of their slaves? If that was a common practice, founded on general
  • interest, it would surely have been embraced by Cato, who was a great
  • economist, and lived in times when the ancient frugality and simplicity
  • of manners were still in credit and reputation.
  • It is expressly remarked by the writers of the Roman law that scarce
  • any ever purchase slaves with a view of breeding from them.​[51]
  • Our lackeys and housemaids, I own, do not serve much to multiply
  • their species; but the ancients, besides those who attended on their
  • person, had all their labour performed by slaves, who lived, many of
  • them, in their family; and some great men possessed to the number of
  • 10,000. If there be any suspicion, therefore, that this institution was
  • unfavourable to propagation (and the same reason, at least in part,
  • holds with regard to ancient slaves as well as modern servants), how
  • destructive must slavery have proved!
  • History mentions a Roman nobleman who had 400 slaves under the same
  • roof with him; and having been assassinated at home by the furious
  • revenge of one of them, the law was executed with rigour, and all
  • without exception were put to death. Many other Roman noblemen had
  • families equally, or more numerous, and I believe every one will allow
  • that this would scarcely be practicable were we to suppose all the
  • slaves married and the females to be breeders.​[52]
  • So early as the poet Hesiod married slaves, whether male or female,
  • were esteemed very inconvenient. How much more where families had
  • increased to such an enormous size, as in Rome, and where simplicity of
  • manners was banished from all ranks of people?
  • Xenophon in his _Economics_, where he gives directions for the
  • management of a farm, recommends a strict care and attention of
  • laying the male and the female slaves at a distance from each other.
  • He seems not to suppose that they are ever married. The only slaves
  • among the Greeks that appear to have continued their own breed were the
  • Helotes, who had houses apart, and were more the slaves of the public
  • than of individuals.
  • The same author tells us that Nicias’s overseer, by an agreement with
  • his master, was obliged to pay him an obolus a day for each slave,
  • besides maintaining them and keeping up the number. Had the ancient
  • slaves been all breeders, this last circumstance of the contract had
  • been superfluous.
  • The ancients talk so frequently of a fixed, stated portion of
  • provisions assigned to each slave, that we are naturally led to
  • conclude that slaves lived almost all single, and received that portion
  • as a kind of board-wages.
  • The practice, indeed, of marrying the slaves seems not to have been
  • very common even among the country-labourers, where it is more
  • naturally to be expected. Cato, enumerating the slaves requisite
  • to labour a vineyard of a hundred acres, makes them to amount to
  • fifteen—the overseer and his wife (_villicus_ and _villica_) and
  • thirteen male slaves; for an olive plantation of 240 acres, the
  • overseer and his wife and eleven male slaves; and so in proportion to a
  • greater or less plantation or vineyard.
  • Varro, citing this passage of Cato, allows his computation to be just
  • in every respect except the last. “For as it is requisite,” says he,
  • “to have an overseer and his wife, whether the vineyard or plantation
  • be great or small, this must alter the exactness of the proportion.”
  • Had Cato’s computation been erroneous in any other respect it had
  • certainly been corrected by Varro, who seems fond of discovering so
  • trivial an inaccuracy.
  • The same author, as well as Columella, recommends it as requisite to
  • give a wife to the overseer in order to attach him the more strongly to
  • his master’s service. This was therefore a peculiar indulgence granted
  • to a slave in whom so great a confidence was reposed.
  • In the same place Varro mentions it as a useful precaution not to buy
  • too many slaves from the same nations, lest they beget factions and
  • seditions in the family; a presumption that in Italy the greatest part,
  • even of the country-labouring slaves—for he speaks of no other—were
  • bought from the remoter provinces. All the world knows that the
  • family-slaves in Rome, who were instruments of show and luxury, were
  • commonly imported from the east. “Hoc profecere,” says Pliny, speaking
  • of the jealous care of masters, “mancipiorum legiones, et in domo turba
  • externa ac servorum quoque causa nomenclator adhibendus.”
  • It is indeed recommended by Varro to propagate young shepherds in the
  • family from the old ones; for as grazing farms were commonly in remote
  • and cheap places, and each shepherd lived in a cottage apart, his
  • marriage and increase were not liable to the same inconveniences as
  • in dearer places and where many servants lived in a family, which was
  • universally the case in such of the Roman farms as produced wine or
  • corn. If we consider this exception with regard to the shepherds, and
  • weigh the reasons of it, it will serve for a strong confirmation of all
  • our foregoing suspicions.
  • Columella, I own, advises the master to give a reward, and even liberty
  • to a female slave that had reared him above three children, a proof
  • that sometimes the ancients propagated from their slaves, which,
  • indeed, cannot be denied. Were it otherwise the practice of slavery,
  • being so common in antiquity, must have been destructive to a degree
  • which no expedient could repair. All I pretend to infer from these
  • reasonings is that slavery is in general disadvantageous both to the
  • happiness and populousness of mankind, and that its place is much
  • better supplied by the practice of hired servants.
  • The laws, or, as some writers call them, the seditions of the Gracchi,
  • were occasioned by their observing the increase of slaves all over
  • Italy, and the diminution of free citizens. Appian ascribes this
  • increase to the propagation of the slaves; Plutarch to the purchasing
  • of barbarians, who were chained and imprisoned, βαρβαρικα
  • δεσμωτηρια. It is to be presumed that both causes concurred.
  • Sicily, says Florus, was full of _ergastula_, and was cultivated by
  • labourers in chains. Eunus and Athenio excited the servile war by
  • breaking up these monstrous prisons and giving liberty to 60,000
  • slaves. The younger Pompey augmented his army in Spain by the same
  • expedient. If the country-labourers throughout the Roman Empire were
  • so generally in this situation, and if it was difficult or impossible
  • to find separate lodgings for the families of the city-servants,
  • how unfavourable to propagation, as well as to humanity, must the
  • institution of domestic slavery be esteemed.
  • Constantinople at present requires the same recruits of slaves from
  • all the provinces which Rome did of old, and these provinces are of
  • consequence far from being populous.
  • Egypt, according to Monsieur Maillet, sends continual colonies of black
  • slaves to the other parts of the Turkish Empire, and receives annually
  • an equal return of white; the one brought from the inland parts of
  • Africa, the other from Mingrella, Circassia, and Tartary.
  • Our modern convents are no doubt very bad institutions, but there is
  • reason to suspect that anciently every great family in Italy, and
  • probably in other parts of the world, was a species of convent. And
  • though we have reason to detest all those popish institutions as
  • nurseries of the most abject superstition, burdensome to the public
  • and oppressive to the poor prisoners, male as well as female, yet may
  • it be questioned whether they be so destructive to the populousness
  • of a state as is commonly imagined. Were the land which belongs to a
  • convent bestowed on a nobleman, he would spend its revenue on dogs,
  • horses, grooms, footmen, cooks, and housemaids, and his family would
  • not furnish many more citizens than the convent.
  • The common reason why parents thrust their daughters into nunneries
  • is that they may not be overburdened with too numerous a
  • family; but the ancients had a method almost as innocent and more
  • effectual to that purpose—viz., the exposing their children in
  • the earliest infancy. This practice was very common, and is not
  • mentioned by any author of those times with the horror it deserves, or
  • scarce​[53] even with disapprobation. Plutarch—the humane, good-natured
  • Plutarch​[54]—recommends it as a virtue in Attalus, King of Pergamus,
  • that he murdered, or, if you will, exposed all his own children
  • in order to leave his crown to the son of his brother, Eumenes,
  • signalising in this manner his gratitude and affection to Eumenes, who
  • had left him his heir preferable to that son. It was Solon, the most
  • celebrated of the sages of Greece, who gave parents permission by law
  • to kill their children.
  • Shall we then allow these two circumstances to compensate each
  • other—viz., monastic vows and the exposing of children, and to be
  • unfavourable in equal degrees to the propagation of mankind? I doubt
  • the advantage is here on the side of antiquity. Perhaps, by an odd
  • connection of causes, the barbarous practice of the ancients might
  • rather render those times more populous. By removing the terrors of too
  • numerous a family it would engage many people in marriage, and such is
  • the force of natural affection that very few in comparison would have
  • resolution enough to carry into execution their former intentions.
  • China, the only country where this cruel practice of exposing children
  • prevails at present, is the most populous country we know, and every
  • man is married before he is twenty. Such early marriages could scarcely
  • be general had not men the prospect of so easy a method of getting rid
  • of their children. I own that Plutarch speaks of it as a very universal
  • maxim of the poor to expose their children, and as the rich were then
  • averse to marriage on account of the courtship they met with from those
  • who expected legacies from them, the public must have been in a
  • bad situation between them.​[55]
  • Of all sciences there is none where first appearances are more
  • deceitful than in politics. Hospitals for foundlings seem favourable
  • to the increase of numbers, and perhaps may be so when kept under
  • proper restrictions; but when they open the door to every one, without
  • distinction, they have probably a contrary effect, and are pernicious
  • to the state. It is computed that every ninth child born at Paris is
  • sent to the hospital, though it seems certain, according to the common
  • course of human affairs, that it is not a hundredth part whose parents
  • are altogether incapacitated to rear and educate them. The infinite
  • difference, for health, industry, and morals, between an education in
  • an hospital and that in a private family should induce us not to make
  • the entrance into an hospital too easy and engaging. To kill one’s own
  • child is shocking to nature, and must therefore be pretty unusual;
  • but to turn over the care of him upon others is very tempting to the
  • natural indolence of mankind.
  • Having considered the domestic life and manners of the ancients
  • compared to those of the moderns, where in the main we seem rather
  • superior so far as the present question is concerned, we shall now
  • examine the political customs and institutions of both ages, and weigh
  • their influence in retarding or forwarding the propagation of mankind.
  • Before the increase of the Roman power, or rather till its full
  • establishment, almost all the nations which are the scene of
  • ancient history were divided into small territories or petty
  • commonwealths, where of course a great equality of fortune prevailed,
  • and the centre of the government was always very near its frontiers.
  • This was the situation of affairs not only in Greece and Italy,
  • but also in Spain, Gaul, Germany, Africa, and a great part of the
  • Lesser Asia. And it must be owned that no institution could be more
  • favourable to the propagation of mankind; for though a man of an
  • overgrown fortune, not being able to consume more than another, must
  • share it with those who serve and attend him, yet their possession
  • being precarious, they have not the same encouragement to marriage as
  • if each had a small fortune secure and independent. Enormous cities
  • are, besides, destructive to society, beget vice and disorder of all
  • kinds, starve the remoter provinces, and even starve themselves by
  • the prices to which they raise all provisions. Where each man had his
  • little house and field to himself, and each county had its capital,
  • free and independent, what a happy situation of mankind! How favourable
  • to industry and agriculture, to marriage and propagation! The prolific
  • virtue of men, were it to act in its full extent, without that
  • restraint which poverty and necessity imposes on it, would double the
  • number every generation; and nothing surely can give it more liberty
  • than such small commonwealths, and such an equality of fortune among
  • the citizens. All small states naturally produce equality of fortune
  • because they afford no opportunities of great increase, but small
  • commonwealths much more by that division of power and authority which
  • is essential to them.
  • When Xenophon returned after the famous expedition with Cyrus, he hired
  • himself and 6000 of the Greeks into the service of Seuthes, a prince of
  • Thrace; and the articles of his agreement were that each soldier should
  • receive a daric a month, each captain two darics, and he himself, as
  • general, four; a regulation of pay which would not a little surprise
  • our modern officers.
  • Demosthenes and Æschines, with eight more, were sent ambassadors to
  • Philip of Macedon, and their appointments for above four months
  • were a thousand drachmas, which is less than a drachma a day for each
  • ambassador. But a drachma a day—nay, sometimes two, was the pay of a
  • common foot-soldier.
  • A centurion among the Romans had only double pay to a private man in
  • Polybius’s time, and we accordingly find the gratuities after a triumph
  • regulated by that proportion. But Mark Anthony and the triumvirate
  • gave the centurions five times the reward of the other; so much had
  • the increase of the commonwealth increased the inequality among the
  • citizens.​[56]
  • It must be owned that the situation of affairs in modern times with
  • regard to civil liberty, as well as equality of fortune, is not near
  • so favourable either to the propagation or happiness of mankind.
  • Europe is shared out mostly into great monarchies, and such parts of
  • it as are divided into small territories are commonly governed by
  • absolute princes, who ruin their people by a mimicry of the greater
  • monarchs in the splendour of their court and number of their forces.
  • Switzerland alone and Holland resemble the ancient republics, and
  • though the former is far from possessing any advantage either of
  • soil, climate, or commerce, yet the numbers of people with which it
  • abounds, notwithstanding their enlisting themselves into every service
  • in Europe, prove sufficiently the advantages of their political
  • institutions.
  • The ancient republics derived their chief or only security from the
  • numbers of their citizens. The Trachinians having lost great numbers
  • of their people, the remainder, instead of enriching themselves by
  • the inheritance of their fellow-citizens, applied to Sparta, their
  • metropolis, for a new stock of inhabitants. The Spartans immediately
  • collected ten thousand men, among whom the old citizens divided the
  • lands of which the former proprietors had perished.
  • After Timoleon had banished Dionysius from Syracuse and had
  • settled the affairs of Sicily, finding the cities of Syracuse and
  • Sellinuntium extremely depopulated by tyranny, war, and faction,
  • he invited over from Greece some new inhabitants to repeople them.
  • Immediately forty thousand men (Plutarch says sixty thousand) offered
  • themselves, and he distributed so many lots of land among them, to the
  • great satisfaction of the ancient inhabitants; a proof at once of the
  • maxims of ancient policy, which affected populousness more than riches,
  • and of the good effects of these maxims in the extreme populousness
  • of that small country Greece, which could at once supply so large a
  • colony. The case was not much different with the Romans in early times.
  • “He is a pernicious citizen,” said M. Curius, “who cannot be contented
  • with seven acres.”​[57] Such ideas of equality could not fail of
  • producing great numbers of people.
  • We must now consider what disadvantages the ancients lay under with
  • regard to populousness, and what checks they received from their
  • political maxims and institutions. There are commonly compensations in
  • every human condition, and though these compensations be not always
  • perfectly equal, yet they serve, at least, to restrain the prevailing
  • principle. To compare them and estimate their influence is indeed
  • very difficult, even where they take place in the same age, and in
  • neighbouring countries; but where several ages have intervened, and
  • only scattered lights are afforded us by ancient authors, what can we
  • do but amuse ourselves by talking, _pro_ and _con_, on an interesting
  • subject, and thereby correcting all hasty and violent determinations?
  • First, we may observe that the ancient republics were almost in
  • perpetual war, a natural effect of their martial spirit, their love
  • of liberty, their mutual emulation, and that hatred which generally
  • prevails among nations that live in a close neighbourhood. Now, war
  • in a small state is much more destructive than in a great one, both
  • because all the inhabitants in the former case must serve in the
  • armies, and because the state is all frontier and all exposed to the
  • inroads of the enemy.
  • The maxims of ancient war were much more destructive than those of
  • modern, chiefly by the distribution of plunder, in which the soldiers
  • were indulged. The private men in our armies are such a low set of
  • people that we find any abundance beyond their simple pay breeds
  • confusion and disorder, and a total dissolution of discipline. The very
  • wretchedness and meanness of those who fill the modern armies render
  • them less destructive to the countries which they invade; one instance,
  • among many, of the deceitfulness of first appearances in all political
  • reasonings.​[58]
  • Ancient battles were much more bloody by the very nature of the weapons
  • employed in them. The ancients drew up their men sixteen or twenty,
  • sometimes fifty men deep, which made a narrow front, and it was not
  • difficult to find a field in which both armies might be marshalled and
  • might engage with each other. Even where any body of the troops was
  • kept off by hedges, hillocks, woods, or hollow ways, the battle was
  • not so soon decided between the contending parties but that the others
  • had time to overcome the difficulties which opposed them and take part
  • in the engagement. And as the whole armies were thus engaged, and each
  • man closely buckled to his antagonist, the battles were commonly very
  • bloody, and great slaughter was made on both sides, especially on the
  • vanquished. The long thin lines required by firearms, and the
  • quick decision of the fray, render our modern engagements but partial
  • rencounters, and enable the general who is foiled in the beginning
  • of the day to draw off the greatest part of his army, sound and
  • entire. Could Folard’s project of the column take place (which seems
  • impracticable​[59]) it would render modern battles as destructive as
  • the ancient.
  • The battles of antiquity, both by their duration and their resemblance
  • of single combats, were wrought up to a degree of fury quite unknown to
  • later ages. Nothing could then engage the combatants to give quarter
  • but the hopes of profit by making slaves of their prisoners. In civil
  • wars, as we learn from Tacitus, the battles were the most bloody,
  • because the prisoners were not slaves.
  • What a stout resistance must be made where the vanquished expected so
  • hard a fate! How inveterate the rage where the maxims of war were, in
  • every respect, so bloody and severe!
  • Instances are very frequent in ancient history of cities besieged whose
  • inhabitants, rather than open their gates, murdered their wives and
  • children, and rushed themselves on a voluntary death, sweetened perhaps
  • with a little prospect of revenge upon the enemy. Greeks as well as
  • barbarians have been often wrought up to this degree of fury. And the
  • same determined spirit and cruelty must, in many other instances less
  • remarkable, have been extremely destructive to human society in those
  • petty commonwealths which lived in a close neighbourhood, and were
  • engaged in perpetual wars and contentions.
  • Sometimes the wars in Greece, says Plutarch, were carried on entirely
  • by inroads and robberies and piracies. Such a method of war must be
  • more destructive in small states than the bloodiest battles and sieges.
  • By the laws of the twelve tables, possession for two years
  • formed a prescription for land; one year for movables;​[60] an
  • indication that there was not in Italy during that period much more
  • order, tranquillity, and settled police than there is at present among
  • the Tartars.
  • The only cartel I remember in ancient history is that between Demetrius
  • Poliorcetes and the Rhodians, when it was agreed that a free citizen
  • should be restored for 1000 drachmas, a slave bearing arms for 500.
  • But, secondly, it appears that ancient manners were more unfavourable
  • than the modern, not only in times of war but also in those of peace;
  • and that too in every respect, except the love of civil liberty and
  • equality, which is, I own, of considerable importance. To exclude
  • faction from a free government is very difficult, if not altogether
  • impracticable; but such inveterate rage between the factions and
  • such bloody maxims are found, in modern times, amongst religious
  • parties alone, where bigoted priests are the accusers, judges, and
  • executioners. In ancient history we may always observe, where one
  • party prevailed, whether the nobles or people (for I can observe no
  • difference in this respect​[61]), that they immediately butchered all
  • of the opposite party who fell into their hands, and banished such as
  • had been so fortunate as to escape their fury. No form of process, no
  • law, no trial, no pardon. A fourth, a third, perhaps near a half of
  • the city were slaughtered or expelled every revolution; and the exiles
  • always joined foreign enemies and did all the mischief possible to
  • their fellow-citizens, till fortune put it in their power to take full
  • revenge by a new revolution. And as these were very frequent in such
  • violent governments, the disorder, diffidence, jealousy, enmity which
  • must prevail are not easy for us to imagine in this age of the world.
  • There are only two revolutions I can recollect in ancient history
  • which passed without great severity and great effusion of blood in
  • massacres and assassinations—viz., the restoration of the Athenian
  • democracy by Thrasybulus, and the subduing the Roman republic by
  • Cæsar. We learn from ancient history that Thrasybulus passed a general
  • amnesty for all past offences, and first introduced that word as well
  • as practice into Greece. It appears, however, from many orations of
  • Lysias, that the chief, and even some of the subaltern offenders in
  • the preceding tyranny were tried and capitally punished. This is a
  • difficulty not cleared up, and even not observed by antiquarians and
  • historians. And as to Cæsar’s clemency, though much celebrated, it
  • would not gain great applause in the present age. He butchered, for
  • instance, all Cato’s senate, when he became master of Utica; and these,
  • we may readily believe, were not the most worthless of the party. All
  • those who had borne arms against that usurper were forfeited, and, by
  • Hirtius’s law, declared incapable of all public offices.
  • These people were extremely fond of liberty, but seem not to have
  • understood it very well. When the Thirty Tyrants first established
  • their dominion at Athens, they began with seizing all the sycophants
  • and informers who had been so troublesome during the Democracy, and
  • putting them to death by an arbitrary sentence and execution. “Every
  • man,” says Sallust and Lysias,​[62] “rejoiced at these punishments;”
  • not considering that liberty was from that moment annihilated.
  • The utmost energy of the nervous style of Thucydides, and the
  • copiousness and expression of the Greek language, seem to sink under
  • that historian when he attempts to describe the disorders which arose
  • from faction throughout all the Greek commonwealths. You would
  • imagine that he still labours with a thought greater than he can find
  • words to communicate, and he concludes his pathetic description with
  • an observation which is at once very refined and very solid. “In
  • these contests,” says he, “those who were dullest and most stupid,
  • and had the least foresight, commonly prevailed; for being conscious
  • of this weakness, and dreading to be over-reached by those of greater
  • penetration, they went to work hastily, without premeditation, by the
  • sword and poniard, and thereby prevented their antagonists, who were
  • forming fine schemes and projects for their destruction.”​[63]
  • Not to mention Dionysius the elder, who is computed to have butchered
  • in cold blood above 10,000 of his fellow-citizens, nor Agathocles,
  • Nabis, and others still more bloody than he, the transactions, even in
  • free governments, were extremely violent and destructive. At Athens,
  • the Thirty Tyrants and the nobles in a twelvemonth murdered, without
  • trial, about 1200 of the people, and banished above the half of the
  • citizens that remained.​[64] In Argos, near the same time, the people
  • killed 1200 of the nobles, and afterwards their own demagogues, because
  • they had refused to carry their prosecutions further. The people also
  • in Corcyra killed 1500 of the nobles and banished a thousand. These
  • numbers will appear the more surprising if we consider the
  • extreme smallness of these states. But all ancient history is full of
  • such instances.​[65]
  • When Alexander ordered all the exiles to be restored through all the
  • cities, it was found that the whole amounted to 20,000 men, the remains
  • probably of still greater slaughters and massacres. What an astonishing
  • multitude in so narrow a country as ancient Greece! And what domestic
  • confusion, jealousy, partiality, revenge, heart-burnings must tear
  • those cities, where factions were wrought up to such a degree of fury
  • and despair!
  • “It would be easier,” says Isocrates to Philip, “to raise an
  • army in Greece at present from the vagabonds than from the cities.”
  • Even where affairs came not to such extremities (which they failed not
  • to do almost in every city twice or thrice every century), property was
  • rendered very precarious by the maxims of ancient government. Xenophon,
  • in the banquet of Socrates, gives us a very natural, unaffected
  • description of the tyranny of the Athenian people. “In my poverty,”
  • says Charmides, “I am much more happy than ever I was while possessed
  • of riches; as much as it is happier to be in security than in terrors,
  • free than a slave, to receive than to pay court, to be trusted than
  • suspected. Formerly I was obliged to caress every informer, some
  • imposition was continually laid upon me, and it was never allowed me to
  • travel or be absent from the city. At present, when I am poor, I look
  • big and threaten others. The rich are afraid of me, and show me every
  • kind of civility and respect, and I am become a kind of tyrant in the
  • city.”
  • In one of the pleadings of Lysias, the orator very coolly speaks of it,
  • by the by, as a maxim of the Athenian people, that whenever they wanted
  • money they put to death some of the rich citizens as well as strangers,
  • for the sake of the forfeiture. In mentioning this, he seems to have no
  • intention of blaming them, still less of provoking them who were his
  • audience and judges.
  • Whether a man was a citizen or a stranger among that people, it seems
  • indeed requisite either that he should impoverish himself or the people
  • would impoverish him, and perhaps kill him into the bargain. The orator
  • last mentioned gives a pleasant account of an estate laid out in the
  • public service​[66]—that is, above the third of it in raree-shows and
  • figured dances.
  • I need not insist on the Greek tyrannies, which were altogether
  • horrible. Even the mixed monarchies, by which most of the ancient
  • states of Greece were governed before the introduction of republics,
  • were very unsettled. Scarce any city but Athens, says Isocrates, could
  • show a succession of kings for four or five generations.
  • Besides many other obvious reasons for the instability of ancient
  • monarchies, the equal division of property among the brothers in
  • private families must, by a necessary consequence, contribute to
  • unsettle and disturb the state. The universal preference given to the
  • elder by modern laws, though it increases the inequality of fortunes,
  • has, however, this good effect, that it accustoms men to the same idea
  • of public succession, and cuts off all claim and pretension of the
  • younger.
  • The new settled colony of Heraclea, falling immediately into factions,
  • applied to Sparta, who sent Heripidas with full authority to quiet
  • their dissensions. This man, not provoked by any opposition, not
  • inflamed by party rage, knew no better expedient than immediately
  • putting to death about 500 of the citizens. A strong proof how deeply
  • rooted these violent maxims of government were throughout all Greece.
  • If such was the disposition of men’s minds among that refined people,
  • what may be expected in the commonwealths of Italy, Africa, Spain, and
  • Gaul, which were denominated barbarous? Why otherwise did the Greeks
  • so much value themselves on their humanity, gentleness, and moderation
  • above all other nations? This reasoning seems very natural; but
  • unluckily the history of the Roman commonwealth in its earlier times,
  • if we give credit to the received accounts, stands against us. No blood
  • was ever shed in any sedition at Rome till the murder of the Gracchi.
  • Dionysius Halicarnassæus, observing the singular humanity of the Roman
  • people in this particular, makes use of it as an argument that they
  • were originally of Grecian extraction; whence we may conclude that the
  • factions and revolutions in the barbarous republics were usually more
  • violent than even those of Greece above mentioned.
  • If the Romans were so late in coming to blows, they made ample
  • compensation after they had once entered upon the bloody scene; and
  • Appian’s history of their civil wars contains the most frightful
  • picture of massacres, proscriptions, and forfeitures that ever was
  • presented to the world. What pleases most in that historian is that he
  • seems to feel a proper resentment of these barbarous proceedings, and
  • talks not with that provoking coolness and indifference which custom
  • had produced in many of the Greek historians.​[67]
  • The maxims of ancient politics contain, in general, so little humanity
  • and moderation that it seems superfluous to give any particular reason
  • for the violences committed at any particular period; yet I cannot
  • forbear observing that the laws in the latter ages of the Roman
  • commonwealth were so absurdly contrived that they obliged the heads of
  • parties to have recourse to these extremities. All capital punishments
  • were abolished. However criminal, or, what is more, however dangerous
  • any citizen might be, he could not regularly be punished otherwise than
  • by banishment; and it became necessary in the revolutions of party to
  • draw the sword of private vengeance; nor was it easy, when laws were
  • once violated, to set bounds to these sanguinary proceedings. Had
  • Brutus himself prevailed over the Triumvirate, could he, in common
  • prudence, have allowed Octavius and Anthony to live, and have contented
  • himself with banishing them to Rhodes or Marseilles, where they might
  • still have plotted new commotions and rebellions? His executing C.
  • Antonius, brother to the Triumvir, shows evidently his sense of the
  • matter. Did not Cicero, with the approbation of all the wise and
  • virtuous of Rome, arbitrarily put to death Catiline’s associates
  • contrary to law and without any trial or form of process? And if he
  • moderated his executions, did it not proceed either from the clemency
  • of his temper or the conjunctures of the times? A wretched security in
  • a government which pretends to laws and liberty!
  • Thus, one extreme produces another. In the same manner as excessive
  • severity in the laws is apt to beget great relaxation in their
  • execution, so their excessive lenity naturally produces cruelty and
  • barbarity. It is dangerous to force us, in any case, to pass their
  • sacred boundaries.
  • One general cause of the disorders so frequent in all ancient
  • governments seems to have consisted in the great difficulty of
  • establishing any aristocracy in those ages, and the perpetual
  • discontents and seditions of the people whenever even the meanest
  • and most beggarly were excluded from the legislature and from public
  • offices. The very quality of freeman gave such a rank, being opposed
  • to that of slave, that it seemed to entitle the possessor to every
  • power and privilege of the commonwealth. Solon’s laws excluded no
  • freeman from votes or elections, but confined some magistracies to a
  • particular census; yet were the people never satisfied till those laws
  • were repealed. By the treaty with Antipater, no Athenian had a vote
  • whose census was less than 2000 drachmas (about £60 sterling). And
  • though such a government would to us appear sufficiently democratical,
  • it was so disagreeable to that people that above two-thirds of them
  • immediately left their country. Cassander reduced that census to the
  • half, yet still the government was considered as an oligarchical
  • tyranny and the effect of foreign violence.
  • Servius Tullius’s laws seem very equal and reasonable, by fixing the
  • power in proportion to the property, yet the Roman people could never
  • be brought quietly to submit to them.
  • In those days there was no medium between a severe, jealous
  • aristocracy, ruling over discontented subjects, and a turbulent,
  • factious, tyrannical democracy.
  • But, thirdly, there are many other circumstances in which ancient
  • nations seem inferior to the modern, both for the happiness and
  • increase of mankind. Trade, manufactures, industry were nowhere in
  • former ages so flourishing as they are at present in Europe. The only
  • garb of the ancients, both for males and females, seems to have been
  • a kind of flannel which they wore commonly white or gray, and which
  • they scoured as often as it grew dirty. Tyre, which carried on, after
  • Carthage, the greatest commerce of any city in the Mediterranean
  • before it was destroyed by Alexander, was no mighty city, if we credit
  • Arrian’s account of its inhabitants.​[68] Athens is commonly
  • supposed to have been a trading city; but it was as populous before the
  • Median War as at any time after it, according to Herodotus,​[69] and
  • yet its commerce at that time was so inconsiderable that, as the same
  • historian observes, even the neighbouring coasts of Asia were as little
  • frequented by the Greeks as the Pillars of Hercules—for beyond these he
  • conceived nothing.
  • Great interest of money and great profits of trade are an infallible
  • indication that industry and commerce are but in their infancy. We
  • read in Lysias of 100 per cent. profit made of a cargo of two talents,
  • sent to no greater distance than from Athens to the Adriatic. Nor is
  • this mentioned as an instance of exorbitant profit. Antidorus, says
  • Demosthenes, paid three talents and a half for a house which he let at
  • a talent a year; and the orator blames his own tutors for not employing
  • his money to like advantage. “My fortune,” says he, “in eleven years
  • minority ought to have been tripled.” The value of twenty of the slaves
  • left by his father he computes at 40 minas, and the yearly profit of
  • their labour at 12. The most moderate interest at Athens (for there
  • was higher often paid) was 12 per cent., and that paid monthly. Not to
  • insist upon the exorbitant interest of 34 per cent. to which the vast
  • sums distributed in elections had raised money at Rome, we find that
  • Verres, before that factious period, stated 24 per cent. for money,
  • which he left in the publicans’ hands. And though Cicero declaims
  • against this article, it is not on account of the extravagant usury,
  • but because it had never been customary to state any interest on such
  • occasions. Interest, indeed, sunk at Rome after the settlement of the
  • empire; but it never remained any considerable time so low as
  • in the commercial states of modern ages.
  • Among the other inconveniences which the Athenians felt from the
  • fortifying Decelia by the Lacedemonians, it is represented by
  • Thucydides as one of the most considerable that they could not bring
  • over their corn from Eubea by land, passing by Oropus; but were
  • obliged to embark it and to sail about the promontory of Sunium—a
  • surprising instance of the imperfection of ancient navigation, for the
  • water-carriage is not here above double the land.
  • I do not remember any passage in any ancient author where the growth
  • of any city is ascribed to the establishment of a manufacture. The
  • commerce which is said to flourish is chiefly the exchange of those
  • commodities for which different soils and climates were suited. The
  • sale of wine and oil into Africa, according to Diodorus Siculus, was
  • the foundation of the riches of Agrigentum. The situation of the city
  • of Sybaris, according to the same author, was the cause of its immense
  • populousness, being built near the two rivers, Crathys and Sybaris. But
  • these two rivers, we may observe, are not navigable, and could only
  • produce some fertile valleys for agriculture and husbandry—an advantage
  • so inconsiderable that a modern writer would scarcely have taken notice
  • of it.
  • The barbarity of the ancient tyrants, together with the extreme
  • love of liberty which animated those ages, must have banished every
  • merchant and manufacturer, and have quite depopulated the state, had it
  • subsisted upon industry and commerce. While the cruel and suspicious
  • Dionysius was carrying on his butcheries, who that was not detained
  • by his landed property, and could have carried with him any art or
  • skill to procure a subsistence in other countries, would have remained
  • exposed to such implacable barbarity? The persecutions of Philip II.
  • and Louis XIV. filled all Europe with the manufacturers of Flanders and
  • of France.
  • I grant that agriculture is the species of industry which is chiefly
  • requisite to the subsistence of multitudes, and it is possible that
  • this industry may flourish even where manufactures and other
  • arts are unknown and neglected. Switzerland is at present a very
  • remarkable instance, where we find at once the most skilful husbandmen
  • and the most bungling tradesmen that are to be met with in all Europe.
  • That agriculture flourished in Greece and Italy, at least in some parts
  • of them, and at some periods, we have reason to presume; and whether
  • the mechanical arts had reached the same degree of perfection may not
  • be esteemed so material, especially if we consider the great equality
  • in the ancient republics, where each family was obliged to cultivate
  • with the greatest care and industry its own little field in order to
  • its subsistence.
  • But is it just reasoning, because agriculture may in some instances
  • flourish without trade or manufactures, to conclude that, in any great
  • extent of country and for any great tract of time, it would subsist
  • alone? The most natural way surely of encouraging husbandry is first to
  • excite other kinds of industry, and thereby afford the labourer a ready
  • market for his commodities and a return of such goods as may contribute
  • to his pleasure and enjoyment. This method is infallible and universal,
  • and as it prevails more in modern government than in the ancient, it
  • affords a presumption of the superior populousness of the former.
  • Every man, says Xenophon, may be a farmer; no art or skill is
  • requisite: all consists in the industry and attention to the execution.
  • A strong proof, as Columella hints, that agriculture was but little
  • known in the age of Xenophon.
  • All our later improvements and refinements, have they operated
  • nothing towards the easy subsistence of men, and consequently towards
  • their propagation and increase? Our superior skill in mechanics, the
  • discovery of new worlds, by which commerce has been so much enlarged,
  • the establishment of posts, and the use of bills of exchange: these
  • seem all extremely useful to the encouragement of art, industry, and
  • populousness. Were we to strike off these, what a check should we give
  • to every kind of business and labour, and what multitudes of families
  • would immediately perish from want and hunger! And it seems not
  • probable that we could supply the place of these new inventions
  • by any other regulation or institution.
  • Have we reason to think that the police of ancient states was any wise
  • comparable to that of modern, or that men had then equal security
  • either at home or in their journeys by land or water? I question not
  • but every impartial examiner would give us the preference in this
  • particular.
  • Thus, upon comparing the whole, it seems impossible to assign any just
  • reason why the world should have been more populous in ancient than in
  • modern times. The equality of property among the ancients, liberty,
  • and the small divisions of their states, were indeed favourable to
  • the propagation of mankind; but their wars were more bloody and
  • destructive, their governments more factious and unsettled, commerce
  • and manufactures more feeble and languishing, and the general police
  • more loose and irregular. These latter disadvantages seem to form a
  • sufficient counterbalance to the former advantages, and rather favour
  • the opposite opinion to that which commonly prevails with regard to
  • this subject.
  • But there is no reasoning, it may be said, against matter of fact. If
  • it appear that the world was then more populous than at present, we may
  • be assured that our conjectures are false, and that we have overlooked
  • some material circumstance in the comparison. This I readily own: all
  • our preceding reasonings I acknowledge to be mere trifling, or, at
  • least, small skirmishes and frivolous rencounters which decide nothing.
  • But unluckily the main combat, where we compare facts, cannot be
  • rendered much more decisive. The facts delivered by ancient authors are
  • either so uncertain or so imperfect as to afford us nothing positive
  • in this matter. How indeed could it be otherwise? The very facts which
  • we must oppose to them in computing the greatness of modern states are
  • far from being either certain or complete. Many grounds of calculation
  • proceeded on by celebrated writers are little better than those of the
  • Emperor Heliogabalus, who formed an estimate of the immense greatness
  • of Rome from ten thousand pound weight of cobwebs which had been found
  • in that city.
  • It is to be remarked that all kinds of numbers are uncertain in ancient
  • manuscripts, and have been subject to much greater corruptions than
  • any other part of the text, and that for a very obvious reason. Any
  • alteration in other places commonly affects the sense or grammar, and
  • is more readily perceived by the reader and transcriber.
  • Few enumerations of inhabitants have been made of any tract of country
  • by any ancient author of good authority so as to afford us a large
  • enough view for comparison.
  • It is probable that there was formerly a good foundation for the number
  • of citizens assigned to any free city, because they entered for a share
  • of the government, and there were exact registers kept of them. But as
  • the number of slaves is seldom mentioned, this leaves us in as great
  • uncertainty as ever with regard to the populousness even of single
  • cities.
  • The first page of Thucydides is, in my opinion, the commencement of
  • real history. All preceding narrations are so intermixed with fable
  • that philosophers ought to abandon them, in a great measure, to the
  • embellishment of poets and orators.​[70]
  • With regard to remote times, the numbers of people assigned are often
  • ridiculous, and lose all credit and authority. The free citizens of
  • Sybaris, able to bear arms and actually drawn out in battle, were
  • 300,000. They encountered at Siagra with 100,000 citizens of Crotona,
  • another Greek city contiguous to them, and were defeated. This is
  • Diodorus Siculus’s account, and is very seriously insisted on by
  • that historian. Strabo also mentions the same number of Sybarites.
  • Diodorus Siculus, enumerating the inhabitants of Agrigentum, when it
  • was destroyed by the Carthaginians, says that they amounted to 20,000
  • citizens, 200,000 strangers, besides slaves, who, in so opulent a
  • city as he represents it, would probably be at least as numerous. We
  • must remark that the women and the children are not included, and
  • that therefore, upon the whole, the city must have contained near two
  • millions of inhabitants.​[71] And what was the reason of so immense an
  • increase! They were very industrious in cultivating the neighbouring
  • fields, not exceeding a small English county; and they traded with
  • their wine and oil to Africa, which, at that time, had none of these
  • commodities.
  • Ptolemy, says Theocritus, commanded 33,339 cities. I suppose the
  • singularity of the number was the reason of assigning it. Diodorus
  • Siculus assigns three millions of inhabitants to Egypt, a very small
  • number; but then he makes the number of their cities amount to
  • 18,000—an evident contradiction.
  • He says the people were formerly seven millions. Thus remote times are
  • always most envied and admired.
  • That Xerxes’s army was extremely numerous I can readily believe, both
  • from the great extent of his empire and from the foolish practice
  • of the Eastern nations of encumbering their camp with a superfluous
  • multitude; but will any rational man cite Herodotus’s wonderful
  • narrations as an authority? There is something very rational, I own,
  • in Lysias’s argument upon this subject. Had not Xerxes’ army been
  • incredibly numerous, says he, he had never built a bridge over the
  • Hellespont: it had been much easier to have transported his men over so
  • short a passage, with the numerous shipping of which he was master.
  • Polybius says that the Romans, between the first and second Punic Wars,
  • being threatened with an invasion from the Gauls, mustered all
  • their own forces and those of their allies, and found them amount to
  • seven hundred thousand men able to bear arms. A great number surely,
  • and which, when joined to the slaves, is probably not less, if not
  • rather more than that extent of country affords at present.​[72] The
  • enumeration too seems to have been made with some exactness, and
  • Polybius gives us the detail of the particulars; but might not the
  • number be imagined in order to encourage the people?
  • Diodorus Siculus makes the same enumeration amount to near a million.
  • These variations are suspicious. He plainly, too, supposes that Italy
  • in his time was not so populous, another very suspicious circumstance;
  • for who can believe that the inhabitants of that country diminished
  • from the time of the first Punic War to that of the Triumvirates?
  • Julius Cæsar, according to Appian, encountered four millions of Gauls,
  • killed one million, and took another million prisoners.​[73] Supposing
  • the number of the enemy’s army and of the killed could be exactly
  • assigned, which never is possible, how could it be known how often the
  • same man returned into the armies, or how distinguish the new from the
  • old levied soldiers? No attention ought ever to be given to such loose,
  • exaggerated calculations; especially where the author tells us not the
  • mediums upon which the calculations were founded.
  • Paterculus makes the number killed by Cæsar amount only to 400,000: a
  • much more probable account, and more easily reconciled to the history
  • of these wars given by that conqueror himself in his _Commentaries_.
  • One would imagine that every circumstance of the life and actions of
  • Dionysius the elder might be regarded as authentic and free from all
  • fabulous exaggeration, both because he lived at a time when
  • letters flourished most in Greece and because his chief historian was
  • Philistus, a man allowed to be of great genius, and who was a courtier
  • and minister of that prince. But can we admit that he had a standing
  • army of 100,000 foot, 10,000 horse, and a fleet of 400 galleys? These,
  • we may observe, were mercenary forces, and subsisted upon their pay,
  • like our armies in Europe. For the citizens were all disarmed; and
  • when Dion afterwards invaded Sicily and called on his countrymen to
  • vindicate their liberty, he was obliged to bring arms along with him,
  • which he distributed among those who joined him. In a state where
  • agriculture alone flourishes there may be many inhabitants, and if
  • these be all armed and disciplined, a great force may be called out
  • upon occasion; but great numbers of mercenary troops can never be
  • maintained without either trade and manufactures, or very extensive
  • dominions. The United Provinces never were masters of such a force by
  • sea and land as that which is said to belong to Dionysius; yet they
  • possess as large a territory, perfectly well cultivated, and have
  • infinitely more resources from their commerce and industry. Diodorus
  • Siculus allows that, even in his time, the army of Dionysius appeared
  • incredible; that is, as I interpret it, it was entirely a fiction, and
  • the opinion arose from the exaggerated flattery of the courtiers, and
  • perhaps from the vanity and policy of the tyrant himself.
  • It is a very usual fallacy to consider all the ages of antiquity
  • as one period, and to compute the numbers contained in the great
  • cities mentioned by ancient authors as if these cities had been all
  • contemporary. The Greek colonies flourished extremely in Sicily during
  • the age of Alexander; but in Augustus’s time they were so decayed that
  • almost all the product of that fertile island was consumed in Italy.
  • Let us now examine the numbers of inhabitants assigned to particular
  • cities in antiquity, and omitting the numbers of Nineveh, Babylon,
  • and the Egyptian Thebes, let us confine ourselves to the sphere of
  • real history, to the Grecian and Roman states. I must own, the
  • more I consider this subject the more am I inclined to scepticism with
  • regard to the great populousness ascribed to ancient times.
  • Athens is said by Plato to be a very great city; and it was surely
  • the greatest of all the Greek​[74] cities, except Syracuse, which
  • was nearly about the same size in Thucydides’ time, and afterwards
  • increased beyond it; for Cicero​[75] mentions it as the greatest of
  • all the Greek cities in his time, not comprehending, I suppose, either
  • Antioch or Alexandria under that denomination. Athenæus says that, by
  • the enumeration of Demetrius Phalereus, there were in Athens 21,000
  • citizens, 10,000 strangers, and 400,000 slaves. This number is very
  • much insisted on by those whose opinion I call in question, and is
  • esteemed a fundamental fact to their purpose; but, in my opinion, there
  • is no point of criticism more certain than that Athenæus and Ctesicles,
  • whom he cites, are here mistaken, and that the number of slaves is
  • augmented by a whole cypher, and ought not to be regarded as more than
  • 40,000.
  • Firstly, when the number of citizens is said to be 21,000 by
  • Athenæus,​[76] men of full age are only understood. For (1) Herodotus
  • says that Aristagoras, ambassador from the Ionians, found it harder
  • to deceive one Spartan than 30,000 Athenians, meaning in a loose way
  • the whole state, supposed to be met in one popular assembly, excluding
  • the women and children. (2) Thucydides says that, making allowance
  • for all the absentees in the fleet, army, garrisons, and for people
  • employed in their private affairs, the Athenian Assembly never rose to
  • five thousand. (3) The forces enumerated by the same historian,​[77]
  • being all citizens, and amounting to 13,000 heavy-armed infantry,
  • prove the same method of calculation, as also the whole tenor
  • of the Greek historians, who always understand men of full age when
  • they assign the number of citizens in any republic. Now, these being
  • but the fourth of the inhabitants, the free Athenians were by this
  • account 84,000, the strangers 40,000, and the slaves, calculating by
  • the smaller number, and allowing that they married and propagated at
  • the same rate with freemen, were 160,000, and the whole inhabitants
  • 284,000—a large enough number surely. The other number, 1,720,000,
  • makes Athens larger than London and Paris united.
  • Secondly, there were but 10,000 houses in Athens.
  • Thirdly, though the extent of the walls, as given us by Thucydides, be
  • great (viz., eighteen miles, beside the sea-coast), yet Xenophon says
  • there was much waste ground within the walls. They seemed indeed to
  • have joined four distinct and separate cities.​[78]
  • Fourthly, no insurrection of the slaves, nor suspicion of insurrection,
  • are ever mentioned by historians, except one commotion of the miners.
  • Fifthly, the Athenians’ treatment of their slaves is said by Xenophon,
  • and Demosthenes, and Plautus to have been extremely gentle and
  • indulgent, which could never have been the case had the disproportion
  • been twenty to one. The disproportion is not so great in any of our
  • colonies, and yet we are obliged to exercise a very rigorous military
  • government over the negroes.
  • Sixthly, no man is ever esteemed rich for possessing what may be
  • reckoned an equal distribution of property in any country, or
  • even triple or quadruple that wealth. Thus, every person in England is
  • computed by some to spend sixpence a day; yet is he estimated but poor
  • who has five times that sum. Now, Timarchus is said by Æschines to have
  • been left in easy circumstances, but he was master only of ten slaves
  • employed in manufactures. Lysias and his brother, two strangers, were
  • proscribed by the Thirty for their great riches, though they had but
  • sixty apiece. Demosthenes was left very rich by his father, yet he had
  • no more than fifty-two slaves. His workhouse, of twenty cabinet-makers,
  • is said to have been a very considerable manufactory.
  • Seventhly, during the Decelian War, as the Greek historians call it,
  • 20,000 slaves deserted and brought the Athenians to great distress, as
  • we learn from Thucydides. This could not have happened had they been
  • only the twentieth part. The best slaves would not desert.
  • Eighthly, Xenophon proposes a scheme for entertaining by the public
  • 10,000 slaves. “And that so great a number may possibly be supported
  • any one will be convinced,” says he, “who considers the numbers we
  • possessed before the Decelian War”—a way of speaking altogether
  • incompatible with the larger number of Athenæus.
  • Ninthly, the whole census of the state of Athens was less than 6000
  • talents; and though numbers in ancient manuscripts be often suspected
  • by critics, yet this is unexceptionable, both because Demosthenes, who
  • gives it, gives also the detail, which checks him, and because Polybius
  • assigns the same number and reasons upon it. Now, the most vulgar
  • slave could yield by his labour an obolus a day, over and above his
  • maintenance, as we learn from Xenophon, who says that Nicias’s overseer
  • paid his master so much for slaves, whom he employed in digging of
  • mines. If you will take the pains to estimate an obolus a day and the
  • slaves at 400,000, computing only at four years’ purchase, you will
  • find the sum above 12,000 talents, even though allowance be made for
  • the great number of holidays in Athens. Besides, many of the slaves
  • would have a much greater value from their art. The lowest
  • that Demosthenes estimates any of his father’s slaves is two minas a
  • head; and upon this supposition it is a little difficult, I confess,
  • to reconcile even the number of 40,000 slaves with the census of 6000
  • talents.
  • Tenthly, Chios is said by Thucydides to contain more slaves than
  • any Greek city except Sparta. Sparta then had more than Athens, in
  • proportion to the number of citizens. The Spartans were 9000 in the
  • town, 30,000 in the country. The male slaves, therefore, of full age,
  • must have been more than 780,000; the whole more than 3,120,000—a
  • number impossible to be maintained in a narrow barren country such as
  • Laconia, which had no trade. Had the Helotes been so very numerous,
  • the murder of 2000 mentioned by Thucydides would have irritated them
  • without weakening them.
  • Besides, we are to consider that the number assigned by Athenæus,​[79]
  • whatever it is, comprehends all the inhabitants of Attica as well as
  • those of Athens. The Athenians affected much a country life, as we
  • learn from Thucydides, and when they were all chased into town by the
  • invasion of their territory during the Peloponnesian War, the city
  • was not able to contain them, and they were obliged to lie in the
  • porticoes, temples, and even streets, for want of lodging.
  • The same remark is to be extended to all the other Greek cities, and
  • when the number of the citizens is assigned we must always understand
  • it of the inhabitants of the neighbouring country as well as of the
  • city. Yet, even with this allowance, it must be confessed that Greece
  • was a populous country and exceeded what we could imagine of so narrow
  • a territory, naturally not very fertile, and which drew no supplies of
  • corn from other places; for, excepting Athens, which traded
  • to Pontus for that commodity, the other cities seem to have subsisted
  • chiefly from their neighbouring territory.​[80]
  • Rhodes is well known to have been a city of extensive commerce and of
  • great fame and splendour, yet it contained only 6000 citizens able to
  • bear arms when it was besieged by Demetrius.
  • Thebes was always one of the capital cities of Greece, but the number
  • of its citizens exceeded not those of Rhodes.​[81] Phliasia is said
  • to be a small city by Xenophon, yet we find that it contained
  • 6000 citizens. I pretend not to reconcile these two facts. Perhaps
  • Xenophon calls Phliasia a small town because it made but a small figure
  • in Greece and maintained only a subordinate alliance with Sparta;
  • or perhaps the country belonging to it was extensive, and most of
  • the citizens were employed in the cultivation of it and dwelt in the
  • neighbouring villages.
  • Mantinea was equal to any city in Arcadia, consequently it was equal
  • to Megalopolis, which was fifty stadia, or sixty miles and a quarter
  • in circumference. But Mantinea had only 3000 citizens. The Greek
  • cities, therefore, contained often fields and gardens, together with
  • the houses, and we cannot judge of them by the extent of their walls.
  • Athens contained no more than 10,000 houses, yet its walls, with the
  • sea-coast, were about twenty miles in extent. Syracuse was twenty-two
  • miles in circumference, yet was scarcely ever spoken of by the
  • ancients as more populous than Athens. Babylon was a square of fifteen
  • miles, or sixty miles in circuit; but it contained large cultivated
  • fields and enclosures, as we learn from Pliny. Though Aurelian’s wall
  • was fifty miles in circumference, the circuit of all the thirteen
  • divisions of Rome, taken apart, according to Publius Victor, was only
  • about forty-three miles. When an enemy invaded the country all the
  • inhabitants retired within the walls of the ancient cities, with their
  • cattle and furniture and instruments of husbandry, and the great height
  • to which the walls were raised enabled a small number to defend them
  • with facility.
  • “Sparta,” says Xenophon,​[82] “is one of the cities of Greece that has
  • the fewest inhabitants.” Yet Polybius says that it was forty-eight
  • stadia in circumference, and was round.
  • All the Ætolians able to bear arms in Antipater’s time, deducting some
  • few garrisons, were but ten thousand men.
  • Polybius tells us that the Achæan league might, without any
  • inconvenience, march thirty or forty thousand men; and this account
  • seems very probable, for that league comprehended the greatest
  • part of Peloponnesus. Yet Pausanias, speaking of the same period, says
  • that all the Achæans able to bear arms, even when several manumitted
  • slaves were joined to them, did not amount to fifteen thousand.
  • The Thessalians, till their final conquest by the Romans, were in all
  • ages turbulent, factious, seditious, disorderly. It is not, therefore,
  • natural to suppose that that part of Greece abounded much in people.
  • We are told by Thucydides that the part of Peloponnesus adjoining to
  • Pylos was desert and uncultivated. Herodotus says that Macedonia was
  • full of lions and wild bulls, animals which can only inhabit vast
  • unpeopled forests. These were the two extremities of Greece.
  • All the inhabitants of Epirus, of all ages, sexes, and conditions, who
  • were sold by Paulus Æmilius, amounted only to 150,000. Yet Epirus might
  • be double the extent of Yorkshire.
  • Justin tells us that when Philip of Macedon was declared head of the
  • Greek confederacy he called a congress of all the states, except the
  • Lacedemonians, who refused to concur; and he found the force of the
  • whole, upon computation, to amount to 200,000 infantry and 15,000
  • cavalry. This must be understood to be all the citizens capable of
  • bearing arms, for as the Greek republics maintained no mercenary
  • forces, and had no militia distinct from the whole body of the
  • citizens, it is not conceivable what other medium there could be of
  • computation. That such an army could ever by Greece be brought into
  • the field, and could be maintained there, is contrary to all history.
  • Upon this supposition, therefore, we may thus reason. The free Greeks
  • of all ages and sexes were 860,000. The slaves, estimating them by
  • the number of Athenian slaves as above, who seldom married or had
  • families, were double the male citizens of full age—viz., 430,000.
  • And all the inhabitants of ancient Greece, excepting Laconia, were
  • about 1,290,000—no mighty number, nor exceeding what may be found at
  • present in Scotland, a country of nearly the same extent, and very
  • indifferently peopled.
  • We may now consider the numbers of people in Rome and Italy, and
  • collect all the lights afforded us by scattered passages in ancient
  • authors. We shall find, upon the whole, a great difficulty in fixing
  • any opinion on that head, and no reason to support those exaggerated
  • calculations so much insisted on by modern writers.
  • Dionysius Halicarnassæus says that the ancient walls of Rome were
  • nearly of the same compass with those of Athens, but that the suburbs
  • ran out to a great extent, and it was difficult to tell where the town
  • ended or the country began. In some places of Rome, it appears from
  • the same author, from Juvenal, and from other ancient writers,​[83]
  • that the houses were high, and families lived in separate storeys,
  • one above another; but it is probable that these were only the poorer
  • citizens, and only in some few streets. If we may judge from the
  • younger Pliny’s​[84] account of his house, and from Bartoli’s plans
  • of ancient buildings, the men of quality had very spacious palaces;
  • and their buildings were like the Chinese houses at this day, where
  • each apartment is separated from the rest, and rises no higher
  • than a single storey. To which, if we add that the Roman nobility much
  • affected porticoes, and even woods, in town, we may perhaps allow
  • Vossius (though there is no manner of reason for it) to read the famous
  • passage of the elder Pliny​[85] his own way, without admitting
  • the extravagant consequences which he draws from it.
  • The number of citizens who received corn by the public distribution
  • in Augustus’s time was 200,000. This one would esteem a pretty certain
  • ground of calculation, yet it is attended with such circumstances as
  • throw us back into doubt and uncertainty.
  • Did the poorer citizens only receive the distribution? It was
  • calculated, to be sure, chiefly for their benefit; but it appears from
  • a passage in Cicero that the rich might also take their portion, and
  • that it was esteemed no reproach in them to apply for it.
  • To whom was the corn given—whether only to heads of families, or to
  • every man, woman, and child? The portion every month was five modii to
  • each (about five-sixths of a bushel). This was too little for a family,
  • and too much for an individual. A very accurate antiquarian therefore
  • infers that it was given to every man of full years, but he allows the
  • matter to be uncertain.
  • Was it strictly inquired whether the claimant lived within the
  • precincts of Rome, or was it sufficient that he presented himself at
  • the monthly distribution? This last seems more probable.​[86]
  • Were there no false claimants? We are told that Cæsar struck off at
  • once 170,000, who had crept in without a just title; and it is very
  • little probable that he remedied all abuses.
  • But, lastly, what proportion of slaves must we assign to these
  • citizens? This is the most material question, and the most uncertain.
  • It is very doubtful whether Athens can be established as a rule for
  • Rome. Perhaps the Athenians had more slaves, because they employed
  • them in manufactures, for which a capital city like Rome seems not so
  • proper. Perhaps, on the other hand, the Romans had more slaves, on
  • account of their superior luxury and riches.
  • There were exact bills of mortality kept at Rome; but no ancient
  • author has given us the number of burials, except Suetonius, who tells
  • us that in one season there were 30,000 dead carried into the temple
  • of Libetina; but this was during a plague, which can afford no certain
  • foundation for any inference.
  • The public corn, though distributed only to 200,000 citizens,
  • affected very considerably the whole agriculture of Italy, a fact
  • no way reconcilable to some modern exaggerations with regard to the
  • inhabitants of that country.
  • The best ground of conjecture I can find concerning the greatness
  • of ancient Rome is this: We are told by Herodian that Antioch and
  • Alexandria were very little inferior to Rome. It appears from Diodorus
  • Siculus that one straight street of Alexandria, reaching from port to
  • port, was five miles long; and as Alexandria was much more extended in
  • length than breadth, it seems to have been a city nearly of the bulk of
  • Paris,​[87] and Rome might be about the size of London.
  • There lived in Alexandria, in Diodorus Siculus’s time, 300,000 free
  • people, comprehending, I suppose, women and children.​[88] But what
  • number of slaves? Had we any just ground to fix these at an equal
  • number with the free inhabitants, it would favour the foregoing
  • calculation.
  • There is a passage in Herodian which is a little surprising. He says
  • positively that the palace of the emperor was as large as all the rest
  • of the city. This was Nero’s golden house, which is indeed represented
  • by Suetonius and Pliny​[89] as of an enormous extent, but no power of
  • imagination can make us conceive it to bear any proportion to such a
  • city as London.
  • We may observe that, had the historian been relating Nero’s
  • extravagance, and had he made use of such an expression, it would have
  • had much less weight, these rhetorical exaggerations being so apt to
  • creep into an author’s style even when the most chaste and correct; but
  • it is mentioned by Herodian only by the by, in relating the quarrels
  • between Geta and Caracalla.
  • It appears from the same historian that there was then much land
  • uncultivated and put to no manner of use, and he ascribes it as a great
  • praise to Pertinax that he allowed every one to take such land either
  • in Italy or elsewhere and cultivate it as he pleased, without paying
  • any taxes. Lands uncultivated and put to no manner of use! This is not
  • heard of in any part of Christendom, except perhaps in some remote
  • parts of Hungary, as I have been informed. And it surely corresponds
  • very ill with that idea of the extreme populousness of antiquity so
  • much insisted on.
  • We learn from Vopiscus that there was in Etruria much fertile land
  • uncultivated, which the Emperor Aurelian intended to convert into
  • vineyards, in order to furnish the Roman people with a gratuitous
  • distribution of wine: a very proper expedient to dispeople still
  • further that capital and all the neighbouring territories.
  • It may not be amiss to take notice of the account which Polybius gives
  • of the great herds of swine to be met with in Tuscany and Lombardy, as
  • well as in Greece, and of the method of feeding them which was then
  • practised. “There are great herds of swine,” says he, “throughout all
  • Italy, particularly in former times, through Etruria and Cisalpine
  • Gaul. And a herd frequently contains a thousand or more swine. When
  • one of these herds in feeding meets with another they mix together,
  • and the swineherds have no other expedient to separate them than to go
  • to different quarters, where they sound their horn, and these animals,
  • being accustomed to that signal, run immediately each to the horn of
  • his own keeper. Whereas in Greece, if the herds of swine happen to
  • mix in the forests, he who has the greatest flock takes cunningly the
  • opportunity of driving all away. And thieves are very apt to purloin
  • the straggling hogs which have wandered to a great distance from their
  • keeper in search of food.”
  • May we not infer from this account that the North of Italy was then
  • much less peopled and worse cultivated than at present? How could these
  • vast herds be fed in a country so thick of enclosures, so improved by
  • agriculture, so divided by farms, so planted with vines and
  • corn intermingled together? I must confess that Polybius’s relation has
  • more the air of that economy which is to be met with in our American
  • colonies than the management of a European country.
  • We meet with a reflection in Aristotle’s​[90] _Ethics_ which seems to
  • me unaccountable on any supposition, and by proving too much in favour
  • of our present reasoning, may be thought really to prove nothing. That
  • philosopher, treating of friendship, and observing that that relation
  • ought neither to be contracted to the very few nor extended over a
  • great multitude, illustrates his opinion by the following argument. “In
  • like manner,” says he, “as a city cannot subsist if it either have so
  • few inhabitants as ten, or so many as a hundred thousand, so is there
  • a mediocrity required in the number of friends, and you destroy the
  • essence of friendship by running into either extreme.” What! impossible
  • that a city can contain a hundred thousand inhabitants! Had Aristotle
  • never seen nor heard of a city which was near so populous? This, I must
  • own, passes my comprehension.
  • Pliny tells us that Seleucia, the seat of the Greek empire in the
  • East, was reported to contain 600,000 people. Carthage is said by
  • Strabo to have contained 700,000. The inhabitants of Pekin are not
  • much more numerous. London, Paris, and Constantinople may admit of
  • nearly the same computation; at least, the two latter cities do not
  • exceed it. Rome, Alexandria, Antioch we have already spoke of. From the
  • experience of past and present ages one might conjecture that there
  • is a kind of impossibility that any city could ever rise much beyond
  • this proportion. Whether the grandeur of a city be founded on commerce
  • or on empire, there seems to be invincible obstacles which prevent
  • its further progress. The seats of vast monarchies, by introducing
  • extravagant luxury, irregular expense, idleness, dependence, and false
  • ideas of rank and superiority, are improper for commerce.
  • Extensive commerce checks itself by raising the price of all labour and
  • commodities. When a great court engages the attendance of a numerous
  • nobility possessed of overgrown fortunes, the middling gentry remain
  • in their provincial towns, where they can make a figure on a moderate
  • income. And if the dominions of a state arrive at an enormous size,
  • there necessarily arise many capitals in the remoter provinces, whither
  • all the inhabitants except a few courtiers repair for education,
  • fortune, and amusement.​[91] London, by uniting extensive commerce and
  • middling empire, has perhaps arrived at a greatness which no city will
  • ever be able to exceed.
  • Choose Dover or Calais for a centre: draw a circle of two hundred miles
  • radius; you comprehend London, Paris, the Netherlands, the United
  • Provinces, and some of the best cultivated counties of France and
  • England. It may safely, I think, be affirmed that no spot of ground
  • can be found in antiquity, of equal extent, which contained near so
  • many great and populous cities, and was so stocked with riches and
  • inhabitants. To balance, in both periods, the states which possessed
  • most art, knowledge, civility, and the best police seems the truest
  • method of comparison.
  • It is an observation of L’Abbé du Bos that Italy is warmer at present
  • than it was in ancient times. “The annals of Rome tell us,” says he,
  • “that in the year 480 A.U.C. the winter was so severe that it destroyed
  • the trees. The Tiber froze in Rome, and the ground was covered with
  • snow for forty days. When Juvenal describes a superstitious woman, he
  • represents her as breaking the ice of the Tiber that she might perform
  • her ablutions.
  • “‘Hybernum fracta glacie descendet in amnem,
  • Ter matutino Tyberi mergetur.’
  • “He speaks of that river’s freezing as a common event. Many passages
  • of Horace suppose the streets of Rome full of snow and ice. We should
  • have more certainty with regard to this point had the ancients known
  • the use of thermometers; but their writers, without intending it,
  • give us information sufficient to convince us that the winters are
  • now much more temperate at Rome than formerly. At present the Tiber
  • no more freezes at Rome than the Nile at Cairo. The Romans esteem the
  • winter very rigorous if the snow lies two days, and if one sees for
  • eight-and-forty hours a few icicles hang from a fountain that has a
  • north exposition.”
  • The observation of this ingenious critic may be extended to other
  • European climates. Who could discover the mild climate of France in
  • Diodorus Siculus’s description of that of Gaul? “As it is a northern
  • climate,” says he, “it is infested with cold to an extreme degree. In
  • cloudy weather, instead of rain, there fall great snows, and in clear
  • weather it there freezes so excessive hard that the rivers acquire
  • bridges of their own substance, over which not only single travellers
  • may pass, but large armies, accompanied with all their baggage and
  • loaded waggons. And there being many rivers in Gaul—the Rhone, the
  • Rhine, etc.—almost all of them are frozen over, and it is usual, in
  • order to prevent falling, to cover the ice with chaff and straw at the
  • places where the road passes.” “Colder than a Gallic winter” is used by
  • Petronius as a proverbial expression.
  • “North of the Cevennes,” says Strabo, “Gaul produces not figs and
  • olives, and the vines which have been planted bear not grapes that will
  • ripen.”
  • Ovid positively maintains, with all the serious affirmation of prose,
  • that the Euxine Sea was frozen over every winter in his time, and
  • he appeals to Roman governors, whom he names, for the truth of his
  • assertion. This seldom or never happens at present in the latitude of
  • Tomi, whither Ovid was banished. All the complaints of the same poet
  • seem to mark a rigour of the seasons which is scarce experienced at
  • present in Petersburg or Stockholm.
  • Tournefort, a Provençal, who had travelled into the same
  • countries, observes that there is not a finer climate in the world;
  • and he asserts that nothing but Ovid’s melancholy could have given him
  • such dismal ideas of it.
  • But the facts mentioned by that poet are too circumstantial to bear any
  • such interpretation.
  • Polybius says that the climate in Arcadia was very cold, and the air
  • moist.
  • “Italy,” says Varro, “is the most temperate climate in Europe. The
  • inland parts” (Gaul, Germany, and Pannonia, no doubt) “have almost
  • perpetual winter.”
  • The northern parts of Spain, according to Strabo, are but ill inhabited
  • because of the great cold.
  • Allowing, therefore, this remark to be just, that Europe is become
  • warmer than formerly, how can we account for it? Plainly by no other
  • method than by supposing that the land is at present much better
  • cultivated, and that the woods are cleared which formerly threw a shade
  • upon the earth and kept the rays of the sun from penetrating to it. Our
  • northern colonies in America become more temperate in proportion as the
  • woods are felled,​[92] but in general, every one may remark that cold
  • still makes itself more severely felt both in North and South America,
  • than in places under the same latitude in Europe.
  • Saserna, quoted by Columella, affirmed that the disposition of the
  • heavens was altered before his time, and that the air had become much
  • milder and warmer. “As appears hence,” says he, “that many places now
  • abound with vineyards and olive plantations which formerly, by reason
  • of the rigour of the climate, could raise none of these productions.”
  • Such a change, if real, will be allowed an evident sign of the better
  • cultivation and peopling of countries before the age of Saserna;​[93]
  • and if it be continued to the present times, is a proof that
  • these advantages have been continually increasing throughout this part
  • of the world.
  • Let us now cast our eye over all the countries which were the scene
  • of ancient and modern history, and compare their past and present
  • situation. We shall not, perhaps, find such foundation for the
  • complaint of the present emptiness and depopulation of the world. Egypt
  • is represented by Maillet, to whom we owe the best account of it, as
  • extremely populous, though he esteems the number of its inhabitants
  • to be diminished. Syria, and the Lesser Asia, as well as the coast of
  • Barbary, I can really own to be very desert in comparison of their
  • ancient condition. The depopulation of Greece is also very obvious. But
  • whether the country now called Turkey in Europe may not, in general,
  • contain as many inhabitants as during the flourishing period of Greece
  • may be a little doubtful. The Thracians seem then to have lived like
  • the Tartars at present, by pillage and plunder; the Getes were still
  • more uncivilized, and the Illyrians were no better. These occupy
  • nine-tenths of that country, and though the government of the Turks be
  • not very favourable to industry and propagation, yet it preserves at
  • least peace and order among the inhabitants, and is preferable to that
  • barbarous, unsettled condition in which they anciently lived.
  • Poland and Muscovy in Europe are not populous, but are certainly much
  • more so than the ancient Sarmatia and Scythia, where no husbandry or
  • tillage was ever heard of, and pasturage was the sole art by which
  • the people were maintained. The like observation may be extended to
  • Denmark and Sweden. No one ought to esteem the immense swarms of
  • people which formerly came from the North, and overran all Europe, to
  • be any objection to this opinion. Where a whole nation, or even half
  • of it, remove their seat, it is easy to imagine what a prodigious
  • multitude they must form, with what desperate valour they must make
  • their attacks, and how the terror they strike into the invaded nations
  • will make these magnify, in their imagination, both the courage and
  • multitude of the invaders. Scotland is neither extensive nor populous,
  • but were the half of its inhabitants to seek new seats they
  • would form a colony as large as the Teutons and Cimbri, and would
  • shake all Europe, supposing it in no better condition for defence than
  • formerly.
  • Germany has surely at present twenty times more inhabitants than in
  • ancient times, when they cultivated no ground, and each tribe valued
  • itself on the extensive desolation which it spread around, as we
  • learn from Cæsar, and Tacitus, and Strabo. A proof that the division
  • into small republics will not alone render a nation populous, unless
  • attended with the spirit of peace, order, and industry.
  • The barbarous condition of Britain in former times is well known, and
  • the thinness of its inhabitants may easily be conjectured, both from
  • their barbarity and from a circumstance mentioned by Herodian, that all
  • Britain was marshy, even in Severus’s time, after the Romans had been
  • fully settled in it above a whole century.
  • It is not easily imagined that the Gauls were anciently much more
  • advanced in the arts of life than their northern neighbours, since they
  • travelled to this island for their education in the mysteries of the
  • religion and philosophy of the Druids.​[94] I cannot therefore think
  • that Gaul was then near so populous as France is at present.
  • Were we to believe, indeed, and join together the testimony of Appian
  • and that of Diodorus Siculus, we must admit an incredible populousness
  • in Gaul. The former historian says that there were 400 nations in that
  • country; the latter affirms that the largest of the Gallic nations
  • consisted of 200,000 men, besides women and children, and the least
  • of 50,000. Calculating therefore at a medium, we must admit of near
  • 200,000,000 of people in a country which we esteem populous at present,
  • though supposed to contain little more than twenty.​[95] Such
  • calculations therefore by their extravagance lose all manner of
  • authority. We may observe that that equality of property, to which
  • the populousness of antiquity may be ascribed, had no place among the
  • Gauls. Their intestine wars also, before Cæsar’s time, were almost
  • perpetual. And Strabo observes that though all Gaul was cultivated,
  • yet it was not cultivated with any skill or care, the genius of the
  • inhabitants leading them less to arts than arms, till their slavery to
  • Rome produced peace among themselves.
  • Cæsar enumerates very particularly the great forces which were levied
  • at Belgium to oppose his conquests, and makes them amount to 208,000.
  • These were not the whole people able to bear arms in Belgium; for the
  • same historian tells us that the Bellovaci could have brought a hundred
  • thousand men into the field, though they engaged only for sixty. Taking
  • the whole, therefore, in this proportion of ten to six, the sum of
  • fighting men in all the states of Belgium was about 350,000; all the
  • inhabitants a million and a half. And Belgium being about the fourth of
  • Gaul, that country might contain six millions, which is not the third
  • of its present inhabitants.​[96] We are informed by Cæsar that the
  • Gauls had no fixed property in land; but that the chieftains, when any
  • death happened in a family, made a new division of all the lands among
  • the several members of the family. This is the custom of Tanistry,
  • which so long prevailed in Ireland, and which retained that
  • country in a state of misery, barbarism, and desolation.
  • The ancient Helvetia was 250 miles in length and 180 in breadth,
  • according to the same author, yet contained only 360,000 inhabitants.
  • The Canton of Berne alone has at present as many people.
  • After this computation of Appian and Diodorus Siculus, I know not
  • whether I dare affirm that the modern Dutch are more numerous than the
  • ancient Batavi.
  • Spain is decayed from what it was three centuries ago; but if we step
  • backward two thousand years and consider the restless, turbulent,
  • unsettled condition of its inhabitants, we may probably be inclined
  • to think that it is now much more populous. Many Spaniards killed
  • themselves when deprived of their arms by the Romans. It appears from
  • Plutarch that robbery and plunder were esteemed honourable among the
  • Spaniards. Hirtius represents in the same light the situation of that
  • country in Cæsar’s time, and he says that every man was obliged to
  • live in castles and walled towns for his security. It was not till its
  • final conquest under Augustus that these disorders were repressed.
  • The account which Strabo and Justin give of Spain corresponds exactly
  • with those above mentioned. How much therefore must it diminish from
  • our idea of the populousness of antiquity when we find that Cicero,
  • comparing Italy, Africa, Gaul, Greece, and Spain, mentions the great
  • number of inhabitants as the peculiar circumstance which rendered this
  • latter country formidable.​[97]
  • Italy, it is probable however, has decayed; but how many great cities
  • does it still contain? Venice, Genoa, Pavia, Turin, Milan, Naples,
  • Florence, Leghorn, which either subsisted not in ancient times,
  • or were then very inconsiderable. If we reflect on this, we shall not
  • be apt to carry matters to so great an extreme as is usual with regard
  • to this subject.
  • When the Roman authors complain that Italy, which formerly exported
  • corn, became dependent on all the provinces for its daily bread, they
  • never ascribe this alteration to the increase of its inhabitants, but
  • to the neglect of tillage and agriculture. A natural effect of that
  • pernicious practice of importing corn in order to distribute it gratis
  • among the Roman citizens, and a very bad means of multiplying the
  • inhabitants of any country.​[98] The sportula, so much talked of by
  • Martial and Juvenal, being presents regularly made by the great lords
  • to their smaller clients, must have had a like tendency to produce
  • idleness, debauchery, and a continual decay among the people. The
  • parish-rates have at present the same bad consequences in England.
  • Were I to assign a period when I imagine this part of the world might
  • possibly contain more inhabitants than at present, I should pitch
  • upon the age of Trajan and the Antonines, the great extent of the
  • Roman Empire being then civilized and cultivated, settled almost in a
  • profound peace both foreign and domestic, and living under the same
  • regular police and government.​[99] But we are told that all
  • extensive governments, especially absolute monarchies, are destructive
  • to population, and contain a secret vice and poison, which destroy the
  • effect of all these promising appearances. To confirm this, there is a
  • passage cited from Plutarch, which being somewhat singular, we shall
  • here examine it.
  • That author, endeavouring to account for the silence of many of the
  • oracles, says that it may be ascribed to the present desolation of the
  • world, proceeding from former wars and factions, which common calamity,
  • he adds, has fallen heavier upon Greece than on any other country;
  • insomuch that the whole could scarce at present furnish three thousand
  • warriors, a number which, in the time of the Median War, were supplied
  • by the single city of Megara. The gods, therefore, who affect works
  • of dignity and importance, have suppressed many of their oracles, and
  • deign not to use so many interpreters of their will to so diminutive a
  • people.
  • I must confess that this passage contains so many difficulties that
  • I know not what to make of it. You may observe that Plutarch assigns
  • for a cause of the decay of mankind not the extensive dominion of the
  • Romans, but the former wars and factions of the several nations, all
  • which were quieted by the Roman arms. Plutarch’s reasoning, therefore,
  • is directly contrary to the inference which is drawn from the fact he
  • advances.
  • Polybius supposes that Greece had become more prosperous and
  • flourishing after the establishment of the Roman yoke;​[100] and though
  • that historian wrote before these conquerors had degenerated
  • from being the patrons to be the plunderers of mankind, yet as we find
  • from Tacitus that the severity of the emperors afterwards checked the
  • licence of the governors, we have no reason to think that extensive
  • monarchy so destructive as it is so often represented.
  • We learn from Strabo that the Romans, from their regard to the Greeks,
  • maintained, to his time, most of the privileges and liberties of
  • that celebrated nation, and Nero afterwards rather increased them.
  • How therefore can we imagine that the Roman yoke was so burdensome
  • over that part of the world? The oppression of the proconsuls was
  • restrained, and the magistracies in Greece being all bestowed in the
  • several cities by the free votes of the people, there was no great
  • necessity for the competitors to attend the emperor’s court. If great
  • numbers went to seek their fortunes in Rome, and advance themselves by
  • learning or eloquence, the commodities of their native country, many
  • of them would return with the fortunes which they had acquired, and
  • thereby enrich the Grecian commonwealths.
  • But Plutarch says that the general depopulation had been more sensibly
  • felt in Greece than in any other country. How is this reconcilable to
  • its superior privileges and advantages?
  • Besides, this passage by proving too much really proves nothing. Only
  • three thousand men able to bear arms in all Greece! Who can admit so
  • strange a proposition, especially if we consider the great number
  • of Greek cities whose names still remain in history, and which are
  • mentioned by writers long after the age of Plutarch? There are there
  • surely ten times more people at present, when there scarce remains
  • a city in all the bounds of ancient Greece. That country is still
  • tolerably cultivated, and furnishes a sure supply of corn in case of
  • any scarcity in Spain, Italy, or the South of France.
  • We may observe that the ancient frugality of the Greeks, and their
  • equality of property, still subsisted during the age of Plutarch, as
  • appears from Lucian. Nor is there any ground to imagine that
  • that country was possessed by a few masters and a great number of
  • slaves.
  • It is probable, indeed, that military discipline, being entirely
  • useless, was extremely neglected in Greece after the establishment
  • of the Roman Empire; and if these commonwealths, formerly so warlike
  • and ambitious, maintained each of them a small city-guard to prevent
  • mobbish disorders, it is all they had occasion for; and these, perhaps,
  • did not amount to three thousand men throughout all Greece. I own that
  • if Plutarch had this fact in his eye, he is here guilty of a very gross
  • paralogism, and assigns causes nowise proportioned to the effects. But
  • is it so great a prodigy that an author should fall into a mistake of
  • this nature?​[101]
  • But whatever force may remain in this passage of Plutarch, we shall
  • endeavour to counterbalance it by as remarkable a passage in Diodorus
  • Siculus, where the historian, after mentioning Ninus’s army of
  • 1,700,000 foot and 200,000 horse, endeavours to support the credibility
  • of this account by some posterior facts; and adds that we must not
  • form a notion of the ancient populousness of mankind from the present
  • emptiness and depopulation which is spread over the world. Thus an
  • author, who lived at that very period of antiquity which is represented
  • as most populous,​[102] complains of the desolation which then
  • prevailed, gives the preference to former times, and has recourse to
  • ancient fables as a foundation for his opinion. The humour of blaming
  • the present and admiring the past is strongly rooted in human nature,
  • and has an influence even on persons endued with the most profound
  • judgment and most extensive learning.
  • NOTES, OF THE POPULOUSNESS OF ANCIENT NATIONS.
  • [39] An ingenious writer has honoured this discourse with an answer
  • full of politeness, erudition, and good sense. So learned a refutation
  • would have made the author suspect that his reasonings were entirely
  • overthrown, had he not used the precaution from the beginning to keep
  • himself on the sceptical side; and having taken this advantage of the
  • ground, he was enabled, though with much inferior forces, to preserve
  • himself from a total defeat. That reverend gentleman will always find,
  • where his antagonist is so entrenched, that it will be difficult to
  • enforce him. Varro, in such a situation, could defend himself against
  • Hannibal, Pharnaces against Cæsar. The author, however, very willingly
  • acknowledges that his antagonist has detected many mistakes both in
  • his authorities and reasonings; and it was owing entirely to that
  • gentleman’s indulgence that many more errors were not remarked. In this
  • edition advantage has been taken of his learned animadversions, and the
  • essay has been rendered less imperfect than formerly.
  • [40] Columella says (lib. 3, cap. 8) that in Egypt and Africa the
  • bearing of twins was frequent and even customary; _gemini partus
  • familiares, ac pæne solennes sunt_. If this was true, there is a
  • physical difference both in countries and ages, for travellers make
  • no such remarks of these countries at present; on the contrary, we
  • are apt to suppose the northern nations more fertile. As those two
  • countries were provinces of the Roman Empire, it is difficult, though
  • not altogether absurd, to suppose that such a man as Columella might be
  • mistaken with regard to them.
  • [41] This too is a good reason why the smallpox does not depopulate
  • countries so much as may at first sight be imagined. Where there
  • is room for more people they will always arise, even without the
  • assistance of naturalisation bills. It is remarked by Don Geronimo
  • de Ustariz that the provinces of Spain which send most people to the
  • Indies are most populous, which proceeds from their superior riches.
  • [42] The same practice was common in Rome, but Cicero seems not to
  • think this evidence so certain as the testimony of free citizens. (_Pro
  • Cælio_.)
  • [43] Epistle 122. The inhuman sports exhibited at Rome may justly be
  • considered too as an effect of the people’s contempt for slaves, and
  • was also a great cause of the general inhumanity of their princes and
  • rulers. Who can read the accounts of the amphitheatrical entertainments
  • without horror? Or who is surprised that the emperors should treat
  • that people in the same way the people treated their inferiors?
  • One’s humanity on that occasion is apt to renew the barbarous wish
  • of Caligula, that the people had but one neck. A man could almost be
  • pleased by a single blow to put an end to such a race of monsters. “You
  • may thank God,” says the author above cited (Epistle 7), addressing
  • himself to the Roman people, “that you have a master (viz., the mild
  • and merciful Nero) who is incapable of learning cruelty from your
  • example.” This was spoken in the beginning of his reign; but he fitted
  • them very well afterwards, and no doubt was considerably improved by
  • the sight of the barbarous objects to which he had from his infancy
  • been accustomed.
  • [44] We may here observe that if domestic slavery really increased
  • populousness, it would be an exception to the general rule, that the
  • happiness of any society and its populousness are necessary attendants.
  • A master, from humour or interest, may make his slaves very unhappy,
  • and yet be careful, from interest, to increase their number. Their
  • marriage is not a matter of choice with them, no more than any other
  • action of their life.
  • [45] Ten thousand slaves in a day have been often sold for the use of
  • the Romans at Delus in Cilicia.—Strabo, lib. 14.
  • [46] As _servus_ was the name of the genus, and _verna_ of the
  • species, without any correlative, this forms a strong presumption
  • that the latter were by far the least numerous. It is a universal
  • observation which we may form upon language that where two related
  • parts of a whole bear any proportion to each other in numbers, rank,
  • or consideration, there are always correlative terms invented which
  • answer to both the parts, and express their mutual relation. If they
  • bear no proportion to each other, the term is only invented for the
  • less, and marks its distinction from the whole. Thus man and woman,
  • master and servant, father and son, prince and subject, stranger and
  • citizen are correlative terms; but the words—seaman, carpenter, smith,
  • tailor, etc., have no correspondent terms which express those who are
  • no seaman, no carpenter, etc. Languages differ very much with regard
  • to the particular words where this distinction obtains, and may thence
  • afford very strong inferences concerning the manners and customs of
  • different nations. The military government of the Roman emperors had
  • exalted the soldiery so high that they balanced all the other orders of
  • the state; hence _miles_ and _paganus_ became relative terms, a thing
  • till then unknown to ancient, and still so to modern languages. Modern
  • superstition has exalted the clergy so high that they overbalance
  • the whole state; hence clergy and laity are terms opposed in all
  • modern languages, and in these alone. And from the same principles I
  • infer that if the number of slaves bought by the Romans from foreign
  • countries had not extremely exceeded those bred at home, _verna_ would
  • have had a correlative which would have expressed the former species of
  • slaves; but these, it would seem, composed the main body of the ancient
  • slaves, and the latter were but a few exceptions.
  • [47] _Verna_ is used by the Roman writers as a word equivalent to
  • _scurra_, on account of the petulance and impudence of those slaves.
  • (Mart., lib. 1, ep. 42.) Horace also mentions the _vernæ procaces_; and
  • Petronius (cap. 24), _vernula urbanitas_. Seneca (_de provid._, cap.
  • 1), _vernularum licentia_.
  • [48] It is computed in the West Indies that a stock of slaves grow
  • worse five per cent. every year unless new slaves be bought to recruit
  • them. They are not able to keep up their number even in those warm
  • countries where clothes and provisions are so easily got. How much more
  • must this happen in European countries, and in or near great cities?
  • [49] Corn. Nepos in _Vita Attici_. We may remark that Atticus’s estate
  • lay chiefly in Epirus, which being a remote, desolate place, would
  • render it profitable for him to rear slaves there.
  • [50] κλινοποι οι, makers of those beds which the ancients lay upon at
  • meals.
  • [51] “Non temere ancillæ ejus rei causa comparantur ut pariant”
  • (_Digest._ lib. 5, tit. 3, _de hæred. petit._ _lex_ 27). The following
  • texts are to the same purpose:—“Spadonem morbosum non esse, neque
  • vitiosum, verius mihi videtur; sed sanum esse, sicuti illum qui unum
  • testiculum habet, qui etiam generare potest” (_Digest._ lib. 2, tit.
  • 1, _de ædilitio edicto_, _lex 6_, § 2). “Sin autem quis ita spado sit,
  • ut tam necessaria pars corporis penitus absit, morbosus est” (_Id._
  • _lex 7_). His impotence, it seems, was only regarded so far as his
  • health or life might be affected by it; in other respects he was full
  • as valuable. The same reasoning is employed with regard to female
  • slaves. “Quæritur de ea muliere quæ semper mortuos parit, an morbosa
  • sit? et ait Sabinus, si vulvæ vitio hoc contingit, morbosam esse”
  • (_Id._ _lex_ 14). It has even been doubted whether a woman pregnant
  • was morbid or vitiated, and it is determined that she is sound, not on
  • account of the value of her offspring, but because it is the natural
  • part or office of women to bear children. “Si mulier prægnans venerit,
  • inter omnes convenit sanam eam esse. Maximum enim ac præcipuum munus
  • fœminarum accipere ac tueri conceptum. Puerperam quoque sanam esse; si
  • modo nihil extrinsecus accedit, quod corpus ejus in aliquam valetudinem
  • immitteret. De sterili Cœlius distinguere Trebatium dicit, ut si natura
  • sterilis sit, sana sit; si vitio corporis, contra” (_Id._).
  • [52] The slaves in the great houses had little rooms assigned them,
  • called _cellæ_; whence the name of cell was transferred to the monk’s
  • room in a convent. See further on this head, Just. Lipsius, Saturn.
  • 1, cap. 14. These form strong presumptions against the marriage and
  • propagation of the family slaves.
  • [53] Tacitus blames it—_De morib. Germ._
  • [54] _De fraterno amore._ Seneca also approves of the exposing of
  • sickly, infirm children (_De ira_, lib. i. cap. 15).
  • [55] The practice of leaving great sums of money to friends, though one
  • had near relations, was common in Greece as well as Rome, as we may
  • gather from Lucian. This practice prevails much less in modern times;
  • and Ben Jonson’s _Volpone_ is therefore almost entirely extracted from
  • ancient authors, and suits better the manners of those times.
  • It may justly be thought that the liberty of divorces in Rome was
  • another discouragement to marriage. Such a practice prevents not
  • quarrels from humour, but rather increases them; and occasions also
  • those from interest, which are much more dangerous and destructive.
  • Perhaps too the unnatural lusts of the ancients ought to be taken into
  • consideration as of some moment.
  • [56] Cæsar gave the centurions ten times the gratuity of the common
  • soldiers (_De bell. Gallico_, lib. viii.). In the Rhodian cartel,
  • mentioned afterwards, no distinction in the ransom was made on account
  • of ranks in the army.
  • [57] Plin. lib. 18, cap. 3. The same author, in cap. 6, says, “Verumque
  • fatentibus latifundia perdidere Italiam; jam vero et provincias. Sex
  • domo semissem Africæ possidebant, cum interfecit eos Nero princeps.” In
  • this view the barbarous butchery committed by the first Roman emperors
  • was not perhaps so destructive to the public as we may imagine. These
  • never ceased till they had extinguished all the illustrious families
  • which had enjoyed the plunder of the world during the latter ages
  • of the republic. The new nobles who rose in their place were less
  • splendid, as we learn from Tacit. _Ann._ lib. 3, cap. 55.
  • [58] The ancient soldiers, being free citizens above the lowest
  • rank, were all married. Our modern soldiers are either forced to
  • live unmarried, or their marriages turn to small account towards the
  • increase of mankind—a circumstance which ought, perhaps, to be taken
  • into consideration, as of some consequence in favour of the ancients.
  • [59] What is the advantage of the column after it has broken the
  • enemy’s line? Only that it then takes them in flank, and dissipates
  • whatever stands near it by a fire from all sides; but till it has
  • broken them, does it not present a flank to the enemy, and that exposed
  • to their musketry, and, what is much worse, to their cannon?
  • [60] Inst. lib. 2, cap. 6. It is true the same law seems to have
  • been continued till the time of Justinian, but abuses introduced by
  • barbarism are not always corrected by civility.
  • [61] Lysias, who was himself of the popular faction and very narrowly
  • escaped from the Thirty Tyrants, says that the democracy was as violent
  • a government as the oligarchy. Orat. 24, _de statu. popul._
  • [62] Orat. 24. And in Orat. 29 he mentions the factious spirit of the
  • popular assemblies as the only cause why these illegal punishments
  • should displease.
  • [63] Lib. 3. The country in Europe in which I have observed the
  • factions to be most violent, and party hatred the strongest, is
  • Ireland. This goes so far as to cut off even the most common
  • intercourse of civilities between the Protestants and Catholics. Their
  • cruel insurrections, and the severe revenges which they have taken of
  • each other, are the causes of this mutual ill-will, which is the chief
  • source of the disorder, poverty, and depopulation of that country. The
  • Greek factions I imagine to have been inflamed still to a higher degree
  • of rage, the revolutions being commonly more frequent, and the maxims
  • of assassination much more avowed and acknowledged.
  • [64] Diod. Sic., lib. 14. Isocrates says there were only 5000 banished.
  • He makes the number of those killed amount to 1500. Areop. Æschines
  • _contra Ctesiph._ assigns precisely the same number. Seneca (_De tranq.
  • anim._ cap. 5) says 1300.
  • [65] We shall mention from Diodorus Siculus alone a few which passed in
  • the course of sixty years during the most shining age of Greece. There
  • were banished from Sybaris 500 of the nobles and their partisans (lib.
  • 12 p. 77, _ex edit._ Rhodomanni); of Chians, 600 citizens banished
  • (lib. 13 p. 189); at Ephesus, 340 killed, 1000 banished (lib. 13 p.
  • 223); of Cyrenians, 500 nobles killed, all the rest banished (lib. 14
  • p. 263); the Corinthians killed 120, banished 500 (lib. 14 p. 304);
  • Phæbidas the Spartan banished 300 Bæotians (lib. 15 p. 342). Upon the
  • fall of the Lacedemonians, democracies were restored in many cities,
  • and severe vengeance taken of the nobles, after the Greek manner. But
  • matters did not end there, for the banished nobles, returning in many
  • places, butchered their adversaries at Phialæ in Corinth, in Megara,
  • in Phliasia. In this last place they killed 300 of the people; but
  • these again revolting, killed above 600 of the nobles and banished the
  • rest (lib. 15 p. 357). In Arcadia 1400 banished, besides many killed.
  • The banished retired to Sparta and Pallantium. The latter delivered up
  • to their countrymen, and all killed (lib. 15 p. 373). Of the banished
  • from Argos and Thebes there were 500 in the Spartan army (_id._ p.
  • 374). Here is a detail of the most remarkable of Agathocles’ cruelties
  • from the same author. The people before his usurpation had banished
  • 600 nobles (lib. 19 p. 655). Afterwards that tyrant, in concurrence
  • with the people, killed 4000 nobles and banished 6000 (_id._ p. 647).
  • He killed 4000 people at Gela (_id._ p. 741). By Agathocles’ brother
  • 8000 banished from Syracuse (lib. 20 p. 757). The inhabitants of
  • Ægesta, to the number of 40,000, were killed—man, woman, and child;
  • and with tortures, for the sake of their money (_id._ p. 802). All the
  • relations—viz., father, brother, children, grandfather, of his Libyan
  • army, killed (_id._ p. 103). He killed 7000 exiles after capitulation
  • (_id._ p. 816). It is to be remarked that Agathocles was a man of great
  • sense and courage; his violent tyranny, therefore, is a stronger proof
  • of the manners of the age.
  • [66] In order to recommend his client to the favour of the people, he
  • enumerates all the sums he had expended. When χορηγος, 30 minas; upon
  • a chorus of men, 20 minas; ειπυρριχιστας, 8 minas; ανδρασι χορηγων, 50
  • minas; κυκλικῳ χορῳ, 3 minas; seven times trierarch, where he spent
  • 6 talents: taxes, once 30 minas, another time 40; γυμνασιαρχων, 12
  • minas; χορηγος παιδικῳ χορῳ, 15 minas; κομοδοις χορηγων, 18 minas;
  • πυρριχισταις αγενειοις, 7 minas; τριηρει ἁμιλλομενος, 15 minas;
  • αρχιθεωρος, 30 minas. In the whole, ten talents 38 minas—an immense
  • sum for an Athenian fortune, and what alone would be esteemed great
  • riches (Orat. 20). It is true, he says, the law did not oblige him
  • absolutely to be at so much expense, not above a fourth; but without
  • the favour of the people nobody was so much as safe, and this was the
  • only way to gain it. See further, Orat. 24, _de pop. statu._ In another
  • place, he introduces a speaker who says that he had spent his whole
  • fortune—and an immense one, eighty talents—for the people (Orat. 25,
  • _de prob. Evandri_). The μετοικοι, or strangers, find, says he, if they
  • do not contribute largely enough to the people’s fancy, that they have
  • reason to repent (Orat. 30, _contra Phil._). You may see with what care
  • Demosthenes displays his expenses of this nature, when he pleads for
  • himself _de corona_; and how he exaggerates Midias’s stinginess in this
  • particular, in his accusation of that criminal. All this, by the by, is
  • the mark of a very iniquitous judicature: and yet the Athenians valued
  • themselves on having the most legal and regular administration of any
  • people in Greece.
  • [67] The authorities cited above are all historians, orators, and
  • philosophers whose testimony is unquestioned. It is dangerous to rely
  • upon writers who deal in ridicule and satire. What will posterity, for
  • instance, infer from this passage of Dr. Swift? “I told him that in the
  • kingdom of Tribnia (Britain), by the natives called Langdon (London),
  • where I had sojourned some time in my travels, the bulk of the people
  • consist in a manner wholly of discoverers, witnesses, informers,
  • accusers, prosecutors, evidences, swearers, together with their several
  • subservient and subaltern instruments, all under the colours, the
  • conduct, and pay of ministers of state and their deputies. The plots
  • in that kingdom are usually the workmanship of those persons,” etc.
  • (_Gulliver’s Travels._) Such a representation might suit the government
  • of Athens, but not that of England, which is a prodigy even in modern
  • times for humanity, justice, and liberty. Yet the Doctor’s satire,
  • though carried to extremes, as is usual with him, even beyond other
  • satirical writers, did not altogether want an object. The Bishop of
  • Rochester, who was his friend, and of the same party, had been banished
  • a little before by a bill of attainder with great justice, but without
  • such a proof as was legal, or according to the strict forms of common
  • law.
  • [68] Lib. 2. There were 8000 killed during the siege, and the whole
  • captives amounted to 30,000. Diodorus Siculus (lib. 17) says only
  • 13,000; but he accounts for this small number by saying that the
  • Tyrians had sent away beforehand part of their wives and children to
  • Carthage.
  • [69] Lib. 5. He makes the number of the citizens amount to 30,000.
  • [70] In general there is more candour and sincerity in ancient
  • historians, but less exactness and care, than in the moderns. Our
  • speculative factions, especially those of religion, throw such an
  • illusion over our minds that men seem to regard impartiality to their
  • adversaries and to heretics as a vice or weakness; but the commonness
  • of books, by means of printing, has obliged modern historians to be
  • more careful in avoiding contradictions and incongruities. Diodorus
  • Siculus is a good writer, but it is with pain I see his narration
  • contradict in so many particulars the two most authentic pieces of all
  • Greek history—viz., Xenophon’s Expedition and Demosthenes’ Orations.
  • Plutarch and Appian seem scarce ever to have read Cicero’s Epistles.
  • [71] Diogenes Laertius (in _vita Empedoclis_) says that Agrigentum
  • contained only 800,000 inhabitants.
  • [72] The country that supplied this number was not above a third of
  • Italy—viz., the Pope’s dominions, Tuscany, and a part of the kingdom
  • of Naples; but perhaps in those early times there were very few slaves
  • except in Rome, or the great cities.
  • [73] Plutarch (in _vita Cæs._) makes the number that Cæsar fought with
  • amount only to three millions; Julian (in _Cæsaribus_) to two.
  • [74] Argos seems also to have been a great city, for Lysias contents
  • himself with saying that it did not exceed Athens. (Orat. 34.)
  • [75] Orat. _contra Verem_, lib. 4, cap. 52. Strabo, lib. 6, says it
  • was twenty-two miles in compass; but then we are to consider that it
  • contained two harbours within it, one of which was a very large one,
  • and might be regarded as a kind of bay.
  • [76] Demosthenes assigns 20,000.
  • [77] Lib. 2. Diodorus Siculus’s account perfectly agrees (lib. 12).
  • [78] We are to observe that when Dionysius Halicarnassæus says that if
  • we regard the ancient walls of Rome the extent of the city will not
  • appear greater than that of Athens, he must mean the Acropolis and high
  • town only. No ancient author ever speaks of the Pyræum, Phalerus, and
  • Munychia as the same with Athens; much less can it be supposed that
  • Dionysius would consider the matter in that light after the walls of
  • Cimon and Pericles were destroyed and Athens was entirely separated
  • from these other towns. This observation destroys all Vossius’s
  • reasonings and introduces common sense into these calculations.
  • [79] The same author affirms that Corinth had once 460,000 slaves,
  • Ægina 470,000; but the foregoing arguments hold stronger against these
  • facts, which are indeed entirely absurd and impossible. It is however
  • remarkable that Athenæus cites so great an authority as Aristotle for
  • this last fact; and the scholiast on Pindar mentions the same number of
  • slaves in Ægina.
  • [80] Demost. _contra Lept._ The Athenians brought yearly from Pontus
  • 400,000 medimni or bushels of corn, as appeared from the custom-house
  • books; and this was the greatest part of their importation. This, by
  • the by, is a strong proof that there is some great mistake in the
  • foregoing passage of Athenæus, for Attica itself was so barren in corn
  • that it produced not enough even to maintain the peasants. Tit. Liv.,
  • lib. 43; cap. 6, Lucian, in his _navigium sive vota_, says that a ship,
  • which by the dimensions he gives seems to have been about the size of
  • our third rates, carried as much corn as would maintain all Attica for
  • a twelvemonth. But perhaps Athens was decayed at that time, and besides
  • it is not safe to trust such loose rhetorical calculations.
  • [81] Diod. Sic., lib. 17. When Alexander attacked Thebes we may safely
  • conclude that almost all the inhabitants were present. Whoever is
  • acquainted with the spirit of the Greeks, especially of the Thebans,
  • will never suspect that any of them would desert their country when it
  • was reduced to such extreme peril and distress. As Alexander took the
  • town by storm, all those who bore arms were put to the sword without
  • mercy, and they amounted only to 6000 men. Among these were some
  • strangers and manumitted slaves. The captives, consisting of old men,
  • women, children, and slaves, were sold, and they amounted to 30,000. We
  • may therefore conclude that the free citizens in Thebes, of both sexes
  • and all ages, were near 24,000, the strangers and slaves about 12,000,
  • These last, we may observe, were somewhat fewer in proportion than at
  • Athens; as is reasonable to imagine from this circumstance, that Athens
  • was a town of more trade to support slaves, and of more entertainment
  • to allure strangers. It is also to be remarked that thirty-six thousand
  • was the whole number of people, both in the city of Thebes and the
  • neighbouring territory; a very moderate number, it must be confessed,
  • and this computation being founded in facts which appear undisputable,
  • must have great weight in the present controversy. The above-mentioned
  • number of Rhodians, too, were all the inhabitants of the island who
  • were free and able to bear arms.
  • [82] _De rep. Laced._ This passage is not easily reconciled with that
  • of Plutarch above, who says that Sparta had 9000 citizens.
  • [83] Strabo, lib. 5, says that the Emperor Augustus prohibited the
  • raising houses higher than seventy feet. In another passage, lib. 16,
  • he speaks of the houses of Rome as remarkably high. See also to the
  • same purpose Vitruvius, lib. 2, cap. 8. Aristides the Sophist, in his
  • oration εις Ρωμην, says that Rome consisted of cities on the top of
  • cities; and that if one were to spread it out and unfold it, it would
  • cover the whole surface of Italy. Where an author indulges himself in
  • such extravagant declamations, and gives so much in to the hyperbolical
  • style, one knows not how far he must be reduced. But this reasoning
  • seems natural: if Rome was built in so scattered a manner as Dionysius
  • says, and ran so much into the country, there must have been very few
  • streets where the houses were raised so high. It is only for want of
  • ground that anybody builds in that inconvenient manner.
  • [84] Lib. 2, epist. 16; lib. 5, epist. 6. It is true Pliny there
  • describes a country house; but since that was the idea which the
  • ancients formed of a magnificent and convenient building, the great
  • men would certainly build the same way in town. “In laxitatem ruris
  • excurrunt,” says Seneca of the rich and voluptuous, epist. 114.
  • Valerius Maximus, lib. 4, cap. 4, speaking of Cincinnatus’ field of
  • four acres, says: “Augustus se habitare nunc putat, cujus domus tantum
  • patet quantum Cincinnati rura patuerant.” To the same purpose see lib.
  • 36, cap. 15; also lib. 18, cap. 2.
  • [85] “Mœnia ejus (Romæ) collegere ambitu imperatoribus, censoribusque
  • Vespasianis, A.U.C. 828, pass. xiii. MCC, complexa montes septem,
  • ipsa dividitur in regiones quatuordecim, compita earum 265. Ejusdem
  • spatii mensura, currente a milliario in capite Rom. Fori statuto, ad
  • singulas portas, quæ sunt hodie numero 37, ita ut duodecim portæ semel
  • numerentur, prætereanturque ex veteribus septem, quæ esse desierunt,
  • efficit passuum per directum 30,775. Ad extrema vero tectorum cum
  • castris prætoris ab eodem Milliario, per vicos omnium viarum, mensura
  • collegit paulo amplius septuaginta millia passuum. Quo si quis
  • altitudinem tectorum addat, dignam profecto, æstimationem concipiat,
  • fateaturque nullius urbis magnitudinem in toto orbe potuisse ei
  • comparari.” (Pliny, lib. 3, cap. 5.)
  • All the best manuscripts of Pliny read the passage as here cited, and
  • fix the compass of the walls of Rome to be thirteen miles. The question
  • is, what Pliny means by 30,775 paces, and how that number was formed?
  • The manner in which I conceive it is this: Rome was a semicircular
  • area of thirteen miles circumference. The Forum, and consequently the
  • Milliarium, we know was situated on the banks of the Tiber, and near
  • the centre of the circle, or upon the diameter of the semicircular
  • area. Though there were thirty-seven gates to Rome, yet only twelve of
  • them had straight streets, leading from them to the Milliarium. Pliny,
  • therefore, having assigned the circumference of Rome, and knowing that
  • that alone was not sufficient to give us a just notion of its surface,
  • uses this further method. He supposes all the streets leading from the
  • Milliarium to the twelve gates to be laid together into one straight
  • line, and supposes we run along that line so as to count each gate
  • once, in which case, he says that the whole line is 30,775 paces; or,
  • in other words, that each street or radius of the semicircular area is
  • upon an average two miles and a half, and the whole length of Rome is
  • five miles, and its breadth about half as much, besides the scattered
  • suburbs.
  • Père Hardouin understands this passage in the same manner, with regard
  • to the laying together the several streets of Rome into one line in
  • order to compose 30,775 paces; but then he supposes that streets led
  • from the Milliarium to every gate, and that no street exceeded 800
  • paces in length. But (1) a semicircular area whose radius was only
  • 800 paces could never have a circumference near thirteen miles, the
  • compass of Rome as assigned by Pliny. A radius of two miles and a half
  • forms very nearly that circumference. (2) There is an absurdity in
  • supposing a city so built as to have streets running to its centre from
  • every gate in its circumference. These streets must interfere as they
  • approach. (3) This diminishes too much from the greatness of ancient
  • Rome, and reduces that city below even Bristol or Rotterdam.
  • The sense which Vossius, in his _Observationes Variæ_, puts on this
  • passage of Pliny errs widely in the other extreme. One manuscript of
  • no authority, instead of thirteen miles, has assigned thirty miles for
  • the compass of the walls of Rome; and Vossius understands this only
  • of the curvilinear part of the circumference, supposing that, as the
  • Tiber formed the diameter, there were no walls built on that side. But
  • (1) this reading is allowed contrary to almost all the manuscripts.
  • (2) Why should Pliny, a concise writer, repeat the compass of the
  • walls of Rome in two successive sentences? (3) Why repeat it with so
  • sensible a variation? (4) What is the meaning of Pliny’s mentioning
  • twice the Milliarium if a line was measured that had no dependence on
  • the Milliarium? (5) Aurelian’s wall is said by Vopiscus to have been
  • drawn _laxiore ambitu_, and to have comprehended all the buildings
  • and suburbs on the north side of the Tiber, yet its compass was only
  • fifty miles; and even here critics suspect some mistake or corruption
  • in the text. It is not probable that Rome would diminish from Augustus
  • to Aurelian. It remained still the capital of the same empire; and
  • none of the civil wars in that long period, except the tumults on
  • the death of Maximus and Balbinus, ever affected the city. Caracalla
  • is said by Aurelius Victor to have increased Rome. (6) There are no
  • remains of ancient buildings which mark any such greatness of Rome.
  • Vossius’s reply to this objection seems absurd—that the rubbish would
  • sink sixty or seventy feet below ground. It appears from Spartian (_in
  • vita Severi_) that the five-mile stone _in via Lavicana_ was out of the
  • city. (7) Olympiodorus and Publius Victor fix the number of houses in
  • Rome to be between forty and fifty thousand. (8) The very extravagance
  • of the consequences drawn by this critic, as well as Lipsius, if they
  • be necessary, destroys the foundation on which they are grounded—that
  • Rome contained fourteen millions of inhabitants, while the whole
  • kingdom of France contains only five, according to his computation, etc.
  • The only objection to the sense which we have affixed above to the
  • passage of Pliny seems to lie in this, that Pliny, after mentioning
  • the thirty-seven gates of Rome, assigns only a reason for suppressing
  • the seven old ones, and says nothing of the eighteen gates, the
  • streets leading from which terminated, according to my opinion, before
  • they reached the Forum. But as Pliny was writing to the Romans, who
  • perfectly knew the disposition of the streets, it is not strange
  • he should take a circumstance for granted which was so familiar to
  • everybody. Perhaps, too, many of these gates led to wharves upon the
  • river.
  • [86] Not to take the people too much from their business, Augustus
  • ordained the distribution of corn to be made only thrice a year; but
  • the people, finding the monthly distribution more convenient (as
  • preserving, I suppose, a more regular economy in their family), desired
  • to have them restored. (Sueton. August. cap. 40.) Had not some of the
  • people come from some distance for their corn, Augustus’s precaution
  • seems superfluous.
  • [87] Quintus Curtius says its walls were only ten miles in
  • circumference when founded by Alexander (lib. 4, cap. 8). Strabo, who
  • had travelled to Alexandria, as well as Diodorus Siculus, says it was
  • scarce four miles long, and in most places about a mile broad (lib.
  • 17). Pliny says it resembled a Macedonian cassock, stretching out in
  • the corners (lib. 5, cap. 10). Notwithstanding this bulk of Alexandria,
  • which seems but moderate, Diodorus Siculus, speaking of its circuit as
  • drawn by Alexander (which it never exceeded, as we learn from Ammianus
  • Marcellinus, lib. 22, cap. 16), says it was μεγεθει διαφεροντα,
  • extremely great (_ibid._). The reason why he assigns for its surpassing
  • all cities of the world (for he excepts not Rome) is that it contained
  • 300,000 free inhabitants. He also mentions the revenues of the
  • kings—viz., 6000 talents—as another circumstance to the same purpose,
  • no such mighty sum in our eyes, even though we make allowances for
  • the different value of money. What Strabo says of the neighbouring
  • country means only that it was well peopled, οἰκουμενα καλως. Might
  • not one affirm, without any great hyperbole, that the whole banks of
  • the river from Gravesend to Windsor are one city? This is even more
  • than Strabo says of the banks of the lake Mareotis, and of the canal
  • to Canopus. It is a vulgar saying in Italy that the King of Sardinia
  • has but one town in Piedmont—for it is all a town. Agrippa in Josephus
  • (_de bello Judaie_, lib. 2, cap. 16), to make his audience comprehend
  • the excessive greatness of Alexandria, which he endeavours to magnify,
  • describes only the compass of the city as drawn by Alexander, a clear
  • proof that the bulk of the inhabitants were lodged there, and that the
  • neighbouring country was no more than what might be expected about all
  • great towns, very well cultivated and well peopled.
  • [88] He says ἐλευθεροι, not πολιται, which last expression must have
  • been understood of citizens alone, and grown men.
  • [89] He says (in _Nerone_, cap. 30) that a portico or piazza of it
  • was 3000 feet long; “tanta laxitas ut porticus triplices milliarias
  • haberet.” He cannot mean three miles, for the whole extent of the house
  • from the Palatine to the Esquiline was not near so great. So when
  • Vopiscus, in _Aureliano_, mentions a portico of Sallust’s gardens,
  • which he calls _porticus milliariensis_, it must be understood of a
  • thousand feet. So also Horace—
  • “Nulla decempedis
  • Metata privatis opacam
  • Porticus excipiebat Arcton.” (Lib. ii. ode 15.)
  • So also in lib. i. Satyr. 8—
  • “Mille pedes in fronte, trecentos cippus in agrum
  • Hic dabat.”
  • [90] Lib. ix. cap. 10. His expression is ἀνθρωπος, not πολιτης;
  • inhabitant, not citizen.
  • [91] Such were Alexandria, Antioch, Carthage, Ephesus, Lyons, etc.,
  • in the Roman Empire. Such are even Bordeaux, Toulouse, Dijon, Rennes,
  • Rouen, Aix, etc., in France; Dublin, Edinburgh, York, in the British
  • dominions.
  • [92] The warm southern colonies also become more healthful; and it is
  • remarkable that in the Spanish histories of the first discovery and
  • conquest of these countries they appear to have been very healthful,
  • being then well peopled and cultivated. No account of the sickness or
  • decay of Cortes’s or Pizarro’s small armies.
  • [93] He seems to have lived about the time of the younger Africanus.
  • (Lib. i. cap. 1.)
  • [94] Cæsar, _De bello Gallico_, lib. 16. Strabo (lib. 7) says the Gauls
  • were not much more improved than the Germans.
  • [95] Ancient Gaul was more extensive than modern France.
  • [96] It appears from Cæsar’s account that the Gauls had no domestic
  • slaves, who formed a different order from the Plebes. The whole common
  • people were indeed a kind of slaves to the nobility, as the people
  • of Poland are at this day; and a nobleman of Gaul had sometimes ten
  • thousand dependants of this kind. Nor can we doubt that the armies were
  • composed of the people as well as of the nobility. An army of 100,000
  • noblemen from a very small state is incredible. The fighting men
  • amongst the Helvetii were the fourth part of the whole inhabitants—a
  • clear proof that all the males of military age bore arms. See Cæsar,
  • _De bello Gall._, lib. 1.
  • We may remark that the numbers in Cæsar’s commentaries can be more
  • depended on than those of any other ancient author, because of the
  • Greek translation which still remains, and which checks the Latin
  • original.
  • [97] “Nec numero Hispanos, nec robore Gallos, nec calliditate Pœnos,
  • nec artibus Græcos, nec denique hoc ipso hujus gentis, ac terræ
  • domestico nativoque sensu, Italos ipsos ac Latinos—superavimus.” (_De
  • harusp. resp._, cap. 9.) The disorders of Spain seem to have been
  • almost proverbial: “Nec impacatos a tergo horrebis Iberos.” (Virg.
  • _Georg._, lib. 3.) The Iberi are here plainly taken by a poetical
  • figure for robbers in general.
  • [98] Though the observations of l’Abbé du Bos should be admitted that
  • Italy is now warmer than in former times, the consequence may not be
  • necessary that it is more populous or better cultivated. If the other
  • countries of Europe were more savage and woody, the cold winds that
  • blew from them might affect the climate of Italy.
  • [99] The inhabitants of Marseilles lost not their superiority over
  • the Gauls in commerce and the mechanic arts till the Roman dominion
  • turned the latter from arms to agriculture and civil life. (See Strabo,
  • lib. 4.) That author, in several places, repeats the observation
  • concerning the improvement arising from the Roman arts and civility,
  • and he lived at the time when the change was new and would be more
  • sensible. So also Pliny: “Quis enim non, communicato orbe terrarum,
  • majestate Romani imperii, profecisse vitam putet, commercio rerum ac
  • societate festae pacis, omniaque etiam, quae occulta antea fuerant, in
  • promiscuo usu facta.” (Lib. 14, proœm.) “Numine deum electa [speaking
  • of Italy] quae coelum ipsum clarius faceret, sparsa congregaret
  • imperia, ritusque molliret, et tot populorum discordes, ferasque
  • linguas fermonis commercio contraheret ad colloquia, et humanitatem
  • homini daret; breviterque, una cunctarum gentium in toto orbe patria
  • fieret.” (Lib. 2, cap. 5.) Nothing can be stronger to this purpose
  • than the following passage from Tertullian, who lived about the age of
  • Severus:—“Certe quidem ipse orbis in promptu est, cultior de die et
  • instructior pristino. Omnia jam pervia, omnia nota, omnia negotiosa.
  • Solitudines famosas retro fundi amoenissimi obliteraverunt, silvas arva
  • domuerunt, feras pecora fugaverunt; arenae seruntur, saxa panguntur,
  • paludes eliquantur, tantae urbes, quantae non casae quondam. Jam nec
  • insulae horrent, nec scopuli terrent; ubique domus, ubique populus,
  • ubique respublica, ubique vita. Summum testimonium frequentiae humanae,
  • onerosi sumus mundo, vix nobis elementa sufficiunt; et necessitates
  • arctiores, et quaerelae apud omnes, dum jam nos natura non sustinet.”
  • (_De anima_, cap. 30.) The air of rhetoric and declamation which
  • appears in this passage diminishes somewhat from its authority, but
  • does not entirely destroy it. The same remark may be extended to the
  • following passage of Aristides the Sophist, who lived in the age of
  • Adrian. “The whole world,” says he, addressing himself to the Romans,
  • “seems to keep one holiday, and mankind, laying aside the sword which
  • they formerly wore, now betake themselves to feasting and to joy.
  • The cities, forgetting their ancient contentions, preserve only one
  • emulation, which shall embellish itself most by every art and ornament?
  • Theatres everywhere arise, amphitheatres, porticoes, aqueducts,
  • temples, schools, academies; and one may safely pronounce that the
  • sinking world has been again raised by your auspicious empire. Nor have
  • cities alone received an increase of ornament and beauty; but the whole
  • earth, like a garden or paradise, is cultivated and adorned; insomuch
  • that such of mankind as are placed out of the limits of your empire
  • (who are but few) seem to merit our sympathy and compassion.”
  • It is remarkable that though Diodorus Siculus makes the inhabitants of
  • Egypt, when conquered by the Romans, amount only to three millions, yet
  • Josephus (_De bello Jud._, lib. 2, cap. 16) says that its inhabitants,
  • excluding those of Alexandria, were seven millions and a half in the
  • reign of Nero, and he expressly says that he drew this account from
  • the books of the Roman publicans who levied the poll-tax. Strabo
  • (lib. 17) praises the superior police of the Romans with regard to
  • the finances of Egypt above that of its former monarchs, and no part
  • of administration is more essential to the happiness of a people;
  • yet we read in Athenæus (lib. 1, cap. 25), who flourished during the
  • reign of the Antonines, that the town Mareia, near Alexandria, which
  • was formerly a large city, had dwindled into a village. This is not,
  • properly speaking, a contradiction. Suidas (August) says that the
  • Emperor Augustus, having numbered the whole Roman Empire, found it
  • contained only 4,101,017 men (ἀνδρες). There is here surely some great
  • mistake, either in the author or transcriber; but this authority,
  • feeble as it is, may be sufficient to counterbalance the exaggerated
  • accounts of Herodotus and Diodorus Siculus with regard to more early
  • times.
  • [100] Lib. 2, cap. 62. It may perhaps be imagined that Polybius, being
  • dependent on Rome, would naturally extol the Roman dominion; but, in
  • the first place, Polybius, though one sees sometimes instances of his
  • caution, discovers no symptoms of flattery. Secondly, this opinion is
  • only delivered in a single stroke, by the by, while he is intent upon
  • another subject, and it is allowed, if there be any suspicion of an
  • author’s insincerity, that these oblique propositions discover his real
  • opinion better than his more formal and direct assertions.
  • [101] I must confess that that discourse of Plutarch concerning the
  • silence of the oracles is in general of so odd a texture, and so unlike
  • his other productions, that one is at a loss what judgment to form of
  • it. It is written in dialogue, which is a method of composition that
  • Plutarch commonly little affects. The personages he introduces advance
  • very wild, absurd, and contradictory opinions, more like visionary
  • systems or ravings of Plato than the solid sense of Plutarch. There
  • runs also through the whole an air of superstition and credulity which
  • resembles very little the spirit that appears in other philosophical
  • compositions of that author; for it is remarkable that though Plutarch
  • be an historian as superstitious as Herodotus or Livy, yet there is
  • scarcely in all antiquity a philosopher less superstitious, excepting
  • Cicero and Lucian. I must therefore confess that a passage of Plutarch,
  • cited from this discourse, has much less authority with me than if it
  • had been found in most of his other compositions.
  • There is only one other discourse of Plutarch liable to like
  • objections—viz., that concerning those whose punishment is delayed by
  • the Deity. It is also written in dialogue, contains like superstitious,
  • wild visions, and seems to have been chiefly composed in rivalship to
  • Plato, particularly his last book, _De Republica_.
  • And here I cannot but observe that Monsieur Fontenelle, a writer
  • eminent for candour, seems to have departed a little from his usual
  • character when he endeavours to throw a ridicule upon Plutarch on
  • account of passages to be met with in this dialogue concerning oracles.
  • The absurdities here put into the mouths of the several personages are
  • not to be ascribed to Plutarch. He makes them refute each other, and in
  • general he seems to intend the ridiculing of those very opinions which
  • Fontenelle would ridicule him for maintaining. (See _Histoires des
  • Oracles_.)
  • [102] He was contemporary with Cæsar and Augustus.
  • OF THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT.
  • As no party, in the present age, can support itself without a
  • philosophical or speculative system of principles annexed to its
  • political or practical one, we accordingly find that each of the
  • parties into which this nation is divided has reared up a fabric of the
  • former kind, in order to protect and cover that scheme of actions which
  • it pursues. The people being commonly very rude builders, especially
  • in this speculative way, and more especially still when actuated by
  • party zeal, it is natural to imagine that their workmanship must
  • be a little unshapely, and discover evident marks of that violence
  • and hurry in which it was raised. The one party, by tracing up the
  • origin of government to the Deity, endeavour to render government
  • so sacred and inviolate that it must be little less than
  • sacrilege, however disorderly it may become, to touch or invade it
  • in the smallest article. The other party, by founding government
  • altogether on the consent of the people, suppose that there is a kind
  • of original contract by which the subjects have reserved the power of
  • resisting their sovereign whenever they find themselves aggrieved by
  • that authority with which they have, for certain purposes, voluntarily
  • entrusted him. These are the speculative principles of the two parties,
  • and these too are the practical consequences deduced from them.
  • I shall venture to affirm that both these systems of speculative
  • principles are just, though not in the sense intended by the parties;
  • and that both the schemes of practical consequences are prudent, though
  • not in the extremes to which each party, in opposition to the other,
  • has commonly endeavoured to carry them.
  • That the Deity is the ultimate author of all government will never be
  • denied by any who admits a general providence, and allows that all
  • events in the universe are conducted by a uniform plan and directed
  • to wise purposes. As it is impossible for the human race to subsist,
  • at least in any comfortable or secure state, without the protection
  • of government, government must certainly have been intended by that
  • beneficent Being, who means the good of all His creatures; and as it
  • has universally, in fact, taken place in all countries and all ages,
  • we may conclude, with still greater certainty, that it was intended
  • by that omniscient Being, who can never be deceived by any event or
  • operation. But since he gave rise to it, not by any particular or
  • miraculous interposition but by his concealed and universal efficacy,
  • a sovereign cannot, properly speaking, be called his vicegerent in
  • any other sense than every power or force being derived from him
  • may be said to act by his commission. Whatever actually happens is
  • comprehended in the general plan or intention of providence; nor has
  • the greatest and most lawful prince any more reason, upon that account,
  • to plead a peculiar sacredness or inviolable authority, than
  • an inferior magistrate, or even a usurper, or even a robber and a
  • pirate. The same divine superintendent who, for wise purposes, invested
  • an Elizabeth or a Henry​[103] with authority, did also, for purposes
  • no doubt equally wise, though unknown, bestow power on a Borgia or an
  • Angria. The same causes which gave rise to the sovereign power in every
  • state, established likewise every petty jurisdiction in it, and every
  • limited authority. A constable therefore, no less than a king, acts by
  • a divine commission, and possesses an indefeasible right.
  • When we consider how nearly equal all men are in their bodily force,
  • and even in their mental powers and faculties, till cultivated by
  • education, we must necessarily allow that nothing but their own consent
  • could at first associate them together, and subject them to any
  • authority. The people, if we trace government to its first origin in
  • the woods and deserts, are the source of all power and jurisdiction,
  • and voluntarily, for the sake of peace and order, abandoned their
  • native liberty, and received laws from their equal and companion.
  • The conditions upon which they were willing to submit were either
  • expressed, or were so clear and obvious that it might well be esteemed
  • superfluous to express them. If this, then, be meant by the original
  • contract, it cannot be denied that all government is at first founded
  • on a contract, and that the most ancient rude combinations of mankind
  • were formed entirely by that principle. In vain are we sent to the
  • records to seek for this charter of our liberties. It was not written
  • on parchment, nor yet on leaves or barks of trees. It preceded the
  • use of writing and all the other civilized arts of life. But we trace
  • it plainly in the nature of man, and in the equality which we find in
  • all the individuals of that species. The force which now prevails,
  • and which is founded on fleets and armies, is plainly political, and
  • derived from authority, the effect of established government. A man’s
  • natural force consists only in the vigour of his limbs and the
  • firmness of his courage, which could never subject multitudes to the
  • command of one. Nothing but their own consent, and their sense of the
  • advantages of peace and order, could have had that influence.
  • But philosophers who have embraced a party (if that be not a
  • contradiction in terms) are not contented with these concessions.
  • They assert, not only that government in its earliest infancy arose
  • from consent or the voluntary combination of the people, but also
  • that, even at present, when it has attained its full maturity, it
  • rests on no other foundation. They affirm that all men are still
  • born equal, and owe allegiance to no prince or government unless
  • bound by the obligation and sanction of a promise. And as no man,
  • without some equivalent, would forgo the advantages of his native
  • liberty and subject himself to the will of another, this promise is
  • always understood to be conditional, and imposes on him no obligation
  • unless he meets with justice and protection from his sovereign. These
  • advantages the sovereign promises him in return, and if he fails in
  • the execution, he has broke, on his part, the articles of engagement,
  • and has thereby freed his subjects from all obligations to allegiance.
  • Such, according to these philosophers, is the foundation of authority
  • in every government, and such the right of resistance possessed by
  • every subject.
  • But would these reasoners look abroad into the world they would meet
  • with nothing that in the least corresponds to their ideas, or can
  • warrant so refined and philosophical a theory. On the contrary, we
  • find everywhere princes who claim their subjects as their property,
  • and assert their independent right of sovereignty from conquest or
  • succession. We find also everywhere subjects who acknowledge this
  • right in their princes, and suppose themselves born under obligations
  • of obedience to a certain sovereign, as much as under the ties of
  • reverence and duty to certain parents. These connections are always
  • conceived to be equally independent of our consent, in Persia
  • and China; in France and Spain; and even in Holland and England,
  • wherever the doctrines above mentioned have not been carefully
  • inculcated. Obedience or subjection becomes so familiar that most
  • men never make any inquiry about its origin or cause, more than about
  • the principle of gravity, resistance, or the most universal laws of
  • nature. Or if curiosity ever move them, so soon as they learn that they
  • themselves and their ancestors have for several ages, or from time
  • immemorial, been subject to such a government or such a family, they
  • immediately acquiesce and acknowledge their obligation to allegiance.
  • Were you to preach, in most parts of the world, that political
  • connections are founded altogether on voluntary consent or a mutual
  • promise, the magistrate would soon imprison you, as seditious, for
  • loosening the ties of obedience; if your friends did not shut you up,
  • as delirious, for advancing such absurdities. It is strange that an
  • act of the mind which every individual is supposed to have formed—and
  • after he came to the use of reason too, otherwise it could have no
  • authority—that this act, I say, should be so unknown to all of them,
  • that over the face of the whole earth there scarce remain any traces or
  • memory of it.
  • But the contract on which government is founded is said to be the
  • original contract, and consequently may be supposed too old to fall
  • under the knowledge of the present generation. If the agreement by
  • which savage men first associated and conjoined their force be here
  • meant, this is acknowledged to be real; but being so ancient, and being
  • obliterated by a thousand changes of government and princes, it cannot
  • now be supposed to retain any authority. If we would say anything to
  • the purpose, we must assert that every particular government which is
  • lawful, and which imposes any duty of allegiance on the subject, was at
  • first founded on consent and a voluntary compact. But besides that this
  • supposes the consent of the fathers to bind the children, even to the
  • most remote generations (which republican writers will never allow),
  • besides this, I say, it is not justified by history or experience in
  • any age or country of the world.
  • Almost all the governments which exist at present, or of which
  • there remains any record in story, have been founded originally either
  • on usurpation or conquest, or both, without any pretence of a fair
  • consent or voluntary subjection of the people. When an artful and bold
  • man is placed at the head of an army or faction, it is often easy for
  • him, by employing sometimes violence, sometimes false pretences, to
  • establish his dominion over a people a hundred times more numerous
  • than his partisans. He allows no such open communication that his
  • enemies can know with certainty their number or force. He gives them no
  • leisure to assemble together in a body to oppose him. Even all those
  • who are the instruments of his usurpation may wish his fall, but their
  • ignorance of each other’s intentions keeps them in awe, and is the sole
  • cause of his security. By such arts as these many governments have been
  • established, and this is all the original contract they have to boast
  • of.
  • The face of the earth is continually changing by the increase of small
  • kingdoms into great empires, by the dissolution of great empires into
  • smaller kingdoms, by the planting of colonies, by the migration of
  • tribes. Is there anything discoverable in all these events but force
  • and violence? Where is the mutual agreement or voluntary association so
  • much talked of?
  • Even the smoothest way by which a nation may receive a foreign master,
  • by marriage or a will, is not extremely honourable for the people; but
  • supposes them to be disposed of, like a dowry or a legacy, according to
  • the pleasure or interest of their rulers.
  • But where no force interposes, and election takes place, what is this
  • election so highly vaunted? It is either the combination of a few great
  • men who decide for the whole, and will allow no opposition, or it is
  • the fury of a rabble that follow a seditious leader, who is not known,
  • perhaps, to a dozen among them, and who owes his advancement merely to
  • his own impudence, or to the momentary caprice of his fellows.
  • Are these disorderly elections, which are rare too, of such
  • mighty authority as to be the only lawful foundation of all government
  • and allegiance?
  • In reality there is not a more terrible event than a total dissolution
  • of government, which gives liberty to the multitude, and makes the
  • determination or choice of a new establishment depend upon a number
  • which nearly approaches the body of the people; for it never comes
  • entirely to the whole body of them. Every wise man, then, wishes to
  • see, at the head of a powerful and obedient army, a general who may
  • speedily seize the prize and give to the people a master, which they
  • are so unfit to choose for themselves. So little correspondent is fact
  • and reality to those philosophical notions.
  • Let not the establishment at the Revolution deceive us, or make us so
  • much in love with a philosophical origin to government as to imagine
  • all others monstrous and irregular. Even that event was far from
  • corresponding to these refined ideas. It was only the succession,
  • and that only in the regal part of the government, which was then
  • changed; and it was only the majority of seven hundred who determined
  • that change for near ten millions. I doubt not, indeed, but the bulk
  • of these ten millions acquiesced willingly in the determination; but
  • was the matter left, in the least, to their choice? Was it not justly
  • supposed to be from that moment decided, and every man punished who
  • refused to submit to the new sovereign? How otherways could the matter
  • have ever been brought to any issue or conclusion?
  • The Republic of Athens was, I believe, the most extensive democracy
  • which we read of in history. Yet if we make the requisite allowances
  • for the women, the slaves, and the strangers, we shall find that
  • that establishment was not at first made, nor any law ever voted, by
  • a tenth part of those who were bound to pay obedience to it; not to
  • mention the islands and foreign dominions which the Athenians claimed
  • as theirs by right of conquest. And as it is well known that popular
  • assemblies in that city were always full of licence and disorder,
  • notwithstanding the forms and laws by which they were checked, how
  • much more disorderly must they be where they form not the established
  • constitution, but meet tumultuously on the dissolution of the ancient
  • government in order to give rise to a new one? How chimerical must it
  • be to talk of a choice in any such circumstances?
  • The Achæans enjoyed the freest and most perfect democracy of all
  • antiquity; yet they employed force to oblige some cities to enter into
  • their league, as we learn from Polybius.
  • Henry IV. and Henry VII. of England had really no other title to the
  • throne but a parliamentary election; yet they never would acknowledge
  • it, for fear of weakening their authority. Strange! if the only real
  • foundation of all authority be consent and promise.
  • It is vain to say that all governments are, or should be, at first,
  • founded on popular consent, as much as the necessity of human affairs
  • will admit. This favours entirely my pretension. I maintain that human
  • affairs will never admit of this consent; seldom of the appearance of
  • it. But that conquest or usurpation—that is, in plain terms, force—by
  • dissolving the ancient governments, is the origin of almost all the
  • new ones which ever were established in the world; and that in the few
  • cases, where consent may seem to have taken place, it was commonly so
  • irregular, so confined, or so much intermixed either with fraud or
  • violence, that it cannot have any great authority.
  • My intention here is not to exclude the consent of the people from
  • being one just foundation of government where it has place. It is
  • surely the best and most sacred of any. I only pretend that it has very
  • seldom had place in any degree, and never almost in its full extent;
  • and that therefore some other foundation of government must also be
  • admitted.
  • Were all men possessed of so inflexible a regard to justice that, of
  • themselves, they would totally abstain from the properties of others,
  • they had for ever remained in a state of absolute liberty without
  • subjection to any magistrates or political society; but this
  • is a state of perfection, of which human nature is justly esteemed
  • incapable. Again, were all men possessed of so just an understanding
  • as always to know their own interest, no form of government had ever
  • been submitted to but what was established on consent, and was fully
  • canvassed by each member of the society; but this state of perfection
  • is likewise much superior to human nature. Reason, history, and
  • experience show us that all political societies have had an origin much
  • less accurate and regular; and were one to choose a period of time
  • when the people’s consent was least regarded in public transactions,
  • it would be precisely on the establishment of a new government. In a
  • settled constitution their inclinations are often studied; but during
  • the fury of revolutions, conquests, and public convulsions, military
  • force or political craft usually decides the controversy.
  • When a new government is established, by whatever means, the people are
  • commonly dissatisfied with it, and pay obedience more from fear and
  • necessity than from any idea of allegiance or of moral obligation. The
  • prince is watchful and jealous, and must carefully guard against every
  • beginning or appearance of insurrection. Time, by degrees, removes
  • all these difficulties, and accustoms the nation to regard, as their
  • lawful or native princes, that family whom at first they considered as
  • usurpers or foreign conquerors. In order to found this opinion, they
  • have no recourse to any notion of voluntary consent or promise, which,
  • they know, never was in this case either expected or demanded. The
  • original establishment was formed by violence, and submitted to from
  • necessity. The subsequent administration is also supported by power,
  • and acquiesced in by the people, not as a matter of choice, but of
  • obligation. They imagine not that their consent gives their prince a
  • title; but they willingly consent because they think that, from long
  • possession, he has acquired a title independent of their choice or
  • inclination.
  • Should it be said that by living under the dominion of a prince
  • which one might leave, every individual has given a tacit consent to
  • his authority, and promised him obedience, it may be answered that
  • such implied consent can only take place where a man imagines that
  • the matter depends on his choice. But where he thinks (as all mankind
  • do who are born under established governments) that by his birth he
  • owes allegiance to a certain prince or certain government, it would be
  • absurd to infer a consent or choice, which he expressly, in this case,
  • renounces and abjures.
  • Can we seriously say that a poor peasant or artisan has a free choice
  • to leave his own country, when he knows no foreign language or manners,
  • and lives from day to day by the same small wages which he acquires?
  • We may as well assert that a man, by remaining in a vessel, freely
  • consents to the dominion of the master, though he was carried on board
  • while asleep, and must leap into the ocean and perish the moment he
  • leaves her.
  • What if the prince forbid his subjects to quit his dominions, as in
  • Tiberius’s time it was regarded as a crime in a Roman knight that he
  • had attempted to fly to the Parthians, in order to escape the tyranny
  • of that emperor? Or as the ancient Muscovites prohibited all travelling
  • under pain of death? And did a prince observe that many of his subjects
  • were seized with the frenzy of transporting themselves to foreign
  • countries, he would doubtless, with great reason and justice, restrain
  • them, in order to prevent the depopulation of his own kingdom. Would he
  • forfeit the allegiance of all his subjects by so wise and reasonable a
  • law? Yet the freedom of their choice is surely, in that case, ravished
  • from them.
  • A company of men who should leave their native country in order to
  • people some uninhabited region might dream of recovering their native
  • freedom; but they would soon find that their prince still laid claim to
  • them, and called them his subjects, even in their new settlement. And
  • in this he would but act conformably to the common ideas of mankind.
  • The truest tacit consent of this kind which is ever observed is when
  • a foreigner settles in any country, and is beforehand acquainted with
  • the prince and government and laws to which he must submit; yet is his
  • allegiance, though more voluntary, much less expected or depended on
  • than that of a natural born subject. On the contrary, his native prince
  • still asserts a claim to him. And if he punishes not the renegade when
  • he seizes him in war with his new prince’s commission, this clemency
  • is not founded on the municipal law, which in all countries condemns
  • the prisoner, but on the consent of princes who have agreed to this
  • indulgence in order to prevent reprisals.
  • Suppose a usurper, after having banished his lawful prince and royal
  • family, should establish his dominion for ten or a dozen years in any
  • country, and should preserve such exact discipline in his troops and so
  • regular a disposition in his garrisons that no insurrection had ever
  • been raised, or even murmur heard, against his administration, can it
  • be asserted that the people, who in their hearts abhor his treason,
  • have tacitly consented to his authority and promised him allegiance
  • merely because, from necessity, they live under his dominion? Suppose
  • again their natural prince restored, by means of an army which
  • he assembles in foreign countries, they receive him with joy and
  • exultation, and show plainly with what reluctance they had submitted to
  • any other yoke. I may now ask upon what foundation the prince’s title
  • stands? Not on popular consent surely; for though the people willingly
  • acquiesce in his authority, they never imagine that their consent makes
  • him sovereign. They consent because they apprehend him to be already,
  • by birth, their lawful sovereign. And as to that tacit consent, which
  • may now be inferred from their living under his dominion, this is no
  • more than what they formerly gave to the tyrant and usurper.
  • When we assert that all lawful government arises from the people,
  • we certainly do them more honour than they deserve, or even expect
  • and desire from us. After the Roman dominions became too unwieldy
  • for the republic to govern, the people over the whole known
  • world were extremely grateful to Augustus for that authority which,
  • by violence, he had established over them; and they showed an equal
  • disposition to submit to the successor whom he left them by his last
  • will and testament. It was afterwards their misfortune that there never
  • was in one family any long, regular succession; but that their line
  • of princes was continually broke, either by private assassination or
  • public rebellion. The prætorean bands, on the failure of every family,
  • set up one emperor, the legions in the East a second, those in Germany
  • perhaps a third; and the sword alone could decide the controversy. The
  • condition of the people in that mighty monarchy was to be lamented,
  • not because the choice of the emperor was never left to them, for that
  • was impracticable, but because they never fell under any succession of
  • masters, who might regularly follow each other. As to the violence and
  • wars and bloodshed occasioned by every new settlement, those were not
  • blameable, because they were inevitable.
  • The house of Lancaster ruled in this island about sixty years, yet the
  • partisans of the white rose seemed daily to multiply in England. The
  • present establishment has taken place during a still longer period.
  • Have all views of right in another family been extinguished, even
  • though scarce any man now alive had arrived at years of discretion
  • when it was expelled, or could have consented to its dominion, or have
  • promised it allegiance? A sufficient indication surely of the general
  • sentiment of mankind on this head. For we blame not the partisans
  • of the abdicated family merely on account of the long time during
  • which they have preserved their imaginary fidelity; we blame them for
  • adhering to a family which, we affirm, has been justly expelled, and
  • which, from the moment the new settlement took place, had forfeited all
  • title to authority.
  • But would we have a more regular, at least a more philosophical,
  • refutation of this principle of an original contract or popular
  • consent, perhaps the following observations may suffice.
  • All moral duties may be divided into two kinds. The first are those to
  • which men are impelled by a natural instinct or immediate propensity
  • which operates in them, independent of all ideas of obligation and of
  • all views, either to public or private utility. Of this nature are
  • love of children, gratitude to benefactors, pity to the unfortunate.
  • When we reflect on the advantage which results to society from such
  • humane instincts, we pay them the just tribute of moral approbation and
  • esteem; but the person actuated by them feels their power and influence
  • antecedent to any such reflection.
  • The second kind of moral duties are such as are not supported by any
  • original instinct of nature, but are performed entirely from a sense
  • of obligation, when we consider the necessities of human society and
  • the impossibility of supporting it if these duties were neglected. It
  • is thus justice or a regard to the property of others, fidelity or the
  • observance of promises, become obligatory and acquire an authority over
  • mankind. For as it is evident that every man loves himself better than
  • any other person, he is naturally impelled to extend his acquisitions
  • as much as possible; and nothing can restrain him in this propensity
  • but reflection and experience, by which he learns the pernicious
  • effects of that licence and the total dissolution of society which must
  • ensue from it. His original inclination, therefore, or instinct, is
  • here checked and restrained by a subsequent judgment or observation.
  • The case is precisely the same with the political or civil duty of
  • allegiance as with the natural duties of justice and fidelity. Our
  • primary instincts lead us either to indulge ourselves in unlimited
  • liberty or to seek dominion over others; and it is this reflection only
  • which engages us to sacrifice such strong passions to the interests
  • of peace and order. A very small degree of experience and observation
  • suffices to teach us that society cannot possibly be maintained without
  • the authority of magistrates, and that this authority must soon fall
  • into contempt where exact obedience is not paid to it. The observation
  • of these general and obvious interests is the source of all
  • allegiance, and of that moral obligation which we attribute to it.
  • What necessity, therefore, is there to found the duty of allegiance or
  • obedience to magistrates on that of fidelity or a regard to promises,
  • and to suppose that it is the consent of each individual which subjects
  • him to government, when it appears that both allegiance and fidelity
  • stand precisely on the same foundation, and are both submitted to by
  • mankind, on account of the apparent interests and necessities of human
  • society? We are bound to obey our sovereign, it is said, because we
  • have given a tacit promise to that purpose. But why are we bound to
  • observe our promise? It must here be asserted that the commerce and
  • intercourse of mankind, which are of such mighty advantage, can have no
  • security where men pay no regard to their engagements. In like manner
  • may it be said that men could not live at all in society, at least in a
  • civilized society, without laws and magistrates and judges to prevent
  • the encroachments of the strong upon the weak, of the violent upon the
  • just and equitable. The obligation to allegiance being of like force
  • and authority with the obligation to fidelity, we gain nothing by
  • resolving the one into the other. The general interests or necessities
  • of society are sufficient to establish both.
  • If the reason is asked of that obedience which we are bound to pay
  • to government, I readily answer, because society could not otherwise
  • subsist. And this answer is clear and intelligible to all mankind. Your
  • answer is, because we should keep our word. But besides that, nobody,
  • till trained in a philosophical system, can either comprehend or relish
  • this answer; besides this, I say, you find yourself embarrassed when it
  • is asked why we are bound to keep our word, and you can give no other
  • answer but what would immediately, without any circuit, have accounted
  • for our obligation to allegiance.
  • But to whom is allegiance due? And who are our lawful sovereigns?
  • This question is often the most difficult of any, and liable to
  • infinite discussions. When people are so happy that they can answer,
  • “Our present sovereign, who inherits, in a direct line, from
  • ancestors that have governed us for many ages,” this answer admits
  • of no reply, even though historians, in tracing up to the remotest
  • antiquity the origin of that royal family, may find, as commonly
  • happens, that its first authority was derived from usurpation and
  • violence. It is confessed that private justice, or the abstinence
  • from the properties of others, is a most cardinal virtue; yet reason
  • tells us that there is no property in durable objects, such as lands
  • or houses, when carefully examined in passing from hand to hand, but
  • must in some period have been founded on fraud and injustice. The
  • necessities of human society, neither in private nor public life, will
  • allow of such an accurate inquiry; and there is no virtue or moral duty
  • but what may with facility be refined away if we indulge in a false
  • philosophy, in sifting and scrutinizing it, by every captious rule of
  • logic, in every light or position in which it may be placed.
  • The questions with regard to public property have filled infinite
  • volumes of law and philosophy, if in both we add the commentators to
  • the original text; and in the end we may safely pronounce that many of
  • the rules there established are uncertain, ambiguous, and arbitrary.
  • The like opinion may be formed with regard to the successions and
  • rights of princes and forms of government. Many cases no doubt occur,
  • especially in the infancy of any government, which admit of no
  • determination from the laws of justice and equity; and our historian
  • Rapin allows that the controversy between Edward III. and Philip de
  • Valois was of this nature, and could be decided only by an appeal to
  • heaven—that is, by war and violence.
  • Who shall tell me whether Germanicus or Drusus ought to have succeeded
  • Tiberius had he died while they were both alive without naming either
  • of them for his successor? Ought the right of adoption to be received
  • as equivalent to that of blood in a nation where it had the same effect
  • in private families, and had already in two instances taken place in
  • the public? Ought Germanicus to be esteemed the eldest son because he
  • was born before Drusus, or the younger because he was adopted
  • after the birth of his brother? Ought the right of the elder to be
  • regarded in a nation where the eldest brother had no advantage in the
  • succession of private families? Ought the Roman Empire at that time to
  • be esteemed hereditary because of two examples, or ought it even so
  • early to be regarded as belonging to the stronger or present possessor
  • as being founded on so recent a usurpation?
  • Commodus mounted the throne after a pretty long succession of excellent
  • emperors, who had acquired their title, not by birth or public
  • election, but by the fictitious rite of adoption. That bloody debauchee
  • being murdered by a conspiracy suddenly formed between his wench and
  • her gallant, who happened at that time to be Prætorian Prefect, these
  • immediately deliberated about choosing a master to humankind, to speak
  • in the style of those ages; and they cast their eyes on Pertinax.
  • Before the tyrant’s death was known the Prefect went silently to that
  • senator, who, on the appearance of the soldiers, imagined that his
  • execution had been ordered by Commodus. He was immediately saluted
  • Emperor by the officer and his attendants; cheerfully proclaimed by the
  • populace; unwillingly submitted to by the guards; formally recognised
  • by the senate; and passively received by the provinces and armies of
  • the Empire.
  • The discontent of the Prætorian bands soon broke out in a sudden
  • sedition, which occasioned the murder of that excellent prince; and
  • the world being now without a master and without government, the
  • guards thought proper to set the Empire formally to sale. Julian, the
  • purchaser, was proclaimed by the soldiers, recognized by the senate,
  • and submitted to by the people, and must also have been submitted to
  • by the provinces had not the envy of the legions begot opposition and
  • resistance. Pescennius Niger in Syria elected himself Emperor, gained
  • the tumultuary consent of his army, and was attended with the secret
  • good-will of the senate and people of Rome. Albinus in Britain found an
  • equal right to set up his claim; but Severus, who governed Pannonia,
  • prevailed in the end above both of them. That able politician
  • and warrior, finding his own birth and dignity too much inferior to the
  • imperial crown, professed at first an intention only of revenging the
  • death of Pertinax. He marched as general into Italy, defeated Julian,
  • and without our being able to fix any precise commencement even of the
  • soldiers’ consent, he was from necessity acknowledged Emperor by the
  • senate and people, and fully established in his violent authority by
  • subduing Niger and Albinus.
  • “Inter hæc Gordianus Cæsar,” says Capitolinus, speaking of another
  • period, “sublatus a militibus, Imperator, est appellatus, quia non erat
  • alius in præsenti.” It is to be remarked that Gordian was a boy of
  • fourteen years of age.
  • Frequent instances of a like nature occur in the history of the
  • emperors; in that of Alexander’s successors, and of many other
  • countries. Nor can anything be more unhappy than a despotic government
  • of that kind, where the succession is disjointed and irregular, and
  • must be determined on every occasion by force or election. In a free
  • government the matter is often unavoidable, and is also much less
  • dangerous. The interests of liberty may there frequently lead the
  • people in their own defence to alter the succession of the crown,
  • and the constitution being compounded of parts, may still maintain a
  • sufficient stability by resting on the aristocratical or democratical
  • members, though the monarchical be altered from time to time in order
  • to accommodate it to the former.
  • In an absolute government when there is no legal prince who has a title
  • to the throne, it may safely be determined to belong to the first
  • occupier. Instances of this kind are but too frequent, especially in
  • the Eastern monarchies. When any race of princes expires the will or
  • destination of the last sovereign will be regarded as a title. Thus the
  • edict of Louis XIV., who called the bastard princes to the succession
  • in case of the failure of all the legitimate princes, would, in such
  • an event, have some authority.​[104] Thus the will of Charles
  • II. disposed of the whole Spanish monarchy. The cession of the ancient
  • proprietor, especially when joined to conquest, is likewise esteemed
  • a very good title. The general bond of obligation which unites us
  • to government is the interest and necessities of society, and this
  • obligation is very strong. The determination of it to this or that
  • particular prince or form of government is frequently more uncertain
  • and dubious. Present possession has considerable authority in these
  • cases, and greater than in private property, because of the disorders
  • which attend all revolutions and changes of government.​[105]
  • We shall only observe, before we conclude, that though an appeal to
  • general opinion may justly, in the speculative sciences of metaphysics,
  • natural philosophy, or astronomy, be esteemed unfair and inconclusive,
  • yet in all questions with regard to morals, as well as criticism, there
  • is really no standard by which any controversy can ever be decided.
  • And nothing is a clearer proof that a theory of this kind is erroneous
  • than to find that it leads to paradoxes which are repugnant to the
  • common sentiments of mankind and to general practice and opinion. The
  • doctrine which founds all lawful government on an original contract,
  • or consent of the people, is plainly of this kind; nor has the
  • ablest of its partisans in prosecution of it scrupled to affirm that
  • absolute monarchy is inconsistent with civil society, and so can be no
  • form of civil government at all,​[106] and that the supreme power in a
  • state cannot take from any man by taxes and impositions any part of his
  • property without his own consent or that of his representatives.​[107]
  • What authority any moral reasoning can have which leads to opinions so
  • wide of the general practice of mankind in every place but this single
  • kingdom it is easy to determine.​[108]
  • NOTES, OF THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT.
  • [103] Henry IV. of France.
  • [104] It is remarkable that in the remonstrance of the Duke
  • of Bourbon and the legitimate princes against this destination of
  • Louis XIV., the doctrine of the original contract is insisted on, even
  • in that absolute government. The French nation, say they, choosing
  • Hugh Capet and his posterity to rule over them and their posterity,
  • where the former line fails, there is a tacit right reserved to
  • choose a new royal family; and this right is invaded by calling the
  • bastard princes to the throne without the consent of the nation. But
  • the Comte de Boulainvilliers, who wrote in defence of the bastard
  • princes, ridicules this notion of an original contract, especially
  • when applied to Hugh Capet; who mounted the throne, says he, by
  • the same arts which have ever been employed by all conquerors and
  • usurpers. He got his title, indeed, recognized by the states after
  • he had put himself in possession. But is this a choice or contract?
  • The Comte de Boulainvilliers, we may observe, was a noted republican;
  • but being a man of learning, and very conversant in history, he knew
  • the people were never almost consulted in these revolutions and new
  • establishments, and that time alone bestowed right and authority on
  • what was commonly at first founded on force and violence. (See _État de
  • la France_, vol. iii.)
  • [105] The crime of rebellion amongst the ancients was commonly
  • marked by the terms νεωτεριζειν, _novas res moliri_.
  • [106] See Locke on Government, chap. 7, § 90.
  • [107] Locke on Government, chap. 11, § 138, 139, 140.
  • [108] The only passage I meet with in antiquity where the
  • obligation of obedience to government is ascribed to a promise is in
  • Plato—_in Critone_, where Socrates refuses to escape from prison,
  • because he had tacitly promised to obey the laws. Thus he builds a Tory
  • consequence of passive obedience on a Whig foundation of the original
  • contract.
  • New discoveries are not to be expected in these matters. If no
  • man, till very lately, ever imagined that government was founded
  • on contract, it is certain it cannot, in general, have any such
  • foundation.
  • OF PASSIVE OBEDIENCE.
  • In the former essay we endeavoured to refute the speculative systems
  • of politics advanced in this nation, as well the religious system of
  • the one party as the philosophical of the other. We come now to examine
  • the practical consequences deduced by each party with regard to the
  • measures of submission due to sovereigns.
  • As the obligation to justice is founded entirely on the interests of
  • society, which require mutual abstinence from property, in order to
  • preserve peace among mankind, it is evident that, when the execution
  • of justice would be attended with very pernicious consequences, that
  • virtue must be suspended, and give place to public utility in such
  • extraordinary and such pressing emergencies. The maxim, _fiat
  • Justitia, ruat Cœlum_ (let justice be performed though the universe
  • be destroyed), is apparently false, and by sacrificing the end to
  • the means shows a preposterous idea of the subordination of duties.
  • What governor of a town makes any scruple of burning the suburbs
  • when they facilitate the advances of the enemy? Or what general
  • abstains from plundering a neutral country when the necessities of
  • war require it, and he cannot otherwise maintain his army? The case
  • is the same with the duty of allegiance; and common sense teaches
  • us, that as government binds us to obedience only on account of its
  • tendency to public utility, that duty must always, in extraordinary
  • cases, when public ruin would evidently attend obedience, yield to
  • the primary and original obligation. _Salus populi suprema Lex_ (the
  • safety of the people is the supreme law). This maxim is agreeable to
  • the sentiments of mankind in all ages; nor is any one, when he reads
  • of the insurrections against a Nero, or a Philip, so infatuated with
  • party-systems as not to wish success to the enterprise and praise the
  • undertakers. Even our high monarchical party, in spite of their sublime
  • theory, are forced in such cases to judge and feel and approve in
  • conformity to the rest of mankind.
  • Resistance, therefore, being admitted in extraordinary emergencies,
  • the question can only be among good reasoners with regard to the
  • degree of necessity which can justify resistance and render it lawful
  • or commendable. And here I must confess that I shall always incline
  • to their side who draw the bond of allegiance the closest possible,
  • and consider an infringement of it as the last refuge in desperate
  • cases when the public is in the highest danger from violence and
  • tyranny; for besides the mischiefs of a civil war, which commonly
  • attends insurrection, it is certain that where a disposition to
  • rebellion appears among any people it is one chief cause of tyranny
  • in the rulers, and forces them into many violent measures which they
  • never would have embraced had every one seemed inclined to submission
  • and obedience. It is thus the tyrannicide or assassination,
  • approved of by ancient maxims, instead of keeping tyrants and usurpers
  • in awe, made them ten times more fierce and unrelenting; and is now
  • justly, upon that account, abolished by the laws of nations, and
  • universally condemned as a base and treacherous method of bringing to
  • justice these disturbers of society.
  • Besides, we must consider that, as obedience is our duty in the
  • common course of things, it ought chiefly to be inculcated; nor can
  • anything be more preposterous than an anxious care and solicitude in
  • stating all the cases in which resistance may be allowed. Thus, though
  • a philosopher reasonably acknowledges in the course of an argument
  • that the rules of justice may be dispensed with in cases of urgent
  • necessity, what should we think of a preacher or casuist who should
  • make it his chief study to find out such cases and enforce them with
  • all the vehemence of argument and eloquence? Would he not be better
  • employed in inculcating the general doctrine than in displaying the
  • particular exceptions, which we are, perhaps, but too much inclined of
  • ourselves to embrace and extend?
  • There are, however, two reasons which may be pleaded in defence of that
  • party among us who have, with so much industry, propagated the maxims
  • of resistance—maxims which, it must be confessed, are in general so
  • pernicious and so destructive of civil society. The first is that their
  • antagonists carrying the doctrine of obedience to such an extravagant
  • height as not only never to mention the exceptions in extraordinary
  • cases (which might perhaps be excusable), but even positively to
  • exclude them, it became necessary to insist on these exceptions, and
  • defend the rights of injured truth and liberty. The second and perhaps
  • better reason is founded on the nature of the British constitution and
  • form of government.
  • It is almost peculiar to our constitution to establish a first
  • magistrate with such high pre-eminence and dignity that, though limited
  • by the laws, he is in a manner, so far as regards his own person, above
  • the laws, and can neither be questioned nor punished for any injury
  • or wrong which may be committed by him. His ministers alone,
  • or those who act by his commission, are obnoxious to justice; and
  • while the prince is thus allured by the prospect of personal safety
  • to give the laws their free course, an equal security is in effect
  • obtained by the punishment of lesser offenders, and at the same time a
  • civil war is avoided, which would be the infallible consequence were
  • an attack at every turn made directly upon the sovereign. But though
  • the constitution pays this salutary compliment to the prince, it can
  • never reasonably be understood by that maxim to have determined its
  • own destruction, or to have established a tame submission where he
  • protects his ministers, perseveres in injustice, and usurps the whole
  • power of the commonwealth. This case, indeed, is never expressly put by
  • the laws, because it is impossible for them in their ordinary course
  • to provide a remedy for it, or establish any magistrate with superior
  • authority to chastise the exorbitancies of the prince. But as a right
  • without remedy would be the greatest of all absurdities, the remedy in
  • this case is the extraordinary one of resistance, when affairs come
  • to that extremity that the constitution can be defended by it alone.
  • Resistance, therefore, must of course become more frequent in the
  • British Government than in others which are simpler and consist of
  • fewer parts and movements. Where the king is an absolute sovereign, he
  • has little temptation to commit such enormous tyranny as may justly
  • provoke rebellion; but where he is limited, his imprudent ambition,
  • without any great vices, may run him into that perilous situation.
  • This is commonly supposed to have been the case with Charles I., and
  • if we may now speak truth, after animosities are laid, this was also
  • the case with James II. These were harmless, if not, in their private
  • character, good men; but mistaking the nature of our constitution, and
  • engrossing the whole legislative power, it became necessary to oppose
  • them with some vehemence, and even to deprive the latter formally of
  • that authority which he had used with such imprudence and indiscretion.
  • OF THE COALITION OF PARTIES.
  • To abolish all distinctions of party may not be practicable, perhaps
  • not desirable, in a free government. The only parties which are
  • dangerous are such as entertain opposite views with regard to the
  • essentials of government, the succession of the crown, or the
  • more considerable privileges belonging to the several members of
  • the constitution; where there is no room for any compromise or
  • accommodation, and where the controversy may appear so momentous as to
  • justify even an opposition by arms to the pretensions of antagonists.
  • Of this nature was the animosity continued for above a century between
  • the parties in England—an animosity which broke out sometimes into
  • civil war, which occasioned violent revolutions, and which continually
  • endangered the peace and tranquillity of the nation. But as there
  • has appeared of late the strongest symptoms of a universal desire to
  • abolish these party distinctions, this tendency to a coalition affords
  • the most agreeable prospect of future happiness, and ought to be
  • carefully cherished and promoted by every lover of his country.
  • There is not a more effectual method of promoting so good an end than
  • to prevent all unreasonable insult and triumph of the one party over
  • the other, to encourage moderate opinions, to find the proper medium
  • in all disputes, to persuade each that its antagonist may possibly be
  • sometimes in the right, and to keep a balance in the praise and blame
  • which we bestow on either side. The two former essays, concerning
  • the original contract and passive obedience, are calculated for this
  • purpose with regard to the philosophical controversies between the
  • parties, and tend to show that neither side are in these respects so
  • fully supported by reason as they endeavour to flatter themselves.
  • We shall proceed to exercise the same moderation with regard to the
  • historical disputes, by proving that each party was justified by
  • plausible topics, that there were on both sides wise men who
  • meant well to their country, and that the past animosity between the
  • factions had no better foundation than narrow prejudice or interested
  • passion.
  • The popular party, who afterwards acquired the name of Whigs, might
  • justify by very specious arguments that opposition to the crown, from
  • which our present free constitution is derived. Though obliged to
  • acknowledge that precedents in favour of prerogative had uniformly
  • taken place during many reigns before Charles I., they thought
  • that there was no reason for submitting any longer to so dangerous
  • an authority. Such might have been their reasoning. The rights of
  • mankind are so sacred that no prescription of tyranny or arbitrary
  • power can have authority sufficient to abolish them. Liberty is the
  • most inestimable of all blessings, and wherever there appears any
  • probability of recovering it, a nation may willingly run many hazards,
  • and ought not even to repine at the greatest effusion of blood or
  • dissipation of treasure. All human institutions, and none more than
  • government, are in continual fluctuation. Kings are sure to embrace
  • every opportunity of extending their prerogatives, and if favourable
  • incidents be not also laid hold of to extend and secure the privileges
  • of the people, a universal despotism must for ever prevail among
  • mankind. The example of all the neighbouring nations proves that
  • it is no longer safe to entrust with the crown the same exorbitant
  • prerogatives which had formerly been exercised during rude and simple
  • ages. And though the example of many late reigns may be pleaded in
  • favour of a power in the prince somewhat arbitrary, more remote reigns
  • afford instances of stricter limitations imposed on the crown, and
  • those pretensions of the Parliament, now branded with the title of
  • innovations, are only a recovery of the just rights of the people.
  • These views, far from being odious, are surely large and generous and
  • noble. To their prevalence and success the kingdom owes its liberty,
  • perhaps its learning, its industry, commerce, and naval power. By them
  • chiefly the English name is distinguished among the society
  • of nations, and aspires to a rivalship with that of the freest and
  • most illustrious commonwealths of antiquity. But as all these mighty
  • consequences could not reasonably be foreseen at the time when the
  • contest began, the royalists of that age wanted not specious arguments
  • on their side, by which they could justify their defence of the then
  • established prerogatives of the crown. We shall state the question, as
  • it might appear to them at the assembling of that Parliament, which by
  • their violent encroachments on the crown, began the civil wars.
  • The only rule of government, they might have said, known and
  • acknowledged among men, is use and practice. Reason is so uncertain
  • a guide that it will always be exposed to doubt and controversy.
  • Could it ever render itself prevalent over the people, men had always
  • retained it as their sole rule of conduct; they had still continued
  • in the primitive, unconnected state of nature, without submitting
  • to political government, whose sole basis is not pure reason, but
  • authority and precedent. Dissolve these ties, you break all the bonds
  • of civil society, and leave every man at liberty to consult his
  • particular interest, by those expedients which his appetite, disguised
  • under the appearance of reason, shall dictate to him. The spirit of
  • innovation is in itself pernicious, however favourable its particular
  • object may sometimes appear. A truth so obvious that the popular party
  • themselves are sensible of it, and therefore cover their encroachments
  • on the crown by the plausible pretence of their recovering the ancient
  • liberties of the people.
  • But the present prerogatives of the crown, allowing all the
  • suppositions of that party, have been incontestably established
  • ever since the accession of the house of Tudor, a period which,
  • as it now comprehends a hundred and sixty years, may be allowed
  • sufficient to give stability to any constitution. Would it not have
  • appeared ridiculous in the reign of the Emperor Adrian to talk of the
  • constitution of the republic as the rule of government, or to suppose
  • that the former rights of the senate and consuls and tribunes
  • were still subsisting?
  • But the present claims of the English monarchs are infinitely more
  • favourable than those of the Roman emperors during that age. The
  • authority of Augustus was a plain usurpation, grounded only on military
  • violence, and forms such an era in the Roman history as is obvious
  • to every reader. But if Henry VII. really, as some pretend, enlarged
  • the power of the crown, it was only by insensible acquisitions which
  • escaped the apprehension of the people, and have scarcely been remarked
  • even by historians and politicians. The new government, if it deserves
  • the name, is an imperceptible transition from the former; is entirely
  • engrafted on it; derives its title fully from that root; and is to be
  • considered only as one of those gradual revolutions to which human
  • affairs in every nation will be for ever subject.
  • The House of Tudor, and after them that of Stuart, exercised no
  • prerogatives, but what had been claimed and exercised by the
  • Plantagenets. Not a single branch of their authority can be said to
  • be altogether an innovation. The only difference is that perhaps the
  • more ancient kings exerted these powers only by intervals, and were not
  • able, by reason of the opposition of their barons, to render them so
  • steady a rule of administration.​[109] But the sole inference from this
  • fact is that those times were more turbulent and seditious, and that
  • the laws have happily of late gained the ascendant.
  • Under what pretence can the popular party now talk of recovering the
  • ancient constitution? The former control over the kings was not
  • placed in the commons, but in the barons. The people had no authority,
  • and even little or no liberty, till the crown, by suppressing these
  • factious tyrants, enforced the execution of the laws, and obliged all
  • the subjects equally to respect each other’s rights, privileges, and
  • properties. If we must return to the ancient barbarous and Gothic
  • constitution, let those gentlemen, who now behave themselves with so
  • much insolence to their sovereign, set the first example. Let them
  • make court to be admitted as retainers to a neighbouring baron, and by
  • submitting to slavery under him, acquire some protection to themselves,
  • together with the power of exercising rapine and oppression over their
  • inferior slaves and villains. This was the condition of the commons
  • among their remote ancestors.
  • But how far back shall we go, in having recourse to ancient
  • constitutions and governments? There was a constitution still more
  • ancient than that to which these innovators affect so much to appeal.
  • During that period there was no Magna Charta. The barons themselves
  • possessed few regular, stated privileges, and the House of Commons
  • probably had not an existence.
  • It is pleasant to hear a house, while they are usurping the whole
  • power of the government, talk of reviving ancient institutions. Is it
  • not known that, though the representatives received wages from their
  • constituents, to be a member of their house was always considered as
  • a burden, and a freedom from it as a privilege? Will they persuade us
  • that power, which of all human acquisitions is the most coveted, and
  • in comparison of which even reputation and pleasure and riches are
  • slighted, could ever be regarded as a burden by any man?
  • The property acquired of late by the commons, it is said, entitles
  • them to more power than their ancestors enjoyed. But to what is
  • this increase of their property owing, but to an increase of their
  • liberty and their security? Let them therefore acknowledge that their
  • ancestors, while the crown was restrained by the seditious barons,
  • really enjoyed less liberty than they themselves have attained,
  • after the sovereign acquired the ascendant, and let them enjoy that
  • liberty with moderation, and not forfeit it by new exorbitant claims,
  • and by rendering it a pretence for endless innovations.
  • The true rule of government is the present established practice of the
  • age. That has most authority, because it is recent. It is also better
  • known for the same reason. Who has assured those tribunes that the
  • Plantagenets did not exercise as high acts of authority as the Tudors?
  • The historians, they say, do not mention them; but the historians
  • are also silent with regard to the chief exertions of prerogative by
  • the Tudors. Where any power or prerogative is fully and undoubtedly
  • established, the exercise of it passes for a thing of course, and
  • readily escapes the notice of history and annals. Had we no other
  • monuments of Elizabeth’s reign than what are preserved even by Camden,
  • the most copious, judicious, and exact of our historians, we should be
  • entirely ignorant of the most important maxims of her government.
  • Was not the present monarchical government to its full extent
  • authorized by lawyers, recommended by divines, acknowledged by
  • politicians, acquiesced in—nay, passionately cherished—by the people in
  • general; and all this during a period of at least a hundred and sixty
  • years, and till of late, without the least murmur or controversy? This
  • general consent surely, during so long a time, must be sufficient to
  • render a constitution legal and valid. If the origin of all power be
  • derived, as is pretended, from the people, here is their consent in the
  • fullest and most ample terms that can be desired or imagined.
  • But the people must not pretend, because they can, by their consent,
  • lay the foundations of government, that therefore they are to be
  • permitted, at their pleasure, to overthrow and subvert them. There
  • is no end of these seditious and arrogant claims. The power of the
  • crown is now openly struck at; the nobility are also in visible peril;
  • the gentry will soon follow; the popular leaders, who will
  • then assume the name of gentry, will next be exposed to danger; and
  • the people themselves, having become incapable of civil government,
  • and lying under the restraint of no authority, must, for the sake of
  • peace, admit, instead of their legal and mild monarchs, a succession of
  • military and despotic tyrants.
  • These consequences are the more to be dreaded, as the present fury of
  • the people, though glossed over by pretensions to civil liberty, is in
  • reality incited by the fanaticism of religion, a principle the most
  • blind, headstrong, and ungovernable by which human nature can ever
  • possibly be actuated. Popular rage is dreadful, from whatever motive
  • derived, but must be attended with the most pernicious consequences
  • when it arises from a principle which disclaims all control by human
  • law, reason, or authority.
  • These are the arguments which each party may make use of to justify
  • the conduct of their predecessors during that great crisis. The
  • event has shown that the reasonings of the popular party were better
  • founded; but perhaps, according to the established maxims of lawyers
  • and politicians, the views of the royalists ought beforehand to have
  • appeared more solid, more safe, and more legal. But this is certain,
  • that the greater moderation we now employ in representing past events,
  • the nearer we shall be to produce a full coalition of the parties and
  • an entire acquiescence in our present happy establishment. Moderation
  • is of advantage to every establishment; nothing but zeal can overturn
  • a settled power, and an over-active zeal in friends is apt to beget a
  • like spirit in antagonists. The transition from a moderate opposition
  • against an establishment to an entire acquiescence in it is easy and
  • insensible.
  • There are many invincible arguments which should induce the malcontent
  • party to acquiesce entirely in the present settlement of the
  • constitution. They now find that the spirit of civil liberty, though
  • at first connected with religious fanaticism, could purge itself from
  • that pollution, and appear under a more genuine and engaging aspect—a
  • friend to toleration, and an encourager of all the enlarged and
  • generous sentiments that do honour to human nature. They may observe
  • that the popular claims could stop at a proper period, and after
  • retrenching the exorbitant prerogatives of the crown, could still
  • maintain a due respect to monarchy, to nobility, and to all ancient
  • institutions. Above all, they must be sensible that the very principle
  • which made the strength of their party, and from which it derived
  • its chief authority, has now deserted them and gone over to their
  • antagonists. The plan of liberty is settled, its happy effects are
  • proved by experience, a long tract of time has given it stability, and
  • whoever would attempt to overturn it, and to recall the past government
  • or abdicated family, would, besides other more criminal imputations,
  • be exposed in their turn to the reproach of faction and innovation.
  • While they peruse the history of past events, they ought to reflect,
  • both that the rights of the crown are long since annihilated, and that
  • the tyranny and violence and oppression to which they often gave rise
  • are ills from which the established liberty of the constitution has now
  • at last happily protected the people. These reflections will prove a
  • better security to our freedom and privileges than to deny, contrary
  • to the clearest evidence of facts, that such regal powers ever had
  • any existence. There is not a more effectual method of betraying a
  • cause than to lay the strength of the argument on a wrong place, and
  • by disputing an untenable post inure the adversaries to success and
  • victory.
  • NOTE, OF THE COALITION OF PARTIES.
  • [109] The author believes that he was the first writer who advanced
  • that the family of Tudor possessed in general more authority than their
  • immediate predecessors—an opinion which, he hopes, will be supported by
  • history, but which he proposes with some diffidence. There are strong
  • symptoms of arbitrary power in some former reigns, even after signing
  • of the charters. The power of the crown in that age depended less on
  • the constitution than on the capacity and vigour of the prince who wore
  • it.
  • OF THE PROTESTANT SUCCESSION.
  • I suppose that a member of Parliament in the reign of King William
  • or Queen Anne, while the establishment of the Protestant Succession
  • was yet uncertain, were deliberating concerning the party he would
  • choose in that important question, and weighing with impartiality
  • the advantages and disadvantages on each side. I believe the
  • following particulars would have entered into his consideration.
  • He would easily perceive the great advantages resulting from the
  • restoration of the Stuart family, by which we should preserve the
  • succession clear and undisputed, free from a pretender, with such a
  • specious title as that of blood, which with the multitude is always
  • the claim the strongest and most easily comprehended. It is in vain to
  • say, as many have done, that the question with regard to governors,
  • independent of government, is frivolous and little worth disputing,
  • much less fighting about. The generality of mankind never will enter
  • into these sentiments; and it is much happier, I believe, for society
  • that they do not, but rather continue in their natural prejudices and
  • prepossessions. How could stability be preserved in any monarchical
  • government (which, though perhaps not the best, is, and always has
  • been, the most common of any) unless men had so passionate a regard
  • for the true heir of their royal family, and even though he be weak in
  • understanding, or infirm in years, gave him so great a preference above
  • persons the most accomplished in shining talents or celebrated for
  • great achievements? Would not every popular leader put in his claim at
  • every vacancy, or even without any vacancy, and the kingdom become the
  • theatre of perpetual wars and convulsions? The condition of the Roman
  • Empire surely was not in this respect much to be envied, nor is that
  • of the Eastern nations, who pay little regard to the title of their
  • sovereigns, but sacrifice them every day to the caprice or momentary
  • humour of the populace or soldiery. It is but a foolish wisdom which
  • is so carefully displayed in under-valuing princes and placing them
  • on a level with the meanest of mankind. To be sure, an anatomist
  • finds no more in the greatest monarch than in the lowest peasant or
  • day-labourer, and a moralist may perhaps frequently find less. But
  • what do all these reflections tend to? We all of us still retain these
  • prejudices in favour of birth and family, and neither in our serious
  • occupations nor most careless amusements can we ever get entirely
  • rid of them. A tragedy that should represent the adventures
  • of sailors or porters, or even of private gentlemen, would presently
  • disgust us; but one that introduces kings and princes acquires in our
  • eyes an air of importance and dignity. Or should a man be able, by his
  • superior wisdom, to get entirely above such prepossessions, he would
  • soon, by means of the same wisdom, again bring himself down to them for
  • the sake of society, whose welfare he would perceive to be intimately
  • connected with them. Far from endeavouring to undeceive the people in
  • this particular, he would cherish such sentiments of reverence to their
  • princes as requisite to preserve a due subordination in society. And
  • though the lives of twenty thousand men be often sacrificed to maintain
  • a king in possession of his throne, or preserve the right of succession
  • undisturbed, he entertains no indignation at the loss on pretence that
  • every individual was perhaps in himself as valuable as the prince he
  • served. He considers the consequences of violating the hereditary right
  • of kings—consequences which may be felt for many centuries; while the
  • loss of several thousand men brings so little prejudice to a large
  • kingdom that it may not be perceived a few years afterwards.
  • The advantages of the Hanover succession are of an opposite nature,
  • and arise from this very circumstance, that it violates hereditary
  • right, and places on the throne a prince to whom birth gave no title
  • to that dignity. It is evident to any one who considers the history
  • of this island that the privileges of the people have during the last
  • two centuries been continually upon the increase, by the division of
  • the church-lands, by the alienations of the barons’ estates, by the
  • progress of trade, and above all by the happiness of our situation,
  • which for a long time gave us sufficient security without any standing
  • army or military establishment. On the contrary, public liberty
  • has, almost in every other nation of Europe, been during the same
  • period extremely upon the decline, while the people were disgusted
  • at the hardships of the old feudal militia, and chose rather to
  • entrust their prince with mercenary armies, which he easily turned
  • against themselves. It was nothing extraordinary, therefore, that
  • some of our British sovereigns mistook the nature of the
  • constitution and genius of the people; and as they embraced all the
  • favourable precedents left them by their ancestors, they overlooked
  • all those which were contrary, and which supposed a limitation in our
  • government. They were encouraged in this mistake by the example of all
  • the neighbouring princes, who, bearing the same title or appellation,
  • and being adorned with the same ensigns of authority, naturally led
  • them to claim the same powers and prerogatives.​[110] The flattery
  • of courtiers further blinded them, and above all that of the
  • clergy, who from several passages of Scripture, and these wrested too,
  • had erected a regular and avowed system of tyranny and despotic power.
  • The only method of destroying at once all these exorbitant claims and
  • pretensions was to depart from the true hereditary line, and choose
  • a prince who, being plainly a creature of the public, and receiving
  • the crown on conditions, expressed and avowed, found his authority
  • established on the same bottom with the privileges of the people.
  • By electing him in the royal line we cut off all hopes of ambitious
  • subjects who might in future emergencies disturb the government by
  • their cabals and pretensions; by rendering the crown hereditary in
  • his family we avoided all the inconveniences of elective monarchy;
  • and by excluding the lineal heir we secured all our constitutional
  • limitations, and rendered our government uniform and of a piece. The
  • people cherish monarchy because protected by it, the monarch favours
  • liberty because created by it. And thus every advantage is obtained
  • by the new establishment, as far as human skill and wisdom can extend
  • itself.
  • These are the separate advantages of fixing the succession, either in
  • the house of Stuart or in that of Hanover. There are also disadvantages
  • on each establishment, which an impartial patriot would ponder and
  • examine, in order to form a just judgment upon the whole.
  • The disadvantages of the Protestant Succession consist in the foreign
  • dominions which are possessed by the princes of the Hanover line, and
  • which it might be supposed would engage us in the intrigues and wars of
  • the Continent, and lose us in some measure the inestimable advantage we
  • possess of being surrounded and guarded by the sea which we command.
  • The disadvantages of recalling the abdicated family consist
  • chiefly in their religion, which is more prejudicial to society than
  • that established among us is contrary to it, and affords no toleration,
  • or peace, or security to any other religion.
  • It appears to me that all these advantages and disadvantages are
  • allowed on both sides; at least, by every one who is at all susceptible
  • of argument or reasoning. No subject, however loyal, pretends to deny
  • that the disputed title and foreign dominions of the present royal
  • family are a loss; nor is there any partisan of the Stuart family but
  • will confess that the claim of hereditary, indefeasible right, and the
  • Roman Catholic religion, are also disadvantages in that family. It
  • belongs, therefore, to a philosopher alone, who is of neither party,
  • to put all these circumstances in the scale and to assign to each of
  • them its proper poise and influence. Such a one will readily, at first,
  • acknowledge that all political questions are infinitely complicated,
  • and that there scarce ever occurs in any deliberation a choice which
  • is either purely good or purely ill. Consequences, mixed and varied,
  • may be foreseen to flow from every measure—and many consequences
  • unforeseen do always, in fact, result from it. Hesitation, and reserve,
  • and suspense are therefore the only sentiment he brings to this essay
  • or trial; or if he indulges any passion it is that of derision and
  • ridicule against the ignorant multitude, who are always clamorous and
  • dogmatical even in the nicest questions, of which, from want of temper,
  • perhaps still more than of understanding, they are altogether unfit
  • judges.
  • But to say something more determinate on this head, the following
  • reflections will, I hope, show the temper, if not the understanding of
  • a philosopher.
  • Were we to judge merely by first appearances and by past experience, we
  • must allow that the advantages of a parliamentary title of the house of
  • Hanover are much greater than those of an undisputed hereditary title
  • in the house of Stuart, and that our fathers acted wisely in preferring
  • the former to the latter. So long as the house of Stuart reigned in
  • Britain, which, with some interruption, was above eighty years,
  • the government was kept in a continual fever by the contentions between
  • the privileges of the people and the prerogatives of the crown. If
  • arms were dropped, the noise of disputes continued; or, if these were
  • silenced, jealousy still corroded the heart, and threw the nation into
  • an unnatural ferment and disorder. And while we were thus occupied in
  • domestic contentions, a foreign power, dangerous, if not fatal, to
  • public liberty, erected itself in Europe without any opposition from
  • us, and even sometimes with our assistance.
  • But during these last sixty years, when a parliamentary establishment
  • has taken place, whatever factions may have prevailed either among the
  • people or in public assemblies, the whole force of our constitution
  • has always fallen to one side, and an uninterrupted harmony has been
  • preserved between our princes and our parliaments. Public liberty, with
  • internal peace and order, has flourished almost without interruption;
  • trade and manufactures and agriculture have increased; the arts and
  • sciences and philosophy have been cultivated. Even religious parties
  • have been necessitated to lay aside their mutual rancour, and the glory
  • of the nation has spread itself all over Europe; while we stand the
  • bulwark against oppression, and the great antagonist of that power
  • which threatens every people with conquest and subjection. So long
  • and so glorious a period no nation almost can boast of; nor is there
  • another instance in the whole history of mankind that so many millions
  • of people have during such a space of time been held together in a
  • manner so free, so rational, and so suitable to the dignity of human
  • nature.
  • But though this recent instance seems clearly to decide in favour of
  • the present establishment, there are some circumstances to be thrown
  • into the other scale, and it is dangerous to regulate our judgment by
  • one event or example.
  • We have had two rebellions during the flourishing period above
  • mentioned, besides plots and conspiracies without number; and, if none
  • of these have produced any very fatal event, we may ascribe
  • our escape chiefly to the narrow genius of those princes who disputed
  • our establishment, and may esteem ourselves so far fortunate. But the
  • claims of the banished family, I fear, are not yet antiquated, and
  • who can foretell that their future attempts will produce no greater
  • disorder?
  • The disputes between privilege and prerogative may easily be composed
  • by laws, and votes, and conferences, and concessions, where there is
  • tolerable temper or prudence on both sides, or on either side. Among
  • contending titles the question can only be determined by the sword, and
  • by devastation, and by civil war.
  • A prince who fills the throne with a disputed title dares not arm his
  • subjects, the only method of securing a people fully, both against
  • domestic oppression and foreign conquest.
  • Notwithstanding all our riches and renown, what a critical escape
  • did we lately make from dangers, which were owing, not so much to
  • bad conduct and ill success in war, as to the pernicious practice of
  • mortgaging our finances, and the still more pernicious maxim of never
  • paying off our encumbrances? Such fatal measures could never have been
  • embraced had it not been to secure a precarious establishment.​[111]
  • But to convince us that an hereditary title is to be embraced rather
  • than a parliamentary one, which is not supported by any other views
  • or motives, a man needs only transport himself back to the era of the
  • Restoration, and suppose that he had had a seat in that Parliament
  • which recalled the royal family, and put a period to the greatest
  • disorders that ever arose from the opposite pretensions of prince and
  • people. What would have been thought of one that had proposed at that
  • time to set aside Charles II. and settle the crown on the Duke of York
  • or Gloucester, merely in order to exclude all high claims like those of
  • their father and grandfather? Would not such a one have been
  • regarded as a very extravagant projector, who loved dangerous remedies,
  • and could tamper and play with a government and national constitution
  • like a quack with a sickly patient?
  • The advantages which result from a parliamentary title, preferably
  • to an hereditary one, though they are great, are too refined ever to
  • enter into the conception of the vulgar. The bulk of mankind would
  • never allow them to be sufficient for committing what would be regarded
  • as an injustice to the prince. They must be supported by some gross,
  • popular, and familiar topics; and wise men, though convinced of their
  • force, would reject them in compliance with the weakness and prejudices
  • of the people. An encroaching tyrant or deluded bigot alone, by his
  • misconduct, is able to enrage the nation and render practicable what
  • was always perhaps desirable.
  • In reality, the reason assigned by the nation for excluding the race
  • of Stuart, and so many other branches of the royal family, is not on
  • account of their hereditary title (which, however just in itself,
  • would, to vulgar apprehensions, have appeared altogether absurd),
  • but on account of their religion, which leads us to compare the
  • disadvantages above mentioned of each establishment.
  • I confess that, considering the matter in general, it were much to be
  • wished that our prince had no foreign dominions, and could confine all
  • his attention to the government of this island. For, not to mention
  • some real inconveniences that may result from territories on the
  • Continent, they afford such a handle for calumny and defamation as is
  • greedily seized by the people, who are always disposed to think ill
  • of their superiors. It must, however, be acknowledged that Hanover
  • is perhaps the spot of ground in Europe the least inconvenient for a
  • King of Britain. It lies in the heart of Germany, at a distance from
  • the Great Powers which are our natural rivals; it is protected by the
  • laws of the Empire as well as by the arms of its own sovereign, and it
  • serves only to connect us more closely with the house of Austria, which
  • is our natural ally.
  • In the last war it has been of service to us, by furnishing us with a
  • considerable body of auxiliary troops, the bravest and most faithful
  • in the world. The Elector of Hanover is the only considerable prince
  • in the Empire who has pursued no separate end, and has raised up no
  • stale pretensions during the late commotions of Europe, but has acted
  • all along with the dignity of a King of Britain. And ever since the
  • accession of that family it would be difficult to show any harm we have
  • ever received from the electoral dominions, except that short disgust
  • in 1718, with Charles XII., who, regulating himself by maxims very
  • different from those of other princes, made a personal quarrel of every
  • public injury.​[112]
  • The religious persuasion of the house of Stuart is an inconvenience
  • of a much deeper dye, and would threaten us with much more dismal
  • consequences. The Roman Catholic religion, with its huge train of
  • priests and friars, is vastly more expensive than ours. Even though
  • unaccompanied with its natural attendants of inquisitors, and stakes,
  • and gibbets, it is less tolerating; and not contented with dividing
  • the sacerdotal from the regal office (which must be prejudicial to
  • any state), it bestows the former on a foreigner, who has always a
  • separate, and may often have an opposite interest to that of the public.
  • But were this religion ever so advantageous to society, it is contrary
  • to that which is established among us, and which is likely to keep
  • possession for a long time of the minds of the people; and though it
  • is much to be hoped that the progress of reason and philosophy will,
  • by degrees, abate the virulent acrimony of opposite religions all over
  • Europe, yet the spirit of moderation has as yet made too slow advances
  • to be entirely trusted. The conduct of the Saxon family, where the
  • same person can be a Catholic King and Protestant Elector, is perhaps
  • the first instance in modern times of so reasonable and prudent a
  • behaviour. And the gradual progress of the Catholic superstition does,
  • even there, prognosticate a speedy alteration; after which it
  • is justly to be apprehended that the persecutions will put a speedy
  • period to the Protestant religion in the place of its nativity.
  • Thus, upon the whole, the advantages of the settlement in the family
  • of Stuart, which frees us from a disputed title, seem to bear some
  • proportion with those of the settlement in the family of Hanover,
  • which frees us from the claims of prerogative; but at the same time
  • its disadvantages, by placing on the throne a Roman Catholic, are much
  • greater than those of the other establishment, in settling the crown on
  • a foreign prince. What party an impartial patriot, in the reign of King
  • William or Queen Anne, would have chosen amidst these opposite views
  • may perhaps to some appear hard to determine. For my part, I esteem
  • liberty so invaluable a blessing in society, that whatever favours its
  • progress and security can scarce be too fondly cherished by every one
  • who is a lover of humankind.
  • But the settlement in the house of Hanover has actually taken place.
  • The princes of that family, without intrigue, without cabal, without
  • solicitation on their part, have been called to mount our throne by
  • the united voice of the whole legislative body. They have, since their
  • accession, displayed in all their actions the utmost mildness, equity,
  • and regard to the laws and constitution. Our own ministers, our own
  • parliaments, ourselves have governed us, and if aught ill has befallen
  • us we can only blame fortune or ourselves. What a reproach must we
  • become among nations if, disgusted with a settlement so deliberately
  • made, and whose conditions have been so religiously observed, we should
  • throw everything again into confusion, and by our levity and rebellious
  • disposition prove ourselves totally unfit for any state but that of
  • absolute slavery and subjection?
  • The greatest inconvenience attending a disputed title is that it brings
  • us in danger of civil wars and rebellions. What wise man, to avoid this
  • inconvenience, would run directly upon a civil war and rebellion? Not
  • to mention that so long possession, secured by so many laws, must ere
  • this time, in the apprehension of a great part of the nation,
  • have begot a title in the house of Hanover independent of their present
  • possession, so that now we should not, even by a revolution, obtain the
  • end of avoiding a disputed title.
  • No revolution made by national forces will ever be able, without some
  • other great necessity, to abolish our debts and encumbrances, in which
  • the interest of so many persons is concerned. And a revolution made
  • by foreign forces is a conquest—a calamity with which the precarious
  • balance of power threatens us, and which our civil dissensions are
  • likely, above all other circumstances, to bring upon us.
  • NOTES, OF THE PROTESTANT SUCCESSION.
  • [110] It appears from the speeches and proclamations and whole train
  • of King James I.’s actions, as well as his son’s, that they considered
  • the English government as a simple monarchy, and never imagined that
  • any considerable part of their subjects entertained a contrary idea.
  • This made them discover their pretensions without preparing any force
  • to support them, and even without reserve or disguise, which are always
  • employed by those who enter upon any new project, or endeavour to
  • innovate in any government. King James told his Parliament plainly,
  • when they meddled in State affairs, “Ne sutor ultra crepidam.” He used
  • also at his table, in promiscuous companies, to advance his notions in
  • a manner still more undignified, as we may learn from a story told in
  • the life of Mr. Waller, and which that poet used frequently to repeat.
  • When Mr. Waller was young, he had the curiosity to go to court; and
  • he stood in the circle and saw King James dine where, amongst other
  • company, there sat at table two bishops. The King, openly and aloud,
  • proposed this question: “Whether he might not take his subjects’ money,
  • when he had occasion for it, without all this formality of Parliament?”
  • The one bishop readily replied, “God forbid you should not, for you are
  • the breath of our nostrils.” The other bishop declined answering, and
  • said he was not skilled in Parliamentary cases; but upon the King’s
  • urging him, and saying he would admit of no evasion, his lordship
  • replied very pleasantly, “Why, then, I think your Majesty may lawfully
  • take my brother’s money, for he offers it.” In Sir Walter Raleigh’s
  • preface to the _History of the World_ there is this remarkable passage:
  • “Philip II., by strong hand and main force, attempted to make himself
  • not only an absolute monarch over the Netherlands, like unto the kings
  • and sovereigns of England and France, but, Turk-like, to tread under
  • his feet all their natural and fundamental laws, privileges and ancient
  • rights.” Spenser, speaking of some grants of the English kings to the
  • Irish corporations, says: “All which, though at the time of their first
  • grant they were tolerable, and perhaps reasonable, yet now are most
  • unreasonable and inconvenient. But all these will easily be cut off
  • with the superior power of her Majesty’s prerogative, against which her
  • own grants are not to be pleaded or enforced.” (_State of Ireland_, p.
  • 1537, edit. 1706.)
  • As these were very common, if not perhaps the universal notions of
  • the times, the two first princes of the house of Stuart were the more
  • excusable for their mistake. And Rapin, suitable to his usual malignity
  • and partiality, seems to treat them with too much severity upon account
  • of it.
  • [111] Those who consider how universal this pernicious practice of
  • funding has become all over Europe may perhaps dispute this last
  • opinion, but we lay under less necessity than other States.
  • [112] This was published in the year 1752.
  • IDEA OF A PERFECT COMMONWEALTH.
  • Of all mankind there are none so pernicious as political projectors, if
  • they have power, nor so ridiculous if they want it; as, on the other
  • hand, a wise politician is the most beneficial character in nature if
  • accompanied with authority; and the most innocent, and not altogether
  • useless, even if deprived of it. It is not with forms of government
  • as with other artificial contrivances, where an old engine may be
  • rejected, if we can discover another more accurate and commodious, or
  • where trials may safely be made, even though the success be doubtful.
  • An established government has an infinite advantage, by that very
  • circumstance of its being established; the bulk of mankind being
  • governed by authority, not reason, and never attributing authority
  • to anything that has not the recommendation of antiquity. To tamper,
  • therefore, in this affair, or try projects merely upon the credit of
  • supposed argument and philosophy, can never be the part of a wise
  • magistrate, who will bear a reverence to what carries the marks of
  • age; and though he may attempt some improvements for the public good,
  • yet will he adjust his innovations as much as possible to the
  • ancient fabric, and preserve entire the chief pillars and supports of
  • the constitution.
  • The mathematicians in Europe have been much divided concerning that
  • figure of a ship which is the most commodious for sailing; and Huygens,
  • who at last determined this controversy, is justly thought to have
  • obliged the learned, as well as commercial world; though Columbus had
  • sailed to America, and Sir Francis Drake made the tour of the world,
  • without any such discovery. As one form of government must be allowed
  • more perfect than another, independent of the manners and humours of
  • particular men, why may we not inquire what is the most perfect of all,
  • though the common botched and inaccurate governments seem to serve
  • the purposes of society, and though it be not so easy to establish a
  • new government as to build a vessel upon a new plan? The subject is
  • surely the most worthy curiosity of any the wit of man can possibly
  • devise. And who knows, if this controversy were fixed by the universal
  • consent of the learned, but in some future age an opportunity might be
  • afforded of reducing the theory to practice, either by a dissolution
  • of the old governments, or the combination of men to form a new one in
  • some distant part of the world? In all cases it must be advantageous
  • to know what is most perfect in the kind, that we may be able to bring
  • any real constitution or form of government as near it as possible,
  • by such gentle alterations and innovations as may not give too great
  • disturbance to society.
  • All I pretend to in the present essay is to revive this subject of
  • speculation, and therefore I shall deliver my sentiments in as few
  • words as possible. A long dissertation on that head would not, I
  • apprehend, be very acceptable to the public, who will be apt to regard
  • such disquisitions both as useless and chimerical.
  • All plans of government which suppose great reformation in the manners
  • of mankind are plainly imaginary. Of this nature are the _Republic_ of
  • Plato and the _Utopia_ of Sir Thomas More. The _Oceana_ is the only
  • valuable model of a commonwealth that has as yet been offered to the
  • public.
  • The chief defects of the _Oceana_ seem to be these—First, its rotation
  • is inconvenient, by throwing men, of whatever ability, by intervals,
  • out of public employments. Secondly, its Agrarian is impracticable.
  • Men will soon learn the art, which was practised in ancient Rome,
  • of concealing their possessions under other people’s names, till at
  • last the abuse will become so common, that they will throw off even
  • the appearance of restraint. Thirdly, the _Oceana_ provides not a
  • sufficient security for liberty, or the redress of grievances. The
  • senate must propose, and the people consent; by which means the
  • senate have not only a negative upon the people, but, what is of
  • infinitely greater consequence, their negative goes before the votes
  • of the people. Were the king’s negative of the same nature in the
  • English constitution, and could he prevent any bill from coming into
  • Parliament, he would be an absolute monarch. As his negative follows
  • the votes of the Houses, it is of little consequence; such a difference
  • is there in the manner of placing the same thing. When a popular bill
  • has been debated in the two Houses, is brought to maturity, all its
  • conveniences and inconveniences weighed and balanced, if afterwards
  • it be presented for the Royal assent, few princes will venture to
  • reject the unanimous desire of the people. But could the king crush
  • a disagreeable bill in embryo (as was the case, for some time, in
  • the Scots Parliament, by means of the Lords of the Articles) the
  • British Government would have no balance, nor would grievances ever
  • be redressed. And it is certain that exorbitant power proceeds not,
  • in any government, from new laws so much as from neglecting to remedy
  • the abuses which frequently rise from the old ones. A government, says
  • Machiavel, must often be brought back to its original principles. It
  • appears then, that in the _Oceana_ the whole legislature may be said to
  • rest in the senate; which Harrington would own to be an inconvenient
  • form of government, especially after the Agrarian is abolished.
  • Here is a form of government to which I cannot, in theory, discover any
  • considerable objection,
  • Let Great Britain and Ireland, or any territory of equal extent,
  • be divided into a hundred counties, and each county into a hundred
  • parishes, making in all ten thousand. If the country purposed to be
  • erected into a commonwealth be of more narrow extent, we may diminish
  • the number of counties; but never bring them below thirty. If it be of
  • greater extent, it were better to enlarge the parishes, or throw more
  • parishes into a county, than increase the number of counties.
  • Let all the freeholders of ten pounds a year in the country, and all
  • the householders worth two hundred pounds in the town parishes, meet
  • annually in the parish church, and choose, by ballot, some freeholder
  • of the county for their member, whom we shall call the county
  • representative.
  • Let the hundred county representatives, two days after their election,
  • meet in the county-town, and choose by ballot, from their own body, ten
  • county magistrates and one senator. There are, therefore, in the whole
  • commonwealth, one hundred senators, eleven hundred county magistrates,
  • and ten thousand county representatives; for we shall bestow on all
  • senators the authority of county magistrates, and on all county
  • magistrates the authority of county representatives.
  • Let the senators meet in the capital, and be endowed with the whole
  • executive power of the commonwealth; the power of peace and war, of
  • giving orders to generals, admirals, and ambassadors, and, in short,
  • all the prerogatives of a British king, except his negative.
  • Let the county representatives meet in their particular counties, and
  • possess the whole legislative power of the commonwealth; the greatest
  • number of counties deciding the question; and where these are equal,
  • let the senate have the casting vote.
  • Every new law must first be debated in the senate; and though rejected
  • by it, if ten senators insist and protest, it must be sent down to the
  • counties. The senate may join to the copy of the law their reasons for
  • receiving or rejecting it.
  • Because it would be troublesome to assemble all the county
  • representatives for every trivial law that may be requisite, the
  • senate have their choice of sending down the law either to the county
  • magistrates or county representatives.
  • The magistrates, though the law be referred to them, may, if they
  • please, call the representatives, and submit the affair to their
  • determination.
  • Whether the law be referred by the senate to the county magistrates
  • or representatives, a copy of it, and of the senate’s reasons, must
  • be sent to every representative eight days before the day appointed
  • for the assembling, in order to deliberate concerning it. And though
  • the determination be, by the senate, referred to the magistrates, if
  • five representatives of the county order the magistrates to assemble
  • the whole court of representatives, and submit the affair to their
  • determination, they must obey.
  • Either the county magistrates or representatives may give to the
  • senator of the county the copy of a law to be proposed to the senate;
  • and if five counties concur in the same order, the law, though
  • refused by the senate, must come either to the county magistrates or
  • representatives, as is contained in the order of the five counties.
  • Any twenty counties, by a vote either of their magistrates or
  • representatives, may throw any man out of all public offices for a
  • year. Thirty counties for three years.
  • The senate has a power of throwing out any member or number of members
  • of its own body, not to be re-elected for that year. The senate cannot
  • throw out twice in a year the senator of the same county.
  • The power of the old senate continues for three weeks after the
  • annual election of the county representatives. Then all the new
  • senators are shut up in a conclave, like the cardinals, and by an
  • intricate ballot, such as that of Venice or Malta, they choose the
  • following magistrates:—A protector, who represents the dignity of the
  • commonwealth and presides in the senate, two secretaries of state,
  • these six councils: a council of state, a council of religion and
  • learning, a council of trade, a council of laws, a council
  • of war, a council of the admiralty, each council consisting of five
  • persons; together with six commissioners of the treasury and a first
  • commissioner. All these must be senators. The senate also names all the
  • ambassadors to foreign courts, who may either be senators or not.
  • The senate may continue any or all of these, but must re-elect them
  • every year.
  • The protector and two secretaries have session and suffrage in the
  • council of state. The business of that council is all foreign politics.
  • The council of state has session and suffrage in all the other councils.
  • The council of religion and learning inspects the universities and
  • clergy. That of trade inspects everything that may affect commerce.
  • That of laws inspects all the abuses of laws by the inferior
  • magistrates, and examines what improvements may be made of the
  • municipal law. That of war inspects the militia and its discipline,
  • magazines, stores, etc., and when the republic is in war, examines into
  • the proper orders for generals. The council of admiralty has the same
  • power with regard to the navy, together with the nomination of the
  • captains and all inferior officers.
  • None of these councils can give orders themselves, except where
  • they receive such powers from the senate. In other cases, they must
  • communicate everything to the senate.
  • When the senate is under adjournment, any of the councils may assemble
  • it before the day appointed for its meeting.
  • Besides these councils or courts, there is another called the court
  • of competitors, which is thus constituted:—If any candidates for the
  • office of senator have more votes than a third of the representatives,
  • that candidate who has most votes next to the senator elected,
  • becomes incapable for one year of all public offices, even of being a
  • magistrate or representative; but he takes his seat in the court of
  • competitors. Here then is a court which may sometimes consist of a
  • hundred members, sometimes have no members at all, and by that means be
  • for a year abolished.
  • The court of competitors has no power in the commonwealth. It has
  • only the inspection of the public accounts and the accusing any man
  • before the senate. If the senate acquit him, the court of competitors
  • may, if they please, appeal to the people, either magistrates or
  • representatives. Upon that appeal the magistrates or representatives
  • meet at the day appointed by the court of competitors, and choose in
  • each county three persons, from which number every senator is excluded.
  • These to the number of three hundred meet in the capital, and bring the
  • person accused to a new trial.
  • The court of competitors may propose any law to the senate, and if
  • refused, may appeal to the people—that is to the magistrates or
  • representatives, who examine it in their counties. Every senator who is
  • thrown out of the senate by a vote of the court, takes his seat in the
  • court of competitors.
  • The senate possesses all the judicative authority of the House of
  • Lords—that is, all the appeals from the inferior courts. It likewise
  • nominates the Lord Chancellor and all the officers of the law.
  • Every county is a kind of republic within itself, and the
  • representatives may make county-laws, which have no authority until
  • three months after they are voted. A copy of the law is sent to the
  • senate and to every other county. The senate or any single county may
  • at any time annul any law of another county.
  • The representatives have all the authority of the British justices of
  • peace in trials, commitments, etc.
  • The magistrates have the nomination of all the officers of the revenue
  • in each county. All causes with regard to the revenue are appealed
  • ultimately to the magistrates. They pass the accounts of all the
  • officers, but must have all their own accounts examined and passed at
  • the end of the year by the representatives.
  • The magistrates name rectors or ministers to all the parishes.
  • The Presbyterian government is established, and the highest
  • ecclesiastical court is an assembly or synod of all the presbyters of
  • the county. The magistrates may take any cause from this court, and
  • determine it themselves.
  • The magistrates may try and depose or suspend any presbyter.
  • The militia is established in imitation of that of Switzerland, which,
  • being well known, we shall not insist upon it. It will only be proper
  • to make this addition, that an army of 20,000 men be annually drawn out
  • by rotation, paid and encamped during six weeks in summer, that the
  • duty of a camp may not be altogether unknown.
  • The magistrates nominate all the colonels and downwards. The senate all
  • upwards. During war, the general nominates the colonel and downwards,
  • and his commission is good for a twelvemonth; but after that, it must
  • be confirmed by the magistrates of the county to which the regiment
  • belongs. The magistrates may break any officer in the county regiment,
  • and the senate may do the same to any officer in the service. If the
  • magistrates do not think proper to confirm the general’s choice, they
  • may nominate another officer in the place of him they reject.
  • All crimes are tried within the county by the magistrates and a jury;
  • but the senate can stop any trial, and bring it before themselves.
  • Any county may indict any man before the senate for any crime.
  • The protector, the two secretaries, the council of state, with any
  • five more that the senate appoints on extraordinary emergencies, are
  • possessed of dictatorial power for six months.
  • The protector may pardon any person condemned by the inferior courts.
  • In time of war, no officer of the army that is in the field can have
  • any civil office in the commonwealth.
  • The capital, which we shall call London, may be allowed four
  • members in the senate. It may therefore be divided into four
  • counties. The representatives of each of these choose one senator
  • and ten magistrates. There are therefore in the city four
  • senators, forty-four magistrates, and four hundred representatives.
  • The magistrates have the same authority as in the counties. The
  • representatives also have the same authority; but they never meet in
  • one general court. They give their votes in their particular county or
  • division of hundreds.
  • When they enact any city-law, the greatest number of counties or
  • divisions determines the matter; and where these are equal, the
  • magistrates have the casting vote.
  • The magistrates choose the mayor, sheriff, recorder, and other officers
  • of the city.
  • In the commonwealth, no representative, magistrate, or senator, as
  • such, has any salary. The protector, secretaries, councils, and
  • ambassadors have salaries.
  • The first year in every century is set apart to correct all
  • inequalities which time may have produced in the representative. This
  • must be done by the legislature.
  • The following political aphorisms may explain the reason of these
  • orders.
  • The lower sort of people and small proprietors are good enough judges
  • of one not very distant from them in rank or habitation, and therefore,
  • in their parochial meetings, will probably choose the best, or nearly
  • the best representative; but they are wholly unfit for county-meetings
  • and for electing into the higher offices of the republic. Their
  • ignorance gives the grandees an opportunity of deceiving them.
  • Ten thousand, even though they were not annually elected, are a large
  • enough basis for any free government. It is true the nobles in Poland
  • are more than 10,000, and yet these oppress the people; but as power
  • continues there always in the same persons and families, this makes
  • them, in a manner, a different nation from the people. Besides, the
  • nobles are there united under a few heads of families.
  • All free governments must consist of two councils, a less and a
  • greater; or, in other words, of a senate and people. The people, as
  • Harrington observes, would want wisdom without the senate; the senate
  • without the people would want honesty.
  • A large assembly of 1000, for instance, to represent the people,
  • if allowed to debate, would fall into disorder. If not allowed to
  • debate, the senate has a negative upon them, and the worst kind of
  • negative—that before resolution.
  • Here therefore is an inconvenience which no government has yet fully
  • remedied, but which is the easiest to be remedied in the world. If the
  • people debate, all is confusion; if they do not debate, they can only
  • resolve, and then the senate carves for them. Divide the people into
  • many separate bodies, and then they may debate with safety, and every
  • inconvenience seems to be prevented.
  • Cardinal de Retz says that all numerous assemblies, however composed,
  • are mere mob, and swayed in their debates by the least motive. This we
  • find confirmed by daily experience. When an absurdity strikes a member,
  • he conveys it to his neighbour, and so on till the whole be infected.
  • Separate this great body, and though every member be only of middling
  • sense, it is not probable that anything but reason can prevail over the
  • whole. Influence and example being removed, good sense will always get
  • the better of bad among a number of people. Good sense is one thing;
  • but follies are numberless, and every man has a different one. The only
  • way of making a people wise is to keep them from uniting into large
  • assemblies.
  • There are two things to be guarded against in every senate—its
  • combination and its division. Its combination is most dangerous, and
  • against this inconvenience we have provided the following remedies:—1.
  • The great dependence of the senators on the people by annual election,
  • and that not by an undistinguishing rabble, like the English electors,
  • but by men of fortune and education. 2. The small power they are
  • allowed. They have few offices to dispose of. Almost all are given by
  • the magistrates in the counties. 3. The court of competitors which,
  • being composed of men that are their rivals next to them in interest
  • and uneasy in their present situation, will be sure to take all
  • advantages against them.
  • The division of the senate is prevented—1. By the smallness
  • of their number. 2. As faction supposes a combination to a separate
  • interest, it is prevented by their dependence on the people. 3. They
  • have a power of expelling any factious member. It is true when another
  • member of the same spirit comes from the county, they have no power of
  • expelling him; nor is it fit they should, for that shows the humour to
  • be in the people, and probably arises from some ill-conduct in public
  • affairs. 4. Almost any man in a senate so regularly chosen by the
  • people may be supposed fit for any civil office. It would be proper,
  • therefore, for the senate to form some general resolutions with regard
  • to the disposing of offices among the members, which resolutions would
  • not confine them in critical times, when extraordinary parts on the one
  • hand, or extraordinary stupidity on the other, appears in any senator;
  • but yet they would be sufficient to prevent intrigue and faction, by
  • making the disposal of the offices a thing of course. For instance, let
  • it be a resolution:—That no man shall enjoy any office till he has sat
  • four years in the senate; that, except ambassadors, no man shall be in
  • office two years following; that no man shall attain the higher offices
  • but through the lower; that no man shall be protector twice, etc. The
  • senate of Venice govern themselves by such resolutions.
  • In foreign politics the interest of the senate can scarce ever be
  • divided from that of the people, and therefore it is fit to make
  • the senate absolute with regard to them, otherwise there could be
  • no secrecy nor refined policy. Besides, without money no alliance
  • can be executed, and the senate is still sufficiently dependent. Not
  • to mention that the legislative power being always superior to the
  • executive, the magistrates or representatives may interpose, whenever
  • they think proper.
  • The chief support of the British Government is the Opposition of
  • interests; but that, though in the main serviceable, breeds endless
  • factions. In the foregoing plan, it does all the good without any of
  • the harm. The competitors have no power of controlling the senate; they
  • have only the power of accusing and appealing to the people.
  • It is necessary, likewise, to prevent both combination and division in
  • the thousand magistrates. This is done sufficiently by the separation
  • of places and interests.
  • But lest that should not be enough, their dependence on the 10,000 for
  • their elections serves to the same purpose.
  • Nor is that all: for the 10,000 may resume the power whenever they
  • please; and not only when they all please, but when any five of a
  • hundred please, which will happen upon the very first suspicion of a
  • separate interest.
  • The 10,000 are too large a body either to unite or divide, except
  • when they meet in one place, and fall under the guidance of ambitious
  • leaders. Not to mention their annual election by the whole body of the
  • people that are of any consideration.
  • A small commonwealth is the happiest government in the world within
  • itself, because everything lies under the eye of the rulers; but it may
  • be subdued by great force from without. This scheme seems to have all
  • the advantages both of a great and a little commonwealth.
  • Every county-law may be annulled either by the senate or another
  • county, because that shows an opposition of interest: in which case no
  • part ought to decide for itself. The matter must be referred to the
  • whole, which will best determine what agrees with general interest.
  • As to the clergy and militia, the reasons of these orders are obvious.
  • Without the dependence of the clergy on the civil magistrates, and
  • without a militia, it is folly to think any free government will ever
  • have security or stability.
  • In many governments the inferior magistrates have no rewards but what
  • arise from their ambition, vanity, or public spirit. The salaries of
  • the French judges amount not to the interest of the sums they pay
  • for their offices. The Dutch burgomasters have little more immediate
  • profit than the English justices of peace, or the members of the
  • House of Commons formerly. But lest any should suspect that this
  • would beget negligence in the administration (which is little to be
  • feared, considering the natural ambition of mankind), let the
  • magistrates have competent salaries. The senators have access to so
  • many honourable and lucrative offices that their attendance needs not
  • be bought. There is little attendance required of the representatives.
  • That the foregoing plan of government is practicable no one can
  • doubt, who considers the resemblance it bears to the commonwealth of
  • the United Provinces, formerly one of the wisest and most renowned
  • governments in the world. The alterations in the present scheme are all
  • evidently to the better. 1. The representation is more equal. 2. The
  • unlimited power of the burgomasters in the towns, which forms a perfect
  • aristocracy in the Dutch commonwealth, is corrected by a well-tempered
  • democracy, in giving to the people the annual election of the county
  • representatives. 3. The negative, which every province and town has
  • upon the whole body of the Dutch republic, with regard to alliances,
  • peace and war, and the imposition of taxes, is here removed. 4. The
  • counties, in the present plan, are not so independent of each other,
  • nor do they form separate bodies so much as the seven provinces; where
  • the jealousy and envy of the smaller provinces and towns against the
  • greater, particularly Holland and Amsterdam, have frequently disturbed
  • the government. 5. Larger powers, though of the safest kind, are
  • entrusted to the senate than the States-General possess; by which means
  • the former may become more expeditious and secret in their resolutions
  • than it is possible for the latter.
  • The chief alterations that could be made on the British Government, in
  • order to bring it to the most perfect model of living monarchy, seem to
  • be the following:—First, The plan of the Republican Parliament ought
  • to be restored, by making the representation equal, and by allowing
  • none to vote in the county elections who possess not a property of 200
  • pounds value. Secondly, As such a House of Commons would be too weighty
  • for a frail House of Lords like the present, the bishops and Scots
  • peers ought to be removed, whose behaviour, in former Parliaments,
  • destroyed entirely the authority of that House. The number of the
  • Upper House ought to be raised to three or four hundred; their
  • seats not hereditary, but during life. They ought to have the election
  • of their own members; and no commoner should be allowed to refuse a
  • seat that was offered him. By this means the House of Lords would
  • consist entirely of the men of chief credit, ability, and interest
  • of the nation; and every turbulent leader in the House of Commons
  • might be taken off and connected in interest with the House of Peers.
  • Such an aristocracy would be a splendid barrier both to the monarchy
  • and against it. At present the balance of our Government depends in
  • some measure on the ability and behaviour of the sovereign, which are
  • variable and uncertain circumstances.
  • I allow that this plan of limited monarchy, however corrected, is still
  • liable to three great inconveniences. First, it removes not entirely,
  • though it may soften, the parties of court and country; secondly, the
  • king’s personal character must still have a great influence on the
  • Government; thirdly, the sword is in the hands of a single person,
  • who will always neglect to discipline the militia, in order to have a
  • pretence for keeping up a standing army. It is evident that this is
  • a mortal distemper in British Government, of which it must at last
  • inevitably perish. I must, however, confess that Sweden seems in some
  • measure to have remedied this inconvenience, and to have a militia,
  • with its limited monarchy, as well as a standing army, which is less
  • dangerous than the British.
  • We shall conclude this subject with observing the falsehood of the
  • common opinion that no large state, such as France or Britain,
  • could ever be modelled into a commonwealth, but that such a form
  • of government can only take place in a city or small territory.
  • The contrary seems evident. Though it is more difficult to form a
  • republican government in an extensive country than in a city, there
  • is more facility, when once it is formed, of preserving it steady and
  • uniform, without tumult and faction. It is not easy for the distant
  • parts of a large state to combine in any plan of free government; but
  • they easily conspire in the esteem and reverence of a single
  • person, who, by means of this popular favour, may seize the power,
  • and forcing the more obstinate to submit, may establish a monarchical
  • government. On the other hand, a city readily concurs in the same
  • notions of government, the natural equality of property favours
  • liberty, and the nearness of habitation enables the citizens mutually
  • to assist each other. Even under absolute princes the subordinate
  • government of cities is commonly republican; while that of counties
  • and provinces is monarchical. But these same circumstances, which
  • facilitate the erection of commonwealths in cities, render their
  • constitution more frail and uncertain. Democracies are turbulent. For
  • however the people may be separated or divided into small parties,
  • either in their votes or elections, their near habitation in a
  • city will always make the force of popular tides and currents very
  • sensible. Aristocracies are better adapted for peace and order, and
  • accordingly were most admired by ancient writers; but they are jealous
  • and oppressive. In a large government, which is modelled with masterly
  • skill, there is compass and room enough to refine the democracy from
  • the lower people, who may be admitted into the first elections or first
  • concoction of the commonwealth to the higher magistrates who direct all
  • the movements. At the same time, the parts are so distant and remote
  • that it is very difficult, either by intrigue, prejudice, or passion,
  • to hurry them into any measures against the public interest.
  • It is needless to inquire whether such a government would be immortal.
  • I allow the justness of the poet’s exclamation on the endless projects
  • of human race, “Man and for ever!” The world itself probably is not
  • immortal. Such consuming plagues may arise as would leave even a
  • perfect government a weak prey to its neighbours. We know not to what
  • lengths enthusiasm or other extraordinary motions of the human mind
  • may transport men, to the neglect of all order and public good. Where
  • difference of interest is removed, whimsical and unaccountable factions
  • often arise from personal favour or enmity. Perhaps rust may grow to
  • the springs of the most accurate political machine and disorder
  • its motions. Lastly, extensive conquests, when pursued, must be the
  • ruin of every free government; and of the more perfect governments
  • sooner than of the imperfect, because of the very advantages which
  • the former possess above the latter. And though such a state ought
  • to establish a fundamental law against conquests, yet republics have
  • ambition as well as individuals, and present interest makes men
  • forgetful of their posterity. It is a sufficient incitement to human
  • endeavours that such a government would flourish for many ages, without
  • pretending to bestow on any work of man that immortality which the
  • Almighty seems to have refused to his own productions.
  • THAT POLITICS MAY BE REDUCED TO A SCIENCE.
  • It is a question with many whether there be any essential difference
  • between one form of government and another? and whether every
  • form may not become good or bad according as it is well or ill
  • administered?​[113] Were it once admitted that all governments are
  • alike, and that the only difference consists in the character and
  • conduct of the governors, most political disputes would be at an end,
  • and all zeal for one constitution above another must be esteemed mere
  • bigotry and folly. But, though a friend to moderation, I cannot forbear
  • condemning this sentiment, and should be sorry to think that human
  • affairs admit of no greater stability than what they receive from the
  • casual humours and characters of particular men.
  • It is true, those who maintain that the goodness of all government
  • consists in the goodness of the administration, may cite many
  • particular instances in history where the very same government in
  • different hands has varied suddenly into the two opposite extremes of
  • good and bad. Compare the French Government under Henry III. and under
  • Henry IV. Oppression, levity, artifice on the part of the rulers;
  • faction, sedition, treachery, rebellion, disloyalty on the part of the
  • subjects: these compose the character of the former miserable era.
  • But when the patriot and heroic prince who succeeded was once firmly
  • seated on the throne, the government, the people, everything seemed
  • to be totally changed; and all from the difference of the temper and
  • sentiments of these two sovereigns. An equal difference of a contrary
  • kind may be found on comparing the reigns of Elizabeth and James—at
  • least with regard to foreign affairs; and instances of this kind may be
  • multiplied almost without number from ancient as well as modern history.
  • But here I would beg leave to make a distinction. All absolute
  • governments (and such, in a great measure, was that of England till the
  • middle of the last century, notwithstanding the numerous panegyrics on
  • ancient English liberty) must very much depend on the administration;
  • and this is one of the great inconveniences of that form of government.
  • But a republican and free government would be a most obvious absurdity
  • if the particular checks and controls provided by the constitution
  • had really no influence, and made it not the interest, even of bad
  • men, to operate for the public good. Such is the intention of these
  • forms of government, and such is their real effect where they are
  • wisely constituted: as, on the other hand, they are the sources of all
  • disorder and of the blackest crimes where either skill or honesty has
  • been wanting in their original frame and institution.
  • So great is the force of laws and of particular forms of government,
  • and so little dependence have they on the humours and tempers of men,
  • that consequences almost as general and certain may be deduced from
  • them on most occasions as any which the mathematical sciences
  • afford us.
  • The Roman government gave the whole legislative power to the commons,
  • without allowing a negative either to the nobility or consuls. This
  • unbounded power the commons possessed in a collective, not in a
  • representative body. The consequences were—when the people, by success
  • and conquest, had become very numerous and had spread themselves to
  • a great distance from the capital, the city tribes, though the most
  • contemptible, carried almost every vote. They were, therefore, most
  • cajoled by every one who affected popularity; they were supported
  • in idleness by the general distribution of corn, and by particular
  • bribes, which they received from almost every candidate. By this means
  • they became every day more licentious, and the Campus Martius was a
  • perpetual scene of tumult and sedition: armed slaves were introduced
  • among these rascally citizens, so that the whole government fell into
  • anarchy, and the greatest happiness which the Romans could look for was
  • the despotic power of the Cæsars. Such are the effects of democracy
  • without a representative.
  • A nobility may possess the whole or any part of the legislative power
  • of a state in two different ways. Either every nobleman shares the
  • power as part of the whole body, or the whole body enjoys the power as
  • composed of parts which have each a distinct power and authority. The
  • Venetian aristocracy is an instance of the first kind of government;
  • the Polish of the second. In the Venetian government the whole body of
  • nobility possesses the whole power, and no nobleman has any authority
  • which he receives not from the whole. In the Polish government every
  • nobleman, by means of his fiefs, has a peculiar hereditary authority
  • over his vassals, and the whole body has no authority but what it
  • receives from the concurrence of its parts. The distinct operations
  • and tendencies of these two species of government might be made most
  • apparent even _à priori_. A Venetian nobility is infinitely preferable
  • to a Polish, let the humours and education of men be ever so
  • much varied. A nobility who possess their power in common will preserve
  • peace and order both among themselves and their subjects, and no member
  • can have authority enough to control the laws for a moment. The nobles
  • will preserve their authority over the people, but without any grievous
  • tyranny or any breach of private property, because such a tyrannical
  • government promotes not the interest of the whole body, however it
  • may that of some individuals. There will be a distinction of rank
  • between the nobility and people, but this will be the only distinction
  • in the state. The whole nobility will form one body, and the whole
  • people another, without any of those private feuds and animosities
  • which spread ruin and desolation everywhere. It is easy to see the
  • disadvantages of a Polish nobility in every one of these particulars.
  • It is possible so to constitute a free government as that a single
  • person—call him doge, prince, or king—shall possess a very large share
  • of power, and shall form a proper balance or counterpoise to the other
  • parts of the legislature. This chief magistrate may be either elective
  • or hereditary, and though the former institution may, to a superficial
  • view, appear the most advantageous, yet a more accurate inspection will
  • discover in it greater inconveniences than in the latter, and such as
  • are founded on causes and principles eternal and immutable. The filling
  • of the throne in such a government is a point of too great and too
  • general interest not to divide the whole people into factions, from
  • whence a civil war, the greatest of ills, may be apprehended almost
  • with certainty upon every vacancy. The prince elected must be either a
  • foreigner or a native; the former will be ignorant of the people whom
  • he is to govern, suspicious of his new subjects and suspected by them,
  • giving his confidence entirely to strangers, who will have no other
  • care but of enriching themselves in the quickest manner, while their
  • master’s favour and authority are able to support them. A native will
  • carry into the throne all his private animosities and friendships,
  • and will never be regarded, in his elevation, without exciting the
  • sentiments of envy in those who formerly considered him as
  • their equal. Not to mention that a crown is too high a reward ever
  • to be given to merit alone, and will always induce the candidates
  • to employ force, or money, or intrigue to procure the votes of the
  • electors; so that such an election will give no better chance for
  • superior merit in the prince than if the state had trusted to birth
  • alone for determining their sovereign.
  • It may therefore be pronounced as a universal axiom in politics that
  • a hereditary prince, a nobility without vassals, and a people voting
  • by their representatives form the best monarchy, aristocracy, and
  • democracy. But in order to prove more fully that politics admit of
  • general truths which are invariable by the humour or education either
  • of subject or sovereign, it may not be amiss to observe some other
  • principles of this science which may seem to deserve that character.
  • It may easily be observed that though free governments have been
  • commonly the most happy for those who partake of their freedom, yet
  • are they the most ruinous and oppressive to their provinces; and this
  • observation may, I believe, be fixed as a maxim of the kind we are
  • here speaking of. When a monarch extends his dominions by conquest he
  • soon learns to consider his old and his new subjects as on the same
  • footing, because, in reality, all his subjects are to him the same,
  • except the few friends and favourites with whom he is personally
  • acquainted. He does not, therefore, make any distinction between them
  • in his general laws, and at the same time is no less careful to prevent
  • all particular acts of oppression on the one as on the other. But a
  • free state necessarily makes a great distinction, and must always do
  • so, till men learn to love their neighbours as well as themselves. The
  • conquerors, in such a government, are all legislators, and will be sure
  • so to contrive matters, by restrictions of trade and by taxes, as to
  • draw some private, as well as public advantage from their conquests.
  • Provincial governors have also a better chance in a republic to
  • escape with their plunder by means of bribery and interest; and their
  • fellow-citizens, who find their own state to be enriched by
  • the spoils of the subject-provinces, will be the more inclined to
  • tolerate such abuses. Not to mention that it is a necessary precaution
  • in a free state to change the governors frequently, which obliges
  • these temporary tyrants to be more expeditious and rapacious, that
  • they may accumulate sufficient wealth before they give place to their
  • successors. What cruel tyrants were the Romans over the world during
  • the time of their commonwealth! It is true they had laws to prevent
  • oppression in their provincial magistrates, but Cicero informs us that
  • the Romans could not better consult the interest of the provinces
  • than by repealing these very laws. “For in that case,” says he, “our
  • magistrates, having entire impunity, would plunder no more than would
  • satisfy their own rapaciousness; whereas at present they must also
  • satisfy that of their judges, and of all the great men of Rome whose
  • protection they stand in need of.” Who can read of the cruelties and
  • oppressions of Verres without horror and astonishment? And who is not
  • touched with indignation to hear that after Cicero had exhausted on
  • that abandoned criminal all the thunders of his eloquence, and had
  • prevailed so far as to get him condemned to the utmost extent of the
  • laws, yet that cruel tyrant lived peaceably to old age in opulence
  • and ease, and thirty years afterwards was put into the proscription
  • by Mark Anthony on account of his exorbitant wealth, where he fell,
  • with Cicero himself, and all the most virtuous men of Rome? After the
  • dissolution of the commonwealth the Roman yoke became easier upon the
  • provinces, as Tacitus informs us; and it may be observed that many of
  • the worst emperors—Domitian, for instance—were very careful to prevent
  • all oppression of the provinces. In Tiberius’s time Gaul was esteemed
  • richer than Italy itself; nor do I find during the whole time of the
  • Roman monarchy that the empire became less rich or populous in any
  • of its provinces, though indeed its valour and military discipline
  • were always upon the decline. The oppression and tyranny of the
  • Carthaginians over their subject-states in Africa went so far, as we
  • learn from Polybius, that, not content with exacting the half
  • of all the produce of the ground, which of itself was a very high rent,
  • they also loaded them with many other taxes. If we pass from ancient
  • to modern times, we shall always find the observation to hold. The
  • provinces of absolute monarchies are always better treated than those
  • of free states. Compare the _Païs conquis_ of France with Ireland, and
  • you will be convinced of this truth; though this latter kingdom, being
  • in a good measure peopled from England, possesses so many rights and
  • privileges as should naturally make it challenge better treatment than
  • that of a conquered province. Corsica is also an obvious instance to
  • the same purpose.
  • There is an observation of Machiavel, with regard to the conquests of
  • Alexander the Great, which I think may be regarded as one of those
  • eternal political truths which no time nor accidents can vary. It may
  • seem strange, says that politician, that such sudden conquests as
  • those of Alexander should be settled so peaceably by his successors,
  • and that the Persians, during all the confusions and civil wars of
  • the Greeks, never made the smallest effort towards the recovery of
  • their former independent government. To satisfy us concerning the
  • cause of this remarkable event, we may consider that a monarch may
  • govern his subjects in two different ways. He may either follow the
  • maxims of the eastern princes, and stretch his power so far as to
  • leave no distinction of ranks among his subjects, but what proceeds
  • immediately from himself—no advantages of birth; no hereditary honours
  • and possessions; and, in a word, no credit among the people except from
  • his commission alone. Or a monarch may exert his power after a milder
  • manner, like our European princes, and leave other sources of honour,
  • beside his smile and favour: birth, titles, possessions, valour,
  • integrity, knowledge, or great and fortunate achievements. In the
  • former species of government, after a conquest, it is impossible ever
  • to shake off the yoke, since no one possesses among the people so much
  • personal credit and authority as to begin such an enterprise; whereas,
  • in the latter, the least misfortune or discord of the victors
  • will encourage the vanquished to take arms, who have leaders ready to
  • prompt and conduct them in every undertaking.​[114]
  • Such is the reasoning of Machiavel, which seems to me very solid and
  • conclusive, though I wish he had not mixed falsehood with truth in
  • asserting that monarchies governed according to the Eastern policy,
  • though more easily kept when once subdued, yet are the most difficult
  • to subdue, since they cannot contain any powerful subject whose
  • discontent and faction may facilitate the enterprises of an enemy. For
  • besides that such a tyrannical government enervates the courage of men
  • and renders them indifferent towards the fortunes of their sovereign;
  • besides this, I say, we find by experience that even the temporary and
  • delegated authority of the generals and magistrates being always, in
  • such governments, as absolute within its sphere as that of the prince
  • himself, is able, with barbarians accustomed to a blind submission, to
  • produce the most dangerous and fatal revolutions. So that, in every
  • respect, a gentle government is preferable, and gives the greatest
  • security to the sovereign as well as to the subject.
  • Legislators, therefore, ought not to trust the future government of
  • a state entirely to chance, but ought to provide a system of laws to
  • regulate the administration of public affairs to the latest posterity.
  • Effects will always correspond to causes, and wise regulations in any
  • commonwealth are the most valuable legacy which can be left to future
  • ages. In the smallest court or office the stated forms and methods
  • by which business must be conducted are found to be a considerable
  • check on the natural depravity of mankind. Why should not the case be
  • the same in public affairs? Can we ascribe the stability and wisdom
  • of the Venetian Government through so many ages to anything but the
  • form of government? And is it not easy to point out those defects in
  • the original constitution which produced the tumultuous governments
  • of Athens and Rome, and ended at last in the ruin of these two famous
  • republics? And so little dependence has this affair on the humours and
  • education of particular men that one part of the same republic may be
  • wisely conducted and another weakly, by the very same men, merely on
  • account of the difference of the forms and institutions by
  • which these parts are regulated. Historians inform us that this was
  • actually the case with Genoa; for while the state was always full of
  • sedition, and tumult, and disorder, the bank of St. George, which had
  • become a considerable part of the people, was conducted for several
  • ages with the utmost integrity and wisdom.
  • The ages of greatest public spirit are not always most eminent for
  • private virtue. Good laws may beget order and moderation in the
  • government where the manners and customs have instilled little humanity
  • or justice into the tempers of men. The most illustrious period of
  • the Roman history, considered in a political view, is that between
  • the beginning of the first and the end of the last Punic War; the
  • due balance between the nobility and people being then fixed by the
  • contests of the tribunes, and not being yet lost by the extent of
  • conquests. Yet at this very time the horrid practice of poisoning was
  • so common that, during part of the season, a prætor punished capitally
  • for this crime above three thousand persons in a part of Italy, and
  • found informations of this nature still multiplying upon him. There is
  • a similar, or rather a worse instance in the more early times of the
  • commonwealth; so depraved in private life were that people, whom in
  • their histories we so much admire. I doubt not but they were really
  • more virtuous during the time of the two Triumvirates, when they were
  • tearing their common country to pieces, and spreading slaughter and
  • desolation over the face of the earth merely for the choice of tyrants.
  • Here, then, is a sufficient inducement to maintain, with the utmost
  • zeal, in every free state, those forms and institutions by which
  • liberty is secured, the public good consulted, and the avarice or
  • ambition of particular men restrained and punished. Nothing does
  • more honour to human nature than to see it susceptible of so noble
  • a passion, as nothing can be a greater indication of meanness of
  • heart in any man than to see him devoid of it. A man who loves only
  • himself, without regard to friendship and merit, is a detestable
  • monster; and a man who is only susceptible of friendship, without
  • public spirit or a regard to the community, is deficient in the most
  • material part of virtue.
  • But this is a subject which needs not be longer insisted on at present.
  • There are enough of zealots on both sides who kindle up the passions
  • of their partisans, and under the pretence of public good pursue the
  • interests and ends of their particular faction. For my part I shall
  • always be more fond of promoting moderation than zeal, though perhaps
  • the surest way of producing moderation in every party is to increase
  • our zeal for the public. Let us therefore try, if it be possible, from
  • the foregoing doctrine to draw a lesson of moderation with regard to
  • the parties into which our country is at present divided; at the same
  • time, that we allow not this moderation to abate the industry and
  • passion with which every individual is bound to pursue the good of his
  • country.
  • Those who either attack or defend a minister in such a government as
  • ours, where the utmost liberty is allowed, always carry matters to an
  • extreme, and exaggerate his merit or demerit with regard to the public.
  • His enemies are sure to charge him with the greatest enormities, both
  • in domestic and foreign management, and there is no meanness or crime
  • of which, in their account, he is not capable. Unnecessary wars,
  • scandalous treaties, profusion of public treasure, oppressive taxes,
  • every kind of mal-administration is ascribed to him. To aggravate the
  • charge, his pernicious conduct, it is said, will extend its baleful
  • influence even to posterity, by undermining the best constitution in
  • the world, and disordering that wise system of laws, institutions,
  • and customs by which our ancestors for so many centuries have been so
  • happily governed. He is not only a wicked minister in himself, but has
  • removed every security provided against wicked ministers for the future.
  • On the other hand, the partisans of the minister make his panegyric run
  • as high as the accusation against him, and celebrate his wise, steady,
  • and moderate conduct in every part of his administration. The honour
  • and interest of the nation supported abroad, public credit
  • maintained at home, persecution restrained, faction subdued: the merit
  • of all these blessings is ascribed solely to the minister. At the same
  • time he crowns all his other merits by a religious care of the best
  • constitution in the world, which he has preserved in all its parts, and
  • has transmitted entire to be the happiness and security of the latest
  • posterity.
  • When this accusation and panegyric are received by the partisans of
  • each party, no wonder they beget a most extraordinary ferment on
  • both sides, and fill the nation with the most violent animosities.
  • But I would fain persuade these party-zealots that there is a flat
  • contradiction both in the accusation and panegyric, and that it were
  • impossible for either of them to run so high were it not for this
  • contradiction. If our constitution be really that noble fabric, the
  • pride of Britain, the envy of our neighbours, raised by the labour of
  • so many centuries, repaired at the expense of so many millions, and
  • cemented by such a profusion of blood—I say, if our constitution does
  • in any degree deserve these eulogies, it would never have suffered
  • a wicked and weak minister to govern triumphantly for a course of
  • twenty years, when opposed by the greatest geniuses of the nation,
  • who exercised the utmost liberty of tongue and pen, in Parliament
  • and in their frequent appeals to the people. But if the minister
  • be wicked and weak to the degree so strenuously insisted on, the
  • constitution must be faulty in its original principles, and he cannot
  • consistently be charged with undermining the best constitution in the
  • world. A constitution is only so far good as it provides a remedy
  • against mal-administration, and if the British constitution, when in
  • its greatest vigour, and repaired by two such remarkable events as
  • the Revolution and Accession, by which our ancient royal family was
  • sacrificed to it—if our constitution, I say, with so great advantages
  • does not, in fact, provide any such remedy, we are rather beholden
  • to any minister who undermines it and affords us an opportunity of
  • erecting in its place a better constitution.
  • I would make use of the same topics to moderate the zeal of
  • those who defend the minister. Is our constitution so excellent? Then a
  • change of ministry can be no such dreadful event, since it is essential
  • to such a constitution, in every ministry, both to preserve itself
  • from violation and to prevent all enormities in the administration.
  • Is our constitution very bad? Then so extraordinary a jealousy and
  • apprehension on account of changes is ill-placed, and a man should no
  • more be anxious in this case than a husband, who had married a wife
  • from the stews, should be watchful to prevent her infidelity. Public
  • affairs in such a constitution must necessarily go to confusion,
  • by whatever hands they are conducted, and the zeal of patriots is
  • much less requisite in that case than the patience and submission of
  • philosophers. The virtue and good intentions of Cato and Brutus are
  • highly laudable, but to what purpose did their zeal serve? To nothing
  • but to hasten the fatal period of the Roman government, and render its
  • convulsions and dying agonies more violent and painful.
  • I would not be understood to mean that public affairs deserve no care
  • and attention at all. Would men be moderate and consistent, their
  • claims might be admitted—at least might be examined. The country-party
  • might still assert that our constitution, though excellent, will admit
  • of mal-administration to a certain degree, and therefore, if the
  • minister be bad, it is proper to oppose him with a suitable degree of
  • zeal. And, on the other hand, the court-party may be allowed, upon the
  • supposition that the minister were good, to defend, and with some zeal
  • too, his administration. I would only persuade men not to contend,
  • as if they were fighting _pro aris et focis_, and change a good
  • constitution into a bad one by the violence of their factions.​[115]
  • I have not here considered anything that is personal in the present
  • controversy. In the best civil constitution, where every man is
  • restrained by the most rigid laws, it is easy to discover either the
  • good or bad intentions of a minister, and to judge whether his personal
  • character deserves love or hatred. But such questions are of little
  • importance to the public, and lay those who employ their pens upon them
  • under a just suspicion either of malevolence or flattery.
  • NOTES, POLITICS REDUCED TO A SCIENCE.
  • [113]
  • “For forms of government let fools contest;
  • Whate’er is best administer’d is best.”
  • _Essay on Man_, Book iii.
  • [114] I have taken it for granted, according to the supposition of
  • Machiavel, that the ancient Persians had no nobility, though there is
  • reason to suspect that the Florentine secretary, who seems to have
  • been better acquainted with the Roman than the Greek authors, was
  • mistaken in this particular. The more ancient Persians, whose manners
  • are described by Xenophon, were a free people, and had nobility. Their
  • ὁμοτιμοι were preserved even after the extending of their conquests
  • and the consequent change of their government. Arrian mentions them in
  • Darius’s time (_De exped. Alex._, lib. 2). Historians also speak often
  • of the persons in command as men of family. Tygranes, who was general
  • of the Medes under Xerxes, was of the race of Achmænes (Herod., lib.
  • 7, cap. 62). Artachæas, who directed the cutting of the canal about
  • Mount Athos, was of the same family (_id._, cap. 117). Megabyzus was
  • one of the seven eminent Persians who conspired against the Magi. His
  • son Zopyrus was in the highest command under Darius, and delivered
  • Babylon to him. His grandson Megabyzus commanded the army defeated at
  • Marathon. His great grandson Zopyrus was also eminent, and was banished
  • Persia (Herod., lib. 3; Thuc., lib. 1). Rosaces, who commanded an army
  • in Egypt under Artaxerxes, was also descended from one of the seven
  • conspirators (Diod. Sic., lib. 16). Agesilaus (in Xenophon, _Hist.
  • Græc._ lib. 4), being desirous of making a marriage betwixt King Cotys,
  • his ally, and the daughter of Spithridates, a Persian of rank who had
  • deserted to him, first asks Cotys what rank Spithridates is of. One of
  • the most considerable in Persia, says Cotys. Ariæus, when offered the
  • sovereignty by Clearchus and the ten thousand Greeks, refused it as
  • of too low a rank, and said that so many eminent Persians would never
  • endure his rule (_id._, _De exped._ lib. 2). Some of the families,
  • descended from the seven Persians above mentioned, remained during
  • all Alexander’s successors; and Mithridates, in Antiochus’s time, is
  • said by Polybius to be descended from one of them (lib. 5, cap. 43).
  • Artabazus was esteemed, as Arrian says, εν τοις πρωτοις Περσων (lib.
  • 3). And when Alexander married in one day eighty of his captains to
  • Persian women, his intention plainly was to ally the Macedonians with
  • the most eminent Persian families (_id._, lib. 7). Diodorus Siculus
  • says they were of the most noble birth in Persia (lib. 17). The
  • government of Persia was despotic, and conducted in many respects after
  • the Eastern manner, but was not carried so far as to extirpate all
  • nobility, and confound all ranks and orders. It left men who were still
  • great, by themselves and their family, independent of their office and
  • commission. And the reason why the Macedonians kept so easily dominion
  • over them was owing to other causes easy to be found in the historians,
  • though it must be owned that Machiavel’s reasoning was in itself just,
  • however doubtful its application to the present case.
  • [115] What our author’s opinion was of the famous minister here pointed
  • at may be learned from that essay, printed in the former editions,
  • under the title of “A Character of Sir Robert Walpole.” It was as
  • follows:—“There never was a man whose actions and character have been
  • more earnestly and openly canvassed than those of the present minister,
  • who, having governed a learned and free nation for so long a time,
  • amidst such mighty opposition, may make a large library of what has
  • been written for and against him, and is the subject of above half the
  • paper that has been blotted in the nation within these twenty years.
  • I wish, for the honour of our country, that any one character of him
  • had been drawn with such judgment and impartiality as to have credit
  • with posterity, and to show that our liberty has, once at least, been
  • employed to good purpose. I am only afraid of failing in the former
  • quality of judgment; but if it should be so, it is but one page more
  • thrown away, after a hundred thousand, upon the same subject, that have
  • perished and become useless. In the meantime, I shall flatter myself
  • with the pleasing imagination that the following character will be
  • adopted by future historians:—
  • “Sir Robert Walpole, Prime Minister of Great Britain, is a man of
  • ability, not a genius; good-natured, not virtuous; constant, not
  • magnanimous; moderate, not equitable.​[116] His virtues, in some
  • instances, are free from the alloy of those vices which usually
  • accompany such virtues. He is a generous friend, without being a bitter
  • enemy. His vices, in other instances, are not compensated by those
  • virtues which are nearly allied to them: his want of enterprise is not
  • attended with frugality. The private character of the man is better
  • than the public, his virtues more than his vices, his fortune greater
  • than his fame. With many good qualities he has incurred the public
  • hatred; with good capacity he has not escaped ridicule. He would have
  • been esteemed more worthy of his high station had he never possessed
  • it; and is better qualified for the second than for the first place in
  • any Government. His ministry has been more advantageous to his family
  • than to the public, better for this age than for posterity, and more
  • pernicious by bad precedents than by real grievances. During his time
  • trade has flourished, liberty declined, and learning gone to ruin. As I
  • am a man, I love him; as I am a scholar, I hate him; as I am a Briton,
  • I calmly wish his fall. And were I a member of either House I would
  • give my vote for removing him from St. James’s, but should be glad to
  • see him retire to Houghton Hall, to pass the remainder of his days in
  • ease and pleasure.”
  • The author is pleased to find that after animosities are laid, and
  • calumny has ceased, the whole nation almost have returned to the
  • same moderate sentiments with regard to this great man, if they
  • are not rather become more favourable to him, by a very natural
  • transition from one extreme to another. The author would not oppose
  • those humane sentiments towards the dead, though he cannot forbear
  • observing that the not paying more of our public debts was, as hinted
  • in this character, a great, and the only great error in that long
  • administration.
  • [116] Moderate in the exercise of power, not equitable in engrossing it.
  • OF THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF GOVERNMENT.
  • Nothing is more surprising to those who consider human affairs with
  • a philosophical eye, than to see the easiness with which the many
  • are governed by the few; and to observe the implicit submission with
  • which men resign their own sentiments and passions to those of their
  • rulers. When we inquire by what means this wonder is brought about, we
  • shall find that, as force is always on the side of the governed, the
  • governors have nothing to support them but opinion. It is therefore
  • on opinion only that government is founded, and this maxim extends
  • to the most despotic and most military governments, as well as to
  • the most free and most popular. The Soldan of Egypt, or the Emperor
  • of Rome, might drive his harmless subjects like brute beasts against
  • their sentiments and inclination; but he must, at least, have led his
  • mamalukes, or prætorian bands, like men, by their opinion.
  • Opinion is of two kinds—viz., opinion of interest and opinion of
  • right. By opinion of interest, I chiefly understand the sense of the
  • public advantage which is reaped from government, together with the
  • persuasion that the particular government which is established is
  • equally advantageous with any other that could easily be settled. When
  • this opinion prevails among the generality of a state, or among
  • those who have the force in their hands, it gives great security to any
  • government.
  • Right is of two kinds—right to power and right to property. What
  • prevalence opinion of the first kind has over mankind may easily be
  • understood by observing the attachment which all nations have to
  • their ancient government, and even to those names which have had the
  • sanction of antiquity. Antiquity always begets the opinion of right,
  • and whatever disadvantageous sentiments we may entertain of mankind,
  • they are always found to be prodigal both of blood and treasure in
  • the maintenance of public justice. This passion we may denominate
  • enthusiasm, or we may give it what appellation we please; but a
  • politician who should overlook its influence on human affairs would
  • prove himself but of a very limited understanding. There is, indeed,
  • no particular in which at first sight there may appear a greater
  • contradiction in the frame of the human mind than the present. When men
  • act in a faction they are apt, without any shame or remorse, to neglect
  • all the ties of honour and morality in order to serve their party;
  • and yet when a faction is formed upon a point of right or principle,
  • there is no occasion where men discover a greater obstinacy and a more
  • determined sense of justice and equity. The same social disposition of
  • mankind is the cause of both these contradictory appearances.
  • It is sufficiently understood that the opinion of right to property is
  • of the greatest moment in all matters of government. A noted author
  • has made property the foundation of all government; and most of our
  • political writers seem inclined to follow him in that particular. This
  • is carrying the matter too far; but still it must be owned that the
  • opinion of right to property has a great influence in this subject.
  • Upon these three opinions, therefore, of public interest, of right to
  • power, and of right to property, are all governments founded, and all
  • authority of the few over the many. There are indeed other principles
  • which add force to these, and determine, limit, or alter their
  • operation; such as self-interest, fear, and affection. But
  • still we may assert that these other principles can have no influence
  • alone, but suppose the antecedent influence of those opinions above
  • mentioned. They are therefore to be esteemed the secondary, not the
  • original principles of government.
  • For, first, as to self-interest, by which I mean the expectation of
  • particular rewards, distinct from the general protection which we
  • receive from government, it is evident that the magistrate’s authority
  • must be antecedently established, or at least be hoped for, in order
  • to produce this expectation. The prospect of reward may augment the
  • authority with regard to some particular persons, but can never give
  • birth to it with regard to the public. Men naturally look for the
  • greatest favours from their friends and acquaintance, and therefore the
  • hopes of any considerable number of the state would never centre in any
  • particular set of men if these men had no other title to magistracy,
  • and had no separate influence over the opinions of mankind. The same
  • observation may be extended to the other two principles of fear and
  • affection. No man would have any reason to fear the fury of a tyrant
  • if he had no authority over any but from fear; since as a single man
  • his bodily force can reach but a small way, and all further power he
  • possesses must be founded either on our opinion or on the presumed
  • opinion of others. And though affection to wisdom and virtue in a
  • sovereign extends very far and has great influence, yet he must be
  • antecedently supposed invested with a public character, otherwise the
  • public esteem will serve him in no stead, nor will his virtue have any
  • influence beyond a narrow sphere.
  • A government may endure for several ages, though the balance of power
  • and the balance of property do not agree. This chiefly happens where
  • any rank or order of the state has acquired a large share of the
  • property, but from the original constitution of the government has no
  • share of the power. Under what pretext would any individual of that
  • order assume authority in public affairs? As men are commonly much
  • attached to their ancient government, it is not to be expected
  • that the public would ever favour such usurpations. But where the
  • original constitution allows any share of power, though small, to an
  • order of men who possess a large share of the property, it is easy for
  • them gradually to stretch their authority and bring the balance of
  • power to coincide with that of property. This has been the case with
  • the House of Commons in England.
  • Most writers who have treated of the British Government have supposed
  • that as the House of Commons represents all the commons of Great
  • Britain, so its weight in the scale is proportioned to the property
  • and power of all whom it represents. But this principle must not be
  • received as absolutely true. For though the people are apt to attach
  • themselves more to the House of Commons than to any other member of the
  • constitution—that House being chosen by them as their representatives
  • and as the public guardians of their liberty—yet are there instances
  • where the House, even when in opposition to the Crown, has not been
  • followed by the people; as we may particularly observe of the Tory
  • House of Commons in the reign of King William. Were the members of the
  • House obliged to receive instructions from their constituents, like the
  • Dutch deputies, this would entirely alter the case; and if such immense
  • power and riches as those of the whole commons of Britain were brought
  • into the scale, it is not easy to conceive that the Crown could either
  • influence the multitude of people or withstand that overbalance of
  • property. It is true the Crown has great influence over the collective
  • body of Britain in the elections of members; but were this influence,
  • which at present is only exerted once in seven years, to be employed in
  • bringing over the people to every vote, it would soon be wasted, and
  • no skill, popularity or revenue, could support it. I must, therefore,
  • be of opinion that an alteration in this particular would introduce a
  • total alteration in our government, and would soon reduce it to a pure
  • republic; and perhaps to a republic of no inconvenient form. For though
  • the people collected in a body like the Roman tribes be quite unfit for
  • government, yet when dispersed in small bodies they are more
  • susceptible both of reason and order; the force of popular currents
  • and tides is in a great measure broken; and the public interest may be
  • pursued with some method and constancy. But it is needless to reason
  • any further concerning a form of government which is never likely to
  • have place in Britain, and which seems not to be the aim of any party
  • amongst us. Let us cherish and improve our ancient government as much
  • as possible, without encouraging a passion for such dangerous novelties.
  • OF POLITICAL SOCIETY.
  • Had every man sufficient sagacity to perceive at all times the strong
  • interest which binds him to the observance of justice and equity, and
  • strength of mind sufficient to persevere in a steady adherence to a
  • general and a distant interest, in opposition to the allurements of
  • present pleasure and advantage—there had never, in that case, been any
  • such thing as government or political society, but each man following
  • his natural liberty had lived in entire peace and harmony with all
  • others. What need of positive laws where natural justice is, of itself,
  • a sufficient restraint? Why create magistrates where there never arises
  • any disorder or iniquity? Why abridge our native freedom when, in every
  • instance, the utmost exertion of it is found innocent and beneficial?
  • It is evident that if government were totally useless it never could
  • have place, and that the sole foundation of the duty of allegiance is
  • the advantage which it procures to society by preserving peace and
  • order among mankind.
  • When a number of political societies are erected, and maintain a
  • great intercourse together, a new set of rules are immediately
  • discovered to be useful in that particular situation, and
  • accordingly take place under the title of “Laws of Nations.” Of this
  • kind are the sacredness of the persons of ambassadors, abstaining from
  • poisoned arms, quarter in war, with others of that kind, which are
  • plainly calculated for the advantage of states and kingdoms in their
  • intercourse with each other.
  • The rules of justice, such as prevail among individuals, are not
  • entirely suspended among political societies. All princes pretend a
  • regard to the rights of others; and some, no doubt, without hypocrisy.
  • Alliances and treaties are every day made between independent states,
  • which would only be so much waste of parchment if they were not found,
  • by experience, to have some influence and authority. But here is the
  • difference between kingdoms and individuals. Human nature cannot by
  • any means subsist without the association of individuals; and that
  • association never could have place were no regard paid to the laws
  • of equity and justice. Disorder, confusion, the war of all against
  • all, are the necessary consequences of such a licentious conduct.
  • But nations can subsist without intercourse. They may even subsist,
  • in some degree, under a general war. The observance of justice,
  • though useful among them, is not guarded by so strong a necessity as
  • among individuals; and the moral obligation holds proportion with
  • the usefulness. All politicians will allow, and most philosophers,
  • that reasons of state may, in particular emergencies, dispense with
  • the rules of justice, and invalidate any treaty or alliance where
  • the strict observance of it would be prejudicial in a considerable
  • degree to either of the contracting parties. But nothing less than the
  • extremest necessity, it is confessed, can justify individuals in a
  • breach of promise, Or an invasion of the properties of others.
  • In a confederated commonwealth, such as the Achæan Republic of old, or
  • the Swiss Cantons and United Provinces in modern times; as the league
  • has here a peculiar utility, the conditions of union have a peculiar
  • sacredness and authority, and a violation of them would be equally
  • criminal, Or even more criminal than any private injury or injustice.
  • The long and helpless infancy of man requires the combination of
  • parents for the subsistence of their young, and that combination
  • requires the virtue of chastity or fidelity to the marriage-bed.
  • Without such a utility, it will readily be owned that such a virtue
  • would never have been thought of.
  • An infidelity of this nature is much more pernicious in women than in
  • men; hence the laws of chastity are much stricter over the one sex than
  • over the other.
  • These rules have all a reference to generation, and yet women past
  • child-bearing are no more supposed to be exempted from them than those
  • in the flower of their youth and beauty. General rules are often
  • extended beyond the principle whence they first arise, and this holds
  • in all matters of taste and sentiment. It is a vulgar story at Paris
  • that during the rage of the Mississippi a hump-backed fellow went
  • every day into the Rue de Quincempoix, where the stock-jobbers met in
  • great crowds, and was well paid for allowing them to make use of his
  • hump as a desk in order to sign their contracts upon it. Would the
  • fortune which he raised by this invention make him a handsome fellow,
  • though it be confessed that personal beauty arises very much from ideas
  • of utility? The imagination is influenced by association of ideas,
  • which, though they arise at first from the judgment, are not easily
  • altered by every particular exception that occurs to us. To which we
  • may add, in the present case of chastity, that the example of the old
  • would be pernicious to the young, and that women, continually thinking
  • that a certain time would bring them the liberty of indulgence, would
  • naturally advance that period and think more lightly of this whole duty
  • so requisite to society.
  • Those who live in the same family have such frequent opportunities of
  • licence of this kind that nothing could preserve purity of manners were
  • marriage allowed among the nearest relations, or were any intercourse
  • of love between them ratified by law and custom. Incest, therefore,
  • being pernicious in a superior degree, has also a superior turpitude
  • and moral deformity annexed to it.
  • What is the reason why, by the Athenian laws, one might marry a
  • half-sister by the father but not by the mother? Plainly this:—The
  • manners of the Athenians were so reserved that a man was never
  • permitted to approach the women’s apartment, even in the same family,
  • unless where he visited his own mother. His step-mother and her
  • children were as much shut up from him as the women of any other
  • family, and there was as little danger of any criminal correspondence
  • between them. Uncles and nieces, for a like reason, might marry at
  • Athens, but neither these nor half-brothers and sisters could contract
  • that alliance at Rome, where the intercourse was more open between the
  • sexes. Public utility is the cause of all these variations.
  • To repeat to a man’s prejudice anything that escaped him in private
  • conversation, or to make any such use of his private letters, is highly
  • blamed. The free and social intercourse of minds must be extremely
  • checked where no such rules of fidelity are established.
  • Even in repeating stories, whence we can see no ill consequences
  • to result, the giving one’s authors is regarded as a piece of
  • indiscretion, if not of immorality. These stories, in passing from hand
  • to hand and receiving all the usual variations, frequently come about
  • to the persons concerned and produce animosities and quarrels among
  • people whose intentions are the most innocent and inoffensive.
  • To pry into secrets, to open or even read the letters of others, to
  • play the spy upon their words and looks and actions—what habits more
  • inconvenient in society? what habits, of consequence, more blameable?
  • This principle is also the foundation of most of the laws of good
  • manners, a kind of lesser morality calculated for the ease of company
  • and conversation. Too much or too little ceremony are both blamed,
  • and everything which promotes ease without an indecent familiarity is
  • useful and laudable.
  • Constancy in friendships, attachments, and intimacies is
  • commonly very commendable, and is requisite to support trust and
  • good correspondence in society. But in places of general though
  • casual concourse, where the pursuit of health and pleasure brings
  • people promiscuously together, public conveniency has dispensed with
  • this maxim, and custom there promotes an unreserved conversation for
  • the time by indulging the privilege of dropping afterwards every
  • indifferent acquaintance without breach of civility or good manners.
  • Even in societies which are established on principles the most immoral
  • and the most destructive to the interests of the general society there
  • are required certain rules which a species of false honour as well as
  • private interest engages the members to observe. Robbers and pirates,
  • it has often been remarked, could not maintain their pernicious
  • confederacy did they not establish a new distributive justice among
  • themselves and recall those laws of equity which they have violated
  • with the rest of mankind.
  • “I hate a drinking companion,” says the Greek proverb, “who never
  • forgets.” The follies of the last debauch should be buried in eternal
  • oblivion, in order to give full scope to the follies of the next.
  • Among nations where an immoral gallantry, if covered with a thin veil
  • of mystery, is in some degree authorized by custom, there immediately
  • arise a set of rules calculated for the conveniency of that attachment.
  • The famous court or parliament of love in Provence decided formerly all
  • difficult cases of this nature.
  • In societies for play there are laws required for the conduct of the
  • game, and these laws are different in each game. The foundation, I own,
  • of such societies is frivolous, and the laws are in a great measure,
  • though not altogether, capricious and arbitrary. So far is there a
  • material difference between them and the rules of justice, fidelity and
  • loyalty. The general societies of men are absolutely requisite for the
  • subsistence of the species, and the public conveniency, which regulates
  • morals, is inviolably established in the nature of man and of the world
  • in which he lives. The comparison, therefore, in these respects
  • is very imperfect. We may only learn from it the necessity of rules
  • wherever men have any intercourse with each other.
  • They cannot even pass each other on the road without rules. Waggoners,
  • coachmen, and postilions have principles by which they give way, and
  • these are chiefly founded on mutual ease and convenience. Sometimes
  • also they are arbitrary, at least dependent on a kind of capricious
  • analogy, like many of the reasonings of lawyers.​[117]
  • To carry the matter further, we may observe that it is impossible for
  • men so much as to murder each other without statutes and maxims and
  • an idea of justice and honour. War has its laws as well as peace, and
  • even that sportive kind of war carried on among wrestlers, boxers,
  • cudgel-players, gladiators, is regulated by fixed principles. Common
  • interest and utility beget infallibly a standard of right and wrong
  • among the parties concerned.
  • NOTE, OF POLITICAL SOCIETY.
  • [117] That the lighter machine yields to the heavier, and in machines
  • of the same kind, that the empty yields to the loaded—this rule is
  • founded on convenience. That those who are going to the capital take
  • place of those who are coming from it—this seems to be founded on
  • some idea of the dignity of the great city, and of the preference of
  • the future to the past. From like reasons, among foot-walkers, the
  • right-hand entitles a man to the wall and prevents jostling, which
  • peaceable people find very disagreeable and inconvenient.
  • ALPHABETICAL ARRANGEMENT OF AUTHORITIES CITED BY HUME.
  • ÆMILIUS, PAULUS, Roman general, B.C. 230–157. Defeated Perseus of
  • Macedonia.
  • AGATHOCLES, tyrant of Syracuse, born _circa_ B.C. 361, died 289.
  • ALCIBIADES, Athenian general and statesman, born B.C. 450, died B.C.
  • 404. A disciple of Socrates, and noted for dissoluteness.
  • ALEXANDER the Great, born B.C. 356, died 323.
  • ANACHARSIS, Scythian philosopher, B.C. 600. Much esteemed by Solon.
  • ANTHONY, MARK, Triumvir, born _circa_ B.C. 85, died B.C. 30. Best
  • known through his association with Cleopatra.
  • ANTIGONUS, one of the greatest generals of Alexander the Great. Slain
  • in 301 at Ipsus.
  • ANTIPATER, minister of Philip of Macedon and Alexander the Great, died
  • B.C. 319.
  • APPIANUS (Appian), belonged to the time of Trajan, and wrote the
  • history of Rome in Greek.
  • ARATUS, general of the Achæan League, born B.C. 271, died 213.
  • ARBUTHNOT, JOHN, physician, born 1675, died 1735. Associate of Pope
  • and Swift, and wrote on ancient measures, weights, and coins.
  • ARISTOTLE, philosopher, the Stagirite, born B.C. 384, died 332. Tutor
  • of Alexander the Great.
  • ARRIANUS, Greek historian, resided at Rome in the second century, a
  • disciple of Epictetus, died _circa_ A.D. 160.
  • ATHENÆUS, grammarian, born in Egypt in the third century.
  • ATTALUS, King of Pergamus, died B.C. 197.
  • AUGUSTUS, first Roman Emperor, born B.C. 63, grandnephew of Julius
  • Cæsar, died A.D. 14.
  • CÆSAR, CAIUS JULIUS, B.C. 100–44, Roman warrior and administrator,
  • known to every schoolboy from his _Commentaries_.
  • CAMILLUS, MARCUS FURIUS, died B.C. 365, Roman warrior, six times
  • military tribune and five times dictator.
  • CARACALLA, brother of Geta, whom he murdered A.D. 212.
  • CATALINA, LUCIUS SERGIUS (Catiline), died B.C. 62, noted for his
  • depraved habits and his conspiracy that drew from Cicero his famous
  • orations.
  • CATO, MARCUS PORCIUS, surnamed from Utica, his birthplace, Uticensis,
  • died B.C. 46.
  • CATO, the elder, born B.C. 234, died 149, noted for his courage and
  • temperance.
  • CICERO, MARCUS TULLIUS, Roman orator, born B.C. 106, died 43.
  • CLAUDIUS, Roman Emperor, born B.C. 9, died A.D. 54. Visited Britain
  • A.D. 43.
  • CLEOMENES, King of Sparta, died B.C. 220.
  • CLODIUS, enemy of Cicero, died B.C. 52. Used to go about Rome with an
  • intimidating band of gladiators.
  • COLUMELLA, native of Spain, resided at Rome in the reign of Claudius,
  • A.D. 41–54.
  • COMMODUS, Roman Emperor, son of Marcus Aurelius, born A.D. 161, died
  • 192.
  • CTESIPHON. In his defence Demosthenes delivered his famous oration “On
  • the Crown” in B.C. 330.
  • DEMETRIUS PHALEREUS, Greek orator and statesman, born B.C. 345, died
  • _circa_ 283.
  • DEMOSTHENES, Greek orator, B.C. 385–322, whose speeches against
  • the encroachments of Philip of Macedon have given the general term
  • “philippics” to powerful invective.
  • DION CASSIUS, _circa_ 200–250, wrote history of Rome in Greek.
  • DIONYSIUS HALICARNASSÆUS, Greek rhetorician and historian, born B.C.
  • 29, died B.C. 7. Chief work, _Roman Archæology_.
  • DIONYSIUS, the elder, tyrant of Syracuse, B.C. 430–367; besides being
  • a warrior, was a patron of literary men and artists. Built Lautumiæ,
  • the famous prison, called also the “Ear of Dionysius.”
  • DIODORUS SICULUS, wrote a universal history, flourished _circa_ B.C.
  • 50.
  • DRUSUS, Roman consul, born B.C. 38.
  • EPAMINONDAS, Theban statesman and general, died B.C. 362.
  • FLORUS, Roman historian, lived in the reigns of Trajan and Hadrian.
  • FOLARD, JEAN CHARLES, military tactician, born at Avignon 1669, died
  • 1752, published an edition of _Polybius_.
  • GARCILASSO DE LA VEGA, called the Inca because descended from the
  • royal family of Peru (1530–1620), wrote _History of Peru_ and _History
  • of Florida_.
  • GEE, JOSHUA, eighteenth-century London merchant, wrote _Trade and
  • Navigation of Great Britain_ (1730).
  • GERMANICUS, son of Nero, died A.D. 19, aged 34.
  • GETA, second son of Emperor Severus, born A.D. 189, died 212.
  • GUICCIARDINI, FRANCISCO, Italian historian (1482–1540).
  • HANNIBAL, great Carthaginian general, born B.C. 247, died 183.
  • HELIOGABALUS, Roman emperor, born _circa_ A.D. 205, died 222.
  • HERODIAN, flourished in the third century, wrote in Greek a history of
  • the period from the death of Marcus Aurelius to 238.
  • HESIOD, one of the earliest Greek poets, supposed to have flourished
  • in the eighth century B.C. “Works and Days” is his best known poem.
  • HIERO II., King of Syracuse, died B.C. 215, aged 92. Archimedes lived
  • in his reign.
  • HIRTIUS, Roman consul, contemporary with Cæsar and Cicero; is said to
  • be the author of the eighth book of Cæsar’s _Commentaries_.
  • HYPERIDES, Athenian orator, died B.C. 322, disciple of Plato.
  • ISOCRATES, Greek orator, born B.C. 436, died 338.
  • JUSTIN, a Latin historian, lived in second or third century,
  • epitomized _Historiæ Philippicæ of Trogus Pompeius, a native of Gaul_.
  • LIVIUS, TITUS (Livy), historian of Rome (B.C. 59–17). Of his 142
  • books, only 35 have been preserved.
  • LONGINUS, DIONYSIUS, Greek philosopher, died B.C. 273. His extensive
  • knowledge earned him the title of “The living library.”
  • LUCIAN, Greek writer, lived in the time of Marcus Aurelius.
  • LYCURGUS, Spartan lawgiver, whose severe regulations made the Spartans
  • a race of warriors, is said to have flourished in the ninth century
  • B.C.
  • LYSIAS, Greek orator, born B.C. 458, died 373, wrote 230 orations, of
  • which only 35 remain.
  • MACHIAVELLI, Florentine statesman and historian, born 1469, died 1527.
  • MAILLET, French writer, born 1656, died 1738, consul in Egypt and at
  • Leghorn.
  • MARTIAL, Roman poet, born A.D. 43.
  • MASSINISSA, King of Numidia, born B.C. 238, died 148.
  • MAZARIN, JULES, cardinal, and first minister of Louis XIV. (1602–61).
  • NABIS, Spartan tyrant, died B.C. 192, noted for his cruelty.
  • NERO, Roman emperor, born A.D. 37, died 67.
  • OCTAVIUS, became Emperor Augustus.
  • OVIDIUS PUBLIUS NASO (Ovid), Roman poet, B.C. 43–A.D. 18, enjoyed the
  • patronage of Augustus until banished A.D. 8. Chief works—_Amores_, _De
  • Arte Amandi_, _Fasti_.
  • PATERCULUS, Roman historian, born _circa_ B.C. 19, died A.D. 31.
  • PAUSANIAS, Greek writer, flourished _circa_ A.D. 120–140.
  • PERSEUS, or PERSES, last King of Macedonia. Ascended the throne B.C.
  • 178.
  • PESCENIUS NIGER, became Roman Emperor in 193.
  • PETRONIUS, died A.D. 66, Roman author, lived at the court of Nero, and
  • acquired celebrity for his licentiousness.
  • PHILIP of Macedon, born 382, assassinated 336.
  • PLATO, born B.C. 429, died 347.
  • PLAUTUS, Roman comedy writer, born _circa_ B.C. 255, died 184.
  • PLINY. There were two Plinys—one born A.D. 23, the other, nephew
  • of the preceding, A.D. 62. The former was a naturalist; the latter
  • a pleader and soldier, whose chief writings are his account of the
  • Christians and _Epistles_.
  • PLUTARCH, celebrated biographer, died _circa_ B.C. 120.
  • POLYBIUS, Greek historian, B.C. 204–122. His history deals with Greece
  • and Rome during the period 220–146, and is of great importance.
  • POMPEY the younger, born B.C. 75.
  • PRUSIAS, King of Bithynia, _circa_ B.C. 190.
  • PYRRHUS, King of Epirus, B.C. 318–272, one of the greatest warriors of
  • ancient days.
  • SALLUSTIUS, CRISPUS CAIUS, Roman historian, B.C. 86–35, excluded from
  • the Senate on account of his debauchery.
  • SENECA, LUCIUS ANNÆUS, Roman philosopher, A.D. 3–65, belonged to the
  • Stoic school, and was believed to have been acquainted with St. Paul.
  • SERVIUS TULLIUS, sixth King of Rome, changed the constitution so that
  • the plebs obtained political power.
  • SEVERUS, Roman Emperor, born A.D. 146, died at York 211. Wrote history
  • of his own reign.
  • SOLON, celebrated Athenian legislator, died _circa_ B.C. 558, aged
  • eighty. Established the principle that property, not birth, should
  • entitle to state honours and offices.
  • STRABO, Greek historian and geographer, born _circa_ B.C. 50, died
  • _circa_ A.D. 20. His chief work in seventeen books gives a description
  • of different countries, manners and customs, particulars of their
  • history, and eminent men.
  • SUETONIUS, Roman historian, born _circa_ A.D. 75, died _circa_ 160.
  • TACITUS, Roman historian, born _circa_ A.D. 54. His _Annales_ cover
  • the period A.D. 14–68.
  • THEOCRITUS, Greek poet, lived third century B.C., considered the
  • father of pastoral poetry. Visited the court of Ptolemæus Soter.
  • THRASYBULUS, Athenian naval commander, died B.C. 389.
  • THUCYDIDES, Greek historian, born B.C. 471, died _circa_ 401. His
  • great work, the history of the Peloponnesian War, is the first example
  • of philosophical history.
  • TIBERIUS, CLAUDIUS NERO, Roman Emperor, B.C. 42–A.D. 37, succeeded
  • Augustus A.D. 14.
  • TIMOLEON, Greek general, born in Corinth _circa_ B.C. 400, died 337.
  • Resided at Syracuse.
  • TISSAPHERNES, Persian satrap, died B.C. 395. An intimate friend of
  • Alcibiades.
  • TRAJANUS, MARCUS ULPIUS (Trajan), Roman Emperor, A.D. 52–117.
  • Succeeded to the throne in 98, and surnamed by the Senate “Optimus.”
  • VARRO, Roman writer, born B.C. 116, died 28. Reputed the most learned
  • among the Romans, and wrote 490 books.
  • VAUBAN, SÉBASTIEN LE PRESTRE DE, Marshal of France and great military
  • engineer, 1633–1707. Published works on sieges, frontiers, etc., and
  • left twelve folio volumes of MS., and was pronounced the most upright,
  • simple, true, and modest man of his age.
  • VESPASIAN, TITUS FLAVIUS, Roman Emperor, born A.D. 9, died 79.
  • VOPISCUS, Syracusan, flourished _circa_ A.D. 304. Wrote histories.
  • XENOPHON, Greek historian, born circa B.C. 450, a disciple and friend
  • of Socrates.
  • THE END.
  • THE WALTER SCOTT PUBLISHING CO., LTD., FELLING-ON-TYNE.
  • ADVERTISEMENTS, from the Walter Scott Publishing Company, Limited,
  • London and Felling-on-Tyne.
  • THE WORLD’S LITERARY MASTERPIECES.
  • The Scott Library.
  • Maroon Cloth, Gilt. Price 1s. net per Volume.
  • VOLUMES ALREADY ISSUED—
  • 1 Malory’s Romance of King Arthur and the Quest of the Holy Grail.
  • Edited by Ernest Rhys.
  • 2 Thoreau’s Walden. With Introductory Note by Will H. Dircks.
  • 3 Thoreau’s “Week.” With Prefatory Note by Will H. Dircks.
  • 4 Thoreau’s Essays. Edited, With an Introduction, by Will H. Dircks.
  • 5 Confessions of an English Opium-eater, Etc. By Thomas De Quincey.
  • With Introductory Note by William Sharp.
  • 6 Landor’s Imaginary Conversations. Selected, with Introduction, by
  • Havelock Ellis.
  • 7 Plutarch’s Lives (Langhorne). With Introductory Note by B. J. Snell,
  • M.A.
  • 8 Browne’s Religio Medici, etc. With Introduction by J. Addington
  • Symonds.
  • 9 Shelley’s Essays and Letters. Edited, with Introductory Note, by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 10 Swift’s Prose Writings. Chosen and Arranged, with Introduction, by
  • Walter Lewin.
  • 11 My Study Windows. By James Russell Lowell. With Introduction by R.
  • Garnett, LL.D.
  • 12 Lowell’s Essays on the English Poets. With a new Introduction by
  • Mr. Lowell.
  • 13 The Biglow Papers. By James Russell Lowell. With a Prefatory Note
  • by Ernest Rhys.
  • 14 Great English Painters. Selected from Cunningham’s _Lives_. Edited
  • by William Sharp.
  • 15 Byron’s Letters and Journals. Selected, with Introduction, by
  • Mathilde Blind.
  • 16 Leigh Hunt’s Essays. With Introduction and Notes by Arthur Symons.
  • 17 Longfellow’s “Hyperion,” “Kavanagh,” and “The Trouveres.” With
  • Introduction by W. Tirebuck.
  • 18 Great Musical Composers. by G. F. Ferris. Edited, with
  • Introduction, by Mrs. William Sharp.
  • 19 The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius. Edited by Alice Zimmern.
  • 20 The Teaching of Epictetus. Translated from the Greek, with
  • Introduction and Notes, by T. W. Rolleston.
  • 21 Selections from Seneca. With Introduction by Walter Clode.
  • 22 Specimen Days in America. By Walt Whitman. Revised by the Author,
  • with fresh Preface.
  • 23 Democratic Vistas, and Other Papers. By Walt Whitman. (Published by
  • arrangement with the Author.)
  • 24 White’s Natural History of Selborne, with a Preface by Richard
  • Jefferies.
  • 25 Defoe’s Captain Singleton. Edited, with Introduction, by H.
  • Halliday Sparling.
  • 26 Mazzini’s Essays: Literary, Political, and Religious. With
  • Introduction by William Clarke.
  • 27 Prose Writings of Heine. With Introduction by Havelock Ellis.
  • 28 Reynolds’s Discourses. With Introduction by Helen Zimmern.
  • 29 Papers of Steele and Addison. Edited by Walter Lewin.
  • 30 Burns’s Letters. Selected and Arranged, with Introduction, by J.
  • Logie Robertson, M.A.
  • 31 Volsunga Saga. William Morris. With Introduction by H. H. Sparling.
  • 32 Sartor Resartus. By Thomas Carlyle. With Introduction by Ernest
  • Rhys.
  • 33 Select Writings of Emerson with Introduction by Percival Chubb.
  • 34 Autobiography of Lord Herbert. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Will H. Dircks.
  • 35 English Prose, From Maundeville to Thackeray. Chosen and Edited by
  • Arthur Galton.
  • 36 The Pillars of Society, and Other Plays. By Henrik Ibsen. Edited,
  • with an Introduction, by Havelock Ellis.
  • 37 Irish Fairy and Folk Tales. Edited and Selected by W. B. Yeats.
  • 38 Essays of Dr. Johnson, with Biographical Introduction and Notes by
  • Stuart J. Reid.
  • 39 Essays of William Hazlitt. Selected and Edited, with Introduction
  • and Notes, by Frank Carr.
  • 40 Landor’s Pentameron, and Other Imaginary Conversations. Edited,
  • with a Preface, by H. Ellis.
  • 41 Poe’s Tales and Essays. Edited, with Introduction, by Ernest Rhys.
  • 42 Vicar of Wakefield. By Oliver Goldsmith. Edited, with Preface, by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 43 Political Orations, from Wentworth to Macaulay. Edited, with
  • Introduction, by William Clarke.
  • 44 The Autocrat of the Breakfast-table. By Oliver Wendell Holmes.
  • 45 The Poet at the Breakfast-table. By Oliver Wendell Holmes.
  • 46 The Professor at the Breakfast-table. By Oliver Wendell Holmes.
  • 47 Lord Chesterfield’s Letters to his Son. Selected, with
  • Introduction, by Charles Sayle.
  • 48 Stories from Carleton. Selected, with Introduction, by W. Yeats.
  • 49 Jane Eyre. By Charlotte Brontë. Edited by Clement K. Shorter.
  • 50 Elizabethan England. Edited by Lothrop Withington, with a Preface
  • by Dr. Furnivall.
  • 51 The Prose Writings of Thomas Davis. Edited by T. W. Rolleston.
  • 52 Spence’s Anecdotes. A Selection. Edited, with an Introduction and
  • Notes, by John Underhill.
  • 53 More’s Utopia, and Life of Edward V. Edited, with an Introduction,
  • by Maurice Adams.
  • 54 Sadi’s Gulistan, or Flower Garden. Translated, with an Essay, by
  • James Ross.
  • 55 English Fairy and Folk Tales. Edited by E. Sidney Hartland.
  • 56 Northern Studies. By Edmund Gosse. With a Note by Ernest Rhys.
  • 57 Early Reviews of Great Writers. Edited by E. Stevenson.
  • 58 Aristotle’s Ethics. With George Henry Lewes’s Essay on Aristotle
  • prefixed.
  • 59 Landor’s Pericles and Aspasia. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Havelock Ellis.
  • 60 Annals of Tacitus. Thomas Gordon’s Translation. Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by Arthur Galton.
  • 61 Essays of Elia. By Charles Lamb. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 62 Balzac’s Shorter Stories. Translated by William Wilson and the
  • Count Stenbock.
  • 63 Comedies of de Musset. Edited, with an Introductory Note, by S. L.
  • Gwynn.
  • 64 Coral Reefs. By Charles Darwin. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Dr. J. W. Williams.
  • 65 Sheridan’s Plays. Edited, with an Introduction, by Rudolf Dircks.
  • 66 Our Village. By Miss Mitford. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 67 Master Humphrey’s Clock, and other Stories. By Charles Dickens.
  • With Introduction by Frank T. Marzials.
  • 68 Oxford Movement, The. Being a Selection from “Tracts for the
  • Times.” Edited, with an Introduction, by William G. Hutchison.
  • 69 Essays and Papers by Douglas Jerrold. Edited by Walter Jerrold.
  • 70 Vindication of the Rights of Woman. By Mary Wollstonecraft.
  • Introduction by Mrs. E. Robins Pennell.
  • 71 “The Athenian Oracle.” A Selection. Edited by John Underhill, with
  • Prefatory Note by Walter Besant.
  • 72 Essays of Sainte-beuve. Translated and Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by Elizabeth Lee.
  • 73 Selections from Plato. From the translation of Sydenham and Taylor.
  • Edited by T. W. Rolleston.
  • 74 Heine’s Italian Travel Sketches, etc. Translated by Elizabeth A.
  • Sharp. With an Introduction from the French of Theophile Gautier.
  • 75 Schiller’s Maid of Orleans. Translated, with an Introduction, by
  • Major-General Patrick Maxwell.
  • 76 Selections from Sydney Smith. Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 77 The New Spirit. By Havelock Ellis.
  • 78 The Book of Marvellous Adventures. From the “Morte d’Arthur.”
  • Edited by Ernest Rhys. [This, together with No. 1, forms the complete
  • “Morte d’Arthur.”]
  • 79 Essays and Aphorisms. By Sir Arthur Helps. With an Introduction by
  • E. A. Helps.
  • 80 Essays of Montaigne. Selected, with a Prefatory Note, by Percival
  • Chubb.
  • 81 The Luck of Barry Lyndon. By W. M. Thackeray. Edited by F. T.
  • Marzials.
  • 82 Schiller’s William Tell. Translated, with an Introduction, by
  • Major-General Patrick Maxwell.
  • 83 Carlyle’s Essays on German Literature. With an Introduction by
  • Ernest Rhys.
  • 84 Plays and Dramatic Essays of Charles Lamb. Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by Rudolf Dircks.
  • 85 The Prose of Wordsworth. Selected and Edited, with an Introduction,
  • by Professor William Knight.
  • 86 Essays, Dialogues, and Thoughts of Count Giacomo Leopardi.
  • Translated, with an Introduction and Notes, by Major-General Patrick
  • Maxwell.
  • 87 The Inspector-general. A Russian Comedy. By Nikolai V. Gogol.
  • Translated from the original, with an Introduction and Notes, by
  • Arthur A. Sykes.
  • 88 Essays and Apothegms of Francis, Lord Bacon. Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by John Buchan.
  • 89 Prose of Milton. Selected and Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Richard Garnett, LL.D.
  • 90 The Republic of Plato. Translated by Thomas Taylor, with an
  • Introduction by Theodore Wratislaw.
  • 91 Passages from Froissart. With an Introduction by Frank T. Marzials.
  • 92 The Prose and Table Talk of Coleridge. Edited by Will H. Dircks.
  • 93 Heine in Art and Letters. Translated by Elizabeth A. Sharp.
  • 94 Selected Essays of de Quincey. With an Introduction by Sir George
  • Douglas, Bart.
  • 95 Vasari’s Lives of Italian Painters. Selected and Prefaced by
  • Havelock Ellis.
  • 96 Laocoon, and other Prose Writings of Lessing. A new Translation by
  • W. B. Rönnfeldt.
  • 97 Pelleas and Melisanda, and the Sightless. Two Plays by Maurice
  • Maeterlinck. Translated from the French by Laurence Alma Tadema.
  • 98 The Complete Angler of Walton and Cotton. Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by Charles Hill Dick.
  • 99 Lessing’s Nathan the Wise. Translated by Major-General Patrick
  • Maxwell.
  • 100 The Poetry of the Celtic Races, and other Essays of Ernest Renan.
  • Translated by W. G. Hutchison.
  • 101 Criticisms, Reflections, and Maxims of Goethe. Translated, with an
  • Introduction, by W. B. Rönnfeldt.
  • 102 Essays of Schopenhauer. Translated by Mrs. Rudolf Dircks. With an
  • Introduction.
  • 103 Renan’s Life of Jesus. Translated, with an Introduction, by
  • William G. Hutchison.
  • 104 The Confessions of Saint Augustine. Edited, with an Introduction,
  • by Arthur Symons.
  • 105 The Principles of Success in Literature. By George Henry Lewes.
  • Edited by T. Sharper Knowlson.
  • 106 The Lives of Dr. John Donne, Sir Henry Wotton, Mr. Richard Hooker,
  • Mr. George Herbert, and Dr. Robert Sanderson. By Izaac Walton. Edited,
  • with an Introduction, by Charles Hill Dick.
  • 108 Renan’s Antichrist. Translated, with an Introduction, by W. G.
  • Hutchison.
  • 109 Orations of Cicero. Selected and Edited, with an Introduction, by
  • Fred. W. Norris.
  • 110 Reflections on the Revolution in France. By Edmund Burke. With an
  • Introduction by George Sampson.
  • 111 The Letters of the Younger Pliny. Series I. Translated, with an
  • Introductory Essay, by John B. Firth, B.A., Late Scholar of Queen’s
  • College, Oxford.
  • 112 The Letters of the Younger Pliny. Series II. Translated by John B.
  • Firth, B.A.
  • 113 Selected Thoughts of Blaise Pascal. Translated, with an
  • Introduction and Notes, by Gertrude Burford Rawlings.
  • 114 Scots Essayists: from Stirling to Stevenson, Edited, with an
  • Introduction, by Oliphant Smeaton.
  • 115 On Liberty. By John Stuart Mill. With an Introduction by W. L.
  • Courtney.
  • 116 The Discourse on Method and Metaphysical Meditations of René
  • Descartes. Translated, with Introduction, by Gertrude B. Rawlings.
  • 117 Kâlidâsa’s Sakuntalâ, Etc. Edited, With An Introduction, by T.
  • Holme.
  • 118 Newman’s University Sketches. Edited, with Introduction, by George
  • Sampson.
  • 119 Newman’s Select Essays. Edited, with an Introduction, by George
  • Sampson.
  • 120 Renan’s Marcus Aurelius. Translated, with an Introduction, by
  • William G. Hutchison.
  • 121 Froude’s Nemesis of Faith. With an Introduction by William G.
  • Hutchison.
  • 122 What is Art? By Leo Tolstoy. Translated from the Original Russian
  • MS., with Introduction, by Alymer Maude.
  • 123 Hume’s Political Essays. Edited, with an Introduction, by W. B.
  • Robertson.
  • OTHER VOLUMES IN PREPARATION.
  • IN ONE VOLUME.
  • _Crown 8vo, Cloth, Richly Gilt. Price 3s. 6d._
  • Musicians Wit, Humour, and Anecdote: Being _on Dits_ of Composers,
  • Singers, and Instrumentalists of All Times.
  • By Frederick J. Crowest,
  • Author of “The Great Tone Poets,” “The Story of British Music”; Editor
  • of “The Master Musicians” Series, etc., etc.
  • Profusely Illustrated with Quaint Drawings by J. P. Donne.
  • _WHAT THE REVIEWERS SAY_:—
  • “It is one of those delightful medleys of anecdote of all times,
  • seasons, and persons, in every page of which there is a new specimen
  • of humour, strange adventure, and quaint saying.”—T. P. O’Connor in
  • _T. P.’s Weekly_.
  • “A remarkable collection of good stories which must have taken years
  • of perseverance to get together.”—_Morning Leader._
  • “A book which should prove acceptable to two large sections of the
  • public—those who are interested in musicians and those who have an
  • adequate sense of the comic.”—_Globe._
  • _The Makers of British Art._
  • _A NEW SERIES OF MONOGRAPHS OF BRITISH PAINTERS._
  • Each volume illustrated with Twenty Full-page Reproductions and a
  • Photogravure Portrait.
  • _Square Crown 8vo, Cloth, Gilt Top, Deckled Edges, 3s. 6d. net._
  • _VOLUMES READY._
  • Landseer, Sir Edwin. By the Editor.
  • “This little volume may rank as the most complete account of Landseer
  • that the world is likely to possess.”—_Times._
  • Reynolds, Sir Joshua. By Elsa d’Esterre-Keeling.
  • “To the series entitled ‘The Makers of British Art’ Miss Elsa
  • d’Esterre-Keeling contributes an admirable little volume on Sir Joshua
  • Reynolds. Miss Keeling’s style is sprightly and epigrammatic, and her
  • judgments are well considered.”—_Daily Telegraph._
  • Turner, J. M. W. By Robert Chignell, Author of “The Life and Paintings
  • of Vicat Cole, R.A.”
  • Romney, George. By Sir Herbert Maxwell, Bart., F.R.S., M.P.
  • “Likely to remain the best account of the painter’s life.”—_Athenæum._
  • Wilkie, Sir David. By Professor Bayne.
  • Constable, John. By the Right Hon. Lord Windsor.
  • Raeburn, Sir Henry. By Edward Pinnington.
  • Gainsborough, Thomas. By A. E. Fletcher.
  • Hogarth, William. By Prof. G. Baldwin Brown.
  • Moore, Henry. By Frank J. Maclean.
  • _IN PREPARATION._
  • MILLAIS—LEIGHTON—MORLAND.
  • Crown 8vo, about 350 pp. each, Cloth Cover, 2/6 per Vol.; Half-Polished
  • Morocco, Gilt Top, 5s.
  • Count Tolstoy’s Works.
  • The following Volumes are already issued—
  • A Russian Proprietor.
  • The Cossacks.
  • Ivan Ilyitch, and Other Stories.
  • My Religion.
  • Life.
  • My Confession.
  • Childhood, Boyhood, Youth.
  • The Physiology of War.
  • Anna Karénina. 3/6.
  • What to Do?
  • War and Peace. (4 vols.)
  • The Long Exile, etc.
  • Sevastopol.
  • The Kreutzer Sonata, and Family Happiness.
  • The Kingdom of God Is Within You.
  • Work While Ye Have the Light.
  • The Gospel in Brief.
  • Uniform with the above—
  • Impressions of Russia. By Dr. Georg Brandes.
  • Post 4to, Cloth, Price 1s.
  • Patriotism and Christianity.
  • To which is appended a Reply to Criticisms of the Work. By Count
  • Tolstoy.
  • 1/‐ Booklets by Count Tolstoy.
  • Bound in White Grained Boards, with Gilt Lettering.
  • Where Love is, There God is Also.
  • The Two Pilgrims.
  • What Men Live by.
  • The Godson.
  • If You Neglect the Fire, You Don’t Put it Out.
  • What Shall it Profit a Man?
  • 2/‐ Booklets by Count Tolstoy.
  • New Editions, Revised.
  • Small 12mo, Cloth, with Embossed Design on Cover, each containing Two
  • Stories by Count Tolstoy, and Two Drawings by H. R. Millar. In Box,
  • Price 2s. each.
  • Volume I. contains—
  • Where Love is, There God is Also.
  • The Godson.
  • Volume II. contains—
  • What Men Live by.
  • What Shall it Profit a Man?
  • Volume III. contains—
  • The Two Pilgrims.
  • If You Neglect the Fire, You Don’t Put it Out.
  • Volume IV. contains—
  • Master and Man.
  • Volume V. contains—
  • Tolstoy’s Parables.
  • _Crown 8vo, Cloth, 3s. 6d. each; some vols., 6s._
  • _The Contemporary Science Series._
  • Edited by Havelock Ellis.
  • Illustrated Vols. between 300 and 400 pp. each.
  • Evolution of Sex. By Professors Geddes and Thomson. 6s.
  • Electricity in Modern Life. By G. W. de Tunzelmann.
  • The Origin of the Aryans. By Dr. Taylor.
  • Physiognomy and Expression. By P. Mantegazza.
  • Evolution and Disease. By J. B. Sutton.
  • The Village Community. By G. L. Gomme.
  • The Criminal. By Havelock Ellis. New Edition. 6s.
  • Sanity and Insanity. By Dr. C. Mercier.
  • Hypnotism. By Dr. Albert Moll (Berlin).
  • Manual Training. By Dr. Woodward (St. Louis).
  • Science of Fairy Tales. By E. S. Hartland.
  • Primitive Folk. By Elie Reclus.
  • Evolution of Marriage. By Ch. Letourneau.
  • Bacteria and Their Products. By Dr. Woodhead.
  • Education and Heredity. By J. M. Guyau.
  • The Man of Genius. By Prof. Lombroso.
  • Property: Its Origin. By Ch. Letourneau.
  • Volcanoes Past and Present. By Prof. Hull.
  • Public Health Problems. By Dr. J. F. Sykes.
  • Modern Meteorology. By Frank Waldo, Ph.D.
  • The Germ-plasm. By Professor Weismann. 6s.
  • The Industries of Animals. By F. Houssay.
  • Man and Woman. By Havelock Ellis. 6s.
  • Modern Capitalism. By John A. Hobson, M.A.
  • Thought-Transference. By F. Podmore, M.A.
  • Comparative Psychology. By Prof. C. L. Morgan, F.R.S. 6s.
  • The Origins of Invention. By O. T. Mason.
  • The Growth of the Brain. By H. H. Donaldson.
  • Evolution in Art. By Prof. A. C. Haddon, F.R.S.
  • Hallucinations and Illusions. By E. Parish. 6s.
  • Psychology of the Emotions. By Prof. Ribot. 6s.
  • The New Psychology. By Dr. E. W. Scripture. 6s.
  • Sleep: Its Physiology, Pathology, Hygiene, and Psychology. By Marie de
  • Manacéïne.
  • The Natural History of Digestion. By A. Lockhart Gillespie, M.D.,
  • F.R.C.P. Ed., F.R.S. Ed. 6s.
  • Degeneracy: Its Causes, Signs, and Results. By Prof. Eugene S. Talbot,
  • M.D., Chicago. 6s.
  • The History of the European Fauna. By R. F. Scharff, B.Sc., Ph.D.,
  • F.Z.S. 6s.
  • The Races of Man: A Sketch of Ethnography and Anthropology. By J.
  • Deniker. 6s.
  • The Psychology of Religion. By Prof. Starbuck. 6s.
  • The Child. By Alexander Francis Chamberlain, M.A., Ph.D. 6s.
  • The Mediterranean Race. By Prof. Sergi. 6s.
  • The Study of Religion. By Morris Jastrow, Jun., Ph.D. 6s.
  • History of Geology and Palæontology. By Prof. Karl Alfred von Zittel,
  • Munich. 6s.
  • The Making of Citizens: A Study in Comparative Education. By R. E.
  • Hughes, M.A. 6s.
  • Morals: A Treatise on the Psycho-Sociological Bases of Ethics. By
  • Prof. G. L. Duprat.
  • Earthquakes, a Study of Recent. By Prof. Charles Davison, D.Sc.,
  • F.G.S. 6s.
  • SPECIAL EDITION OF THE CANTERBURY POETS.
  • _Square 8vo, Cloth, Gilt Top Elegant, Price 2s._
  • Each Volume with a Frontispiece in Photogravure.
  • Christian Year. With Portrait of John Keble.
  • Longfellow. With Portrait of Longfellow.
  • Shelley. With Portrait of Shelley.
  • Wordsworth. With Portrait of Wordsworth.
  • Whittier. With Portrait of Whittier.
  • Burns. Songs with Portrait of Burns, and View of “The Auld Brig o’
  • Doon.”
  • Burns. Poems with Portrait of Burns, and View of “The Auld Brig o’
  • Doon.”
  • Keats. With Portrait of Keats.
  • Emerson. With Portrait of Emerson.
  • Sonnets of this Century. Portrait of P. B. Marston.
  • Whitman. With Portrait of Whitman.
  • Love Letters of a Violinist. Portrait of Eric Mackay.
  • Scott. Lady of the Lake, etc. with Portrait of Sir Walter Scott, and
  • View of “The Silver Strand, Loch Katrine.”
  • Scott. Marmion, etc. with Portrait of Sir Walter Scott, and View of
  • “The Silver Strand, Loch Katrine.”
  • Children of the Poets. With an Engraving of “The Orphans,” by
  • Gainsborough.
  • Sonnets of Europe. With Portrait of J. A. Symonds.
  • Sydney Dobell. With Portrait of Sydney Dobell.
  • Herrick. With Portrait of Herrick.
  • Ballads and Rondeaus. Portrait of W. E. Henley.
  • Irish Minstrelsy. With Portrait of Thomas Davis.
  • Paradise Lost. With Portrait of Milton.
  • Fairy Music. Engraving from Drawing by C. E. Brock.
  • Golden Treasury. With Engraving of Virgin Mother.
  • American Sonnets. With Portrait of J. R. Lowell.
  • Imitation of Christ. With Engraving, “Ecce Homo.”
  • Painter Poets. With Portrait of Walter Crane.
  • Women Poets. With Portrait of Mrs. Browning.
  • Poems of Hon. Roden Noel. Portrait of Hon. R. Noel.
  • American Humorous Verse. Portrait of Mark Twain.
  • Songs of Freedom. With Portrait of William Morris.
  • Scottish Minor Poets. With Portrait of R. Tannahill.
  • Contemporary Scottish Verse. With Portrait of Robert Louis Stevenson.
  • Paradise Regained. With Portrait of Milton.
  • Cavalier Poets. With Portrait of Suckling.
  • Humorous Poems. With Portrait of Hood.
  • Herbert. With Portrait of Herbert.
  • Poe. With Portrait of Poe.
  • Owen Meredith. With Portrait of late Lord Lytton.
  • Love Lyrics. With Portrait of Raleigh.
  • German Ballads. With Portrait of Schiller.
  • Campbell. With Portrait of Campbell.
  • Canadian Poems. With View of Mount Stephen.
  • Early English Poetry. With Portrait of Earl of Surrey.
  • Allan Ramsay. With Portrait of Ramsay.
  • Spenser. With Portrait of Spenser.
  • Chatterton. With Engraving, “The Death of Chatterton.”
  • Cowper. With Portrait of Cowper.
  • Chaucer. With Portrait of Chaucer.
  • Coleridge. With Portrait of Coleridge.
  • Pope. With Portrait of Pope.
  • Byron. Miscellaneous with Portraits of Byron.
  • Byron. Don Juan with Portraits of Byron.
  • Jacobite Songs. With Portrait of Prince Charlie.
  • Border Ballads. With View of Neidpath Castle.
  • Australian Ballads. With Portrait of A. L. Gordon.
  • Hogg. With Portrait of Hogg.
  • Goldsmith. With Portrait of Goldsmith.
  • Moore. With Portrait of Moore.
  • Dora Greenwell. With Portrait of Dora Greenwell.
  • Blake. With Portrait of Blake.
  • Poems of Nature. With Portrait of Andrew Lang.
  • Praed. With Portrait.
  • Southey. With Portrait.
  • Hugo. With Portrait.
  • Goethe. With Portrait.
  • Beranger. With Portrait.
  • Heine. With Portrait.
  • Sea Music. With View of Corbière Rocks, Jersey.
  • Song-tide. With Portrait of Philip Bourke Marston.
  • Lady of Lyons. With Portrait of Bulwer Lytton.
  • Shakespeare: Songs and Sonnets. With Portrait.
  • Ben Jonson. With Portrait.
  • Horace. With Portrait.
  • Crabbe. With Portrait.
  • Cradle Songs. With Engraving from Drawing by T. E. Macklin.
  • Ballads of Sport. With Engraving from Drawing by T. E. Macklin.
  • Matthew Arnold. With Portrait.
  • Austin’s Days of the Year, With Portrait.
  • Clough’s Bothie, and other Poems. With View.
  • Browning’s Pippa Passes, etc. With Portrait.
  • Browning’s Blot in the ’Scutcheon, etc. With Portrait.
  • Browning’s Dramatic Lyrics. With Portrait.
  • Mackay’s Lover’s Missal. With Portrait.
  • Kirke White’s Poems. With Portrait.
  • Lyra Nicotiana. With Portrait.
  • Aurora Leigh. With Portrait of E. B. Browning.
  • Naval Songs. With Portrait of Lord Nelson.
  • Tennyson: In Memoriam, Maud, etc. With Portrait.
  • Tennyson: English Idyls, The Princess, etc. With View of Farringford
  • House.
  • War Songs. With Portrait of Lord Roberts.
  • James Thomson. With Portrait.
  • Alexander Smith. With Portrait.
  • _The Music Story Series._
  • _A SERIES OF LITERARY-MUSICAL MONOGRAPHS._
  • Edited by FREDERICK J. CROWEST, Author of “The Great Tone Poets,” etc.,
  • etc.
  • Illustrated with Photogravure and Collotype Portraits, Half-tone and
  • Line Pictures, Facsimiles, etc.
  • _Square Crown 8vo, Cloth, 3s. 6d. net._
  • VOLUMES NOW READY.
  • The Story of Oratorio. By Annie W. Patterson, B.A., Mus. Doc.
  • The Story of Notation. By C. F. Abdy Williams, M.A., Mus. Bac.
  • The Story of the Organ. By C. F. Abdy Williams, M.A., Author of “Bach”
  • and “Handel” (“Master Musicians’ Series”).
  • The Story of Chamber Music. By N. Kilburn Mus. Bac. (Cantab.),
  • Conductor of the Middlesbrough, Sunderland, and Bishop Auckland
  • Musical Societies.
  • The Story of the Violin. By Paul Stoeving, Professor of the Violin,
  • Guildhall School of Music, London.
  • The Story of the Harp. By William H. Grattan Flood, Author of “History
  • of Irish Music.”
  • The Story of Organ Music. By C. F. Abdy Williams, M.A., Mus. Bac.
  • IN PREPARATION.
  • The Story of the Pianoforte. By Algernon S. Rose, Author of “Talks
  • with Bandsmen.”
  • The Story of English Minstrelsy. By Edmondstoune Duncan.
  • The Story of the Orchestra. By Stewart Macpherson, Fellow and
  • Professor, Royal Academy of Music.
  • The Story of Musical Sound. By Churchill Sibley, Mus. Doc.
  • The Story of Church Music. By The Editor.
  • Etc., Etc., Etc.
  • * * * * * *
  • Transcriber’s note:
  • Original spelling and grammar have been generally retained, with
  • some exceptions noted below.
  • Page xi. The phrase ‹Weath of Nations› was changed to ‹Wealth of
  • Nations›.
  • Page xiii. The phrase ‹‘I am much pleased with› was changed to ‹“I am
  • much pleased with›.
  • Page xxiii. The phrase ‹int his room while› was changed to ‹into his
  • room while›.
  • Page 144. The phrases ‹Xerxes’s army› and ‹Xerxes’ army› are both
  • retained.
  • Page 157n. The phrase ‹much rom their business› was changed to ‹much
  • from their business›.
  • Pages 162–163. The phrases ‹“that in the year› (p. 162) and ‹north
  • exposition.”› (p. 163) contain unbalanced quotation marks in the
  • original. Two new double quotation marks have been inserted to balance
  • these, at ‹“‘Hybernum fracta› and ‹“He speaks of that river’s›.
  • Page 254. The phrase ‹SAMILLUS, MARCUS FURIUS› was changed to
  • ‹CAMILLUS, MARCUS FURIUS›.
  • Page 258. This (originally unnumbered) page begins sixteen pages
  • of advertisements from The Walter Scott Publishing Co. A new
  • heading ‹ADVERTISEMENTS› was inserted. This new heading contains
  • also the footer text that was originally printed on each page of the
  • ads section. The ads were printed in several different styles with
  • considerable variation. The styling has been herein greatly simplified.
  • Several large curly brackets ‹}› that graphically indicate combination
  • of information on two or more lines of text have been eliminated, by
  • restructuring the text. Ditto marks ‹Do.› were also removed.
  • ***END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HUME'S POLITICAL DISCOURSES***
  • ******* This file should be named 59792-0.txt or 59792-0.zip *******
  • This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/5/9/7/9/59792
  • Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will
  • be renamed.
  • Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
  • law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
  • so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
  • States without permission and without paying copyright
  • royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
  • of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm
  • concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
  • and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive
  • specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this
  • eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook
  • for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports,
  • performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given
  • away--you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks
  • not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the
  • trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
  • START: FULL LICENSE
  • THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  • PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
  • To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
  • distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
  • (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
  • Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org/license.
  • Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
  • and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
  • (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
  • the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
  • destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your
  • possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
  • Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
  • by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the
  • person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph
  • 1.E.8.
  • 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
  • used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
  • agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
  • things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
  • paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this
  • agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  • 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the
  • Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
  • of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual
  • works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
  • States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
  • United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
  • claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
  • displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
  • all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
  • that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting
  • free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
  • Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily
  • comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
  • same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when
  • you share it without charge with others.
  • 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
  • what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
  • in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
  • check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
  • agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
  • distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
  • other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no
  • representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
  • country outside the United States.
  • 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
  • 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
  • immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear
  • prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work
  • on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the
  • phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed,
  • performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
  • most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no
  • restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it
  • under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this
  • eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the
  • United States, you'll have to check the laws of the country where you
  • are located before using this ebook.
  • 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is
  • derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
  • contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
  • copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
  • the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
  • redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
  • either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
  • obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
  • with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
  • must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
  • additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
  • will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works
  • posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
  • beginning of this work.
  • 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
  • work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
  • 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
  • electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
  • prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
  • active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License.
  • 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
  • compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
  • any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
  • to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format
  • other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official
  • version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site
  • (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
  • to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
  • of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain
  • Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the
  • full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
  • 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
  • performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
  • unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
  • access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • provided that
  • * You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
  • the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
  • you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
  • to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has
  • agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
  • within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
  • legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
  • payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
  • Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation."
  • * You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
  • you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
  • does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
  • copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
  • all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works.
  • * You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
  • any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
  • electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
  • receipt of the work.
  • * You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
  • distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  • 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than
  • are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
  • from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and The
  • Project Gutenberg Trademark LLC, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
  • 1.F.
  • 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
  • effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
  • works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
  • contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
  • or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
  • intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
  • other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
  • cannot be read by your equipment.
  • 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
  • of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
  • liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
  • fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
  • LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
  • PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
  • TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
  • LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
  • INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
  • DAMAGE.
  • 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
  • defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
  • receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
  • written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
  • received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
  • with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
  • with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
  • lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
  • or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
  • opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
  • the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
  • without further opportunities to fix the problem.
  • 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
  • in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO
  • OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
  • LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
  • 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
  • warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
  • damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
  • violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
  • agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
  • limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
  • unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
  • remaining provisions.
  • 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
  • trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
  • providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in
  • accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
  • production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
  • including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
  • the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
  • or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or
  • additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any
  • Defect you cause.
  • Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
  • electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
  • computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
  • exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
  • from people in all walks of life.
  • Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
  • assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
  • goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
  • remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
  • and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future
  • generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
  • Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
  • www.gutenberg.org
  • Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation
  • The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
  • 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
  • state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
  • Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
  • number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
  • U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
  • The Foundation's principal office is in Fairbanks, Alaska, with the
  • mailing address: PO Box 750175, Fairbanks, AK 99775, but its
  • volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous
  • locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt
  • Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to
  • date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and
  • official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact
  • For additional contact information:
  • Dr. Gregory B. Newby
  • Chief Executive and Director
  • gbnewby@pglaf.org
  • Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation
  • Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
  • spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
  • increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
  • freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
  • array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
  • ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
  • status with the IRS.
  • The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
  • charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
  • States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
  • considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
  • with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
  • where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
  • DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular
  • state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
  • have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
  • against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
  • approach us with offers to donate.
  • International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
  • any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
  • outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
  • Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
  • methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
  • ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
  • donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works.
  • Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be
  • freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
  • distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of
  • volunteer support.
  • Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
  • editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
  • the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
  • necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
  • edition.
  • Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search
  • facility: www.gutenberg.org
  • This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
  • including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
  • subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.