- Project Gutenberg's Philosophical Works, v. 2 (of 4), by David Hume
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most
- other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
- whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of
- the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at
- www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you'll have
- to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this ebook.
- Title: Philosophical Works, v. 2 (of 4)
- Including all the Essays, and Exhibiting the more Important
- Alterations and Corrections in the Successive Editions
- Published by the Author
- Author: David Hume
- Release Date: December 22, 2016 [EBook #53792]
- Language: English
- *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS, V. 2 (OF 4) ***
- Produced by Madelaine Kilsby and Marc D'Hooghe at Free
- Literature (back online soon in an extended version, also
- linking to free sources for education worldwide ... MOOC's,
- educational materials,...) Images generously made available
- by the Bodleian Library, Oxford.
- THE
- PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS
- OF
- DAVID HUME.
- INCLUDING ALL THE ESSAYS, AND EXHIBITING THE
- MORE IMPORTANT ALTERATIONS AND CORRECTIONS
- IN THE SUCCESSIVE EDITIONS PUBLISHED
- BY THE AUTHOR.
- IN FOUR VOLUMES.
- VOL. II.
- EDINBURGH:
- PRINTED FOR ADAM BLACK AND WILLIAM TAIT;
- AND CHARLES TAIT, 63, FLEET STREET,
- LONDON.
- MDCCCXXVI.
- CONTENTS OF VOLUME SECOND.
- TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE.
- BOOK II.--OF THE PASSIONS.
- PART I.
- OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY.
- Division of the Subject
- Of Pride and Humility, their Objects and Causes
- Whence these Objects and Causes are derived
- Of the Relations of Impressions and Ideas
- Of the Influence of these Relations on Pride and Humility
- Limitations of this System
- Of Vice and Virtue
- Of Beauty and Deformity
- Of external Advantages and Disadvantages
- Of Property and Riches
- Of the Love of Fame
- Of Pride and Humility of Animals
- PART II.
- OF LOVE AND HATRED.
- Of the Objects and Causes of Love and Hatred
- Experiments to confirm this System
- Difficulties solved
- Of the Love of Relations
- Of our Esteem for the Rich and Powerful
- Of Benevolence and Anger
- Of Compassion
- Of Malice and Envy
- Of the mixture of Benevolence and Anger with Compassion and Malice
- Of Respect and Contempt
- Of the Amorous Passion, or Love betwixt the Sexes
- Of Love and Hatred of Animals
- PART III.
- OF THE WILL AND DIRECT PASSIONS.
- Of Liberty and Necessity
- The Same subject continued
- Of the Influencing Motives of the Will
- Of the Causes of the Violent Passions
- Of the Effects of Custom
- Of the Influence of the Imagination on the Passions
- Of Contiguity and Distance in Space and Time
- The same Subject continued
- Of the Direct Passions
- Of Curiosity, or the Love of Truth
- BOOK III.--OF MORALS.
- PART I.
- OF VIRTUE AND VICE IN GENERAL.
- Moral Distinctions not derived from Reason
- Moral Distinctions derived from a Moral Sense
- PART II.
- OF JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE.
- Justice, whether a natural or artificial Virtue?
- Of the Origin of Justice and Property
- Of the Rules which determine Property
- Of the Transference of Property by Consent
- Of the Obligation of Promises
- Some farther Reflections concerning Justice and Injustice
- Of the Origin of Government
- Of the Source of Allegiance
- Of the Measures of Allegiance
- Of the Objects of Allegiance
- Of the Laws of Nations
- Of Chastity and Modesty
- PART III.
- OF THE OTHER VIRTUES AND VICES.
- Of the Origin of the Natural Virtues and Vices
- Of Greatness of Mind
- Of Goodness and Benevolence
- Of Natural Abilities
- Some farther Reflections concerning the Natural Virtues
- Conclusion of this Book
- Dialogues concerning Natural Religion
- Appendix to the Treatise of Human Nature
- BOOK II.
- OF THE PASSIONS
- PART I.
- OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY.
- SECTION I.
- DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT.
- As all the perceptions of the mind may be divided into _impressions_
- and _ideas_, so the impressions admit of another division into
- _original_ and _secondary_. This division of the impressions is the
- same with that which I formerly made use of[1] when I distinguished
- them into impressions of _sensation_ and _reflection_. Original
- impressions, or impressions of sensation, are such as, without any
- antecedent perception, arise in the soul, from the constitution of the
- body, from the animal spirits, or from the application of objects to
- the external organs. Secondary, or reflective impressions, are such as
- proceed from some of these original ones, either immediately, or by the
- interposition of its idea. Of the first kind are all the impressions of
- the senses, and all bodily pains and pleasures: of the second are the
- passions, and other emotions resembling them.
- 'Tis certain that the mind, in its perceptions, must begin somewhere;
- and that since the impressions precede their correspondent ideas, there
- must be some impressions, which, without any introduction, make their
- appearance in the soul. As these depend upon natural and physical
- causes, the examination of them would lead me too far from my present
- subject, into the sciences of anatomy and natural philosophy. For this
- reason I shall here confine myself to those other impressions, which
- I have called secondary and reflective, as arising either from the
- original impressions, or from their ideas. Bodily pains and pleasures
- are the source of many passions, both when felt and considered by the
- mind; but arise originally in the soul, or in the body, whichever you
- please to call it, without any preceding thought or perception. A fit
- of the gout produces a long train of passions, as grief, hope, fear;
- but is not derived immediately from any affection or idea.
- The reflective impressions may be divided into two kinds, viz. the
- _calm_ and the _violent_. Of the first kind is the sense of beauty and
- deformity in action, composition, and external objects. Of the second
- are the passions of love and hatred, grief and joy, pride and humility.
- This division is far from being exact. The raptures of poetry and music
- frequently rise to the greatest height; while those other impressions,
- properly called _passions_, may decay into so soft an emotion, as to
- become in a manner imperceptible. But as, in general, the passions
- are more violent than the emotions arising from beauty and deformity,
- these impressions have been commonly distinguished from each other. The
- subject of the human mind being so copious and various, I shall here
- take advantage of this vulgar and specious division, that I may proceed
- with the greater order; and, having said all I thought necessary
- concerning our ideas, shall now explain those violent emotions or
- passions, their nature, origin, causes and effects.
- When we take a survey of the passions, there occurs a division of
- them into _direct_ and _indirect_. By direct passions I understand
- such as arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure.
- By indirect, such as proceed from the same principles, but by the
- conjunction of other qualities. This distinction I cannot at present
- justify or explain any farther. I can only observe in general, that
- under the indirect passions I comprehend pride, humility, ambition,
- vanity, love, hatred, envy, pity, malice, generosity, with their
- dependents. And under the direct passions, desire, aversion, grief,
- joy, hope, fear, despair, and security. I shall begin with the former.
- [1] Book I. Part I. Sect. 2.
- SECTION II.
- OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY, THEIR OBJECTS AND CAUSES.
- The passions of _pride_ and _humility_ being simple and uniform
- impressions, 'tis impossible we can ever, by a multitude of words,
- give a just definition of them, or indeed of any of the passions. The
- utmost we can pretend to is a description of them, by an enumeration
- of such circumstances as attend them: but as these words, _pride_ and
- _humility_, are of general use, and the impressions they represent the
- most common of any, every one, of himself, will be able to form a just
- idea of them, without any danger of mistake. For which reason, not
- to lose time upon preliminaries, I shall immediately enter upon the
- examination of these passions.
- 'Tis evident, that pride and humility, though directly contrary, have
- yet the same _object_. This object is self, or that succession of
- related ideas and impressions, of which we have an intimate memory
- and consciousness. Here the view always fixes when we are actuated by
- either of these passions. According as our idea of ourself is more or
- less advantageous, we feel either of those opposite affections, and are
- elated by pride, or dejected with humility. Whatever other objects may
- be comprehended by the mind, they are always considered with a view to
- ourselves; otherwise they would never be able either to excite these
- passions, or produce the smallest increase or diminution of them. When
- self enters not into the consideration, there is no room either for
- pride or humility.
- But though that connected succession of perceptions, which we call
- _self_ be always the object of these two passions, 'tis impossible
- it can be their _cause_, or be sufficient alone to excite them. For
- as these passions are directly contrary, and have the same object in
- common; were their object also their cause, it could never produce
- any degree of the one passion, but at the same time it must excite
- an equal degree of the other; which opposition and contrariety must
- destroy both. 'Tis impossible a man can at the same time be both proud
- and humble; and where he has different reasons for these passions, as
- frequently happens, the passions either take place alternately, or, if
- they encounter, the one annihilates the other, as far as its strength
- goes, and the remainder only of that which is superior, continues to
- operate upon the mind. But in the present case neither of the passions
- could ever become superior; because, supposing it to be the view only
- of ourself which excited them, that being perfectly indifferent to
- either, must produce both in the very same proportion; or, in other
- words, can produce neither. To excite any passion, and at the same time
- raise an equal share of its antagonist, is immediately to undo what was
- done, and must leave the mind at last perfectly calm and indifferent.
- We must therefore make a distinction betwixt the cause and the object
- of these passions; betwixt that idea which excites them, and that to
- which they direct their view when excited. Pride and humility, being
- once raised, immediately turn our attention to ourself, and regard that
- as their ultimate and final object; but there is something farther
- requisite in order to raise them: something, which is peculiar to
- one of the passions, and produces not both in the very same degree.
- The first idea that is presented to the mind is that of the cause or
- productive principle. This excites the passion connected with it; and
- that passion, when excited, turns our view to another idea, which is
- that of self. Here then is a passion placed betwixt two ideas, of which
- the one produces it, and the other is produced by it. The first idea
- therefore represents the cause, the second the _object_ of the passion.
- To begin with the causes of pride and humility; we may observe, that
- their most obvious and remarkable property is the vast variety of
- _subjects_ on which they may be placed. Every valuable quality of the
- mind, whether of the imagination, judgment, memory or disposition;
- wit, good sense, learning, courage, justice, integrity; all these are
- the causes of pride, and their opposites of humility. Nor are these
- passions confined to the mind, but extend their view to the body
- likewise. A man may be proud of his beauty, strength, agility, good
- mien, address in dancing, riding, fencing, and of his dexterity in
- any manual business or manufacture. But this is not all. The passion,
- looking farther, comprehends whatever objects are in the least allied
- or related to us. Our country, family, children, relations, riches,
- houses, gardens, horses, dogs, clothes; any of these may become a cause
- either of pride or of humility.
- From the consideration of these causes, it appears necessary we should
- make a new distinction in the causes of the passion, betwixt that
- _quality_ which operates, and the _subject_ on which it is placed. A
- man, for instance, is vain of a beautiful house which belongs to him,
- or which he has himself built and contrived. Here the object of the
- passion is himself, and the cause is the beautiful house: which cause
- again is subdivided into two parts, viz. the quality, which operates
- upon the passion, and the subject, in which the quality inheres. The
- quality is the beauty, and the subject is the house, considered as his
- property or contrivance. Both these parts are essential, nor is the
- distinction vain and chimerical. Beauty, considered merely as such,
- unless placed upon something related to us, never produces any pride or
- vanity; and the strongest relation alone, without beauty, or something
- else in its place, has as little influence on that passion. Since,
- therefore, these two particulars are easily separated, and there is a
- necessity for their conjunction, in order to produce the passion, we
- ought to consider them as component parts of the cause; and infix in
- our minds an exact idea of this distinction.
- SECTION III.
- WHENCE THESE OBJECTS AND CAUSES ARE DERIVED.
- Being so far advanced as to observe a difference betwixt the _object_
- of the passions and their _cause_, and to distinguish in the cause the
- _quality_, which operates on the passions, from the _subject_, in which
- it inheres; we now proceed to examine what determines each of them to
- be what it is, and assigns such a particular object and quality, and
- subject to these affections. By this means we shall fully understand
- the origin of pride and humility.
- 'Tis evident, in the first place, that these passions are determined
- to have self for their _object_, not only by a natural, but also by an
- original property. No one can doubt but this property is _natural_,
- from the constancy and steadiness of its operations. 'Tis always self,
- which is the object of pride and humility; and whenever the passions
- look beyond, 'tis still with a view to ourselves; nor can any person or
- object otherwise have any influence upon us.
- That this proceeds from an _original_ quality or primary impulse, will
- likewise appear evident, if we consider that 'tis the distinguishing
- characteristic of these passions. Unless nature had given some original
- qualities to the mind, it could never have any secondary ones; because
- in that case it would have no foundation for action, nor could ever
- begin to exert itself. Now these qualities, which we must consider as
- original, are such as are most inseparable from the soul, and can be
- resolved into no other: and such is the quality which determines the
- object of pride and humility.
- We may, perhaps, make it a greater question, whether the _causes_ that
- produce the passion, be as _natural_ as the object to which it is
- directed, and whether all that vast variety proceeds from caprice, or
- from the constitution of the mind. This doubt we shall soon remove, if
- we cast our eye upon human nature, and consider that, in all nations
- and ages, the same objects still give rise to pride and humility; and
- that upon the view even of a stranger, we can know pretty nearly what
- will either increase or diminish his passions of this kind. If there
- be any variation in this particular, it proceeds from nothing but a
- difference in the tempers and complexions of men, and is, besides, very
- inconsiderable. Can we imagine it possible, that while human nature
- remains the same, men will ever become entirely indifferent to their
- power, riches, beauty or personal merit, and that their pride and
- vanity will not be affected by these advantages?
- But though the causes of pride and humility be plainly _natural_, we
- shall find, upon examination, that they are not _original_, and that
- 'tis utterly impossible they should each of them be adapted to these
- passions by a particular provision and primary constitution of nature.
- Beside their prodigious number, many of them are the effects of art,
- and arise partly from the industry, partly from the caprice, and partly
- from the good fortune of men. Industry produces houses, furniture,
- clothes. Caprice determines their particular kinds and qualities. And
- good fortune frequently contributes to all this, by discovering the
- effects that result from the different mixtures and combinations
- of bodies. 'Tis absurd therefore to imagine, that each of these was
- foreseen and provided for by nature, and that every new production
- of art, which causes pride or humility, instead of adapting itself
- to the passion by partaking of some general quality that naturally
- operates on the mind, is itself the object of an original principle,
- which till then lay concealed in the soul, and is only by accident
- at last brought to light. Thus the first mechanic that invented a
- fine scrutoire, produced pride in him who became possessed of it, by
- principles different from those which made him proud of handsome chairs
- and tables. As this appears evidently ridiculous, we must conclude,
- that each cause of pride and humility is not adapted to the passions
- by a distinct original quality, but that there are some one or more
- circumstances common to all of them, on which their efficacy depends.
- Besides, we find in the course of nature, that though the effects be
- many, the principles from which they arise are commonly but few and
- simple, and that 'tis the sign of an unskilful naturalist to have
- recourse to a different quality, in order to explain every different
- operation. How much more must this be true with regard to the human
- mind, which, being so confined a subject, may justly be thought
- incapable of containing such a monstrous heap of principles, as would
- be necessary to excite the passions of pride and humility, were each
- distinct cause adapted to the passion by a distinct set of principles!
- Here, therefore, moral philosophy is in the same condition as natural,
- with regard to astronomy before the time of Copernicus. The ancients,
- though sensible of that maxim, _that Nature does nothing in vain_,
- contrived such intricate systems of the heavens, as seemed inconsistent
- with true philosophy, and gave place at last to something more simple
- and natural. To invent without scruple a new principle to every
- new phenomenon, instead of adapting it to the old; to overload our
- hypothesis with a variety of this kind, are certain proofs that none of
- these principles is the just one, and that we only desire, by a number
- of falsehoods, to cover our ignorance of the truth.
- SECTION IV.
- OF THE RELATIONS OF IMPRESSIONS AND IDEAS.
- Thus we have established two truths without any obstacle or difficulty,
- _that 'tis from natural principles this variety of causes excite
- pride and humility_, and _that 'tis not by a different principle each
- different cause is adapted to its passion_. We shall now proceed to
- inquire how we may reduce these principles to a lesser number, and find
- among the causes something common on which their influence depends.
- In order to this, we must reflect on certain properties of human
- nature, which, though they have a mighty influence on every operation
- both of the understanding and passions, are not commonly much insisted
- on by philosophers. The _first_ of these is the association of ideas,
- which I have so often observed and explained. 'Tis impossible for the
- mind to fix itself steadily upon one idea for any considerable time;
- nor can it by its utmost efforts ever arrive at such a constancy. But
- however changeable our thoughts may be, they are not entirely without
- rule and method in their changes. The rule by which they proceed, is to
- pass from one object to what is resembling, contiguous to, or produced
- by it. When one idea is present to the imagination, any other, united
- by these relations naturally follows it, and enters with more facility
- by means of that introduction.
- The _second_ property I shall observe in the human mind is a like
- association of impressions. All resembling impressions are connected
- together, and no sooner one arises than the rest immediately follow.
- Grief and disappointment give rise to anger, anger to envy, envy to
- malice, and malice to grief again, till the whole circle be completed.
- In like manner our temper, when elevated with joy, naturally throws
- itself into love, generosity, pity, courage, pride, and the other
- resembling affections. 'Tis difficult for the mind, when actuated
- by any passion, to confine itself to that passion alone, without
- any change or variation. Human nature is too inconstant to admit of
- any such regularity. Changeableness is essential to it. And to what
- can it so naturally change as to affections or emotions, which are
- suitable to the temper, and agree with that set of passions which
- then prevail? 'Tis evident then there is an attraction or association
- among impressions, as well as among ideas; though with this remarkable
- difference, that ideas are associated by resemblance, contiguity, and
- causation, and impressions only by resemblance.
- In the _third_ place, 'tis observable of these two kinds of
- association, that they very much assist and forward each other, and
- that the transition is more easily made where they both concur in
- the same object. Thus, a man who, by an injury from another, is very
- much discomposed and ruffled in his temper, is apt to find a hundred
- subjects of discontent, impatience, fear, and other uneasy passions,
- especially if he can discover these subjects in or near the person who
- was the cause of his first passion. Those principles which forward
- the transition of ideas here concur with those which operate on the
- passions; and both uniting in one action, bestow on the mind a double
- impulse. The new passion, therefore, must arise with so much greater
- violence, and the transition to it must be rendered so much more easy
- and natural.
- Upon this occasion I may cite the authority of an elegant writer, who
- expresses himself in the following manner:--"As the fancy delights in
- every thing that is great, strange or beautiful, and is still more
- pleased the more it finds of these perfections in the _same_ object,
- so it is capable of receiving a new satisfaction by the assistance of
- another sense. Thus, any continued sound, as the music of birds or a
- fall of waters, awakens every moment the mind of the beholder, and
- makes him more attentive to the several beauties of the place that lie
- before him. Thus, if there arises a fragrancy of smells or perfumes,
- they heighten the pleasure of the imagination, and make even the
- colours and verdure of the landscape appear more agreeable; for the
- ideas of both senses recommend each other, and are pleasanter together
- than when they enter the mind separately: as the different colours of a
- picture, when they are well disposed, set off one another, and receive
- an additional beauty from the advantage of the situation." In this
- phenomenon we may remark the association both of impressions and ideas,
- as well as the mutual assistance they lend each other.
- SECTION V.
- OF THE INFLUENCE OF THESE RELATIONS ON PRIDE AND HUMILITY.
- These principles being established on unquestionable experience, I
- begin to consider how we shall apply them, by revolving over all the
- causes of pride and humility, whether these causes be regarded as the
- qualities that operate, or as the subjects on which the qualities
- are placed. In examining these _qualities_, I immediately find many
- of them to concur in producing the sensation of pain and pleasure,
- independent of those affections which I here endeavour to explain. Thus
- the beauty of our person, of itself, and by its very appearance, gives
- pleasure as well as pride; and its deformity, pain as well as humility.
- A magnificent feast delights us, and a sordid one displeases. What I
- discover to be true in some instances, I _suppose_ to be so in all,
- and take it for granted at present, without any farther proof, that
- every cause of pride, by its peculiar qualities, produces a separate
- pleasure, and of humility a separate uneasiness.
- Again, in considering the _subjects_, to which these qualities
- adhere, I make a new _supposition_, which also appears probable from
- many obvious instances, viz. that these subjects are either parts
- of ourselves, or something nearly related to us. Thus the good and
- bad qualities of our actions and manners constitute virtue and vice,
- and determine our personal character, than which nothing operates
- more strongly on these passions. In like manner, 'tis the beauty or
- deformity of our person, houses, equipage, or furniture, by which
- we are rendered either vain or humble. The same qualities, when
- transferred to subjects, which bear us no relation, influence not in
- the smallest degree either of these affections.
- Having thus in a manner supposed two properties of the causes of
- these affections, viz. that the _qualities_ produce a separate
- pain or pleasure, and that the _subjects_, on which the qualities
- are placed, are related to self; I proceed to examine the passions
- themselves, in order to find something in them correspondent to the
- supposed properties of their causes. _First_, I find, that the peculiar
- object of pride and humility is determined by an original and natural
- instinct, and that 'tis absolutely impossible, from the primary
- constitution of the mind, that these passions should ever look beyond
- self, or that individual person, of whose actions and sentiments each
- of us is intimately conscious. Here at last the view always rests,
- when we are actuated by either of these passions; nor can we, in that
- situation of mind, ever lose sight of this object. For this I pretend
- not to give any reason; but consider such a peculiar direction of the
- thought as an original quality.
- The _second_ quality which I discover in these passions, and which
- I likewise consider as an original quality, is their sensations, or
- the peculiar emotions they excite in the soul, and which constitute
- their very being and essence. Thus, pride is a pleasant sensation, and
- humility a painful; and upon the removal of the pleasure and pain,
- there is in reality no pride nor humility. Of this our very feeling
- convinces us; and beyond our feeling, 'tis here in vain to reason or
- dispute.
- If I compare therefore these two _established_ properties of the
- passions, viz. their object, which is self, and their sensation, which
- is either pleasant or painful, to the two _supposed_ properties of the
- causes, viz. their relation to self, and their tendency to produce a
- pain or pleasure independent of the passion; I immediately find, that
- taking these suppositions to be just, the true system breaks in upon me
- with an irresistible evidence. That cause, which excites the passion,
- is related to the object, which nature has attributed to the passion;
- the sensation, which the cause separately produces, is related to
- the sensation of the passion: from this double relation of ideas and
- impressions, the passion is derived. The one idea is easily converted
- into its correlative; and the one impression into that which resembles
- and corresponds to it: with how much greater facility must this
- transition be made, where these movements mutually assist each other,
- and the mind receives a double impulse from the relations both of its
- impressions and ideas!
- That we may comprehend this the better, we must suppose that nature
- has given to the organs of the human mind a certain disposition fitted
- to produce a peculiar impression or emotion, which we call _pride_:
- to this emotion she has assigned a certain idea, viz. that of _self_,
- which it never fails to produce. This contrivance of nature is easily
- conceived. We have many instances of such a situation of affairs.
- The nerves of the nose and palate are so disposed, as in certain
- circumstances to convey such peculiar sensations to the mind: the
- sensations of lust and hunger always produce in us the idea of those
- peculiar objects, which are suitable to each appetite. These two
- circumstances are united in pride. The organs are so disposed as to
- produce the passion; and the passion, after its production, naturally
- produces a certain idea. All this needs no proof. 'Tis evident we never
- should be possessed of that passion, were there not a disposition of
- mind proper for it; and 'tis as evident, that the passion always turns
- our view to ourselves, and makes us think of our own qualities and
- circumstances.
- This being fully comprehended, it may now be asked, _Whether nature
- produces the passion immediately of herself, or whether she must be
- assisted by the cooperation of other causes_? For 'tis observable,
- that in this particular her conduct is different in the different
- passions and sensations. The palate must be excited by an external
- object, in order to produce any relish: but hunger arises internally,
- without the concurrence of any external object. But however the case
- may stand with other passions and impressions, 'tis certain that pride
- requires the assistance of some foreign object, and that the organs
- which produce it exert not themselves like the heart and arteries, by
- an original internal movement. For, _first_, daily experience convinces
- us, that pride requires certain causes to excite it, and languishes
- when unsupported by some excellency in the character, in bodily
- accomplishments, in clothes, equipage, or fortune. _Secondly_, 'tis
- evident pride would be perpetual if it arose immediately from nature,
- since the object is always the same, and there is no disposition of
- body peculiar to pride, as there is to thirst and hunger. _Thirdly_,
- humility is in the very same situation with pride; and therefore either
- must, upon this supposition, be perpetual likewise, or must destroy the
- contrary passion from the very first moment; so that none of them could
- ever make its appearance. Upon the whole, we may rest satisfied with
- the foregoing conclusion, that pride must have a cause as well as an
- object, and that the one has no influence without the other.
- The difficulty, then, is only to discover this cause, and find what
- it is that gives the first motion to pride, and sets those organs
- in action which are naturally fitted to produce that emotion. Upon
- my consulting experience, in order to resolve this difficulty, I
- immediately find a hundred different causes that produce pride; and
- upon examining these causes, I suppose, what at first I perceive to
- be probable, that all of them concur in two circumstances, which are,
- that of themselves they produce an impression allied to the passion,
- and are placed on a subject allied to the object of the passion. When I
- consider after this the nature of _relation_, and its effects both on
- the passions and ideas, I can no longer doubt upon these suppositions,
- that 'tis the very principle which gives rise to pride, and bestows
- motion on those organs, which, being naturally disposed to produce that
- affection, require only a first impulse or beginning to their action.
- Any thing that gives a pleasant sensation, and is related to self,
- excites the passion of pride, which is also agreeable, and has self for
- its object.
- What I have said of pride is equally true of humility. The sensation
- of humility is uneasy, as that of pride is agreeable; for which reason
- the separate sensation arising from the causes must be reversed, while
- the relation to self continues the same. Though pride and humility
- are directly contrary in their effects and in their sensations, they
- have notwithstanding the same object; so that 'tis requisite only to
- change the relation of impressions without making any change upon that
- of ideas. Accordingly we find, that a beautiful house belonging to
- ourselves produces pride; and that the same house, still belonging
- to ourselves, produces humility, when by any accident its beauty is
- changed into deformity, and thereby the sensation of pleasure, which
- corresponded to pride, is transformed into pain, which is related
- to humility. The double relation between the ideas and impressions
- subsists in both cases, and produces an easy transition from the one
- emotion to the other.
- In a word, nature has bestowed a kind of attraction on certain
- impressions and ideas, by which one of them, upon its appearance,
- naturally introduces its correlative. If these two attractions or
- associations of impressions and ideas concur on the same object, they
- mutually assist each other, and the transition of the affections and
- of the imagination is made with the greatest ease and facility. When
- an idea produces an impression, related to an impression, which is
- connected with an idea related to the first idea, these two impressions
- must be in a manner inseparable, nor will the one in any case be
- unattended with the other. 'Tis after this manner that the particular
- causes of pride and humility are determined. The quality which operates
- on the passion produces separately an impression resembling it; the
- subject to which the quality adheres is related to self, the object of
- the passion: no wonder the whole cause, consisting of a quality and of
- a subject, does so unavoidably give rise to the passion.
- To illustrate this hypothesis, we may compare it to that by which I
- have already explained the belief attending the judgments which we
- form from causation. I have observed, that in all judgments of this
- kind, there is always a present impression and a related idea; and
- that the present impression gives a vivacity to the fancy, and the
- relation conveys this vivacity, by an easy transition, to the related
- idea. Without the present impression, the attention is not fixed, nor
- the spirits excited. Without the relation, this attention rests on
- its first object, and has no farther consequence. There is evidently
- a great analogy betwixt that hypothesis, and our present one of an
- impression and idea, that transfuse themselves into another impression
- and idea by means of their double relation: which analogy must be
- allowed to be no despicable proof of both hypotheses.
- SECTION VI.
- LIMITATIONS OF THIS SYSTEM.
- But before we proceed farther in this subject, and examine particularly
- all the causes of pride and humility, 'twill be proper to make some
- limitations to the general system, _that all agreeable objects, related
- to ourselves by an association of ideas and of impressions, produce
- pride, and disagreeable ones, humility_: and these limitations are
- derived from the very nature of the subject.
- I. Suppose an agreeable object to acquire a relation to self, the
- first passion that appears on this occasion is joy; and this passion
- discovers itself upon a slighter relation than pride and vain-glory.
- We may feel joy upon being present at a feast, where our senses are
- regaled with delicacies of every kind: but 'tis only the master of
- the feast, who, beside the same joy, has the additional passion of
- self-applause and vanity. 'Tis true, men sometimes boast of a great
- entertainment, at which they have only been present; and by so small
- a relation convert their pleasure into pride: but however this must in
- general be owned, that joy arises from a more inconsiderable relation
- than vanity, and that many things, which are too foreign to produce
- pride, are yet able to give us a delight and pleasure. The reason
- of the difference may be explained thus. A relation is requisite to
- joy, in order to approach the object to us, and make it give us any
- satisfaction. But beside this, which is common to both passions,
- 'tis requisite to pride, in order to produce a transition from one
- passion to another, and convert the satisfaction into vanity. As it
- has a double task to perform, it must be endowed with double force and
- energy. To which we may add, that where agreeable objects bear not
- a very close relation to ourselves, they commonly do to some other
- person; and this latter relation not only excels, but even diminishes,
- and sometimes destroys the former, as we shall see afterwards.[2]
- Here then is the first limitation we must make to our general position,
- _that every thing related to us, which produces pleasure or pain,
- produces likewise pride or humility_. There is not only a relation
- required, but a close one, and a closer than is required to joy.
- II. The second limitation is, that the agreeable or disagreeable
- object be not only closely related, but also peculiar to ourselves, or
- at least common to us with a few persons. 'Tis a quality observable
- in human nature, and which we shall endeavour to explain afterwards,
- that every thing, which is often presented, and to which we have been
- long accustomed, loses its value in our eyes, and is in a little
- time despised and neglected. We likewise judge of objects more from
- comparison than from their real and intrinsic merit; and where we
- cannot by some contrast enhance their value, we are apt to overlook
- even what is essentially good in them. These qualities of the mind have
- an effect upon joy as well as pride; and 'tis remarkable, that goods,
- which are common to all mankind, and have become familiar to us by
- custom, give us little satisfaction, though perhaps of a more excellent
- kind than those on which, for their singularity, we set a much higher
- value. But though this circumstance operates on both these passions, it
- has a much greater influence on vanity. We are rejoiced for many goods,
- which, on account of their frequency, give us no pride. Health, when it
- returns after a long absence, affords us a very sensible satisfaction;
- but is seldom regarded as a subject of vanity, because 'tis shared with
- such vast numbers.
- The reason why pride is so much more delicate in this particular than
- joy, I take to be as follows. In order to excite pride, there are
- always two objects we must contemplate, viz. the _cause_, or that
- object which produces pleasure; and self, which is the real object of
- the passion. But joy has only one object necessary to its production,
- viz. that which gives pleasure; and though it be requisite that this
- bear some relation to self, yet that is only requisite in order to
- render it agreeable; nor is self, properly speaking, the object of
- this passion. Since, therefore, pride has, in a manner, two objects to
- which it directs our view, it follows, that where neither of them have
- any singularity, the passion must be more weakened upon that account
- than a passion which has only one object. Upon comparing ourselves
- with others, as we are every moment apt to do, we find we are not in
- the least distinguished; and, upon comparing the object we possess, we
- discover still the same unlucky circumstance. By two comparisons so
- disadvantageous, the passion must be entirely destroyed.
- III. The third limitation is, that the pleasant or painful object be
- very discernible and obvious, and that not only to ourselves but to
- others also. This circumstance, like the two foregoing, has an effect
- upon joy as well as pride. We fancy ourselves more happy, as well as
- more virtuous or beautiful, when we appear so to others; but are still
- more ostentatious of our virtues than of our pleasures. This proceeds
- from causes which I shall endeavour to explain afterwards.
- IV. The fourth limitation is derived from the inconstancy of the cause
- of these passions, and from the short duration of its connexion with
- ourselves. What is casual and inconstant gives but little joy, and less
- pride. We are not much satisfied with the thing itself; and are still
- less apt to feel any new degrees of self-satisfaction upon its account.
- We foresee and anticipate its change by the imagination, which makes
- us little satisfied with the thing: we compare it to ourselves, whose
- existence is more durable, by which means its inconstancy appears still
- greater. It seems ridiculous to infer an excellency in ourselves from
- an object which is of so much shorter duration, and attends us during
- so small a part of our existence. 'Twill be easy to comprehend the
- reason why this cause operates not with the same force in joy as in
- pride; since the idea of self is not so essential to the former passion
- as to the latter.
- V. I may add, as a fifth limitation, or rather enlargement of this
- system, that _general rules_ have a great influence upon pride and
- humility, as well as on all the other passions. Hence we form a notion
- of different ranks of men, suitable to the power or riches they are
- possessed of; and this notion we change not upon account of any
- peculiarities of the health or temper of the persons, which may deprive
- them of all enjoyment in their possessions. This may be accounted for
- from the same principles that explained the influence of general rules
- on the understanding. Custom readily carries us beyond the just bounds
- in our passions as well as in our reasonings.
- It may not be amiss to observe on this occasion, that the influence
- of general rules and maxims on the passions very much contributes to
- facilitate the effects of all the principles, which we shall explain
- in the progress of this Treatise. For 'tis evident, that if a person,
- full grown, and of the same nature with ourselves, were on a sudden
- transported into our world, he would be very much embarrassed with
- every object, and would not readily find what degree of love or hatred,
- pride or humility, or any other passion he ought to attribute to it.
- The passions are often varied by very inconsiderable principles; and
- these do not always play with a perfect regularity, especially on the
- first trial. But as custom and practice have brought to light all
- these principles, and have settled the just value of every thing; this
- must certainly contribute to the easy production of the passions, and
- guide us, by means of general established maxims, in the proportions
- we ought to observe in preferring one object to another. This remark
- may, perhaps, serve to obviate difficulties that may arise concerning
- some causes which I shall hereafter ascribe to particular passions,
- and which may be esteemed too refined to operate so universally and
- certainly as they are found to do. I shall close this subject with a
- reflection derived from these five limitations. This reflection is,
- that the persons who are proudest, and who, in the eye of the world,
- have most reason for their pride, are not always the happiest; nor
- the most humble always the most miserable, as may at first sight be
- imagined from this system. An evil may be real, though its cause has
- no relation to us: it may be real, without being peculiar: it may be
- real without showing itself to others: it may be real, without being
- constant: and it may be real, without falling under the general rules.
- Such evils as these will not fail to render us miserable, though they
- have little tendency to diminish pride: and perhaps the most real and
- the most solid evils of life will be found of this nature.
- [2] Part. II. Sect. 4.
- SECTION VII.
- OF VICE AND VIRTUE.
- Taking these limitations along with us, let us proceed to examine the
- causes of pride and humility, and see whether in every case we can
- discover the double relations by which they operate on the passions.
- If we find that all these causes are related to self, and produce a
- pleasure or uneasiness separate from the passion, there will remain no
- farther scruple with regard to the present system. We shall principally
- endeavour to prove the latter point, the former being in a manner
- self-evident.
- To begin with _vice_ and _virtue_, which are the most obvious causes
- of these passions, 'twould be entirely foreign to my present purpose
- to enter upon the controversy, which of late years has so much excited
- the curiosity of the public, _whether these moral distinctions be
- founded on natural and original principles, or arise from interest
- and education_. The examination of this I reserve for the following
- book; and, in the mean time, shall endeavour to show, that my system
- maintains its ground upon either of these hypotheses, which will be a
- strong proof of its solidity.
- For, granting that morality had no foundation in nature, it must still
- be allowed, that vice and virtue, either from self-interest or the
- prejudices of education, produce in us a real pain and pleasure; and
- this we may observe to be strenuously asserted by the defenders of
- that hypothesis. Every passion, habit, or turn of character (say they)
- which has a tendency to our advantage or prejudice, gives a delight
- or uneasiness; and 'tis from thence the approbation or disapprobation
- arises. We easily gain from the liberality of others, but are always in
- danger of losing by their avarice: courage defends us, but cowardice
- lays us open to every attack: justice is the support of society, but
- injustice, unless checked, would quickly prove its ruin: humility
- exalts, but pride mortifies us. For these reasons the former qualities
- are esteemed virtues, and the latter regarded as vices. Now, since
- 'tis granted there is a delight or uneasiness still attending merit or
- demerit of every kind, this is all that is requisite for my purpose.
- But I go farther, and observe, that this moral hypothesis and my
- present system not only agree together, but also that, allowing the
- former to be just, 'tis an absolute and invincible proof of the latter.
- For if all morality be founded on the pain or pleasure which arises
- from the prospect of any loss or advantage that may result from our own
- characters, or from those of others, all the effects of morality must
- be derived from the same pain or pleasure, and, among the rest, the
- passions of pride and humility. The very essence of virtue, according
- to this hypothesis, is to produce pleasure, and that of vice to give
- pain. The virtue and vice must be part of our character, in order to
- excite pride or humility. What farther proof can we desire for the
- double relation of impressions and ideas?
- The same unquestionable argument may be derived from the opinion
- of those who maintain that morality is something real, essential,
- and founded on nature. The most probable hypothesis, which has been
- advanced to explain the distinction betwixt vice and virtue, and
- the origin of moral rights and obligations, is, that from a primary
- constitution of nature, certain characters and passions, by the very
- view and contemplation, produce a pain, and others in like manner
- excite a pleasure. The uneasiness and satisfaction are not only
- inseparable from vice and virtue, but constitute their very nature and
- essence. To approve of a character is to feel an original delight upon
- its appearance. To disapprove of it is to be sensible of an uneasiness.
- The pain and pleasure therefore being the primary causes of vice and
- virtue, must also be the causes of all their effects, and consequently
- of pride and humility, which are the unavoidable attendants of that
- distinction.
- But, supposing this hypothesis of moral philosophy should be allowed to
- be false, 'tis still evident that pain and pleasure, if not the causes
- of vice and virtue, are at least inseparable from them. A generous and
- noble character affords a satisfaction even in the survey; and when
- presented to us, though only in a poem or fable, never fails to charm
- and delight us. On the other hand, cruelty and treachery displease
- from their very nature; nor is it possible ever to reconcile us to
- these qualities, either in ourselves or others. Thus, one hypothesis of
- morality is an undeniable proof of the foregoing system, and the other
- at worst agrees with it.
- But pride and humility arise not from these qualities alone of the
- mind, which, according to the vulgar systems of ethicks, have been
- comprehended as parts of moral duty, but from any other that has a
- connexion with pleasure and uneasiness. Nothing flatters our vanity
- more than the talent of pleasing by our wit, good humour, or any other
- accomplishment; and nothing gives us a more sensible mortification than
- a disappointment in any attempt of that nature. No one has ever been
- able to tell what _wit_ is, and to show why such a system of thought
- must be received under that denomination, and such another rejected.
- 'Tis only by taste we can decide concerning it, nor are we possessed
- of any other standard, upon which we can form a judgment of this kind.
- Now, what is this _taste_, from which true and false wit in a manner
- receive their being, and without which no thought can have a title to
- either of these denominations? 'Tis plainly nothing but a sensation of
- pleasure from true wit, and of uneasiness from false, without our being
- able to tell the reasons of that pleasure or uneasiness. The power of
- bestowing these opposite sensations is, therefore, the very essence
- of true and false wit, and consequently the cause of that pride or
- humility which arises from them.
- There may perhaps be some, who, being accustomed to the style of the
- schools and pulpit, and having never considered human nature in any
- other light, than that in which _they_ place it, may here be surprised
- to hear me talk of virtue as exciting pride, which they look upon as a
- vice; and of vice as producing humility, which they have been taught
- to consider as a virtue. But not to dispute about words, I observe,
- that by _pride_ I understand that agreeable impression, which arises in
- the mind, when the view either of our virtue, beauty, riches or power,
- makes us satisfied with ourselves; and that by _humility_ I mean the
- opposite impression. 'Tis evident the former impression is not always
- vicious, nor the latter virtuous. The most rigid morality allows us
- to receive a pleasure from reflecting on a generous action; and 'tis
- by none esteemed a virtue to feel any fruitless remorses upon the
- thoughts of past villany and baseness. Let us, therefore, examine these
- impressions, considered in themselves; and inquire into their causes,
- whether placed on the mind or body, without troubling ourselves at
- present with that merit or blame, which may attend them.
- SECTION VIII.
- OF BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY.
- Whether we consider the body as a part of ourselves, or assent to those
- philosophers, who regard it as something external, it must still be
- allowed to be near enough connected with us to form one of these double
- relations, which I have asserted to be necessary to the causes of
- pride and humility. Wherever, therefore, we can find the other relation
- of impressions to join to this of ideas, we may expect with assurance
- either of these passions, according as the impression is pleasant or
- uneasy. But _beauty_ of all kinds gives us a peculiar delight and
- satisfaction; as _deformity_ produces pain, upon whatever subject it
- may be placed, and whether surveyed in an animate or inanimate object.
- If the beauty or deformity, therefore, be placed upon our own bodies,
- this pleasure or uneasiness must be converted into pride or humility,
- as having in this case all the circumstances requisite to produce a
- perfect transition of impressions and ideas. These opposite sensations
- are related to the opposite passions. The beauty or deformity is
- closely related to self, the object of both these passions. No wonder,
- then, our own beauty becomes an object of pride, and deformity of
- humility.
- But this effect of personal and bodily qualities is not only a proof
- of the present system, by showing that the passions arise not in
- this case without all the circumstances I have required, but may be
- employed as a stronger and more convincing argument. If we consider
- all the hypotheses which have been formed either by philosophy
- or common reason, to explain the difference betwixt beauty and
- deformity, we shall find that all of them resolve into this, that
- beauty is such an order and construction of parts, as, either by the
- _primary constitution_ of our nature, by _custom_, or by _caprice_,
- is fitted to give a pleasure and satisfaction to the soul. This is
- the distinguishing character of beauty, and forms all the difference
- betwixt it and deformity, whose natural tendency is to produce
- uneasiness. Pleasure and pain, therefore, are not only necessary
- attendants of beauty and deformity, but constitute their very essence.
- And, indeed, if we consider that a great part of the beauty which we
- admire either in animals or in other objects is derived from the idea
- of convenience and utility, we shall make no scruple to assent to
- this opinion. That shape which produces strength is beautiful in one
- animal; and that which is a sign of agility, in another. The order and
- convenience of a palace are no less essential to its beauty than its
- mere figure and appearance. In like manner the rules of architecture
- require, that the top of a pillar should be more slender than its base,
- and that because such a figure conveys to us the idea of security,
- which is pleasant; whereas the contrary form gives us the apprehension
- of danger, which is uneasy. From innumerable instances of this kind,
- as well as from considering that beauty, like wit, cannot be defined,
- but is discerned only by a taste or sensation, we may conclude that
- beauty is nothing but a form, which produces pleasure, as deformity
- is a structure of parts which conveys pain; and since the power of
- producing pain and pleasure make in this manner the essence of beauty
- and deformity, all the effects of these qualities must be derived from
- the sensation; and among the rest pride and humility, which of all
- their effects are the most common and remarkable.
- This argument I esteem just and decisive; but in order to give greater
- authority to the present reasoning, let us suppose it false for a
- moment, and see what will follow. 'Tis certain, then, that if the power
- of producing pleasure and pain forms not the essence of beauty and
- deformity, the sensations are at least inseparable from the qualities,
- and 'tis even difficult to consider them apart. Now, there is nothing
- common to natural and moral beauty (both of which are the causes of
- pride), but this power of producing pleasure; and as a common effect
- always supposes a common cause, 'tis plain that pleasure must in both
- cases be the real and influencing cause of the passion. Again, there
- is nothing originally different betwixt the beauty of our bodies and
- the beauty of external and foreign objects, but that the one has
- a near relation to ourselves, which is waiting in the other. This
- original difference, therefore, must be the cause of all their other
- differences, and, among the rest, of their different influence upon the
- passion of pride, which is excited by the beauty of our person, but
- is not affected in the least by that of foreign and external objects.
- Placing then these two conclusions together, we find they compose the
- preceding system betwixt them, viz. that pleasure, as a related or
- resembling impression, when placed on a related object, by a natural
- transition produces pride, and its contrary, humility. This system,
- then, seems already sufficiently confirmed by experience, though we
- have not yet exhausted all our arguments.
- 'Tis not the beauty of the body alone that produces pride, but also
- its strength and force. Strength is a kind of power, and therefore
- the desire to excel in strength is to be considered as an inferior
- species of _ambition_. For this reason the present phenomenon will be
- sufficiently accounted for in explaining that passion.
- Concerning all other bodily accomplishments, we may observe, in
- general, that whatever in ourselves is either useful, beautiful or
- surprising, is an object of pride, and its contrary of humility. Now,
- 'tis obvious that every thing useful, beautiful or surprising, agrees
- in producing a separate pleasure, and agrees in nothing else. The
- pleasure, therefore, with relation to self, must be the cause of the
- passion.
- Though it should not be questioned whether beauty be not something
- real, and different from the power of producing pleasure, it can never
- be disputed, that, as surprise is nothing but a pleasure arising from
- novelty, it is not, properly speaking, a quality in any object, but
- merely a passion or impression in the soul. It must therefore be from
- that impression that pride by a natural transition arises. And it
- arises so naturally, that there is nothing _in us, or belonging to us_,
- which produces surprise, that does not at the same time excite that
- other passion. Thus, we are vain of the surprising adventures we have
- met with, the escapes we have made, and dangers we have been exposed
- to. Hence the origin of vulgar lying; where men, without any interest,
- and merely out of vanity, heap up a number of extraordinary events,
- which are either the fictions of their brain, or, if true, have at
- least no connexion with themselves. Their fruitful invention supplies
- them with a variety of adventures; and where that talent is wanting,
- they appropriate such as belong to others, in order to satisfy their
- vanity.
- In this phenomenon are contained two curious experiments, which, if
- we compare them together, according to the known rules, by which we
- judge of cause and effect in anatomy, natural philosophy, and other
- sciences, will be an undeniable argument for that influence of the
- double relations above-mentioned. By one of these experiments we find,
- that an object produces pride merely by the interposition of pleasure;
- and that because the quality by which it produces pride, is in reality
- nothing but the power of producing pleasure. By the other experiment
- we find, that the pleasure produces the pride by a transition along
- related ideas; because when we cut off that relation, the passion is
- immediately destroyed. A surprising adventure, in which we have been
- ourselves engaged, is related to us, and by that means produces pride:
- but the adventures of others, though they may cause pleasure, yet, for
- want of this relation of ideas, never excite that passion. What farther
- proof can be desired for the present system?
- There is only one objection to this system with regard to our body;
- which is, that though nothing be more agreeable than health, and more
- painful than sickness, yet commonly men are neither proud of the one,
- nor mortified with the other. This will easily be accounted for, if
- we consider the _second_ and _fourth_ limitations, proposed to our
- general system. It was observed, that no object ever produces pride or
- humility, if it has not something _peculiar_ to ourself; as also, that
- every cause of that passion must be in some measure _constant_, and
- hold some proportion to the duration of ourself, which is its object.
- Now, as health and sickness vary incessantly to all men, and there is
- none who is _solely_ or _certainly_ fixed in either, these accidental
- blessings and calamities are in a manner separated from us, and are
- never considered as connected with our being and existence. And that
- this account is just, appears hence, that wherever a malady of any kind
- is so rooted in our constitution that we no longer entertain any hopes
- of recovery, from that moment it becomes an object of humility; as is
- evident in old men, whom nothing mortifies more than the consideration
- of their age and infirmities. They endeavour, as long as possible, to
- conceal their blindness and deafness, their rheums and gout; nor do
- they ever confess them without reluctance and uneasiness. And though
- young men are not ashamed of every headache or cold they fall into, yet
- no topic is so proper to mortify human pride, and make us entertain a
- mean opinion of our nature, than this, that we are every moment of our
- lives subject to such infirmities. This sufficiently proves that bodily
- pain and sickness are in themselves proper causes of humility; though
- the custom of estimating every thing by comparison more than by its
- intrinsic worth and value, makes us overlook these calamities, which we
- find to be incident to every one, and causes us to form an idea of our
- merit and character independent of them.
- We are ashamed of such maladies as affect others, and are either
- dangerous or disagreeable to them. Of the epilepsy, because it gives
- a horror to every one present; of the itch, because it is infectious;
- of the king's evil, because it commonly goes to posterity. Men always
- consider the sentiments of others in their judgment of themselves. This
- has evidently appeared in some of the foregoing reasonings, and will
- appear still more evidently, and be more fully explained afterwards.
- SECTION IX.
- OF EXTERNAL ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES.
- But though pride and humility have the qualities of our mind and body,
- that is _self_, for their natural and more immediate causes, we find
- by experience that there are many other objects which produce these
- affections, and that the primary one is, in some measure, obscured
- and lost by the multiplicity of foreign and extrinsic. We round a
- vanity upon houses, gardens, equipages, as well as upon personal
- merit and accomplishments; and though these external advantages be
- in themselves widely distant from thought or a person, yet they
- considerably influence even a passion, which is directed to that as
- its ultimate object. This happens when external objects acquire any
- particular relation to ourselves, and are associated or connected with
- us. A beautiful fish in the ocean, an animal in a desart, and indeed
- any thing that neither belongs, nor is related to us, has no manner of
- influence on our vanity, whatever extraordinary qualities it may be
- endowed with, and whatever degree of surprise and admiration it may
- naturally occasion. It must be some way associated with us in order to
- touch our pride. Its idea must hang in a manner upon that of ourselves;
- and the transition from the one to the other must be easy and natural.
- But here 'tis remarkable, that though the relation of _resemblance_
- operates upon the mind in the same manner as contiguity and causation,
- in conveying us from one idea to another, yet 'tis seldom a foundation
- either of pride or of humility. If we resemble a person in any of the
- valuable parts of his character, we must, in some degree, possess the
- quality in which we resemble him; and this quality we always choose
- to survey directly in ourselves, rather than by reflection in another
- person, when we would found upon it any degree of vanity. So that
- though a likeness may occasionally produce that passion, by suggesting
- a more advantageous idea of ourselves, 'tis there the view, fixes at
- last, and the passion finds its ultimate and final cause.
- There are instances, indeed, wherein men show a vanity in resembling
- a great man in his countenance, shape, air, or other minute
- circumstances, that contribute not in any degree to his reputation;
- but it must be confessed, that this extends not very far, nor is of
- any considerable moment in these affections. For this I assign the
- following reason. We can never have a vanity of resembling in trifles
- any person, unless he be possessed of very shining qualities, which
- give us a respect and veneration for him. These qualities, then, are,
- properly speaking, the causes of our vanity, by means of their relation
- to ourselves. Now, after what manner are they related to ourselves?
- They are parts of the person we value, and, consequently, connected
- with these trifles; which are also supposed to be parts of him. These
- trifles are connected with the resembling qualities in us; and these
- qualities in us, being parts, are connected with the whole; and, by
- that means, form a chain of several links betwixt ourselves and the
- shining qualities of the person we resemble. But, besides that this
- multitude of relations must weaken the connexion, 'tis evident the
- mind, in passing from the shining qualities to the trivial ones, must,
- by that contrast, the better perceive the minuteness of the latter, and
- be, in some measure, ashamed of the comparison and resemblance.
- The relation, therefore, of contiguity, or that of causation, betwixt
- the cause and object of pride and humility, is alone requisite to
- give rise to these passions; and these relations are nothing else
- but qualities, by which the imagination is conveyed from one idea to
- another. Now, let us consider what effect these can possibly have upon
- the mind, and by what means they become so requisite to the production
- of the passions. 'Tis evident, that the association of ideas operates
- in so silent and imperceptible a manner, that we are scarce sensible
- of it, and discover it more by its effects than by any immediate
- feeling or perception. It produces no emotion, and gives rise to no
- new impression of any kind, but only modifies those ideas of which the
- mind was formerly possessed, and which it could recal upon occasion.
- From this reasoning, as well as from undoubted experience, we may
- conclude, that an association of ideas, however necessary, is not alone
- sufficient to give rise to any passion.
- 'Tis evident, then, that when the mind feels the passion, either of
- pride or humility, upon the appearance of a related object, there
- is, beside the relation or transition of thought, an emotion, or
- original impression, produced by some other principle. The question
- is, whether the emotion first produced be the passion itself, or some
- other impression related to it. This question we cannot be long in
- deciding. For, besides all the other arguments with which this subject
- abounds, it must evidently appear, that the relation of ideas, which
- experience shows to be so requisite a circumstance to the production
- of the passion, would be entirely superfluous, were it not to second
- a relation of affections, and facilitate the transition from one
- impression to another. If nature produced immediately the passion
- of pride or humility, it would be completed in itself, and would
- require no farther addition or increase from any other affection. But,
- supposing the first emotion to be only related to pride or humility,
- 'tis easily conceived to what purpose the relation of objects may
- serve, and how the two different associations of impressions and ideas,
- by uniting their forces, may assist each other's operation. This is not
- only easily conceived, but, I will venture to affirm, 'tis the only
- manner in which we can conceive this subject. An easy transition of
- ideas, which, of itself, causes no emotion, can never be necessary, or
- even useful to the passions, but by forwarding the transition betwixt
- some related impressions. Not to mention that the same object causes
- a greater or smaller degree of pride, not only in proportion to the
- increase or decrease of its qualities, but also to the distance or
- nearness of the relation, which is a clear argument for the transition
- of affections along the relation of ideas, since every change in the
- relation produces a proportionable change in the passion. Thus one
- part of the preceding system, concerning the relations of ideas, is a
- sufficient proof of the other, concerning that of impressions; and is
- itself so evidently founded on experience, that 'twould be lost time to
- endeavour farther to prove it.
- This will appear still more evidently in particular instances. Men are
- vain of the beauty of their country, of their county, of their parish.
- Here the idea of beauty plainly produces a pleasure. This pleasure
- is related to pride. The object or cause of this pleasure is, by the
- supposition, related to self, or the object of pride. By this double
- relation of impressions and ideas, a transition is made from the one
- impression to the other.
- Men are also vain of the temperature of the climate in which they were
- born; of the fertility of their native soil; of the goodness of the
- wines, fruits, or victuals, produced by it; of the softness or force of
- their language, with other particulars of that kind. These objects have
- plainly a reference to the pleasures of the senses, and are originally
- considered as agreeable to the feeling, taste, or hearing. How is it
- possible they could ever become objects of pride, except by means of
- that transition above explained?
- There are some that discover a vanity of an opposite kind, and affect
- to depreciate their own country, in comparison of those to which
- they have travelled. These persons find, when they are at home, and
- surrounded with their countrymen, that the strong relation betwixt them
- and their own nation is shared with so many, that 'tis in a manner lost
- to them; whereas their distant relation to a foreign country, which is
- formed by their having seen it and lived in it, is augmented by their
- considering how few there are who have done the same. For this reason
- they always admire the beauty, utility, and rarity of what is abroad,
- above what is at home.
- Since we can be vain of a country, climate, or any inanimate object
- which bears a relation to us, 'tis no wonder we are vain of the
- qualities of those who are connected with us by blood or friendship.
- Accordingly we find, that the very same qualities, which in ourselves
- produce pride, produce also, in a lesser degree, the same affection
- when discovered in persons related to us. The beauty, address, merit,
- credit, and honours of their kindred, are carefully displayed by the
- proud, as some of their most considerable sources of their vanity.
- As we are proud of riches in ourselves, so, to satisfy our vanity, we
- desire that every one, who has any connexion with us, should likewise
- be possessed of them, and are ashamed of any one that is mean or poor
- among our friends and relations. For this reason we remove the poor
- as far from us as possible; and as we cannot prevent poverty in some
- distant collaterals, and our forefathers are taken to be our nearest
- relations, upon this account every one affects to be of a good family,
- and to be descended from a long succession of rich and honourable
- ancestors.
- I have frequently observed, that those who boast of the antiquity
- of their families, are glad when they can join this circumstance,
- that their ancestors for many generations have been uninterrupted
- proprietors of the same portion of land, and that their family has
- never changed its possessions, or been transplanted into any other
- county or province. I have also observed, that 'tis an additional
- subject of vanity, when they can boast that these possessions have been
- transmitted through a descent composed entirely of males, and that
- the honours and fortune have never passed through any female. Let us
- endeavour to explain these phenomena by the foregoing system.
- 'Tis evident that, when any one boasts of the antiquity of his family,
- the subjects of his vanity are not merely the extent of time and number
- of ancestors, but also their riches and credit, which are supposed to
- reflect a lustre on himself on account of his relation to them. He
- first considers these objects; is affected by them in an agreeable
- manner; and then returning back to himself, through the relation of
- parent and child, is elevated with the passion of pride, by means of
- the double relation of impressions and ideas. Since, therefore, the
- passion depends on these relations, whatever strengthens any of the
- relations must also increase the passion, and whatever weakens the
- relations must diminish the passion. Now 'tis certain the identity of
- the possession strengthens the relation of ideas arising from blood
- and kindred, and conveys the fancy with greater facility from one
- generation to another, from the remotest ancestors to their posterity,
- who are both their heirs and their descendants. By this facility the
- impression is transmitted more entire, and excites a greater degree of
- pride and vanity.
- The case is the same with the transmission of the honours and fortune
- through a succession of males without their passing through any female.
- 'Tis a quality of human nature, which we shall consider afterwards,[3]
- that the imagination naturally turns to whatever is important and
- considerable; and where two objects are presented to it, a small and
- a great one, usually leaves the former, and dwells entirely upon the
- latter. As in the society of marriage, the male sex has the advantage
- above the female, the husband first engages our attention; and whether
- we consider him directly, or reach him by passing through related
- objects, the thought both rests upon him with greater satisfaction,
- and arrives at him with greater facility than his consort. 'Tis easy
- to see, that this property must strengthen the child's relation to the
- father, and weaken that to the mother. For as all relations are nothing
- but a propensity to pass from one idea to another, whatever strengthens
- the propensity strengthens the relation; and as we have a stronger
- propensity to pass from the idea of the children to that of the father,
- than from the same idea to that of the mother, we ought to regard the
- former relation as the closer and more considerable. This is the reason
- why children commonly bear their father's name, and are esteemed to
- be of nobler or baser birth, according to _his_ family. And though
- the mother should be possessed of a superior spirit and genius to the
- father, as often happens, the _general rule_ prevails, notwithstanding
- the exception, according to the doctrine above explained. Nay, even
- when a superiority of any kind is so great, or when any other reasons
- have such an effect, as to make the children rather represent the
- mother's family than the father's, the general rule still retains
- such an efficacy, that it weakens the relation, and makes a kind of
- break in the line of ancestors. The imagination runs not along them
- with facility, nor is able to transfer the honour and credit of the
- ancestors to their posterity of the same name and family so readily,
- as when the transition is conformable to the general rules, and passes
- from father to son, or from brother to brother.
- [3] Part II. Sect. 2.
- SECTION X.
- OF PROPERTY AND RICHES.
- But the relation which is esteemed the closest, and which, of all
- others, produces most commonly the passion of pride, is that of
- _property_. This relation 'twill be impossible for me fully to explain
- before I come to treat of justice and the other moral virtues. 'Tis
- sufficient to observe on this occasion, that property may be defined,
- _such a relation betwixt a person and an object as permits him, but
- forbids any other, the free use and possession of it, without violating
- the laws of justice and moral equity_. If justice therefore be a
- virtue, which has a natural and original influence on the human mind,
- property may be looked upon as a particular species of _causation_;
- whether we consider the liberty it gives the proprietor to operate
- as he pleases upon the object, or the advantages which he reaps
- from it. 'Tis the same case, if justice, according to the system of
- certain philosophers, should be esteemed an artificial and not a
- natural virtue. For then honour, and custom, and civil laws supply
- the place of natural conscience, and produce in some degree, the same
- effects. This, in the mean time, is certain, that the mention of the
- property naturally carries our thought to the proprietor, and of the
- proprietor to the property; which being a proof of a perfect relation
- of ideas, is all that is requisite to our present purpose. A relation
- of ideas, joined to that of impressions, always produces a transition
- of affections; and therefore, whenever any pleasure or pain arises
- from an object, connected with us by property, we may be certain, that
- either pride or humility must arise from this conjunction of relations,
- if the foregoing system be solid and satisfactory. And whether it be so
- or not, we may soon satisfy ourselves by the most cursory view of human
- life.
- Every thing belonging to a vain man is the best that is any where to
- be found. His houses, equipage, furniture, clothes, horses, hounds,
- excel all others in his conceit; and 'tis easy to observe, that from
- the least advantage in any of these, he draws a new subject of pride
- and vanity. His wine, if you'll believe him, has a finer flavour than
- any other; his cookery is more exquisite; his table more orderly; his
- servant more expert; the air in which he lives more healthful; the soil
- he cultivates more fertile; his fruits ripen earlier, and to greater
- perfection; such a thing is remarkable for its novelty; such another
- for its antiquity: this is the workmanship of a famous artist, that
- belonged to such a prince or great man; all objects, in a word, that
- are useful, beautiful, or surprising, or are related to such, may, by
- means of property, give rise to this passion. These agree in giving
- pleasure, and agree in nothing else. This alone is common to them, and
- therefore must be the quality that produces the passion, which is their
- common effect. As every new instance is a new argument, and as the
- instances are here without number, I may venture to affirm, that scarce
- any system was ever so fully proved by experience, as that which I have
- here advanced.
- If the property of any thing that gives pleasure either by its
- utility, beauty, or novelty, produces also pride by a double relation
- of impressions and ideas; we need not be surprised that the power of
- acquiring this property should have the same effect. Now, riches are to
- be considered as the power of acquiring the property of what pleases;
- and 'tis only in this view they have any influence on the passions.
- Paper will, on many occasions, be considered as riches, and that
- because it may convey the power of acquiring money; and money is not
- riches, as it is a metal endowed with certain qualities of solidity,
- weight, and fusibility; but only as it has a relation to the pleasures
- and conveniences of life. Taking then this for granted, which is in
- itself so evident, we may draw from it one of the strongest arguments
- I have yet employed to prove the influence of the double relations on
- pride and humility.
- It has been observed, in treating of the understanding, that the
- distinction which we sometimes make betwixt a _power_ and the
- _exercise_ of it, is entirely frivolous, and that neither man nor any
- other being ought ever to be thought possessed of any ability, unless
- it be exerted and put in action. But though this be strictly true in
- a just and _philosophical_ way of thinking, 'tis certain it is not
- _the philosophy_ of our passions, but that many things operate upon
- them by means of the idea and supposition of power, independent of
- its actual exercise. We are pleased when we acquire an ability of
- procuring pleasure, and are displeased when another acquires a power of
- giving pain. This is evident from experience; but in order to give a
- just explication of the matter, and account for this satisfaction and
- uneasiness, we must weigh the following reflections.
- 'Tis evident the error of distinguishing power from its exercise
- proceeds not entirely from the scholastic doctrine of _free will_,
- which, indeed, enters very little into common life, and has but small
- influence on our vulgar and popular ways of thinking. According to
- that doctrine, motives deprive us not of free-will, nor take away our
- power of performing or forbearing any action. But according to common
- notions a man has no power, where very considerable motives lie betwixt
- him and the satisfaction of his desires, and determine him to forbear
- what he wishes to perform. I do not think I have fallen into my enemy's
- power when I see him pass me in the streets with a sword by his side,
- while I am, unprovided of any weapon. I know that the fear of the civil
- magistrate is as strong a restraint as any of iron, and that I am in as
- perfect safety as if he were chained or imprisoned. But when a person
- acquires such an authority over me, that not only there is no external
- obstacle to his actions, but also that he may punish or reward me as he
- pleases without any dread of punishment in his turn, I then attribute a
- full power to him, and consider myself as his subject or vassal.
- Now, if we compare these two cases, that of a person who has very
- strong motives of interest or safety to forbear any action, and
- that of another who lies under no such obligation, we shall find,
- according to the philosophy explained in the foregoing book, that
- the only _known_ difference betwixt them lies in this, that in the
- former case we conclude, from _past experience_, that the person never
- will perform that action, and in the latter, that he possibly or
- probably will perform it. Nothing is more fluctuating and inconstant
- on many occasions than the will of man; nor is there any thing but
- strong motives which can give us an absolute certainty in pronouncing
- concerning any of his future actions. When we see a person free
- from these motives, we suppose a possibility either of his acting
- or forbearing; and though, in general, we may conclude him to be
- determined by motives and causes, yet this removes not the uncertainty
- of our judgment concerning these causes, nor the influence of that
- uncertainty on the passions. Since, therefore, we ascribe a power of
- performing an action to every one who has no very powerful motive to
- forbear it, and refuse it to such as have, it may justly be concluded,
- that _power_ has always a reference to its _exercise_, either actual
- or probable, and that we consider a person as endowed with any ability
- when we find, from past experience, that 'tis probable, or at least
- possible, he may exert it. And indeed, as our passions always regard
- the real existence of objects, and we always judge of this reality
- from past instances, nothing can be more likely of itself, without
- any farther reasoning, than that power consists in the possibility or
- probability of any action, as discovered by experience and the practice
- of the world.
- Now, 'tis evident that, wherever a person is in such a situation with
- regard to me that there is no very powerful motive to deter him from
- injuring me, and consequently 'tis _uncertain_ whether he will injure
- me or not, I must be uneasy in such a situation, and cannot consider
- the possibility or probability of that injury without a sensible
- concern. The passions are not only affected by such events as are
- certain and infallible, but also in an inferior degree by such as are
- possible and contingent. And though perhaps I never really feel any
- harm, and discover by the event, that, philosophically speaking, the
- person never had any power of harming me, since he did not exert any,
- this prevents not my uneasiness from the preceding uncertainty. The
- agreeable passions may here operate as well as the uneasy, and convey a
- pleasure when I perceive a good to become either possible or probable
- by the possibility or probability of another's bestowing it on me, upon
- the removal of any strong motives which might formerly have hindered
- him.
- But we may farther observe, that this satisfaction increases, when
- any good approaches, in such a manner that it is in one's _own_ power
- to take or leave it, and there neither is any physical impediment,
- nor any very strong motive to hinder our enjoyment. As all men desire
- pleasure, nothing can be more probable than its existence when there is
- no external obstacle to the producing it, and men perceive no danger
- in following their inclinations. In that case their imagination easily
- anticipates the satisfaction, and conveys the same joy as if they were
- persuaded of its real and actual existence.
- But this accounts not sufficiently for the satisfaction which attends
- riches. A miser receives delight from his money; that is, from the
- _power_ it affords him of procuring all the pleasures and conveniences
- of life, though he knows he has enjoyed his riches for forty years
- without ever enjoying them; and consequently cannot conclude, by any
- species of reasoning, that the real existence of these pleasures is
- nearer, than if he were entirely deprived of all his possessions.
- But though he cannot form any such conclusion in a way of reasoning
- concerning the nearer approach of the pleasure, 'tis certain he
- _imagines_ it to approach nearer, whenever all external obstacles are
- removed, along with the more powerful motives of interest and danger,
- which oppose it. For farther satisfaction on this head, I must refer to
- my account of the will,[4] where I shall explain that false sensation
- of liberty, which makes us imagine we can perform any thing that is not
- very dangerous or destructive. Whenever any other person is under no
- strong obligations of interest to forbear any pleasure, we judge from
- _experience_, that the pleasure will exist, and that he will probably
- obtain it. But when ourselves are in that situation, we judge from an
- _illusion of the fancy_, that the pleasure is still closer and more
- immediate. The will seems to move easily every way, and casts a shadow
- or image of itself even to that side on which it did not settle. By
- means of this image the enjoyment seems to approach nearer to us, and
- gives us the same lively satisfaction as if it were perfectly certain
- and unavoidable.
- 'Twill now be easy to draw this whole reasoning to a point, and
- to prove, that when riches produce any pride or vanity in their
- possessors, as they never fail to do, 'tis only by means of a double
- relation of impressions and ideas. The very essence of riches consists
- in the power of procuring the pleasures and conveniences of life.
- The very essence of this power consists in the probability of its
- exercise, and in its causing us to anticipate, by a _true_ or _false_
- reasoning, the real existence of the pleasure. This anticipation of
- pleasure is, in itself, a very considerable pleasure; and as its cause
- is some possession or property which we enjoy, and which is thereby
- related to us, we here clearly see all the parts of the foregoing
- system most exactly and distinctly drawn out before us.
- For the same reason, that riches cause pleasure and pride, and
- poverty excites uneasiness and humility, power must produce the
- former emotions, and slavery the latter. Power or an authority over
- others makes us capable of satisfying all our desires; as slavery, by
- subjecting us to the will of others, exposes us to a thousand wants and
- mortifications.
- 'Tis here worth observing, that the vanity of power, or shame of
- slavery, are much augmented by the consideration of the persons over
- whom we exercise our authority, or who exercise it over us. For,
- supposing it possible to frame statues of such an admirable mechanism,
- that they could move and act in obedience to the will; 'tis evident the
- possession of them would give pleasure and pride, but not to such a
- degree as the same authority, when exerted over sensible and rational
- creatures, whose condition, being compared to our own, makes it seem
- more agreeable and honourable. Comparison is in every case a sure
- method of augmenting our esteem of any thing. A rich man feels the
- felicity of his condition better by opposing it to that of a beggar.
- But there is a peculiar advantage in power, by the contrast, which
- is, in a manner, presented to us betwixt ourselves and the person we
- command. The comparison is obvious and natural: the imagination finds
- it in the very subject: the passage of the thought to its conception
- is smooth and easy. And that this circumstance has a considerable
- effect in augmenting its influence, will appear afterwards in examining
- the nature of _malice_ and _envy_.
- [4] Part III. Sect. 2.
- SECTION XI.
- OF THE LOVE OF FAME.
- But beside these original causes of pride and humility, there is a
- secondary one in the opinions of others, which has an equal influence
- on the affections. Our reputation, our character, our name, are
- considerations of vast weight and importance; and even the other causes
- of pride, virtue, beauty and riches, have little influence, when not
- seconded by the opinions and sentiments of others. In order to account
- for this phenomenon, 'twill be necessary to take some compass, and
- first explain the nature of _sympathy_.
- No quality of human nature is more remarkable, both in itself and
- in its consequences, than that propensity we have to sympathize
- with others, and to receive by communication their inclinations and
- sentiments, however different from, or even contrary to, our own. This
- is not only conspicuous in children, who implicitly embrace every
- opinion proposed to them; but also in men of the greatest judgment and
- understanding, who find it very difficult to follow their own reason
- or inclination, in opposition to that of their friends and daily
- companions. To this principle we ought to ascribe the great uniformity
- we may observe in the humours and turn of thinking of those of the
- same nation; and 'tis much more probable, that this resemblance arises
- from sympathy, than from any influence of the soil and climate, which,
- though they continue invariably the same, are not able to preserve the
- character of a nation the same for a century together. A good-natured
- man finds himself in an instant of the same humour with his company;
- and even the proudest and most surly take a tincture from their
- countrymen and acquaintance. A cheerful countenance infuses a sensible
- complacency and serenity into my mind; as an angry or sorrowful one
- throws a sudden damp upon me. Hatred, resentment, esteem, love,
- courage, mirth and melancholy; all these passions I feel more from
- communication, than from my own natural temper and disposition. So
- remarkable a phenomenon merits our attention, and must be traced up to
- its first principles.
- When any affection is infused by sympathy, it is at first known only
- by its effects, and by those external signs in the countenance and
- conversation, which convey an idea of it. This idea is presently
- converted into an impression, and acquires such a degree of force
- and vivacity, as to become the very passion itself, and produce an
- equal emotion as any original affection. However instantaneous this
- change of the idea into an impression may be, it proceeds from certain
- views and reflections, which will not escape the strict scrutiny of a
- philosopher, though they may the person himself who makes them.
- 'Tis evident that the idea, or rather impression of ourselves, is
- always intimately present with us, and that our consciousness gives us
- so lively a conception of our own person, that 'tis not possible to
- imagine that any thing can in this particular go beyond it. Whatever
- object, therefore, is related to ourselves, must be conceived with a
- like vivacity of conception, according to the foregoing principles; and
- though this relation should not be so strong as that of causation, it
- must still have a considerable influence. Resemblance and contiguity
- are relations not to be neglected; especially when, by an inference
- from cause and effect, and by the observation of external signs, we are
- informed of the real existence of the object, which is resembling or
- contiguous.
- Now, 'tis obvious that nature has preserved a great resemblance among
- all human creatures, and that we never remark any passion or principle
- in others, of which, in some degree or other, we may not find a
- parallel in ourselves. The case is the same with the fabric of the
- mind as with that of the body. However the parts may differ in shape
- or size, their structure and composition are in general the same.
- There is a very remarkable resemblance, which preserves itself amidst
- all their variety; and this resemblance must very much contribute to
- make us enter into the sentiments of others, and embrace them with
- facility and pleasure. Accordingly we find, that where, beside the
- general resemblance of our natures, there is any peculiar similarity
- in our manners, or character, or country, or language, it facilitates
- the sympathy. The stronger the relation is betwixt ourselves and any
- object, the more easily does the imagination make the transition, and
- convey to the related idea the vivacity of conception, with which we
- always form the idea of our own person.
- Nor is resemblance the only relation which has this effect, but
- receives new force from other relations that may accompany it. The
- sentiments of others have little influence when far removed from
- us, and require the relation of contiguity to make them communicate
- themselves entirely. The relations of blood, being a species of
- causation, may sometimes contribute to the same effect; as also
- acquaintance, which operates in the same manner with education and
- custom, as we shall see more fully afterwards.[5] All these relations,
- when united together, convey the impression or consciousness of our own
- person to the idea of the sentiments or passions of others, and makes
- us conceive them in the strongest and most lively manner.
- It has been remarked in the beginning of this Treatise, that all ideas
- are borrowed from impressions, and that these two kinds of perceptions
- differ only in the degrees of force and vivacity with which they
- strike upon the soul. The component parts of ideas and impressions are
- precisely alike. The manner and order of their appearance may be the
- same. The different degrees of their force and vivacity are, therefore,
- the only particulars that distinguish them: and as this difference may
- be removed, in some measure, by a relation betwixt the impressions
- and ideas, 'tis no wonder an idea of a sentiment or passion may by
- this means be so enlivened as to become the very sentiment or passion.
- The lively idea of any object always approaches its impression; and
- 'tis certain we may feel sickness and pain from the mere force of
- imagination, and make a malady real by often thinking of it. But this
- is most remarkable in the opinions and affections; and 'tis there
- principally that a lively idea is converted into an impression. Our
- affections depend more upon ourselves, and the internal operations of
- the mind, than any other impressions; for which reason they arise more
- naturally from the imagination, and from every lively idea we form of
- them. This is the nature and cause of sympathy; and 'tis after this
- manner we enter so deep into the opinions and affections of others,
- whenever we discover them.
- What is principally remarkable in this whole affair, is the strong
- confirmation these phenomena give to the foregoing system concerning
- the understanding, and consequently to the present one concerning
- the passions, since these are analogous to each other. 'Tis indeed
- evident, that when we sympathize with the passions and sentiments
- of others, these movements appear at first in _our_ mind as mere
- ideas, and are conceived to belong to another person, as we conceive
- any other matter of fact. 'Tis also evident, that the ideas of the
- affections of others are converted into the very impressions they
- represent, and that the passions arise in conformity to the images we
- form of them. All this is an object of the plainest experience, and
- depends not on any hypothesis of philosophy. That science can only be
- admitted to explain the phenomena; though at the same time it must be
- confessed, they are so clear of themselves, that there is but little
- occasion to employ it. For, besides the relation of cause and effect,
- by which we are convinced of the reality of the passion with which we
- sympathize; besides this, I say, we must be assisted by the relations
- of resemblance and contiguity, in order to feel the sympathy in its
- full perfection. And since these relations can entirely convert an
- idea into an impression, and convey the vivacity of the latter into
- the former, so perfectly as to lose nothing of it in the transition,
- we may easily conceive how the relation of cause and effect alone,
- may serve to strengthen and enliven an idea. In sympathy there is an
- evident conversion of an idea into an impression. This conversion
- arises from the relation of objects to ourself. Ourself is always
- intimately present to us. Let us compare all these circumstances, and
- we shall find, that sympathy is exactly correspondent to the operations
- of our understanding; and even contains something more surprising and
- extraordinary.
- 'Tis now time to turn our view from the general consideration of
- sympathy, to its influence on pride and humility, when these passions
- arise from praise and blame, from reputation and infamy. We may
- observe, that no person is ever praised by another for any quality
- which would not, if real, produce of itself a pride in the person
- possessed of it. The eulogiums either turn upon his power, or riches,
- or family, or virtue; all of which are subjects of vanity, that we
- have already explained and accounted for. 'Tis certain, then, that
- if a person considered himself in the same light in which he appears
- to his admirer, he would first receive a separate pleasure, and
- afterwards a pride or self-satisfaction, according to the hypothesis
- above explained. Now, nothing is more natural than for us to embrace
- the opinions of others in this particular, both from _sympathy_,
- which renders all their sentiments intimately present to us, and from
- _reasoning_, which makes us regard their judgment as a kind of argument
- for what they affirm. These two principles of authority and sympathy
- influence almost all our opinions, but must have a peculiar influence
- when we judge of our own worth and character. Such judgments are
- always attended with passion;[6] and nothing tends more to disturb
- our understanding, and precipitate us into any opinions, however
- unreasonable, than their connexion with passion, which diffuses itself
- over the imagination, and gives an additional force to every related
- idea. To which we may add, that, being conscious of great partiality in
- our own favour, we are peculiarly pleased with any thing that confirms
- the good opinion we have of ourselves, and are easily shocked with
- whatever opposes it.
- All this appears very probable in theory; but in order to bestow a
- full certainty on this reasoning, we must examine the phenomena of the
- passions, and see if they agree with it.
- Among these phenomena we may esteem it a very favourable one to our
- present purpose, that though fame in general be agreeable, yet we
- receive a much greater satisfaction from the approbation of those
- whom we ourselves esteem and approve of, than of those whom we hate
- and despise. In like manner we are principally mortified with the
- contempt of persons upon whose judgment we set some value, and are,
- in a great measure, indifferent about the opinions of the rest of
- mankind. But if the mind received from any original instinct a desire
- of fame, and aversion to infamy, fame and infamy would influence us
- without distinction; and every opinion, according as it were favourable
- or unfavourable, would equally excite that desire or aversion. The
- judgment of a fool is the judgment of another person, as well as
- that of a wise man, and is only inferior in its influence on our own
- judgment.
- We are not only better pleased with the approbation of a wise man than
- with that of a fool, but receive an additional satisfaction from the
- former, when 'tis obtained after a long and intimate acquaintance. This
- is accounted for after the same manner.
- The praises of others never give us much pleasure, unless they concur
- with our own opinion, and extol us for those qualities in which we
- chiefly excel. A mere soldier little values the character of eloquence;
- a gownman, of courage; a bishop, of humour; or a merchant, of
- learning. Whatever esteem a man may have for any quality, abstractedly
- considered, when he is conscious he is not possessed of it, the
- opinions of the whole world will give him little pleasure in that
- particular, and that because they never will be able to draw his own
- opinion after them.
- Nothing is more usual than for men of good families, but narrow
- circumstances, to leave their friends and country, and rather seek
- their livelihood by mean and mechanical employments among strangers,
- than among those who are acquainted with their birth and education.
- We shall be unknown, say they, where we go. Nobody will suspect from
- what family we are sprung. We shall be removed from all our friends and
- acquaintance, and our poverty and meanness will by that means sit more
- easy upon us. In examining these sentiments, I find they afford many
- very convincing arguments for my present purpose.
- First, we may infer from them that the uneasiness of being contemned
- depends on sympathy, and that sympathy depends on the relation of
- objects to ourselves, since we are most uneasy under the contempt of
- persons who are both related to us by blood and contiguous in place.
- Hence we seek to diminish this sympathy and uneasiness by separating
- these relations, and placing ourselves in a contiguity to strangers,
- and at a distance from relations.
- Secondly, we may conclude, that relations are requisite to sympathy,
- not absolutely considered as relations, but by their influence
- in converting our ideas of the sentiments of others into the very
- sentiments by means of the association betwixt the idea of their
- persons and that of our own. For here the relations of kindred and
- contiguity both subsist, but not being united in the same persons, they
- contribute in a less degree to the sympathy.
- Thirdly, this very circumstance of the diminution of sympathy, by the
- separation of relations, is worthy of our attention. Suppose I am
- placed in a poor condition among strangers, and consequently am but
- lightly treated; I yet find myself easier in that situation, than when
- I was every day exposed to the contempt of my kindred and countrymen.
- Here I feel a double contempt; from my relations, but they are absent;
- from those about me, but they are strangers. This double contempt is
- likewise strengthened by the two relations of kindred and contiguity.
- But as the persons are not the same who are connected with me by those
- two relations, this difference of ideas separates the impressions
- arising from the contempt, and keeps them from running into each other.
- The contempt of my neighbours has a certain influence, as has also
- that of my kindred; but these influences are distinct and never unite,
- as when the contempt proceeds from persons who are at once both my
- neighbours and kindred. This phenomenon is analogous to the system of
- pride and humility above explained, which may seem so extraordinary to
- vulgar apprehensions.
- Fourthly, a person in these circumstances naturally conceals his birth
- from those among whom he lives, and is very uneasy if any one suspects
- him to be of a family much superior to his present fortune and way of
- living. Every thing in this world is judged of by comparison What is
- an immense fortune for a private gentleman, is beggary for a prince.
- A peasant would think himself happy in what cannot afford necessaries
- for a gentleman. When a man has either been accustomed to a more
- splendid way of living, or thinks himself entitled to it by his birth
- and quality, every thing below is disagreeable and even shameful; and
- 'tis with the greatest industry he conceals his pretensions to a better
- fortune. Here he himself knows his misfortunes; but as those with whom
- he lives are ignorant of them, he has the disagreeable reflection and
- comparison suggested only by his own thoughts, and never receives it by
- a sympathy with others; which must contribute very much to his ease and
- satisfaction.
- If there be any objections to this hypothesis, _that the pleasure which
- we receive from praise arises from a communication of sentiments_, we
- shall find, upon examination, that these objections, when taken in a
- proper light, will serve to confirm it. Popular fame may be agreeable
- even to a man who despises the vulgar; but 'tis because their multitude
- gives them additional weight and authority. Plagiaries are delighted
- with praises, which they are conscious they do not deserve; but this
- is a kind of castle-building, where the imagination amuses itself
- with its own fictions, and strives to render them firm and stable by
- a sympathy with the sentiments of others. Proud men are most shocked
- with contempt, though they do not most readily assent to it; but 'tis
- because of the opposition betwixt the passion, which is natural to
- them, and that received by sympathy. A violent lover, in like manner,
- is very much displeased when you blame and condemn his love; though
- 'tis evident your opposition can have no influence but by the hold it
- takes of himself, and by his sympathy with you. If he despises you, or
- perceives you are in jest, whatever you say has no effect upon him.
- [5] Part II. Sect. 4.
- [6] Book I. Part III. Sect. 10.
- SECTION XII.
- OF THE PRIDE AND HUMILITY OF ANIMALS.
- Thus, in whatever light we consider this subject, we may still
- observe, that the causes of pride and humility correspond exactly to
- our hypothesis, and that nothing can excite either of these passions,
- unless it be both related to ourselves, and produces a pleasure or
- pain independent of the passion. We have not only proved, that a
- tendency to produce pleasure or pain is common to all the causes of
- pride or humility, but also that 'tis the only thing which is common,
- and consequently is the quality by which they operate. We have farther
- proved, that the most considerable causes of these passions are
- really nothing but the power of producing either agreeable or uneasy
- sensations; and therefore that all their effects, and amongst the rest
- pride and humility, are derived solely from that origin. Such simple
- and natural principles, founded on such solid proofs, cannot fail to be
- received by philosophers, unless opposed by some objections that have
- escaped me.
- 'Tis usual with anatomists to join their observations and experiments
- on human bodies to those on beasts; and, from the agreement of these
- experiments, to derive an additional argument for any particular
- hypothesis. 'Tis indeed certain, that where the structure of parts in
- brutes is the same as in men, and the operation of these parts also
- the same, the causes of that operation cannot be different; and that
- whatever we discover to be true of the one species, may be concluded,
- without hesitation, to be certain of the other. Thus, though the
- mixture of humours, and the composition of minute parts, may justly
- be presumed to be somewhat different in men from what it is in mere
- animals, and therefore any experiment we make upon the one concerning
- the effects of medicines, will not always apply to the other, yet, as
- the structure of the veins and muscles, the fabric and situation of the
- heart, of the lungs, the stomach, the liver, and other parts, are the
- same or nearly the same in all animals, the very same hypothesis, which
- in one species explains muscular motion, the progress of the chyle,
- the circulation of the blood, must be applicable to every one; and,
- according as it agrees or disagrees with the experiments we may make in
- any species of creatures, we may draw a proof of its truth or falsehood
- on the whole. Let us therefore apply this method of inquiry, which is
- found so just and useful in reasonings concerning the body, to our
- present anatomy of the mind, and see what discoveries we can make by it.
- In order to this, we must first show the correspondence of _passions_
- in men and animals, and afterwards compare the _causes_, which produce
- these passions.
- 'Tis plain, that almost in every species of creatures, but especially
- of the nobler kind, there are many evident marks of pride and humility.
- The very port and gait of a swan, or turkey, or peacock, show the high
- idea he has entertained of himself, and his contempt of all others.
- This is the more remarkable, that, in the two last species of animals,
- the pride always attends the beauty, and is discovered in the mule
- only. The vanity and emulation of nightingales in singing have been
- commonly remarked; as likewise that of horses in swiftness, of hounds
- in sagacity and smell, of the bull and cock in strength, and of every
- other animal in his particular excellency. Add to this, that every
- species of creatures, which approach so often to man as to familiarize
- themselves with him, show an evident pride in his approbation, and
- are pleased with his praises and caresses, independent of every
- other consideration. Nor are they the caresses of every one without
- distinction which give them this vanity, but those principally of
- the persons they know and love; in the same manner as that passion
- is excited in mankind. All these are evident proofs that pride and
- humility are not merely human passions, but extend themselves over the
- whole animal creation.
- The _causes_ of these passions are likewise much the same in beasts
- as in us, making a just allowance for our superior knowledge and
- understanding. Thus, animals have little or no sense of virtue or vice;
- they quickly lose sight of the relations of blood; and are incapable
- of that of right and property: for which reason the causes of their
- pride and humility must lie solely in the body, and can never be placed
- either in the mind or external objects. But so far as regards the body,
- the same qualities cause pride in the animal as in the human kind; and
- 'tis on beauty, strength, swiftness, or some other useful or agreeable
- quality, that this passage is always founded.
- The next question is, whether, since those passions are the same, and
- arise from the same causes through the whole creation, the _manner_,
- in which the causes operate, be also the same. According to all rules
- of analogy, this is justly to be expected; and if we find upon
- trial, that the explication of these phenomena, which we make use of
- in one species, will not apply to the rest, we may presume that that
- explication, however specious, is in reality without foundation.
- In order to decide this question, let us consider, that there is
- evidently the same _relation_ of ideas, and derived from the same
- causes, in the minds of animals as in those of men. A dog, that has
- hid a bone, often forgets the place; but when brought to it, his
- thought passes easily to what he formerly concealed, by means of the
- contiguity, which produces a relation among his ideas. In like manner,
- when he has been heartily beat in any place, he will tremble on his
- approach to it, even though he discover no signs of any present danger.
- The effects of resemblance are not so remarkable; but as that relation
- makes a considerable ingredient in causation, of which all animals show
- so evident a judgment, we may conclude, that the three relations of
- resemblance, contiguity, and causation operate in the same manner upon
- beasts as upon human creatures.
- There are also instances of the relation of impressions, sufficient to
- convince us, that there is an union of certain affections with each
- other in the inferior species of creatures, as well as in the superior,
- and that their minds are frequently conveyed through a series of
- connected emotions. A dog, when elevated with joy, runs naturally into
- love and kindness, whether of his master or of the sex. In like manner,
- when full of pain and sorrow, he becomes quarrelsome and ill natured;
- and that passion, which at first was grief, is by the smallest occasion
- converted into anger.
- Thus, all the internal principles that are necessary in us to produce
- either pride or humility, are common to all creatures; and since the
- causes, which excite these passions, are likewise the same, we may
- justly conclude, that these causes operate after the same _manner_
- through the whole animal creation. My hypothesis is so simple, and
- supposes so little reflection and judgment, that 'tis applicable
- to every sensible creature; which must not only be allowed to be a
- convincing proof of its veracity, but, I am confident, will be found an
- objection to every other system.
- PART II.
- OF LOVE AND HATRED.
- SECTION I.
- OF THE OBJECT AND CAUSES OF LOVE AND HATRED.
- 'Tis altogether impossible to give any definition of the passions
- of _love_ and _hatred_; and that because they produce merely a
- simple impression, without any mixture or composition. 'Twould be
- as unnecessary to attempt any description of them, drawn from their
- nature, origin, causes, and objects; and that both because these
- are the subjects of our present inquiry, and because these passions
- of themselves are sufficiently known from our common feeling and
- experience. This we have already observed concerning pride and
- humility, and here repeat it concerning love and hatred; and, indeed,
- there is so great a resemblance betwixt these two sets of passions,
- that we shall be obliged to begin with a kind of abridgment of our
- reasonings concerning the former, in order to explain the latter.
- As the immediate _object_ of pride and humility is self, or that
- identical person of whose thoughts, actions and sensations, we are
- intimately conscious; so the _object_ of love and hatred is some
- other person, of whose thoughts, actions and sensations, we are not
- conscious. This is sufficiently evident from experience. Our love and
- hatred are always directed to some sensible being external to us; and
- when we talk of _self-love_, 'tis not in a proper sense, nor has the
- sensation it produces any thing in common with that tender emotion,
- which is excited by a friend or mistress. 'Tis the same case with
- hatred. We may be mortified by our own faults and follies; but never
- feel any anger or hatred, except from the injuries of others.
- But though the object of love and hatred be always some other person,
- 'tis plain that the object is not, properly speaking, the _cause_ of
- these passions, or alone sufficient to excite them. For since love
- and hatred are directly contrary in their sensation, and have the
- same object in common, if that object were also their cause, it would
- produce these opposite passions in an equal degree; and as they must,
- from the very first moment, destroy each other, none of them would ever
- be able to make its appearance. There must, therefore, be some cause
- different from the object.
- If we consider the causes of love and hatred, we shall find they are
- very much diversified, and have not many things in common. The virtue,
- knowledge, wit, good sense, good humour of any person, produce love
- and esteem; as the opposite qualities, hatred and contempt. The same
- passions arise from bodily accomplishments, such as beauty, force,
- swiftness, dexterity; and from their contraries; as likewise from the
- external advantages and disadvantages of family, possessions, clothes,
- nation and climate. There is not one of these objects but what, by
- its different qualities, may produce love and esteem, or hatred and
- contempt.
- From the view of these causes we may derive a new distinction betwixt
- the _quality_ that operates, and the _subject_ on which it is placed.
- A prince that is possessed of a stately palace commands the esteem of
- the people upon that account; and that, _first_, by the beauty of the
- palace; and, _secondly_, by the relation of property, which connects it
- with him. The removal of either of these destroys the passion; which
- evidently proves that the cause is a compounded one.
- 'Twould be tedious to trace the passions of love and hatred through all
- the observations which we have formed concerning pride and humility,
- and which are equally applicable to both sets of passions. 'Twill be
- sufficient to _remark_, in general, that the object of love and hatred
- is evidently some thinking person; and that the sensation of the former
- passion is always agreeable, and of the latter uneasy. We may also
- _suppose_, with some show of probability, _that the cause of both these
- passions is always related to a thinking being_, and _that the cause of
- the former produces a separate pleasure, and of the latter a separate
- uneasiness_.
- One of these suppositions, viz. that the cause of love and hatred must
- be related to a person or thinking being, in order to produce these
- passions, is not only probable, but too evident to be contested. Virtue
- and vice, when considered in the abstract; beauty and deformity, when
- placed on inanimate objects; poverty and riches, when belonging to a
- third person, excite no degree of love or hatred, esteem or contempt,
- towards those who have no relation to them. A person looking out at a
- window sees me in the street, and beyond me a beautiful palace, with
- which I have no concern: I believe none will pretend, that this person
- will pay me the same respect as if I were owner of the palace.
- 'Tis not so evident at first sight, that a relation of impressions
- is requisite to these passions, and that because in the transition
- the one impression is so much confounded with the other, that they
- become in a manner undistinguishable. But as in pride and humility,
- we have easily been able to make the separation, and to prove, that
- every cause of these passions produces a separate pain or pleasure, I
- might here observe the same method with the same success, in examining
- particularly the several causes of love and hatred. But as I hasten to
- a full and decisive proof of these systems, I delay this examination
- for a moment; and in the mean time shall endeavour to convert to my
- present purpose all my reasonings concerning pride and humility, by an
- argument that is founded on unquestionable experience.
- There are few persons that are satisfied with their own character,
- or genius, or fortune, who are not desirous of showing themselves to
- the world, and of acquiring the love and approbation of mankind. Now
- 'tis evident, that the very same qualities and circumstances, which
- are the causes of pride or self-esteem, are also the causes of vanity,
- or the desire of reputation; and that we always put to view those
- particulars with which in ourselves we are best satisfied. But if love
- and esteem were not produced by the same qualities as pride, according
- as these qualities are related to ourselves or others, this method of
- proceeding would be very absurd; nor could men expect a correspondence
- in the sentiments of every other person with those themselves have
- entertained. 'Tis true, few can form exact systems of the passions, or
- make reflections on their general nature and resemblances. But without
- such a progress in philosophy, we are not subject to many mistakes in
- this particular, but are sufficiently guided by common experience, as
- well as by a kind of _presentation_, which tells us what will operate
- on others, by what we feel immediately in ourselves. Since then the
- same qualities that produce pride or humility, cause love or hatred,
- all the arguments that have been employed to prove that the causes
- of the former passions excite a pain or pleasure independent of the
- passion, will be applicable with equal evidence to the causes of the
- latter.
- SECTION II.
- EXPERIMENTS TO CONFIRM THIS SYSTEM.
- Upon duly weighing these arguments, no one will make any scruple to
- assent to that conclusion I draw from them, concerning the transition
- along related impressions and ideas, especially as 'tis a principle in
- itself so easy and natural. But that we may place this system beyond
- doubt, both with regard to love and hatred, pride and humility, 'twill
- be proper to make some new experiments upon all these passions, as well
- as to recal a few of these observations which I have formerly touched
- upon.
- In order to make these experiments, let us suppose I am in company with
- a person, whom I formerly regarded without any sentiments either of
- friendship or enmity. Here I have the natural and ultimate object of
- all these four passions placed before me. Myself am the proper object
- of pride or humility; the other person of love or hatred.
- Regard now with attention the nature of these passions, and their
- situation with respect to each other. 'Tis evident here are four
- affections, placed as it were in a square, or regular connexion with,
- and distance from, each other. The passions of pride and humility,
- as well as those of love and hatred, are connected together by the
- identity of their object, which to the first set of passions is self,
- to the second some other person. These two lines of communication or
- connexion form two opposite sides of the square. Again, pride and love
- are agreeable passions; hatred and humility uneasy. This similitude of
- sensation betwixt pride and love, and that betwixt humility and hatred,
- form a new connexion, and may be considered as the other two sides of
- the square. Upon the whole, pride is connected with humility, love
- with hatred, by their objects or ideas: pride with love, humility with
- hatred, by their sensations or impressions.
- I say then, that nothing can produce any of these passions without
- bearing it a double relation, viz. of ideas to the object of the
- passion, and of sensation to the passion itself. This we must prove by
- our experiments.
- _First experiment_. To proceed with the greater order in these
- experiments, let us first suppose, that being placed in the situation
- above mentioned, viz. in company with some other person, there is an
- object presented, that has no relation either of impressions or ideas
- to any of these passions. Thus, suppose we regard together an ordinary
- stone, or other common object, belonging to neither of us, and causing
- of itself no emotion, or independent pain and pleasure: 'tis evident
- such an object will produce none of these four passions. Let us try it
- upon each of them successively. Let us apply it to love, to hatred, to
- humility, to pride; none of them ever arises in the smallest degree
- imaginable. Let us change the object as oft as we please, provided
- still we choose one that has neither of these two relations. Let us
- repeat the experiment in all the dispositions of which the mind is
- susceptible. No object in the vast variety of nature will, in any
- disposition, produce any passion without these relations.
- _Second experiment_. Since an object that wants both these relations
- can ever produce any passion, let us bestow on it only one of these
- relations, and see what will follow. Thus, suppose I regard a stone,
- or any common object that belongs either to me or my companion, and by
- that means acquires a relation of ideas to the object of the passions:
- 'tis plain that, to consider the matter _a priori_, no emotion of
- any kind can reasonably be expected. For, besides that a relation of
- ideas operates secretly and calmly on the mind, it bestows an equal
- impulse towards the opposite passions of pride and humility, love
- and hatred, according as the object belongs to ourselves or others;
- which opposition of the passions must destroy both, and leave the mind
- perfectly free from any affection or emotion. This reasoning _a priori_
- is confirmed by experience. No trivial or vulgar object, that causes
- not a pain or pleasure independent of the passion, will ever, by its
- property or other relations, either to ourselves or others, be able to
- produce the affections of pride or humility, love or hatred.
- _Third experiment_. 'Tis evident, therefore, that a relation of ideas
- is not able alone to give rise to these affections. Let us now remove
- this relation, and, in its stead, place a relation of impressions,
- by presenting an object, which is agreeable or disagreeable, but has
- no relation either to ourself or companion; and let us observe the
- consequences. To consider the matter first _a priori_, as in the
- preceding experiment, we may conclude that the object will have a
- small, but an uncertain connexion with these passions. For, besides
- that this relation is not a cold and imperceptible one, it has not
- the inconvenience of the relation of ideas, nor directs us with equal
- force to two contrary passions, which, by their opposition, destroy
- each other. But if we consider, on the other hand, that this transition
- from the sensation to the affection is not forwarded by any principle
- that produces a transition of ideas; but, on the contrary, that though
- the one impression be easily transfused into the other, yet the change
- of objects is supposed contrary to all the principles that cause a
- transition of that kind; we may from thence infer, that nothing will
- ever be a steady or durable cause of any passion that is connected with
- the passion merely by a relation of impressions. What our reason would
- conclude from analogy, after balancing these arguments, would be, that
- an object, which produces pleasure or uneasiness, but has no manner of
- connexion either with ourselves or others, may give such a turn to the
- disposition as that it may naturally fall into pride or love, humility
- or hatred, and search for other objects, upon which, by a double
- relation, it can found these affections; but that an object, which has
- only one of these relations, though the most advantageous one, can
- never give rise to any constant and established passion.
- Most fortunately, all this reasoning is found to be exactly
- conformable to experience and the phenomena of the passions. Suppose I
- were travelling with a companion through a country to which we are both
- utter strangers; 'tis evident, that if the prospects be beautiful, the
- roads agreeable, and the inns commodious, this may put me into good
- humour both with myself and fellow-traveller. But as we suppose that
- this country has no relation either to myself or friend, it can never
- be the immediate cause of pride or love; and, therefore, if I found
- not the passion on some other object that bears either of us a closer
- relation, my emotions are rather to be considered as the overflowings
- of an elevate or humane disposition, than as an established passion.
- The case is the same where the object produces uneasiness.
- _Fourth experiment_. Having found, that neither an object, without
- any relation of ideas or impressions, nor an object that has only one
- relation, can ever cause pride or humility, love or hatred; reason
- alone may convince us, without any farther experiment, that whatever
- has a double relation must necessarily excite these passions; since
- 'tis evident they must have some cause. But, to leave as little room
- for doubt as possible, let us renew our experiments, and see whether
- the event in this case answers our expectation. I chuse an object,
- such as virtue, that causes a separate satisfaction: on this object
- I bestow a relation to self; and find, that from this disposition of
- affairs there immediately arises a passion. But what passion? That very
- one of pride, to which this object bears a double relation. Its idea
- is related to that of self, the object of the passion: the sensation
- it causes resembles the sensation of the passion. That I may be sure I
- am not mistaken in this experiment, I remove first one relation, then
- another, and find that each removal destroys the passion, and leaves
- the object perfectly indifferent. But I am not content with this. I
- make a still farther trial; and instead of removing the relation,
- I only change it for one of a different kind. I suppose the virtue
- to belong to my companion, not to myself; and observe what follows
- from this alteration. I immediately perceive the affections to wheel
- about, and leaving pride, where there is only one relation, viz.
- of impressions, fall to the side of love, where they are attracted
- by a double relation of impressions and ideas. By repeating the
- same experiment in changing anew the relation of ideas, I bring the
- affections back to pride; and, by a new repetition, I again place them
- at love or kindness. Being fully convinced of the influence of this
- relation, I try the effects of the other; and, by changing virtue for
- vice, convert the pleasant impression which arises from the former,
- into the disagreeable one which proceeds from the latter. The effect
- still answers expectation. Vice, when placed on another, excites,
- by means of its double relations, the passion of hatred, instead of
- love, which, for the same reason, arises from virtue. To continue the
- experiment, I change anew the relation of ideas, and suppose the vice
- to belong to myself. What follows? What is usual. A subsequent change
- of the passion from hatred to humility. This humility I convert into
- pride by a new change of the impression; and find, after all, that I
- have completed the round, and have by these changes brought back the
- passion to that very situation in which I first found it.
- But to make the matter still more certain, I alter the object; and,
- instead of vice and virtue, make the trial upon beauty and deformity,
- riches and poverty, power and servitude. Each of these objects runs
- the circle of the passions in the same manner, by a change of their
- relations: and in whatever order we proceed, whether through pride,
- love, hatred, humility, or through humility, hatred, love, pride,
- the experiment is not in the least diversified. Esteem and contempt,
- indeed, arise on some occasions instead of love and hatred; but these
- are, at the bottom, the same passions, only diversified by some causes,
- which we shall explain afterwards.
- _Fifth experiment_. To give greater authority to these experiments, let
- us change the situation of affairs as much as possible, and place the
- passions and objects in all the different positions of which they are
- susceptible. Let us suppose, beside the relations above mentioned, that
- the person, along with whom I make all these experiments, is closely
- connected with me either by blood or friendship. He is, we shall
- suppose, my son or brother, or is united to me by a long and familiar
- acquaintance. Let us next suppose, that the cause of the passion
- acquires a double relation of impressions and ideas to this person; and
- let us see what the effects are of all these complicated attractions
- and relations.
- Before we consider what they are in fact, let us determine what they
- ought to be, conformable to my hypothesis. 'Tis plain, that, according
- as the impression is either pleasant or uneasy, the passion of love or
- hatred must arise towards the person who is thus connected to the cause
- of the impression by these double relations which I have all along
- required. The virtue of a brother must make me love him, as his vice
- or infamy must excite the contrary passion. But to judge only from the
- situation of affairs, I should not expect that the affections would
- rest there, and never transfuse themselves into any other impression.
- As there is here a person, who, by means of a double relation, is the
- object of my passion, the very same reasoning leads me to think the
- passion will be carried farther. The person has a relation of ideas
- to myself, according to the supposition; the passion of which he is
- the object, by being either agreeable or uneasy, has a relation of
- impressions to pride or humility. 'Tis evident, then, that one of these
- passions must arise from the love or hatred.
- This is the reasoning I form in conformity to my hypothesis; and am
- pleased to find, upon trial, that every thing answers exactly to my
- expectation. The virtue or vice of a son or brother not only excites
- love or hatred, but, by a new transition from similar causes, gives
- rise to pride or humility. Nothing causes greater vanity than any
- shining quality in our relations; as nothing mortifies us more than
- their vice or infamy. This exact conformity of experience to our
- reasoning is a convincing proof of the solidity of that hypothesis upon
- which we reason.
- _Sixth experiment_. This evidence will be still augmented if we reverse
- the experiment, and, preserving still the same relations, begin only
- with a different passion. Suppose that, instead of the virtue or vice
- of a son or brother, which causes first love or hatred, and afterwards
- pride or humility, we place these good or bad qualities on ourselves,
- without any immediate connexion with the person who is related to us,
- experience shows us, that, by this change of situation, the whole
- chain is broke, and that the mind is not conveyed from one passion to
- another, as in the preceding instance. We never love or hate a son or
- brother for the virtue or vice we discern in ourselves; though 'tis
- evident the same qualities in him give us a very sensible pride or
- humility. The transition from pride or humility to love or hatred,
- is not so natural as from love or hatred to pride or humility. This
- may at first sight be esteemed contrary to my hypothesis, since the
- relations of impressions and ideas are in both cases precisely the
- same. Pride and humility are impressions related to love and hatred.
- Myself am related to the person. It should therefore be expected, that
- like causes must produce like effects, and a perfect transition arise
- from the double relation, as in all other cases. This difficulty we may
- easily solve by the following reflections.
- 'Tis evident that, as we are at all times intimately conscious of
- ourselves, our sentiments and passions, their ideas must strike upon us
- with greater vivacity than the ideas of the sentiments and passions of
- any other person. But every thing that strikes upon us with vivacity,
- and appears in a full and strong light, forces itself, in a manner,
- into our consideration, and becomes present to the mind on the smallest
- hint and most trivial relation. For the same reason, when it is once
- present, it engages the attention, and keeps it from wandering to other
- objects, however strong may be their relation to our first object.
- The imagination passes easily from obscure to lively ideas, but with
- difficulty from lively to obscure. In the one case the relation is
- aided by another principle; in the other case, 'tis opposed by it.
- Now, I have observed, that those two faculties of the mind, the
- imagination and passions, assist each other in their operation when
- their propensities are similar, and when they act upon the same object.
- The mind has always a propensity to pass from a passion to any other
- related to it; and this propensity is forwarded when the object of the
- one passion is related to that of the other. The two impulses concur
- with each other, and render the whole transition more smooth and easy.
- But if it should happen, that, while the relation of ideas, strictly
- speaking, continues the same, its influence in causing a transition
- of the imagination should no longer take place, 'tis evident its
- influence on the passions must also cease, as being dependent entirely
- on that transition. This is the reason why pride or humility is not
- transfused into love or hatred with the same ease that the latter
- passions are changed into the former. If a person be my brother, I am
- his likewise: but though the relations be reciprocal, they have very
- different effects on the imagination. The passage is smooth and open
- from the consideration of any person related to us to that of ourself,
- of whom we are every moment conscious. But when the affections are once
- directed to ourself, the fancy passes not with the same facility from
- that object to any other person, how closely soever connected with us.
- This easy or difficult transition of the imagination operates upon the
- passions, and facilitates or retards their transition; which is a clear
- proof that these two faculties of the passions and imagination are
- connected together, and that the relations of ideas have an influence
- upon the affections. Besides innumerable experiments that prove
- this, we here find, that even when the relation remains; if by any
- particular circumstance its usual effect upon the fancy in producing an
- association or transition of ideas is prevented, its usual effect upon
- the passions, in conveying us from one to another, is in like manner
- prevented.
- Some may, perhaps, find a contradiction betwixt this phenomenon
- and that of sympathy, where the mind passes easily from the idea
- of ourselves to that of any other object related to us. But this
- difficulty will vanish, if we consider that in sympathy our own person
- is not the object of any passion, nor is there any thing that fixes our
- attention on ourselves, as in the present case, where we are supposed
- to be actuated, with pride or humility. Ourself, independent of the
- perception of every other object, is in reality nothing; for which
- reason we must turn our view to external objects, and 'tis natural for
- us to consider with most attention such as lie contiguous to us, or
- resemble us. But when self is the object of a passion, 'tis not natural
- to quit the consideration of it till the passion be exhausted, in
- which case the double relations of impressions and ideas can no longer
- operate.
- _Seventh experiment_. To put this whole reasoning to a farther trial,
- let us make a new experiment; and as we have already seen the effects
- of related passions and ideas, let us here suppose an identity of
- passions along with a relation of ideas; and let us consider the
- effects of this new situation. 'Tis evident a transition of the
- passions from the one object to the other is here in all reason to be
- expected; since the relation of ideas is supposed still to continue,
- and an identity of impressions must produce a stronger connexion,
- than the most perfect resemblance that can be imagined. If a double
- relation, therefore, of impressions and ideas, is able to produce a
- transition from one to the other, much more an identity of impressions
- with a relation of ideas. Accordingly, we find, that when we either
- love or hate any person, the passions seldom continue within their
- first bounds; but extend themselves towards all the contiguous
- objects, and comprehend the friends and relations of him we love or
- hate. Nothing is more natural than to bear a kindness to one brother on
- account of our friendship for another, without any farther examination
- of his character. A quarrel with one person gives us a hatred for the
- whole family, though entirely innocent of that which displeases us.
- Instances of this kind are every where to be met with.
- There is only one difficulty in this experiment which it will be
- necessary to account for, before we proceed any farther. 'Tis evident,
- that though all passions pass easily from one object to another related
- to it, yet this transition is made with greater facility where the
- more considerable object is first presented, and the lesser follows
- it, than where this order is reversed, and the lesser takes the
- precedence. Thus, 'tis more natural for us to love the son upon account
- of the father, than the father upon account of the son; the servant
- for the master, than the master for the servant; the subject for the
- prince, than the prince for the subject. In like manner we more readily
- contract a hatred against a whole family, where our first quarrel
- is with the head of it, than where we are displeased with a son, or
- servant, or some inferior member. In short, our passions, like other
- objects, descend with greater facility than they ascend.
- That we may comprehend wherein consists the difficulty of explaining
- this phenomenon, we must consider, that the very same reason, which
- determines the imagination to pass from remote to contiguous objects
- with more facility than from contiguous to remote, causes it likewise
- to change with more ease the less for the greater, than the greater for
- the less. Whatever has the greatest influence is most taken notice of;
- and whatever is most taken notice of, presents itself most readily
- to the imagination. We are more apt to overlook in any subject what
- is trivial, than what appears of considerable moment; but especially
- if the latter takes the precedence, and first engages our attention.
- Thus, if any accident makes us consider the satellites of Jupiter, our
- fancy is naturally determined to form the idea of that planet; but if
- we first reflect on the principal planet, 'tis more natural for us to
- overlook its attendants. The mention of the provinces of any empire
- conveys our thought to the seat of the empire; but the fancy returns
- not with the same facility to the consideration of the provinces.
- The idea of the servant makes us think of the master; that of the
- subject carries our view to the prince. But the same relation has not
- an equal influence in conveying us back again. And on this is founded
- that reproach of Cornelia to her sons, that they ought to be ashamed
- she should be more known by the title of the daughter of Scipio,
- than by that of the mother of the Gracchi. This was, in other words,
- exhorting them to render themselves as illustrious and famous as their
- grandfather, otherwise the imagination of the people, passing from her
- who was intermediate, and placed in an equal relation to both, would
- always leave them, and denominate her by what was more considerable and
- of greater moment. On the same principle is founded that common custom
- of making wives bear the name of their husbands, rather than husbands
- that of their wives; as also the ceremony of giving the precedency to
- those whom we honour and respect. We might find many other instances to
- confirm this principle, were it not already sufficiently evident.
- Now, since the fancy finds the same facility in passing from the
- lesser to the greater, as from remote to contiguous, why does not
- this easy transition of ideas assist the transition of passions in
- the former case as well as in the latter? The virtues of a friend
- or brother produce first love, and then pride; because in that case
- the imagination passes from remote to contiguous, according to its
- propensity. Our own virtues produce not first pride, and then love to
- a friend or brother; because the passage in that case would be from
- contiguous to remote, contrary to its propensity. But the love or
- hatred of an inferior, causes not readily any passion to the superior,
- though that be the natural propensity of the imagination: while the
- love or hatred of a superior, causes a passion to the inferior,
- contrary to its propensity. In short, the same facility of transition
- operates not in the same manner upon superior and inferior as upon
- contiguous and remote. These two phenomena appear contradictory, and
- require some attention to be reconciled.
- As the transition of ideas is here made contrary to the natural
- propensity of the imagination, that faculty must be overpowered by
- some stronger principle of another kind; and as there is nothing ever
- present to the mind but impressions and ideas, this principle must
- necessarily lie in the impressions. Now, it has been observed, that
- impressions or passions are connected only by their resemblance, and
- that where any two passions place the mind in the same or in similar
- dispositions, it very naturally passes from the one to the other: as on
- the contrary, a repugnance in the dispositions produces a difficulty
- in the transition of the passions. But, 'tis observable, that this
- repugnance may arise from a difference of degree as well as of kind;
- nor do we experience a greater difficulty in passing suddenly from a
- small degree of love to a small degree of hatred, than from a small to
- a great degree of either of these affections. A man, when calm or only
- moderately agitated, is so different, in every respect, from himself,
- when disturbed with a violent passion, that no two persons can be more
- unlike; nor is it easy to pass from the one extreme to the other,
- without a considerable interval betwixt them.
- The difficulty is not less, if it be not rather greater in passing
- from the strong passion to the weak, than in passing from the weak to
- the strong, provided the one passion upon its appearance destroys the
- other, and they do not both of them exist at once. But the case is
- entirely altered, when the passions unite together, and actuate the
- mind at the same time. A weak passion, when added to a strong, makes
- not so considerable change in the disposition, as a strong when added
- to a weak; for which reason there is a closer connexion betwixt the
- great degree and the small, than betwixt the small degree and the great.
- The degree of any passion depends upon the nature of its object; and an
- affection directed to a person, who is considerable in our eyes, fills
- and possesses the mind much more than one, which has for its object
- a person we esteem of less consequence. Here then, the contradiction
- betwixt the propensities of the imagination and passion displays
- itself. When we turn our thought to a great and a small object, the
- imagination finds more facility in passing from the small to the great,
- than from the great to the small; but the affections find a greater
- difficulty: and, as the affections are a more powerful principle than
- the imagination, no wonder they prevail over it, and draw the mind to
- their side. In spite of the difficulty of passing from the idea of
- great to that of little, a passion directed to the former produces
- always a similar passion towards the latter, when the great and little
- are related together. The idea of the servant conveys our thought most
- readily to the master; but the hatred or love of the master produces
- with greater facility anger or good will to the servant. The strongest
- passion in this case takes the precedence; and the addition of the
- weaker making no considerable change on the disposition, the passage is
- by that means rendered more easy and natural betwixt them.
- As, in the foregoing experiment, we found that a relation of ideas,
- which, by any particular circumstance, ceases to produce its usual
- effect of facilitating the transition of ideas, ceases likewise to
- operate on the passions; so, in the present experiment, we find the
- same property of the impressions. Two different degrees of the same
- passion are surely related together; but if the smaller be first
- present, it has little or no tendency to introduce the greater; and
- that because the addition of the great to the little produces a more
- sensible alteration on the temper than the addition of the little to
- the great. These phenomena, when duly weighed, will be found convincing
- proofs of this hypothesis.
- And these proofs will be confirmed, if we consider the manner in which
- the mind here reconciles the contradiction I have observed betwixt the
- passions and the imagination. The fancy passes with more facility from
- the less to the greater, than from the greater to the less. But, on the
- contrary, a violent passion produces more easily a feeble than that
- does a violent. In this opposition, the passion in the end prevails
- over the imagination: but 'tis commonly by complying with it, and
- by seeking another quality, which may counterbalance that principle
- from whence the opposition arises. When we love the father or master
- of a family, we think of his children or servants. But when these are
- present with us, or when it lies any ways in our power to serve them,
- the nearness and contiguity in this case increases their magnitude,
- or at least removes that opposition which the fancy makes to the
- transition of the affections. If the imagination finds a difficulty in
- passing from greater to less, it finds an equal facility in passing
- from remote to contiguous, which brings the matter to an equality, and
- leaves the way open from the one passion to the other.
- _Eighth experiment_. I have observed, that the transition from love or
- hatred to pride or humility, is more easy than from pride or humility
- to love or hatred; and that the difficulty which the imagination finds
- in passing from contiguous to remote, is the cause why we scarce have
- any instance of the latter transition of the affections. I must,
- however, make one exception, viz. when the very cause of the pride
- and humility is placed in some other person. For, in that case, the
- imagination is necessitated to consider the person, nor can it possibly
- confine its view to ourselves. Thus, nothing more readily produces
- kindness and affection to any person than his approbation of our
- conduct and character; as, on the other hand, nothing inspires us with
- a stronger hatred than his blame or contempt. Here, 'tis evident, that
- the original passion is pride or humility, whose object is self; and
- that this passion is transfused into love or hatred, whose object is
- some other person, notwithstanding the rule I have already established,
- _that the imagination passes with difficulty from contiguous to
- remote_. But the transition in this case is not made merely on account
- of the relation betwixt ourselves and the person; but because that very
- person is the real cause of our first passion, and, of consequence, is
- intimately connected with it. 'Tis his approbation that produces pride,
- and disapprobation humility. No wonder, then, the imagination returns
- back again attended with the related passions of love and hatred. This
- is not a contradiction, but an exception to the rule; and an exception
- that arises from the same reason with the rule itself.
- Such an exception as this is, therefore, rather a confirmation of the
- rule. And indeed, if we consider all the eight experiments I have
- explained, we shall find that the same principle appears in all of
- them, and that 'tis by means of a transition arising from a double
- relation of impressions and ideas, pride and humility, love and hatred
- are produced. An object without a relation,[1] or with but one,[2]
- never produces either of these passions; and 'tis found[3] that the
- passion always varies in conformity to the relation. Nay we may
- observe, that where the relation, by any particular circumstance, has
- not its usual effect of producing a transition either of ideas or of
- impressions,[4] it ceases to operate upon the passions, and gives
- rise neither to pride nor love, humility nor hatred. This rule we find
- still to hold good, even under the appearance of its contrary;[5] and
- as relation is frequently experienced to have no effect, which upon
- examination is found to proceed from some particular circumstance
- that prevents the transition; so, even in instances where that
- circumstance, though present, prevents not the transition, 'tis found
- to arise from some other circumstance which counterbalances it. Thus,
- not only the variations resolve themselves into the general principle,
- but even the variations of these variations.
- [1] First experiment.
- [2] Second and third experiments.
- [3] Fourth experiment.
- [4] Sixth experiment.
- [5] Seventh and eighth experiments.
- SECTION III.
- DIFFICULTIES SOLVED.
- After so many and such undeniable proofs drawn from daily experience
- and observation, it may seem superfluous to enter into a particular
- examination of all the causes of love and hatred. I shall therefore
- employ the sequel of this part, _first_, in removing some difficulties
- concerning particular causes of these passions; _secondly_, in
- examining the compound affections, which arise from the mixture of love
- and hatred with other emotions.
- Nothing is more evident, than that any person acquires our kindness, or
- is exposed to our ill-will, in proportion to the pleasure or uneasiness
- we receive from him, and that the passions keep pace exactly with the
- sensations in all their changes and variations. Whoever can find the
- means, either by his services, his beauty, or his flattery, to render
- himself useful or agreeable to us, is sure of our affections; as, on
- the other hand, whoever harms or displeases us never fails to excite
- our anger or hatred. When our own nation is at war with any other,
- we detest them under the character of cruel, perfidious, unjust, and
- violent; but always esteem ourselves and allies equitable, moderate,
- and merciful. If the general of our enemies be successful, 'tis with
- difficulty we allow him the figure and character of a man. He is a
- sorcerer; he has a communication with demons, as is reported of Oliver
- Cromwell and the Duke of Luxembourg; he is bloody-minded, and takes a
- pleasure in death and destruction. But if the success be on our side,
- our commander has all the opposite good qualities, and is a pattern
- of virtue, as well as of courage and conduct. His treachery we call
- policy; his cruelty is an evil inseparable from war. In short, every
- one of his faults we either endeavour to extenuate, or dignify it with
- the name of that virtue which approaches it. 'Tis evident the same
- method of thinking rims through common life.
- There are some who add another condition, and require not only that the
- pain and pleasure arise from the person, but likewise that it arise
- knowingly, and with a particular design and intention. A man who wounds
- and harms us by accident, becomes not our enemy upon that account; nor
- do we think ourselves bound, by any ties of gratitude, to one who does
- us any service after the same manner. By the intention we judge of the
- actions; and, according as that is good or bad, they become causes of
- love or hatred.
- But here we must make a distinction. If that quality in another, which
- pleases or displeases, be constant and inherent in his person and
- character, it will cause love or hatred, independent of the intention:
- but otherwise a knowledge and design is requisite, in order to give
- rise to these passions. One that is disagreeable by his deformity or
- folly, is the object of our aversion, though nothing be more certain,
- than that he has not the least intention of displeasing us by these
- qualities. But if the uneasiness proceed not from a quality, but an
- action, which is produced and annihilated in a moment, 'tis necessary,
- in order to produce some relation, and connect this action sufficiently
- with the person, that it be derived from a particular forethought and
- design. 'Tis not enough that the action arise from the person, and
- have him for its immediate cause and author. This relation alone is
- too feeble and inconstant to be a foundation for these passions. It
- reaches not the sensible and thinking part, and neither proceeds from
- any thing _durable_ in him, nor leaves any thing behind it, but passes
- in a moment, and is as if it had never been. On the other hand, an
- intention shows certain qualities, which, remaining after the action is
- performed, connect it with the person, and facilitate the transition
- of ideas from one to the other. We can never think of him without
- reflecting on these qualities, unless repentance and a change of life
- have produced an alteration in that respect; in which case the passion
- is likewise altered. This, therefore, is one reason why an intention is
- requisite to excite either love or hatred.
- But we must farther consider, that an intention, besides its
- strengthening the relation of ideas, is often necessary to produce a
- relation of impressions, and give rise to pleasure and uneasiness. For
- 'tis observable, that the principal part of an injury is the contempt
- and hatred which it shows in the person that injures us; and without
- that, the mere harm gives us a less sensible uneasiness. In like
- manner, a good office is agreeable, chiefly because it flatters our
- vanity, and is a proof of the kindness and esteem of the person who
- performs it. The removal of the intention removes the mortification
- in the one case, and vanity in the other; and must of course cause a
- remarkable diminution in the passions of love and hatred.
- I grant, that these effects of the removal of design, hatred, in
- diminishing the relations of impressions and ideas, are not entire, nor
- able to remove every degree of these relations. But then I ask, if the
- removal of design be able entirely to remove the passion of love and
- hatred? Experience, I am sure, informs us of the contrary, nor is there
- any thing more certain than that men often fall into a violent anger
- for injuries which they themselves must own to be entirely involuntary
- and accidental. This emotion, indeed, cannot be of long continuance,
- but still is sufficient to show, that there is a natural connexion
- betwixt uneasiness and anger, and that the relation of impressions will
- operate upon a very small relation of ideas. But when the violence of
- the impression is once a little abated, the defect of the relation
- begins to be better felt; and as the character of a person is no wise
- interested in such injuries as are casual and involuntary, it seldom
- happens that on their account we entertain a lasting enmity.
- To illustrate this doctrine by a parallel instance, we may observe,
- that not only the uneasiness which proceeds from another by accident,
- has but little force to excite our passion, but also that which arises
- from an acknowledged necessity and duty. One that has a real design of
- harming us, proceeding not from hatred and ill will, but from justice
- and equity, draws not upon him our anger, if we be in any degree
- reasonable; notwithstanding he is both the cause, and the knowing
- cause, of our sufferings. Let us examine a little this phenomenon.
- 'Tis evident, in the first place, that this circumstance is not
- decisive; and though it may be able to diminish the passions, 'tis
- seldom it can entirely remove them. How few criminals are there who
- have no ill will to the person that accuses them, or to the judge that
- condemns them, even though they be conscious of their own deserts!
- In like manner our antagonist in a lawsuit, and our competitor for
- any office, are commonly regarded as our enemies, though we must
- acknowledge, if we would but reflect a moment, that their motive is
- entirely as justifiable as our own.
- Besides we may consider, that when we receive harm from any person,
- we are apt to imagine him criminal, and 'tis with extreme difficulty
- we allow of his justice and innocence. This is a clear proof that,
- independent of the opinion of iniquity, any harm or uneasiness has a
- natural tendency to excite our hatred, and that afterwards we seek for
- reasons upon which we may justify and establish the passion. Here the
- idea of injury produces not the passion, but arises from it.
- Nor is it any wonder that passion should produce the opinion of injury;
- since otherwise it must suffer a considerable diminution, which all the
- passions avoid as much as possible. The removal of injury may remove
- the anger, without proving that the anger arises only from the injury.
- The harm and the justice are two contrary objects, of which the one has
- a tendency to produce hatred, and the other love; and 'tis according
- to their different degrees, and our particular turn of thinking, that
- either of the objects prevails and excites its proper passion.
- SECTION IV.
- OF THE LOVE OF RELATIONS.
- Having given a reason why several actions that cause a real pleasure or
- uneasiness excite not any degree, or but a small one, of the passion of
- love or hatred towards the actors, 'twill be necessary to show wherein
- consists the pleasure or uneasiness of many objects which we find by
- experience to produce these passions.
- According to the preceding system, there is always required a double
- relation of impressions and ideas betwixt the cause and effect, in
- order to produce either love or hatred. But though this be universally
- true, 'tis remarkable that the passion of love may be excited by
- only one _relation_ of a different kind, viz. betwixt ourselves and
- the object; or, more properly speaking, that this relation is always
- attended with both the others. Whoever is united to us by any connexion
- is always sure of a share of our love, proportioned to the connexion,
- without inquiring into his other qualities. Thus, the relation of
- blood produces the strongest tie the mind is capable of in the love of
- parents to their children, and a lesser degree of the same affection
- as the relation lessens. Nor has consanguinity alone this effect, but
- any other relation without exception. We love our countrymen, our
- neighbours, those of the same trade, profession, and even name with
- ourselves. Every one of these relations is esteemed some tie, and gives
- a title to a share of our affection.
- There is another phenomenon which is parallel to this, viz. that
- _acquaintance_, without any kind of relation, gives rise to love and
- kindness. When we have contracted a habitude and intimacy with any
- person, though in frequenting his company we have not been able to
- discover any very valuable quality of which he is possessed; yet we
- cannot forbear preferring him to strangers of whose superior merit we
- are fully convinced. These two phenomena of the effects of relation
- and acquaintance will give mutual light to each other, and may be both
- explained from the same principle.
- Those who take a pleasure in declaiming against human nature have
- observed, that man is altogether insufficient to support himself,
- and that, when you loosen all the holds which he has of external
- objects, he immediately drops down into the deepest melancholy and
- despair. From this, say they, proceeds that continual search after
- amusement in gaming, in hunting, in business, by which we endeavour
- to forget ourselves, and excite our spirits from the languid state
- into which they fall when not sustained by some brisk and lively
- emotion. To this method of thinking I so far agree, that I own the
- mind to be insufficient, of itself, to its own entertainment, and that
- it naturally seeks after foreign objects which may produce a lively
- sensation, and agitate the spirits. On the appearance of such an object
- it awakes, as it were, from a dream; the blood flows with a new tide;
- the heart is elevated; and the whole man acquires a vigour which he
- cannot command in his solitary and calm moments. Hence company is
- naturally so rejoicing, as presenting the liveliest of all objects,
- viz. a rational and thinking being like ourselves, who communicates
- to us all the actions of his mind, makes us privy to his inmost
- sentiments and affections, and lets us see, in the very instant of
- their production, all the emotions which are caused by any object.
- Every lively idea is agreeable, but especially that of a passion,
- because such an idea becomes a kind of passion, and gives a more
- sensible agitation to the mind than any other image or conception.
- This being once admitted, all the rest is easy. For as the company of
- strangers is agreeable to us for _a short time_, by enlivening our
- thought, so the company of our relations and acquaintance must be
- peculiarly agreeable, because it has this effect in a greater degree,
- and is of more _durable_ influence. Whatever is related to us is
- conceived in a lively manner by the easy transition from ourselves
- to the related object. Custom also, or acquaintance, facilitates the
- entrance, and strengthens the conception of any object. The first case
- is parallel to our reasonings from cause and effect; the second to
- education. And as reasoning and education concur only in producing a
- lively and strong idea of any object, so is this the only particular
- which is common to relation and acquaintance. This must therefore be
- the influencing quality by which they produce all their common effects;
- and love or kindness being one of these effects, it must be from the
- force and liveliness of conception that the passion is derived. Such a
- conception is peculiarly agreeable, and makes us have an affectionate
- regard for every thing that produces it, when the proper object of
- kindness and good will.
- 'Tis obvious that people associate together according to their
- particular tempers and dispositions, and that men of gay tempers
- naturally love the gay, as the serious bear an affection to the
- serious. This not only happens where they remark this resemblance
- betwixt themselves and others, but also by the natural course of the
- disposition, and by a certain sympathy which always arises betwixt
- similar characters. Where they remark the resemblance, it operates
- after the manner of a relation by producing a connexion of ideas. Where
- they do not remark it, it operates by some other principle; and if this
- latter principle be similar to the former, it must be received as a
- confirmation of the foregoing reasoning.
- The idea of ourselves is always intimately present to us, and conveys
- a sensible degree of vivacity to the idea of any other object to
- which we are related. This lively idea changes by degrees into a real
- impression; these two kinds of perception being in a great measure the
- same, and differing only in their degrees of force and vivacity. But
- this change must be produced with the greater ease, that our natural
- temper gives us a propensity to the same impression which we observe
- in others, and makes it arise upon any slight occasion. In that case
- resemblance converts the idea into an impression, not only by means
- of the relation, and by transfusing the original vivacity into the
- related idea; but also by presenting such materials as take fire from
- the least spark. And as in both cases a love or affection from the
- resemblance, we may learn that a sympathy with others is agreeable
- only by giving an emotion to the spirits, since an easy sympathy and
- correspondent emotions are alone common to _relation, acquaintance_,
- and _resemblance_.
- The great propensity men have to pride may be considered as another
- similar phenomenon. It often happens, that after we have lived
- a considerable time in any city, however at first it might be
- disagreeable to us, yet as we become familiar with the objects, and
- contract an acquaintance, though merely with the streets and buildings,
- the aversion diminishes by degrees, and at last changes into the
- opposite passion. The mind finds a satisfaction and ease in the view
- of objects to which it is accustomed, and naturally prefers them to
- others, which, though perhaps in themselves more valuable, are less
- known to it. By the same quality of the mind we are seduced into a
- good opinion of ourselves, and of all objects that belong to us. They
- appear in a stronger light, are more agreeable, and consequently fitter
- subjects of pride and vanity than any other.
- It may not be amiss, in treating of the affection we bear our
- acquaintance and relations, to observe some pretty curious phenomena
- which attend it. 'Tis easy to remark in common life, that children
- esteem their relation to their mother to be weakened, in a great
- measure, by her second marriage, and no longer regard her with the same
- eye as if she had continued in her state of widowhood. Nor does this
- happen only when they have felt any inconveniences from her second
- marriage, or when her husband is much her inferior; but even without
- any of these considerations, and merely because she has become part
- of another family. This also takes place with regard to the second
- marriage of a father, but in a much less degree; and 'tis certain the
- ties of blood are not so much loosened in the latter case as by the
- marriage of a mother. These two phenomena are remarkable in themselves,
- but much more so when compared.
- In order to produce a perfect relation betwixt two objects, 'tis
- requisite, not only that the imagination be conveyed from one to the
- other, by resemblance, contiguity or causation, but also that it return
- back from the second to the first with the same ease and facility. At
- first sight this may seem a necessary and unavoidable consequence.
- If one object resemble another, the latter object must necessarily
- resemble the former. If one object be the cause of another, the second
- object is effect to its cause. 'Tis the same with contiguity; and
- therefore the relation being always reciprocal, it may be thought,
- that the return of the imagination from the second to the first must
- also, in every case, be equally natural as its passage from the first
- to the second. But upon farther examination we shall easily discover
- our mistake. For supposing the second object, beside its reciprocal
- relation to the first, to have also a strong relation to a third
- object; in that case the thought, passing from the first object to the
- second, returns not back with the same facility, though the relation
- continues the same, but is readily carried on to the third object,
- by means of the new relation which presents itself, and gives a new
- impulse to the imagination. This new relation, therefore, weakens the
- tie betwixt the first and second objects. The fancy is, by its very
- nature, wavering and inconstant, and considers always two objects as
- more strongly related together, where it finds the passage equally easy
- both in going and returning, than where the transition is easy only in
- one of these motions. The double motion is a kind of a double tie, and
- binds the objects together in the closest and most intimate manner.
- The second marriage of a mother breaks not the relation of child and
- parent; and that relation suffices to convey my imagination from myself
- to her with the greatest ease and facility. But after the imagination
- is arrived at this point of view, it finds its object to be surrounded
- with so many other relations which challenge its regard, that it knows
- not which to prefer, and is at a loss what new object to pitch upon.
- The ties of interest and duty bind her to another family, and prevent
- that return of the fancy from her to myself which is necessary to
- support the union. The thought has no longer the vibration requisite
- to set it perfectly at ease, and indulge its inclination to change.
- It goes with facility, but returns with difficulty; and by that
- interruption finds the relation much weakened from what it would be
- were the passage open and easy on both sides.
- Now, to give a reason why this effect follows not in in the same degree
- upon the second marriage of a father; we may reflect on what has been
- proved already, that though the imagination goes easily from the view
- of a lesser object to that of a greater, yet it returns not with the
- same facility from the greater to the less. When my imagination goes
- from myself to my father, it passes not so readily from him to his
- second wife, nor considers him as entering into a different family,
- but as continuing the head of that family of which I am myself a part.
- His superiority prevents the easy transition of the thought from him
- to his spouse, but keeps the passage still open for a return to myself
- along the same relation of child and parent. He is not sunk in the new
- relation he acquires; so that the double motion or vibration of thought
- is still easy and natural. By this indulgence of the fancy in its
- inconstancy, the tie of child and parent still preserves its full force
- and influence.
- A mother thinks not her tie to a son weakened because 'tis shared with
- her husband; nor a son his with a parent, because 'tis shared with a
- brother. The third object is here related to the first as well as to
- the second: so that the imagination goes and comes along all of them
- with the greatest facility.
- SECTION V.
- OF OUR ESTEEM FOR THE RICH AND POWERFUL.
- Nothing has a greater tendency to give us an esteem for any person than
- his power and riches, or a contempt, than his poverty and meanness:
- and as esteem and contempt are to be considered as species of love and
- hatred, 'twill be proper in this place to explain these phenomena.
- Here it happens, most fortunately, that the greatest difficulty is,
- not to discover a principle capable of producing such an effect,
- but to chuse the chief and predominant among several that present
- themselves. The _satisfaction_ we take in the riches of others, and
- the _esteem_ we have for the possessors, may be ascribed to three
- different causes. _First_, to the objects they possess; such as houses,
- gardens, equipages, which, being agreeable in themselves, necessarily
- produce a sentiment of pleasure in every one that either considers or
- surveys them. _Secondly_, to the expectation of advantage from the
- rich and powerful by our sharing their possessions. _Thirdly_, to
- sympathy, which makes us partake of the satisfaction of every one that
- approaches us. All these principles may concur in producing the present
- phenomenon. The question is, to which of them we ought principally to
- ascribe it.
- 'Tis certain that the first principle, viz. the reflection on
- agreeable objects, has a greater influence than what, at first sight,
- we may be apt to imagine. We seldom reflect on what is beautiful or
- ugly, agreeable or disagreeable, without an emotion of pleasure or
- uneasiness; and though these sensations appear not much, in our common
- indolent way of thinking, 'tis easy, either in reading or conversation,
- to discover them. Men of wit always turn the discourse on subjects
- that are entertaining to the imagination; and poets never present any
- objects but such as are of the same nature. Mr Philips has chosen
- _Cider_ for the subject of an excellent poem. Beer would not have been
- so proper, as being neither so agreeable to the taste nor eye. But he
- would certainly have preferred wine to either of them, could his native
- country have afforded him so agreeable a liquor. We may learn from
- thence, that every thing which is agreeable to the senses, is also, in
- some measure, agreeable to the fancy, and conveys to the thought an
- image of that satisfaction, which it gives by its real application to
- the bodily organs.
- But, though these reasons may induce us to comprehend this delicacy
- of the imagination among the causes of the respect which we pay the
- rich and powerful, there are many other reasons that may keep us from
- regarding it as the sole or principal. For, as the ideas of pleasure
- can have an influence only by means of their vivacity, which makes them
- approach impressions, 'tis most natural those ideas should have that
- influence, which are favoured by most circumstances, and have a natural
- tendency to become strong and lively; such as our ideas of the passions
- and sensations of any human creature. Every human creature resembles
- ourselves, and, by that means, has an advantage above any other object
- in operating on the imagination.
- Besides, if we consider the nature of that faculty, and the great
- influence which all relations have upon it, we shall easily be
- persuaded, that however the ideas of the pleasant wines, music, or
- gardens, which the rich man enjoys, may become lively and agreeable,
- the fancy will not confine itself to them, but will carry its view to
- the related objects, and, in particular, to the person who possesses
- them. And this is the more natural, that the pleasant idea, or image,
- produces here a passion towards the person by means of his relation
- to the object; so that 'tis unavoidable but he must enter into the
- original conception, since he makes the object of the derivative
- passion. But if he enters into the original conception, and is
- considered as enjoying these agreeable objects, 'tis _sympathy_ which
- is properly the cause of the affection; and the _third_ principle is
- more powerful and universal than the _first_.
- Add to this, that riches and power alone, even though unemployed,
- naturally cause esteem and respect; and, consequently, these passions
- arise not from the idea of any beautiful or agreeable objects. 'Tis
- true money implies a kind of representation of such objects by the
- power it affords of obtaining them; and for that reason may still be
- esteemed proper to convey those agreeable images which may give rise to
- the passion. But as this prospect is very distant, 'tis more natural
- for us to take a contiguous object, viz. the satisfaction which this
- power affords the person who is possessed of it. And of this we shall
- be farther satisfied, if we consider that riches represent the goods of
- life only by means of the will which employs them; and therefore imply,
- in their very nature, an idea of the person, and cannot be considered
- without a kind of sympathy with his sensations and enjoyments.
- This we may confirm by a reflection which to some will perhaps appear
- too subtile and refined. I have already observed that power, as
- distinguished from its exercise, has either no meaning at all, or is
- nothing but a possibility or probability of existence, by which any
- object approaches to reality, and has a sensible influence on the
- mind. I have also observed, that this approach, by an illusion of the
- fancy, appears much greater when we ourselves are possessed of the
- power than when it is enjoyed by another; and that, in the former case,
- the objects seem to touch upon the very verge of reality, and convey
- almost an equal satisfaction as if actually in our possession. Now I
- assert, that where we esteem a person upon account of his riches, we
- must enter into this sentiment of the proprietor, and that, without
- such a sympathy, the idea of the agreeable objects, which they give
- him the power to produce, would have but a feeble influence upon
- us. An avaricious man is respected for his money, though he scarce
- is possessed of a _power_; that is, there scarce is a _probability_
- or even _possibility_ of his employing it in the acquisition of the
- pleasures and conveniences of life. To himself alone this power seems
- perfect and entire; and therefore we must receive his sentiments by
- sympathy, before we can have a strong intense idea of these enjoyments,
- or esteem him upon account of them.
- Thus we have found, that the _first_ principle, viz. _the agreeable
- idea of those objects which riches afford the enjoyment of_, resolves
- itself in a great measure into the _third_, and becomes a _sympathy_
- with the person we esteem or love. Let us now examine the _second_
- principle, viz. _the agreeable expectation of advantage_, and see what
- force we may justly attribute to it.
- 'Tis obvious, that, though riches and authority undoubtedly give
- their owner a power of doing us service, yet this power is not to be
- considered as on the same footing with that which they afford him
- of pleasing himself, and satisfying his own appetites. Self-love
- approaches the power and exercise very near each other in the latter
- case; but in order to produce a similar effect in the former, we must
- suppose a friendship and good-will to be conjoined with the riches.
- Without that circumstance 'tis difficult to conceive on what we can
- found our hope of advantage from the riches of others, though there
- is nothing more certain than that we naturally esteem and respect the
- rich, even before we discover in them any such favourable disposition
- towards us.
- But I carry this farther, and observe, not only that we respect the
- rich and powerful where they show no inclination to serve us, but also
- when we lie so much out of the sphere of their activity, that they
- cannot even be supposed to be endowed with that power. Prisoners of
- war are always treated with a respect suitable to their condition; and
- 'tis certain riches go very far towards fixing the condition of any
- person. If birth and quality enter for a share, this still affords us
- an argument of the same kind. For what is it we call a man of birth,
- but one who is descended from a long succession of rich and powerful
- ancestors, and who acquires our esteem by his relation to persons whom
- we esteem? His ancestors, therefore, though dead, are respected in some
- measure on account of their riches, and consequently without any kind
- of expectation.
- But not to go so far as prisoners of war and the dead to find instances
- of this disinterested esteem for riches, let us observe, with a
- little attention, those phenomena that occur to us in common life and
- conversation. A man who is himself of a competent fortune, upon coming
- into a company of strangers, naturally treats them with different
- degrees of respect and deference, as he is informed of their different
- fortunes and conditions; though 'tis impossible he can ever propose,
- and perhaps would not accept of any advantage from them. A traveller is
- always admitted into company, and meets with civility in proportion as
- his train and equipage speak him a man of great or moderate fortune.
- In short, the different ranks of men are in a great measure regulated
- by riches, and that with regard to superiors as well as inferiors,
- strangers as well as acquaintance.
- There is, indeed, an answer to these arguments, drawn from the
- influence of _general rules_. It may be pretended, that, being
- accustomed to expect succour and protection from the rich and powerful,
- and to esteem them upon that account, we extend the same sentiments to
- those who resemble them in their fortune, but from whom we can never
- hope for any advantage. The general rule still prevails, and, by giving
- a bent to the imagination draws along the passion, in the same manner
- as if its proper object were real and existent.
- But that this principle does not here take place, will easily appear,
- if we consider that, in order to establish a general rule, and extend
- it beyond its proper bounds, there is required a certain uniformity
- in our experience, and a great superiority of those instances, which
- are conformable to the rule, above the contrary. But here the case is
- quite otherwise. Of a hundred men of credit and fortune I meet with,
- there is not perhaps one from whom I can expect advantage, so that 'tis
- impossible any custom can ever prevail in the present case.
- Upon the whole, there remains nothing which can give us an esteem for
- power and riches, and a contempt for meanness and poverty, except the
- pride of _sympathy_, by which we enter into the sentiments of rich
- and poor, and partake of their pleasure and uneasiness. Riches give
- satisfaction to their possessor; and this satisfaction is conveyed to
- the beholder by the imagination, which produces an idea resembling
- the original impression in force and vivacity. This agreeable idea or
- impression is connected with love, which is an agreeable passion. It
- proceeds from a thinking conscious being, which is the very object of
- love. From this relation of impressions, and identity of ideas, the
- passion arises according to my hypothesis.
- The best method of reconciling us to this opinion, is to take a general
- survey of the universe, and observe the force of sympathy through the
- whole animal creation, and the easy communication of sentiments from
- one thinking being to another. In all creatures that prey not upon
- others, and are not agitated with violent passions, there appears a
- remarkable desire of company, which associates them together, without
- any advantages they can ever propose to reap from their union. This is
- still more conspicuous in man, as being the creature of the universe
- who has the most ardent desire of society, and is fitted for it by
- the most advantages. We can form no wish which has not a reference to
- society. A perfect solitude is, perhaps, the greatest punishment we can
- suffer. Every pleasure languishes when enjoyed apart from company, and
- every pain becomes more cruel and intolerable. Whatever other passions
- we may be actuated by, pride, ambition, avarice, curiosity, revenge
- or lust, the soul or animating principle of them all is sympathy;
- nor would they have any force, were we to abstract entirely from the
- thoughts and sentiments of others. Let all the powers and elements of
- nature conspire to serve and obey one man; let the sun rise and set
- at his command; the sea and rivers roll as he pleases, and the earth
- furnish spontaneously whatever may be useful or agreeable to him; he
- will still be miserable, till you give him some one person at least
- with whom he may share his happiness, and whose esteem and friendship
- he may enjoy.
- This conclusion, from a general view of human nature, we may confirm by
- particular instances, wherein the force of sympathy is very remarkable.
- Most kinds of beauty are derived from this origin; and though our first
- object be some senseless inanimate piece of matter, 'tis seldom we rest
- there, and carry not our view to its influence on sensible and rational
- creatures. A man who shows us any house or building, takes particular
- care, among other things, to point out the convenience of the
- apartments, the advantages of their situation, and the little room lost
- in the stairs, anti-chambers and passages; and indeed 'tis evident the
- chief part of the beauty consists in these particulars. The observation
- of convenience gives pleasure, since convenience is a beauty. But after
- what manner does it give pleasure? 'Tis certain our own interest is not
- in the least concerned; and as this is a beauty of interest, not of
- form, so to speak, it must delight us merely by communication, and by
- our sympathizing with the proprietor of the lodging. We enter into his
- interest by the force of imagination, and feel the same satisfaction
- that the objects naturally occasion in him.
- This observation extends to tables, chairs, scrutoires, chimneys,
- coaches, saddles, ploughs, and indeed to every work of art; it being
- an universal rule, that their beauty is chiefly derived from their
- utility, and from their fitness for that purpose, to which they are
- destined. But this is an advantage that concerns only the owner, nor is
- there any thing but sympathy, which can interest the spectator.
- 'Tis evident that nothing renders a field more agreeable than its
- fertility, and that scarce any advantages of ornament or situation will
- be able to equal this beauty. 'Tis the same case with particular trees
- and plants, as with the field on which they grow. I know not but a
- plain, overgrown with furze and broom, may be, in itself, as beautiful
- as a hill covered with vines or olive trees, though it will never
- appear so to one who is acquainted with the value of each. But this is
- a beauty merely of imagination, and has no foundation in what appears
- to the senses. Fertility and value have a plain reference to use; and
- that to riches, joy, and plenty, in which, though we have no hope of
- partaking, yet we enter into them by the vivacity of the fancy, and
- share them in some measure with the proprietor.
- There is no rule in painting more reasonable than that of balancing the
- figures, and placing them with the greatest exactness on their proper
- centre of gravity.
- A figure which is not justly balanced is disagreeable; and that because
- it conveys the ideas of its fall, of harm, and of pain; which ideas are
- painful when by sympathy they acquire any degree of force and vivacity.
- Add to this, that the principal part of personal beauty is an air
- of health and vigour, and such a construction of members as promises
- strength and activity. This idea of beauty cannot be accounted for but
- by sympathy.
- In general we may remark, that the minds of men are mirrors to one
- another, not only because they reflect each others emotions, but also
- because those rays of passions, sentiments and opinions, may be often
- reverberated, and may decay away by insensible degrees. Thus, the
- pleasure which a rich man receives from his possessions, being thrown
- upon the beholder, causes a pleasure and esteem; which sentiments again
- being perceived and sympathized with, increase the pleasure of the
- possessor, and, being once more reflected, become a new foundation for
- pleasure and esteem in the beholder. There is certainly an original
- satisfaction in riches derived from that power which they bestow of
- enjoying all the pleasures of life; and as this is their very nature
- and essence, it must be the first source of all the passions which
- arise from them. One of the most considerable of these passions is
- that of love or esteem in others, which, therefore, proceeds from a
- sympathy with the pleasure of the possessor. But the possessor has also
- a secondary satisfaction in riches, arising from the love and esteem
- he acquires by them; and this satisfaction is nothing but a second
- reflection of that original pleasure which proceeded from himself.
- This secondary satisfaction or vanity becomes one of the principal
- recommendations of riches, and is the chief reason why we either
- desire them for ourselves, or esteem them in others. Here then is a
- third rebound of the original pleasure, after which 'tis difficult to
- distinguish the images and reflections, by reason of their faintness
- and confusion.
- SECTION VI.
- OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER.
- Ideas may be compared to the extension and solidity of matter and
- impressions, especially reflective ones, to colours, tastes, smells,
- and other sensible qualities. Ideas never admit of a total union, but
- are endowed with a kind of impenetrability by which they exclude each
- other, and are capable of forming a compound by their conjunction,
- not by their mixture. On the other hand, impressions and passions are
- susceptible of an entire union, and, like colours, may be blended so
- perfectly together, that each of them may lose itself, and contribute
- only to vary that uniform impression which arises from the whole. Some
- of the most curious phenomena of the human mind are derived from this
- property of the passions.
- In examining those ingredients which are capable of uniting with love
- and hatred, I begin to be sensible, in some measure, of a misfortune
- that has attended every system of philosophy with which the world
- has been yet acquainted. 'Tis commonly found, that in accounting
- for the operations of nature by any particular hypothesis, among a
- number of experiments that quadrate exactly with the principles we
- would endeavour to establish, there is always some phenomenon which
- is more stubborn, and will not so easily bend to our purpose. We need
- not be surprised that this should happen in natural philosophy. The
- essence and composition of external bodies are so obscure, that we
- must necessarily, in our reasonings, or rather conjectures concerning
- them, involve ourselves in contradictions and absurdities. But as
- the perceptions of the mind are perfectly known, and I have used all
- imaginable caution in forming conclusions concerning them, I have
- always hoped to keep clear of those contradictions which have attended
- every other system. Accordingly, the difficulty which I have at present
- in my eye is no wise contrary to my system, but only departs a little
- from that simplicity which has been hitherto its principal force and
- beauty.
- The passions of love and hatred are always followed by, or rather
- conjoined with, benevolence and anger. 'Tis this conjunction which
- chiefly distinguishes these affections from pride and humility. For
- pride and humility are pure emotions in the soul, unattended with any
- desire, and not immediately exciting us to action. But love and hatred
- are not completed within themselves, nor rest in that emotion which
- they produce, but carry the mind to something farther. Love is always
- followed by a desire of the happiness of the person beloved, and an
- aversion to his misery: as hatred produces a desire of the misery,
- and an aversion to the happiness of the person hated. So remarkable a
- difference betwixt these two sets of passions of pride and humility,
- love and hatred, which in so many other particulars correspond to each
- other, merits our attention.
- The conjunction of this desire and aversion with love and hatred may
- be accounted for by two different hypotheses. The first is, that love
- and hatred have not only a _cause_ which excites them, viz. pleasure
- and pain, and an _object_ to which they are directed, viz. a person or
- thinking being, but likewise an _end_ which they endeavour to attain,
- viz. the happiness or misery of the person beloved or hated; all which
- views, mixing together, make only one passion. According to this
- system, love is nothing but the desire of happiness to another person,
- and hatred that of misery. The desire and aversion constitute the very
- nature of love and hatred. They are not only inseparable, but the same.
- But this is evidently contrary to experience. For though 'tis certain
- we never love any person without desiring his happiness, nor hate any
- without wishing his misery, yet these desires arise only upon the ideas
- of the happiness or misery of our friend or enemy being presented by
- the imagination, and are not absolutely essential to love and hatred.
- They are the most obvious and natural sentiments of these affections,
- but not the only ones. The passions may express themselves in a hundred
- ways, and may subsist a considerable time, without our reflecting on
- the happiness or misery of their objects; which clearly proves that
- these desires are not the same with love and hatred, nor make any
- essential part of them.
- We may therefore infer, that benevolence and anger are passions
- different from love and hatred, and only conjoined with them by the
- original constitution of the mind. As nature has given to the body
- certain appetites and inclinations, which she increases, diminishes,
- or changes according to the situation of the fluids or solids, she
- has proceeded in the same manner with the mind. According as we
- are possessed with love or hatred, the correspondent desire of the
- happiness or misery of the person who is the object of these passions,
- arises in the mind, and varies with each variation of these opposite
- passions. This order of things, abstractedly considered, is not
- necessary. Love and hatred might have been unattended with any such
- desires, or their particular connexion might have been entirely
- reversed. If nature had so pleased, love might have had the same effect
- as hatred, and hatred as love. I see no contradiction in supposing a
- desire of producing misery annexed to love, and of happiness to hatred.
- If the sensation of the passion and desire be opposite, nature could
- have altered the sensation without altering the tendency of the desire,
- and by that means made them compatible with each other.
- SECTION VII.
- OF COMPASSION.
- But though the desire of the happiness or misery of others, according
- to the love or hatred we bear them, be an arbitrary and original
- instinct implanted in our nature, we find it may be counterfeited on
- many occasions, and may arise from secondary principles. _Pity_ is
- a concern for, and _malice_ a joy in, the misery of others, without
- any friendship or enmity to occasion this concern or joy. We pity
- even strangers, and such as are perfectly indifferent to us: and
- if our ill-will to another proceed from any harm or injury, it is
- not, properly speaking, malice, but revenge. But if we examine these
- affections of pity and malice, we shall find them to be secondary ones,
- arising from original affections, which are varied by some particular
- turn of thought and imagination.
- 'Twill be easy to explain the passion of _pity_, from the precedent
- reasoning concerning _sympathy_. We have a lively idea of every thing
- related to us. All human creatures are related to us by resemblance.
- Their persons, therefore, their interests, their passions, their pains
- and pleasures, must strike upon us in a lively manner, and produce an
- emotion similar to the original one, since a lively idea is easily
- converted into an impression. If this be true in general, it must be
- more so of affliction and sorrow. These have always a stronger and more
- lasting influence than any pleasure or enjoyment.
- A spectator of a tragedy passes through a long train of grief, terror,
- indignation, and other affections, which the poet represents in the
- persons he introduces. As many tragedies end happily, and no excellent
- one can be composed without some reverses of fortune, the spectator
- must sympathize with all these changes, and receive the fictitious
- joy as well as every other passion. Unless therefore it be asserted,
- that every distinct passion is communicated by a distinct original
- quality, and is not derived from the general principle of sympathy
- above explained, it must be allowed that all of them arise from
- that principle. To except any one in particular must appear highly
- unreasonable. As they are all first present in the mind of one person,
- and afterwards appear in the mind of another; and as the manner of
- their appearance, first as an idea, then as an impression, is in every
- case the same, the transition must arise from the same principle. I am
- at least sure, that this method of reasoning would be considered as
- certain, either in natural philosophy or common life.
- Add to this, that pity depends, in a great measure, on the contiguity,
- and even sight of the object, which is a proof that 'tis derived from
- the imagination; not to mention that women and children are most
- subject to pity, as being most guided by that faculty. The same
- infirmity, which makes them faint at the sight of a naked sword, though
- in the hands of their best friend, makes them pity extremely those
- whom they find in any grief or affliction. Those philosophers, who
- derive this passion from I know not what subtile reflections on the
- instability of fortune, and our being liable to the same miseries we
- behold, will find this observation contrary to them among a great many
- others, which it were easy to produce.
- There remains only to take notice of a pretty remarkable phenomenon
- of this passion, which is, that the communicated passion of sympathy
- sometimes acquires strength from the weakness of its original, and
- even arises by a transition from affections which have no existence.
- Thus, when a person obtains any honourable office, or inherits a
- great fortune, we are always the more rejoiced for his prosperity,
- the less sense he seems to have of it, and the greater equanimity and
- indifference he shows in its enjoyment. In like manner, a man who
- is not dejected by misfortunes is the more lamented on account of
- his patience; and if that virtue extends so far as utterly to remove
- all sense of uneasiness, it still farther increases our compassion.
- When a person of merit falls into what is vulgarly esteemed a great
- misfortune, we form a notion of his condition; and, carrying our fancy
- from the cause to the usual effect, first conceive a lively idea of
- his sorrow, and then feel an impression of it, entirely overlooking
- that greatness of mind which elevates him above such emotions, or
- only considering it so far as to increase our admiration, love, and
- tenderness for him. We find from experience, that such a degree of
- passion is usually connected with such a misfortune; and though there
- be an exception in the present case, yet the imagination is affected
- by the _general rule_, and makes us conceive a lively idea of the
- passion, or rather feel the passion itself in the same manner as if
- the person were really actuated by it. From the same principles we
- blush for the conduct of those who behave themselves foolishly before
- us, and that though they show no sense of shame, nor seem in the least
- conscious of their folly. All this proceeds from sympathy, but 'tis
- of a partial kind, and views its objects only on one side, without
- considering the other, which has a contrary effect, and would entirely
- destroy that emotion which arises from the first appearance.
- We have also instances wherein an indifference and insensibility
- under misfortune increases our concern for the misfortunate, even
- though the indifference proceed not from any virtue and magnanimity.
- 'Tis an aggravation of a murder, that it was committed upon persons
- asleep and in perfect security; as historians readily observe of any
- infant prince, who is captive in the hands of his enemies, that he is
- more worthy of compassion the less sensible he is of his miserable
- condition. As we ourselves are here acquainted with the wretched
- situation of the person, it gives us a lively idea and sensation of
- sorrow, which is the passion that _generally_ attends it; and this idea
- becomes still more lively, and the sensation more violent by a contrast
- with that security and indifference which we observe in the person
- himself. A contrast of any kind never fails to effect the imagination,
- especially when presented by the subject; and 'tis on the imagination
- that pity entirely depends.[6]
- [6] To prevent all ambiguity, I must observe, that where I oppose the
- imagination to the memory, I mean in general the faculty that presents
- our fainter ideas. In all other places, and particularly when it is
- opposed to the understanding, I understand the same faculty, excluding
- only our demonstrative and probable reasonings.
- SECTION VIII.
- OF MALICE AND ENVY.
- We must now proceed to account for the passion of _malice_, which
- imitates the effects of hatred as pity does those of love, and gives us
- a joy in the sufferings and miseries of others, without any offence or
- injury on their part.
- So little are men governed by reason in their sentiments and opinions,
- that they always judge more of objects by comparison than from their
- intrinsic worth and value. When the mind considers, or is accustomed
- to any degree of perfection, whatever falls short of it, though really
- estimable, has, notwithstanding, the same effect upon the passions as
- what is defective and ill. This is an _original_ quality of the soul,
- and similar to what we have every day experience of in our bodies.
- Let a man heat one hand and cool the other; the same water will at
- the same time seem both hot and cold, according to the disposition
- of the different organs. A small degree of any quality, succeeding a
- greater, produces the same sensation as if less than it really is, and
- even sometimes as the opposite quality. Any gentle pain that follows a
- violent one, seems as nothing, or rather becomes a pleasure; as, on the
- other hand, a violent pain succeeding a gentle one, is doubly grievous
- and uneasy.
- This no one can doubt of with regard to our passions and sensations.
- But there may arise some difficulty with regard to our ideas and
- objects. When an object augments or diminishes to the eye or
- imagination, from a comparison with others, the image and idea of the
- object are still the same, and are equally extended in the _retina_,
- and in the brain or organ of perception. The eyes refract the rays of
- light, and the optic nerves convey the images to the brain in the very
- same manner, whether a great or small object has preceded; nor does
- even the imagination alter the dimensions of its object on account of
- a comparison with others. The question then is, how, from the same
- impression, and the same idea, we can form such different judgments
- concerning the same object, and at one time admire its bulk, and at
- another despise its littleness? This variation in our judgments must
- certainly proceed from a variation in some perception; but as the
- variation lies not in the immediate impression or idea of the object,
- it must lie in some other impression that accompanies it.
- In order to explain this matter, I shall just touch upon two
- principles, one of which shall be more fully explained in the progress
- of this Treatise; the other has been already accounted for. I believe
- it may safely be established for a general maxim, that no object is
- presented to the senses, nor image formed in the fancy, but what is
- accompanied with some emotion or movement of spirits proportioned
- to it; and however custom may make us insensible of this sensation,
- and cause us to confound it with the object or idea, 'twill be easy,
- by careful and exact experiments, to separate and distinguish them.
- For, to instance only in the cases of extension and number, 'tis
- evident that any very bulky object, such as the ocean, an extended
- plain, a vast chain of mountains, a wide forest; or any very numerous
- collection of objects, such as an army, a fleet, a crowd, excite in
- the mind a sensible emotion; and that the admiration which arises on
- the appearance of such objects is one of the most lively pleasures
- which human nature is capable of enjoying. Now, as this admiration
- increases or diminishes by the increase or diminution of the objects,
- we may conclude, according to our foregoing principles,[7] that 'tis
- a compound effect, proceeding from the conjunction of the several
- effects which arise from each part of the cause. Every part, then, of
- extension, and every unite of number, has a separate emotion attending
- it when conceived by the mind; and though that emotion be not always
- agreeable, yet, by its conjunction with others, and by its agitating
- the spirits to a just pitch, it contributes to the production of
- admiration, which is always agreeable. If this be allowed with respect
- to extension and number, we can make no difficulty with respect to
- virtue and vice, wit and folly, riches and poverty, happiness and
- misery, and other objects of that kind, which are always attended with
- an evident emotion.
- The second principle I shall take notice of is that of our adherence
- to _general rules_; which has such a mighty influence on the actions
- and understanding, and is able to impose on the very senses. When an
- object is found by experience to be always accompanied with another,
- whenever the first object appears, though changed in very material
- circumstances, we naturally fly to the conception of the second, and
- form an idea of it in as lively and strong a manner, as if we had
- inferred its existence by the justest and most authentic conclusion
- of our understanding. Nothing can undeceive us, not even our senses,
- which, instead of correcting this false judgment, are often perverted
- by it, and seem to authorize its errors.
- The conclusion I draw from these two principles, joined to the
- influence of comparison above-mentioned, is very short and decisive.
- Every object is attended with some emotion proportioned to it; a great
- object with a great emotion, a small object with a small emotion.
- A great _object_, therefore, succeeding a small one, makes a great
- _emotion_ succeed a small one. Now, a great emotion succeeding a small
- one becomes still greater, and rises beyond its ordinary proportion.
- But as there is a certain degree of an emotion which commonly attends
- every magnitude of an object, when the emotion increases, we naturally
- imagine that the object has likewise increased. The effect conveys
- our view to its usual cause, a certain degree of emotion to a certain
- magnitude of the object; nor do we consider, that comparison may
- change the emotion without changing any thing in the object. Those
- who are acquainted with the metaphysical part of optics, and know how
- we transfer the judgments and conclusions of the understanding to the
- senses, will easily conceive this whole operation.
- But leaving this new discovery of an impression that secretly attends
- every idea, we must at least allow of that principle from whence the
- discovery arose, _that objects appear greater or less by a comparison
- with others_. We have so many instances of this, that it is impossible
- we can dispute its veracity; and 'tis from this principle I derive the
- passions of malice and envy.
- 'Tis evident we must receive a greater or less satisfaction or
- uneasiness from reflecting on our own condition and circumstances,
- in proportion as they appear more or less fortunate or unhappy,
- in proportion to the degrees of riches, and power, and merit, and
- reputation, which we think ourselves possest of. Now, as we seldom
- judge of objects from their intrinsic value, but form our notions of
- them from a comparison with other objects, it follows, that according
- as we observe a greater or less share of happiness or misery in others,
- we must make an estimate of our own, and feel a consequent pain or
- pleasure. The misery of another gives us a more lively idea of our
- happiness, and his happiness of our misery. The former, therefore,
- produces delight, and the latter uneasiness.
- Here then is a kind of pity reverst, or contrary sensations arising
- in the beholder, from those which are felt by the person whom he
- considers. In general we may observe, that, in all kinds of comparison,
- an object makes us always receive from another, to which it is
- compared, a sensation contrary to what arises from itself in its direct
- and immediate survey. A small object makes a great one appear still
- greater. A great object makes a little one appear less. Deformity of
- itself produces uneasiness, but makes us receive new pleasure by its
- contrast with a beautiful object, whose beauty is augmented by it; as,
- on the other hand, beauty, which of itself produces pleasure, makes us
- receive a new pain by the contrast with any thing ugly, whose deformity
- it augments. The case, therefore, must be the same with happiness and
- misery. The direct survey of another's pleasure naturally gives us
- pleasure, and therefore produces pain when compared with our own. His
- pain, considered in itself, is painful to us, but augments the idea of
- our own happiness, and gives us pleasure.
- Nor will it appear strange, that we may feel a reverst sensation from
- the happiness and misery of others, since we find the same comparison
- may give us a kind of malice against ourselves, and make us rejoice for
- our pains, and grieve for our pleasures. Thus, the prospect of past
- pain is agreeable, when we are satisfied with our present condition;
- as, on the other hand, our past pleasures give us uneasiness, when we
- enjoy nothing at present equal to them. The comparison being the same
- as when we reflect on the sentiments of others, must be attended with
- the same effects.
- Nay, a person may extend this malice against himself, even to his
- present fortune, and carry it so far as designedly to seek affliction,
- and increase his pains and sorrows. This may happen upon two occasions.
- _First_, Upon the distress and misfortune of a friend, or person dear
- to him. _Secondly_, Upon the feeling any remorses for a crime of
- which he has been guilty. 'Tis from the principle of comparison that
- both these irregular appetites for evil arise. A person who indulges
- himself in any pleasure while his friend lies under affliction, feels
- the reflected uneasiness from his friend more sensibly by a comparison
- with the original pleasure which he himself enjoys. This contrast,
- indeed, ought also to enliven the present pleasure. But as grief is
- here supposed to be the predominant passion, every addition falls to
- that side, and is swallowed up in it, without operating in the least
- upon the contrary affection. 'Tis the same case with those penances
- which men inflict on themselves for their past sins and failings. When
- a criminal reflects on the punishment he deserves, the idea of it is
- magnified by a comparison with his present ease and satisfaction, which
- forces him, in a manner, to seek uneasiness, in order to avoid so
- disagreeable a contrast.
- This reasoning will account for the origin of envy as well as of
- malice. The only difference betwixt these passions lies in this,
- that envy is excited by some present enjoyment of another, which, by
- comparison, diminishes our idea of our own: whereas malice is the
- unprovoked desire of producing evil to another, in order to reap a
- pleasure from the comparison. The enjoyment, which is the object of
- envy, is commonly superior to our own. A superiority naturally seems to
- overshade us, and presents a disagreeable comparison. But even in the
- case of an inferiority, we still desire a greater distance, in order to
- augment still more the idea of ourself. When this distance diminishes,
- the comparison is, less to our advantage, and consequently gives us
- less pleasure, and is even disagreeable. Hence arises that species of
- envy which men feel, when they perceive their inferiors approaching or
- overtaking them in the pursuit of glory or happiness. In this envy we
- may see the effects of comparison twice repeated. A man, who compares
- himself to his inferior, receives a pleasure from the comparison; and
- when the inferiority decreases by the elevation of the inferior, what
- should only have been a decrease of pleasure, becomes a real pain, by a
- new comparison with its preceding condition.
- 'Tis worthy of observation concerning that envy which arises from a
- superiority in others, that 'tis not the great disproportion betwixt
- ourself and another, which produces it; but, on the contrary, our
- proximity. A common soldier bears no such envy to his general as
- to his sergeant or corporal; nor does an eminent writer meet with
- so great jealousy in common hackney scribblers, as in authors that
- more nearly approach him. It may indeed be thought, that the greater
- the disproportion is, the greater must be the uneasiness from the
- comparison. But we may consider on the other hand, that the great
- disproportion cuts off the relation, and either keeps us from comparing
- ourselves, with what is remote from us, or diminishes the effects of
- the comparison. Resemblance and proximity always produce a relation of
- ideas; and where you destroy these ties, however other accidents may
- bring two ideas together, as they have no bond or connecting quality
- to join them in the imagination, 'tis impossible they can remain long
- united, or have any considerable influence on each other.
- I have observed, in considering the nature of ambition, that the great
- feel a double pleasure in authority, from the comparison of their own
- condition with that of their slaves; and that this comparison has a
- double influence, because 'tis natural, and presented by the subject.
- When the fancy, in the comparison of objects, passes not easily from
- the one object to the other, the action of the mind is in a great
- measure broke, and the fancy, in considering the second object, begins,
- as it were, upon a new footing. The impression which attends every
- object, seems not greater in that case by succeeding a less of the
- same kind; but these two impressions are distinct, and produce their
- distinct effects, without any communication together. The want of
- relation in the ideas breaks the relation of the impressions, and by
- such a separation prevents their mutual operation and influence.
- To confirm this we may observe, that the proximity in the degree
- of merit is not alone sufficient to give rise to envy, but must be
- assisted by other relations. A poet is not apt to envy a philosopher,
- or a poet of a different kind, of a different nation, or a different
- age. All these differences prevent or weaken the comparison, and
- consequently the passion.
- This too is the reason why all objects appear great or little, merely
- by a comparison with those of the same species. A mountain neither
- magnifies nor diminishes a horse in our eyes; but when a Flemish and a
- Welsh horse are seen together, the one appears greater and the other
- less, then when viewed apart.
- From the same principle we may account for that remark of historians,
- that any party in a civil war always choose to call in a foreign enemy
- at any hazard, rather than submit to their fellow-citizens. Guicciardin
- applies this remark to the wars in Italy, where the relations betwixt
- the different states are, properly speaking, nothing but of name,
- language, and contiguity. Yet even these relations, when joined with
- superiority, by making the comparison more natural, make it likewise
- more grievous, and cause men to search for some other superiority,
- which may be attended with no relation, and by that means may have a
- less sensible influence on the imagination. The mind quickly perceives
- its several advantages and disadvantages; and finding its situation to
- be most uneasy, where superiority is conjoined with other relations,
- seeks its repose as much as possible by their separation, and by
- breaking that association of ideas, which renders the comparison
- so much more natural and efficacious. When it cannot break the
- association, it feels a stronger desire to remove the superiority;
- and this is the reason why travellers are commonly so lavish of their
- praises to the Chinese and Persians, at the same time that they
- depreciate those neighbouring nations which may stand upon a foot of
- rivalship with their native country.
- These examples from history and common experience are rich and
- curious; but we may find parallel ones in the arts, which are no less
- remarkable. Should an author compose a treatise, of which one part
- was serious and profound, another light and humorous, every one would
- condemn so strange a mixture, and would accuse him of the neglect
- of all rules of art and criticism. These rules of art are founded
- on the qualities of human nature; and the quality of human nature,
- which requires a consistency in every performance, is that which
- renders the mind incapable of passing in a moment from one passion and
- disposition to a quite different one. Yet this makes us not blame Mr
- Prior for joining his Alma and his Solomon in the same volume; though
- that admirable poet has succeeded perfectly well in the gaiety of the
- one, as well as in the melancholy of the other. Even supposing the
- reader should peruse these two compositions without any interval, he
- would feel little or no difficulty in the change of passions: why? but
- because he considers these performances as entirely different, and, by
- this break in the ideas, breaks the progress of the affections, and
- hinders the one from influencing or contradicting the other.
- An heroic and burlesque design, united in one picture, would be
- monstrous; though we place two pictures of so opposite a character in
- the same chamber, and even close by each other, without any scruple or
- difficulty.
- In a word, no ideas can affect each other, either by comparison, or by
- the passions they separately produce, unless they be united together
- by some relation which may cause an easy transition of the ideas, and
- consequently of the emotions or impressions attending the ideas, and
- may preserve the one impression in the passage of the imagination
- to the object of the other. This principle is very remarkable,
- because it is analogous to what we have observed both concerning the
- _understanding_ and the _passions_. Suppose two objects to be presented
- to me, which are not connected by any kind of relation. Suppose that
- each of these objects separately produces a passion, and that these
- two passions are in themselves contrary; we find from experience,
- that the want of relation in the objects or ideas hinders the natural
- contrariety of the passions, and that the break in the transition of
- the thought removes the affections from each other, and prevents their
- opposition. 'Tis the same case with comparison; and from both these
- phenomena we may safely conclude, that the relation of ideas must
- forward the transition of impressions, since its absence alone is able
- to prevent it, and to separate what naturally should have operated
- upon each other. When the absence of an object or quality removes any
- usual or natural effect, we may certainly conclude that its presence
- contributes to the production of the effect.
- [7] Book I. Part III. Sect. 15.
- SECTION IX.
- OF THE MIXTURE OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER
- WITH COMPASSION AND MALICE.
- Thus we have endeavoured to account for _pity_ and _malice_. Both these
- affections arise from the imagination, according to the light in which
- it places its object. When our fancy considers directly the sentiments
- of others, and enters deep into them, it makes us sensible of all the
- passions it surveys, but in a particular manner of grief or sorrow.
- On the contrary, when we compare the sentiments of others to our own,
- we feel a sensation directly opposite to the original one, viz. a joy
- from the grief of others, and a grief from their joy. But these are
- only the first foundations of the affections of pity and malice. Other
- passions are afterwards confounded with them. There is always a mixture
- of love or tenderness with pity, and of hatred or anger with malice.
- But it must be confessed, that this mixture seems at first sight to be
- contradictory to my system. For as pity is an uneasiness, and malice a
- joy, arising from the misery of others, pity should naturally, as in
- all other cases, produce hatred, and malice, love. This contradiction I
- endeavour to reconcile, after the following manner.
- In order to cause a transition of passions, there is required a double
- relation of impressions and ideas; nor is one relation sufficient to
- produce this effect. But that we may understand the full force of this
- double relation, we must consider, that 'tis not the present sensation
- alone or momentary pain or pleasure, which determines the character of
- any passion, but the whole bent or tendency of it from the beginning
- to the end. One impression may be related to another, not only when
- their sensations are resembling, as we have all along supposed in the
- preceding cases, but also when their impulses or directions are similar
- and correspondent. This cannot take place with regard to pride and
- humility, because these are only pure sensations, without any direction
- or tendency to action. We are, therefore, to look for instances of
- this peculiar relation of impressions only in such affections as are
- attended with a certain appetite or desire, such as those of love and
- hatred.
- Benevolence, or the appetite which attends love, is a desire of the
- happiness of the person beloved, and an aversion to his misery, as
- anger, or the appetite which attends hatred, is a desire of the misery
- of the person hated, and an aversion to his happiness. A desire,
- therefore, of the happiness of another, and aversion to his misery,
- are similar to benevolence; and a desire of his misery and aversion
- to his happiness, are correspondent to anger. Now, pity is a desire
- of happiness to another, and aversion to his misery, as malice is the
- contrary appetite. Pity, then, is related to benevolence, and malice to
- anger; and as benevolence has been already found to be connected with
- love, by a natural and original quality, and anger with hatred, 'tis by
- this chain the passions of pity and malice are connected with love and
- hatred.
- This hypothesis is founded on sufficient experience. A man, who, from
- any motives, has entertained a resolution of performing an action,
- naturally runs into every other view or motive which may fortify that
- resolution, and give it authority and influence on the mind. To confirm
- us in any design, we search for motives drawn from interest, from
- honour, from duty. What wonder, then, that pity and benevolence, malice
- and anger, being the same desires arising from different principles,
- should so totally mix together as to be undistinguishable? As to
- the connexion betwixt benevolence and love, anger and hatred, being
- _original_ and primary, it admits of no difficulty.
- We may add to this another experiment, viz. that benevolence and anger,
- and, consequently, love and hatred, arise when our happiness or misery
- have any dependence on the happiness or misery of another person,
- without any farther relation. I doubt not but this experiment will
- appear so singular as to excuse us for stopping a moment to consider it.
- Suppose that two persons of the same trade should seek employment in a
- town that is not able to maintain both, 'tis plain the success of one
- is perfectly incompatible with that of the other; and that whatever
- is for the interest of either is contrary to that of his rival, and
- so _vice versa_. Suppose, again, that two merchants, though living
- in different parts of the world, should enter into co-partnership
- together, the advantage or loss of one becomes immediately the
- advantage or loss of his partner, and the same fortune necessarily
- attends both. Now, 'tis evident, that, in the first case, hatred
- always follows upon the contrariety of interests; as, in the second,
- love arises from their union. Let us consider to what principle we can
- ascribe these passions.
- 'Tis plain they arise, not from the double relations of impressions and
- ideas, if we regard only the present sensation. For, taking the first
- case of rivalship, though the pleasure and advantage of an antagonist
- necessarily causes my pain and loss, yet, to counterbalance this,
- his pain and loss causes my pleasure and advantage; and, supposing
- him to be unsuccessful, I may, by this means, receive from him a
- superior degree of satisfaction. In the same manner the success of a
- partner rejoices me, but then his misfortunes afflict me in an equal
- proportion; and 'tis easy to imagine that the latter sentiment may, in
- some cases, preponderate. But whether the fortune of a rival or partner
- be good or bad, I always hate the former and love the latter.
- This love of a partner cannot proceed from the relation or connexion
- betwixt us, in the same manner as I love a brother or countryman. A
- rival has almost as close a relation to me as a partner. For, as the
- pleasure of the latter causes my pleasure, and his pain my pain; so the
- pleasure of the former causes my pain, and his pain my pleasure. The
- connexion, then, of cause and effect, is the same in both cases; and
- if, in the one case, the cause and effect has a farther relation of
- resemblance, they have that of contrariety in the other; which, being
- also a species of resemblance, leaves the matter pretty equal.
- The only explication, then, we can give of this phenomenon, is derived
- from that principle of a parallel direction above-mentioned. Our
- concern for our own interest gives us a pleasure in the pleasure, and
- a pain in the pain of a partner, after the same manner as by sympathy
- we feel a sensation correspondent to those which appear in any person
- who is present with us. On the other hand, the same concern for our
- interest makes us feel a pain in the pleasure, and a pleasure in the
- pain of a rival; and, in short, the same contrariety of sentiments
- as arises from comparison and malice. Since, therefore, a parallel
- direction of the affections, proceeding from interest, can give rise to
- benevolence or anger, no wonder the same parallel direction, derived
- from sympathy and from comparison, should have the same effect.
- In general we may observe, that 'tis impossible to do good to others,
- from whatever motive, without feeling some touches of kindness and
- good will towards them; as the injuries we do not only cause hatred in
- the person who suffers them, but even in ourselves. These phenomena,
- indeed, may in part be accounted for from other principles.
- But here there occurs a considerable objection, which 'twill be
- necessary to examine before we proceed any farther. I have endeavoured
- to prove that power and riches, or poverty and meanness, which give
- rise to love or hatred, without producing any original pleasure or
- uneasiness, operate upon us by means of a secondary sensation derived
- from a sympathy with that pain or satisfaction which they produce in
- the person who possesses them. From a sympathy with his pleasure there
- arises love; from that with his uneasiness, hatred. But 'tis a maxim
- which I have just now established, and which is absolutely necessary
- to the explication of the phenomena of pity and malice, "That 'tis not
- the present sensation or momentary pain or pleasure which determines
- the character of any passion, but the general bent or tendency of it
- from the beginning to the end." For this reason, pity or a sympathy
- with pain produces love, and that because it interests us in the
- fortunes of others, good or bad, and gives us a secondary sensation
- correspondent to the primary, in which it has the same influence with
- love and benevolence. Since, then, this rule holds good in one case,
- why does it not prevail throughout, and why does sympathy in uneasiness
- ever produce any passion beside good will and kindness? Is it becoming
- a philosopher to alter his method of reasoning, and run from one
- principle to its contrary, according to the particular phenomenon which
- he would explain?
- I have mentioned two different causes from which a transition of
- passion may arise, viz. a double relation of ideas and impressions,
- and, what is similar to it, a conformity in the tendency and direction
- of any two desires which arise from different principles. Now I
- assert, that when a sympathy with uneasiness is weak, it produces
- hatred or contempt by the former cause; when strong, it produces love
- or tenderness by the latter. This is the solution of the foregoing
- difficulty, which seems so urgent; and this is a principle founded on
- such evident arguments, that we ought to have established it, even
- though it were not necessary to the explication of any phenomenon.
- 'Tis certain, that sympathy is not always limited to the present
- moment, but that we often feel, by communication, the pains and
- pleasures of others which are not in being, and which we only
- anticipate by the force of imagination. For, supposing I saw a person
- perfectly unknown to me, who, while asleep in the fields, was in danger
- of being trod under foot by horses, I should immediately run to his
- assistance; and in this I should be actuated by the same principle
- of sympathy which makes me concerned for the present sorrows of a
- stranger. The bare mention of this is sufficient. Sympathy being
- nothing but a lively idea converted into an impression, 'tis evident
- that, in considering the future possible or probable condition of any
- person, we may enter into it with so vivid a conception as to make it
- our own concern, and by that means be sensible of pains and pleasures
- which neither belong to ourselves, nor at the present instant have any
- real existence.
- But however we may look forward to the future in sympathizing with any
- person, the extending of our sympathy depends in a great measure upon
- our sense of his present condition. 'Tis a great effort of imagination
- to form such lively ideas even of the present sentiments of others as
- to feel these very sentiments; but 'tis impossible we could extend this
- sympathy to the future without being aided by some circumstance in the
- present, which strikes upon us in a lively manner. When the present
- misery of another has any strong influence upon me, the vivacity of the
- conception is not confined merely to its immediate object, but diffuses
- its influence over all the related ideas, and gives me a lively notion
- of all the circumstances of that person, whether past, present, or
- future; possible, probable, or certain. By means of this lively notion
- I am interested in them, take part with them, and feel a sympathetic
- motion in my breast, conformable to whatever I imagine in his. If I
- diminish the vivacity of the first conception, I diminish that of the
- related ideas; as pipes can convey no more water than what arises at
- the fountain. By this diminution I destroy the future prospect which
- is necessary to interest me perfectly in the fortune of another. I may
- feel the present impression, but carry my sympathy no farther, and
- never transfuse the force of the first conception into my ideas of the
- related objects. If it be another's misery which is presented in this
- feeble manner, I receive it by communication, and am affected with all
- the passions related to it: but as I am not so much interested as to
- concern myself in his good fortune as well as his bad, I never feel the
- extensive sympathy, nor the passions related to _it_.
- Now, in order to know what passions are related to these different
- kinds of sympathy, we must consider that benevolence is an original
- pleasure arising from the pleasure of the person beloved, and a pain
- proceeding from his pain: from which correspondence of impressions
- there arises a subsequent desire of his pleasure, and aversion to his
- pain. In order, then, to make a passion run parallel with benevolence,
- 'tis requisite we should feel these double impressions, correspondent
- to those of the person whom we consider; nor is any one of them
- alone sufficient for that purpose. When we sympathize only with one
- impression, and that a painful one, this sympathy is related to anger
- and to hatred, upon account of the uneasiness it conveys to us. But as
- the extensive or limited sympathy depends upon the force of the first
- sympathy, it follows that the passion of love or hatred depends upon
- the same principle. A strong impression, when communicated, gives a
- double tendency of the passions, which is related to benevolence and
- love by a similarity of direction, however painful the first impression
- might have been. A weak impression that is painful is related to
- anger and hatred by the resemblance of sensations. Benevolence,
- therefore, arises from a great degree of misery, or any degree strongly
- sympathized with: hatred or contempt from a small degree, or one weakly
- sympathized with; which is the principle I intended to prove and
- explain.
- Nor have we only our reason to trust to for this principle, but
- also experience. A certain degree of poverty produces contempt; but
- a degree beyond causes compassion and good will. We may undervalue
- a peasant or servant; but when the misery of a beggar appears very
- great, or is painted in very lively colours, we sympathize with him
- in his afflictions, and feel in our heart evident touches of pity and
- benevolence. The same object causes contrary passions, according to its
- different degrees. The passions, therefore, must depend upon principles
- that operate in such certain degrees, according to my hypothesis. The
- increase of the sympathy has evidently the same effect as the increase
- of the misery.
- A barren or desolate country always seems ugly and disagreeable,
- and commonly inspires us with contempt for the inhabitants. This
- deformity, however, proceeds in a great measure from a sympathy
- with the inhabitants, as has been already observed; but it is only
- a weak one, and reaches no farther than the immediate sensation,
- which is disagreeable. The view of a city in ashes conveys benevolent
- sentiments; because we there enter so deep into the interests of the
- miserable inhabitants, as to wish for their prosperity, as well as feel
- their adversity.
- But though the force of the impression generally produces pity and
- benevolence, 'tis certain that, by being carried too far, it ceases
- to have that effect. This, perhaps, may be worth our notice. When the
- uneasiness is either small in itself, or remote from us, it engages
- not the imagination, nor is able to convey an equal concern for the
- future and contingent good, as for the present and real evil. Upon its
- acquiring greater force, we become so interested in the concerns of the
- person, as to be sensible both of his good and bad fortune; and from
- that complete sympathy there arises pity and benevolence. But 'twill
- easily be imagined, that where the present evil strikes with more than
- ordinary force, it may entirely engage our attention, and prevent that
- double sympathy above mentioned. Thus we find, that though every one,
- but especially women, are apt to contract a kindness for criminals who
- go to the scaffold, and readily imagine them to be uncommonly handsome
- and well-shaped; yet one who is present at the cruel execution of the
- rack, feels no such tender emotions; but is in a manner overcome with
- horror, and has no leisure to temper this uneasy sensation by any
- opposite sympathy.
- But the instance which makes the most clearly for my hypothesis, is
- that wherein, by a change of the objects, we separate the double
- sympathy even from a middling degree of the passion; in which case we
- find that pity, instead of producing love and tenderness as usual,
- always gives rise to the contrary affection. When we observe a person
- in misfortune, we are affected with pity and love; but the author of
- that misfortune becomes the object of our strongest hatred, and is the
- more detested in proportion to the degree of our compassion. Now, for
- what reason should the same passion of pity produce love to the person
- who suffers the misfortune, and hatred to the person who causes it;
- unless it be because, in the latter case, the author bears a relation
- only to the misfortune; whereas, in considering the sufferer, we carry
- our view on every side, and wish for his prosperity, as well as are
- sensible of his affliction?
- I shall just observe, before I leave the present subject, that this
- phenomenon of the double sympathy, and its tendency to cause love,
- may contribute to the production of the kindness which we naturally
- bear our relations and acquaintance. Custom and relation make us enter
- deeply into the sentiments of others; and whatever fortune we suppose
- to attend them, is rendered present to us by the imagination, and
- operates as if originally our own. We rejoice in their pleasures, and
- grieve for their sorrows, merely from the force of sympathy. Nothing
- that concerns them is indifferent to us; and as this correspondence of
- sentiments is the natural attendant of love, it readily produces that
- affection.
- SECTION X.
- OF RESPECT AND CONTEMPT.
- There now remains only to explain the passions of _respect_ and
- _contempt_, along with the _amorous_ affection, in order to understand
- all the passions which have any mixture of love or hatred. Let us begin
- with respect and contempt.
- In considering the qualities and circumstances of others, we may either
- regard them as they really are in themselves; or may make a comparison
- betwixt them and our own qualities and circumstances; or may join these
- two methods of consideration. The good qualities of others, from the
- first point of view, produce love; from the second, humility; and, from
- the third, respect; which is a mixture of these two passions. Their bad
- qualities, after the same manner, cause either hatred, or pride, or
- contempt, according to the light in which we survey them.
- That there is a mixture of pride in contempt, and of humility in
- respect, is, I think, too evident, from their very feeling or
- appearance, to require any particular proof. That this mixture arises
- from a tacit comparison of the person contemned or respected with
- ourselves, is no less evident. The same man may cause either respect,
- love, or contempt, by his condition and talents, according as the
- person who considers him, from his inferior, becomes his equal or
- superior. In changing the point of view, though the object may remain
- the same, its proportion to ourselves entirely alters; which is the
- cause of an alteration in the passions. These passions, therefore,
- arise from our observing the proportion, that is, from a comparison.
- I have already observed, that the mind has a much stronger propensity
- to pride than to humility, and have endeavoured, from the principles
- of human nature, to assign a cause for this phenomenon. Whether my
- reasoning be received or not, the phenomenon is undisputed, and appears
- in many instances. Among the rest, 'tis the reason why there is a much
- greater mixture of pride in contempt, than of humility in respect, and
- why we are more elevated with the view of one below us, than mortified
- with the presence of one above us. Contempt or scorn has so strong a
- tincture of pride, that there scarce is any other passion discernible:
- Whereas in esteem or respect, love makes a more considerable ingredient
- than humility. The passion of vanity is so prompt, that it rouses at
- the least call; while humility requires a stronger impulse to make it
- exert itself.
- But here it may reasonably be asked, why this mixture takes place only
- in some cases, and appears not on every occasion. All those objects
- which cause love, when placed on another person, are the causes of
- pride when transferred to ourselves; and consequently ought to be
- causes of humility as well as love while they belong to others, and are
- only compared to those which we ourselves possess. In like manner every
- quality, which, by being directly considered, produces hatred, ought
- always to give rise to pride by comparison, and, by a mixture of these
- passions of hatred and pride, ought to excite contempt or scorn. The
- difficulty then is, why any objects ever cause pure love or hatred,
- and produce not always the mixt passions of respect and contempt.
- I have supposed all along that the passions of love and pride, and
- those of humility and hatred, are similar in their sensations, and that
- the two former are always agreeable, and that the two latter painful.
- But though this be universally true, 'tis observable, that the two
- agreeable as well as the two painful passions, have some differences,
- and even contrarieties, which distinguish them. Nothing invigorates and
- exalts the mind equally with pride and vanity; though at the same time
- love or tenderness is rather found to weaken and enfeeble it. The same
- difference is observable betwixt the uneasy passions. Anger and hatred
- bestow a new force on all our thoughts and actions; while humility and
- shame deject and discourage us. Of these qualities of the passions,
- 'twill be necessary to form a distinct idea. Let us remember that pride
- and hatred invigorate the soul, and love and humility enfeeble it.
- From this it follows, that though the conformity betwixt love and
- hatred in the agreeableness of their sensation makes them always be
- excited by the same objects, yet this other contrariety is the reason
- why they are excited in very different degrees. Genius and learning are
- _pleasant_ and _magnificent_ objects, and by both these circumstances
- are adapted to pride and vanity, but have a relation to love by their
- pleasure only. Ignorance and simplicity are _disagreeable_ and _mean_,
- which in the same manner gives them a double connexion with humility,
- and a single one with hatred. We may, therefore, consider it as
- certain, that though the same object always produces love and pride,
- humility and hatred, according to its different situations, yet it
- seldom produces either the two former or the two latter passions in the
- same proportion.
- 'Tis here we must seek for a solution of the difficulty
- above-mentioned, why any object ever excites pure love or hatred, and
- does not always produce respect or contempt, by a mixture of humility
- or pride. No quality in another gives rise to humility by comparison,
- unless it would have produced pride by being placed in ourselves;
- and, _vice versa_, no object excites pride by comparison, unless it
- would have produced humility by the direct survey. This is evident,
- objects always produce by _comparison_ a sensation directly contrary to
- their _original_ one. Suppose, therefore, an object to be presented,
- which is peculiarly fitted to produce love, but imperfectly to excite
- pride, this object, belonging to another, gives rise directly to a
- great degree of love, but to a small one of humility by comparison;
- and consequently that latter passion is scarce felt in the compound,
- nor is able to convert the love into respect. This is the case with
- good nature, good humour, facility, generosity, beauty, and many other
- qualities. These have a peculiar aptitude to produce love in others;
- but not so great a tendency to excite pride in ourselves: for which
- reason the view of them, as belonging to another person, produces pure
- love, with but a small mixture of humility and respect. 'Tis easy to
- extend the same reasoning to the opposite passions.
- Before we leave this subject, it may not be amiss to account for a
- pretty curious phenomenon, viz. why we commonly keep at a distance
- such as we contemn, and allow not our inferiors to approach too near
- even in place and situation. It has already been observed, that almost
- every kind of ideas is attended with some emotion, even the ideas of
- number and extension, much more those of such objects as are esteemed
- of consequence in life, and fix our attention. 'Tis not with entire
- indifference we can survey either a rich man or a poor one, but must
- feel some faint touches, at least, of respect in the former case, and
- of contempt in the latter. These two passions are contrary to each
- other; but in order to make this contrariety be felt, the objects must
- be someway related; otherwise the affections are totally separate and
- distinct, and never encounter. The relation takes place wherever the
- persons become contiguous; which is a general reason why we are uneasy
- at seeing such disproportioned objects as a rich man and a poor one, a
- nobleman and a porter, in that situation.
- This uneasiness, which is common to every spectator, must be more
- sensible to the superior; and that because the near approach of the
- inferior is regarded as a piece of ill breeding, and shows that he is
- not sensible of the disproportion, and is no way affected by it. A
- sense of superiority in another breeds in all men an inclination to
- keep themselves at a distance from him, and determines them to redouble
- the marks of respect and reverence, when they are obliged to approach
- him; and where they do not observe that conduct, 'tis a proof they are
- not sensible of his superiority. From hence too it proceeds, that any
- great _difference_ in the degrees of any quality is called a _distance_
- by a common metaphor, which, however trivial it may appear, is founded
- on natural principles of the imagination. A great difference inclines
- us to produce a distance. The ideas of distance and difference are,
- therefore, connected together. Connected ideas are readily taken for
- each other; and this is in general the source of the metaphor, as we
- shall have occasion to observe afterwards.
- SECTION XI.
- OF THE AMOROUS PASSION, OR LOVE BETWIXT THE SEXES.
- Of all the compound passions which proceed from a mixture of love and
- hatred with other affections, no one better deserves our attention,
- than that love which arises betwixt the sexes, as well on account of
- its force and violence, as those curious principles of philosophy, for
- which it affords us an uncontestable argument. 'Tis plain that this
- affection, in its most natural state, is derived from the conjunction
- of three different impressions or passions, viz. the pleasing sensation
- arising from beauty; the bodily appetite for generation; and a generous
- kindness or good will. The origin of kindness from beauty may be
- explained from the foregoing reasoning. The question is, how the bodily
- appetite is excited by it.
- The appetite of generation, when confined to a certain degree, is
- evidently of the pleasant kind, and has a strong connexion with all
- the agreeable emotions. Joy, mirth, vanity, and kindness, are all
- incentives to this desire, as well as music, dancing, wine, and good
- cheer. On the other hand, sorrow, melancholy, poverty, humility are
- destructive of it. From this quality, 'tis easily conceived why it
- should be connected with the sense of beauty.
- But there is another principle that contributes to the same effect.
- I have observed that the parallel direction of the desires is a real
- relation, and, no less than a resemblance in their sensation, produces
- a connexion among them. That we may fully comprehend the extent of
- this relation, we must consider that any principal desire may be
- attended with subordinate ones, which are connected with it, and to
- which, if other desires are parallel, they are by that means related to
- the principal one. Thus, hunger may oft be considered as the primary
- inclination of the soul, and the desire of approaching the meat as the
- secondary one, since 'tis absolutely necessary to the satisfying that
- appetite. If an object, therefore, by any separate qualities, inclines
- us to approach the meat, it naturally increases our appetite; as on the
- contrary, whatever inclines us to set our victuals at a distance, is
- contradictory to hunger, and diminishes our inclination to them. Now,
- 'tis plain, that beauty has the first effect, and deformity the second;
- which is the reason why the former gives us a keener appetite for
- our victuals, and the latter is sufficient to disgust us at the most
- savoury dish that cookery has invented. All this is easily applicable
- to the appetite for generation.
- From these two relations, viz. resemblance and a parallel desire,
- there arises such a connexion betwixt the sense of beauty, the bodily
- appetite, and benevolence, that they become in a manner inseparable;
- and we find from experience, that 'tis indifferent which of them
- advances first, since any of them is almost sure to be attended with
- the related affections. One who is inflamed with lust, feels at least
- a momentary kindness towards the object of it, and at the same time
- fancies her more beautiful than ordinary; as there are many, who
- begin with kindness and esteem for the wit and merit of the person,
- and advance from that to the other passions. But the most common
- species of love is that which first arises from beauty, and afterwards
- diffuses itself into kindness, and into the bodily appetite. Kindness
- or esteem, and the appetite to generation, are too remote to unite
- easily together. The one is, perhaps, the most refined passion of the
- soul, the other the most gross and vulgar. The love of beauty is placed
- in a just medium betwixt them, and partakes of both their natures; from
- whence it proceeds, that 'tis so singularly fitted to produce both.
- This account of love is not peculiar to my system, but is unavoidable
- on any hypothesis. The three affections which compose this passion are
- evidently distinct, and has each of them its distinct object. 'Tis
- certain, therefore, that 'tis only by their relation they produce each
- other. But the relation of passions is not alone sufficient. 'Tis
- likewise necessary there should be a relation of ideas. The beauty of
- one person never inspires us with love for another. This then is a
- sensible proof of the double relation of impressions and ideas. From
- one instance so evident as this we may form a judgment of the rest.
- This may also serve in another view to illustrate what I have insisted
- on concerning the origin of pride and humility, love and hatred. I have
- observed, that though self be the object of the first set of passions,
- and some other person of the second, yet these objects cannot alone
- be the causes of the passions, as having each of them a relation to
- two contrary affections, which must from the very first moment destroy
- each other. Here then is the situation of the mind, as I have already
- described it. It has certain organs naturally fitted to produce a
- passion; that passion, when produced, naturally turns the view to a
- certain object. But this not being sufficient to produce the passion,
- there is required some other emotion, which, by a double relation of
- impressions and ideas, may set these principles in action, and bestow
- on them their first impulse. This situation is still more remarkable
- with regard to the appetite of generation. Sex is not only the object,
- but also the cause of the appetite. We not only turn our view to it,
- when actuated by that appetite, but the reflecting on it suffices to
- excite the appetite. But as this cause loses its force by too great
- frequency, 'tis necessary it should be quickened by some new impulse;
- and that impulse we find to arise from the _beauty_ of the _person_;
- that is, from a double relation of impressions and ideas. Since this
- double relation is necessary where an affection has both a distinct
- cause and object, how much more so where it has only a distinct object
- without any determinate cause!
- SECTION XII.
- OF THE LOVE AND HATRED OF ANIMALS.
- But to pass from the passions of love and hatred, and from their
- mixtures and compositions, as they appear in man, to the same
- affections as they display themselves in brutes, we may observe, not
- only that love and hatred are common to the whole sensitive creation,
- but likewise that their causes, as above explained, are of so simple
- a nature that they may easily be supposed to operate on mere animals.
- There is no force of reflection or penetration required. Every thing
- is conducted by springs and principles, which are not peculiar to man,
- or any one species of animals. The conclusion from this is obvious in
- favour of the foregoing system.
- Love, in animals, has not for its only object animals of the same
- species, but extends itself farther, and comprehends almost every
- sensible and thinking being. A dog naturally loves a man above his own
- species, and very commonly meets with a return of affection.
- As animals are but little susceptible either of the pleasures or pains
- of the imagination, they can judge of objects only by the sensible
- good or evil which they produce, and from _that_ must regulate their
- affections towards them. Accordingly we find, that by benefits or
- injuries we produce their love or hatred; and that, by feeding and
- cherishing any animal, we quickly acquire his affections; as by beating
- and abusing him we never fail to draw on us his enmity and ill-will.
- Love in beasts is not caused so much by relation as in our species; and
- that because their thoughts are not so active as to trace relations,
- except in very obvious instances. Yet 'tis easy to remark, that on
- some occasions it has a considerable influence upon them. Thus,
- acquaintance, which has the same effect as relation, always produces
- love in animals, either to men or to each other. For the same reason,
- any likeness among them is the source of affection. An ox confined to a
- park with horses, will naturally join their company, if I may so speak,
- but always leaves it to enjoy that of his own species, where he has the
- choice of both.
- The affection of parents to their young proceeds from a peculiar
- instinct in animals, as well as in our species.
- 'Tis evident that _sympathy_, or the communication of passions, takes
- place among animals, no less than among men. Fear, anger, courage,
- and other affections, are frequently communicated from one animal to
- another, without their knowledge of that cause which produced the
- original passion. Grief likewise is received by sympathy, and produces
- almost all the same consequences, and excites the same emotions, as in
- our species. The howlings and lamentations of a dog produce a sensible
- concern in his fellows. And 'tis remarkable, that though almost all
- animals use in play the same member, and nearly the same action as
- in fighting; a lion, a tiger, a cat, their paws; an ox, his horns;
- a dog, his teeth; a horse, his heels: yet they most carefully avoid
- harming their companion, even though they have nothing to fear from his
- resentment; which is an evident proof of the sense brutes have of each
- other's pain and pleasure.
- Every one has observed how much more dogs are animated when they hunt
- in a pack, than when they pursue their game apart; and 'tis evident
- this can proceed from nothing but from sympathy. 'Tis also well known
- to hunters, that this effect follows in a greater degree, and even in
- too great a degree, where too packs that are strangers to each other
- are joined together. We might, perhaps, be at a loss to explain this
- phenomenon, if we had not experience of a similar in ourselves.
- Envy and malice are passions very remarkable in animals. They are
- perhaps more common than pity; as requiring less effort of thought and
- imagination.
- PART III.
- OF THE WILL AND DIRECT PASSIONS.
- SECTION I.
- OF LIBERTY AND NECESSITY.
- We come now to explain the _direct_ passions, or the impressions which
- arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. Of this
- kind are, _desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear._
- Of all the immediate effects of pain and pleasure, there is none more
- remarkable than the _will_; and though, properly speaking, it be not
- comprehended among the passions, yet, as the full understanding of its
- nature and properties is necessary to the explanation of them, we shall
- here make it the subject of our inquiry. I desire it may be observed,
- that, by the _will_, I mean nothing but _the internal impression we
- feel, and are conscious of, when we knowingly give rise to any new
- motion of our body, or new perception of our mind_. This impression,
- like the preceding ones of pride and humility, love and hatred, 'tis
- impossible to define, and needless to describe any farther; for
- which reason we shall cut off all those definitions and distinctions
- with which philosophers are wont to perplex rather than clear up this
- question; and entering at first upon the subject, shall examine that
- long-disputed question concerning _liberty and necessity_, which occurs
- so naturally in treating of the will.
- 'Tis universally acknowledged that the operations of external bodies
- are necessary; and that, in the communication of their motion, in their
- attraction, and mutual cohesion, there are not the least traces of
- indifference or liberty. Every object is determined by an absolute fate
- to a certain degree and direction of its motion, and can no more depart
- from that precise line in which it moves, than it can convert itself
- into an angel, or spirit, or any superior substance. The actions,
- therefore, of matter, are to be regarded as instances of necessary
- actions; and whatever is, in this respect, on the same footing with
- matter, must be acknowledged to be necessary. That we may know whether
- this be the case with the actions of the mind, we shall begin with
- examining matter, and considering on what the idea of a necessity in
- its operations are founded, and why we conclude one body or action to
- be the infallible cause of another.
- It has been observed already, that in no single instance the ultimate
- connexion of any objects is discoverable either by our senses or
- reason, and that we can never penetrate so far into the essence and
- construction of bodies, as to perceive the principle on which their
- mutual influence depends. 'Tis their constant union alone with which
- we are acquainted; and 'tis from the constant union the necessity
- arises. If objects had not an uniform and regular conjunction with
- each other, we should never arrive at any idea of cause and effect;
- and even after all, the necessity which enters into that idea, is
- nothing but a determination of the mind to pass from one object to
- its usual attendant, and infer the existence of one from that of the
- other. Here then are two particulars which we are to consider as
- essential to necessity, viz. the constant _union_ and the _inference_
- of the mind; and wherever we discover these, we must acknowledge a
- necessity. As the actions of matter have no necessity but what is
- derived from these circumstances, and it is not by any insight into
- the essence of bodies we discover their connexion, the absence of
- this insight, while the union and inference remain, will never, in
- any case, remove the necessity. 'Tis the observation of the union
- which produces the inference; for which reason it might be thought
- sufficient, if we prove a constant union in the actions of the mind,
- in order to establish the inference along with the necessity of these
- actions. But that I may bestow a greater force on my reasoning, I shall
- examine these particulars apart, and shall first prove from experience
- that our actions have a constant union with our motives, tempers, and
- circumstances, before I consider the inferences we draw from it.
- To this end a very slight and general view of the common course of
- human affairs will be sufficient. There is no light in which we can
- take them that does not confirm this principle. Whether we consider
- mankind according to the difference of sexes, ages, governments,
- conditions, or methods of education; the same uniformity and regular
- operation of natural principles are discernible. Like causes still
- produce like effects; in the same manner as in the mutual action of the
- elements and powers of nature.
- There are different trees which regularly produce fruit, whose relish
- is different from each other; and this regularity will be admitted as
- an instance of necessity and causes in external bodies. But are the
- products of Guienne and of Champagne more regularly different than
- the sentiments, actions, and passions of the two sexes, of which the
- one are distinguished by their force and maturity, the other by their
- delicacy and softness?
- Are the changes of our body from infancy to old age more regular and
- certain than those of our mind and conduct? And would a man be more
- ridiculous, who would expect that an infant of four years old will
- raise a weight of three hundred pounds, than one who, from a person of
- the same age, would look for a philosophical reasoning, or a prudent
- and well concerted action?
- We must certainly allow, that the cohesion of the parts of matter
- arises from natural and necessary principles, whatever difficulty we
- may find in explaining them: and for a like reason we must allow, that
- human society is founded on like principles; and our reason in the
- latter case is better than even that in the former; because we not
- only observe that men _always_ seek society, but can also explain the
- principles on which this universal propensity is founded. For it is
- more certain that two flat pieces of marble will unite together, than
- two young savages of different sexes will copulate? Do the children
- arise from this copulation more uniformly, than does the parents' care
- for their safety and preservation? And after they have arrived at years
- of discretion by the care of their parents, are the inconveniences
- attending their separation more certain than their foresight of these
- inconveniences, and their care of avoiding them by a close union and
- confederacy?
- The skin, pores, muscles, and nerves of a day-labourer, are different
- from those of a man of quality: so are his sentiments, actions, and
- manners. The different stations of life influence the whole fabric,
- external and internal; and these different stations arise necessarily,
- because uniformly, from the necessary and uniform principles of human
- nature. Men cannot live without society, and cannot be associated
- without government. Government makes a distinction of property, and
- establishes the different ranks of men. This produces industry,
- traffic, manufactures, lawsuits, war, leagues, alliances, voyages,
- travels, cities, fleets, ports, and all those other actions and objects
- which cause such a diversity, and at the same time maintain such an
- uniformity in human life.
- Should a traveller, returning from a far country, tell us, that he had
- seen a climate in the fiftieth degree of northern latitude, where all
- the fruits ripen and come to perfection in the winter, and decay in the
- summer, after the same manner as in England they are produced and decay
- in the contrary seasons, he would find few so credulous as to believe
- him. I am apt to think a traveller would meet with as little credit,
- who should inform us of people exactly of the same character with those
- in Plato's republic on the one hand, or those in Hobbes's _Leviathan_
- on the other. There is a general course of nature in human actions, as
- well as in the operations of the sun and the climate. There are also
- characters peculiar to different nations and particular persons, as
- well as common to mankind. The knowledge of these characters is founded
- on the observation of an uniformity in the actions that flow from them;
- and this uniformity forms the very essence of necessity.
- I can imagine only one way of eluding this argument, which is by
- denying that uniformity of human actions, on which it is founded. As
- long as actions have a constant union and connexion with the situation
- and temper of the agent, however we may in words refuse to acknowledge
- the necessity, we really allow the thing. Now, some may perhaps find
- a pretext to deny this regular union and connexion. For what is more
- capricious than human actions? What more inconstant than the desires
- of man? And what creature departs more widely, not only from right
- reason, but from his own character and disposition? An hour, a moment
- is sufficient to make him change from one extreme to another, and
- overturn what cost the greatest pain and labour to establish. Necessity
- is regular and certain. Human conduct is irregular and uncertain. The
- one therefore proceeds not from the other.
- To this I reply, that in judging of the actions of men we must proceed
- upon the same maxims, as when we reason concerning external objects.
- When any phenomena are constantly and invariably conjoined together,
- they acquire such a connexion in the imagination, that it passes from
- one to the other without any doubt or hesitation. But below this there
- are many inferior degrees of evidence and probability, nor does one
- single contrariety of experiment entirely destroy all our reasoning.
- The mind balances the contrary experiments, and, deducting the inferior
- from the superior, proceeds with that degree of assurance or evidence,
- which remains. Even when these contrary experiments are entirely equal,
- we remove not the notion of causes and necessity; but, supposing that
- the usual contrariety proceeds from the operation of contrary and
- concealed causes, we conclude, that the chance or indifference lies
- only in our judgment on account of our imperfect knowledge, not in the
- things themselves, which are in every case equally necessary, though,
- to appearance, not equally constant or certain. No union can be more
- constant and certain than that of some actions with some motives and
- characters; and if, in other cases, the union is uncertain, 'tis no
- more than what happens in the operations of body; nor can we conclude
- any thing from the one irregularity which will not follow equally from
- the other.
- 'Tis commonly allowed that madmen have no liberty. But, were we to
- judge by their actions, these have less regularity and constancy than
- the actions of wise men, and consequently are farther removed from
- necessity. Our way of thinking in this particular is, therefore,
- absolutely inconsistent; but is a natural consequence of these confused
- ideas and undefined terms, which we so commonly make use of in our
- reasonings, especially on the present subject.
- We must now show, that, as the _union_ betwixt motives and actions has
- the same constancy as that in any natural operations, so its influence
- on the understanding is also the same, in _determining_ us to infer
- the existence of one from that of another. If this shall appear, there
- is no known circumstance that enters into the connexion and production
- of the actions of matter that is not to be found in all the operations
- of the mind; and consequently we cannot, without a manifest absurdity,
- attribute necessity to the one, and refuse it to the other.
- There is no philosopher, whose judgment is so rivetted to this
- fantastical system of liberty, as not to acknowledge the force of
- _moral evidence_, and both in speculation and practice proceed upon
- it as upon a reasonable foundation. Now, moral evidence is nothing
- but a conclusion concerning the actions of men, derived from the
- consideration of their motives, temper, and situation. Thus, when we
- see certain characters or figures described upon paper, we infer that
- the person who produced them would affirm such facts, the death of
- Cæsar, the success of Augustus, the cruelty of Nero; and, remembering
- many other concurrent testimonies, we conclude that those facts were
- once really existent, and that so many men, without any interest,
- would never conspire to deceive us; especially since they must, in the
- attempt, expose themselves to the derision of all their contemporaries,
- when these facts were asserted to be recent and universally known. The
- same kind of reasoning runs through politics, war, commerce, economy,
- and indeed mixes itself so entirely in human life, that 'tis impossible
- to act or subsist a moment without having recourse to it. A prince who
- imposes a tax upon his subjects, expects their compliance. A general
- who conducts an army, makes account of a certain degree of courage. A
- merchant looks for fidelity and skill in his factor or supercargo. A
- man who gives orders for his dinner, doubts not of the obedience of
- his servants. In short, as nothing more nearly interests us than our
- own actions and those of others, the greatest part of our reasonings
- is employed in judgments concerning them. Now I assert, that whoever
- reasons after this manner, does _ipso facto_ believe the actions of the
- will to arise from necessity, and that he knows not what he means when
- he denies it.
- All those objects, of which we call the one _cause_ and the other
- _effect_, considered in themselves, are as distinct and separate from
- each other as any two things in nature; nor can we ever, by the most
- accurate survey of them, infer the existence of the one from that
- of the other. 'Tis only from experience and the observation of their
- constant union, that we are able to form this inference; and even
- after all, the inference is nothing but the effects of custom on the
- imagination. We must not here be content with saying, that the idea
- of cause and effect arises from objects constantly united; but must
- affirm, that 'tis the very same with the idea of these objects, and
- that the _necessary connexion_ is not discovered by a conclusion of
- the understanding, but is merely a perception of the mind. Wherever,
- therefore, we observe the same union, and wherever the union operates
- in the same manner upon the belief and opinion, we have the idea of
- causes and necessity, though perhaps we may avoid those expressions.
- Motion in one body, in all past instances that have fallen under our
- observation, is followed upon impulse by motion in another. 'Tis
- impossible for the mind to penetrate farther. From this constant union
- it _forms_ the idea of cause and effect, and by its influence _feels_
- the necessity. As there is the same constancy, and the same influence,
- in what we call moral evidence, I ask no more. What remains can only be
- a dispute of words.
- And indeed, when we consider how aptly _natural_ and _moral_ evidence
- cement together, and form only one chain of argument betwixt them, we
- shall make no scruple to allow, that they are of the same nature, and
- derived from the same principles. A prisoner, who has neither money nor
- interest, discover the impossibility of his escape, as well from the
- obstinacy of the gaoler, as from the walls and bars with which he is
- surrounded; and in all attempts for his freedom, chooses rather to work
- upon the stone and iron of the one, than upon the inflexible nature
- of the other. The same prisoner, when conducted to the scaffold,
- foresees his death as certainly from the constancy and fidelity of
- his guards, as from the operation of the axe or wheel. His mind runs
- along a certain train of ideas: the refusal of the soldiers to consent
- to his escape; the action of the executioner; the separation of the
- head and body, bleeding, convulsive motions, and death. Here is a
- connected chain of natural causes and voluntary actions; but the mind
- feels no difference betwixt them in passing from one link to another;
- nor is less certain of the future event than if it were connected
- with the present impressions of the memory and senses by a train of
- causes cemented together by what we are pleased to call a _physical
- necessity_. The same experienced union has the same effect on the mind,
- whether the united objects be motives, volitions and actions, or figure
- and motion. We may change the names of things, but their nature and
- their operation on the understanding never change.
- I dare be positive no one will ever endeavour to refute these
- reasonings otherwise than by altering my definitions, and assigning a
- different meaning to the terms of _cause, and effect, and necessity,
- and liberty, and chance_. According to my definitions, necessity makes
- an essential part of causation; and consequently liberty, by removing
- necessity, removes also causes, and is the very same thing with chance.
- As chance is commonly thought to imply a contradiction, and is at least
- directly contrary to experience, there are always the same arguments
- against liberty or free-will. If any one alters the definitions, I
- cannot pretend to argue with him till I know the meaning he assigns to
- these terms.
- SECTION II.
- THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.
- I believe we may assign the three following reasons for the prevalence
- of the doctrine of liberty, however absurd it may be in one sense,
- and unintelligible in any other. First, after we have performed any
- action, though we confess we were influenced by particular views and
- motives, 'tis difficult for us to persuade ourselves we were governed
- by necessity, and that 'twas utterly impossible for us to have acted
- otherwise, the idea of necessity seeming to imply something of force,
- and violence, and constraint, of which we are not sensible. Few are
- capable of distinguishing betwixt the liberty of _spontaneity_, as it
- is called in the schools, and the liberty of _indifference_; betwixt
- that which is opposed to violence, and that which means a negation of
- necessity and causes. The first is even the most common sense of the
- word; and as 'tis only that species of liberty which it concerns us to
- preserve, our thoughts have been principally turned towards it, and
- have almost universally confounded it with the other.
- Secondly, there is a _false sensation or experience_ even of the
- liberty of indifference, which is regarded as an argument for its real
- existence. The necessity of any action, whether of matter or of the
- mind, is not properly a quality in the agent, but in any thinking or
- intelligent being, who may consider the action, and consists in the
- determination of his thought to infer its existence from some preceding
- objects: as liberty or chance, on the other hand, is nothing but the
- want of that determination, and a certain looseness, which we feel
- in passing or not passing from the idea of one to that of the other.
- Now, we may observe, that though in reflecting on human actions, we
- seldom feel such a looseness or indifference, yet it very commonly
- happens, that, in performing the actions themselves, we are sensible of
- something like it: and as all related or resembling objects are readily
- taken for each other, this has been employed as a demonstrative, or
- even an intuitive proof of human liberty. We feel that our actions
- are subject to our will on most occasions, and imagine we feel that
- the will itself is subject to nothing; because when, by a denial of
- it, we are provoked to try, we feel that it moves easily every way,
- and produces an image of itself even on that side on which it did not
- settle. This image or faint motion, we persuade ourselves, could have
- been completed into the thing itself; because, should that be denied,
- we find, upon a second trial, that it can. But these efforts are all in
- vain; and whatever capricious and irregular actions we may perform, as
- the desire of showing our liberty is the sole motive of our actions, we
- can never free ourselves from the bonds of necessity. We may imagine
- we feel a liberty within ourselves, but a spectator can commonly infer
- our actions from our motives and character; and even where he cannot,
- he concludes in general that he might, were he perfectly acquainted
- with every circumstance of our situation and temper, and the most
- secret springs of our complexion and disposition. Now, this is the very
- essence of necessity, according to the foregoing doctrine.
- A third reason why the doctrine of liberty has generally been better
- received in the world than its antagonist, proceeds from _religion_,
- which has been very unnecessarily interested in this question. There
- is no method of reasoning more common, and yet none more blameable,
- than in philosophical debates to endeavour to refute any hypothesis
- by a pretext of its dangerous consequences to religion and morality.
- When any opinion leads us into absurdities, 'tis certainly false;
- but 'tis not certain an opinion is false, because 'tis of dangerous
- consequence. Such topics, therefore, ought entirely to be foreborn,
- as serving nothing to the discovery of truth, but only to make the
- person of an antagonist odious. This I observe in general, without
- pretending to draw any advantage from it. I submit myself frankly to an
- examination of this kind, and dare venture to affirm, that the doctrine
- of necessity, according to my explication of it, is not only innocent,
- but even advantageous to religion and morality.
- I define necessity two ways, conformable to the two definitions of
- _cause_, of which it makes an essential part. I place it either in the
- constant union and conjunction of like objects, or in the inference
- of the mind from the one to the other. Now, necessity, in both these
- senses, has universally, though tacitly, in the schools, in the pulpit,
- and in common life, been allowed to belong to the will of man; and no
- one has ever pretended to deny, that we can draw inferences concerning
- human actions, and that those inferences are founded on the experienced
- union of like actions with like motives and circumstances. The only
- particular in which any one can differ from me is, either that perhaps
- he will refuse to call this necessity; but as long as the meaning is
- understood, I hope the word can do no harm; or, that he will maintain
- there is something else in the operations of matter. Now, whether it
- be so or not, is of no consequence to religion, whatever it may be to
- natural philosophy. I may be mistaken in asserting, that we have no
- idea of any other connexion in the actions of body, and shall be glad
- to be farther instructed on that head: but sure I am, I ascribe nothing
- to the actions of the mind, but what must readily be allowed of. Let no
- one, therefore, put an invidious construction on my words, by saying
- simply, that I assert the necessity of human actions, and place them
- on the same footing with the operations of senseless matter. I do not
- ascribe to the will that unintelligible necessity, which is supposed
- to lie in matter. But I ascribe to matter that intelligible quality,
- call it necessity or not, which the most rigorous orthodoxy does or
- must allow to belong to the will. I change, therefore, nothing in the
- received systems, with regard to the will, but only with regard to
- material objects.
- Nay, I shall go farther, and assert, that this kind of necessity is so
- essential to religion and morality, that without it there must ensue
- an absolute subversion of both, and that every other supposition is
- entirely destructive to all laws, both _divine_ and _human_. 'Tis
- indeed certain, that as all human laws are founded on rewards and
- punishments, 'tis supposed as a fundamental principle, that these
- motives have an influence on the mind, and both produce the good and
- prevent the evil actions. We may give to this influence what name we
- please; but as 'tis usually conjoined with the action, common sense
- requires it should be esteemed a cause, and be looked upon as an
- instance of that necessity, which I would establish.
- This reasoning is equally solid, when applied to _divine_ laws,
- so far as the Deity is considered as a legislator, and is supposed
- to inflict punishment and bestow rewards with a design to produce
- obedience. But I also maintain, that even where he acts not in his
- magisterial capacity, is regarded as the avenger of crimes merely on
- account of their odiousness and deformity, not only 'tis impossible,
- without the necessary connexion of cause and effect in human actions,
- that punishments could be inflicted compatible with justice and moral
- equity; but also that it could ever enter into the thoughts of any
- reasonable being to inflict them. The constant and universal object
- of hatred or anger is a person or creature endowed with thought and
- consciousness; and when any criminal or injurious actions excite that
- passion, 'tis only by their relation to the person or connexion with
- him. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance, this connexion
- is reduced to nothing, nor are men more accountable for those actions,
- which are designed and premeditated, than for such as are the most
- casual and accidental. Actions are, by their very nature, temporary and
- perishing; and where they proceed not from some cause in the characters
- and disposition of the person who performed them, they infix not
- themselves upon him, and can neither redound to his honour, if good,
- nor infamy, if evil. The action itself may be blameable; it may be
- contrary to all the rules of morality and religion: but the person is
- not responsible for it; and as it proceeded from nothing in him that is
- durable or constant, and leaves nothing of that nature behind it, 'tis
- impossible he can, upon its account, become the object of punishment or
- vengeance. According to the hypothesis of liberty, therefore, a man is
- as pure and untainted, after having committed the most horrid crimes,
- as at the first moment of his birth, nor is his character any way
- concerned in his actions, since they are not derived from it, and the
- wickedness of the one can never be used as a proof of the depravity of
- the other. 'Tis only upon the principles of necessity, that a person
- acquires any merit or demerit from his actions, however the common
- opinion may incline to the contrary.
- But so inconsistent are men with themselves, that though they often
- assert that necessity utterly destroys all merit and demerit either
- towards mankind or superior powers, yet they continue still to reason
- upon these very principles of necessity in all their judgments
- concerning this matter. Men are not blamed for such evil actions
- as they perform ignorantly and casually, whatever may be their
- consequences. Why? but because the causes of these actions are only
- momentary, and terminate in them alone. Men are less blamed for such
- evil actions as they perform hastily and unpremeditately, than for such
- as proceed from thought and deliberation. For what reason? but because
- a hasty temper, though a constant cause in the mind, operates only by
- intervals, and infects not the whole character. Again, repentance wipes
- off every crime, especially if attended with an evident reformation of
- life and manners. How is this to be accounted for? but by asserting
- that actions render a person criminal, merely as they are proofs
- of criminal passions or principles in the mind; and when, by any
- alteration of these principles, they cease to be just proofs, they
- likewise cease to be criminal. But according the doctrine of _liberty_
- or _chance_, they never were just proofs, and consequently never were
- criminal.
- Here then I turn to my adversary, and desire him to free his own system
- from these odious consequences before he charge them upon others.
- Or, if he rather chooses that this question should be decided by fair
- arguments before philosophers, than by declamations before the people,
- let him return to what I have advanced to prove that liberty and chance
- are synonymous; and concerning the nature of moral evidence and the
- regularity of human actions. Upon a review of these reasonings, I
- cannot doubt of an entire victory; and therefore, having proved that
- all actions of the will have particular causes, I proceed to explain
- what these causes are, and how they operate.
- SECTION III.
- OF THE INFLUENCING MOTIVES OF THE WILL.
- Nothing is more usual in philosophy, and even in common life, than to
- talk of the combat of passion and reason, to give the preference to
- reason, and assert that men are only so far virtuous as they conform
- themselves to its dictates. Every rational creature, 'tis said, is
- obliged to regulate his actions by reason; and if any other motive or
- principle challenge the direction of his conduct, he ought to oppose
- it, 'till it be entirely subdued, or at least brought to a conformity
- with that superior principle. On this method of thinking the greatest
- part of moral philosophy, ancient and modern, seems to be founded;
- nor is there an ampler field, as well for metaphysical arguments, as
- popular declamations, than this supposed pre-eminence of reason above
- passion. The eternity, invariableness, and divine origin of the former,
- have been displayed to the best advantage: the blindness, inconstancy,
- and deceitfulness of the latter, have been as strongly insisted on. In
- order to show the fallacy of all this philosophy, I shall endeavour to
- prove _first_, that reason alone can never be a motive to any action
- of the will; and _secondly_, that it can never oppose passion in the
- direction of the will.
- The understanding exerts itself after two different ways, as the judges
- from demonstration or probability; as it regards the abstract relations
- of our ideas, or those relations of objects of which experience only
- gives us information. I believe it scarce will be asserted, that the
- first species of reasoning alone is ever the cause of any action. As
- its proper province is the world of ideas, and as the will always
- places us in that of realities, demonstration and volition seem upon
- that account to be totally removed from each other. Mathematics,
- indeed, are useful in all mechanical operations, and arithmetic in
- almost every art and profession: but 'tis not of themselves they have
- any influence. Mechanics are the art of regulating the motions of
- bodies _to some designed end or purpose_; and the reason why we employ
- arithmetic in fixing the proportions of numbers, is only that we may
- discover the proportions of their influence and operation. A merchant
- is desirous of knowing the sum total of his accounts with any person:
- why? but that he may learn what sum will have the same _effects_ in
- paying his debt, and going to market, as all the particular articles
- taken together. Abstract or demonstrative reasoning, therefore, never
- influences any of our actions, but only as it directs our judgment
- concerning causes and effects; which leads us to the second operation
- of the understanding.
- 'Tis obvious, that when we have the prospect of pain or pleasure from
- any object, we feel a consequent emotion of aversion or propensity,
- and are carried to avoid or embrace what will give us this uneasiness
- or satisfaction. 'Tis also obvious, that this emotion rests not here,
- but, making us cast our view on every side, comprehends whatever
- objects are connected with its original one by the relation of cause
- and effect. Here then reasoning takes place to discover this relation;
- and according as our reasoning varies, our actions receive a subsequent
- variation. But 'tis evident, in this case, that the impulse arises not
- from reason, but is only directed by it. 'Tis from the prospect of pain
- or pleasure that the aversion or propensity arises towards any object:
- and these emotions extend themselves to the causes and effects of that
- object, as they are pointed out to us by reason and experience. It can
- never in the least concern us to know, that such objects are causes,
- and such others effects, if both the causes and effects be indifferent
- to us. Where the objects themselves do not affect us, their connexion
- can never give them any influence; and 'tis plain that, as reason is
- nothing but the discovery of this connexion, it cannot be by its means
- that the objects are able to affect us.
- Since reason alone can never produce any action, or give rise to
- volition, I infer, that the same faculty is as incapable of preventing
- volition, or of disputing the preference with any passion or emotion.
- This consequence is necessary. 'Tis impossible reason could have the
- latter effect of preventing, volition, but by giving an impulse in a
- contrary direction to our passion; and that impulse, had it operated
- alone, would have been able to produce volition. Nothing can oppose or
- retard the impulse of passion, but a contrary impulse; and if this
- contrary impulse ever arises from reason, that latter faculty must
- have an original influence on the will, and must be able to cause, as
- well as hinder, any act of volition. But if reason has no original
- influence, 'tis impossible it can withstand any principle which has
- such an efficacy, or ever keep the mind in suspence a moment. Thus,
- it appears, that the principle which opposes our passion, cannot be
- the same with reason, and is only called so in an improper sense. We
- speak not strictly and philosophically, when we talk of the combat of
- passion and of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of
- the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve
- and obey them. As this opinion may appear somewhat extraordinary, it
- may not be improper to confirm it by some other considerations.
- A passion is an original existence, or, if you will, modification of
- existence, and contains not any representative quality, which renders
- it a copy of any other existence or modification. When I am angry, I
- am actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no more
- a reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick, or
- more than five feet high. 'Tis impossible, therefore, that this passion
- can be opposed by, or be contradictory to, truth and reason; since this
- contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas, considered as
- copies, with those objects which they represent.
- What may at first occur on this head is, that as nothing can be
- contrary to truth or reason, except what has a reference to it, and as
- the judgments of our understanding only have this reference, it must
- follow, that passions can be contrary to reason only, so far as they
- are _accompanied_ with some judgment or opinion. According to this
- principle, which is so obvious and natural, 'tis only in two senses
- that any affection can be called unreasonable. First, When a passion,
- such as hope or fear, grief or joy, despair or security, is founded
- on the supposition of the existence of objects, which really do not
- exist. Secondly, When in exerting any passion in action, we choose
- means sufficient for the designed end, and deceive ourselves in our
- judgment of causes and effects. Where a passion is neither founded on
- false suppositions, nor chooses means insufficient for the end, the
- understanding can neither justify nor condemn it. 'Tis not contrary to
- reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching
- of my finger. 'Tis not contrary to reason for me to choose my total
- ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian, or person wholly
- unknown to me. 'Tis as little contrary to reason to prefer even my
- own acknowledged lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent
- affection for the former than the latter. A trivial good may, from
- certain circumstances, produce a desire superior to what arises from
- the greatest and most valuable enjoyment; nor is there any thing more
- extraordinary in this, than in mechanics to see one pound weight raise
- up a hundred by the advantage of its situation. In short, a passion
- must be accompanied with some false judgment, in order to its being
- unreasonable; and even then, 'tis not the passion, properly speaking,
- which is unreasonable, but the judgment.
- The consequences are evident. Since a passion can never, in any sense,
- be called unreasonable, but when founded on a false supposition,
- or when it chuses means insufficient for the designed end, 'tis
- impossible, that reason and passion can ever oppose each other, or
- dispute for the government of the will and actions. The moment we
- perceive the falsehood of any supposition, or the insufficiency of
- any means, our passions yield to our reason without any opposition.
- I may desire any fruit as of an excellent relish; but whenever
- you convince me of my mistake, my longing ceases. I may will the
- performance of certain actions as means of obtaining any desired good;
- but as my willing of these actions is only secondary, and founded on
- the supposition that they are causes of the proposed effect; as soon
- as I discover the falsehood of that supposition, they must become
- indifferent to me.
- 'Tis natural for one, that does not examine objects with a strict
- philosophic eye, to imagine, that those actions of the mind are
- entirely the same, which produce not a different sensation, and are
- not immediately distinguishable to the feeling and perception. Reason,
- for instance, exerts itself without producing any sensible emotion;
- and except in the more sublime disquisitions of philosophy, or in the
- frivolous subtilties of the schools, scarce ever conveys any pleasure
- or uneasiness. Hence it proceeds, that every action of the mind which
- operates with the same calmness and tranquillity, is confounded
- with reason by all those who judge of things from the first view
- and appearance. Now 'tis certain there are certain calm desires and
- tendencies, which, though they be real passions, produce little emotion
- in the mind, and are more known by their effects than by the immediate
- feeling or sensation. These desires are of two kinds; either certain
- instincts originally implanted in our natures, such as benevolence and
- resentment, the love of life, and kindness to children; or the general
- appetite to good, and aversion to evil, considered merely as such. When
- any of these passions are calm, and cause no disorder in the soul,
- they are very readily taken for the determinations of reason, and are
- supposed to proceed from the same faculty with that which judges of
- truth and falsehood. Their nature and principles have been supposed the
- same, because their sensations are not evidently different.
- Beside these calm passions, which often determine the will, there are
- certain violent emotions of the same kind, which have likewise a great
- influence on that faculty. When I receive any injury from another, I
- often feel a violent passion of resentment, which makes me desire his
- evil and punishment, independent of all considerations of pleasure and
- advantage to myself. When I am immediately threatened with any grievous
- ill, my fears, apprehensions and aversions rise to a great height, and
- produce a sensible emotion.
- The common error of metaphysicians has lain in ascribing the direction
- of the will entirely to one of these principles, and supposing the
- other to have no influence. Men often act knowingly against their
- interest; for which reason, the view of the greatest possible good
- does not always influence them. Men often counteract a violent passion
- in prosecution of their interests and designs; 'tis not, therefore,
- the present uneasiness alone which determines them. In general we may
- observe, that both these principles, operate on the will; and where
- they are contrary, that either of them prevails, according to the
- _general_ character or _present_ disposition of the person. What we
- call strength of mind, implies the prevalence of the calm passions
- above the violent; though we may easily observe, there is no man so
- constantly possessed of this virtue, as never on any occasion to yield
- to the solicitations of passion and desire. From these variations
- of temper proceeds the great difficulty of deciding concerning the
- actions and resolutions of men, where there is any contrariety of
- motives and passions.
- SECTION IV.
- OF THE CAUSES OF THE VIOLENT PASSIONS.
- There is not in philosophy a subject of more nice speculation than
- this, of the different _causes_ and _effects_ of the calm and violent
- passions. 'Tis evident, passions influence not the will in proportion
- to their violence, or the disorder they occasion in the temper;
- but, on the contrary, that when a passion has once become a settled
- principle of action, and is the predominant inclination of the soul,
- it commonly produces no longer any sensible agitation. As repeated
- custom and its own force have made every thing yield to it, it directs
- the actions and conduct without that opposition and emotion which so
- naturally attend every momentary gust of passion. We must, therefore,
- distinguish betwixt a calm and a weak passion; betwixt a violent and
- a strong one. But notwithstanding this, 'tis certain that, when we
- would govern a man, and push him to any action, 'twill commonly be
- better policy to work upon the violent than the calm passions, and
- rather take him by his inclination, than what is vulgarly called his
- _reason_. We ought to place the object in such particular situations
- as are proper to increase the violence of the passion. For we may
- observe, that all depends upon the situation of the object, and that a
- variation in this particular will be able to change the calm and the
- violent passions into each other. Both these kinds of passions pursue
- good, and avoid evil; and both of them are increased or diminished by
- the increase or diminution of the good or evil. But herein lies the
- difference betwixt them: the same good, when near, will cause a violent
- passion, which, when remote, produces only a calm one. As this subject
- belongs very properly to the present question concerning the will, we
- shall here examine it to the bottom, and shall consider some of those
- circumstances and situations of objects, which render a passion either
- calm or violent.
- 'Tis a remarkable property of human nature, that any emotion which
- attends a passion, is easily converted into it, though in their
- natures they be originally different from, and even contrary to, each
- other. 'Tis true, in order to make a perfect union among the passions,
- there is always required a double relation of impressions and ideas;
- nor is one relation sufficient for that purpose. But though this be
- confirmed by undoubted experience, we must understand it with its
- proper limitations, and must regard the double relation as requisite
- only to make one passion produce another. When two passions are already
- produced by their separate causes, and are both present in the mind,
- they readily mingle and unite, though they have but one relation,
- and sometimes without any. The predominant passion swallows up the
- inferior, and converts it into itself. The spirits, when once excited,
- easily receive a change in their direction; and 'tis natural to imagine
- this change will come from the prevailing affection. The connexion is
- in many respects closer betwixt any two passions, than betwixt any
- passion and indifference.
- When a person is once heartily in love, the little faults and caprice
- of his mistress, the jealousies and quarrels to which that commerce is
- so subject, however unpleasant, and related to anger and hatred, are
- yet found to give additional force to the prevailing passion. 'Tis a
- common artifice of politicians, when they would affect any person very
- much by a matter of fact, of which they intend to inform him, first to
- excite his curiosity, delay as long as possible the satisfying it, and
- by that means raise his anxiety and impatience to the utmost, before
- they give him a full insight into the business. They know that his
- curiosity will precipitate him into the passion they design to raise,
- and assist the object in its influence on the mind. A soldier advancing
- to the battle, is naturally inspired with courage and confidence,
- when he thinks on his friends and fellow-soldiers; and is struck with
- fear and terror, when he reflects on the enemy. Whatever new emotion,
- therefore, proceeds from the former, naturally increases the courage;
- as the same emotion, proceeding from the latter, augments the fear,
- by the relation of ideas, and the conversion of the inferior emotion
- into the predominant. Hence it is, that in martial discipline, the
- uniformity and lustre of our habit, the regularity of our figures and
- motions, with all the pomp and majesty of war, encourage ourselves and
- allies; while the same objects in the enemy strike terror into us,
- though agreeable and beautiful in themselves.
- Since passions, however independent, are naturally transfused into each
- other, if they are both present at the same time, it follows, that when
- good or evil is placed in such a situation as to cause any particular
- emotion beside its direct passion of desire or aversion, that latter
- passion must acquire new force and violence.
- This happens, among other cases, whenever any object excites contrary
- passions. For 'tis observable that an opposition of passions commonly
- causes a new emotion in the spirits, and produces more disorder than
- the concurrence of any two affections of equal force. This new emotion
- is easily converted into the predominant passion, and increases its
- violence beyond the pitch it would have arrived at had it met with
- no opposition. Hence we naturally desire what is forbid, and take a
- pleasure in performing actions, merely because they are unlawful.
- The notion of duty, when opposite to the passions, is seldom able to
- overcome them; and, when it fails of that effect, is apt rather to
- increase them, by producing an opposition in our motives and principles.
- The same effect follows, whether the opposition arises from internal
- motives or external obstacles. The passion commonly acquires new
- force and violence in both cases. The efforts which the mind makes to
- surmount the obstacle, excite the spirits and enliven the passion.
- Uncertainty has the same influence as opposition. The agitation of the
- thought, the quick turns it makes from one view to another, the variety
- of passions which succeed each other, according to the different views;
- all these produce an agitation in the mind, and transfuse themselves
- into the predominant passion.
- There is not, in my opinion, any other natural cause why security
- diminishes the passions, than because it removes that uncertainty which
- increases them. The mind, when left to itself, immediately languishes,
- and, in order to preserve its ardour, must be every moment supported by
- a new flow of passion. For the same reason, despair, though contrary to
- security, has a like influence.
- 'Tis certain, nothing more powerful animates any affection, than to
- conceal some part of its object by throwing it into a kind of shade,
- which, at the same time that it shows enough to prepossess us in
- favour of the object, leaves still some work for the imagination.
- Besides, that obscurity is always attended with a kind of uncertainty;
- the effort which the fancy makes to complete the idea, rouses the
- spirits, and gives an additional force to the passion.
- As despair and security, though contrary to each other, produce the
- same effects, so absence is observed to have contrary effects, and, in
- different circumstances, either increases or diminishes our affections.
- The Duc de la Rochefoucault has very well observed, that absence
- destroys weak passions, but increases strong; as the wind extinguishes
- a candle, but blows up a fire. Long absence naturally weakens our idea,
- and diminishes the passion; but where the idea is so strong and lively
- as to support itself, the uneasiness, arising from absence, increases
- the passion, and gives it new force and violence.
- SECTION V.
- OF THE EFFECTS OF CUSTOM.
- But nothing has a greater effect both to increase and diminish our
- passions, to convert pleasure into pain, and pain into pleasure, than
- custom and repetition. Custom has two _original_ effects upon the mind,
- in bestowing a _facility_ in the performance of any action, or the
- conception of any object, and afterwards a _tendency or inclination_
- towards it; and from these we may account for all its other effects,
- however extraordinary.
- When the soul applies itself to the performance of any action, or the
- conception of any object to which it is not accustomed, there is a
- certain unpliableness in the faculties, and a difficulty of the spirits
- moving in their new direction. As this difficulty excites the spirits,
- 'tis the source of wonder, surprise, and of all the emotions which
- arise from novelty, and is in itself very agreeable, like every thing
- which enlivens the mind to a moderate degree. But though surprise be
- agreeable in itself, yet, as it puts the spirits in agitation, it not
- only augments our agreeable affections, but also our painful, according
- to the foregoing principle, _that every emotion which precedes or
- attends a passion is easily converted into it_. Hence, every thing
- that is new is most affecting, and gives us either more pleasure or
- pain than what, strictly speaking, naturally belongs to it. When it
- often returns upon us, the novelty wears off, the passions subside, the
- hurry of the spirits is over, and we survey the objects with greater
- tranquillity.
- By degrees, the repetition produces a facility, which is another
- very powerful principle of the human mind, and an infallible source
- of pleasure where the facility goes not beyond a certain degree. And
- here 'tis remarkable, that the pleasure which arises from a moderate
- facility has not the same tendency with that which arises from
- novelty, to augment the painful as well as the agreeable affections.
- The pleasure of facility does not so much consist in any ferment of
- the spirits, as in their orderly motion, which will sometimes be so
- powerful as even to convert pain into pleasure, and give us a relish in
- time for what at first was most harsh and disagreeable.
- But, again, as facility converts pain into pleasure, so it often
- converts pleasure into pain when it is too great, and renders the
- actions of the mind so faint and languid, that they are no longer able
- to interest and support it. And indeed scarce any other objects become
- disagreeable through custom, but such as are naturally attended with
- some emotion or affection, which is destroyed by the too frequent
- repetition. One can consider the clouds, and heavens, and trees,
- and stones, however frequently repeated, without ever feeling any
- aversion. But when the fair sex, or music, or good cheer, or any thing
- that naturally ought to be agreeable, becomes indifferent, it easily
- produces the opposite affection.
- But custom not only gives a facility to perform any action, but
- likewise an inclination and tendency towards it, where it is not
- entirely disagreeable, and can never be the object of inclination.
- And this is the reason why custom increases all _active_ habits, but
- diminishes _passive_, according to the observation of a late eminent
- philosopher. The facility takes off from the force of the passive
- habits by rendering the motion of the spirits faint and languid. But as
- in the active, the spirits are sufficiently supported of themselves,
- the tendency of the mind gives them new force, and bends them more
- strongly to the action.
- SECTION VI.
- OF THE INFLUENCE OF THE IMAGINATION ON THE PASSIONS.
- 'Tis remarkable, that the imagination and affections have a close union
- together, and that nothing, which affects the former, can be entirely
- indifferent to the latter. Wherever our ideas of good or evil acquire
- a new vivacity, the passions become more violent, and keep pace with
- the imagination in all its variations. Whether this proceeds from
- the principle above-mentioned, _that any attendant emotion is easily
- converted into the Predominant_, I shall not determine. 'Tis sufficient
- for my present purpose, that we have many instances to confirm this
- influence of the imagination upon the passions.
- Any pleasure with which we are acquainted, affects us more than any
- other which we own to be superior, but of whose nature we are wholly
- ignorant. Of the one we can form a particular and determinate idea:
- the other we conceive under the general notion of pleasure; and 'tis
- certain, that the more general and universal any of our ideas are, the
- less influence they have upon the imagination. A general idea, though
- it be nothing but a particular one considered in a certain view, is
- commonly more obscure; and that because no particular idea, by which we
- represent a general one, is ever fixed or determinate, but may easily
- be changed for other particular ones, which will serve equally in the
- representation.
- There is a noted passage in the history of Greece, which may serve
- for our present purpose. Themistocles told the Athenians, that he had
- formed a design, which would be highly useful to the public, but which
- 'twas impossible for him to communicate to them without ruining the
- execution, since its success depended entirely on the secrecy with
- which it should be conducted. The Athenians, instead of granting him
- full power to act as he thought fitting, ordered him to communicate his
- design to Aristides, in whose prudence they had an entire confidence,
- and whose opinion they were resolved blindly to submit to. The design
- of Themistocles was secretly to set fire to the fleet of all the
- Grecian commonwealths, which was assembled in a neighbouring port,
- and which, being once destroyed, would give the Athenians the empire
- of the sea without any rival. Aristides returned to the assembly, and
- told them, that nothing could be more advantageous than the design of
- Themistocles; but at the same time that nothing could be more unjust:
- upon which the people unanimously rejected the project.
- A late celebrated historian[1] admires this passage of ancient history
- as one of the most singular that is any where to be met with. "Here,"
- says he, "they are not philosophers, to whom 'tis easy in their schools
- to establish the finest maxims and most sublime rules of morality, who
- decide that interest ought never to prevail above justice. 'Tis a whole
- people interested in the proposal which is made to them, who consider
- it as of importance to the public good, and who, notwithstanding,
- reject it unanimously, and without hesitation, merely because it is
- contrary to justice." For my part I see nothing so extraordinary in
- this proceeding of the Athenians. The same reasons which render it so
- easy for philosophers to establish these sublime maxims, tend, in part,
- to diminish the merit of such a conduct in that people. Philosophers
- never balance betwixt profit and honesty, because their decisions are
- general, and neither their passions nor imaginations are interested
- in the objects. And though, in the present case, the advantage was
- immediate to the Athenians, yet as it was known only under the general
- notion of advantage, without being conceived by any particular idea, it
- must have had a less considerable influence on their imaginations, and
- have been a less violent temptation, than if they had been acquainted
- with all its circumstances: otherwise 'tis difficult to conceive,
- that a whole people, unjust and violent as men commonly are, should
- so unanimously have adhered to justice, and rejected any considerable
- advantage.
- Any satisfaction which we lately enjoyed, and of which the memory is
- fresh and recent, operates on the will with more violence than another
- of which the traces are decayed, and almost obliterated. From whence
- does this proceed, but that the memory in the first case assists the
- fancy, and gives an additional force and vigour to its conceptions?
- The image of the past pleasure being strong and violent, bestows these
- qualities on the idea of the future pleasure, which is connected with
- it by the relation of resemblance.
- A pleasure which is suitable to the way of life in which we are
- engaged, excites more our desires and appetites than another which is
- foreign to it. This phenomenon may be explained from the same principle.
- Nothing is more capable of infusing any passion into the mind, than
- eloquence, by which objects are represented in their strongest and most
- lively colours. We may of ourselves acknowledge, that such an object
- is valuable, and such another odious; but till an orator excites the
- imagination, and gives force to these ideas, they may have but a feeble
- influence either on the will or the affections.
- But eloquence is not always necessary. The bare opinion of another,
- especially when enforced with passion, will cause an idea of good or
- evil to have an influence upon us, which would otherwise have been
- entirely neglected. This proceeds from the principle of sympathy or
- communication; and sympathy, as I have already observed, is nothing
- but the conversion of an idea into an impression by the force of
- imagination.
- 'Tis remarkable, that lively passions commonly attend a lively
- imagination. In this respect, as well as others, the force of the
- passion depends as much on the temper of the person, as the nature or
- situation of the object.
- I have already observed, that belief is nothing but a lively idea
- related to a present impression. This vivacity is a requisite
- circumstance to the exciting all our passions, the calm as well as the
- violent; nor has a mere fiction of the imagination any considerable
- influence upon either of them. 'Tis too weak to take any hold of the
- mind, or be attended with emotion.
- [1] Mons. Rollin.
- SECTION VII.
- OF CONTIGUITY AND DISTANCE IN SPACE AND TIME.
- There is an easy reason why every thing contiguous to us, either in
- space or time, should be conceived with a peculiar force and vivacity,
- and excel every other object in its influence on the imagination.
- Ourself is intimately present to us, and whatever is related to self
- must partake of that quality. But where an object is so far removed
- as to have lost the advantage of this relation, why, as it is farther
- removed, its idea becomes still fainter and more obscure, would
- perhaps require a more particular examination.
- 'Tis obvious that the imagination can never totally forget the
- points of space and time in which we are existent; but receives such
- frequent advertisements of them from the passions and senses, that,
- however it may turn its attention to foreign and remote objects, it
- is necessitated every moment to reflect on the present. 'Tis also
- remarkable, that in the conception of those objects which we regard as
- real and existent, we take them in their proper order and situation,
- and never leap from one object to another, which is distant from it,
- without running over, at least in a cursory manner, all those objects
- which are interposed betwixt them. When we reflect, therefore, on
- any object distant from ourselves, we are obliged not only to reach
- it at first by passing through all the intermediate space betwixt
- ourselves and the object, but also to renew our progress every moment,
- being every moment recalled to the consideration of ourselves and our
- present situation. 'Tis easily conceived, that this interruption must
- weaken the idea, by breaking the action of the mind, and hindering the
- conception from being so intense and continued, as when we reflect on
- a nearer object. The _fewer_ steps we make to arrive at the object,
- and the _smoother_ the road is, this diminution of vivacity is less
- sensibly felt, but still may be observed more or less in proportion to
- the degrees of distance and difficulty.
- Here then we are to consider two kinds of objects, the contiguous and
- remote, of which the former, by means of their relation to ourselves,
- approach an impression in force and vivacity; the latter, by reason of
- the interruption in our manner of conceiving them, appear in a weaker
- and more imperfect light. This is their effect on the imagination.
- If my reasoning be just, they must have a proportionable effect on
- the will and passions. Contiguous objects must have an influence much
- superior to the distant and remote. Accordingly we find, in common
- life, that men are principally concerned about those objects which are
- not much removed either in space or time, enjoying the present, and
- leaving what is afar off to the care of chance and fortune. Talk to a
- man of his condition thirty years hence, and he will not regard you.
- Speak of what is to happen to-morrow, and he will lend you attention.
- The breaking of a mirror gives us more concern when at home, than the
- burning of a house when abroad, and some hundred leagues distant.
- But farther; though distance, both in space and time, has a
- considerable effect on the imagination, and by that means on the will
- and passions, yet the consequence of a removal in _space_ are much
- inferior to those of a removal in _time_. Twenty years are certainly
- but a small distance of time in comparison of what history and even
- the memory of some may inform them of, and yet I doubt if a thousand
- leagues, or even the greatest distance of place this globe can admit
- of, will so remarkably weaken our ideas, and diminish our passions.
- A West India merchant will tell you, that he is not without concern
- about what passes in Jamaica; though few extend their views so far into
- futurity, as to dread very remote accidents.
- The cause of this phenomenon must evidently lie in the different
- properties of space and time. Without having recourse to metaphysics,
- any one may easily observe, that space or extension consists of a
- number of co-existent parts disposed in a certain order, and capable of
- being at once present to the sight or feeling. On the contrary, time
- or succession, though it consists likewise of parts, never presents
- to us more than one at once; nor is it possible for any two of them
- ever to co-existent. These qualities of the objects have a suitable
- effect on the imagination. The parts of extension being susceptible
- of an union to the senses, acquire an union in the fancy; and as
- the appearance of one part excludes not another, the transition or
- passage of the thought through the contiguous parts is by that means
- rendered more smooth and easy. On the other hand, the incompatibility
- of the parts of time in their real existence separates them in the
- imagination, and makes it more difficult for that faculty to trace any
- long succession or series of events. Every part must appear single and
- alone, nor can regularly have entrance into the fancy without banishing
- what is supposed to have been immediately precedent. By this means any
- distance in time causes a greater interruption in the thought than an
- equal distance in space, and consequently weakens more considerably the
- idea, and consequently the passions; which depend in a great measure on
- the imagination, according to my system.
- There is another phenomenon of a like nature with the foregoing, viz.
- _the superior effects of the same distance in futurity above that in
- the past_. This difference with respect to the will is easily accounted
- for. As none of our actions can alter the past, 'tis not strange it
- should never determine the will. But with respect to the passions, the
- question is yet entire, and well worth the examining.
- Besides the propensity to a gradual progression through the points of
- space and time, we have another peculiarity in our method of thinking,
- which concurs in producing this phenomenon. We always follow the
- succession of time in placing our ideas, and from the consideration of
- any object pass more easily to that which follows immediately after
- it, than to that which went before it. We may learn this, among other
- instances, from the order which is always observed in historical
- narrations. Nothing but an absolute necessity can oblige an historian
- to break the order of time, and in his _narration_ give the precedence
- to an event, which was in _reality_ posterior to another.
- This will easily be applied to the question in hand, if we reflect
- on what I have before observed, that the present situation of the
- person is always that of the imagination, and that 'tis from thence
- we proceed to the conception of any distant object. When the object
- is past, the progression of the thought in passing to it from the
- present is contrary to nature, as proceeding from one point of time
- to that which is preceding, and from that to another preceding, in
- opposition to the natural course of the succession. On the other hand,
- when we turn our thought to a future object, our fancy flows along the
- stream of time, and arrives at the object of an order, which seems
- most natural, passing always from one point of time to that which is
- immediately posterior to it. This easy progression of ideas favours
- the imagination, and makes it conceive its object in a stronger and
- fuller light, than when we are continually opposed in our passage,
- and are obliged to overcome the difficulties arising from the natural
- propensity of the fancy. A small degree of distance in the past
- has, therefore, a greater effect in interrupting and weakening the
- conception, than a much greater in the future. From this effect of it
- on the imagination is derived its influence on the will and passions.
- There is another cause, which both contributes to the same effect, and
- proceeds from the same quality of the fancy, by which we are determined
- to trace the succession of time by a similar succession of ideas.
- When, from the present instant, we consider two points Of time equally
- distant in the future and in the past, 'tis evident that, abstractedly
- considered, their relation to the present is almost equal. For as the
- future will _some time_ be present, so the past was _once_ present.
- If we could, therefore, remove this quality of the imagination, an
- equal distance in the past and in the future would have a similar
- influence. Nor is this only true when the fancy remains fixed, and from
- the present instant surveys the future and the past; but also when it
- changes its situation, and places us in different periods of time. For
- as, on the one hand, in supposing ourselves existent in a point of
- time interposed betwixt the present instant and the future object, we
- find the future object approach to us, and the past retire and become
- more distant: so, on the other hand, in supposing ourselves existent
- in a point of time interposed betwixt the present and the past, the
- past approaches to us, and the future becomes more distant. But from
- the property of the fancy above mentioned, we rather choose to fix
- our thought on the point of time interposed betwixt the present and
- the future, than on that betwixt the present and the past. We advance
- rather than retard our existence; and, following what seems the natural
- succession of time, proceed from past to present, and from present to
- future; by which means we conceive the future as flowing every moment
- nearer us, and the past as retiring. An equal distance, therefore, in
- the past and in the future, has not the same effect on the imagination;
- and that because we consider the one as continually increasing, and
- the other as continually diminishing. The fancy anticipates the course
- of things, and surveys the object in that condition to which it tends,
- as well as in that which is regarded as the present.
- SECTION VIII.
- THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.
- Thus, we have accounted for three phenomena, which seem pretty
- remarkable. Why distance weakens the conception and passion: why
- distance in time has a greater effect than that in space: and why
- distance in past time has still a greater effect than that in future.
- We must now consider three phenomena, which seem to be in a manner the
- reverse of these: why a very great distance increases our esteem and
- admiration for an object: why such a distance in time increases it
- more than that in space: and a distance in past time more than that in
- future. The curiousness of the subject will, I hope, excuse my dwelling
- on it for some time.
- To begin with the first phenomenon, why a great distance increases our
- esteem and admiration for an object; 'tis evident that the mere view
- and contemplation of any greatness, whether successive or extended,
- enlarges the soul, and gives it a sensible delight and pleasure. A wide
- plain, the ocean, eternity, a succession of several ages; all these
- are entertaining objects, and excel every thing, however beautiful,
- which accompanies not its beauty with a suitable greatness. Now, when
- any very distant object is presented to the imagination, we naturally
- reflect on the interposed distance, and by that means conceiving
- something great and magnificent, receive the usual satisfaction. But
- as the fancy passes easily from one idea to another related to it,
- and transports to the second all the passions excited by the first,
- the admiration, which is directed to the distance, naturally diffuses
- itself over the distant object. Accordingly we find, that 'tis not
- necessary the object should be actually distant from us in order to
- cause our admiration; but that 'tis sufficient if, by the natural
- association of ideas, it conveys our view to any considerable distance.
- A great traveller, though in the same chamber, will pass for a very
- extraordinary person; as a Greek medal, even in our cabinet, is
- always esteemed a valuable curiosity. Here the object, by a natural
- transition, conveys our view to the distance; and the admiration which
- arises from that distance, by another natural transition, returns back
- to the object.
- But though every great distance produces an admiration for the distant
- object, a distance in time has a more considerable effect than that
- in space. Ancient busts and inscriptions are more valued than Japan
- tables: and, not to mention the Greeks and Romans, 'tis certain we
- regard with more veneration the old Chaldeans and Egyptians, than the
- modern Chinese and Persians; and bestow more fruitless pains to clear
- up the history and chronology of the former, than it would cost us to
- make a voyage, and be certainly informed of the character, learning,
- and government of the latter. I shall be obliged to make a digression
- in order to explain this phenomenon.
- 'Tis a quality very observable in human nature, that any opposition
- which does not entirely discourage and intimidate us, has rather a
- contrary effect, and inspires us with a more than ordinary grandeur
- and magnanimity. In collecting our force to overcome the opposition, we
- invigorate the soul, and give it an elevation with which otherwise it
- would never have been acquainted. Compliance, by rendering our strength
- useless, makes us insensible of it; but opposition awakens and employs
- it.
- This is also true in the inverse. Opposition not only enlarges the
- soul; but the soul, when full of courage and magnanimity, in a manner
- seeks opposition.
- Spumantemque dari pecora inter inertia votis
- Optat aprum, aut fulvum descendere monte leonem.
- Whatever supports and fills the passions is agreeable to us; as, on the
- contrary, what weakens and enfeebles them is uneasy. As opposition has
- the first effect, and facilitates the second, no wonder the mind, in
- certain dispositions, desires the former, and is averse to the latter.
- These principles have an effect on the imagination as well as on the
- passions. To be convinced of this, we need only consider the influence
- of _heights_ and _depths_ on that faculty. Any great elevation of
- place communicates a kind of pride or sublimity of imagination, and
- gives a fancied superiority over those that lie below; and, _vice
- versa_, a sublime and strong imagination conveys the idea of ascent and
- elevation. Hence it proceeds, that we associate, in a manner, the idea
- of whatever is good with that of height, and evil with lowness. Heaven
- is supposed to be above, and hell below. A noble genius is called an
- elevate and sublime one. _Atque udam spernit humum fugiente penna_. On
- the contrary, a vulgar and trivial conception is styled indifferently
- low or mean. Prosperity is denominated ascent, and adversity descent.
- Kings and princes are supposed to be placed at the top of human
- affairs; as peasants and day-labourers are said to be in the lowest
- stations. These methods of thinking and of expressing ourselves, are
- not of so little consequence as they may appear at first sight.
- 'Tis evident to common sense, as well as philosophy, that there is no
- natural nor essential difference betwixt high and low, and that this
- distinction arises only from the gravitation of matter, which produces
- a motion from the one to the other. The very same direction, which in
- this part of the globe is called _ascent_, is denominated _descent_ in
- our antipodes; which can proceed from nothing but the contrary tendency
- of bodies. Now 'tis certain, that the tendency of bodies, continually
- operating upon our senses, must produce, from custom, a like tendency
- in the fancy; and that when we consider any object situated in an
- ascent, the idea of its weight gives us a propensity to transport it
- from the place in which it is situated to the place immediately below
- it, and so on till we come to the ground, which equally stops the
- body and our imagination. For a like reason we feel a difficulty in
- mounting, and pass not without a kind of reluctance from the inferior
- to that which is situated above it; as if our ideas acquired a kind of
- gravity from their objects. As a proof of this, do we not find, that
- the facility, which is so much studied in music and poetry, is called
- the fall or cadency of the harmony or period; the idea of facility
- communicating to us that of descent, in the same manner as descent
- produces a facility?
- Since the imagination, therefore, in running from low to high, finds
- an opposition in its internal qualities and principles, and since
- the soul, when elevated with joy and courage, in a manner seeks
- opposition, and throws itself with alacrity into any scene of thought
- or action where its courage meets with matter to nourish and employ
- it, it follows, that every thing which invigorates and enlivens the
- soul, whether by touching the passions or imagination, naturally
- conveys to the fancy this inclination for ascent, and determines it to
- run against the natural stream of its thoughts and conceptions. This
- aspiring progress of the imagination suits the present disposition of
- the mind; and the difficulty, instead of extinguishing its vigour and
- alacrity, has the contrary effect of sustaining and increasing it.
- Virtue, genius, power and riches, are for this reason associated with
- height and sublimity, as poverty, slavery and folly, are conjoined
- with descent and lowness. Were the case the same with us as Milton
- represents it to be with the angels, to whom _descent is adverse_, and
- who _cannot sink without labour and compulsion_, this order of things
- would be entirely inverted; as appears hence, that the very nature of
- ascent and descent is derived from the difficulty and propensity, and
- consequently every one of their effects proceeds from that origin.
- All this is easily applied to the present question, why a considerable
- distance in time produces a greater veneration for the distant
- objects than a like removal in space. The imagination moves with more
- difficulty in passing from one portion of time to another, than in
- a transition through the parts of space; and that because space or
- extension appears united to our senses, while time or succession is
- always broken and divided. This difficulty, when joined with a small
- distance, interrupts and weakens the fancy, but has a contrary effect
- in a great removal. The mind, elevated by the vastness of its object,
- is still farther elevated by the difficulty of the conception, and,
- being obliged every moment to renew its efforts in the transition
- from one part of time to another, feels a more vigorous and sublime
- disposition than in a transition through the parts of space, where
- the ideas flow along with easiness and facility. In this disposition,
- the imagination, passing, as is usual, from the consideration of the
- distance to the view of the distant objects, gives us a proportionable
- veneration for it; and this is the reason why all the relicks of
- antiquity are so precious in our eyes, and appear more valuable than
- what is brought even from the remotest parts of the world.
- The third phenomenon I have remarked will be a full confirmation of
- this. 'Tis not every removal in time which has the effect of producing
- veneration and esteem. We are not apt to imagine our posterity
- will excel us, or equal our ancestors. This phenomenon is the more
- remarkable, because any distance in futurity weakens not our ideas so
- much as an equal removal in the past. Though a removal in the past,
- when very great, increases our passions beyond a like removal in the
- future, yet a small removal has a greater influence in diminishing them.
- In our common way of thinking we are placed in a kind of middle station
- betwixt the past and future; and as our imagination finds a kind of
- difficulty in running along the former, and a facility in following
- the course of the latter, the difficulty conveys the notion of ascent,
- and the facility of the contrary. Hence we imagine our ancestors to
- be, in a manner, mounted above us, and our posterity to lie below us.
- Our fancy arrives not at the one without effort, but easily reaches
- the other: which effort weakens the conception, where the distance is
- small; but enlarges and elevates the imagination, when attended with a
- suitable object. As on the other hand, the facility assists the fancy
- in a small removal, but takes off from its force when it contemplates
- any considerable distance.
- It may not be improper, before we leave this subject of the will, to
- resume, in a few words, all that has been said concerning it, in order
- to set the whole more distinctly before the eyes of the reader. What we
- commonly understand by _passion_ is a violent and sensible emotion of
- mind, when any good or evil is presented, or any object, which, by the
- original formation of our faculties, is fitted to excite an appetite.
- By _reason_ we mean affections of the very same kind with the former,
- but such as operate more calmly, and cause no disorder in the temper:
- which tranquillity leads us into a mistake concerning them, and causes
- us to regard them as conclusions only of our intellectual faculties.
- Both the _causes_ and _effects_ of these violent and calm passions are
- pretty variable, and depend, in a great measure, on the peculiar temper
- and disposition of every individual. Generally speaking, the violent
- passions have a more powerful influence on the will; though 'tis
- often found that the calm ones, when corroborated by reflection, and
- seconded by resolution, are able to control them in their most furious
- movements. What makes this whole affair more uncertain, is, that a calm
- passion may easily be changed into a violent one, either by a change
- of temper, or of the circumstances and situation of the object; as by
- the borrowing of force from any attendant passion, by custom, or by
- exciting the imagination. Upon the whole, this struggle of passion
- and of reason, as it is called, diversifies human life, and makes men
- so different not only from each other, but also from themselves in
- different times. Philosophy can only account for a few of the greater
- and more sensible events of this war; but must leave all the smaller
- and more delicate revolutions, as dependent on principles too fine and
- minute for her comprehension.
- SECTION IX.
- OF THE DIRECT PASSIONS.
- 'Tis easy to observe, that the passions, both direct and indirect,
- are founded on pain and pleasure, and that, in order to produce an
- affection of any kind, 'tis only requisite to present some good or
- evil. Upon the removal of pain and pleasure, there immediately follows
- a removal of love and hatred, pride and humility, desire and aversion,
- and of most of our reflective or secondary impressions.
- The impressions which arise from good and evil most naturally, and
- with the least preparation, are the _direct_ passions of desire and
- aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear, along with volition. The mind,
- by an _original_ instinct, tends to unite itself with the good, and
- to avoid the evil, though they be conceived merely in idea, and be
- considered as to exist in any future period of time.
- But supposing that there is an immediate impression of pain or
- pleasure, and _that_ arising from an object related to ourselves or
- others, this does not prevent the propensity or aversion, with the
- consequent emotions, but, by concurring with certain dormant principles
- of the human mind, excites the new impressions of pride or humility,
- love or hatred. That propensity which unites us to the object, or
- separates us from it, still continues to operate, but in conjunction
- with the _indirect_ passions which arise from a double relation of
- impressions and ideas.
- These indirect passions, being always agreeable or uneasy, give in
- their turn additional force to the direct passions, and increase
- our desire and aversion to the object. Thus, a suit of fine clothes
- produces pleasure from their beauty; and this pleasure produces the
- direct passions, or the impressions of volition and desire. Again,
- when these clothes are considered as belonging to ourself, the double
- relation conveys to us the sentiment of pride, which is an indirect
- passion; and the pleasure which attends that passion returns back to
- the direct affections, and gives new force to our desire or volition,
- joy or hope.
- When good is certain or probable, it produces _joy_. When evil is in
- the same situation, there arises _grief or sorrow_.
- When either good or evil is uncertain, it gives rise to _fear_ or
- _hope_, according to the degrees of uncertainty on the one side or the
- other.
- _Desire_ arises from good considered simply; and _aversion_ is derived
- from evil. The _will_ exerts itself, when either the good or the
- absence of the evil may be attained by any action of the mind or body.
- Beside good and evil, or, in other words, pain and pleasure, the direct
- passions frequently arise from a natural impulse or instinct, which is
- perfectly unaccountable. Of this kind is the desire of punishment to
- our enemies, and of happiness to our friends; hunger, lust, and a few
- other bodily appetites. These passions, properly speaking, produce
- good and evil, and proceed not from them, like the other affections.
- None of the direct affections seem to merit our particular attention,
- except hope and fear, which we shall here endeavour to account for.
- 'Tis evident that the very same event, which, by its certainty,
- would produce grief or joy, gives always rise to fear or hope, when
- only probable and uncertain. In order, therefore, to understand the
- reason why this circumstance makes such a considerable difference, we
- must reflect on what I have already advanced in the preceding book
- concerning the nature of probability.
- Probability arises from an opposition of contrary chances or causes, by
- which the mind is not allowed to fix on either side, but is incessantly
- tost from one to another, and at one moment is determined to consider
- an object as existent, and at another moment as the contrary. The
- imagination or understanding, call it which you please, fluctuates
- betwixt the opposite views; and though perhaps it may be oftener turned
- to the one side than the other, 'tis impossible for it, by reason of
- the opposition of causes or chances, to rest on either. The _pro_ and
- _con_ of the question alternately prevail; and the mind, surveying the
- object in its opposite principles, finds such a contrariety as utterly
- destroys all certainty and established opinion.
- Suppose, then, that the object, concerning whose reality we are
- doubtful, is an object either of desire or aversion, 'tis evident
- that, according as the mind turns itself either to the one side or
- the other, it must feel a momentary impression of joy or sorrow. An
- object, whose existence we desire, gives satisfaction, when we reflect
- on those causes which produce it; and, for the same reason, excites
- grief or uneasiness from the opposite consideration: so that as the
- understanding, in all probable questions, is divided betwixt the
- contrary points of view, the affections must in the same manner be
- divided betwixt opposite emotions.
- Now, if we consider the human mind, we shall find, that, with regard
- to the passions, 'tis not of the nature of a wind-instrument of music,
- which, in running over all the notes, immediately loses the sound
- after the breath ceases; but rather resembles, a string-instrument,
- where, after each stroke, the vibrations still retain some sound, which
- gradually and insensibly decays. The imagination is extremely quick
- and agile; but the passions are slow and restive: for which reason,
- when any object is presented that affords a variety of views to the
- one, and emotions to the other, though the fancy may change its views
- with great celerity, each stroke will not produce a clear and distinct
- note of passion, but the one passion will always be mixt and confounded
- with the other. According as the probability inclines to good or evil,
- the passion of joy or sorrow predominates in the composition: because
- the nature of probability is to cast a superior number of views or
- chances on one side; or, which is the same thing, a superior number of
- returns of one passion; or, since the dispersed passions are collected
- into one, a superior degree of that passion. That is, in other words,
- the grief and joy being intermingled with each other, by means of
- the contrary views of the imagination, produce, by their union, the
- passions of hope and fear.
- Upon this head there may be started a very curious question concerning
- that contrariety of passions which is our present subject. 'Tis
- observable, that where the objects of contrary passions are presented
- at once, beside the increase of the predominant passion (which has
- been already explained, and commonly arises at their first shock
- or rencounter), it sometimes happens that both the passions exist
- successively, and by short intervals; sometimes, that they destroy each
- other, and neither of them takes place; and sometimes that both of them
- remain united in the mind. It may therefore be asked, by what theory
- we can explain these variations, and to what general principle we can
- reduce them.
- When the contrary passions arise from objects entirely different, they
- take place alternately, the want of relation in the ideas separating
- the impressions from each other, and preventing their opposition. Thus,
- when a man is afflicted for the loss of a lawsuit, and joyful for the
- birth of a son, the mind running from the agreeable to the calamitous
- object, with whatever celerity it may perform this motion, can scarcely
- temper the one affection with the other, and remain betwixt them in a
- state of indifference.
- It more easily attains that calm situation, when the same event is of
- a mixt nature, and contains something adverse and something prosperous
- in its different circumstances. For in that case, both the passions,
- mingling with each other by means of the relation, become mutually
- destructive, and leave the mind in perfect tranquillity.
- But suppose, in the third place, that the object is not a compound
- of good or evil, but is considered as probable or improbable in any
- degree; in that case I assert, that the contrary passions will both
- of them be present at once in the soul, and, instead of destroying
- and tempering each other, will subsist together, and produce a third
- impression or affection by their union. Contrary passions are not
- capable of destroying each other, except when their contrary movements
- exactly rencounter, and are opposite in their direction, as well as
- in the sensation they produce. This exact rencounter depends upon the
- relations of those ideas from which they are derived, and is more or
- less perfect, according to the degrees of the relation. In the case
- of probability, the contrary chances are so far related that they
- determine concerning the existence or non-existence of the same object.
- But this relation is far from being perfect, since some of the chances
- lie on the side of existence, and others on that of non-existence,
- which are objects altogether incompatible. 'Tis impossible, by one
- steady view, to survey the opposite chances, and the events dependent
- on them; but 'tis necessary that the imagination should run alternately
- from the one to the other. Each view of the imagination produces its
- peculiar passion, which decays away by degrees, and is followed by a
- sensible vibration after the stroke. The incompatibility of the views
- keeps the passions from shocking in a direct line, if that expression
- may be allowed; and yet their relation is sufficient to mingle their
- fainter emotions. 'Tis after this manner that hope and fear arise from
- the different mixture of these opposite passions of grief and joy, and
- from their imperfect union and conjunction.
- Upon the whole, contrary passions succeed each other alternately, when
- they arise from different objects; they mutually destroy each other,
- when they proceed from different parts of the same; and they subsist,
- both of them, and mingle together, when they are derived from the
- contrary and incompatible chances or possibilities on which any one
- object depends. The influence of the relations of ideas is plainly
- seen in this whole affair. If the objects of the contrary passions
- be totally different, the passions are like two opposite liquors in
- different bottles, which have no influence on each other. If the
- objects be intimately connected, the passions are like an _alkali_ and
- an _acid_, which, being mingled, destroy each other. If the relation
- be more imperfect, and consists in the contradictory views of the same
- object, the passions are like oil and vinegar, which, however mingled,
- never perfectly unite and incorporate.
- As the hypothesis concerning hope and fear carries its own evidence
- along with it, we shall be the more concise in our proofs. A few strong
- arguments are better than many weak ones.
- The passions of fear and hope may arise when the chances are equal on
- both sides, and no superiority can be discovered in the one above the
- other. Nay, in this situation the passions are rather the strongest, as
- the mind has then the least foundation to rest upon, and is tossed with
- the greatest uncertainty. Throw in a superior degree of probability to
- the side of grief, you immediately see that passion diffuse itself over
- the composition, and tincture it into fear. Increase the probability,
- and by that means the grief, the fear prevails still more and more,
- till at last it runs insensibly, as the joy continually diminishes,
- into pure grief. After you have brought it to this situation, diminish
- the grief, after the same manner that you increased it, by diminishing
- the probability on that side, and you'll see the passion clear every
- moment, 'till it changes insensibly into hope; which again runs, after
- the same manner, by slow degrees, into joy, as you increase that part
- of the composition by the increase of the probability. Are not these
- as plain proofs, that the passions of fear and hope are mixtures of
- grief and joy, as in optics 'tis a proof, that a coloured ray of the
- sun passing through a prism, is a composition of two others, when, as
- you diminish or increase the quantity of either, you find it prevail
- proportionably more or less in the composition? I am sure neither
- natural nor moral philosophy admits of stronger proofs.
- Probability is of two kinds, either when the object is really in itself
- uncertain, and to be determined by chance; or when, though the object
- be already certain, yet 'tis uncertain to our judgment, which finds
- a number of proofs on each side of the question. Both these kinds of
- probabilities cause fear and hope; which can only proceed from that
- property, in which they agree, viz. the uncertainty and fluctuation
- they bestow on the imagination by the contrariety of views which is
- common to both.
- 'Tis a probable good or evil that commonly produces hope or fear;
- because probability, being a wavering and unconstant method of
- surveying an object, causes naturally a like mixture and uncertainty
- of passion. But we may observe, that wherever, from other causes, this
- mixture can be produced, the passions of fear and hope will arise,
- even though there be no probability; which must be allowed to be a
- convincing proof of the present hypothesis.
- We find that an evil, barely conceived as _possible_, does sometimes
- produce fear; especially if the evil be very great. A man cannot think
- of excessive pains and tortures without trembling, if he be in the
- least danger of suffering them. The smallness of the probability is
- compensated by the greatness of the evil; and the sensation is equally
- lively, as if the evil were more probable. One view or glimpse of the
- former has the same effect as several of the latter.
- But they are not only possible evils that cause fear, but even some
- allowed to be _impossible_; as when we tremble on the brink of a
- precipice, though we know ourselves to be in perfect security, and
- have it in our choice whether we will advance a step farther. This
- proceeds from the immediate presence of the evil, which influences the
- imagination in the same manner as the certainty of it would do; but
- being encountered by the reflection on our security, is immediately
- retracted, and causes the same kind of passion, as when, from a
- contrariety of chances, contrary passions are produced.
- Evils that are _certain_ have sometimes the same effect in producing
- fear, as the possible or impossible. Thus, a man in a strong prison
- well-guarded, without the least means of escape, trembles at the
- thought of the rack, to which he is sentenced. This happens only when
- the certain evil is terrible and confounding; in which case the mind
- continually rejects it with horror, while it continually presses in
- upon the thought. The evil is there fixed and established, but the mind
- cannot endure to fix upon it; from which fluctuation and uncertainty
- there arises a passion of much the same appearance with fear.
- But 'tis not only where good or evil is uncertain, as to its
- _existence_, but also as to its _kind_, that fear or hope arises. Let
- one be told by a person, whose veracity he cannot doubt of, that one
- of his sons is suddenly killed, 'tis evident the passion this event
- would occasion, would not settle into pure grief, till he got certain
- information which of his sons he had lost. Here there is an evil
- certain, but the kind of it uncertain: consequently the fear we feel on
- this occasion is without the least mixture of joy, and arises merely
- from the fluctuation of the fancy betwixt its objects. And though each
- side of the question produces here the same passion, yet that passion
- cannot settle, but receives from the imagination a tremulous and
- unsteady motion, resembling in its cause, as well as in its sensation,
- the mixture and contention of grief and joy.
- From these principles we may account for a phenomenon in the passions,
- which at first sight seems very extraordinary, viz. that surprise is
- apt to change into fear, and every thing that is unexpected affrights
- us. The most obvious conclusion from this is, that human nature is
- in general pusillanimous; since, upon the sudden appearance of any
- object, we immediately conclude it to be an evil, and, without waiting
- till we can examine its nature, whether it be good or bad, are at
- first affected with fear. This, I say, is the most obvious conclusion;
- but upon farther examination, we shall find that the phenomenon is
- otherwise to be accounted for. The suddenness and strangeness of an
- appearance naturally excite a commotion in the mind, like every thing
- for which we are not prepared, and to which we are not accustomed. This
- commotion, again, naturally produces a curiosity or inquisitiveness,
- which, being very violent, from the strong and sudden impulse of
- the object, becomes uneasy, and resembles in its fluctuation and
- uncertainty, the sensation of fear, or the mixed passions of grief and
- joy. This image of fear naturally converts into the thing itself, and
- gives us a real apprehension of evil, as the mind always forms its
- judgments more from its present disposition than from the nature of its
- objects.
- Thus all kinds of uncertainty have a strong connexion with fear, even
- though they do not cause any opposition of passions by the opposite
- views and considerations they present to us. A person who has left his
- friend in any malady, will feel more anxiety upon his account, than if
- he were present, though perhaps he is not only incapable of giving him
- assistance, but likewise of judging of the event of his sickness. In
- this case, though the principle object of the passion, viz. the life or
- death of his friend, be to him equally uncertain when present as when
- absent; yet there are, a thousand little circumstances of his friend's
- situation and condition, the knowledge of which fixes the idea, and
- prevents that fluctuation and uncertainty so nearly allied to fear.
- Uncertainty is, indeed, in one respect, as nearly allied to hope as to
- fear, since it makes an essential part in the composition of the former
- passion; but the reason why it inclines not to that side, is, that
- uncertainty alone is uneasy, and has a relation of impressions to the
- uneasy passions.
- 'Tis thus our uncertainty concerning any minute circumstance relating
- to a person, increases our apprehensions of his death or misfortune.
- Horace has remarked this phenomenon:
- Ut assidens implumibus pullus avis
- Serpentium allapsus timet,
- Magis relictis; non, ut adsit, auxili
- Latura plus presentibus.
- But this principle of the connexion of fear with uncertainty I carry
- farther, and observe, that any doubt produces that passion, even
- though it presents nothing to us on any side but what is good and
- desirable. A virgin, on her bridal-night goes to bed full of fears and
- apprehensions, though she expects nothing but pleasure of the highest
- kind, and what she has long wished for. The newness and greatness of
- the event, the confusion of wishes and joys, so embarrass the mind,
- that it knows not on what passion to fix itself; from whence arises
- a fluttering or unsettledness of the spirits, which being, in some
- degree, uneasy, very naturally degenerates into fear.
- Thus we still find, that whatever causes any fluctuation or mixture of
- passions, with any degree of uneasiness, always produces fear, or at
- least a passion so like it, that they are scarcely to be distinguished.
- I have here confined myself to the examination of hope and fear in
- their most simple and natural situation, without considering all the
- variations they may receive from the mixture of different views and
- reflections. _Terror, consternation, astonishment, anxiety_, and
- other passions of that kind, are nothing but different species and
- degrees of fear. 'Tis easy to imagine how a different situation of the
- object, or a different turn of thought, may change even the sensation
- of a passion; and this may in general account for all the particular
- subdivisions of the other affections, as well as of fear. Love may
- show itself in the shape of _tenderness, friendship, intimacy, esteem,
- good-will_, and in many other appearances; which at the bottom are the
- same affections, and arise from the same causes, though with a small
- variation, which it is not necessary to give any particular account of.
- 'Tis for this reason I have all along confined myself to the principal
- passion.
- The same care of avoiding prolixity is the reason why I waive the
- examination of the will and direct passions, as they appear in animals;
- since nothing is more evident, than that they are of the same nature,
- and excited by the same causes as in human creatures. I leave this to
- the reader's own observation, desiring him at the same time to consider
- the additional force this bestows on the present system.
- SECTION X.
- OF CURIOSITY, OR THE LOVE OF TRUTH.
- But methinks we have been not a little inattentive to run over so
- many different parts of the human mind, and examine so many passions,
- without taking once into consideration that love of truth, which was
- the first source of all our inquiries. 'Twill therefore be proper,
- before we leave this subject, to bestow a few reflections on that
- passion, and show its origin in human nature. 'Tis an affection of so
- peculiar a kind, that it would have been impossible to have treated of
- it under any of those heads, which we have examined, without danger of
- obscurity and confusion.
- Truth is of two kinds, consisting either in the discovery of the
- proportions of ideas, considered as such, or in the conformity of our
- ideas of objects to their real existence. 'Tis certain that the former
- species of truth is not desired merely as truth, and that 'tis not the
- justness of our conclusions, which alone gives the pleasure. For these
- conclusions are equally just, when we discover the equality of two
- bodies by a pair of compasses, as when we learn it by a mathematical
- demonstration; and though in the one case the proofs be demonstrative,
- and in the other only sensible, yet generally speaking, the mind
- acquiesces with equal assurance in the one as in the other. And in
- an arithmetical operation, where both the truth and the assurance are
- of the same nature, as in the most profound algebraical problem, the
- pleasure is very inconsiderable, if rather it does not degenerate
- into pain: which is an evident proof, that the satisfaction, which we
- sometimes receive from the discovery of truth, proceeds not from it,
- merely as such, but only as endowed with certain qualities.
- The first and most considerable circumstance requisite to render
- truth agreeable, is the genius and capacity which is employed in its
- invention and discovery. What is easy and obvious is never valued;
- and even what is _in itself_ difficult, if we come to the knowledge
- of it without difficulty, and without any stretch of thought or
- judgment, is but little regarded. We love to trace the demonstrations
- of mathematicians; but should receive small entertainment from a person
- who should barely inform us of the proportions of lines and angles,
- though we reposed the utmost confidence both in his judgment and
- veracity. In this case 'tis sufficient to have ears to learn the truth.
- We never are obliged to fix our attention or exert our genius; which of
- all other exercises of the mind is the most pleasant and agreeable.
- But though the exercise of genius be the principal source of that
- satisfaction we receive from the sciences, yet I doubt if it be alone
- sufficient to give us any considerable enjoyment. The truth we discover
- must also be of some importance. 'Tis easy to multiply algebraical
- problems to infinity, nor is there any end in the discovery of the
- proportions of conic sections; though few mathematicians take any
- pleasure in these researches, but turn their thoughts to what is
- more useful and important. Now the question is, after what manner
- this utility and importance operate upon us? The difficulty on this
- head arises from hence, that many philosophers have consumed their
- time, have destroyed their health, and neglected their fortune, in
- the search of such truths, as they esteemed important and useful to
- the world, though it appeared from their whole conduct and behaviour,
- that they were not endowed with any share of public spirit, nor had
- any concern for the interests of mankind. Were they convinced that
- their discoveries were of no consequence, they would entirely lose all
- relish for their studies, and that though the consequences be entirely
- indifferent to them; which seems to be a contradiction.
- To remove this contradiction, we must consider, that there are certain
- desires and inclinations, which go no farther than the imagination,
- and are rather the faint shadows and images of passions, than any
- real affections. Thus, suppose a man, who takes a survey of the
- fortifications of any city; considers their strength and advantages,
- natural or acquired; observes the disposition and contrivance of the
- bastions, ramparts, mines, and other military works; 'tis plain that,
- in proportion as all these are fitted to attain their ends, he will
- receive a suitable pleasure and satisfaction. This pleasure, as it
- arises from the utility, not the form of the objects, can be no other
- than a sympathy with the inhabitants, for whose security all this art
- is employed; though 'tis possible that this person, as a stranger or
- an enemy, may in his heart have no kindness for them, or may even
- entertain a hatred against them.
- It may indeed be objected, that such a remote sympathy is a very slight
- foundation for a passion, and that so much industry and application,
- as we frequently observe in philosophers, can never be derived from so
- inconsiderable an original. But here I return to what I have already
- remarked, that the pleasure of study consists chiefly in the action
- of the mind, and the exercise of the genius and understanding in the
- discovery or comprehension of any truth. If the importance of the truth
- be requisite to complete the pleasure, 'tis not on account of any
- considerable addition which of itself it brings to our enjoyment, but
- only because 'tis in some measure requisite to fix our attention. When
- we are careless and inattentive, the same action of the understanding
- has no effect upon us, nor is able to convey any of that satisfaction
- which arises from it when we are in another disposition.
- But beside the action of the mind, which is the principal foundation
- of the pleasure, there is likewise required a degree of success in
- the attainment of the end, or the discovery of that truth we examine.
- Upon this head I shall make a general remark, which may be useful
- on many occasions, viz. that where the mind pursues any end with
- passion, though that passion be not derived originally from the end,
- but merely from the action and pursuit, yet, by the natural course
- of the affections, we acquire a concern for the end itself, and are
- uneasy under any disappointment we meet with in the pursuit of it.
- This proceeds from the relation and parallel direction of the passions
- above-mentioned.
- To illustrate all this by a similar instance, I shall observe, that
- there cannot be two passions more nearly resembling each other than
- those of hunting and philosophy, whatever disproportion may at first
- sight appear betwixt them. 'Tis evident, that the pleasure of hunting
- consists in the action of the mind and body; the motion, the attention,
- the difficulty, and the uncertainty. 'Tis evident, likewise, that these
- actions must be attended with an idea of utility, in order to their
- having any effect upon us. A man of the greatest fortune, and the
- farthest removed from avarice, though he takes a pleasure in hunting
- after partridges and pheasants, feels no satisfaction in shooting crows
- and magpies; and that because he considers the first as fit for the
- table, and the other as entirely useless. Here 'tis certain, that the
- utility or importance of itself causes no real passion, but is only
- requisite to support the imagination; and the same person who overlooks
- a ten times greater profit in any other subject, is pleased to bring
- home half a dozen woodcocks or plovers, after having employed several
- hours in hunting after them. To make the parallel betwixt hunting and
- philosophy more complete, we may observe, that though in both cases
- the end of our action may in itself be despised, yet, in the heat of
- the action, we acquire such an attention to this end, that we are very
- uneasy under any disappointments, and are sorry when we either miss our
- game, or fall into any error in our reasoning.
- If we want another parallel to these affections, we may consider the
- passion of gaming, which affords a pleasure from the same principles
- as hunting and philosophy. It has been remarked, that the pleasure of
- gaming arises not from interest alone, since many leave a sure gain for
- this entertainment; neither is it derived from the game alone, since
- the same persons have no satisfaction when they play for nothing; but
- proceeds from both these causes united, though separately they have
- no effect. 'Tis here, as in certain chemical preparations, where the
- mixture of two clear and transparent liquids produces a third, which is
- opaque and coloured.
- The interest which we have in any game engages our attention, without
- which we can have no enjoyment, either in that or in any other action.
- Our attention being once engaged, the difficulty, variety, and sudden
- reverses of fortune; still farther interest us; and 'tis from that
- concern our satisfaction arises. Human life is so tiresome a scene, and
- men generally are of such indolent dispositions, that whatever amuses
- them, though by a passion mixed with pain, does in the main give them a
- sensible pleasure. And this pleasure is here increased by the nature of
- the objects, which, being sensible and of a narrow compass, are entered
- into with facility, and are agreeable to the imagination.
- The same theory that accounts for the love of truth in mathematics
- and algebra, may be extended to morals, politics, natural philosophy,
- and other studies, where we consider not the abstract relations of
- ideas, but their real connexions and existence. But beside the love of
- knowledge which displays itself in the sciences, there is a certain
- curiosity implanted in human nature, which is a passion derived from
- a quite different principle. Some people have an insatiable desire of
- knowing the actions and circumstances of their neighbours, though their
- interest be no way concerned in them, and they must entirely depend on
- others for their information; in which case there is no room for study
- or application. Let us search for the reason of this phenomenon.
- It has been proved at large, that the influence of belief is at once
- to enliven and infix any idea in the imagination, and prevent all kind
- of hesitation and uncertainty about it. Both these circumstances are
- advantageous. By the vivacity of the idea we interest the fancy, and
- produce, though in a lesser degree, the same pleasure which arises from
- a moderate passion. As the vivacity of the idea gives pleasure, so its
- certainty prevents uneasiness, by fixing one particular idea in the
- mind, and keeping it from wavering in the choice of its objects. 'Tis a
- quality of human nature which is conspicuous on many occasions, and is
- common both to the mind and body, that too sudden and violent a change
- is unpleasant to us, and that, however any objects may in themselves be
- indifferent, yet their alteration gives uneasiness. As 'tis the nature
- of doubt to cause a variation in the thought, and transport us suddenly
- from one idea to another, it must of consequence be the occasion of
- pain. This pain chiefly takes place where interest, relation, or the
- greatness and novelty of any event interests us in it. 'Tis not every
- matter of fact of which we have a curiosity to be informed; neither are
- they such only as we have an interest to know. 'Tis sufficient if the
- idea strikes on us with such force, and concerns us so nearly, as to
- give us an uneasiness in its instability and inconstancy. A stranger,
- when he arrives first at any town, may be entirely indifferent about
- knowing the history and adventures of the inhabitants; but as he
- becomes farther acquainted with them, and has lived any considerable
- time among them, he acquires the same curiosity as the natives. When
- we are reading the history of a nation, we may have an ardent desire
- of clearing up any doubt or difficulty that occurs in it; but become
- careless in such researches, when the ideas of these events are, in a
- great measure, obliterated.
- BOOK III.
- OF MORALS.
- PART I.
- OF VIRTUE AND VICE IN GENERAL.
- SECTION I.
- MORAL DISTINCTIONS NOT DERIVED FROM REASON.
- There is an inconvenience which attends all abstruse reasoning, that
- it may silence, without convincing an antagonist, and requires the
- same intense study to make us sensible of its force, that was at first
- requisite for its invention. When we leave our closet, and engage
- in the common affairs of life, its conclusions seem to vanish like
- the phantoms of the night on the appearance of the morning; and 'tis
- difficult for us to retain even that conviction which we had attained
- with difficulty. This is still more conspicuous in a long chain of
- reasoning, where we must preserve to the end the evidence of the first
- propositions, and where we often lose sight of all the most received
- maxims, either of philosophy or common life. I am not, however, without
- hopes, that the present system of philosophy will acquire new force
- as it advances; and that our reasonings concerning _morals_ will
- corroborate whatever has been said concerning the _understanding_ and
- the _passions_. Morality is a subject that interests us above all
- others; we fancy the peace of society to be at stake in every decision
- concerning it; and 'tis evident, that this concern must make our
- speculations appear more real and solid, than where the subject is in
- a great measure indifferent to us. What affects us, we conclude can
- never be a chimera; and, as our passion is engaged on the one side
- or the other, we naturally think that the question lies within human
- comprehension; which, in other cases of this nature, we are apt to
- entertain some doubt of. Without this advantage, I never should have
- ventured upon a third volume of such abstruse philosophy, in an age
- wherein the greatest part of men seem agreed to convert reading into
- an amusement, and to reject every thing that requires any considerable
- degree of attention to be comprehended.
- It has been observed, that nothing is ever present to the mind but its
- perceptions; and that all the actions of seeing, hearing, judging,
- loving, hating, and thinking, fall under this denomination. The mind
- can never exert itself in any action which we may not comprehend
- under the term of _perception_; and consequently that term is no less
- applicable to those judgments by which we distinguish moral good and
- evil, than to every other operation of the mind. To approve of one
- character, to condemn another, are only so many different perceptions.
- Now, as perceptions resolve themselves into two kinds, viz.
- _impressions_ and _ideas_, this distinction gives rise to a question,
- with which we shall open up our present inquiry concerning morals,
- _whether 'tis by means of our ideas or impressions we distinguish
- betwixt vice and virtue, and pronounce an action blameable or
- praiseworthy_? This will immediately cut off all loose discourses and
- declamations, and reduce us to something precise and exact on the
- present subject.
- Those who affirm that virtue is nothing but a conformity to reason;
- that there are eternal fitnesses and unfitnesses of things, which
- are the same to every rational being that considers them; that the
- immutable measures of right and wrong impose an obligation, not
- only on human creatures, but also on the Deity himself: all these
- systems concur in the opinion, that morality, like truth, is discerned
- merely by ideas, and by their juxtaposition and comparison. In order,
- therefore, to judge of these systems, we need only consider, whether it
- be possible, from reason alone, to distinguish betwixt moral good and
- evil, or whether there must concur some other principles to enable us
- to make that distinction.
- If morality had naturally no influence on human passions and actions,
- 'twere in vain to take such pains to inculcate it; and nothing would be
- more fruitless than that multitude of rules and precepts with which all
- moralists abound. Philosophy is commonly divided into _speculative_ and
- _practical_; and as morality is always comprehended under the latter
- division, 'tis supposed to influence our passions and actions, and to
- go beyond the calm and indolent judgments of the understanding. And
- this is confirmed by common experience, which informs us, that men are
- often governed by their duties, and are deterred from some actions by
- the opinion of injustice, and impelled to others by that of obligation.
- Since morals, therefore, have an influence on the actions and
- affections, it follows, that they cannot be derived from reason; and
- that because reason alone, as we have already proved, can never have
- any such influence. Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent
- actions. Reason of itself is utterly impotent in this particular. The
- rules of morality, therefore, are not conclusions of our reason.
- No one, I believe, will deny the justness of this inference; nor is
- there any other means of evading it, than by denying that principle,
- on which it is founded. As long as it is allowed, that reason has
- no influence on our passions and actions, 'tis in vain to pretend
- that morality is discovered only by a deduction of reason. An
- active principle can never be founded on an inactive; and it reason
- be inactive in itself, it must remain so in all its shapes and
- appearances, whether it exerts itself in natural or moral subjects,
- whether it considers the powers of external bodies, or the actions of
- rational beings.
- It would be tedious to repeat all the arguments, by which I have
- proved,[1] that reason is perfectly inert, and can never either prevent
- or produce any action or affection. 'Twill be easy to recollect what
- has been said upon that subject. I shall only recall on this occasion
- one of these arguments, which I shall endeavour to render still more
- conclusive, and more applicable to the present subject.
- Reason is the discovery of truth or falsehood. Truth or falsehood
- consists in an agreement or disagreement either to the _real_ relations
- of ideas, or to _real_ existence and matter of fact. Whatever therefore
- is not susceptible of this agreement or disagreement, is incapable of
- being true or false, and can never be an object of our reason. Now,
- 'tis evident our passions, volitions, and actions, are not susceptible
- of any such agreement or disagreement; being original facts and
- realities, complete in themselves, and implying no reference to other
- passions, volitions, and actions. 'Tis impossible, therefore, they
- can be pronounced either true or false, and be either contrary or
- conformable to reason.
- This argument is of double advantage to our present purpose. For it
- proves _directly_, that actions do not derive their merit from a
- conformity to reason, nor their blame from a contrariety to it; and it
- proves the same truth more _indirectly_, by showing us, that as reason
- can never immediately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or
- approving of it, it cannot be the source of moral good and evil, which
- are found to have that influence. Actions may be laudable or blameable;
- but they cannot be reasonable or unreasonable: laudable or blameable,
- therefore, are not the same with reasonable or unreasonable. The merit
- and demerit of actions frequently contradict, and sometimes control
- our natural propensities. But reason has no such influence. Moral
- distinctions, therefore, are not the offspring of reason. Reason is
- wholly inactive, and can never be the source of so active a principle
- as conscience, or a sense of morals.
- But perhaps it may be said, that though no will or action can
- be immediately contradictory to reason, yet we may find such a
- contradiction in some of the attendants of the action, that is, in
- its causes or effects. The action may cause a judgment, or may be
- _obliquely_ caused by one, when the judgment concurs with a passion;
- and by an abusive way of speaking, which philosophy will scarce allow
- of, the same contrariety may, upon that account, be ascribed to the
- action. How far this truth or falsehood may be the source of morals,
- 'twill now be proper to consider.
- It has been observed, that reason, in a strict and philosophical sense,
- can have an influence on our conduct only after two ways: either when
- it excites a passion, by informing us of the existence of something
- which is a proper object of it; or when it discovers the connexion of
- causes and effects, so as to afford us means of exerting any passion.
- These are the only kinds of judgment which can accompany our actions,
- or can be said to produce them in any manner; and it must be allowed,
- that these judgments may often be false and erroneous. A person may be
- affected with passion, by supposing a pain or pleasure to lie in an
- object, which has no tendency to produce either of these sensations, or
- which produces the contrary to what is imagined. A person may also take
- false measures for the attaining of his end, and may retard, by his
- foolish conduct, instead of forwarding the execution of any project.
- These false judgments may be thought to affect the passions and
- actions, which are connected with them, and may be said to render them
- unreasonable, in a figurative and improper way of speaking. But though
- this be acknowledged, 'tis easy to observe, that these errors are so
- far from being the source of all immorality, that they are commonly
- very innocent, and draw no manner of guilt upon the person who is so
- unfortunate as to fall into them. They extend not beyond a mistake of
- _fact_, which moralists have not generally supposed criminal, as being
- perfectly involuntary. I am more to be lamented than blamed, if I am
- mistaken with regard to the influence of objects in producing pain or
- pleasure, or if I know not the proper means of satisfying my desires.
- No one can ever regard such errors as a defect in my moral character.
- A fruit, for instance, that is really disagreeable, appears to me
- at a distance, and, through mistake, I fancy it to be pleasant and
- delicious. Here is one error. I choose certain means of reaching this
- fruit, which are not proper for my end. Here is a second error; nor is
- there any third one, which can ever possibly enter into our reasonings
- concerning actions. I ask, therefore, if a man in this situation, and
- guilty of these two errors, is to be regarded as vicious and criminal,
- however unavoidable they might have been? Or if it be possible to
- imagine, that such errors are the sources of all immorality?
- And here it may be proper to observe, that if moral distinctions be
- derived from the truth or falsehood of those judgments, they must take
- place wherever we form the judgments; nor will there be any difference,
- whether the question be concerning an apple or a kingdom, or whether
- the error be avoidable or unavoidable.
- For as the very essence of morality is supposed to consist in an
- agreement or disagreement to reason, the other circumstances are
- entirely arbitrary, and can never either bestow on any action the
- character of virtuous or vicious, or deprive it of that character. To
- which we may add, that this agreement or disagreement, not admitting of
- degrees, all virtues and vices would of course be equal.
- Should it be pretended, that though a mistake of _fact_ be not
- criminal, yet a mistake of _right_ often is; and that this may be
- the source of immorality: I would answer, that 'tis impossible such
- a mistake can ever be the original source of immorality, since it
- supposes a real right and wrong; that is, a real distinction in morals,
- independent of these judgments. A mistake, therefore, of right, may
- become a species of immorality; but 'tis only a secondary one, and is
- founded on some other antecedent to it.
- As to those judgments which are the _effects_ of our actions, and
- which, when false, give occasion to pronounce the actions contrary
- to truth and reason; we may observe, that our actions never cause
- any judgment, either true or false, in ourselves, and that 'tis only
- on others they have such an influence. 'Tis certain that an action,
- on many occasions, may give rise to false conclusions in others;
- and that a person, who, through a window, sees any lewd behaviour of
- mine with my neighbour's wife, may be so simple as to imagine she is
- certainly my own. In this respect my action resembles somewhat a lie or
- falsehood; only with this difference, which is material, that I perform
- not the action with any intention of giving rise to a false judgment
- in another, but merely to satisfy my lust and passion. It causes,
- however, a mistake and false judgment by accident; and the falsehood of
- its effects may be ascribed, by some odd figurative way of speaking,
- to the action itself. But still I can see no pretext of reason for
- asserting, that the tendency to cause such an error is the first spring
- or original source of all immorality.[2]
- Thus, upon the whole, 'tis impossible that the distinction betwixt
- moral good and evil can be made by reason; since that distinction has
- an influence upon our actions, of which reason alone is incapable.
- Reason and judgment may, indeed, be the mediate cause of an action, by
- prompting or by directing a passion; but it is not pretended that a
- judgment of this kind, either in its truth or falsehood, is attended
- with virtue or vise. And as to the judgments, which are caused by our
- judgments, they can still less bestow those moral qualities on the
- actions which are their causes.
- But, to be more particular, and to show that those eternal immutable
- fitnesses and unfitnesses of things cannot be defended by sound
- philosophy, we may weigh the following considerations.
- If the thought and understanding were alone capable of fixing the
- boundaries of right and wrong, the character of virtuous and vicious
- either must lie in some relations of objects, or must be a matter
- of fact which is discovered by our reasoning. This consequence is
- evident. As' the operations of human understanding divide themselves
- into two kinds, the comparing of ideas, and the inferring of matter
- of fact, were virtue discovered by the understanding, it must be an
- object of one of these operations; nor is there any third operation
- of the understanding which can discover it. There has been an opinion
- very industriously propagated by certain philosophers, that morality
- is susceptible of demonstration; and though no one has ever been able
- to advance a single step in those demonstrations, yet tis taken for
- granted that this science may be brought to an equal certainty with
- geometry or algebra. Upon this supposition, vice and virtue must
- consist in some relations; since 'tis allowed on all hands, that no
- matter of fact is capable of being demonstrated. Let us therefore
- begin with examining this hypothesis, and endeavour, if possible,
- to fix those moral qualities which have been so long the objects of
- our fruitless researches; point out distinctly the relations which
- constitute morality or obligation, that we may know wherein they
- consist, and after what manner we must judge of them.
- If you assert that vice and virtue consist in relations susceptible
- of certainty and demonstration, you must confine yourself to those
- _four_ relations which alone admit of that degree of evidence; and in
- that case you run into absurdities from which you will never be able
- to extricate yourself. For as you make the very essence of morality to
- lie in the relations, and as there is no one of these relations but
- what is applicable, not only to an irrational but also to an inanimate
- object, it follows, that even such objects must be susceptible of
- merit or demerit. _Resemblance, contrariety, degrees in quality_, and
- _proportions in quantity and number_; all these relations belong as
- properly to matter, as to our actions, passions, and volitions. 'Tis
- unquestionable, therefore, that morality lies not in any of these
- relations, nor the sense of it in their discovery.[3]
- Should it be asserted, that the sense of morality consists in
- the discovery of some relation distinct from these, and that our
- enumeration was not complete when we comprehended all demonstrable
- relations under four general heads; to this I know not what to reply,
- till some one be so good as to point out to me this new relation. 'Tis
- impossible to refute a system which has never yet been explained. In
- such a manner of fighting in the dark, a man loses his blows in the
- air, and often places them where the enemy is not present.
- I must therefore, on this occasion, rest contented with requiring the
- two following conditions of any one that would undertake to clear up
- this system. _First_, as moral good and evil belong only to the actions
- of the mind, and are derived from our situation with regard to external
- objects, the relations from which these moral distinctions arise must
- lie only betwixt internal actions and external objects, and must not be
- applicable either to internal actions, compared among themselves, or to
- external objects, when placed in opposition to other external objects.
- For as morality is supposed to attend certain relations, if these
- relations could belong to internal actions considered singly, it would
- follow, that we might be guilty of crimes in ourselves, and independent
- of our situation with respect to the universe; and in like manner, if
- these moral relations could be applied to external objects, it would
- follow, that even inanimate beings would be susceptible of moral beauty
- and deformity. Now, it seems difficult to imagine that any relation can
- be discovered betwixt our passions, volitions and actions, compared
- to external objects, which relation might not belong either to these
- passions and volitions, or to these external objects, compared among
- _themselves_.
- But it will be still more difficult to fulfil the _second_ condition,
- requisite to justify this system. According to the principles of those
- who maintain an abstract rational difference betwixt moral good and
- evil, and a natural fitness and unfitness of things, 'tis not only
- supposed, that these relations, being eternal and immutable, are the
- same, when considered by every rational creature, but their _effects_
- are also supposed to be necessarily the same; and 'tis concluded they
- have no less, or rather a greater, influence in directing the will
- of the Deity, than in governing the rational and virtuous of our own
- species. These two particulars are evidently distinct. 'Tis one thing
- to know virtue, and another to conform the will to it. In order,
- therefore, to prove that the measures of right and wrong are eternal
- laws, _obligatory_ on every rational mind, 'tis not sufficient to show
- the relations upon which they are founded: we must also point out the
- connexion betwixt the relation and the will; and must prove that this
- connexion is so necessary, that in every well-disposed mind, it must
- take place and have its influence; though the difference betwixt these
- minds be in other respects immense and infinite. Now, besides what I
- have already proved, that even in human nature no relation can ever
- alone produce any action; besides this, I say, it has been shown, in
- treating of the understanding, that there is no connexion of cause and
- effect, such as this is supposed to be, which is discoverable otherwise
- than by experience, and of which we can pretend to have any security by
- the simple consideration of the objects. All beings in the universe,
- considered in themselves, appear entirely loose and independent of each
- other. 'Tis only by experience we learn their influence and connexion;
- and this influence we ought never to extend beyond experience.
- Thus it will be impossible to fulfil the _first_ condition required to
- the system of eternal rational measures of right and wrong; because it
- is impossible to show those relations, upon which such a distinction
- may be founded: and 'tis as impossible to fulfil the _second_
- condition; because we cannot prove _a priori_, that these relations, if
- they really existed and were perceived, would be universally forcible
- and obligatory.
- But to make these general reflections more clear and convincing, we may
- illustrate them by some particular instances, wherein this character
- of moral good or evil is the most universally acknowledged. Of all
- crimes that human creatures are capable of committing, the most horrid
- and unnatural is ingratitude, especially when it is committed against
- parents, and appears in the more flagrant instances of wounds and
- death. This is acknowledged by all mankind, philosophers as well as
- the people; the question only arises among philosophers, whether the
- guilt or moral deformity of this action be discovered by demonstrative
- reasoning, or be felt by an internal sense, and by means of some
- sentiment, which the reflecting on such an action naturally occasions.
- This question will soon be decided against the former opinion, if we
- can show the same relations in other objects, without the notion of
- any guilt or iniquity attending them. Reason or science is nothing but
- the comparing of ideas, and the discovery of their relations; and if
- the same relations have different characters, it must evidently follow,
- that those characters are not discovered merely by reason. To put the
- affair, therefore, to this trial, let us choose any inanimate object,
- such as an oak or elm; and let us suppose, that, by the dropping of
- its seed, it produces a sapling below it, which, springing up by
- degrees, at last overtops and destroys the parent tree: I ask, if, in
- this instance, there be wanting any relation which is discoverable
- in parricide or ingratitude? Is not the one tree the cause of the
- other's existence; and the latter the cause of the destruction of the
- former, in the same manner as when a child murders his parent? 'Tis
- not sufficient to reply, that a choice or will is wanting. For in
- the case of parricide, a will does not give rise to any _different_
- relations, but is only the cause from which the action is derived; and
- consequently produces the _same_ relations, that in the oak or elm
- arise from some other principles. 'Tis a will or choice that determines
- a man to kill his parent: and they are the laws of matter and motion,
- that determine a sapling to destroy the oak from which it sprung. Here
- then the same relations have different causes; but still the relations
- are the same: and as their discovery is not in both cases attended with
- a notion of immorality, it follows, that that notion does not arise
- from such a discovery.
- But to choose an instance still more resembling; I would fain ask any
- one, why incest in the human species is criminal, and why the very
- same action, and the same relations in animals, have not the smallest
- moral turpitude and deformity? If it be answered, that this action
- is innocent in animals, because they have not reason sufficient to
- discover its turpitude; but that man, being endowed with that faculty,
- which _ought_ to restrain him to his duty, the same action instantly
- becomes criminal to him. Should this be said, I would reply, that this
- is evidently arguing in a circle. For, before reason can perceive this
- turpitude, the turpitude must exist; and consequently is independent
- of the decisions of our reason, and is their object more properly than
- their effect. According to this system, then, every animal that has
- sense and appetite and will, that is, every animal must be susceptible
- of all the same virtues and vices, for which we ascribe praise and
- blame to human creatures. All the difference is, that our superior
- reason may serve to discover the vice or virtue, and by that means
- may augment the blame or praise: but still this discovery supposes
- a separate being in these moral distinctions, and a being which
- depends only on the will and appetite, and which, both in thought and
- reality, may be distinguished from reason. Animals are susceptible of
- the same relations with respect to each other as the human species,
- and therefore would also be susceptible of the same morality, if the
- essence of morality consisted in these relations. Their want of a
- sufficient degree of reason may hinder them from perceiving the duties
- and obligations of morality, but can never hinder these duties from
- existing; since they must antecedently exist, in order to their being
- perceived. Reason must find them, and can never produce them. This
- argument deserves to be weighed, as being, in my opinion, entirely
- decisive.
- Nor does this reasoning only prove, that morality consists not in any
- relations that are the objects of science; but if examined, will prove
- with equal certainty, that it consists not in any _matter of fact_,
- which can be discovered by the understanding. This is the _second_ part
- of our argument; and if it can be made evident, we may conclude, that
- morality is not an object of reason. But can there be any difficulty in
- proving, that vice and virtue are not matters of fact, whose existence
- we can infer by reason? Take any action allowed to be vicious; wilful
- murder, for instance. Examine it in all lights, and see if you can
- find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call _vice_. In
- whichever way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives,
- volitions and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case.
- The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object.
- You never can find it, till you turn your reflection into your own
- breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you,
- towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but 'tis the object of
- feeling, not of reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So
- that when you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you
- mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a
- feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. Vice and
- virtue, therefore, may be compared to sounds, colours, heat and cold,
- which, according to modern philosophy, are not qualities in objects,
- but perceptions in the mind: and this discovery in morals, like that
- other in physics, is to be regarded as a considerable advancement of
- the speculative sciences; though, like that too, it has little or no
- influence on practice. Nothing can be more real, or concern us more,
- than our own sentiments of pleasure and uneasiness; and if these
- be favourable to virtue, and unfavourable to vice, no more can be
- requisite to the regulation of our conduct and behaviour.
- I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may,
- perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality
- which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that the
- author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and
- establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human
- affairs; when of a sudden I am surprised to find, that instead of the
- usual copulations of propositions, _is_, and _is not_, I meet with no
- proposition that is not connected with an _ought_, or an _ought not_.
- This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence.
- For as this _ought_, or _ought not_, expresses some new relation or
- affirmation, 'tis necessary that it should be observed and explained;
- and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems
- altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from
- others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not
- commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the
- readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention would subvert all
- the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of
- vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor
- is perceived by reason.
- [1] Book II. Part III. Sect. 3
- [2] One might think it were entirely superfluous to prove this, if a
- late author, who has had the good fortune to obtain some reputation,
- had not seriously affirmed, that such a falsehood is the foundation of
- all guilt and moral deformity. That we may discover the fallacy of his
- hypothesis, we need only consider, that a false conclusion is drawn
- from an action, only by means of an obscurity of natural principles,
- which makes a cause be secretly interrupted in its operation, by
- contrary causes, and renders the connexion betwixt two objects
- uncertain and variable. Now, as a like uncertainty and variety of
- causes take place, even in natural objects, and produce a like error in
- our judgment, if that tendency to produce error were the very essence
- of vice and immorality, it should follow, that even inanimate objects
- might be vicious and immoral.
- 'Tis in vain to urge, that inanimate objects act without liberty and
- choice. For as liberty and choice are not necessary to make an action
- produce in us an erroneous conclusion, they can be, in no respect,
- essential to morality; and I do not readily perceive, upon this system,
- how they can ever come to be regarded by it. If the tendency to cause
- error be the origin of immorality, that tendency and immorality would
- in every case be inseparable.
- Add to this, that if I had used the precaution of shutting the windows,
- while I indulged myself in those liberties with my neighbour's wife, I
- should have been guilty of no immorality; and that because my action,
- being perfectly concealed, would have had no tendency to produce any
- false conclusion.
- For the same reason, a thief, who steals in by a ladder at a window,
- and takes all imaginable care to cause no disturbance, is in no
- respect criminal. For either he will not be perceived, or if he be,
- 'tis impossible he can produce any error, nor will any one, from these
- circumstances, take him to be other than what he really is.
- 'Tis well known, that those who are squint-sighted do very readily
- cause mistakes in others, and that we imagine they salute or are
- talking to one person, while they address themselves to another. Are
- they, therefore, upon that account, immoral?
- Besides, we may easily observe, that in all those arguments there is
- an evident reasoning in a circle. A person who takes possession of
- _another's_ goods, and uses them as his _own_, in a manner declares
- them to be his own; and this falsehood is the source of the immorality
- of injustice. But is property, or right, or obligation, intelligible
- without an antecedent morality?
- A man that is ungrateful to his benefactor, in a manner affirms that
- he never received any favours from him. But in what manner? Is it
- because 'tis his duty to be grateful? But this supposes that there is
- some antecedent rule of duty and morals. Is it because human nature is
- generally grateful, and makes us conclude that a man who does any harm,
- never received any favour from the person he harmed? But human nature
- is not so generally grateful as to justify such a conclusion; or, if it
- were, is an exception to a general rule in every case criminal, for no
- other reason than because it is an exception?
- But what may suffice entirely to destroy this whimsical system is,
- that it leaves us under the same difficulty to give a reason why truth
- is virtuous and falsehood vicious, as to account for the merit or
- turpitude of any other action. I shall allow, if you please, that all
- immorality is derived from this supposed falsehood in action, provided
- you can give me any plausible reason why such a falsehood is immoral.
- If you consider rightly of the matter, you will find yourself in the
- same difficulty as at the beginning.
- This last argument is very conclusive; because, if there be not
- an evident merit or turpitude annexed to this species of truth or
- falsehood, it can never have any influence upon our actions. For who
- ever thought of forbearing any action, because others might possibly
- draw false conclusions from it? Or who ever performed any, that he
- might give rise to true conclusions?
- [3] As a proof how confused our way of thinking on this subject
- commonly is, we may observe, that those who assert that morality is
- demonstrable, do not say that morality lies in the relations, and
- that the relations are distinguishable by reason. They only say, that
- reason can discover such an action, in such relations, to be virtuous,
- and such another vicious. It seems they thought it sufficient if they
- could bring the word Relation into the proposition, without troubling
- themselves whether it was to the purpose or not. But here, I think, is
- plain argument. Demonstrative reason discovers only relations. But that
- reason, according to this hypothesis, discovers also vice and virtue.
- These moral qualities, therefore, must be relations. When we blame any
- action, in any situation, the whole complicated object of action and
- situation must form certain relations, wherein the essence of vice
- consists. This hypothesis is not otherwise intelligible. For what
- does reason discover, when it pronounces any action vicious? Does it
- discover a relation or a matter of fact? These questions are decisive,
- and must not be eluded.
- SECTION II.
- MORAL DISTINCTIONS DERIVED FROM A MORAL SENSE.
- Thus the course of the argument leads us to conclude, that since vice
- and virtue are not discoverable merely by reason, or the comparison
- of ideas, it must be by means of some impression or sentiment they
- occasion, that we are able to mark the difference betwixt them. Our
- decisions concerning moral rectitude and depravity are evidently
- perceptions; and as all perceptions are either impressions or ideas,
- the exclusion of the one is a convincing argument for the other.
- Morality, therefore, is more properly felt than judged of; though this
- feeling or sentiment is commonly so soft and gentle that we are apt to
- confound it with an idea, according to our common custom of taking all
- things for the same which have any near resemblance to each other.
- The next question is, of what nature are these impressions, and after
- what manner do they operate upon us? Here we cannot remain long in
- suspense, but must pronounce the impression arising from virtue to be
- agreeable, and that proceeding from vice to be uneasy. Every moment's
- experience must convince us of this. There is no spectacle so fair and
- beautiful as a noble and generous action; nor any which gives us more
- abhorrence than one that is cruel and treacherous. No enjoyment equals
- the satisfaction we receive from the company of those we love and
- esteem; as the greatest of all punishments is to be obliged to pass our
- lives with those we hate or contemn. A very play or romance may afford
- us instances of this pleasure which virtue conveys to us; and pain,
- which arises from vice.
- Now, since the distinguishing impressions by which moral good or evil
- is known, are nothing but _particular_ pains or pleasures, it follows,
- that in all inquiries concerning these moral distinctions, it will be
- sufficient to show the principles which make us feel a satisfaction or
- uneasiness from the survey of any character, in order to satisfy us
- why the character is laudable or blameable. An action, or sentiment,
- or character, is virtuous or vicious; why? because its view causes
- a pleasure or uneasiness of a particular kind. In giving a reason,
- therefore, for the pleasure or uneasiness, we sufficiently explain
- the vice or virtue. To have the sense of virtue, is nothing but to
- _feel_ a satisfaction of a particular kind from the contemplation of a
- character. The very _feeling_ constitutes our praise or admiration. We
- go no farther; nor do we inquire into the cause of the satisfaction.
- We do not infer a character to be virtuous, because it pleases; but in
- feeling that it pleases after such a particular manner, we in effect
- feel that it is virtuous. The case is the same as in our judgments
- concerning all kinds of beauty, and tastes, and sensations. Our
- approbation is implied in the immediate pleasure they convey to us.
- I have objected to the system which establishes eternal rational
- measures of right and wrong, that 'tis impossible to show, in the
- actions of reasonable creatures, any relations which are not found in
- external objects; and therefore, if morality always attended these
- relations, 'twere possible for inanimate matter to become virtuous
- or vicious. Now it may, in like manner, be objected to the present
- system, that if virtue and vice be determined by pleasure and pain,
- these qualities must, in every case, arise from the sensations; and
- consequently any object, whether animate or inanimate, rational or
- irrational, might become morally good or evil, provided it can excite a
- satisfaction or uneasiness. But though this objection seems to be the
- very same, it has by no means the same force in the one case as in the
- other. For, _first_, 'tis evident that, under the term _pleasure_, we
- comprehend sensations, which are very different from each other, and
- which have only such a distant resemblance as is requisite to, make
- them be expressed by the same abstract term. A good composition of
- music and a bottle of good wine equally produce pleasure; and, what is
- more, their goodness is determined merely by the pleasure. But shall we
- say, upon that account, that the wine is harmonious, or the music of a
- good flavour? In like manner, an inanimate object, and the character
- or sentiments of any person, may, both of them, give satisfaction;
- but, as the satisfaction is different, this keeps our sentiments
- concerning them from being confounded, and makes us ascribe virtue to
- the one and not to the other. Nor is every sentiment of pleasure or
- pain which arises from characters and actions, of that _peculiar_ kind
- which makes us praise or condemn. The good qualities of an enemy are
- hurtful to us, but may, still command our esteem and respect. 'Tis
- only when a character is considered in general, without reference to
- our particular interest, that it causes such a feeling or sentiment as
- denominates it morally good or evil. 'Tis true, those sentiments from
- interest and morals are apt to be confounded, and naturally run into
- one another. It seldom happens that we do not think an enemy vicious,
- and can distinguish betwixt his opposition to our interest and real
- villany or baseness. But this hinders not but that the sentiments are
- in themselves distinct; and a man of temper and judgment may preserve
- himself from these illusions. In like manner, though 'tis certain a
- musical voice is nothing but one that naturally gives a _particular_
- kind of pleasure; yet 'tis difficult for a man to be sensible that the
- voice of an enemy is agreeable, or to allow it to be musical. But a
- person of a fine ear, who has the command of himself, can separate
- these feelings, and give praise to what deserves it.
- _Secondly_, we may call to remembrance the preceding system of the
- passions, in order to remark a still more considerable difference
- among our pains and pleasures. Pride and humility, love and hatred,
- are excited, when there is any thing presented to us that both bears
- a relation to the object of the passion, and produces a separate
- sensation, related to the sensation of the passion. Now, virtue and
- vice are attended with these circumstances. They must necessarily be
- placed either in ourselves or others, and excite either pleasure or
- uneasiness; and therefore must give rise to one of these four passions,
- which clearly distinguishes them from the pleasure and pain arising
- from inanimate objects, that often bear no relation to us; and this is,
- perhaps, the most considerable effect that virtue and vice have upon
- the human mind.
- It may now be asked, _in general_ concerning this pain or pleasure that
- distinguishes moral good and evil, _From what principle is it derived,
- and whence does it arise in the human mind_? To this I reply, _first_,
- that 'tis absurd to imagine that, in every particular instance,
- these sentiments are produced by an _original_ quality and _primary_
- constitution. For as the number of our duties is in a manner infinite,
- 'tis impossible that our original instincts should extend to each of
- them, and from our very first infancy impress on the human mind all
- that multitude of precepts which are contained in the completest system
- of ethics. Such a method of proceeding is not conformable to the usual
- maxims by which nature is conducted, where a few principles produce all
- that variety we observe in the universe, and every thing is carried on
- in the easiest and most simple manner. 'Tis necessary, therefore, to
- abridge these primary impulses, and find some more general principles
- upon which all our notions of morals are founded.
- But, in the _second_ place, should it be asked, whether we ought to
- search for these principles in _nature_, or whether we must look for
- them in some other origin? I would reply, that our answer to this
- question depends upon the definition of the word Nature, than which
- there is none more ambiguous and equivocal. If _nature_ be opposed to
- miracles, not only the distinction betwixt vice and virtue is natural,
- but also every event which has ever happened in the world, _excepting
- those miracles on which our religion is founded_. In saying, then, that
- the sentiments of vice and virtue are natural in this sense, we make no
- very extraordinary discovery.
- But _nature_ may also be opposed to rare and unusual; and in this sense
- of the word, which is the common one, there may often arise disputes
- concerning what is natural or unnatural; and one may in general affirm,
- that we are not possessed of any very precise standard by which these
- disputes can be decided. Frequent and rare depend upon the number of
- examples we have observed; and as this number may gradually increase
- or diminish, 'twill be impossible to fix any exact boundaries betwixt
- them. We may only affirm on this head, that if ever there was any thing
- which could be called natural in this sense, the sentiments of morality
- certainly may; since there never was any nation of the world, nor any
- single person in any nation, who was utterly deprived of them, and
- who never, in any instance, showed the least approbation or dislike
- of manners. These sentiments are so rooted in our constitution and
- temper, that, without entirely confounding the human mind by disease or
- madness, 'tis impossible to extirpate and destroy them.
- But _nature_ may also be opposed to artifice, as well as to what is
- rare and unusual; and in this sense it may be disputed, whether the
- notions of virtue be natural or not. We readily forget, that the
- designs and projects and views of men are principles as necessary in
- their operation as heat and cold, moist and dry; but, taking them to be
- free and entirely our own, 'tis usual for us to set them in opposition
- to the other principles of nature. Should it therefore be demanded,
- whether the sense of virtue be natural or artificial, I am of opinion
- that 'tis impossible for me at present to give any precise answer to
- this question. Perhaps it will appear afterwards that our sense of some
- virtues is artificial, and that of others natural. The discussion of
- this question will be more proper, when we enter upon an exact detail
- of each particular vice and virtue.[4]
- Mean while, it may not be amiss to observe, from these definitions of
- _natural_ and _unnatural_, that nothing can be more unphilosophical
- than those systems which assert, that virtue is the same with what
- is natural, and vice with what is unnatural. For, in the first sense
- of the word, nature, as opposed to miracles, both vice and virtue
- are equally natural; and, in the second sense, as opposed to what is
- unusual, perhaps virtue will be found to be the most unnatural. At
- least it must be owned, that heroic virtue, being as unusual, is as
- little natural as the most brutal barbarity. As to the third sense of
- the word, 'tis certain that both vice and virtue are equally artificial
- and out of nature. For, however it may be disputed, whether the notion
- of a merit or demerit in certain actions, be natural or artificial,
- 'tis evident that the actions themselves are artificial, and are
- performed with a certain design and intention; otherwise they could
- never be ranked under any of these denominations. 'Tis impossible,
- therefore, that the character of natural and unnatural can ever, in any
- sense, mark the boundaries of vice and virtue.
- Thus we are still brought back to our first position, that virtue is
- distinguished by the pleasure, and vice by the pain, that any action,
- sentiment, or character, gives us by the mere view and contemplation.
- This decision is very commodious; because it reduces us to, this
- simple question, _Why any action or sentiment, upon the general view
- or survey, gives a certain satisfaction or uneasiness_, in order to
- show the origin of its moral rectitude or depravity, without looking
- for any incomprehensible relations and qualities, which never did exist
- in nature, nor even in our imagination, by any clear and distinct
- conception? I flatter myself I have executed a great part of my present
- design by a state of the question, which appears to me so free from
- ambiguity and obscurity.
- [4] In the following discourse, _natural_ is also opposed sometimes to
- _civil_, sometimes to _moral_. The opposition will always discover the
- sense in which it is taken.
- PART II.
- OF JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE.
- SECTION I.
- JUSTICE, WHETHER A NATURAL OR ARTIFICIAL VIRTUE?
- I have already hinted, that our sense of every kind of virtue is not
- natural; but that there are some virtues that produce pleasure and
- approbation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from
- the circumstances and necessity of mankind. Of this kind I assert
- _justice_ to be; and shall endeavour to defend this opinion by a short,
- and, I hope, convincing argument, before I examine the nature of the
- artifice, from which the sense of that virtue is derived.
- 'Tis evident that, when we praise any actions, we regard only the
- motives that produced them, and consider the actions as signs or
- indications of certain principles in the mind and temper. The external
- performance has no merit. We must look within to find the moral
- quality. This we cannot do directly; and therefore fix our attention on
- actions, as on external signs. But these actions are still considered
- as signs; and the ultimate object of our praise and approbation is the
- motive that produced them.
- After the same manner, when we require any action, or blame a person
- for not performing it, we always suppose that one in that situation
- should be influenced by the proper motive of that action, and we
- esteem it vicious in him to be regardless of it. If we find, upon
- inquiry, that the virtuous motive was still powerful over his breast,
- though checked in its operation by some circumstances unknown to us,
- we retract our blame, and have the same esteem for him, as if he had
- actually performed the action which we require of him.
- It appears, therefore, that all virtuous actions derive their merit
- only from virtuous motives, and are considered merely as signs of
- those motives. From this principle I conclude, that the first virtuous
- motive which bestows a merit on any action, can never be a regard
- to the virtue of that action, but must be some other natural motive
- or principle. To suppose, that the mere regard to the virtue of the
- action, may be the first motive which produced the action, and rendered
- it virtuous, is to reason in a circle. Before we can have such a
- regard, the action must be really virtuous; and this virtue must be
- derived from some virtuous motive: and consequently, the virtuous
- motive must be different from the regard to the virtue of the action.
- A virtuous motive is requisite to render an action virtuous. An action
- must be virtuous before we can have a regard to its virtue. Some
- virtuous motive, therefore, must be antecedent to that regard.
- Nor is this merely a metaphysical subtilty; but enters into all our
- reasonings in common life, though perhaps we may not be able to
- place it in such distinct philosophical terms. We blame a father
- for neglecting his child. Why? because it shows a want of natural
- affection, which is the duty of every parent. Were not natural
- affection a duty, the care of children could not be a duty; and 'twere
- impossible we could have the duty in our eye in the attention we give
- to our offspring. In this case, therefore, all men suppose a motive to
- the action distinct from a sense of duty.
- Here is a man that does many benevolent actions; relieves the
- distressed, comforts the afflicted, and extends his bounty even to the
- greatest strangers. No character can be more amiable and virtuous. We
- regard these actions as proofs of the greatest humanity. This humanity
- bestows a merit on the actions. A regard to this merit is, therefore, a
- secondary consideration, and derived from the antecedent principles of
- humanity, which is meritorious and laudable.
- In short, it may be established as an undoubted maxim, _that no action
- can be virtuous, or morally good, unless there be in human nature some
- motive to produce it distinct from the sense of its morality_.
- But may not the sense of morality or duty produce an action, without
- any other motive? I answer, it may; but this is no objection to the
- present doctrine. When any virtuous motive or principle is common in
- human nature, a person who feels his heart devoid of that motive, may
- hate himself upon that account, and may perform the action without the
- motive, from a certain sense of duty, in order to acquire, by practice,
- that virtuous principle, or at least to disguise to himself, as much
- as possible, his want of it. A man that really feels no gratitude in
- his temper, is still pleased to perform grateful actions, and thinks
- he has, by that means, fulfilled his duty. Actions are at first only
- considered as signs of motives: but 'tis usual, in this case, as in
- all others, to fix our attention on the signs, and neglect, in some
- measure, the thing signified. But though, on some occasions, a person
- may perform an action merely out of regard to its moral obligation, yet
- still this supposes in human nature some distinct principles, which are
- capable of producing the action, and whose moral beauty renders the
- action meritorious.
- Now, to apply all this to the present case; I suppose a person to have
- lent me a sum of money, on condition that it be restored in a few days;
- and also suppose, that after the expiration of the term agreed on,
- he demands the sum: I ask, _What reason or motive have I to restore
- the money_? It will perhaps be said, that my regard to justice, and
- abhorrence of villany and knavery, are sufficient reasons for me, if
- I have the least grain of honesty, or sense of duty and obligation.
- And this answer, no doubt, is just and satisfactory to man in his
- civilized state, and when trained up according to a certain discipline
- and education. But in his rude and more natural condition, if you are
- pleased to call such a condition natural, this answer would be rejected
- as perfectly unintelligible and sophistical. For one in that situation
- would immediately ask you, _Wherein consists this honesty and justice,
- which you find in restoring a loan, and abstaining from the property
- of others_? It does not surely lie in the external action. It must,
- therefore, be placed in the motive from which the external action
- is derived. This motive can never be a regard to the honesty of the
- action. For 'tis a plain fallacy to say, that a virtuous motive is
- requisite to render an action honest, and, at the same time, that a
- regard to the honesty is the motive of the action. We can never have a
- regard to the virtue of an action, unless the action be antecedently
- virtuous. No action can be virtuous, but so far as it proceeds from a
- virtuous motive. A virtuous motive, therefore, must precede the regard
- to the virtue; and 'tis impossible that the virtuous motive and the
- regard to the virtue can be the same.
- 'Tis requisite, then, to find some motive to acts of justice and
- honesty, distinct from our regard to the honesty; and in this lies the
- great difficulty. For should we say, that a concern for our private
- interest or reputation, is the legitimate motive to all honest actions:
- it would follow, that wherever that concern ceases, honesty can no
- longer have place. But 'tis certain that self-love, when it acts at its
- liberty, instead of engaging us to honest actions, is the source of all
- injustice and violence; nor can a man ever correct those vices, without
- correcting and restraining the _natural_ movements of that appetite.
- But should it be affirmed, that the reason or motive of such actions
- is the _regard to public interest_, to which nothing is more contrary
- than examples of injustice and dishonesty; should this be said, I
- would propose the three following considerations as worthy of our
- attention. _First_, Public interest is not naturally attached to the
- observation of the rules of justice; but is only connected with it,
- after an artificial convention for the establishment of these rules,
- as shall be shown more at large hereafter. _Secondly_, If we suppose
- that the loan was secret, and that it is necessary for the interest
- of the person, that the money be restored in the same manner (as when
- the lender would conceal his riches), in that case the example ceases,
- and the public is no longer interested in the actions of the borrower;
- though I suppose there is no moralist who will affirm that the duty
- and obligation ceases. _Thirdly_, Experience sufficiently proves that
- men, in the ordinary conduct of life, look not so far as the public
- interest, when they pay their creditors, perform their promises, and
- abstain from theft, and robbery, and injustice of every kind. That is a
- motive too remote and too sublime to affect the generality of mankind,
- and operate with any force in actions so contrary to private interest
- as are frequently those of justice and common honesty.
- In general, it may be affirmed, that there is no such passion in
- human minds as the love of mankind, merely as such, independent of
- personal qualities, of services, or of relation to ourself. 'Tis true,
- there is no human, and indeed no sensible creature, whose happiness
- or misery does not, in some measure, affect us, when brought near
- us, and represented in lively colours: but this proceeds merely from
- sympathy, and is no proof of such an universal affection to mankind,
- since this concern extends itself beyond our own species. An affection
- betwixt the sexes is a passion evidently implanted in human nature; and
- this passion not only appears in its peculiar symptoms, but also in
- inflaming every other principle of affection, and raising a stronger
- love from beauty, wit, kindness, than what would otherwise flow from
- them. Were there an universal love among all human creatures, it would
- appear after the same manner. Any degree of a good quality would cause
- a stronger affection than the same degree of a bad quality would cause
- hatred; contrary to what we find by experience. Men's tempers are
- different, and some have a propensity to the tender, and others to
- the rougher affections: but in the main, we may affirm, that man in
- general, or human nature, is nothing but the object both of love and
- hatred, and requires some other cause, which, by a double relation
- of impressions and ideas, may excite these passions. In vain would
- we endeavour to elude this hypothesis. There are no phenomena that
- point out any such kind affection to men, independent of their merit,
- and every other circumstance. We love company in general; but 'tis as
- we love any other amusement. An Englishman in Italy is a friend; a
- European in China; and perhaps a man would be beloved as such, were we
- to meet him in the moon. But this proceeds only from the relation to
- ourselves; which in these cases gathers force by being confined to a
- few persons.
- If public benevolence, therefore, or a regard to the interests of
- mankind, cannot be the original motive to justice, much less can
- _private benevolence_, or a _regard to the interests of the party
- concerned_, be this motive. For what if he be my enemy, and has given
- me just cause to hate him? What if he be a vicious man, and deserves
- the hatred of all mankind? What if he be a miser, and can make no use
- of what I would deprive him of? What if he be a profligate debauchee,
- and would rather receive harm than benefit from large possessions? What
- if I be in necessity, and have urgent motives to acquire something to
- my family? In all these cases, the original motive to justice would
- fail; and consequently the justice itself, and along with it all
- property, right, and obligation.
- A rich man lies under a moral obligation to communicate to those in
- necessity a share of his superfluities. Were private benevolence the
- original motive to justice, a man would not be obliged to leave others
- in the possession of more than he is obliged to give them. At least,
- the difference would be very inconsiderable. Men generally fix their
- affections more on what they are possessed of, than on what they never
- enjoyed: for this reason, it would be greater cruelty to dispossess a
- man of any thing, than not to give it him. But who will assert, that
- this is the only foundation of justice?
- Besides, we must consider, that the chief reason why men attach
- themselves so much to their possessions, is, that they consider them
- as their property, and as secured to them inviolably by the laws of
- society. But this is a secondary consideration, and dependent on the
- preceding notions of justice and property.
- A man's property is supposed to be fenced against every mortal, in
- every possible case. But private benevolence is, and ought to be,
- weaker in some persons than in others; and in many, or indeed in most
- persons, must absolutely fail. Private benevolence, therefore, is not
- the original motive of justice.
- From all this it follows, that we have no real or universal motive for
- observing the laws of equity, but the very equity and merit of that
- observance; and as no action can be equitable or meritorious, where
- it cannot arise from some separate motive, there is here an evident
- sophistry and reasoning in a circle. Unless, therefore, we will allow
- that nature has established a sophistry, and rendered it necessary and
- unavoidable, we must allow, that the sense of justice and injustice is
- not derived from nature, but arises artificially, though necessarily,
- from education, and human conventions.
- I shall add, as a corollary to this reasoning, that since no action can
- be laudable or blameable, without some motives or impelling passions,
- distinct from the sense of morals, these distinct passions must have a
- great influence on that sense. 'Tis according to their general force
- in human nature that we blame or praise. In judging of the beauty of
- animal bodies, we always carry in our eye the economy of a certain
- species; and where the limbs and features observe that proportion which
- is common to the species, we pronounce them handsome and beautiful.
- In like manner, we always consider the _natural_ and _usual_ force of
- the passions, when we determine concerning vice and virtue; and if the
- passions depart very much from the common measures on either side, they
- are always disapproved as vicious. A man naturally loves his children
- better than his nephews, his nephews better than his cousins, his
- cousins better than strangers, where every thing else is equal. Hence
- arise our common measures of duty, in preferring the one to the other.
- Our sense of duty always follows the common and natural course of our
- passions.
- To avoid giving offence, I must here observe, that when I deny justice
- to be a natural virtue, I make use of the word _natural_, only as
- opposed to _artificial_. In another sense of the word, as no principle
- of the human mind is more natural than a sense of virtue, so no virtue
- is more natural than justice. Mankind is an inventive species; and
- where an invention is obvious and absolutely necessary, it may as
- properly be said to be natural as any thing that proceeds immediately
- from original principles, without the intervention of thought or
- reflection. Though the rules of justice be _artificial_, they are not
- _arbitrary_. Nor is the expression improper to call them _Laws of
- Nature_; if by natural we understand what is common to any species, or
- even if we confine it to mean what is inseparable from the species.
- SECTION II.
- OF THE ORIGIN OF JUSTICE AND PROPERTY.
- We now proceed to examine two questions, viz. _concerning the manner
- in which the rules of justice are established by the artifice of men_;
- and _concerning the reasons which determine us to attribute to the
- observance or neglect of these rules a moral beauty and deformity_.
- These questions will appear afterwards to be distinct. We shall begin
- with the former.
- Of all the animals with which this globe is peopled, there is none
- towards whom nature seems, at first sight, to have exercised more
- cruelty than towards man, in the numberless wants and necessities
- with which she has loaded him, and in the slender means which she
- affords to the relieving these necessities. In other creatures, these
- two particulars generally compensate each other. If we consider the
- lion as a voracious and carnivorous animal, we shall easily discover
- him to be very necessitous; but if we turn our eye to his make and
- temper, his agility, his courage, his arms and his force, we shall
- find that his advantages hold proportion with his wants. The sheep
- and ox are deprived of all these advantages; but their appetites
- are moderate, and their food is of easy purchase. In man alone this
- unnatural conjunction of infirmity and of necessity may be observed
- in its greatest perfection. Not only the food which is required for
- his sustenance flies his search and approach, or at least requires his
- labour to be produced, but he must be possessed of clothes and lodging
- to defend him against the injuries of the weather; though, to consider
- him only in himself, he is provided neither with arms, nor force, nor
- other natural abilities which are in any degree answerable to so many
- necessities.
- 'Tis by society alone he is able to supply his defects, and raise
- himself up to an equality with his fellow-creatures, and even acquire a
- superiority above them. By society all his infirmities are compensated;
- and though in that situation his wants multiply every moment upon him,
- yet his abilities are still more augmented, and leave him in every
- respect more satisfied and happy than 'tis possible for him, in his
- savage and solitary condition, ever to become. When every individual
- person labours apart, and only for himself, his force is too small to
- execute any considerable work; his labour being employed in supplying
- all his different necessities, he never attains a perfection in any
- particular art; and as his force and success are not at all times
- equal, the least failure in either of these particulars must be
- attended with inevitable ruin and misery. Society provides a remedy for
- these _three_ inconveniences. By the conjunction of forces, our power
- is augmented; by the partition of employments, our ability increases;
- and by mutual succour, we are less exposed to fortune and accidents.
- 'Tis by this additional _force, ability_, and _security_, that society
- becomes advantageous.
- But, in order to form society, 'tis requisite not only that it be
- advantageous, but also that men be sensible of these advantages; and
- 'tis impossible, in their wild uncultivated state, that by study and
- reflection alone they should ever be able to attain this knowledge.
- Most fortunately, therefore, there is conjoined to those necessities,
- whose remedies are remote and obscure, another necessity, which,
- having a present and more obvious remedy, may justly be regarded as
- the first and original principle of human society. This necessity is
- no other than that natural appetite betwixt the sexes, which unites
- them together, and preserves their union, till a new tie takes place
- in their concern for their common offspring. This new concern becomes
- also a principle of union betwixt the parents and offspring, and forms
- a more numerous society, where the parents govern by the advantage of
- their superior strength and wisdom, and at the same time are restrained
- in the exercise of their authority by that natural affection which they
- bear their children. In a little time, custom and habit, operating on
- the tender minds of the children, makes them sensible of the advantages
- which they may reap from society, as well as fashions them by degrees
- for it, by rubbing off those rough comers and untoward affections which
- prevent their coalition.
- For it must be confest, that however the circumstances of human
- nature may render an union necessary, and however those passions
- of lust and natural affection may seem to render it unavoidable,
- yet there are other particulars in our _natural temper_, and in our
- _outward circumstances_, which are very incommodious, and are even
- contrary to the requisite conjunction. Among the former we may justly
- esteem our _selfishness_ to be the most considerable. I am sensible
- that, generally speaking, the representations of this quality have
- been carried much too far; and that the descriptions which certain
- philosophers delight so much to form of mankind in this particular, are
- as wide of nature as any accounts of monsters which we meet with in
- fables and romances. So far from thinking that men have no affect ion
- for any thing beyond themselves, I am of opinion that, though it be
- rare to meet with one who loves any single person better than himself,
- yet 'tis as rare to meet with one in whom all the kind affections,
- taken together, do not overbalance all the selfish. Consult common
- experience; do you not see, that though the whole expense of the family
- be generally under the direction of the master of it, yet there are few
- that do not bestow the largest part of their fortunes on the pleasures
- of their wives and the education of their children, reserving the
- smallest portion for their own proper use and entertainment? This is
- what we may observe concerning such as have those endearing ties; and
- may presume, that the case would be the same with others, were they
- placed in a like situation.
- But, though this generosity must be acknowledged to the honour of human
- nature, we may at the same time remark, that so noble an affection,
- instead of fitting men for large societies, is almost as contrary
- to them as the most narrow selfishness. For while each person loves
- himself better than any other single person, and in his love to others
- bears the greatest affection to his relations and acquaintance,
- this must necessarily produce an opposition of passions, and a
- consequent opposition of actions, which cannot but be dangerous to the
- new-established union.
- 'Tis, however, worth while to remark, that this contrariety of
- passions would be attended with but small danger, did it not concur
- with a peculiarity in our _outward circumstances_, which affords it
- an opportunity of exerting itself. There are three different species
- of goods which we are possessed of; the internal satisfaction our
- minds; the external advantages of our body; and the enjoyment of such
- possessions as we have acquired by our industry and good fortune. We
- are perfectly secure in the enjoyment of the first. The second may be
- ravished from us, but can be of no advantage to him who deprives us of
- them. The last only are both exposed to the violence of others, and may
- be transferred without suffering any loss or alteration; while at the
- same time there is not a sufficient quantity of them to supply every
- one's desires and necessities. As the improvement, therefore, of these
- goods is the chief advantage of society, so the _instability_ of their
- possession, along with their _scarcity_, is the chief impediment.
- In vain should we expect to find, in _uncultivated nature_, a remedy to
- this inconvenience; or hope for any inartificial principle of the human
- mind which might control those partial affections, and make us overcome
- the temptations arising from our circumstances. The idea of justice
- can never serve to this purpose, or be taken for a natural principle,
- capable of inspiring men with an equitable conduct towards each other.
- That virtue, as it is now understood, would never have been dreamed
- of among rude and savage men. For the notion of injury or injustice
- implies an immorality or vice committed against some other person: And
- as every immorality is derived from some defect or unsoundness of the
- passions, and as this defect must be judged of, in a great measure,
- from the ordinary course of nature in the constitution of the mind,
- 'twill be easy to know whether we be guilty of any immorality with
- regard to others, by considering the natural and usual force of those
- several affections which are directed towards them. Now, it appears
- that, in the original frame of our mind, our strongest attention
- is confined to ourselves; our next is extended to our relations and
- acquaintance; and 'tis only the weakest which reaches to strangers and
- indifferent persons. This partiality, then, and unequal affection, must
- not only have an influence on our behaviour and conduct in society,
- but even on our ideas of vice and virtue; so as to make us regard any
- remarkable transgression of such a degree of partiality, either by
- too great an enlargement or contraction of the affections, as vicious
- and immoral. This we may observe in our common judgments concerning
- actions, where we blame a person who either centres all his affections
- in his family, or is so regardless of them as, in any opposition
- of interest, to give the preference to a stranger or mere chance
- acquaintance. From all which it follows, that our natural uncultivated
- ideas of morality, instead of providing a remedy for the partiality of
- our affections, do rather conform themselves to that partiality, and
- give it an additional force and influence.
- The remedy, then, is not derived from nature, but from _artifice_;
- or, more properly speaking, nature provides a remedy, in the judgment
- and understanding, for what is irregular and incommodious in the
- affections. For when men, from their early education in society, have
- become sensible of the infinite advantages that result from it, and
- have besides acquired a new affection to company and conversation, and
- when they have observed, that the principal disturbance in society
- arises from those goods, which we call external, and from their
- looseness and easy transition from one person to another, they must
- seek for a remedy, by putting these goods, as far as possible, on the
- same footing with the fixed and constant advantages of the mind and
- body. This can be done after no other manner, than by a convention
- entered into by all the members of the society to bestow stability on
- the possession of those external goods, and leave every one in the
- peaceable enjoyment of what he may acquire by his fortune and industry.
- By this means, every one knows what he may safely possess; and the
- passions are restrained in their partial and contradictory motions. Nor
- is such a restraint contrary to these passions; for, if so, it could
- never be entered into nor maintained; but it is only contrary to their
- heedless and impetuous movement. Instead of departing from our own
- interest, or from that of our nearest friends, by abstaining from the
- possessions of others, we cannot better consult both these interests,
- than by such a convention; because it is by that means we maintain
- society, which is so necessary to their well-being and subsistence, as
- well as to our own.
- This convention is not of the nature of a _promise_; for even promises
- themselves, as we shall see afterwards, arise from human conventions.
- It is only a general sense of common interest; which sense all the
- members of the society express to one another, and which induces them
- to regulate their conduct by certain rules. I observe, that it will
- be for my interest to leave another in the possession of his goods,
- _provided_ he will act in the same manner with regard to me. He is
- sensible of a like interest in the regulation of his conduct. When
- this common sense of interest is mutually expressed, and is known to
- both, it produces a suitable resolution and behaviour. And this may
- properly enough be called a convention or agreement betwixt us, though
- without the interposition of a promise; since the actions of each of
- us have a reference to those of the other, and are performed upon the
- supposition that something is to be performed on the other part. Two
- men who pull the oars of a boat, do it by an agreement or convention,
- though they have never given promises to each other. Nor is the rule
- concerning the stability of possession the less derived from human
- conventions, that it arises gradually, and acquires force by a slow
- progression, and by our repeated experience of the inconveniences
- of transgressing it. On the contrary, this experience assures us
- still more, that the sense of interest has become common to all our
- fellows, and gives us a confidence of the future regularity of their
- conduct; and 'tis only on the expectation of this that our moderation
- and abstinence are founded. In like manner are languages gradually
- established by human conventions, without any promise. In like manner
- do gold and silver become the common measures of exchange, and are
- esteemed sufficient payment for what is of a hundred times their value.
- After this convention, concerning abstinence from the possessions of
- others, is entered into, and every one has acquired a stability in
- his possessions, there immediately arise the ideas of justice and
- injustice; as also those of _property, right_, and _obligation_. The
- latter are altogether unintelligible, without first understanding
- the former. Our property is nothing but those goods, whose constant
- possession is established by the laws of society; that is, by the laws
- of justice. Those, therefore, who make use of the words _property_,
- or _right_, or _obligation_, before they have explained the origin of
- justice, or even make use of them in that explication, are guilty of
- a very gross fallacy, and can never reason upon any solid foundation.
- A man's property is some object related to him. This relation is not
- natural, but moral, and founded on justice. 'Tis very preposterous,
- therefore, to imagine that we can have any idea of property, without
- fully comprehending the nature of justice, and showing its origin in
- the artifice and contrivance of men. The origin of justice explains
- that of property. The same artifice gives rise to both. As our first
- and most natural sentiment of morals is founded on the nature of our
- passions, and gives the preference to ourselves and friends above
- strangers, 'tis impossible there can be naturally any such thing as a
- fixed right or property, while the opposite passions of men impel them
- in contrary directions, and are not restrained by any convention or
- agreement.
- No one can doubt that the convention for the distinction of property,
- and for the stability of possession, is of all circumstances the most
- necessary to the establishment of human society, and that, after the
- agreement for the fixing and observing of this rule, there remains
- little or nothing to be done towards settling a perfect harmony and
- concord. All the other passions, beside this of interest, are either
- easily restrained, or are not of such pernicious consequence when
- indulged. _Vanity_ is rather to be esteemed a social passion, and a
- bond of union among men. _Pity_ and _love_ are to be considered in the
- same light. And as to _envy_ and _revenge_, though pernicious, they
- operate only by intervals, and are directed against particular persons,
- whom we consider as our superiors or enemies. This avidity alone, of
- acquiring goods and possessions for ourselves and our nearest friends,
- is insatiable, perpetual, universal, and directly destructive of
- society. There scarce is any one who is not actuated by it; and there
- is no one who has not reason to fear from it, when it acts without
- any restraint, and gives way to its first and most natural movements.
- So that, upon the whole, we are to esteem the difficulties in the
- establishment of society to be greater or less, according to those we
- encounter in regulating and restraining this passion.
- 'Tis certain, that no affection of the human mind has both a sufficient
- force and a proper direction to counterbalance the love of gain,
- and render men fit members of society, by making them abstain from
- the possessions of others. Benevolence to strangers is too weak for
- this purpose; and as to the other passions, they rather inflame this
- avidity, when we observe, that the larger our possessions are, the more
- ability we have of gratifying all our appetites. There is no passion,
- therefore, capable of controlling the interested affection, but the
- very affection itself, by an alteration of its direction. Now, this
- alteration must necessarily take place upon the least reflection;
- since 'tis evident that the passion is much better satisfied by its
- restraint than by its liberty, and that, in preserving society, we
- make much greater advances in the acquiring possessions, than in the
- solitary and forlorn condition which must follow upon violence and an
- universal license. The question, therefore, concerning the wickedness
- or goodness of human nature, enters not in the least into that other
- question concerning the origin of society; nor is there any thing to
- be considered but the degrees of men's sagacity or folly. For whether
- the passion of self-interest be esteemed vicious or virtuous, 'tis all
- a case, since itself alone restrains it; so that if it be virtuous,
- men become social by their virtue; if vicious, their vice has the same
- effect.
- Now, as 'tis by establishing the rule for the stability of possession
- that this passion restrains itself, if that rule be very abstruse
- and of difficult invention, society must be esteemed in a manner
- accidental, and the effect of many ages. But if it be found, that
- nothing can be more simple and obvious than that rule; that every
- parent, in order to preserve peace among his children, must establish
- it; and that these first rudiments of justice must every day be
- improved, as the society enlarges: if all this appear evident, as it
- certainly must, we may conclude that 'tis utterly impossible for men to
- remain any considerable time in that savage condition which precedes
- society, but that his very first state and situation may justly be
- esteemed social. This, however, hinders not but that philosophers
- may, if they please, extend their reasoning to the supposed _state of
- nature_; provided they allow it to be a mere philosophical fiction,
- which never had, and never could have, any reality. Human nature
- being composed of two principal parts, which are requisite in all
- its actions, the affections and understanding, 'tis certain that the
- blind motions of the former, without the direction of the latter,
- incapacitate men for society; and it may be allowed us to consider
- separately the effects that result from the separate operations
- of these two component parts of the mind. The same liberty may be
- permitted to moral, which is allowed to natural philosophers; and 'tis
- very usual with the latter to consider any motion as compounded and
- consisting of two parts separate from each other, though at the same
- time they acknowledge it to be in itself uncompounded and inseparable.
- This _state of nature_, therefore, is to be regarded as a mere fiction,
- not unlike that of the _golden age_ which poets have invented; only
- with this difference, that the former is described as full of war,
- violence and injustice; whereas the latter is painted out to us as
- the most charming and most peaceable condition that can possibly be
- imagined. The seasons, in that first age of nature, were so temperate,
- if we may believe the poets, that there was no necessity for men to
- provide themselves with clothes and houses as a security against the
- violence of heat and cold. The rivers flowed with wine and milk; the
- oaks yielded honey; and nature spontaneously produced her greatest
- delicacies. Nor were these the chief advantages of that happy age.
- The storms and tempests were not alone removed from nature; but those
- more furious tempests were unknown to human breasts, which now cause
- such uproar, and engender such confusion. Avarice, ambition, cruelty,
- selfishness, were never heard of: cordial affection, compassion,
- sympathy, were the only movements with which the human mind was yet
- acquainted. Even the distinction of _mine_ and _thine_ was banished
- from that happy race of mortals, and carried with them the very notions
- of property and obligation, justice and injustice.
- This, no doubt, is to be regarded as an idle fiction; but yet deserves
- our attention, because nothing can more evidently show the origin of
- those virtues, which are the subjects of our present inquiry. I have
- already observed, that justice takes its rise from human conventions;
- and that these are intended as a remedy to some inconveniences, which
- proceed from the concurrence of certain _qualities_ of the human mind
- with the _situation_ of external objects. The qualities of the mind
- are _selfishness_ and _limited generosity_: and the situation of
- external objects is their _easy change_, joined to their _scarcity_ in
- comparison of the wants and desires of men. But however philosophers
- may have been bewildered in those speculations, poets have been guided
- more infallibly, by a certain taste or common instinct, which, in most
- kinds of reasoning, goes farther than any of that art and philosophy
- with which we have been yet acquainted. They easily perceived, if every
- man had a tender regard for another, or if nature supplied abundantly
- all our wants and desires, that the jealousy of interest, which justice
- supposes, could no longer have place; nor would there be any occasion
- for those distinctions and limits of property and possession, which at
- present are in use among mankind. Increase to a sufficient degree the
- benevolence of men, or the bounty of nature, and you render justice
- useless, by supplying its place with much nobler virtues, and more
- valuable blessings. The selfishness of men is animated by the few
- possessions we have, in proportion to our wants; and 'tis to restrain
- this selfishness, that men have been obliged to separate themselves
- from the community, and to distinguish betwixt their own goods and
- those of others.
- Nor need we have recourse to the fictions of poets to learn this;
- but, beside the reason of the thing, may discover the same truth
- by common experience and observation. 'Tis easy to remark, that a
- cordial affection renders all things common among friends; and that
- married people, in particular, mutually lose their property, and are
- unacquainted with the _mine_ and _thine_, which are so necessary, and
- yet cause such disturbance in human society. The same effect arises
- from any alteration in the circumstances of mankind; as when there is
- such a plenty of any thing as satisfies all the desires of men: in
- which case the distinction of property is entirely lost, and every
- thing remains in common. This we may observe with regard to air and
- water, though the most valuable of all external objects; and may easily
- conclude, that if men were supplied with every thing in the same
- abundance, or if _every one_ had the same affection and tender regard
- for _every one_ as for himself, justice and injustice would be equally
- unknown among mankind.
- Here then is a proposition, which, I think, may be regarded as certain,
- _that 'tis only from the selfishness and confined generosity of men,
- along with the scanty provision nature has made for his wants, that
- justice derives its origin_. If we look backward we shall find,
- that this proposition bestows an additional force on some of those
- observations which we have already made on this subject.
- _First_, We may conclude from it, that a regard to public interest, or
- a strong extensive benevolence, is not our first and original motive
- for the observation of the rules of justice; since 'tis allowed, that
- if men were endowed with such a benevolence, these rules would never
- have been dreamt of.
- _Secondly_, We may conclude from the same principle, that the sense
- of justice is not founded on reason, or on the discovery of certain
- connexions and relations of ideas, which are eternal, immutable,
- and universally obligatory. For since it is confessed, that such an
- alteration as that above-mentioned, in the temper and circumstances
- of mankind, would entirely alter our duties and obligations, 'tis
- necessary upon the common system, _that the sense of virtue is derived
- from reason_, to show the change which this must produce in the
- relations and ideas. But 'tis evident, that the only cause why the
- extensive generosity of man, and the perfect abundance of every thing,
- would destroy the very idea of justice, is, because they render it
- useless; and that, on the other hand, his confined benevolence, and
- his necessitous condition, give rise to that virtue, only by making
- it requisite to the public interest, and to that of every individual.
- 'Twas therefore a concern for our own and the public interest which
- made us establish the laws of justice; and nothing can be more certain,
- than that it is not any relation of ideas which gives us this concern,
- but our impressions and sentiments, without which every thing in nature
- is perfectly indifferent to us, and can never in the least affect us.
- The sense of justice, therefore, is not founded on our ideas, but on
- our impressions.
- _Thirdly_, We may farther confirm the foregoing proposition, _that
- those impressions, which give rise to this sense of justice, are
- not natural to the mind of man, but arise from artifice and human
- conventions_. For, since any considerable alteration of temper and
- circumstances destroys equally justice and injustice; and since such
- an alteration has an effect only by changing our own and the public
- interest, it follows, that the first establishment of the rules of
- justice depends on these different interests. But if men pursued the
- public interest naturally, and with a hearty affection, they would
- never have dreamed of restraining each other by these rules; and if
- they pursued their own interest, without any precaution, they would
- run headlong into every kind of injustice and violence. These rules,
- therefore, are artificial, and seek their end in an oblique and
- indirect manner; nor is the interest which gives rise to them of a kind
- that could be pursued by the natural and inartificial passions of men.
- To make this more evident, consider, that, though the rules of justice
- are established merely by interest, their connexion with interest
- is somewhat singular, and is different from what may be observed on
- other occasions. A single act of justice is frequently contrary to
- _public interest_; and were it to stand alone, without being followed
- by other acts, may, in itself, be very prejudicial to society. When a
- man of merit, of a beneficent disposition, restores a great fortune
- to a miser, or a seditious bigot, he has acted justly and laudably;
- but the public is a real sufferer. Nor is every single act of justice,
- considered apart, more conducive to private interest than to public;
- and 'tis easily conceived how a man may impoverish himself by a signal
- instance of integrity, and have reason to wish, that, with regard to
- that single act, the laws of justice were for a moment suspended in
- the universe. But, however single acts of justice may be contrary,
- either to public or private interest, 'tis certain that the whole plan
- or scheme is highly conducive, or indeed absolutely requisite, both
- to the support of society, and the well-being of every individual.
- 'Tis impossible to separate the good from the ill. Property must be
- stable, and must be fixed by general rules. Though in one instance
- the public be a sufferer, this momentary ill is amply compensated by
- the steady prosecution of the rule, and by the peace and order which
- it establishes in society. And even every individual person must find
- himself a gainer on balancing the account; since, without justice,
- society must immediately dissolve, and every one must fall into that
- savage and solitary condition, which is infinitely worse than the worst
- situation that can possibly be supposed in society. When, therefore,
- men have had experience enough to observe, that, whatever may be the
- consequence of any single act of justice, performed by a single person,
- yet the whole system of actions concurred in by the whole society,
- is infinitely advantageous to the whole, and to every part, it is not
- long before justice and property take place. Every member of society
- is sensible of this interest: every one expresses this sense to his
- fellows, along with the resolution he has taken of squaring his actions
- by it, on condition that others will do the same. No more is requisite
- to induce any one of them to perform an act of justice, who has the
- first opportunity. This becomes an example to others; and thus justice
- establishes itself by a kind of convention or agreement, that is, by
- a sense of interest, supposed to be common to all, and where every
- single act is performed in expectation that others are to perform the
- like. Without such a convention, no one would ever have dreamed that
- there was such a virtue as justice, or have been induced to conform his
- actions to it. Taking any single act, my justice may be pernicious in
- every respect; and 'tis only upon the supposition that others are to
- imitate my example, that I can be induced to embrace that virtue; since
- nothing but this combination can render justice advantageous, or afford
- me any motives to conform myself to its rules.
- We come now to the second question we proposed, viz. _Why we annex the
- idea of virtue to justice, and of vice to injustice_. This question
- will not detain us long after the principles which we have already
- established. All we can say of it at present will be despatched in a
- few words: and for farther satisfaction, the reader must wait till
- we come to the _third_ part of this book. The natural obligation to
- justice, viz. interest, has been fully explained; but as to the _moral_
- obligation, or the sentiment of right and wrong, 'twill first be
- requisite to examine the natural virtues, before we can give a full
- and satisfactory account of it.
- After men have found by experience, that their selfishness and confined
- generosity, acting at their liberty, totally incapacitate them for
- society; and at the same time have observed, that society is necessary
- to the satisfaction of those very passions, they are naturally induced
- to lay themselves under the restraint of such rules, as may render
- their commerce more safe and commodious. To the imposition, then, and
- observance of these rules, both in general, and in every particular
- instance, they are at first induced only by a regard to interest; and
- this motive, on the first formation of society, is sufficiently strong
- and forcible. But when society has become numerous, and has increased
- to a tribe or nation, this interest is more remote; nor do men so
- readily perceive that disorder and confusion follow upon every breach
- of these rules, as in a more narrow and contracted society. But though,
- in our own actions, we may frequently lose sight of that interest which
- we have in maintaining order, and may follow a lesser and more present
- interest, we never fail to observe the prejudice we receive, either
- mediately or immediately, from the injustice of others; as not being
- in that case either blinded by passion, or biassed by any contrary
- temptation. Nay, when the injustice is so distant from us as no way
- to affect our interest, it still displeases us; because we consider
- it as prejudicial to human society, and pernicious to every one that
- approaches the person guilty of it. We partake of their uneasiness
- by _sympathy_; and as every thing which gives uneasiness in human
- actions, upon the general survey, is called Vice, and whatever produces
- satisfaction, in the same manner, is denominated Virtue, this is the
- reason why the sense of moral good and evil follows upon justice and
- injustice. And though this sense, in the present case, be derived only
- from contemplating the actions of others, yet we fail not to extend
- it even to our own actions. The _general rule_ reaches beyond those
- instances from which it arose; while, at the same time, we naturally
- _sympathize_ with others in the sentiments they entertain of us.
- Though this progress of the sentiments be _natural_, and even
- necessary, 'tis certain, that it is here forwarded by the artifice of
- politicians, who, in order to govern men more easily, and preserve
- peace in human society, have endeavoured to produce an esteem for
- justice, and an abhorrence of injustice. This, no doubt, must have
- its effect; but nothing can be more evident, than that the matter has
- been carried too far by certain writers on morals, who seem to have
- employed their utmost efforts to extirpate all sense of virtue from
- among mankind. Any artifice of politicians may assist nature in the
- producing of those sentiments, which she suggests to us, and may even,
- on some occasions, produce alone an approbation or esteem for any
- particular action; but 'tis impossible it should be the sole cause of
- the distinction we make betwixt vice and virtue. For if nature did not
- aid us in this particular, 'twould be in vain for politicians to talk
- of _honourable_ or _dishonourable, praiseworthy_ or _blameable_. These
- words would be perfectly unintelligible, and would no more have any
- idea annexed to them, than if they were of a tongue perfectly unknown
- to us. The utmost politicians can perform, is to extend the natural
- sentiments beyond their original bounds; but still nature must furnish
- the materials, and give us some notion of moral distinctions.
- As public praise and blame increase our esteem for justice, so private
- education and instruction contribute to the same effect. For as parents
- easily observe, that a man is the more useful, both to himself and
- others, the greater degree of probity and honour he is endowed with,
- and that those principles have, greater force when custom and education
- assist interest and reflection: for these reasons they are induced
- to inculcate on their children, from their earliest infancy, the
- principles of probity, and teach them to regard the observance of those
- rules by which society is maintained, as worthy and honourable, and
- their violation as base and infamous. By this means the sentiments of
- honour may take root in their tender minds, and acquire such firmness
- and solidity, that they may fall little short of those principles which
- are the most essential to our natures, and the most deeply radicated in
- our internal constitution.
- What farther contributes to increase their solidity, is the interest
- of our reputation, after the opinion, _that a merit or demerit attends
- justice or injustice_, is once firmly established among mankind.
- There is nothing which touches us more nearly than our reputation,
- and nothing on which our reputation more depends than our conduct
- with relation to the property of others. For this reason, every one
- who has any regard to his character, or who intends to live on good
- terms with mankind, must fix an inviolable law to himself, never, by
- any temptation, to be induced to violate those principles which are
- essential to a man of probity and honour.
- I shall make only one observation before I leave this subject, viz.
- that, though I assert that, in the _state of_ nature, or that imaginary
- state which preceded society, there be neither justice nor injustice,
- yet I assert not that it was allowable, in such a state, to violate
- the property of others. I only maintain, that there was no such thing
- as property; and consequently could be no such thing as justice or
- injustice. I shall have occasion to make a similar reflection with
- regard to _promises_, when I come to treat of them; and I hope this
- reflection, when duly weighed, will suffice to remove all odium from
- the foregoing opinions, with regard to justice and injustice.
- SECTION III.
- OF THE RULES WHICH DETERMINE PROPERTY.
- Though the establishment of the rule, concerning the stability of
- possession, be not only useful, but even absolutely necessary to human
- society, it can never serve to any purpose, while it remains in such
- general terms. Some method must be shown, by which we may distinguish
- what particular goods are to be assigned to each particular person,
- while the rest of mankind are excluded from their possession and
- enjoyment. Our next business, then, must be to discover the reasons
- which modify this general rule, and fit it to the common use and
- practice of the world.
- 'Tis obvious, that those reasons are not derived from any utility or
- advantage, which either the _particular_ person or the public may
- reap from his enjoyment of any _particular_ goods, beyond what would
- result from the possession of them by any other person. 'Twere better,
- no doubt, that every one were possessed of what is most suitable
- to him, and proper for his use: But besides, that this relation of
- fitness may be common to several at once, 'tis liable to so many
- controversies, and men are so partial and passionate in judging of
- these controversies, that such a loose and uncertain rule would be
- absolutely incompatible with the peace of human society. The convention
- concerning the stability of possession is entered into, in order to cut
- off all occasions of discord and contention; and this end would never
- be attained, were we allowed to apply this rule differently in every
- particular case, according to every particular utility which might be
- discovered in such an application. Justice, in her decisions, never
- regards the fitness or unfitness of objects to particular persons, but
- conducts herself by more extensive views. Whether a man be generous, or
- a miser, he is equally well received by her, and obtains, with the same
- facility, a decision in his favour, even for what is entirely useless
- to him.
- It follows, therefore, that the general rule, _that possession must be
- stable_, is not applied by particular judgments, but by other general
- rules, which must extend to the whole society, and be inflexible
- either by spite or favour. To illustrate this, I propose the following
- instance. I first consider men in their savage and solitary condition;
- and suppose that, being sensible of the misery of that state, and
- foreseeing the advantages that would result from society, they seek
- each other's company, and make an offer of mutual protection and
- assistance. I also suppose that they are endowed with such sagacity as
- immediately to perceive that the chief impediment to this project of
- society and partnership lies in the avidity and selfishness of their
- natural temper; to remedy which, they enter into a convention which for
- the stability of possession, and for mutual restraint and forbearance.
- I am sensible that this method of proceeding is not altogether natural;
- but, besides that, I here only suppose those reflections to be formed
- at once, which, in fact, arise insensibly and by degrees; besides this,
- I say, 'tis very possible that several persons, being by different
- accidents separated from the societies to which they formerly belonged,
- may be obliged to form a new society among themselves; in which case
- they are entirely in the situation above-mentioned.
- 'Tis evident, then, that their first difficulty in this situation,
- after the general convention for the establishment of society, and for
- the constancy of possession, is, how to separate their possessions,
- and assign to each his particular portion, which he must for the
- future unalterably enjoy. This difficulty will not detain them long;
- but it must immediately occur to them, as the most natural expedient,
- that every one continue to enjoy what he is at present master of, and
- that property or constant possession be conjoined to the immediate
- possession. Such is the effect of custom, that it not only reconciles
- us to any thing we have long enjoyed, but even gives us an affection
- for it, and makes us prefer it to other objects, which may be more
- valuable, but are less known to us. What has long lain under our eye,
- and has often been employed to our advantage, _that_ we are always the
- most unwilling to part with; but can easily live without possessions
- which we never have enjoyed, and are not accustomed to. 'Tis evident,
- therefore, that men would easily acquiesce in this expedient, _that
- every one continue to enjoy what he is at present possessed of_; and
- this is the reason why they would so naturally agree in preferring
- it.[1]
- But we may observe, that, though the rule of the assignment of property
- to the present possessor be natural, and by that means useful, yet
- its utility extends not beyond the first formation of society; nor
- would any thing be more pernicious than the constant observance of
- it; by which restitution would be excluded, and every injustice would
- be authorized and rewarded. We must, therefore, seek for some other
- circumstance, that may give rise to property after society is once
- established; and of this kind I find four most considerable, viz.
- Occupation, Prescription, Accession, and Succession. We shall briefly
- examine each of these, beginning with _occupation_.
- The possession of all external goods is changeable and uncertain;
- which is one of the most considerable impediments to the establishment
- of society, and is the reason why, by universal agreement, express
- or tacit, men restrain themselves by what we now call the rules of
- justice and equity. The misery of the condition which precedes this
- restraint, is the cause why we submit to that remedy as quickly as
- possible; and this affords us an easy reason why why annex the idea of
- property to the first possession, or to _occupation_. Men are unwilling
- to leave property in suspense, even for the shortest time, or open the
- least door to violence and disorder. To which we may add, that the
- first possession always engages the attention most; and did we neglect
- it, there would be no colour of reason for assigning property to any
- succeeding possession.[2]
- There remains nothing but to determine exactly what is meant by
- possession; and this is not so easy as may at first sight be imagined.
- We are said to be in possession of any thing, not only when we
- immediately touch it, but also when we are so situated with respect
- to it, as to have it in our power to use it; and may move, alter,
- or destroy it, according to our present pleasure or advantage. This
- relation, then, is a species of cause and effect; and as property is
- nothing but a stable possession, derived from the rules of justice,
- or the conventions of men, 'tis to be considered as the same species
- of relation. But here we may observe, that, as the power of using any
- object becomes more or less certain, according as the interruptions
- we may meet with are more or less probable; and as this probability
- may increase by insensible degrees, 'tis in many cases impossible to
- determine when possession begins or ends; nor is there any certain
- standard by which we can decide such controversies. A wild boar that
- falls into our snares, is deemed to be in our possession if it be
- impossible for him to escape. But what do we mean by impossible? How
- do we separate this impossibility from an improbability? And how
- distinguish that exactly from a probability? Mark the precise limits of
- the one and the other, and show the standard, by which we may decide
- all disputes that may arise, and, as we find, by experience, frequently
- do arise upon this subject.[3]
- But such disputes may not arise concerning the real existence of
- property and possession, but also concerning their extent; and these
- disputes are often susceptible of no decision, or can be decided by no
- other faculty than the imagination. A person who lands on the shore of
- a small island that is desart and uncultivated is deemed its possessor
- from the very first moment, and acquires the property of the whole;
- because the object is there bounded and circumscribed in the fancy, and
- at the same time is proportioned to the new possessor. The same person
- landing on a desart island as large as Great Britain, extends his
- property no farther than his immediate possession; though a numerous
- colony are esteemed the proprietors of the whole from the instant of
- their debarkment.
- But if it often happens that the title of first possession becomes
- obscure through time, and that 'tis impossible to determine many
- controversies which may arise concerning it; in that case, long
- possession or _prescription_ naturally takes place, and gives a person
- a sufficient property in any thing he enjoys. The nature of human
- society admits not of any great accuracy; nor can we always remount
- to the first origin of things, in order to determine their present
- condition. Any considerable space of time sets objects at such a
- distance that they seem in a manner to lose their reality, and have
- as little influence on the mind as if they never had been in being. A
- man's title that is clear and certain at present, will seem obscure
- and doubtful fifty years hence, even though the facts on which it is
- founded should be proved with the greatest evidence and certainty.
- The same facts have not the same influence after so long an interval
- of time. And this may be received as a convincing argument for our
- preceding doctrine with regard to property and justice. Possession
- during a long tract of time conveys a title to any object. But as 'tis
- certain that, however every thing be produced in time, there is nothing
- real that is produced by time, it follows, that property being produced
- by time, is not any thing real in the objects, but is the offspring of
- the sentiments, on which alone time is found to have any influence.[4]
- We acquire the property of objects by _accession_, when they are
- connected in an intimate manner with objects that are already our
- property, and at the same time are inferior to them. Thus, the fruits
- of our garden, the offspring of our cattle, and the work of our slaves,
- are all of them esteemed our property, even before possession. Where
- objects are connected together in the imagination, they are apt to be
- put on the same footing, and are commonly supposed to be endowed with
- the same qualities. We readily pass from one to the other, and make no
- difference in our judgments concerning them, especially if the latter
- be inferior to the former. [5]
- The right of _succession_ is a very natural one, from the presumed
- consent of the parent or near relation, and from the general interest
- of mankind, which requires that men's possessions should pass to those
- who are dearest to them, in order to render them more industrious
- and frugal. Perhaps these causes are seconded by the influence of
- _relation_, or the association of ideas, by which we are naturally
- directed to consider the son after the parent's decease, and ascribe
- to him a title to his father's possessions. Those goods must become the
- property of somebody: but _of whom_ is the question. Here 'tis evident
- the person's children naturally present themselves to the mind; and
- being already connected to those possessions by means of their deceased
- parent, we are apt to connect them still farther by the relation of
- property. Of this there are many parallel instances.[6]
- [1] No questions in philosophy are more difficult, than when a number
- of causes present themselves for the same phenomenon, to determine
- which is the principal and predominant. There seldom is any very
- precise argument to fix our choice, and men must be contented to
- be guided by a kind of taste or fancy, arising from analogy, and a
- comparison of similar instances. Thus, in the present case, there
- are, no doubt, motives of public interest for most of the rules
- which determine property; but still I suspect, that these rules are
- principally fixed by the imagination, or the more frivolous properties
- of our thought and conception. I shall continue to explain these
- causes, leaving it to the reader's choice, whether he will prefer those
- derived from public utility, or those derived from the imagination. We
- shall begin with the right of the present possessor.
- 'Tis a quality which I have already observed(*) in human nature, that
- when two objects appear in a close relation to each other, the mind is
- apt to ascribe to them any additional relation, in order to complete
- the union; and this inclination is so strong, as often to make us run
- into errors (such as that of the conjunction of thought and matter) if
- we find that they can serve to that purpose. Many of our impressions
- are incapable of place or local position; and yet those very
- impressions we suppose to have a local conjunction with the impressions
- of sight and touch, merely because they are conjoined by causation, and
- are already united in the imagination. Since, therefore, we can feign a
- new relation, and even an absurd one, in order to complete any union,
- 'twill easily be imagined, that if there be any relations which depend
- on the mind, 'twill readily conjoin them to any preceding relation,
- and unite, by a new bond, such objects as have already an union in the
- fancy. Thus, for instance, we never fail, in our arrangement of bodies,
- to place those which are resembling in contiguity to each other, or at
- least in _correspondent_ points of view; because we feel a satisfaction
- in joining the relation of contiguity to that of resemblance, or the
- resemblance of situation to that of qualities. And this is easily
- accounted for from the known properties of human nature. When the mind
- is determined to join certain objects, but undetermined in its choice
- of the particular objects, it naturally turns its eye to such as are
- related together. They are already united in the mind: they present
- themselves at the same time to the conception; and instead of requiring
- any new reason for their conjunction, it would require a very powerful
- reason to make us overlook this natural affinity. This we shall have
- occasion to explain more fully afterwards when we come to treat of
- _beauty_. In the mean time, we may content ourselves with observing,
- that the same love of order and uniformity which arranges the books in
- a library, and the chairs in a parlour, contributes to the formation
- of society, and to the well-being of mankind, by modifying the general
- rule concerning the stability of possession. And as property forms a
- relation betwixt a person and an object, 'tis natural to found it on
- some preceding relation; and, as property is nothing but a constant
- possession, secured by the laws of society, 'tis natural to add it to
- the present possession, which is a relation that resembles it. For
- this also has its influence. If it be natural to conjoin till sorts of
- relations, 'tis more so to conjoin such relations as are resembling,
- and are related together. (*) Book I. Part IV. Sect. 5
- [2] Some philosophers account for the right of occupation, by saying
- that every one has a property in his own labour; and when he joins that
- labour to any thing, it gives him the property of the whole: but, I.
- There are several kinds of occupation where we cannot be said to join
- our labour to the object we acquire: as when we possess a meadow by
- grazing our cattle upon it 2. This accounts for the matter by means of
- _accession_; which is taking a needless circuit. 3. We cannot be said
- to join our labour to any thing but in a figurative sense. Properly
- speaking, we only make an alteration on it by our labour. This forms
- a relation betwixt us and the object; and thence arises the property,
- according to the preceding principles.
- [3] If we seek a solution of these difficulties in reason and public
- interest, we never shall find satisfaction; and if we look for it in
- the imagination, 'tis evident, that the qualities which operate upon
- that faculty, run so insensibly and gradually into each other, that
- 'tis impossible to give them any precise bounds or termination. The
- difficulties on this head must increase, when we consider that our
- judgment alters very sensibly according to the subject, and that the
- same power and proximity will be deemed possession in one case, which
- is not esteemed such in another. A person who has hunted a hare to
- the last degree of weariness, would look upon it as an injustice for
- another to rush in before him, and seize his prey. But the same person,
- advancing to pluck an apple that hangs within his reach, has no reason
- to complain if another, more alert, passes him, and takes possession.
- What is the reason of this difference, but that immobility, not being
- natural to the hare, but the effect of industry, forms in that case a
- strong relation with the hunter, which is wanting in the other?
- Here, then, it appears, that a certain and infallible power of
- enjoyment, without touch or some other sensible relation, often
- produces not property: and I farther observe, that a sensible relation,
- without any present power, is sometimes sufficient to give a title to
- any object. The sight of a thing is seldom a considerable relation, and
- is only regarded as such, when the object is hidden, or very obscure;
- in which case we find that the view alone conveys a property; according
- to that maxim, _that even a whole continent belongs to the nation which
- first discovered it_. 'Tis however remarkable, that both in the case of
- discovery and that of possession, the first discoverer and possessor
- must join to the relation an intention of rendering himself proprietor,
- otherwise the relation will not have its effect; and that because the
- connexion in our fancy betwixt the property and the relation is not so
- great but that it requires to be helped by such an intention.
- From all these circumstances, 'tis easy to see how perplexed many
- questions may become concerning the acquisition of property by
- occupation; and the least effort of thought may present us with
- instances which are not susceptible of any reasonable decision. If we
- prefer examples which are real to such as are feigned, we may consider
- the following one, which is to be met with in almost every writer
- that has treated of the laws of nature. Two Grecian colonies, leaving
- their native country in search of new seats, were informed that a city
- near them was deserted by its inhabitants. To know the truth of this
- report, they despatched at once two messengers, one from each colony,
- who finding, on their approach, that the information was true, begun a
- race together, with an intention to take possession of the city, each
- of them for his countrymen. One of these messengers, finding that he
- was not an equal match for the other, launched his spear at the gates
- of the city, and was so fortunate as to fix it there before the arrival
- of his companion. This produced a dispute betwixt the two colonies,
- which of them was the proprietor of the empty city; and this dispute
- still subsists among philosophers. For my part, I find the dispute
- impossible to be decided, and that because the whole question hangs
- upon the fancy, which in this case is not possessed of any precise or
- determinate standard upon which it can give sentence. To make this
- evident, let us consider, that if these two persons had been simply
- members of the colonies, and not messengers or deputies, their actions
- would not have been of any consequence; since in that case their
- relation to the colonies would have been but feeble and imperfect. Add
- to this, that nothing determined them to run to the gates rather than
- the walls or any other part of the city, but that the gates, being the
- most *obviated*, and remarkable part, satisfy the fancy best in taking
- them for the whole; as we find by the poets, who frequently draw their
- images and metaphors from them. Besides, we may consider that the touch
- or contact of the one messenger is not properly possession, no more
- than the piercing the gates with the spear, but only forms a relation;
- and there is a relation in the other case equally obvious, though not
- perhaps of equal force. Which of these relations, then, conveys a right
- and property, or whether any of them be sufficient for that effect, I
- leave to the decision of such as are wiser than myself.
- [4] Present possession is plainly a relation betwixt a person and an
- object; but is not sufficient to counterbalance the relation of first
- possession, unless the former be long and uninterrupted; in which case
- the relation is increased on the side of the present possession by
- the extent of time, and diminished on that of first possession by the
- distance. This change in the relation produces a consequent change in
- the property.
- [5] This source of property can never be explained but from the
- imagination; and one may affirm, that the causes are here unmixed. We
- shall proceed to explain them more particularly, and illustrate them by
- examples from common life and experience.
- It has been observed above, that the mind has a natural propensity to
- join relations, especially resembling ones, and finds a kind of fitness
- and uniformity in such an union. From this propensity are derived these
- laws of nature, _that upon the first formation of society, property
- always follows the present possession_; and afterwards, _that it arises
- from first or from long possession_. Now, we may easily observe, that
- relation is not confined merely to one degree; but that from an object
- that is related to us, we acquire a relation to every other object
- which is related to it, and so on, till the thought loses the chain by
- too long a progress. However the relation may weaken by each remove,
- 'tis not immediately destroyed; but frequently connects two objects
- by means of an intermediate one, which is related to both. And this
- principle is of such force as to give rise to the right of _accession_,
- and causes us to acquire the property, not only of such objects as we
- are immediately possessed of, but also of such as are closely connected
- with them.
- Suppose a German, a Frenchman, and a Spaniard, to come into a room
- where there are placed upon the table three bottles of wine, Rhenish,
- Burgundy, and Port; and suppose they should fall a quarrelling about
- the division of them, a person who was chosen for umpire would
- naturally, to show his impartiality, give every one the product of his
- own country; and this from a principle which, in some measure, is the
- source of those laws of nature that ascribe property to occupation,
- prescription and accession.
- In all these cases, and particularly that of accession, there is first
- a _natural_ union betwixt the idea of the person and that of the
- object, and afterwards a new and moral union produced by that right
- or property which we ascribe to the person. But here there occurs a
- difficulty which merits our attention, and may afford us an opportunity
- of putting to trial that singular method of reasoning which has been
- employed on the present subject. I have already observed, that the
- imagination passes with greater facility from little to great, than
- from great to little, and that the transition of ideas is always easier
- and smoother in the former case than in the latter. Now, as the right
- of accession arises from the easy transition of ideas by which related
- objects are connected together, it should naturally be imagined that
- the right of accession must increase in strength, in proportion as
- the transition of ideas is performed with greater facility. It may
- therefore be thought; that when we have acquired the property of any
- small object, we shall readily consider any great object related to it
- as an accession, and as belonging to the proprietor of the small one;
- since the transition is in that case very easy from the small object
- to the great one, and should connect them together in the closest
- manner. But in fact the case is always found to be otherwise. The
- empire of Great Britain seems to draw along with it the dominion of
- the Orkneys, the Hebrides, the Isle of Man, and the Isle of Wight; but
- the authority over those lesser islands does not naturally imply any
- title to Great Britain. In short, a small object naturally follows a
- great one as its accession; but a great one is never supposed to belong
- to the proprietor of a small one related to it, merely on account of
- that property and relation. Yet in this latter case the transition of
- ideas is smoother from the proprietor to the small object which is
- his property, and from the small object to the great one, than in the
- former case from the proprietor to the great object, and from the great
- one to the small. It may therefore be thought, that these phenomena are
- objections to the foregoing hypothesis, _that the ascribing of property
- to accession is nothing but an effect of the relations of ideas, and of
- the smooth transition of the imagination_.
- 'Twill be easy to solve this objection, if we consider the agility and
- unsteadiness of the imagination, with the different views in which it
- is continually placing its objects. When we attribute to a person a
- property in two objects, we do not always pass from the person to one
- object, and from that to the other related to it. The objects being
- here to be considered as the property of the person, we are apt to join
- them together, and place them in the same light. Suppose, therefore,
- a great and a small object to be related together, if a person be
- strongly related to the great object, he will likewise be strongly
- related to both the objects considered together, because he is related
- to the most considerable part. On the contrary, if he be only related
- to the small object, he will not be strongly related to both considered
- together, since his relation lies only with the most trivial part,
- which is not apt to strike us in any great degree when we consider the
- whole. And this is the reason why small objects become accessions to
- great ones, and not great to small.
- 'Tis the general opinion of philosophers and civilians, that the sea is
- incapable of becoming the property of any nation; and that because 'tis
- impossible to take possession of it, or form any such distinct relation
- with it, as may be the foundation of property. Where this reason
- ceases, property immediately takes place. Thus, the most strenuous
- advocates for the liberty of the seas universally allow, that friths
- and bays naturally belong as an accession to the proprietors of the
- surrounding continent These have properly no more bond or union with
- the land than the _Pacific_ ocean would have; but having an union in
- the fancy, and being at the same time _inferior_, they are of course
- regarded as an accession.
- The property of rivers, by the laws of most nations, and by the natural
- turn of our thought, is attributed to the proprietors of their banks,
- excepting such vast rivers as the Rhine or the Danube, which seem too
- large to the imagination to follow as an accession the property of
- the neighbouring fields. Yet even these rivers are considered as the
- property of that nation through whose dominions they run; the idea of
- a nation being a suitable bulk to correspond with them, and bear them
- such a relation in the fancy.
- The accessions which are made to lands bordering upon rivers, follow
- the land, say the civilians, provided it be made by what they
- call _alluvion_, that is, insensibly and imperceptibly; which are
- circumstances that mightily assist the imagination in the conjunction.
- Where there is any considerable portion torn at once from one bank,
- and joined to another, it becomes not his property whose land it falls
- on, till it unite with the land, and till the trees or plants have
- spread their roots into both. Before that, the imagination does not
- sufficiently join them.
- There are other cases which somewhat resemble this of accession,
- but which, at the bottom, are considerably different, and merit our
- attention. Of this kind is the conjunction of the properties of
- different persons, after such a manner as not to admit of _separation_.
- The question is, to whom the united mass must belong.
- Where this conjunction is of such a nature as to admit of _division_,
- but not of _separation_, the decision is natural and easy. The
- whole mass must be supposed to be common betwixt the proprietors
- of the several parts, and afterwards must be divided according to
- the proportions of these parts. But here I cannot forbear taking
- notice of a remarkable subtilty of the Roman law, in distinguishing
- betwixt _confusion_ and _commixtion_. Confusion is an union of two
- bodies, such as different liquors, where the parts become entirely
- undistinguishable. Commixtion is the blending of two bodies, such as
- two bushels of corn, where the parts remain separate in an obvious and
- visible manner. As in the latter case the imagination discovers not so
- entire an union as in the former, but is able to trace and preserve
- a distinct idea of the property of each; this is the reason why the
- _civil_ law, though it established an entire community in the case of
- _confusion_, and after that a proportional division, yet in the case of
- _commixtion_, supposes each of the proprietors to maintain a distinct
- right; however, necessity may at last force them to submit to the same
- division. _Quod si frumentum Titii frumento tuo mistum fuerit: siquidem
- ex voluntate vestra, communc est: quia singula corpora, id est, singula
- grana, quæ a cujusque propria fuerunt, ex consensu vestro communicata
- sunt. Quod si casu id mistum fuerit, vel Titius id miscuerit sine
- tua voluntate, non videtur id communc esse; quia singula corpora
- in sua substantia durant. Sed nec magis istis casibus commune sit
- frumentum quam grex intelligitur esse communis, si pecora Titii tuis
- pecoribus mista fuerint. Sed si ab alterutro vestrum totum id frumentum
- retineatur, in rem quidem actio pro modo frumenti cujusque competit.
- Arbitrio autem judicis, ut ipse æstimet quale cujusque frumentum
- fuerit_. Inst. Lib. II. Tit I. § 28.
- Where the properties of two persons are united after such a manner as
- neither to admit of _division_ nor _separation_, as when one builds a
- house on another's ground, in that case the whole must belong to one of
- the proprietors; and here I assert, that it naturally is conceived to
- belong to the proprietor of the most considerable part. For, however
- the compound object may have a relation to two different persons, and
- carry our view at once to both of them, yet, as the most considerable
- part principally engages our attention, and by the strict union draws
- the inferior along it; for this reason, the whole bears a relation to
- the proprietor of that part, and is regarded as his property. The only
- difficulty is, what we shall be pleased to call the most considerable
- part, and most attractive to the imagination.
- This quality depends on several different circumstances which have
- little connexion with each other. One part of a compound object may
- become more considerable than another, either because it is more
- constant and durable; because it is of greater value; because it is
- more obvious and remarkable; because it is of greater extent; or
- because its existence is more separate and independent. 'Twill be easy
- to conceive, that, as these circumstances may be conjoined and opposed
- in all the different ways, and according to all the different degrees,
- which can be imagined, there will result many cases where the reasons
- on both sides are so equally balanced, that 'tis impossible for us to
- give any satisfactory decision. Here, then, is the proper business of
- municipal laws, to fix what the principles of human nature have left
- undetermined.
- The superficies yields to the soil, says the civil law: the writing to
- the paper: the canvas to the picture. These decisions do not well agree
- together, and are a proof of the contrariety of those principles from
- which they are derived.
- But of all the questions of this kind, the most curious is that which
- for so many ages divided the disciples of _Proculus_ and _Sabinus_.
- Suppose a person should make a cup from the metal of another, or a ship
- from his wood, and suppose the proprietor of the metal or wood should
- demand his goods, the question is, whether he acquires a title to the
- cup or ship. _Sabinus_ maintained the affirmative, and asserted, that
- the substance or matter is the foundation of all the qualities; that
- it is incorruptible and immortal, and therefore superior to the form,
- which is casual and dependent. On the other hand, _Proculus_ observed,
- that the form is the most obvious and remarkable part, and that from
- it bodies are denominated of this or that particular species. To which
- he might have added, that the matter or substance is in most bodies
- so fluctuating and uncertain, that 'tis utterly impossible to trace
- it in all its changes. For my part, I know not from what principles
- such a controversy can be certainly determined. I shall therefore
- content myself with observing, that the decision of _Trebonian_ seems
- to me pretty ingenious; that the cup belongs to the proprietor of the
- metal, because it can be brought back to its first form: but that the
- ship belongs to the author of its form, for a contrary reason. But,
- however ingenious this reason may seem, it plainly depends upon the
- fancy, which, by the possibility of such a reduction, finds a closer
- connexion and relation betwixt a cup and the proprietor of its metal,
- than betwixt a ship and the proprietor of its wood, where the substance
- is more fixed and unalterable.
- [6] In examining the different titles to authority in government,
- we shall meet with many reasons to convince us that the right of
- succession depends, in a great measure, on the imagination. Meanwhile I
- shall rest contented with observing one example, which belongs to the
- present subject. Suppose that a person die without children, and that
- a dispute arises among his relations concerning his inheritance; 'tis
- evident, that if his riches be derived partly from his father, partly
- from his mother, the most natural way of determining such a dispute
- is, to divide his possessions, and assign each part to the family from
- whence it is derived. Now, as the person is supposed to have been
- once the full and entire proprietor of those goods, I ask, what is it
- makes us find a certain equity and natural reason in this partition,
- except it be the imagination? His affection to these families does not
- depend upon his possessions; for which reason his consent can never be
- presumed precisely for such a partition. And as to the public interest,
- it seems not to be in the least concerned on the one side or the other.
- SECTION IV.
- OF THE TRANSFERENCE OF PROPERTY BY CONSENT.
- However useful, or even necessary, the stability of possession may be
- to human society, 'tis attended with very considerable inconveniences.
- The relation of fitness or suitableness ought never to enter into
- consideration, in distributing the properties of mankind; but we must
- govern ourselves by rules which are more general in their application,
- and more free from doubt and uncertainty. Of this kind is _present_
- possession upon the first establishment of society; and afterwards
- _occupation, prescription, accession_, and _succession_. As these
- depend very much on chance, they must frequently prove contradictory
- both to men's wants and desires; and persons and possessions must often
- be very ill adjusted. This is a grand inconvenience, which calls for a
- remedy. To apply one directly, and allow every man to seize by violence
- what he judges to be fit for him, would destroy society; and therefore
- the rules of justice seek some medium betwixt a rigid stability and
- this changeable and uncertain adjustment. But there is no medium
- better than that obvious one, that possession and property should
- always be stable, except when the proprietor consents to bestow them on
- some other person. This rule can have no ill consequence in occasioning
- wars and dissensions, since the proprietor's consent, who alone is
- concerned, is taken along in the alienation; and it may serve to many
- good purposes in adjusting property to persons. Different parts of the
- earth produce different commodities; and not only so, but different
- men both are by nature fitted for different employments, and attain
- to greater perfection in any one, when they confine themselves to it
- alone. All this requires a mutual exchange and commerce; for which
- reason the translation of property by consent is founded on a law of
- nature, as well as its stability without such a consent.
- So far is determined by a plain utility and interest. But perhaps 'tis
- from more trivial reasons, that _delivery_, or a sensible transference
- of the object, is commonly required by civil laws, and also by the laws
- of nature, according to most authors, as a requisite circumstance in
- the translation of property. The property of an object, when taken for
- something real, without any reference to morality, or the sentiments of
- the mind, is a quality perfectly insensible, and even inconceivable;
- nor can we form any distinct notion, either of its stability or
- translation. This imperfection of our ideas is less sensibly felt with
- regard to its stability, as it engages less our attention, and is
- easily past over by the mind, without any scrupulous examination. But
- as the translation of property from one person to another is a more
- remarkable event, the defect of our ideas becomes more sensible on that
- occasion, and obliges us to turn ourselves on every side in search of
- some remedy. Now, as nothing more enlivens any idea than a present
- impression, and a relation betwixt that impression and the idea; 'tis
- natural for us to seek some false light from this quarter. In order
- to aid the imagination in conceiving the transference of property, we
- take the sensible object, and actually transfer its possession to the
- person on whom we would bestow the property. The supposed resemblance
- of the actions, and the presence of this sensible delivery, deceive the
- mind, and make it fancy that it conceives the mysterious transition of
- the property. And that this explication of the matter is just, appears
- hence, that men have invented a _symbolical_ delivery, to satisfy the
- fancy where the real one is impracticable. Thus the giving the keys of
- a granary, is understood to be the delivery of the corn contained in
- it: the giving of stone and earth represents the delivery of a manor.
- This is a kind of superstitious practice in civil laws, and in the laws
- of nature, resembling the _Roman Catholic_ superstitions in religion.
- As the _Roman Catholics_ represent the inconceivable mysteries of the
- _Christian_ religion, and render them more present to the mind, by
- a taper, or habit, or grimace, which is supposed to resemble them;
- so lawyers and moralists have run into like inventions for the same
- reason, and have endeavoured by those means to satisfy themselves
- concerning the transference of property by consent.
- SECTION V.
- OF THE OBLIGATION OF PROMISES.
- That the rule of morality, which enjoins the performance of
- promises, is not _natural_, will sufficiently appear from these two
- propositions, which I proceed to prove, viz. _that a promise would not
- be intelligible before human conventions had established it; and that
- even if it were intelligible, it would not be attended with any moral
- obligation_.
- I say, _first_, that a promise is not intelligible naturally, nor
- antecedent to human conventions; and that a man, unacquainted with
- society, could never enter into any engagements with another, even
- though they could perceive each other's thoughts by intuition. If
- promises be natural and intelligible, there must be some act of the
- mind attending these words, I _promise_; and on this act of the mind
- must the obligation depend. Let us therefore run over all the faculties
- of the soul, and see which of them is exerted in our promises.
- The act of the mind, expressed by a promise, is not a _resolution_ to
- perform any thing; for that alone never imposes any obligation. Nor is
- it a _desire_ of such a performance; for we may bind ourselves without
- such a desire, or even with an aversion, declared and avowed. Neither
- is it the _willing_ of that action which we promise to perform; for a
- promise always regards some future time, and the will has an influence
- only on present actions. It follows, therefore, that since the act of
- the mind, which enters into a promise, and produces its obligation,
- is neither the resolving, desiring, nor willing any particular
- performance, it must necessarily be the _willing_ of that _obligation_
- which arises from the promise. Nor is this only a conclusion of
- philosophy, but is entirely conformable to our common ways of thinking
- and of expressing ourselves, when we say that we are bound by our
- own consent, and that the obligation arises from our mere will and
- pleasure. The only question then is, whether there be not a manifest
- absurdity in supposing this act of the mind, and such an absurdity as
- no man could fall into, whose ideas are not confounded with prejudice
- and the fallacious use of language.
- All morality depends upon our sentiments; and when any action or
- quality of the mind pleases us _after a certain manner_, we say it is
- virtuous; and when the neglect or non-performance of it displeases
- us _after a like manner_, we say that we lie under an obligation
- to perform it. A change of the obligation supposes a change of the
- sentiment; and a creation of a new obligation supposes some new
- sentiment to arise. But 'tis certain we can naturally no more change
- our own sentiments than the motions of the heavens; nor by a single
- act of our will, that is, by a promise, render any action agreeable or
- disagreeable, moral or immoral, which, without that act, would have
- produced contrary impressions, or have been endowed with different
- qualities. It would be absurd, therefore, to will any new obligation,
- that is, any new sentiment of pain or pleasure; nor is it possible
- that men could naturally fall into so gross an absurdity. A promise,
- therefore, is _naturally_ something altogether unintelligible, nor is
- there any act of the mind belonging to it.[7]
- But, _secondly_, if there was any act of the mind belonging to it, it
- could not _naturally_ produce any obligation. This appears evidently
- from the foregoing reasoning. A promise creates a new obligation. A new
- obligation supposes new sentiments to arise. The will never creates new
- sentiments. There could not naturally, therefore, arise any obligation
- from a promise, even supposing the mind could fall into the absurdity
- of willing that obligation.
- The same truth may be proved still more evidently by that reasoning
- which proved justice in general to be an artificial virtue. No action
- can be required of us as our duty, unless there be implanted in
- human nature some actuating passion or motive capable of producing
- the action. This motive cannot be the sense of duty. A sense of
- duty supposes an antecedent obligation; and where an action is not
- required by any natural passion, it cannot be required by any natural
- obligation; since it may be omitted without proving any defect or
- imperfection in the mind and temper, and consequently without any
- vice. Now, 'tis evident we have no motive leading us to the performance
- of promises, distinct from a sense of duty. If we thought that promises
- had no moral obligation, we never should feel any inclination to
- observe them. This is not the case with the natural virtues. Though
- there was no obligation to relieve the miserable, our humanity would
- lead us to it; and when we omit that duty, the immorality of the
- omission arises from its being a proof that we want the natural
- sentiments of humanity. A father knows it to be his duty to take care
- of his children, but he has also a natural inclination to it. And if
- no human creature had that inclination, no one could lie under any
- such obligation. But as there is naturally no inclination to observe
- promises distinct from a sense of their obligation, it follows,
- that fidelity is no natural virtue, and that promises have no force
- antecedent to human conventions.
- If any one dissent from this, he must give a regular proof of these two
- propositions, viz. _that there is a peculiar act of the mind annexed
- to promises_; and _that consequent to this act of the mind, there
- arises an inclination to perform, distinct from a sense of duty_. I
- presume that it is impossible to prove either of these two points; and
- therefore I venture to conclude, that promises are human inventions,
- founded on the necessities and interests of society.
- In order to discover these necessities and interests, we must consider
- the same qualities of human nature which we have already found to give
- rise to the preceding laws of society. Men being naturally selfish, or
- endowed only with a confined generosity, they are not easily induced to
- perform any action for the interest of strangers, except with a view
- to some reciprocal advantage, which they had no hope of obtaining
- but by such a performance. Now, as it frequently happens that these
- mutual performances cannot be finished at the same instant, 'tis
- necessary that one party be contented to remain in uncertainty, and
- depend upon the gratitude of the other for a return of kindness. But
- so much corruption is there among men, that, generally speaking, this
- becomes but a slender security; and as the benefactor is here supposed
- to bestow his favours with a view to self-interest, this both takes
- off from the obligation, and sets an example of selfishness, which
- is the true mother of ingratitude. Were we, therefore, to follow the
- natural course of our passions and inclinations, we should perform
- but few actions for the advantage of others from disinterested views,
- because we are naturally very limited in our kindness and affection;
- and we should perform as few of that kind out of regard to interest,
- because we cannot depend upon their gratitude. Here, then, is the
- mutual commerce of good offices in a manner lost among mankind, and
- every one reduced to his own skill and industry for his well-being
- and subsistence. The invention of the law of nature, concerning the
- _stability_ of possession, has already rendered men tolerable to each
- other; that of the _transference_ of property and possession by consent
- has begun to render them mutually advantageous; but still these laws
- of nature, however strictly observed, are not sufficient to render
- them so serviceable to each other as by nature they are fitted to
- become. Though possession be _stable_, men may often reap but small
- advantage from it, while they are possessed of a greater quantity of
- any species of goods than they have occasion for, and at the same
- time suffer by the want of others. The _transference_ of property,
- which is the proper remedy for this inconvenience, cannot remedy it
- entirely; because it can only take place with regard to such objects
- as are _present_ and _individual_, but not to such as are _absent_ or
- _general_. One cannot transfer the property of a particular house,
- twenty leagues distant, because the consent cannot be attended with
- delivery, which is a requisite circumstance. Neither can one transfer
- the property of ten bushels of corn, or five hogsheads of wine, by the
- mere expression and consent, because these are only general terms, and
- have no direct relation to any particular heap of corn or barrels of
- wine. Besides, the commerce of mankind is not confined to the barter
- of commodities, but may extend to services and actions, which we may
- exchange to our mutual interest and advantage. Your corn is ripe
- to-day; mine will be so to-morrow. 'Tis profitable for us both that I
- should labour with you to-day, and that you should aid me to-morrow. I
- have no kindness for you, and know you have as little for me. I will
- not, therefore, take any pains upon your account; and should I labour
- with you upon my own account, in expectation of a return, I know I
- should be disappointed, and that I should in vain depend upon your
- gratitude. Here, then, I leave you to labour alone: you treat me in the
- same manner. The seasons change; and both of us lose our harvests for
- want of mutual confidence and security.
- All this is the effect of the natural and inherent principles and
- passions of human nature; and as these passions and principles are
- unalterable, it may be thought that our conduct, which depends on them,
- must be so too, and that 'twould be in vain, either for moralists or
- politicians, to tamper with us, or attempt to change the usual course
- of our actions, with a view to public interest. And, indeed, did the
- success of their designs depend upon their success in correcting the
- selfishness and ingratitude of men, they would never make any progress,
- unless aided by Omnipotence, which is alone able to new-mould the
- human mind, and change its character in such fundamental articles.
- All they can pretend to is, to give a new direction to those natural
- passions, and teach us that we can better satisfy our appetites in an
- oblique and artificial manner, than by their headlong and impetuous
- motion. Hence I learn to do a service to another, without bearing him
- any real kindness; because I foresee that he will return my service,
- in expectation of another of the same kind, and in order to maintain
- the same correspondence of good offices with me or with others. And
- accordingly, after I have served him, and he is in possession of the
- advantage arising, from my action, he is induced to perform his part,
- as foreseeing the consequences of his refusal.
- But though this self-interested commerce of men begins to take place,
- and to predominate in society, it does not entirely abolish the more
- generous and noble intercourse of friendship and good offices. I may
- still do services to such persons as I love, and am more particularly
- acquainted with, without any prospect of advantage; and they may
- make me a return in the same manner, without any view but that of
- recompensing my past services. In order, therefore, to distinguish
- those two different sorts of commerce, the interested and the
- disinterested, there is a _certain form of words_ invented for the
- former, by which we bind ourselves to the performance of any action.
- This form of words constitutes what we call a _promise_, which is
- the sanction of the interested commerce of mankind. When a man says
- _he promises any thing_, he in effect expresses a _resolution_ of
- performing it; and along with that, by making use of this _form of
- words,_, subjects himself to the penalty of never being trusted again
- in case of failure. A resolution is the natural act of the mind, which
- promises express; but were there no more than a resolution in the case,
- promises would only declare our former motives, and would not create
- any new motive or obligation. They are the conventions of men, which
- create a new motive, when experience has taught us that human affairs
- would be conducted much more for mutual advantage, were there certain
- _symbols_ or _signs_ instituted, by which we might give each other
- security of our conduct in any particular incident. After these signs
- are instituted, whoever uses them is immediately bound by his interest
- to execute his engagements, and must never expect to be trusted any
- more, if he refuse to perform what he promised.
- Nor is that knowledge, which is requisite to make mankind sensible of
- this interest in the _institution_ and _observance_ of promises, to be
- esteemed superior to the capacity of human nature, however savage and
- uncultivated. There needs but a very little practice of the world, to
- make us perceive all these consequences and advantages. The shortest
- experience of society discovers them to every mortal; and when each
- individual perceives the same sense of interest in all his fellows, he
- immediately performs his part of any contract, as being assured that
- they will not be wanting in theirs. All of them, by concert, enter
- into a scheme of actions, calculated for common benefit, and agree to
- be true to their word; nor is there any thing requisite to form this
- concert or convention, but that every one have a sense of interest
- in the faithful fulfilling of engagements, and express that sense to
- other members of the society. This immediately causes that interest
- to operate upon them; and interest is the _first_ obligation to the
- performance of promises.
- Afterwards a sentiment of morals concurs with interest, and becomes
- a new obligation upon mankind. This sentiment of morality, in the
- performance of promises, arises from the same principles as that
- in the abstinence from the property of others. _Public interest,
- education_, and _the artifices of politicians_, have the same effect
- in both cases. The difficulties that occur to us in supposing a moral
- obligation to attend promises, we either surmount or elude. For
- instance, the expression of a resolution is not commonly supposed to
- be obligatory; and we cannot readily conceive how the making use of a
- certain form of words should be able to cause any material difference.
- Here, therefore, we _feign_ a new act of the mind, which we call the
- _willing_ an obligation; and on this we suppose the morality to depend.
- But we have proved already, that there is no such act of the mind, and
- consequently, that promises impose no natural obligation.
- To confirm this, we may subjoin some other reflections concerning
- that will, which is supposed to enter into a promise, and to cause
- its obligation. 'Tis evident, that the will alone is never supposed
- to cause the obligation, but must be expressed by words or signs, in
- order to impose a tie upon any man. The expression being once brought
- in as subservient to the will, soon becomes the principal part of the
- promise; nor will a man be less bound by his word, though he secretly
- give a different direction to his intention, and withhold himself
- both from a resolution, and from willing an obligation. But though the
- expression makes on most occasions the whole of the promise, yet it
- does not always so; and one who should make use of any expression of
- which he knows not the meaning, and which he uses without any intention
- of binding himself, would not certainly be bound by it. Nay, though he
- knows its meaning, yet if he uses it in jest only, and with such signs
- as show evidently he has no serious intention of binding himself, he
- would not lie under any obligation of performance; but 'tis necessary
- that the words be a perfect expression of the will, without any
- contrary signs. Nay, even this we must not carry so far as to imagine,
- that one, whom, by our quickness of understanding, we conjecture, from
- certain signs, to have an intention of deceiving us, is not bound by
- his expression or verbal promise, if we accept of it; but must limit
- this conclusion to those cases where the signs are of a different kind
- from those of deceit. All these contradictions are easily accounted
- for, if the obligation of promises be merely a human invention for the
- convenience of society; but will never be explained, if it be something
- _real_ and _natural_, arising from any action of the mind or body.
- I shall farther observe, that, since every new promise imposes a new
- obligation of morality on the person who promises, and since this
- new obligation arises from his will; 'tis one of the most mysterious
- and incomprehensible operations that can possibly be imagined, and
- may even be compared to _transubstantiation_, or _holy orders_,[8]
- where a certain form of words, along with a certain intention,
- changes entirely the nature of an external object, and even of a
- human creature. But though these mysteries be so far alike, 'tis very
- remarkable that they differ widely in other particulars, and that this
- difference may be regarded as a strong proof of the difference of their
- origins. As the obligation of promises is an invention for the interest
- of society, 'tis warped into as many different forms as that interest
- requires, and even runs into direct contradictions, rather than lose
- sight of its object. But as those other monstrous doctrines are mere
- priestly inventions, and have no public interest in view, they are less
- disturbed in their progress by new obstacles; and it must be owned,
- that, after the first absurdity, they follow more directly the current
- of reason and good sense. Theologians clearly perceived, that the
- external form of words, being mere sound, require an intention to make
- them have any efficacy; and that this intention being once considered
- as a requisite circumstance, its absence must equally prevent the
- effect, whether avowed or concealed, whether sincere or deceitful.
- Accordingly, they have commonly determined, that the intention of
- the priest makes the sacrament, and that when he secretly withdraws
- his intention, he is highly criminal in himself; but still destroys
- the baptism, or communion, or holy orders. The terrible consequences
- of this doctrine were not able to hinder its taking place; as the
- inconvenience of a similar doctrine, with regard to promises, have
- prevented that doctrine from establishing itself. Men are always more
- concerned about the present life than the future; and are apt to think
- the smallest evil which regards the former, more important than the
- greatest which regards the latter.
- We may draw the same conclusion, concerning the origin of promises,
- from the force which is supposed to invalidate all contracts, and
- to free us from their obligation. Such a principle is a proof
- that promises have no natural obligation, and are mere artificial
- contrivances for the convenience and advantage of society. If we
- consider aright of the matter, force is not essentially different
- from any other motive of hope or fear, which may induce us to engage
- our word, and lay ourselves under any obligation. A man, dangerously
- wounded, who promises a competent sum to a surgeon to cure him, would
- certainly be bound to performance; though the case be not so much
- different from that of one who promises a sum to a robber, as to
- produce so great a difference in our sentiments of morality, if these
- sentiments were not built entirely on public interest and convenience.
- [7] Were morality discoverable by reason, and not by sentiment, 'twould
- be still more evident that promises could make no alteration upon it.
- Morality is supposed to consist in relation. Every new imposition of
- morality, therefore, must arise from some new relation of objects;
- and consequently the will could not produce immediately any change in
- morals, but could have that effect only by producing a change upon the
- objects. But as the moral obligation of a promise is the pure effect
- of the will, without the least change in any part of the universe, it
- follows, that promises have no natural obligation.
- Should it be said, that this act of the will, being in effect a new
- object, produces new relations and new duties; I would answer, that
- this is a pure sophism, which may be detected by a very moderate share
- of accuracy and exactness. To will a new obligation, is to will a new
- relation of objects; and therefore, if this new relation of objects
- were formed by the volition itself, we should, in effect, will the
- volition, which is plainly absurd and impossible. The will has here
- no object to which it could tend, but must return upon itself in
- _infinitum_. The new obligation depends upon new relations. The new
- relations depend upon a new volition. The new volition has for object a
- new obligation, and consequently new relations, and consequently a new
- volition; which volition, again, has in view a new obligation, relation
- and volition, without any termination. 'Tis impossible, therefore, we
- could ever will a new obligation; and consequently 'tis impossible the
- will could ever accompany a promise, or produce a new obligation of
- morality.
- [8] I mean so far as holy orders are supposed to produce the _indelible
- Character_. In other respects they are only a legal qualification.
- SECTION VI.
- SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE.
- We have now run over the three fundamental laws of nature, _that of the
- stability of possession, of its transference by consent_, and _of the
- performance of promises_. 'Tis on the strict observance of those three
- laws that the peace and security of human society entirely depend; nor
- is there any possibility of establishing a good correspondence among
- men, where these are neglected. Society is absolutely necessary for
- the well-being of men; and these are as necessary to the supports
- of society. Whatever restraint they may impose on the passions of
- men, they are the real offspring of those passions, and are only a
- more artful and more refined way of satisfying them. Nothing is more
- vigilant and inventive than our passions; and nothing is more obvious
- than the convention for the observance of these rules. Nature has,
- therefore, trusted this affair entirely to the conduct of men, and has
- not placed in the mind any peculiar original principles, to determine
- us to a set of actions, into which the other principles of our frame
- and constitution were sufficient to lead us. And to convince us the
- more fully of this truth, we may here stop a moment, and, from a review
- of the preceding reasonings, may draw some new arguments, to prove that
- those laws, however necessary, are entirely artificial, and of human
- invention; and consequently, that justice is an artificial, and not a
- natural virtue.
- I. The first argument I shall make use of is derived from the vulgar
- definition of justice. Justice is commonly defined to be _a constant
- and perpetual will of giving every one his due_. In this definition
- 'tis supposed that there are such things as right and property,
- independent of justice, and antecedent to it; and that they would have
- subsisted, though men had never dreamt of practising such a virtue.
- I have already observed, in a cursory manner, the fallacy of this
- opinion, and shall here continue to open up, a little more distinctly,
- my sentiments on that subject.
- I shall begin with observing, that this quality, which we call
- _property_, is like many of the imaginary qualities of the
- _Peripatetic_ philosophy, and vanishes upon a more accurate inspection
- into the subject, when considered apart from our moral sentiments, 'Tis
- evident property does not consist in any of the sensible qualities
- of the object. For these may continue invariably the same, while the
- property changes. Property, therefore, must consist in some relation of
- the object. But 'tis not in its relation with regard to other external
- and inanimate objects. For these may also continue invariably the
- same, while the property changes. This quality, therefore, consists in
- the relations of objects to intelligent and rational beings. But 'tis
- not the external and corporeal relation which forms the essence of
- property. For that relation may be the same betwixt inanimate objects,
- or with regard to brute creatures; though in those cases it forms no
- property. 'Tis therefore in some internal relation that the property
- consists; that is, in some influence which the external relations of
- the object have on the mind and actions. Thus, the external relation
- which we call _occupation_ or first possession, is not of itself
- imagined to be the property of the object, but only to cause its
- property. Now, 'tis evident this external relation causes nothing in
- external objects, and has only an influence on the mind, by giving us
- a sense of duty in abstaining from that object, and in restoring it to
- the first possessor. These actions are properly what we call _justice_;
- and consequently 'tis on that virtue that the nature of property
- depends, and not the virtue on the property.
- If any one, therefore, would assert that justice is a natural virtue,
- and injustice a natural vice, he must assert, that abstracting from the
- notions of _property_ and _right_ and _obligation_, a certain conduct
- and train of actions, in certain external relations of objects, has
- naturally a moral beauty or deformity, and causes an original pleasure
- or uneasiness. Thus, the restoring a man's goods to him is considered
- as virtuous, not because nature has annexed a certain sentiment of
- pleasure to such a conduct with regard to the property of others, but
- because she has annexed that sentiment to such a conduct, with regard
- to those external objects of which others have had the first or long
- possession, or which they have received by the consent of those who
- have had first or long possession. If nature has given us no such
- sentiment, there is not naturally, nor antecedent to human conventions,
- any such thing as property. Now, though it seems sufficiently evident,
- in this dry and accurate consideration of the present subject, that
- nature has annexed no pleasure or sentiment of approbation to such a
- conduct, yet, that I may leave as little room for doubt as possible, I
- shall subjoin a few more arguments to confirm my opinion.
- _First_, If nature had given us a pleasure of this kind, it would
- have been as evident and discernible as on every other occasion; nor
- should we have found any difficulty to perceive, that the consideration
- of such actions, in such a situation, gives a certain pleasure and
- sentiment of approbation. We should not have been obliged to have
- recourse to notions of property in the definition of justice, and at
- the same time make use of the notions of justice in the definition of
- pro-property. This deceitful method of reasoning is a plain proof that
- there are contained in the subject some obscurities and difficulties
- which we are not able to surmount, and which we desire to evade by this
- artifice.
- _Secondly_, Those rules by which properties, rights and obligations
- are determined, have in them no marks of a natural origin, but many
- of artifice and contrivance. They are too numerous to have proceeded
- from nature; they are changeable by human laws; and have all of them a
- direct and evident tendency to public good, and the support of civil
- society. This last circumstance is remarkable upon two accounts.
- _First_, Because, though the cause of the establishment of these laws
- had been a _regard_ for the public good, as much as the public good
- is their natural tendency, they would still have been artificial, as
- being purposely contrived, and directed to a certain end. _Secondly_,
- Because, if men had been endowed with such a strong regard for public
- good, they would never have restrained themselves by these rules; so
- that the laws of justice arise from natural principles, in a manner
- still more oblique and artificial. 'Tis self-love which is their real
- origin; and as the self-love of one person is naturally contrary to
- that of another, these several interested passions are obliged to
- adjust themselves after such a manner as to concur in some system
- of conduct and behaviour. This system, therefore, comprehending the
- interest of each individual, is of course advantageous to the public,
- though it be not intended for that purpose by the inventors.
- II. In the _second_ place, we may observe, that all kinds of vice
- and virtue run insensibly into each other, and may approach by such
- imperceptible degrees as will make it very difficult, if not absolutely
- impossible, to determine when the one ends and the other begins; and
- from this observation we may derive a new argument for the foregoing
- principle. For, whatever may be the case with regard to all kinds
- of vice and virtue, 'tis certain that rights, and obligations, and
- property, admit of no such insensible gradation, but that a man
- either has a full and perfect property, or none at all; and is either
- entirely obliged to perform any action, or lies under no manner of
- obligation. However civil laws may talk of a perfect _dominion_, and of
- an imperfect, 'tis easy to observe, that this arises from a fiction,
- which has no foundation in reason, and can never enter into our notions
- of natural justice and equity. A man that hires a horse, though but
- for a day, has as full a right to make use of it for that time, as he
- whom we call its proprietor has to make use of it any other day; and
- 'tis evident that, however the use may be bounded in time or degree,
- the right itself is not susceptible of any such gradation, but is
- absolute and entire, so far as it extends. Accordingly, we may observe,
- that this right both arises and perishes in an instant; and that a man
- entirely acquires the property of any object by occupation, or the
- consent of the proprietor; and loses it by his own consent, without any
- of that insensible gradation which is remarkable in other qualities and
- relations. Since, therefore, this is the case with regard to property,
- and rights, and obligations, I ask, how it stands with regard to
- justice and injustice? After whatever manner you answer this question,
- you run into inextricable difficulties. If you reply, that justice
- and injustice admit of degree, and run insensibly into each other,
- you expressly contradict the foregoing position, that obligation and
- property are not susceptible of such a gradation. These depend entirely
- upon justice and injustice, and follow them in all their variations.
- Where the justice is entire, the property is also entire: where the
- justice is imperfect, the property must also be imperfect. And _vice
- versa_, if the property admit of no such variations, they must also
- be incompatible with justice. If you assent, therefore, to this last
- proposition, and assert that justice and injustice are not susceptible
- of degrees, you in effect assert that they are not _naturally_ either
- vicious or virtuous; since vice and virtue, moral good and evil, and
- indeed all _natural_ qualities, run insensibly into each other, and are
- on many occasions undistinguishable.
- And here it may be worth while to observe, that though abstract
- reasoning and the general maxims of philosophy and law establish this
- position, _that property, and right, and obligation, admit not of
- degrees_, yet, in our common and negligent way of thinking, we find
- great difficulty to entertain that opinion, and do even secretly
- embrace the contrary principle. An object must either be in the
- possession of one person or another. An action must either be performed
- or not. The necessity there is of choosing one side in these dilemmas,
- and the impossibility there often is of finding any just medium, oblige
- us, when we reflect on the matter, to acknowledge that all property and
- obligations are entire. But, on the other hand, when we consider the
- origin of property and obligation, and find that they depend on public
- utility, and sometimes on the propensity of the imagination, which
- are seldom entire on any side, we are naturally inclined to imagine
- that these moral relations admit of an insensible gradation. Hence
- it is that in references, where the consent of the parties leave the
- referees entire masters of the subject, they commonly discover so much
- equity and justice on both sides as induces them to strike a medium,
- and divide the difference betwixt the parties. Civil judges, who have
- not this liberty, but are obliged to give a decisive sentence on some
- one side, are often at a loss how to determine, and are necessitated
- to proceed on the most frivolous reasons in the world. Half rights
- and obligations, which seem so natural in common life, are perfect
- absurdities in their tribunal; for which reason they are often obliged
- to take half arguments for whole ones, in order to terminate the affair
- one way or other.
- III. The _third_ argument of this kind I shall make use of may be
- explained thus. If we consider the ordinary course of human actions,
- we shall find that the mind restrains not itself by any general and
- universal rules, but acts on most occasions as it is determined by
- its present motives and inclination. As each action is a particular
- individual event, it must proceed from particular principles, and from
- our immediate situation within ourselves, and with respect to the rest
- of the universe. If on some occasions we extend our motives beyond
- those very circumstances which gave rise to them, and form something
- like _general rides_ for our conduct, 'tis easy to observe that these
- rules are not perfectly inflexible, but allow of many exceptions.
- Since, therefore, this is the ordinary course of human actions, we
- may conclude that the laws of justice, being universal and perfectly
- inflexible, can never be derived from nature, nor be the immediate
- offspring of any natural motive or inclination. No action can be either
- morally good or evil, unless there be some natural passion or motive to
- impel us to it, or deter us from it; and tis evident that the morality
- must be susceptible of all the same variations which are natural to the
- passion. Here are two persons who dispute for an estate; of whom one is
- rich, a fool, and a bachelor; the other poor, a man of sense, and has a
- numerous family: the first is my enemy; the second my friend. Whether
- I be actuated in this affair by a view to public or private interest,
- by friendship or enmity, I must be induced to do my utmost to procure
- the estate to the latter. Nor would any consideration of the right and
- property of the persons be able to restrain me, were I actuated only
- by natural motives, without any combination or convention with others.
- For as all property depends on morality, and as all morality depends
- on the ordinary course of our passions and actions, and as these again
- are only directed by particular motives, 'tis evident such a partial
- conduct must be suitable to the strictest morality, and could never
- be a violation of property. Were men, therefore, to take the liberty
- of acting with regard to the laws of society, as they do in every
- other affair, they would conduct themselves, on most occasions, by
- particular judgments, and would take into consideration the characters
- and circumstances of the persons, as well as the general nature of the
- question. But 'tis easy to observe, that this would produce an infinite
- confusion in human society, and that the avidity and partiality of men
- would quickly bring disorder into the world, if not restrained by some
- general and inflexible principles. 'Twas therefore with a view to this
- inconvenience, that men have established those principles, and have
- agreed to restrain themselves by general rules, which are unchangeable
- by spite and favour, and by particular views of private or public
- interest. These rules, then, are artificially invented for a certain
- purpose, and are contrary to the common principles of human nature,
- which accommodate themselves to circumstances, and have no stated
- invariable method of operation.
- Nor do I perceive how I can easily be mistaken in this matter. I see
- evidently, that when any man imposes on himself general inflexible
- rules in his conduct with others, he considers certain objects as
- their property, which he supposes to be sacred and inviolable. But
- no proposition can be more evident, than that property is perfectly
- unintelligible without first supposing justice and injustice; and that
- these virtues and vices are as unintelligible, unless we have motives,
- independent of the morality, to impel us to just actions, and deter
- us from unjust ones. Let those motives, therefore, be what they will,
- they must accommodate themselves to circumstances, and must admit of
- all the variations which human affairs, in their incessant revolutions,
- are susceptible of. They are, consequently, a very improper foundation
- for such rigid inflexible rules as the laws of nature; and 'tis evident
- these laws can only be derived from human conventions, when men have
- perceived the disorders that result from following their natural and
- variable principles.
- Upon the whole, then, we are to consider this distinction betwixt
- justice and injustice, as having two different foundations, viz.
- that of _interest_, when men observe, that 'tis impossible to live
- in society without restraining themselves by certain rules; and that
- of _morality_, when this interest is once observed, and men receive
- a pleasure from the view of such actions as tend to the peace of
- society, and an uneasiness from such as are contrary to it. 'Tis the
- voluntary convention and artifice of men which makes the first interest
- take place; and therefore those laws of justice are so far to be
- considered as _artificial_. After that interest is once established and
- acknowledged, the sense of morality in the observance of these rules
- follows _naturally_, and of itself; though tis certain, that it is also
- augmented by a new _artifice_, and that the public instructions of
- politicians, and the private education of parents, contribute to the
- giving us a sense of honour and duty, in the strict regulation of our
- actions with regard to the properties of others.
- SECTION VII.
- OF THE ORIGIN OF GOVERNMENT.
- Nothing is more certain, than that men are in a great measure governed
- by interest, and that, even when they extend their concern beyond
- themselves, 'tis not to any great distance; nor is it usual for
- them, in common life, to look farther than their nearest friends and
- acquaintance. 'Tis no less certain, that 'tis impossible for men to
- consult their interest in so effectual a manner, as by an universal and
- inflexible observance of the rules of justice, by which alone they can
- preserve society, and keep themselves from falling into that wretched
- and savage condition which is commonly represented as the _state of
- nature_. And as this interest which all men have in the upholding of
- society, and the observation of the rules of justice, is great, so
- is it palpable and evident, even to the most rude and uncultivated
- of the human race; and 'tis almost impossible for any one who has
- had experience of society, to be mistaken in this particular. Since,
- therefore, men are so sincerely attached to their interest, and their
- interest is so much concerned in the observance of justice, and this
- interest is so certain and avowed, it may be asked, how any disorder
- can ever arise in society, and what principle there is in human nature
- so _powerful_ as to overcome so strong a passion, or so _violent_ as to
- obscure so clear a knowledge?
- It has been observed, in treating of the Passions, that men are
- mightily governed by the imagination, and proportion their affections
- more to the light under which any object appears to them, than to its
- real and intrinsic value. What strikes upon them with a strong and
- lively idea commonly prevails above what lies in a more obscure light;
- and it must be a great superiority of value that is able to compensate
- this advantage. Now, as every thing that is contiguous to us, either in
- space or time, strikes upon us with such an idea, it has a proportional
- effect on the will and passions, and commonly operates with more force
- than any object that lies in a more distant and obscure light. Though
- we may be fully convinced, that the latter object excels the former, we
- are not able to regulate our actions by this judgment, but yield to the
- solicitations of our passions, which always plead in favour of whatever
- is near and contiguous.
- This is the reason why men so often act in contradiction to their known
- interest; and, in particular, why they prefer any trivial advantage
- that is present, to the maintenance of order in society, which so
- much depends on the observance of justice. The consequences of every
- breach of equity seem to lie very remote, and and are not liable to
- counterbalance any immediate advantage that may be reaped from it. They
- are, however, never the less real for being remote; and as all men are,
- in some degree, subject to the same weakness, it necessarily happens,
- that the violations of equity must become very frequent in society,
- and the commerce of men, by that means, be rendered very dangerous
- and uncertain. You have the same propension that I have in favour of
- what is contiguous above what is remote. You are, therefore, naturally
- carried to commit acts of injustice as well as me. Your example both
- pushes me forward in this way by imitation, and also affords me a new
- reason for any breach of equity, by showing me, that I should be the
- cully of my integrity, if I alone should impose on myself a severe
- restraint amidst the licentiousness of others.
- This quality, therefore, of human nature, not only is very dangerous
- to society, but also seems, on a cursory view, to be incapable of any
- remedy. The remedy can only come from the consent of men; and if men
- be incapable of themselves to prefer remote to contiguous, they will
- never consent to any thing which would oblige them to such a choice,
- and contradict, in so sensible a manner, their natural principles and
- propensities. Whoever chooses the means, chooses also the end; and
- if it be impossible for us to prefer what is remote, 'tis equally
- impossible for us to submit to any necessity which would oblige us to
- such a method of acting.
- But here 'tis observable, that this infirmity of human nature becomes
- a remedy to itself, and that we provide against our negligence about
- remote objects, merely because we are naturally inclined to that
- negligence. When we consider any objects at a distance, all their
- minute distinctions vanish, and we always give the preference to
- whatever is in itself preferable, without considering its situation and
- circumstances. This gives rise to what, in an improper sense, we call
- _reason_, which is a principle that is often contradictory to those
- propensities that display themselves upon the approach of the object.
- In reflecting on any action which I am to perform a twelvemonth hence,
- I always resolve to prefer the greater good, whether at that time it
- will be more contiguous or remote; nor does any difference in that
- particular make a difference in my present intentions and resolutions.
- My distance from the final determination makes all those minute
- differences vanish, nor am I affected by any thing but the general and
- more discernible qualities of good and evil. But on my nearer approach,
- those circumstances which I at first overlooked begin to appear, and
- have an influence on my conduct and affections. A new inclination to
- the present good springs up, and makes it difficult for me to adhere
- inflexibly to my first purpose and resolution. This natural infirmity
- I may very much regret, and I may endeavour, by all possible means, to
- free myself from it. I may have recourse to study and reflection within
- myself; to the advice of friends; to frequent meditation, and repeated
- resolution: And having experienced how ineffectual all these are, I
- may embrace with pleasure any other expedient by which I may impose a
- restraint upon myself, and guard against this weakness.
- The only, difficulty, therefore, is to find out this expedient, by
- which men cure their natural weakness, and lay themselves under the
- necessity of observing the laws of justice and equity, notwithstanding
- their violent propension to prefer contiguous to remote. 'Tis
- evident such a remedy can never be effectual without correcting
- this propensity; and as 'tis impossible to change or correct any
- thing material in our nature, the utmost we can do is to change our
- circumstances and situation, and render the observance of the laws of
- justice our nearest interest, and their violation our most remote.
- But this being impracticable with respect to all mankind, it can only
- take place with respect to a few, whom we thus immediately interest
- in the execution of justice. These are the persons whom we call civil
- magistrates, kings and their ministers, our governors and rulers,
- who, being indifferent persons to the greatest part of the state,
- have no interest, or but a remote one, in any act of injustice; and,
- being satisfied with their present condition, and with their part in
- society, have an immediate interest in every execution of justice,
- which is so necessary to the upholding of society. Here, then, is the
- origin of civil government and society. Men are not able radically to
- cure, either in themselves or others, that narrowness of soul which
- makes them prefer the present to the remote. They cannot change their
- natures. All they can do is to change their situation, and render
- the observance of justice the immediate interest of some particular
- persons, and its violation their more remote. These persons, then, are
- not only induced to observe those rules in their own conduct, but also
- to constrain others to a like regularity, and enforce the dictates of
- equity through the whole society. And if it be necessary, they may
- also interest others more immediately in the execution of justice, and
- create a number of officers, civil and military, to assist them in
- their government.
- But this execution of justice, though the principal, is not the
- only advantage of government. As violent passion hinders men from
- seeing distinctly the interest they have in an equitable behaviour
- towards others, so it hinders them from seeing that equity itself,
- and gives them a remarkable partiality in their own favours. This
- inconvenience is corrected in the same manner as that above mentioned.
- The same persons who execute the laws of justice, will also decide all
- controversies concerning them; and, being indifferent to the greatest
- part of the society, will decide them more equitably than every one
- would in his own case.
- By means of these two advantages in the _execution_ and _decision_
- of justice, men acquire a security against each other's weakness and
- passion, as well as against their own, and, under the shelter of their
- governors, begin to taste at ease the sweets of society and mutual
- assistance. But government extends farther its beneficial influence;
- and, not contented to protect men in those conventions they make for
- their mutual interest, it often obliges them to make such conventions,
- and forces them to seek their own advantage, by a concurrence in some
- common end or purpose. There is no quality in human nature which causes
- more fatal errors in our conduct, than that which leads us to prefer
- whatever is present to the distant and remote, and makes us desire
- objects more according to their situation than their intrinsic value.
- Two neighbours may agree to drain a meadow, which they possess in
- common: because 'tis easy for them to know each other's mind; and each
- must perceive, that the immediate consequence of his failing in his
- part, is the abandoning the whole project. But 'tis very difficult, and
- indeed impossible, that a thousand persons should agree in any such
- action; it being difficult for them to concert so complicated a design,
- and still more difficult for them to execute it; while each seeks a
- pretext to free himself of the trouble and expense, and would lay the
- whole burden on others. Political society easily remedies both these
- inconveniences. Magistrates find an immediate interest in the interest
- of any considerable part of their subjects. They need consult nobody
- but themselves to form any scheme for the promoting of that interest.
- And as the failure of any one piece in the execution is connected,
- though not immediately, with the failure of the whole, they prevent
- that failure, because they find no interest in it, either immediate
- or remote. Thus, bridges are built, harbours opened, ramparts raised,
- canals formed, fleets equipped, and armies disciplined, every where,
- by the care of government, which, though composed of men subject to
- all human infirmities, becomes, by one of the finest and most subtile
- inventions imaginable, a composition which is in some measure exempted
- from all these infirmities.
- SECTION VIII.
- OF THE SOURCE OF ALLEGIANCE.
- Though government be an invention very advantageous, and even in some
- circumstances absolutely necessary to mankind, it is not necessary in
- all circumstances; nor is it impossible for men to preserve society
- for some time, without having recourse to such an invention. Men, 'tis
- true, are always much inclined to prefer present interest to distant
- and remote; nor is it easy for them to resist the temptation of any
- advantage that they may immediately enjoy, in apprehension of an evil
- that lies at a distance from them; but still this weakness is less
- conspicuous where the possessions and the pleasures of life are few
- and of little value, as they always are in the infancy of society.
- An Indian is but little tempted to dispossess another of his hut, or
- to steal his bow, as being already provided of the same advantages;
- and as to any superior fortune which may attend one above another in
- hunting and fishing, 'tis only casual and temporary, and will have
- but small tendency to disturb society. And so far am I from thinking
- with some philosophers, that men are utterly incapable of society
- without government, that I assert the first rudiments of government
- to arise from quarrels, not among men of the same society, but among
- those of different societies. A less degree of riches will suffice
- to this latter effect, is requisite for the former. Men fear nothing
- from public war and violence but the resistance they meet with, which,
- because they share it in common, seems less terrible, and, because it
- comes from strangers, seems less pernicious in its consequences, than
- when they are exposed singly against one whose commerce is advantageous
- to them, and without whose society 'tis impossible they can subsist.
- Now foreign war, to a society without government, necessarily produces
- civil war. Throw any considerable goods among men, they instantly fall
- a quarrelling, while each strives to get possession of what pleases
- him, without regard to the consequences. In a foreign war, the most
- considerable of all goods, life and limbs, are at stake; and as every
- one shuns dangerous ports, seizes the best arms, seeks excuse for the
- slightest wounds, the laws, which may be well enough observed while
- men were calm, can now no longer take place, when they are in such
- commotion.
- This we find verified in the American tribes, where men live in concord
- and amity among themselves, without any established government, and
- never pay submission to any of their fellows, except in time of war,
- when their captain enjoys a shadow of authority, which he loses after
- their return from the field and the establishment of peace with the
- neighbouring tribes. This authority, however, instructs them in the
- advantages of government, and teaches them to have recourse to it,
- when, either by the pillage of war, by commerce, or by any fortuitous
- inventions, their riches and possessions have become so considerable
- as to make them forget, on every emergence, the interest they have in
- the preservation of peace and justice. Hence we may give a plausible
- reason, among others, why all governments are at first monarchical,
- without any mixture and variety; and why republics arise only from the
- abuses of monarchy and despotic power. Camps are the true mothers of
- cities; and as war cannot be administered, by reason of the suddenness
- of every exigency, without some authority in a single person, the same
- kind of authority naturally takes place in that civil government which
- succeeds the military. And this reason I take to be more natural than
- the common one derived from patriarchal government, or the authority
- of a father, which is said first to take place in one family, and to
- accustom the members of it to the government of a single person. The
- state of society without government is one of the most natural states
- of men, and must subsist with the conjunction of many families, and
- long after the first generation. Nothing but an increase of riches
- and possessions could oblige men to quit it; and so barbarous and
- uninstructed are all societies on their first formation, that many
- years must elapse before these can increase to such a degree as to
- disturb men in the enjoyment of peace and concord.
- But though it be possible for men to maintain a small uncultivated
- society without government, 'tis impossible they should maintain a
- society of any kind without justice, and the observance of those
- three fundamental laws concerning the stability of possession, its
- translation by consent, and the performance of promises. These are
- therefore antecedent to government, and are supposed to impose an
- obligation, before the duty of allegiance to civil magistrates has
- once been thought of. Nay, I shall go farther, and assert, that
- government, _upon its first establishment_, would naturally be supposed
- to derive its obligation from those laws of of nature, and, in
- particular, from that concerning the performance of promises. When men
- have once perceived the necessity of government to maintain peace and
- execute justice, they would naturally assemble together, would choose
- magistrates, determine their power, and _promise_ them obedience. As
- a promise is supposed to be a bond or security already in use, and
- attended with a moral obligation, 'tis to be considered as the original
- sanction of government, and as the source of the first obligation to
- obedience. This reasoning appears so natural, that it has become the
- foundation of our fashionable system of politics, and is in a manner
- the creed of a party amongst us, who pride themselves, with reason, on
- the soundness of their philosophy, and their liberty of thought. 'All
- men,' say they, 'are born free and equal: government and superiority
- can only be established by consent: the consent of men, in establishing
- government, imposes on them a new obligation, unknown to the laws
- of nature. Men, therefore, are bound to obey their magistrates,
- only because they promise it; and if they had not given their word,
- either expressly or tacitly, to preserve allegiance, it would never
- have become a part of their moral duty. This conclusion, however,
- when carried so far as to comprehend government in all its ages and
- situations, is entirely erroneous; and I maintain, that though the duty
- of allegiance be at first grafted on the obligation of promises, and be
- for some time supported by that obligation, yet it quickly takes root
- of itself, and has an original obligation and authority, independent
- of all contracts. This is a principle of moment, which we must examine
- with care and attention, before we proceed any farther.
- 'Tis reasonable for those philosophers who assert justice to be a
- natural virtue, and antecedent to human conventions, to resolve all
- civil allegiance into the obligation of a promise, and assert that 'tis
- our own consent alone which binds us to any submission to magistracy.
- For as all government is plainly an invention of men, and the origin of
- most governments is known in history, 'tis necessary to mount higher,
- in order to find the source of our political duties, if we would assert
- them to have any _natural_ obligation of morality. These philosophers,
- therefore, quickly observe, that society is as ancient as the human
- species, and those three fundamental laws of nature as ancient as
- society; so that, taking advantage of the antiquity and obscure origin
- of these laws, they first deny them to be artificial and voluntary
- inventions of men, and then seek to ingraft on them those other duties
- which are more plainly artificial. But being once undeceived in this
- particular, and having found that _natural_ as well as _civil_ justice
- derives its origin from human conventions, we shall quickly perceive
- how fruitless it is to resolve the one into the other, and seek, in the
- laws of nature, a stronger foundation for our political duties than
- interest and human conventions; while these laws themselves are built
- on the very same foundation. On whichever side we turn this subject,
- we shall find that these two kinds of duty are exactly on the same
- footing, and have the same source both of their _first invention_ and
- _moral obligation_. They are contrived to remedy like inconveniences,
- and acquire their moral sanction in the same manner, from their
- remedying those inconveniences. These are two points which we shall
- endeavour to prove as distinctly as possible.
- We have already shown, that men _invented_ the three fundamental
- laws of nature, when they observed the necessity of society to their
- mutual subsistence, and found that 'twas impossible to maintain any
- correspondence together, without some restraint on their natural
- appetites. The same self-love, therefore, which renders men so
- incommodious to each other, taking a new and more convenient direction,
- produces the rules of justice, and is the _first_ motive of their
- observance. But when men have observed, that though the rules of
- justice be sufficient to maintain any society, yet 'tis impossible
- for them, of themselves, to observe those rules in large and polished
- societies; they establish government as a new invention to attain
- their ends, and preserve the old, or procure new advantages, by a more
- strict execution of justice. So far, therefore, our _civil_ duties are
- connected with our _natural_, that the former are invented chiefly for
- the sake of the latter; and that the principal object of government
- is to constrain men to observe the laws of nature. In this respect,
- however, that law of nature, concerning the performance of promises, is
- only comprised along with the rest; and its exact observance is to be
- considered as an effect of the institution of government, and not the
- obedience to government as an effect of the obligation of a promise.
- Though the object of our civil duties be the enforcing of our natural,
- yet the _first_[9] motive of the invention, as well as performance
- of both, is nothing but self-interest; and since there is a separate
- interest in the obedience to government, from that in the performance
- of promises, we must also allow of a separate obligation. To obey the
- civil magistrate is requisite to preserve order and concord in society.
- To perform promises is requisite to beget mutual trust and confidence
- in the common offices of life. The ends, as well as the means, are
- perfectly distinct; nor is the one subordinate to the other.
- To make this more evident, let us consider, that men will often bind
- themselves by promises to the performance of what it would have been
- their interest to perform, independent of these promises; as when they
- would give others a fuller security, by superadding a new obligation
- of interest to that which they formerly lay under. The interest in the
- performance of promises, besides its moral obligation, is general,
- avowed, and of the last consequence in life. Other interests may be
- more particular and doubtful; and we are apt to entertain a greater
- suspicion, that men may indulge their humour or passion in acting
- contrary to them. Here, therefore, promises come naturally in play, and
- are often required for fuller satisfaction and security. But supposing
- those other interests to be as general and avowed as the interest in
- the performance of a promise, they will be regarded as on the same
- footing, and men will begin to repose the same confidence in them. Now
- this is exactly the case with regard to our civil duties, or obedience
- to the magistrate; without which no government could subsist, nor any
- peace or order be maintained in large societies, where there are so
- many possessions on the one hand, and so many wants, real or imaginary,
- on the other. Our civil duties, therefore, must soon detach themselves
- from our promises, and acquire a separate force and influence. The
- interest in both is of the very same kind; 'tis general, avowed,
- and prevails in all times and places. There is, then, no pretext of
- reason for founding the one upon the other, while each of them has a
- foundation peculiar to itself. We might as well resolve the obligation
- to abstain from the possessions of others, into the obligation of a
- promise, as that of allegiance. The interests are not more distinct in
- the one case than the other. A regard to property is not more necessary
- to natural society, than obedience is to civil society or government;
- nor is the former society more necessary to the being of mankind,
- than the latter to their well-being and happiness. In short, if the
- performance of promises be advantageous, so is obedience to government;
- if the former interest be general, so is the latter; if the one
- interest be obvious and avowed, so is the other. And as these two rules
- are founded on like obligations of interest, each of them must have a
- peculiar authority, independent of the other.
- But 'tis not only the _natural_ obligations of interest, which are
- distinct in promises and allegiance; but also the _moral_ obligations
- of honour and conscience: nor does the merit or demerit of the one
- depend in the least upon that of the other. And, indeed, if we consider
- the close connexion there is betwixt the natural and moral obligations,
- we shall find this conclusion to be entirely unavoidable. Our interest
- is always engaged on the side of obedience to magistracy; and there is
- nothing but a great present advantage that can lead us to rebellion, by
- making us overlook the remote interest which we have in the preserving
- of peace and order in society. But though a present interest may thus
- blind us with regard to our own actions, it takes not place with regard
- to those of others; nor hinders them from appearing in their true
- colours, as highly prejudicial to public interest, and to our own in
- particular. This naturally gives us an uneasiness, in considering such
- seditious and disloyal actions, and makes us attach to them the idea
- of vice and moral deformity. 'Tis the same principle which causes us
- to disapprove of all kinds of private injustice, and, in particular,
- of the breach of promises. We blame all treachery and breach of faith;
- because we consider, that the freedom and extent of human commerce
- depend entirely on a fidelity with regard to promises. We blame all
- disloyalty to magistrates; because we perceive that the execution of
- justice, in the stability of possession, its translation by consent,
- and the performance of promises, is impossible, without submission to
- government. As there are here two interests entirely distinct from each
- other, they must give rise to two moral obligations, equally separate
- and independent. Though there was no such thing as a promise in the
- world, government would still be necessary in all large and civilized
- societies; and if promises had only their own proper obligation,
- without the separate sanction of government, they would have but little
- efficacy in such societies. This separates the boundaries of our public
- and private duties, and shows that the latter are more dependent on the
- former, than the former on the latter. _Education_, and _the artifice
- of politicians_, concur to bestow a farther morality on loyalty, and to
- brand all rebellion with a greater degree of guilt and infamy. Nor is
- it a wonder that politicians should be very industrious in inculcating
- such notions, where their interest is so particularly concerned.
- Lest those arguments should not appear entirely conclusive (as I think
- they are), I shall have recourse to authority, and shall prove, from
- the universal consent of mankind, that the obligation of submission to
- government is not derived from any promise of the subjects. Nor need
- any one wonder, that though I have all along endeavoured to establish
- my system on pure reason, and have scarce ever cited the judgment even
- of philosophers or historians on any article, I should now appeal to
- popular authority, and oppose the sentiments of the rabble to any
- philosophical reasoning. For it must be observed, that the opinions of
- men, in this case, carry with them a peculiar authority, and are, in
- a great measure, infallible. The distinction of moral good and evil
- is founded on the pleasure or pain which results from the view of any
- sentiment or character; and, as that pleasure or pain cannot be unknown
- to the person who feels it, it follows,[10] that there is just so much
- vice or virtue in any character as every one places in it, and that
- 'tis impossible in this particular we can ever be mistaken. And, though
- our judgments concerning the _origin_ of any vice or virtue, be not so
- certain as those concerning their _degrees_, yet, since the question in
- this case regards not any philosophical origin of an obligation, but a
- plain matter of fact, 'tis not easily conceived how we can fall into
- an error. A man who acknowledges himself to be bound to another for
- a certain sum, must certainly know whether it be by his own bond, or
- that of his father; whether it be of his mere good will, or for money
- lent him; and under what conditions, and for what purposes, he has
- bound himself. In like manner, it being certain that there is a moral
- obligation to submit to government, because everyone thinks so; it must
- be as certain that this obligation arises not from a promise; since no
- one, whose judgment has not been led astray by too strict adherence to
- a system of philosophy, has ever yet dreamt of ascribing it to that
- origin. Neither magistrates nor subjects have formed this idea of our
- civil duties.
- We find, that magistrates are so far from deriving their authority, and
- the obligation to obedience in their subjects, from the foundation of
- a promise or original contract, that they conceal, as far as possible,
- from their people, especially from the vulgar, that they have their
- origin from thence. Were this the sanction of government, our rulers
- would never receive it tacitly, which is the utmost that can be
- pretended; since what is given tacitly and insensibly, can never have
- such influence on mankind as what is performed expressly and openly.
- A tacit promise is, where the will is signified by other more diffuse
- signs than those of speech; but a will there must certainly be in the
- case, and that can never escape the person's notice who exerted it,
- however silent or tacit. But were you to ask the far greatest part of
- the nation, whether they had ever consented to the authority of their
- rulers, or promised to obey them, they would be inclined to think very
- strangely of you; and would certainly reply, that the affair depended
- not on their consent, but that they were born to such an obedience.
- In consequence of this opinion, we frequently see them imagine such
- persons to be their natural rulers, as are at that time deprived of
- all power and authority, and whom no man, however foolish, would
- voluntarily choose; and this merely because they are in that line
- which ruled before, and in that decree of it which used to succeed:
- though perhaps in so distant a period, that scarce any man alive could
- ever have given any promise of obedience. Has a government, then, no
- authority over such as these, because they never consented to it,
- and would esteem the very attempt of such a free choice a piece of
- arrogance and impiety? We find by experience, that it punishes them
- very freely for what it calls treason and rebellion, which, it seems,
- according to this system, reduces itself to common injustice. If you
- say, that by dwelling in its dominions, they in effect consented to
- the established government, I answer, that this can only be where they
- think the affair depends on their choice, which few or none beside
- those philosophers have ever yet imagined. It never was pleaded as an
- excuse for a rebel, that the first act he performed, after he came
- to years of discretion, was to levy war against the sovereign of the
- state; and that, while he was a child he could not bind himself by his
- own consent, and having become a man, showed plainly, by the first act
- he performed, that he had no design to impose on himself any obligation
- to obedience. We find, on the contrary, that civil laws punish this
- crime at the same age as any other which is criminal of itself,
- without our consent; that is, when the person is come to the full use
- of reason: whereas to this crime it ought in justice to allow some
- intermediate time, in which a tacit consent at least might be supposed.
- To which we may add, that a man living under an absolute government
- would owe it no allegiance; since, by its very nature, it depends not
- on consent. But as that is as _natural_ and _common_ a government as
- any, it must certainly occasion some obligation; and 'tis plain from
- experience, that men who are subjected to it do always think so. This
- is a clear proof, that we do not commonly esteem our allegiance to
- be derived from our consent or promise; and a farther proof is, that
- when our promise is upon any account expressly engaged, we always
- distinguish exactly betwixt the two obligations, and believe the one to
- add more force to the other, than in a repetition of the same promise.
- Where no promise is given, a man looks not on his faith as broken
- in private matters, upon account of rebellion; but keeps those two
- duties of honour and allegiance perfectly distinct and separate. As
- the uniting of them was thought by these philosophers a very subtile
- invention, this is a convincing proof that 'tis not a true one; since
- no man can either give a promise, or be restrained by its sanction and
- obligation, unknown to himself.
- SECTION IX.
- OF THE MEASURES OF ALLEGIANCE.
- Those political writers who have had recourse to a promise, or original
- contract, as the source of our allegiance to government, intended
- to establish a principle which is perfectly just and reasonable;
- though the reasoning upon which they endeavoured to establish it, was
- fallacious and sophistical. They would prove, that our submission to
- government admits of exceptions, and that an egregious tyranny in the
- rulers is sufficient to free the subjects from all ties of allegiance.
- Since men enter into society, say they, and submit themselves to
- government by their free and voluntary consent, they must have in
- view certain advantages which they, propose to reap from it, and for
- which they are contented to resign their native liberty. There is
- therefore something mutual engaged on the part of the magistrate,
- viz. protection and security; and 'tis only by the hopes he affords
- of these advantages, that he can ever persuade men to submit to him.
- But when, instead of protection and security, they meet with tyranny
- and oppression, they are freed from their promises, (as happens in
- all conditional contracts), and return to that state of liberty
- which preceded the institution of government. Men would never be so
- foolish as to enter into such engagements as should turn entirely
- to the advantage of others, without any view of bettering their own
- condition. Whoever proposes to draw any profit from our submission,
- must engage himself, either expressly or tacitly, to make us reap some
- advantage from his authority; nor ought he to expect, that, without the
- performance of his part, we will ever continue in obedience.
- I repeat it: This conclusion is just, though the principles be
- erroneous; and I flatter myself, that I can establish the same
- conclusion on more reasonable principles. I shall not take such a
- compass, in establishing our political duties, as to assert that men
- perceive the advantages of government; that they institute government
- with a view to those advantages; that this institution requires a
- promise of obedience, which imposes a moral obligation to a certain
- degree, but, being conditional, ceases to be binding whenever the other
- contracting party performs not his part of the engagement. I perceive,
- that a promise itself arises entirely from human conventions, and is
- invented with a view to a certain interest. I seek, therefore, some
- such interest more immediately connected with government, and which may
- be at once the original motive to its institution, and the source of
- our obedience to it. This interest I find to consist in the security
- and protection which we enjoy in political society, and which we can
- never attain when perfectly free and independent. As the interest,
- therefore, is the immediate sanction of government, the one can have no
- longer being than the other; and whenever the civil magistrate carries
- his oppression so far as to render his authority perfectly intolerable,
- we are no longer bound to submit to it. The cause ceases; the effect
- must cease also.
- So far the conclusion is immediate and direct, concerning the _natural_
- obligation which we have to allegiance. As to the _moral_ obligation,
- we may observe, that the maxim would here be false, that _when the
- cause ceases the effect must cease also_. For there is a principle
- of human nature, which we have frequently taken notice of, that men
- are mightily addicted to _general rules_, and that we often carry our
- maxims beyond those reasons which first induced us to establish them.
- Where cases are similar in many circumstances, we are apt to put them
- on the same footing, without considering that they differ in the most
- material circumstances, and that the resemblance is more apparent than
- real. It may therefore be thought, that, in the case of allegiance,
- our moral obligation of duty will not cease, even though the natural
- obligation of interest, which is its cause, has ceased; and that men
- may be bound by _conscience_ to submit to a tyrannical government,
- against their own and the public interest. And indeed, to the force of
- this argument I so far submit, as to acknowledge, that general rules
- commonly extend beyond the principles on which they are founded; and
- that we seldom make any exception to them, unless that exception have
- the qualities of a general rule, and be founded on very numerous and
- common instances. Now this I assert to be entirely the present case.
- When men submit to the authority of others, 'tis to procure themselves
- some security against the wickedness and injustice of men, who are
- perpetually carried, by their unruly passions, and by their present
- and immediate interest, to the violation of all the laws of society.
- But as this imperfection is inherent in human nature, we know that it
- must attend men in all their states and conditions; and that those
- whom we choose for rulers, do not immediately become of a superior
- nature to the rest of mankind, upon account of their superior power and
- authority. What we expect from them depends not on a change of their
- nature, but of their situation, when they acquire a more immediate
- interest in the preservation of order and the execution of justice.
- But, besides that this interest is only more immediate in the execution
- of justice among their subjects; besides this, I say, we may often
- expect, from the irregularity of human nature, that they will neglect
- even this immediate interest, and be transported by their passions
- into all the excesses of cruelty and ambition. Our general knowledge
- of human nature, our observation of the past history of mankind,
- our experience of present times; all these causes must induce us to
- open the door of exceptions, and must make us conclude, that we may
- resist the more violent effects of supreme power without any crime or
- injustice.
- Accordingly we may observe, that this is both the general practice and
- principle of mankind, and that no nation that could find any remedy,
- ever yet suffered the cruel ravages of a tyrant, or were blamed for
- their resistance. Those who took up arms against Dionysius or Nero, or
- Philip the Second, have the favour of every reader in the perusal of
- their history; and nothing but the most violent perversion of common
- sense can ever lead us to condemn them. 'Tis certain, therefore, that
- in all our notions of morals, we never entertain such an absurdity
- as that of passive obedience, but make allowances for resistance in
- the more flagrant instances of tyranny and oppression. The general
- opinion of mankind has some authority in all cases; but in this of
- morals 'tis perfectly infallible. Nor is it less infallible, because
- men cannot distinctly explain the principles on which it is founded.
- Few persons can carry on this train of reasoning: 'Government is a mere
- human invention for the interest of society. Where the tyranny of the
- governor removes this interest, it also removes the natural obligation
- to obedience. The moral obligation is founded on the natural, and
- therefore must cease where _that_ ceases; especially where the subject
- is such as makes us foresee very many occasions wherein the natural
- obligation may cease, and causes us to form a kind of general rule for
- the regulation of our conduct in such occurrences.' But though this
- train of reasoning be too subtile for the vulgar, 'tis certain that
- all men have an implicit notion of it, and are sensible that they owe
- obedience to government merely on account of the public interest; and,
- at the same time, that human nature is so subject to frailties and
- passions, as may easily pervert this institution, and change their
- governors into tyrants and public enemies. If the sense of public
- interest were not our original motive to obedience, I would fain ask,
- what other principle is there in human nature capable of subduing
- the natural ambition of men, and forcing them to such a submission?
- Imitation and custom are not sufficient. For the question still recurs,
- what motive first produces those instances of submission which we
- imitate, and that train of actions which produces the custom? There
- evidently is no other principle than public interest; and if interest
- first produces obedience to government, the obligation to obedience
- must cease whenever the interest ceases in any great degree, and in a
- considerable number of instances.
- SECTION X.
- OF THE OBJECTS OF ALLEGIANCE.
- But though, on some occasions, it may be justifiable, both in sound
- politics and morality, to resist supreme power, 'tis certain that, in
- the ordinary course of human affairs, nothing can be more pernicious
- and criminal; and that, besides the convulsions which always attend
- revolutions, such a practice tends directly to the subversion of
- all government, and the causing an universal anarchy and confusion
- among mankind. As numerous and civilized societies cannot subsist
- without government, so government is entirely useless without an exact
- obedience. We ought always to weigh the advantages which we reap from
- authority, against the disadvantages: and by this means we shall become
- more scrupulous of putting in practice the doctrine of resistance. The
- common rule requires submission; and 'tis only in cases of grievous
- tyranny and oppression, that the exception can take place.
- Since, then, such a blind submission is commonly due to magistracy,
- the next question is, _to whom it is due, and whom we are to regard
- as our lawful magistrates_? In order to answer this question, let us
- recollect what we have already established concerning the origin of
- government and political society. When men have once experienced the
- impossibility of preserving any steady order in society, while every
- one is his own master, and violates or observes the laws of interest,
- according to his present interest or pleasure, they naturally run into
- the invention of government, and put it out of their own power, as far
- as possible, to transgress the laws of society. Government, therefore,
- arises from the voluntary convention of men; and 'tis evident, that the
- same convention which establishes government, will also determine the
- persons who are to govern, and will remove all doubt and ambiguity in
- this particular. And the voluntary consent of men must here have the
- greater efficacy, that the authority of the magistrate does _at first_
- stand upon the foundation of a promise of the subjects, by which they
- bind themselves to obedience, as in every other contract or engagement.
- The same promise, then, which binds them to obedience, ties them down
- to a particular person, and makes him the object of their allegiance.
- But when government has been established on this footing for some
- considerable time, and the separate interest which we have in
- submission has produced a separate sentiment of morality, the case
- is entirely altered, and a promise is no longer able to determine
- the particular magistrate; since it is no longer considered as the
- foundation of government. We naturally suppose ourselves born to
- submission; and imagine that such particular persons have a right to
- command, as we on our part are bound to obey. These notions of right
- and obligation are derived from nothing but the _advantage_ we reap
- from government, which gives us a repugnance to practise resistance
- ourselves, and makes us displeased with any instance of it in others.
- But here 'tis remarkable, that in this new state of affairs, the
- original sanction of government, which is _interest_, is not admitted
- to determine the persons whom we are to obey, as the original sanction
- did at first, when affairs were on the footing of a _promise_. A
- _promise_ fixes and determines the persons, without any uncertainty:
- but 'tis evident, that if men were to regulate their conduct in this
- particular, by the view of a peculiar _interest_, either public or
- private, they would involve themselves in endless confusion, and
- would render all government, in a great measure, ineffectual. The
- private interest of every one is different; and, though the public
- interest in itself be always one and the same, yet it becomes the
- source of as great dissensions, by reason of the different opinions
- of particular persons concerning it. The same interest, therefore,
- which causes us to submit to magistracy, makes us renounce itself in
- the choice of our magistrates, and binds us down to a certain form of
- government, and to particular persons, without allowing us to aspire
- to the utmost perfection in either. The case is here the same as
- in that law of nature concerning the stability of possession. 'Tis
- highly advantageous, and even absolutely necessary to society, that
- possession should be stable; and this leads us to the establishment of
- such a rule: but we find, that were we to follow the same advantage,
- in assigning particular possessions to particular persons, we should
- disappoint our end, and perpetuate the confusion which that rule is
- intended to prevent. We must therefore proceed by general rules, and
- regulate ourselves by general interests, in modifying the law of
- nature concerning the stability of possession. Nor need we fear, that
- our attachment to this law will diminish upon account of the seeming
- frivolousness of those interests by which it is determined. The
- impulse of the mind is derived from a very strong interest; and those
- other more minute interests serve only to direct the motion, without
- adding any thing to it, or diminishing from it. 'Tis the same case
- with government. Nothing is more advantageous to society than such
- an invention; and this interest is sufficient to make us embrace it
- with ardour and alacrity; though we are obliged afterwards to regulate
- and direct our devotion to government by several considerations which
- are not of the same importance, and to choose our magistrates without
- having in view any particular advantage from the choice.
- The _first_ of those principles I shall take notice of, as a foundation
- of the right of magistracy, is that which gives authority to all the
- most established governments of the world, without exception: I mean,
- _long possession_ in any one form of government, or succession of
- princes. 'Tis certain, that if we remount to the first origin of every
- nation, we shall find, that there scarce is any race of kings, or form
- of a commonwealth, that is not primarily founded on usurpation and
- rebellion, and whose title is not at first worse than doubtful and
- uncertain. Time alone gives solidity to their right; and, operating
- gradually on the minds of men, reconciles them to any authority, and
- makes it seem just and reasonable. Nothing causes any sentiment to have
- a greater influence upon us than custom, or turns our imagination more
- strongly to any object. When we have been long accustomed to obey any
- set of men, that general instinct or tendency which we have to suppose
- a moral obligation attending loyalty, takes easily this direction, and
- chooses that set of men for its objects. 'Tis interest which gives the
- general instinct; but 'tis custom which gives the particular direction.
- And here 'tis observable, that the same length of time has a different
- influence on our sentiments of morality, according to its different
- influence on the mind. We naturally judge of every thing by comparison;
- and since, in considering the fate of kingdoms and republics, we
- embrace a long extent of time, a small duration has not, in this
- case, a like influence on our sentiments, as when we consider any
- other object. One thinks he acquires a right to a horse, or a suit
- of clothes, in a very short time; but a century is scarce sufficient
- to establish any new government, or remove all scruples in the minds
- of the subjects concerning it. Add to this, that a shorter period of
- time will suffice to give a prince a title to any additional power
- he may usurp, than will serve to fix his right, where the whole
- is an usurpation. The kings of France have not been possessed of
- absolute power for above two reigns; and yet nothing will appear
- more extravagant to Frenchmen than to talk of their liberties. If we
- consider what has been said concerning _accession_, we shall easily
- account for this phenomenon.
- When there is no form of government established by _long_ possession,
- the _present_ possession is sufficient to supply its place, and may
- be regarded as the _second_ source of all public authority. Right
- to authority is nothing but the constant possession of authority,
- maintained by the laws of society and the interests of mankind; and
- nothing can be more natural than to join this constant possession to
- the present one, according to the principles above mentioned. If the
- same principles did not take place with regard to the property of
- private persons, 'twas because these principles were counterbalanced
- by very strong considerations of interest; when we observed, that all
- restitution would by that means be prevented, and every violence be
- authorized and protected. And, though the same motives may seem to
- have force with regard to public authority, yet they are opposed by a
- contrary interest; which consists in the preservation of peace, and the
- avoiding of all changes, which, however they may be easily produced in
- private affairs, are unavoidably attended with bloodshed and confusion
- where the public is interested.
- Any one who, finding the impossibility of accounting for the right of
- the present possessor, by any received system of ethics, should resolve
- to deny absolutely that right, and assert that it is not authorized
- by morality, would be justly thought to maintain a very extravagant
- paradox, and to shock the common sense and judgment of mankind. No
- maxim is more conformable, both to prudence and morals, than to
- submit quietly to the government which we find established in the
- country where we happen to live, without inquiring too curiously into
- its origin and first establishment. Few governments will bear being
- examined so rigorously. How many kingdoms are there at present in the
- world, and how many more do we find in history, whose governors have no
- better foundation for their authority than that of present possession!
- To confine ourselves to the Roman and Grecian empire; is it not
- evident, that the long succession of emperors, from the dissolution
- of the Roman liberty, to the final extinction of that empire by the
- Turks, could not so much as pretend to any other title to the empire?
- The election of the senate was a mere form, which always followed the
- choice of the legions; and these were almost always divided in the
- different provinces, and nothing but the sword was able to terminate
- the difference. 'Twas by the sword, therefore, that every emperor
- acquired, as well as defended, his right; and we must either say, that
- all the known world, for so many ages, had no government, and owed no
- allegiance to any one, or must allow, that the right of the stronger,
- in public affairs, is to be received as legitimate, and authorized by
- morality, when not opposed by any other title.
- The right of _conquest_ may be considered as a _third_ source of the
- title of sovereigns. This right resembles very much that of present
- possession, but has rather a superior force, being seconded by the
- notions of glory and honour which we ascribe to _conquerors_, instead
- of the sentiments of hatred and detestation which attend _usurpers_.
- Men naturally favour those they love; and therefore are more apt to
- ascribe a right to successful violence, betwixt one sovereign and
- another, than to the successful rebellion of a subject against his
- sovereign.[11]
- When neither long possession, nor present possession, nor conquest take
- place, as when the first sovereign who founded any monarchy dies; in
- that case, the right of _succession_ naturally prevails in their stead,
- and men are commonly induced to place the son of their late monarch
- on the throne, and suppose him to inherit his father's authority. The
- presumed consent of the father, the imitation of the succession to
- private families, the interest which the state has in choosing the
- person who is most powerful and has the most numerous followers; all
- these reasons lead men to prefer the son of their late monarch to any
- other person.[12]
- These reasons have some weight; but I am persuaded, that, to one who
- considers impartially of the matter, 'twill appear that there concur
- some principles of the imagination along with those views of interest.
- The royal authority seems to be connected with the young prince even in
- his father's lifetime, by the natural transition of the thought, and
- still more after his death; so that nothing is more natural than to
- complete this union by a new relation, and by putting him actually in
- possession of what seems so naturally to belong to him.
- To confirm this, we may weigh the following phenomena, which are
- pretty curious in their kind. In elective monarchies, the right of
- succession has no place by the laws and settled custom; and yet its
- influence is so natural, that 'tis impossible entirely to exclude it
- from the imagination, and render the subjects indifferent to the son
- of their deceased monarch. Hence, in some governments of this kind,
- the choice commonly falls on one or other of the royal family; and
- in some governments they are all excluded. Those contrary phenomena
- proceed from the same principle. Where the royal family is excluded,
- 'tis from a refinement in politics, which makes people sensible of
- their propensity to choose a sovereign in that family, and gives them
- a jealousy of their liberty, lest their new monarch, aided by this
- propensity, should establish his family, and destroy the freedom of
- elections for the future.
- The history of Artaxerxes and the younger Cyrus, may furnish us with
- some reflections to the same purpose. Cyrus pretended a right to the
- throne above his elder brother, because he was born after his father's
- accession. I do not pretend that this reason was valid. I would only
- infer from it, that he would never have made use of such a pretext,
- were it not for the qualities of the imagination above-mentioned, by
- which we are naturally inclined to unite by a new relation whatever
- objects we find already united. Artaxerxes had an advantage above his
- brother, as being the eldest son, and the first in succession; but
- Cyrus was more closely related to the royal authority, as being begot
- after his father was invested with it.
- Should it here be pretended, that the view of convenience may be
- the source of all the right of succession, and that men gladly take
- advantage of any rule by which they can fix the successor of their
- late sovereign, and prevent that anarchy and confusion which attends
- all new elections; to this I would answer, that I readily allow that
- this motive may contribute something to the effect; but at the same
- time I assert, that, without another principle, 'tis impossible such
- a motive should take place. The interest of a nation requires that the
- succession to the crown should be fixed one way or other; but 'tis the
- same thing to its interest in what way it be fixed; so that if the
- relation of blood had not an effect independent of public interest, it
- would never have been regarded without a positive law; and 'twould have
- been impossible that so many positive laws of different nations could
- ever have concurred precisely in the same views and intentions.
- This leads us to consider the _fifth_ source of authority, viz.
- _positive laws_, when the legislature establishes a certain form
- of government and succession of princes. At first sight, it may be
- thought that this must resolve into some of the preceding titles of
- authority. The legislative power, whence the positive law is derived,
- must either be established by original contract, long possession,
- present possession, conquest, or succession; and consequently the
- positive law must derive its force from some of those principles. But
- here 'tis remarkable, that though a positive law can only derive its
- force from these principles, yet it acquires not all the force of the
- principle from whence it is derived, but loses considerably in the
- transition, as it is natural to imagine. For instance, a government is
- established for many centuries on a certain system of laws, forms, and
- methods of succession. The legislative power, established by this long
- succession, changes, all on a sudden, the whole system of government,
- and introduces a new constitution in its stead. I believe few of the
- subjects will think themselves bound to comply with this alteration,
- unless it have an evident tendency to the public good, but will think
- themselves still at liberty to return to the ancient government. Hence
- the notion of _fundamental_ laws, which are supposed to be unalterable
- by the will of the sovereign; and of this nature the Salic law is
- understood to be in France. How far these fundamental laws extend, is
- not determined in any government, nor is it possible it ever should.
- There is such an insensible gradation from the most material laws to
- the most trivial, and from the most ancient laws to the most modern,
- that 'twill be impossible to set bounds to the legislative power, and
- determine how far it may innovate in the principles of government. That
- is the work more of imagination and passion than of reason.
- Whoever considers the history of the several nations of the world,
- their revolutions, conquests, increase and diminution, the manner in
- which their particular governments are established, and the successive
- right transmitted from one person to another, will soon learn to treat
- very lightly all disputes concerning the rights of princes, and will be
- convinced that a strict adherence to any general rules, and the rigid
- loyalty to particular persons and families, on which some people set
- so high a value, are virtues that hold less of reason than of bigotry
- and superstition. In this particular, the study of history confirms the
- reasonings of true philosophy, which, showing us the original qualities
- of human nature, teaches us to regard the controversies in politics as
- incapable of any decision in most cases, and as entirely subordinate
- to the interests of peace and liberty. Where the public good does
- not evidently demand a change, 'tis certain that the concurrence
- of all those titles, _original contract, long possession, present
- possession, succession_, and _positive laws_, forms the strongest title
- to sovereignty, and is justly regarded as sacred and inviolable. But
- when these titles are mingled and opposed in different degrees, they
- often occasion perplexity, and are less capable of solution from the
- arguments of lawyers and philosophers, than from the swords of the
- soldiery. Who shall tell me, for instance, whether Germanicus or Drusus
- ought to have succeeded Tiberius, had he died while they were both
- alive, without naming any of them for his successor? Ought the right
- of adoption to be received as equivalent to that of blood, in a nation
- where it had the same effect in private families, and had already,
- in two instances, taken place in the public? Ought Germanicus to be
- esteemed the eldest son, because he was born before Drusus; or the
- younger, because he was adopted after the birth of his brother? Ought
- the right of the elder to be regarded in a nation, where the eldest
- brother had no advantage in the succession to private families? Ought
- the Roman empire at that time to be esteemed hereditary, because of two
- examples; or ought it, even so early, to be regarded as belonging to
- the stronger, or the present possessor, as being founded on so recent
- an usurpation? Upon whatever principles we may pretend to answer these
- and such like questions, I am afraid we shall never be able to satisfy
- an impartial inquirer, who adopts no party in political controversies,
- and will be satisfied with nothing but sound reason and philosophy.
- But here an English reader will be apt to inquire concerning that
- famous _revolution_ which has had such a happy influence on our
- constitution, and has been attended with such mighty consequences.
- We have already remarked, that, in the case of enormous tyranny and
- oppression, 'tis lawful to take arms even against supreme power; and
- that, as government is a mere human invention, for mutual advantage
- and security, it no longer imposes any obligation, either natural or
- moral, when once it ceases to have that tendency. But though this
- _general_ principle be authorized by common sense, and the practice
- of all ages, 'tis certainly impossible for the laws, or even for
- philosophy, to establish any _particular_ rules by which we may
- know when resistance is lawful, and decide all controversies which
- may arise on that subject. This may not only happen with regard to
- supreme power, but 'tis possible, even in some constitutions, where
- the legislative authority is not lodged in one person, that there
- may be a magistrate so eminent and powerful as to oblige the laws to
- keep silence in this particular. Nor would this silence be an effect
- only of their _respect_, but also of their _prudence_; since 'tis
- certain, that, in the vast variety of circumstances which occur in
- all governments, an exercise of power, in so great a magistrate, may
- at one time be beneficial to the public, which at another time would
- be pernicious and tyrannical. But notwithstanding this silence of
- the laws in limited monarchies, 'tis certain that the people still
- retain the right of resistance; since 'tis impossible, even in the
- most despotic governments, to deprive them of it. The same necessity
- of self-preservation, and the same motive of public good, give them
- the same liberty in the one case as in the other. And we may farther
- observe, that in such mixed governments, the cases wherein resistance
- is lawful must occur much oftener, and greater indulgence be given to
- the subjects to defend themselves by force of arms, than in arbitrary
- governments. Not only where the chief magistrate enters into measures
- in themselves extremely pernicious to the public, but even when he
- would encroach on the other parts of the constitution, and extend his
- power beyond the legal bounds, it is allowable to resist and dethrone
- him; though such resistance and violence may, in the general tenor of
- the laws, be deemed unlawful and rebellious. For, besides that nothing
- is more essential to public interest than the preservation of public
- liberty, 'tis evident, that if such a mixed government be once supposed
- to be established, every part or member of the constitution must have
- a right of self-defence, and of maintaining its ancient bounds against
- the encroachment of every other authority. As matter would have been
- created in vain, were it deprived of a power of resistance, without
- which no part of it could preserve a distinct existence, and the whole
- might be crowded up into a single point; so 'tis a gross absurdity to
- suppose, in any government, a right without a remedy, or allow that the
- supreme power is shared with the people, without allowing that 'tis
- lawful for them to defend their share against every invader. Those,
- therefore, who would seem to respect our free government, and yet deny
- the right of resistance, have renounced all pretensions to common
- sense, and do not merit a serious answer.
- It does not belong to my present purpose to show, that these general
- principles are applicable to the late _revolution_; and that all the
- rights and privileges which ought to be sacred to a free nation, were
- at that time threatened with the utmost danger. I am better pleased to
- leave this controverted subject, if it really admits of controversy,
- and to indulge myself in some philosophical reflections which naturally
- arise from that important event.
- _First_, We may observe, that should the _lords_ and _commons_ in our
- constitution, without any reason from public interest, either depose
- the king in being, or, after his death, exclude the prince, who, by
- laws and settled custom, ought to succeed, no one would esteem their
- proceedings legal, or think themselves bound to comply with them.
- But should the king, by his unjust practices, or his attempts for a
- tyrannical and despotic power, justly forfeit his legal, it then not
- only becomes morally lawful and suitable to the nature of political
- society to dethrone him; but, what is more, we are apt likewise to
- think, that the remaining members of the constitution acquire a right
- of excluding his next heir, and of choosing whom they please for his
- successor. This is founded on a very singular quality of our thought
- and imagination. When a king forfeits his authority, his heir ought
- naturally to remain in the same situation as if the king were removed
- by death; unless by mixing himself in the tyranny, he forfeit it for
- himself. But though this may seem reasonable, we easily comply with the
- contrary opinion. The deposition of a king, in such a government as
- ours, is certainly an act beyond all common authority; and an illegal
- assuming a power for public good, which, in the ordinary course of
- government, can belong to no member of the constitution. When the
- public good is so great and so evident as to justify the action, the
- commendable use of this license causes us naturally to attribute to the
- _parliament_ a right of using farther licenses; and the ancient bounds
- of the laws being once transgressed with approbation, we are not apt
- to be so strict in confining ourselves precisely within their limits.
- The mind naturally runs on with any train of action which it has begun;
- nor do we commonly make any scruple concerning our duty, after the
- first action of any kind which we perform. Thus at the _revolution_,
- no one who thought the deposition of the father justifiable, esteemed
- themselves to be confined to his infant son; though, had that unhappy
- monarch died innocent at that time, and had his son, by any accident,
- been conveyed beyond seas, there is no doubt but a regency would have
- been appointed till he should come to age, and could be restored to
- his dominions. As the slightest properties of the imagination have
- an effect on the judgments of the people, it shows the wisdom of the
- laws and of the parliament to take advantage of such properties, and
- to choose the magistrates either in or out of a line, according as the
- vulgar will most naturally attribute authority and right to them.
- _Secondly_, Though the accession of the Prince of Orange to the throne,
- might at first give occasion to many disputes, and his title be
- contested, it ought not now to appear doubtful, but must have acquired
- a sufficient authority from those three princes who have succeeded
- him upon the same title. Nothing is more usual, though nothing may,
- at first sight, appear more unreasonable, than this way of thinking.
- Princes often _seem_ to acquire a right from their successors, as well
- as from their ancestors; and a king who, during his lifetime, might
- justly be deemed an usurper, will be regarded by posterity as a lawful
- prince, because he has had the good fortune to settle his family on
- the throne, and entirely change the ancient form of government. Julius
- Cæsar is regarded as the first Roman emperor; while Sylla and Marius,
- whose titles were really the same as his, are treated as tyrants and
- usurpers. Time and custom give authority to all forms of government,
- and all successions of princes; and that power, which at first was
- founded only on injustice and violence, becomes in time legal and
- obligatory. Nor does the mind rest there; but, returning back upon
- its footsteps, transfers to their predecessors and ancestors that
- right which it naturally ascribes to the posterity, as being related
- together, and united in the imagination. The present King of France
- makes Hugh Capet a more lawful prince than Cromwell; as the established
- liberty of the Dutch is no inconsiderable apology for their obstinate
- resistance to Philip the Second.
- [10] This proposition must hold strictly true with regard to every
- quality that is determined merely by sentiment. In what sense we can
- talk either of a _right_ or a _wrong_ taste in morals, eloquence, or
- beauty, shall be considered afterwards. In the mean time it may be
- observed, that there is such an uniformity in the _general_ sentiments
- of mankind, as to render such questions of but small importance.
- [11] It is not here asserted, that _present possession_ or _conquest_
- are sufficient to give a title against _long possession_ and _positive
- laws_: but only that they have some force, and will be able to cast
- the balance where the titles are otherwise equal, and will even be
- sufficient _sometimes_ to sanctify the weaker title. What degree of
- force they have is difficult to determine. I believe all moderate men
- will allow, that they have great force in all disputes concerning the
- rights of princes.
- [12] To prevent mistakes I must observe, that this case of succession
- is not the same with that of hereditary monarchies, where custom has
- fixed the right of succession. These depend upon the principle of long
- possession above explained.
- SECTION XI.
- OF THE LAWS OF NATIONS.
- When civil government has been established over the greatest part of
- mankind, and different societies have been formed contiguous to each
- other, there arises a new set of duties among the neighbouring states,
- suitable to the nature of that commerce which they carry on with each
- other. Political writers tell us, that in every kind of intercourse
- a body politic is to be considered as one person; and indeed, this
- assertion is so far just, that different nations, as well as private
- persons, require mutual assistance; at the same time that their
- selfishness and ambition are perpetual sources of war and discord. But
- though nations in this particular resemble individuals, yet as they are
- very different in other respects, no wonder they regulate themselves by
- different maxims, and give rise to a new set of rules, which we call
- _the laws of nations_. Under this head we may comprise the sacredness
- of the persons of ambassadors, the declaration of war, the abstaining
- from poisoned arms, with other duties of that kind, which are evidently
- calculated for the commerce that is peculiar to different societies.
- But though these rules be superadded to the laws of nature, the former
- do not entirely abolish the latter; and one may safely affirm, that the
- three fundamental rules of justice, the stability of possession, its
- transference by consent, and the performance of promises, are duties
- of princes as well as of subjects. The same interest produces the same
- effect in both cases. Where possession has no stability, there must
- be perpetual war. Where property is not transferred by consent, there
- can be no commerce. Where promises are not observed, there can be no
- leagues nor alliances. The advantages, therefore, of peace, commerce,
- and mutual succour, make us extend to different kingdoms the same
- notions of justice which take place among individuals.
- There is a maxim very current in the world, which few politicians are
- willing to avow, but which has been authorized by the practice of
- all ages, _that there is a system of morals calculated for princes,
- much more free than that which ought to govern private persons_.
- 'Tis evident this is not to be understood of the lesser _extent_ of
- public duties and obligations; nor will any one be so extravagant as
- to assert, that the most solemn treaties ought to have no force among
- princes. For as princes do actually form treaties among themselves,
- they must propose some advantage from the execution of them; and the
- prospect of such advantage for the future must engage them to perform
- their part, and must establish that law of nature. The meaning,
- therefore, of this political maxim is, that though the morality of
- princes has the same _extent_, yet it has not the same _force_ as
- that of private persons, and may lawfully be transgressed from a
- more trivial motive. However shocking such a proposition may appear
- to certain philosophers, 'twill be easy to defend it upon those
- principles, by which we have accounted for the origin of justice and
- equity.
- When men have found by experience that 'tis impossible to subsist
- without society, and that 'tis impossible to maintain society, while
- they give free course to their appetites; so urgent an interest
- quickly restrains their actions, and imposes an obligation to observe
- those rules which we call _the laws of justice_. This obligation of
- interest rests not here; but, by the necessary course of the passions
- and sentiments, gives rise to the moral obligation of duty; while we
- approve of such actions as tend to the peace of society, and disapprove
- of such as tend to its disturbance. The same _natural_ obligation of
- interest takes place among independent kingdoms, and gives rise to
- the same _morality_; so that no one of ever so corrupt morals will
- approve of a prince, who voluntarily, and of his own accord, breaks his
- word, or violates any treaty. But here we may observe, that though the
- intercourse of different states be advantageous, and even sometimes
- necessary, yet it is not so necessary nor advantageous as that among
- individuals, without which 'tis utterly impossible for human nature
- ever to subsist. Since, therefore, the _natural_ obligation to justice,
- among different states, is not so strong as among individuals, the
- _moral_ obligation which arises from it must partake of its weakness;
- and we must necessarily give a greater indulgence to a prince or
- minister who deceives another, than to a private gentleman who breaks
- his word of honour.
- Should it be asked, _what proportion these two species of morality
- bear to each other_? I would answer, that this is a question to which
- we can never give any precise answer; nor is it possible to reduce to
- numbers the proportion, which we ought to fix betwixt them. One may
- safely affirm, that this proportion finds itself without any art or
- study of men; as we may observe on many other occasions. The practice
- of the world goes farther in teaching us the degrees of our duty,
- than the most subtile philosophy which was ever yet invented. And
- this may serve as a convincing proof, that all men have an implicit
- notion of the foundation of those moral rules concerning natural and
- civil justice, and are sensible that they arise merely from human
- conventions, and from the interest which we have in the preservation
- of peace and order. For otherwise the diminution of the interest would
- never produce a relaxation of the morality, and reconcile us more
- easily to any transgression of justice among princes and republics,
- than in the private commerce of one subject with another.
- SECTION XII.
- OF CHASTITY AND MODESTY.
- If any difficulty attend this system concerning the laws of nature and
- nations, 'twill be with regard to the universal approbation or blame
- which follows their observance or transgression, and which some may not
- think sufficiently explained from the general interests of society.
- To remove, as far as possible, all scruples of this kind, I shall
- here consider another set of duties, viz. the _modesty_ and _chastity_
- which belong to the fair sex: and I doubt not but these virtues will be
- found to be still more conspicuous instances of the operation of those
- principles which I have insisted on.
- There are some philosophers who attack the female virtues with great
- vehemence, and fancy they have gone very far in detecting popular
- errors, when they can show, that there is no foundation in nature for
- all that exterior modesty which we require in the expressions, and
- dress, and behaviour of the fair sex. I believe I may spare myself the
- trouble of insisting on so obvious a subject, and may proceed, without
- farther preparation, to examine after what manner such notions arise
- from education, from the voluntary conventions of men, and from the
- interest of society.
- Whoever considers the length and feebleness of human infancy, with
- the concern which both sexes naturally have for their offspring, will
- easily perceive, that there must be an union of male and female for the
- education of the young, and that this union must be of considerable
- duration. But, in order to induce the men to impose on themselves this
- restraint, and undergo cheerfully all the fatigues and expenses to
- which it subjects them, they must believe that their children are their
- own, and that their natural instinct is not directed to a wrong object,
- when they give a loose to love and tenderness. Now, if we examine the
- structure of the human body, we shall find, that this security is very
- difficult to be attained on our part; and that since, in the copulation
- of the sexes, the principle of generation goes from the man to the
- woman, an error may easily take place on the side of the former, though
- it be utterly impossible with regard to the latter. From this trivial
- and anatomical observation is derived that vast difference betwixt the
- education and duties of the two sexes.
- Were a philosopher to examine the matter a _priori_, he would reason
- after the following manner. Men are induced to labour for the
- maintenance and education of their children, by the persuasion that
- they are really their own; and therefore 'tis reasonable, and even
- necessary, to give them some security in this particular. This security
- cannot consist entirely in the imposing of severe punishments on any
- transgressions of conjugal fidelity on the part of the wife; since
- these public punishments cannot be inflicted without legal proof, which
- 'tis difficult to meet with in this subject. What restraint, therefore,
- shall we impose on women, in order to counterbalance so strong a
- temptation as they have to infidelity? There seems to be no restraint
- possible, but in the punishment of bad fame or reputation; a punishment
- which has a mighty influence on the human mind, and at the same time
- is inflicted by the world upon surmises and conjectures, and proofs
- that would never be received in any court of judicature. In order,
- therefore, to impose a due restraint on the female sex, we must attach
- a peculiar degree of shame to their infidelity, above what arises
- merely from its injustice, and must bestow proportionable praises on
- their chastity.
- But though this be a very strong motive to fidelity, our philosopher
- would quickly discover that it would not alone be sufficient to that
- purpose. All human creatures, especially of the female sex, are apt
- to overlook remote motives in favour of any present temptation: the
- temptation is here the strongest imaginable; its approaches are
- insensible and seducing; and a woman easily finds, or flatters
- herself she shall find, certain means of securing her reputation, and
- preventing all the pernicious consequences of her pleasures. 'Tis
- necessary, therefore, that, beside the infamy attending such licenses,
- there should be some preceding backwardness or dread, which may prevent
- their first approaches, and may give the female sex a repugnance to
- all expressions, and postures, and liberties, that have an immediate
- relation to that enjoyment.
- Such would be the reasonings of our speculative philosopher; but I am
- persuaded that, if he had not a perfect knowledge of human nature, he
- would be apt to regard them as mere chimerical speculations, and would
- consider the infamy attending infidelity, and backwardness to all its
- approaches, as principles that were rather to be wished than hoped
- for in the world. For what means, would he say, of persuading mankind
- that the transgressions of conjugal duty are more infamous than any
- other kind of injustice, when 'tis evident they are more excusable,
- upon account of the greatness of the temptation? And what possibility
- of giving a backwardness to the approaches of a pleasure to which
- nature has inspired so strong a propensity, and a propensity that 'tis
- absolutely necessary in the end to comply with, for the support of the
- species?
- But speculative reasonings, which cost so much pains to philosophers,
- are often formed by the world naturally, and without reflection; as
- difficulties which seem unsurmountable in theory, are easily got over
- in practice. Those who have an interest in the fidelity of women,
- naturally disapprove of their infidelity, and all the approaches to it.
- Those who have no interest are carried along with the stream. Education
- takes possession of the ductile minds of the fair sex in their
- infancy. And when a general rule of this kind is once established,
- men are apt to extend it beyond those principles from which it first
- arose. Thus, bachelors, however debauched, cannot choose but be shocked
- with any instance of lewdness or impudence in woman. And though all
- these maxims have a plain reference to generation, yet women past
- child-bearing have no more privilege in this respect than those who
- are in the flower of their youth and beauty. Men have undoubtedly an
- implicit notion, that all those ideas of modesty and decency have a
- regard to generation; since they impose not the same laws, _with the
- same force_, on the male sex, where that reason takes not place. The
- exception is there obvious and extensive, and founded on a remarkable
- difference, which produces a clear separation and disjunction of ideas.
- But as the case is not the same with regard to the different ages of
- women, for this reason, though men know that these notions are founded
- on the public interest, yet the general rule carries us beyond the
- original principle, and makes us extend the notions of modesty over the
- whole sex, from their earliest infancy to their extremest old age and
- infirmity.
- Courage, which is the point of honour among men, derives its merit in a
- great measure from artifice, as well as the chastity of women; though
- it has also some foundation in nature, as we shall see afterwards.
- As to the obligations which the male sex lie under with regard to
- chastity, we may observe that, according to the general notions of
- the world, they bear nearly the same proportion to the obligations of
- women, as the obligations of the law of nations do to those of the
- law of nature. 'Tis contrary to the interest of civil society, that
- men should have an _entire_ liberty of indulging their appetites
- in venereal enjoyment; but as this interest is weaker than in the
- case of the female sex, the moral obligation arising from it must be
- proportionably weaker. And to prove this we need only appeal to the
- practice and sentiments of all nations and ages.
- PART III.
- OF THE OTHER VIRTUES AND VICES.
- SECTION I.
- OF THE ORIGIN OF THE NATURAL VIRTUES AND VICES.
- We come now to the examination of such virtues and vices as are
- entirely natural, and have no dependence on the artifice and
- contrivance of men. The examination of these will conclude this system
- of morals.
- The chief spring or actuating principle of the human mind is pleasure
- or pain; and when these sensations are removed, both from our thought
- and feeling, we are in a great measure incapable of passion or action,
- of desire or volition. The most immediate effects of pleasure and pain
- are the propense and averse motions of the mind; which are diversified
- into volition, into desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear,
- according as the pleasure or pain changes its situation, and becomes
- probable or improbable, certain or uncertain, or is considered as out
- of our power for the present moment. But when, along with this, the
- objects that cause pleasure or pain acquire a relation to ourselves or
- others, they still continue to excite desire and aversion, grief and
- joy; but cause, at the same time, the indirect passions of pride or
- humility, love or hatred, which in this case have a double relation of
- impressions and ideas to the pain or pleasure.
- We have already observed, that moral distinctions depend entirely on
- certain peculiar sentiments of pain and pleasure, and that whatever
- mental quality in ourselves or others gives us a satisfaction, by the
- survey or reflection, is of course virtuous; as every thing of this
- nature that gives uneasiness is vicious. Now, since every quality
- in ourselves or others which gives pleasure, always causes pride
- or love, as every one that produces uneasiness excites humility or
- hatred, it follows, that these two particulars are to be considered
- as equivalent, with regard to our mental qualities, _virtue_ and the
- power of producing love or pride, _vice_ and the power of producing
- humility or hatred. In every case, therefore, we must judge of the one
- by the other, and may pronounce any _quality_ of the mind virtuous
- which causes love or pride, and any one vicious which causes hatred or
- humility.
- If any _action_ be either virtuous or vicious, 'tis only as a sign
- of some quality or character. It must depend upon durable principles
- of the mind, which extend over the whole conduct, and enter into
- the personal character. Actions themselves, not proceeding from any
- constant principle, have no influence on love or hatred, pride or
- humility; and consequently are never considered in morality.
- This reflection is self-evident, and deserves to be attended to, as
- being of the utmost importance in the present subject. We are never
- to consider any single action in our inquiries concerning the origin
- of morals, but only the quality or character from which the action
- proceeded. These alone are _durable_ enough to affect our sentiments
- concerning the person. Actions are indeed better indications of a
- character than words, or even wishes and sentiments; but 'tis only so
- far as they are such indications, that they are attended with love or
- hatred, praise or blame.
- To discover the true origin of morals, and of that love or hatred which
- arises from mental qualities, we must take the matter pretty deep, and
- compare some principles which have been already examined and explained.
- We may begin with considering anew the nature and force of _sympathy_.
- The minds of all men are similar in their feelings and operations; nor
- can any one be actuated by any affection of which all others are not
- in some degree susceptible. As in strings equally wound up, the motion
- of one communicates itself to the rest, so all the affections readily
- pass from one person to another, and beget correspondent movements
- in every human creature. When I see the _effects_ of passion in the
- voice and gesture of any person, my mind immediately passes from these
- effects to their causes, and forms such a lively idea of the passion as
- is presently converted into the passion itself. In like manner, when I
- perceive the causes of any emotion, my mind is conveyed to the effects,
- and is actuated with a like emotion. Were I present at any of the more
- terrible operations of surgery, 'tis certain that, even before it
- begun, the preparation of the instruments, the laying of the bandages
- in order, the heating of the irons, with all the signs of anxiety and
- concern in the patient and assistants, would have a great effect upon
- my mind, and excite the strongest sentiments of pity and terror. No
- passion of another discovers itself immediately to the mind. We are
- only sensible of its causes or effects. From _these_ we infer the
- passion; and consequently _these_ give rise to our sympathy.
- Our sense of beauty depends very much on this principle; and where
- any object has a tendency to produce pleasure in its possessor, it is
- always regarded as beautiful; as every object that has a tendency to
- produce pain, is disagreeable and deformed. Thus, the conveniency of a
- house, the fertility of a field, the strength of a horse, the capacity,
- security, and swift-sailing of a vessel, form the principal beauty of
- these several objects. Here the object, which is denominated beautiful,
- pleases only by its tendency to produce a certain effect. That effect
- is the pleasure or advantage of some other person. Now, the pleasure of
- a stranger for whom we have no friendship, pleases us only by sympathy.
- To this principle, therefore, is owing the beauty which we find in
- every thing that is useful. How considerable a part this is of beauty
- will easily appear upon reflection. Wherever an object has a tendency
- to produce pleasure in the possessor, or, in other words, is the proper
- _cause_ of pleasure, it is sure to please the spectator, by a delicate
- sympathy with the possessor. Most of the works of art are esteemed
- beautiful, in proportion to their fitness for the use of man; and even
- many of the productions of nature derive their beauty from that source.
- Handsome and beautiful, on most occasions, is not an absolute, but a
- relative quality, and pleases us by nothing but its tendency to produce
- an end that is agreeable.[1]
- The same principle produces, in many instances, our sentiments of
- morals, as well as those of beauty. No virtue is more esteemed than
- justice, and no vice more detested than injustice; nor are there
- any qualities which go farther to the fixing the character, either
- as amiable or odious. Now justice is a moral virtue, merely because
- it has that tendency to the good of mankind, and indeed is nothing
- but an artificial invention to that purpose. The same may be said of
- allegiance, of the laws of nations, of modesty, and of good manners.
- All these are mere human contrivances for the interest of society. And
- since there is a very strong sentiment of morals, which in all nations
- and all ages has attended them, we must allow that the reflecting on
- the tendency of characters and mental qualities is sufficient to give
- us the sentiments of approbation and blame. Now, as the means to an
- end can only be agreeable where the end is agreeable, and as the good
- of society, where our own interest is not concerned, or that of our
- friends, pleases only by sympathy, it follows, that sympathy is the
- source of the esteem which we pay to all the artificial virtues.
- Thus it appears, _that_ sympathy is a very powerful principle in
- human nature, _that_ it has a great influence on our taste of beauty,
- and _that_ it produces our sentiment of morals in all the artificial
- virtues. From thence we may presume, that it also gives rise to many
- of the other virtues, and that qualities acquire our approbation
- because of their tendency to the good of mankind. This presumption
- must become a certainty, when we find that most of those qualities
- which we _naturally_ approve of, have actually that tendency, and
- render a man a proper member of society; while the qualities which
- we _naturally_ disapprove of have a contrary tendency, and render
- any intercourse with the person dangerous or disagreeable. For having
- found, that such tendencies have force enough to produce the strongest
- sentiment of morals, we can never reasonably, in these cases, look for
- any other cause of approbation or blame; it being an inviolable maxim
- in philosophy, that where any particular cause is sufficient for an
- effect, we ought to rest satisfied with it, and ought not to multiply
- causes without necessity. We have happily attained experiments in the
- artificial virtues, where the tendency of qualities to the good of
- society is the _sole_ cause of our approbation, without any suspicion
- of the concurrence of another principle. From thence we learn the force
- of that principle. And where that principle may take place, and the
- quality approved of is really beneficial to society, a true philosopher
- will never require any other principle to account for the strongest
- approbation and esteem.
- That many of the natural virtues have this tendency to the good
- of society, no one can doubt of. Meekness, beneficence, charity,
- generosity, clemency, moderation, equity, bear the greatest figure
- among the moral qualities, and are commonly denominated the _social_
- virtues, to mark their tendency to the good of society. This goes so
- far, that some philosophers have represented all moral distinctions
- as the effect of artifice and education, when skilful politicians
- endeavoured to restrain the turbulent passions of men, and make them
- operate to the public good, by the notions of honour and shame. This
- system, however, is not consistent with experience. For, _first_,
- There are other virtues and vices beside those which have this
- tendency to the public advantage and loss. _Secondly_, Had not men a
- natural sentiment of approbation and blame, it could never be excited
- by politicians, nor would the words _laudable_ and _praiseworthy,
- blameable_ and _odious_, be any more intelligible than if they were
- a language perfectly unknown to us, as we have already observed.
- But though this system be erroneous, it may teach us that moral
- distinctions arise in a great measure from the tendency of qualities
- and characters to the interests of society, and that 'tis our concern
- for that interest which makes us approve or disapprove of them. Now,
- we have no such extensive concern for society, but from sympathy; and
- consequently 'tis that principle which takes us so far out of ourselves
- as to give us the same pleasure or uneasiness in the characters of
- others, as if they had a tendency to our own advantage or loss.
- The only difference betwixt the natural virtues and justice lies in
- this, that the good which results from the former arises from every
- single act, and is the object of some natural passion; whereas a
- single act of justice, considered in itself, may often be contrary
- to the public good; and 'tis only the concurrence of mankind, in a
- general scheme or system of action, which is advantageous. When I
- relieve persons in distress, my natural humanity is my motive; and so
- far as my succour extends, so far have I promoted the happiness of my
- fellow-creatures. But if we examine all the questions that come before
- any tribunal of justice, we shall find that, considering each case
- apart, it would as often be an instance of humanity to decide contrary
- to the laws of justice as conformable to them. Judges take from a poor
- man to give to a rich; they bestow on the dissolute the labour of the
- industrious; and put into the hands of the vicious the means of harming
- both themselves and others. The whole scheme, however, of law and
- justice is advantageous to the society; and 'twas with a view to this
- advantage that men, by their voluntary conventions, established it.
- After it is once established by these conventions, it is _naturally_
- attended with a strong sentiment of morals, which can proceed from
- nothing but our sympathy with the interests of society. We need no
- other explication of that esteem which attends such of the natural
- virtues as have a tendency to the public good.
- I must farther add, that there are several circumstances which render
- this hypothesis much more probable with regard to the natural than
- the artificial virtues. 'Tis certain, that the imagination is more
- affected by what is particular, than by what is general; and that the
- sentiments are always moved with difficulty, where their objects are
- in any degree loose and undetermined. Now, every particular act of
- justice is not beneficial to society, but the whole scheme or system;
- and it may not perhaps be any individual person for whom we are
- concerned, who receives benefit from justice, but the whole society
- alike. On the contrary, every particular act of generosity, or relief
- of the industrious and indigent, is beneficial, and is beneficial to
- a particular person, who is not undeserving of it. 'Tis more natural,
- therefore, to think that the tendencies of the latter virtue will
- affect our sentiments, and command our approbation, than those of the
- former; and therefore, since we find that the approbation of the former
- arises from their tendencies, we may ascribe, with better reason, the
- same cause to the approbation of the latter. In any number of similar
- effects, if a cause can be discovered for one, we ought to extend
- that cause to all the other effects which can be accounted for by
- it; but much more, if these other effects be attended with peculiar
- circumstances, which facilitate the operation of that cause.
- Before I proceed farther, I must observe two remarkable circumstances
- in this affair, which may seem objections to the present system. The
- first may be thus explained. When any quality or character has a
- tendency to the good of mankind, we are pleased with it, and approve
- of it, because it presents the lively idea of pleasure; which idea
- affects us by sympathy, and is itself a kind of pleasure. But as this
- sympathy is very variable, it may be thought that our sentiments of
- morals must admit of all the same variations. We sympathize more with
- persons contiguous to us, than with persons remote from us; with our
- acquaintance, than with strangers; with our countrymen, than with
- foreigners. But notwithstanding this variation of our sympathy, we
- give the same approbation to the same moral qualities in China as in
- England. They appear equally virtuous, and recommend themselves equally
- to the esteem of a judicious spectator. The sympathy varies without
- a variation in our esteem. Our esteem, therefore, proceeds not from
- sympathy.
- To this I answer, the approbation of moral qualities most certainly
- is not derived from reason, or any comparison of ideas; but proceeds
- entirely from a moral taste, and from certain sentiments of pleasure
- or disgust, which arise upon the contemplation and view of particular
- qualities or characters. Now, 'tis evident that those sentiments,
- whencever they are derived, must vary according to the distance or
- contiguity of the objects; nor can I feel the same lively pleasure from
- the virtues of a person who lived in Greece two thousand years ago,
- that I feel from the virtues of a familiar friend and acquaintance.
- Yet I do not say that I esteem the one more than the other; and
- therefore, if the variation of the sentiment, without a variation of
- the esteem, be an objection, it must have equal force against every
- other system, as against that of sympathy. But to consider the matter
- aright, it has no force at all; and 'tis the easiest matter in the
- world to account for it. Our situation with regard both to persons and
- things is in continual fluctuation; and a man that lies at a distance
- from us, may in a little time become a familiar acquaintance. Besides,
- every particular man has a peculiar position with regard to others;
- and 'tis impossible we could ever converse together on any reasonable
- terms, were each of us to consider characters and persons only as
- they appear from his peculiar point of view. In order, therefore, to
- prevent those continual _contradictions_, and arrive at a more _stable_
- judgment of things, we fix on some _steady_ and _general_ points of
- view, and always, in our thoughts, place ourselves in them, whatever
- may be our present situation. In like manner, external beauty is
- determined merely by pleasure; and 'tis evident a beautiful countenance
- cannot give so much pleasure, when seen at a distance of twenty paces,
- as when it is brought nearer us. We say not, however, that it appears
- to us less beautiful; because we know what effect it will have in such
- a position, and by that reflection we correct its momentary appearance.
- In general, all sentiments of blame or praise are variable, according
- to our situation of nearness or remoteness with regard to the person
- blamed or praised, and according to the present disposition of our
- mind. But these variations we regard not in our general decisions, but
- still apply the terms expressive of our liking or dislike, in the same
- manner as if we remained in one point of view. Experience soon teaches
- us this method of correcting our sentiments, or at least of correcting
- our language, where the sentiments are more stubborn and unalterable.
- Our servant, if diligent and faithful, may excite stronger sentiments
- of love and kindness than Marcus Brutus, as represented in history;
- but we say not, upon that account, that the former character is more
- laudable than the latter. We know that, were we to approach equally
- near to that renowned patriot, he would command a much higher degree
- of affection and admiration. Such corrections are common with regard
- to all the senses; and indeed 'twere impossible we could ever make use
- of language, or communicate our sentiments to one another, did we not
- correct the momentary appearances of things, and overlook our present
- situation.
- 'Tis therefore from the influence of characters and qualities upon
- those who have an intercourse with any person, that we blame or praise
- him. We consider not whether the persons affected by the qualities
- be our acquaintance or strangers, countrymen or foreigners. Nay, we
- overlook our own interest in those general judgments, and blame not a
- man for opposing us in any of our pretensions, when his own interest
- is particularly concerned. We make allowance for a certain degree of
- selfishness in men, because we know it to be inseparable from human
- nature, and inherent in our frame and constitution. By this reflection
- we correct those sentiments of blame which so naturally arise upon any
- opposition.
- But however the general principle of our blame or praise may be
- corrected by those other principles, 'tis certain they are not
- altogether efficacious, nor do our passions often correspond entirely
- to the present theory. 'Tis seldom men heartily love what lies at
- a distance from them, and what no way redounds to their particular
- benefit; as 'tis no less rare to meet with persons who can pardon
- another any opposition he makes to their interest, however justifiable
- that opposition may be by the general rules of morality. Here we are
- contented with saying, that reason requires such an impartial conduct,
- but that 'tis seldom we can bring ourselves to it, and that our
- passions do not readily follow the determination of our judgment. This
- language will be easily understood, if we consider what we formerly
- said concerning that _reason_ which is able to oppose our passion, and
- which we have found to be nothing but a general calm determination
- of the passions, founded on some distant view or reflection. When
- we form our judgments of persons merely from the tendency of their
- characters to our own benefit, or to that of our friends, we find so
- many contradictions to our sentiments in society and conversation, and
- such an uncertainty from the incessant changes of our situation, that
- we seek some other standard of merit and demerit, which may not admit
- of so great variation. Being thus loosened from our first station, we
- cannot afterwards fix ourselves so commodiously by any means as by a
- sympathy with those who have any commerce with the person we consider.
- This is far from being as lively as when our own interest is concerned,
- or that of our particular friends; nor has it such an influence on our
- love and hatred; but being equally conformable to our calm and general
- principles, 'tis said to have an equal authority over our reason, and
- to command our judgment and opinion. We blame equally a bad action
- which we read of in history, with one performed in our neighbourhood
- t'other day; the meaning of which is, that we know from reflection that
- the former action would excite as strong sentiments of disapprobation
- as the latter, were it placed in the same position.
- I now proceed to the _second_ remarkable circumstance which I proposed
- to take notice of. Where a person is possessed of a character that
- in its natural tendency is beneficial to society, we esteem him
- virtuous, and are delighted with the view of his character, even though
- particular accidents prevent its operation, and incapacitate him from
- being serviceable to his friends and country. Virtue in rags is still
- virtue; and the love which it procures attends a man into a dungeon or
- desart, where the virtue can no longer be exerted in action, and is
- lost to all the world. Now, this may be esteemed an objection to the
- present system. Sympathy interests us in the good of mankind; and if
- sympathy were the source of our esteem for virtue, that sentiment of
- approbation could only take place where the virtue actually attained
- its end, and was beneficial to mankind. Where it fails of its end, 'tis
- only an imperfect means; and therefore can never acquire any merit from
- that end. The goodness of an end can bestow a merit on such means alone
- as are complete, and actually produce the end.
- To this we may reply, that where any object, in all its parts, is
- fitted to attain any agreeable end, it naturally gives us pleasure,
- and is esteemed beautiful, even though some external circumstances be
- wanting to render it altogether effectual. 'Tis sufficient if every
- thing be complete in the object itself. A house that is contrived
- with great judgment for all the commodities of life, pleases us upon
- that account; though perhaps we are sensible, that no one will ever
- dwell in it. A fertile soil, and a happy climate, delight us by a
- reflection on the happiness which they would afford the inhabitants,
- though at present the country be desart and uninhabited. A man, whose
- limbs and shape promise strength and activity, is esteemed handsome,
- though condemned to perpetual imprisonment. The imagination has a set
- of passions belonging to it, upon which our sentiments of beauty much
- depend. These passions are moved by degrees of liveliness and strength,
- which are inferior to _belief_, and independent of the real existence
- of their objects. Where a character is, in every respect, fitted to be
- beneficial to society, the imagination passes easily from the cause to
- the effect, without considering that there are still some circumstances
- wanting to render the cause a complete one. _General rules_ create a
- species of probability, which sometimes influences the judgment, and
- always the imagination.
- 'Tis true, when the cause is complete, and a good disposition is
- attended with good fortune, which renders it really beneficial to
- society, it gives a stronger pleasure to the spectator, and is attended
- with a more lively sympathy. We are more affected by it; and yet we do
- not say that it is more virtuous, or that we esteem it more. We know
- that an alteration of fortune may render the benevolent disposition
- entirely impotent; and therefore we separate, as much as possible, the
- fortune from the disposition. The case is the same as when we correct
- the different sentiments of virtue, which proceed from its different
- distances from ourselves. The passions do not always follow our
- corrections; but these corrections serve sufficiently to regulate our
- abstract notions, and are alone regarded when we pronounce in general
- concerning the degrees of vice and virtue.
- 'Tis observed by critics, that all words or sentences which are
- difficult to the pronunciation, are disagreeable to the ear. There
- is no difference, whether a man hear them pronounced, or read them
- silently to himself. When I run over a book with my eye, I imagine
- I hear it all; and also, by the force of imagination, enter into
- the uneasiness which the delivery of it would give the speaker. The
- uneasiness is not real; but, as such a composition of words has a
- natural tendency to produce it, this is sufficient to affect the
- mind with a painful sentiment, and render the discourse harsh and
- disagreeable. 'Tis a similar case, where any real quality is, by
- accidental circumstances, rendered impotent, and is deprived of its
- natural influence on society.
- Upon these principles we may easily remove any contradiction which
- may appear to be betwixt the _extensive sympathy_, on which our
- sentiments of virtue depend, and that _limited generosity_, which I
- have frequently observed to be natural to men, and which justice and
- property suppose, according to the precedent reasoning. My sympathy
- with another may give me the sentiment of pain and disapprobation, when
- any object is presented that has a tendency to give him uneasiness;
- though I may not be willing to sacrifice any thing of my own interest,
- or cross any of my passions, for his satisfaction. A house may
- displease me by being ill-contrived for the convenience of the owner;
- and yet I may refuse to give a shilling towards the rebuilding of it.
- Sentiments must touch the heart to make them control our passions: but
- they need not extend beyond the imagination, to make them influence
- our taste. When a building seems clumsy and tottering to the eye, it is
- ugly and disagreeable; though we may be fully assured of the solidity
- of the workmanship. 'Tis a kind of fear which causes this sentiment
- of disapprobation; but the passion is not the same with that which we
- feel when obliged to stand under a wall that we really think tottering
- and insecure. The _seeming tendencies_ of objects affect the mind:
- and the emotions they excite are of a like species with those which
- proceed from the _real consequences_ of objects, but their feeling is
- different. Nay, these emotions are so different in their feeling, that
- they may often be contrary, without destroying each other; as when the
- fortifications of a city belonging to an enemy are esteemed beautiful
- upon account of their strength, though we could wish that they were
- entirely destroyed. The imagination adheres to the _general_ views of
- things, and distinguishes the feelings they produce from those which
- arise from our particular and momentary situation.
- If we examine the panegyrics that are commonly made of great men, we
- shall find, that most of the qualities which are attributed to them
- may be divided into two kinds, viz. such as make them perform their
- part in society; and such as render them serviceable to themselves, and
- enable them to promote their own interest. Their _prudence, temperance,
- frugality, industry, assiduity, enterprise, dexterity_, are celebrated,
- as well as their _generosity_ and _humanity_. If we ever give an
- indulgence to any quality that disables a man from making a figure in
- life, 'tis to that of _indolence_, which is not supposed to deprive
- one of his parts and capacity, but only suspends their exercise; and
- that without any inconvenience to the person himself, since 'tis, in
- some measure, from his own choice. Yet indolence is always allowed to
- be a fault, and a very great one, if extreme: nor do a man's friends
- ever acknowledge him to be subject to it, but in order to save his
- character in more material articles. He could make a figure, say they,
- if he pleased to give application: his understanding is sound, his
- conception quick, and his memory tenacious; but he hates business, and
- is indifferent about his fortune. And this a man sometimes may make
- even a subject of vanity, though with the air of confessing a fault:
- because he may think, that this incapacity for business implies much
- more noble qualities; such as a philosophical spirit, a fine taste, a
- delicate wit, or a relish for pleasure and society. But take any other
- case: suppose a quality that, without being an indication of any other
- good qualities, incapacitates a man _always_ for business, and is
- destructive to his interest; such as a blundering understanding, and a
- wrong judgment of every thing in life; inconstancy and irresolution; or
- a want of address in the management of men and business: these are all
- allowed to be imperfections in a character; and many men would rather
- acknowledge the greatest crimes, than have it suspected that they are
- in any degree subject to them.
- 'Tis very happy, in our philosophical researches, when we find the
- same phenomenon diversified by a variety of circumstances; and by
- discovering what is common among them, can the better assure ourselves
- of the truth of any hypothesis we may make use of to explain it. Were
- nothing esteemed virtue but what were beneficial to society, I am
- persuaded that the foregoing explication of the moral sense ought still
- to be received, and that upon sufficient evidence: but this evidence
- must grow upon us, when we find other kinds of virtue which will not
- admit of any explication except from that hypothesis. Here is a man
- who is not remarkably defective in his social qualities; but what
- principally recommends him is his dexterity in business, by which he
- has extricated himself from the greatest difficulties, and conducted
- the most delicate affairs with a singular address and prudence. I
- find an esteem for him immediately to arise in me: his company is a
- satisfaction to me; and before I have any farther acquaintance with
- him, I would rather do him a service than another whose character is
- in every other respect equal, but is deficient in that particular. In
- this case, the qualities that please me are all considered as useful
- to the person, and as having a tendency to promote his interest and
- satisfaction. They are only regarded as means to an end, and please me
- in proportion to their fitness for that end. The end, therefore must
- be agreeable to me. But what makes the end agreeable? The person is a
- stranger: I am no way interested in him, nor lie under any obligation
- to him: his happiness concerns not me, farther than the happiness
- of every human, and indeed of every sensible creature; that is, it
- affects me only by sympathy. From that principle, whenever I discover
- his happiness and good, whether in its causes or effects, I enter so
- deeply into it, that it gives me a sensible emotion. The appearance
- of qualities that have a _tendency_ to promote it, have an agreeable
- effect upon my imagination, and command my love and esteem.
- This theory may serve to explain, why the same qualities, in all cases,
- produce both pride and love, humility and hatred; and the same man
- is always virtuous or vicious, accomplished or despicable to others,
- who is so to himself. A person in whom we discover any passion or
- habit, which originally is only incommodious to himself, becomes always
- disagreeable to us merely on its account; as, on the other hand, one
- whose character is only dangerous and disagreeable to others, can
- never be satisfied with himself, as long as he is sensible of that
- disadvantage. Nor is this observable only with regard to characters and
- manners, but may be remarked even in the most minute circumstances. A
- violent cough in another gives us uneasiness; though in itself it does
- not in the least affect us. A man will be mortified if you tell him he
- has a stinking breath; though 'tis evidently no annoyance to himself.
- Our fancy easily changes its situation; and, either surveying ourselves
- as we appear to others, or considering others as they feel themselves,
- we enter, by that means, into sentiments which no way belong to us,
- and in which nothing but sympathy is able to interest us. And this
- sympathy we sometimes carry so far, as even to be displeased with a
- quality commodious to us, merely because it displeases others, and
- makes us disagreeable in their eyes; though perhaps we never can have
- any interest in rendering ourselves agreeable to them.
- There have been many systems of morality advanced by philosophers
- in all ages; but if they are strictly examined, they may be reduced
- to two, which alone merit our attention. Moral good and evil are
- certainly distinguished by our _sentiments_, not by _reason_: but these
- sentiments may arise either from the mere species or appearance of
- characters and passions, or from reflections on their tendency to the
- happiness of mankind, and of particular persons. My opinion is, that
- both these causes are intermixed in our judgments of morals; after the
- same manner as they are in our decisions concerning most kinds of
- external beauty: though I am also of opinion, that reflections on the
- tendencies of actions have by far the greatest influence, and determine
- all the great lines of our duty. There are, however, instances in cases
- of less moment, wherein this immediate taste or sentiment produces our
- approbation. Wit, and a certain easy and disengaged behaviour, are
- qualities _immediately agreeable_ to others, and command their love
- and esteem. Some of these qualities produce satisfaction in others
- by particular _original_ principles of human nature, which cannot be
- accounted for: odiers may be resolved into principles which are more
- general. This will best appear upon a particular inquiry.
- As some qualities acquire their merit from their being _immediately
- agreeable_ to others, without any tendency to public interest; so some
- are denominated virtuous from their being _immediately agreeable_
- to the person himself, who possesses them. Each of the passions and
- operations of the mind has a particular feeling, which must be either
- agreeable or disagreeable. The first is virtuous, the second vicious.
- This particular feeling constitutes the very nature of the passion; and
- therefore needs not be accounted for.
- But, however directly the distinction of vice and virtue may seem
- to flow from the immediate pleasure or uneasiness, which particular
- qualities cause to ourselves or others, 'tis easy to observe, that it
- has also a considerable dependence on the principle of _sympathy_ so
- often insisted on. We approve of a person who is possessed of qualities
- _immediately agreeable_ to those with whom he has any commerce, though
- perhaps we ourselves never reaped any pleasure from them. We also
- approve of one who is possessed of qualities that are _immediately
- agreeable_ to himself, though they be of no service to any mortal. To
- account for this, we must have recourse to the foregoing principles.
- Thus, to take a general review of the present hypothesis: Every quality
- of the mind is denominated virtuous which gives pleasure by the mere
- survey, as every quality which produces pain is called vicious. This
- pleasure and this pain may arise from four different sources. For
- we reap a pleasure from the view of a character which is naturally
- fitted to be useful to others, or to the person himself, or which is
- agreeable to others, or to the person himself. One may perhaps be
- surprised, that, amidst all these interests and pleasures, we should
- forget our own, which touch us so nearly on every other occasion. But
- we shall easily satisfy ourselves on this head, when we consider, that
- every particular person's pleasure and interest being different, 'tis
- impossible men could ever agree in their sentiments and judgments,
- unless they chose some common point of view, from which they might
- survey their object, and which might cause it to appear the same to all
- of them. Now, in judging of characters, the only interest or pleasure
- which appears the same to every spectator, is that of the person
- himself whose character is examined, or that of persons who have a
- connexion with him. And, though such interests and pleasures touch us
- more faintly than our own, yet, being more constant and universal, they
- counterbalance the latter even in practice, and are alone admitted in
- speculation as the standard of virtue and morality. They alone produce
- that particular feeling or sentiment on which moral distinctions depend.
- As to the good or ill desert of virtue or vice, 'tis an evident
- consequence of the sentiments of pleasure or uneasiness. These
- sentiments produce love or hatred; and love or hatred, by the original
- constitution of human passion, is attended with benevolence or anger;
- that is, with a desire of making happy the person we love, and
- miserable the person we hate. We have treated of this more fully on
- another occasion.
- SECTION II.
- OF GREATNESS OF MIND.
- It may now be proper to illustrate this general system of morals, by
- applying it to particular instances of virtue and vice, and showing how
- their merit or demerit arises from the four sources here explained. We
- shall begin with examining the passions of _pride_ and _humility_, and
- shall consider the vice or virtue that lies in their excesses or just
- proportion. An excessive pride or overweening conceit of ourselves,
- is always esteemed vicious, and is universally hated, as modesty, or
- a just sense of our weakness, is esteemed virtuous, and procures the
- good will of every one. Of the four sources of moral distinctions, this
- is to be ascribed to the _third_; viz. the immediate agreeableness and
- disagreeableness of a quality to others, without any reflections on the
- tendency of that quality.
- In order to prove this, we must have recourse to two principles,
- which are very conspicuous in human nature. The _first_ of these is
- the _sympathy_ and communication of sentiments and passions above
- mentioned. So close and intimate is the correspondence of human souls,
- that no sooner any person approaches me, than he diffuses on me all
- his opinions, and draws along my judgment in a greater or lesser
- degree. And though, on many occasions, my sympathy with him goes not
- so far as entirely to change my sentiments and way of thinking, yet it
- seldom is so weak as not to disturb the easy course of my thought, and
- give an authority to that opinion which is recommended to me by his
- assent and approbation. Nor is it any way material upon what subject he
- and I employ our thoughts. Whether we judge of an indifferent person,
- or of my own character, my sympathy gives equal force to his decision:
- and even his sentiments of his own merit make me consider him in the
- same light in which he regards himself.
- This principle of sympathy is of so powerful and insinuating a nature,
- that it enters into most of our sentiments and passions, and often
- takes place under the appearance of its contrary. For 'tis remarkable,
- that when a person opposes me in any thing which I am strongly bent
- upon, and rouses up my passion by contradiction, I have always a
- degree of sympathy with him, nor does my commotion proceed from any
- other origin. We may here observe an evident conflict or rencounter
- of opposite principles and passions. On the one side, there is that
- passion or sentiment which is natural to me; and 'tis observable, that
- the stronger this passion is, the greater is the commotion. There must
- also be some passion or sentiment on the other side; and this passion
- can proceed from nothing but sympathy. The sentiments of others can
- never affect us, but by becoming in some measure our own; in which case
- they operate upon us, by opposing and increasing our passions, in the
- very same manner as if they had been originally derived from our own
- temper and disposition. While they remain concealed in the minds of
- others, they can never have any influence upon us: and even when they
- are known, if they went no farther than the imagination or conception,
- that faculty is so accustomed to objects of every different kind, that
- a mere idea, though contrary to our sentiments and inclinations, would
- never alone be able to affect us.
- The _second_ principle I shall take notice of is that of _comparison_,
- or the variation of our judgments concerning objects, according to
- the proportion they bear to those with which we compare them. We
- judge more of objects by comparison than by their intrinsic worth and
- value; and regard every thing as mean, when set in opposition to what
- is superior of the same kind. But no comparison is more obvious than
- that with ourselves; and hence it is, that on all occasions it takes
- place, and mixes with most of our passions. This kind of comparison is
- directly contrary to sympathy in its operation, as we have observed in
- treating of _compassion and malice_.[2] _In all kinds of comparison, an
- object makes us always receive from another, to which it is compared,
- a sensation contrary to what arises from itself in its direct and
- immediate survey. The direct survey of another's pleasure naturally
- gives us pleasure; and therefore produces pain, when compared with our
- own. His pain, considered in itself is painful; but augments the idea
- of our own happiness, and gives us pleasure_.
- Since then those principles of sympathy, and a comparison with
- ourselves, are directly contrary, it may be worth while to consider,
- what general rules can be formed, beside the particular temper of
- the person, for the prevalence of the one or the other. Suppose I am
- now in safety at land, and would willingly reap some pleasure from
- this consideration, I must think on the miserable condition of those
- who are at sea in a storm, and must endeavour to render this idea as
- strong and lively as possible, in order to make me more sensible of
- my own happiness. But whatever pains I may take, the comparison will
- never have an equal efficacy, as if I were really on the shore,[3] and
- saw a ship at a distance tost by a tempest, and in danger every moment
- of perishing on a rock or sand-bank. But suppose this idea to become
- still more lively. Suppose the ship to be driven so near me, that I can
- perceive distinctly the horror painted on the countenance of the seamen
- and passengers, hear their lamentable cries, see the dearest friends
- give their last adieu, or embrace with a resolution to perish in each
- other's arms: no man has so savage a heart as to reap any pleasure from
- such a spectacle, or withstand the motions of the tenderest compassion
- and sympathy. 'Tis evident, therefore, there is a medium in this case;
- and that, if the idea be too faint, it has no influence by comparison;
- and on the other hand, if it be too strong, it operates on us entirely
- by sympathy, which is the contrary to comparison. Sympathy being the
- conversion of an idea into an impression, demands a greater force and
- vivacity in the idea than is requisite to comparison.
- All this is easily applied to the present subject. We sink very much
- in our own eyes when in the presence of a great man, or one of a
- superior genius; and this humility makes a considerable ingredient in
- that _respect_ which we pay our superiors, according to our foregoing
- reasonings on that passion.[4] Sometimes even envy and hatred arise
- from the comparison; but in the greatest part of men, it rests at
- respect and esteem. As sympathy has such a powerful influence on the
- human mind, it causes pride to have in some measure the same effect as
- merit; and, by making us enter into those elevated sentiments which the
- proud man entertains of himself, presents that comparison, which is so
- mortifying and disagreeable. Our judgment does not entirely accompany
- him in the flattering conceit in which he pleases himself; but still
- is so shaken as to receive the idea it presents, and to give it an
- influence above the loose conceptions of the imagination. A man who,
- in an idle humour, would form a notion of a person of a merit very
- much superior to his own, would not be mortified by that fiction: but
- when a man, whom we are really persuaded to be of inferior merit, is
- presented to us; if we observe in him any extraordinary degree of pride
- and self-conceit, the firm persuasion he has of his own merit, takes
- hold of the imagination, and diminishes us in our own eyes, in the same
- manner as if he were really possessed of all the good qualities which
- he so liberally attributes to himself. Our idea is here precisely in
- that medium which is requisite to make it operate on us by comparison.
- Were it accompanied with belief, and did the person appear to have
- the same merit which he assumes to himself, it would have a contrary
- effect, and would operate on us by sympathy. The influence of that
- principle would then be superior to that of comparison, contrary to
- what happens where the person's merit seems below his pretensions.
- The necessary consequence of these principles is, that pride, or
- an overweening conceit of ourselves, must be vicious; since it
- causes uneasiness in all men, and presents them every moment with a
- disagreeable comparison. 'Tis a trite observation in philosophy, and
- even in common life and conversation, that 'tis our own pride, which
- makes us so much displeased with the pride of other people; and that
- vanity becomes insupportable to us merely because we are vain. The gay
- naturally associate themselves with the gay, and the amorous with the
- amorous; but the proud never can endure the proud, and rather seek the
- company of those who are of an opposite disposition. As we are all of
- us proud in some degree, pride is universally blamed and condemned
- by all mankind, as having a natural tendency to cause uneasiness in
- others by means of comparison. And this effect must follow the more
- naturally, that those, who have an ill-grounded conceit of themselves,
- are for ever making those comparisons; nor have they any other method
- of supporting their vanity. A man of sense and merit is pleased with
- himself, independent of all foreign considerations; but a fool must
- always find some person that is more foolish, in order to keep himself
- in good humour with his own parts and understanding.
- But though an overweening conceit of our own merit be vicious and
- disagreeable, nothing can be more laudable than to have a value for
- ourselves, where we really have qualities that are valuable. The
- utility and advantage of any quality to ourselves is a source of
- virtue, as well as its agreeableness to others; and 'tis certain, that
- nothing is more useful to us in the conduct of life, than a due degree
- of pride, which makes us sensible of our own merit, and gives us a
- confidence and assurance in all our projects and enterprises. Whatever
- capacity any one may be endowed with, 'tis entirely useless to him, if
- he be not acquainted with it, and form not designs suitable to it. 'Tis
- requisite on all occasions to know our own force; and were it allowable
- to err on either side, 'twould be more advantageous to over-rate our
- merit, than to form ideas of it below its just standard. Fortune
- commonly favours the bold and enterprising; and nothing inspires us
- with more boldness than a good opinion of ourselves.
- Add to this, that though pride, or self-applause, be sometimes
- disagreeable to others, 'tis always agreeable to ourselves; as, on the
- other hand, modesty, though it give pleasure to every one who observes
- it, produces often uneasiness in the person endowed with it. Now, it
- has been observed, that our own sensations determine the vice and
- virtue of any quality, as well as those sensations, which it may excite
- in others.
- Thus, self-satisfaction and vanity may not only be allowable, but
- requisite in a character. 'Tis however certain, that good breeding and
- decency require that we should avoid all signs and expressions, which
- tend directly to show that passion. We have, all of us, a wonderful
- partiality for ourselves, and were we always to give vent to our
- sentiments in this particular, we should mutually cause the greatest
- indignation in each other, not only by the immediate presence of so
- disagreeable a subject of comparison, but also by the contrariety of
- our judgments. In like manner, therefore, as we establish the _laws
- of nature_, in order to secure property in society, and prevent the
- opposition of self-interest, we establish the _rules of good breeding_,
- in order to prevent the opposition of men's pride, and render
- conversation agreeable and offensive. Nothing is more disagreeable than
- a man's overweening conceit of himself. Every one almost has a strong
- propensity to this vice. No one can well distinguish _in himself_
- betwixt the vice and virtue, or be certain that his esteem of his
- own merit is well-founded; for these reasons, all direct expressions
- of this passion are condemned; nor do we make any exception to this
- rule in favour of men of sense and merit. They are not allowed to do
- themselves justice openly in words, no more than other people; and even
- if they show a reserve and secret doubt in doing themselves justice
- in their own thoughts, they will be more applauded. That impertinent,
- and almost universal propensity of men, to overvalue themselves, has
- given us such a _prejudice_ against self-applause, that we are apt to
- condemn it by a _general rule_ wherever we meet with it; and 'tis with
- some difficulty we give a privilege to men of sense, even in their
- most secret thoughts. At least, it must be owned that some disguise in
- this particular is absolutely requisite; and that, if we harbour pride
- in our breasts, we must carry a fair outside, and have the appearance
- of modesty and mutual deference in all our conduct and behaviour. We
- must, on every occasion, be ready to prefer others to ourselves; to
- treat them with a kind of deference, even though they be our equals; to
- seem always the lowest and least in the company, where we are not very
- much distinguished above them; and if we observe these rules in our
- conduct, men will have more indulgence for our secret sentiments, when
- we discover them in an oblique manner.
- I believe no one who has any practice of the world, and can penetrate
- into the inward sentiments of men, will assert that the humility which
- good-breeding and decency require of us, goes beyond the outside,
- or that a thorough sincerity in this particular is esteemed a real
- part of our duty. On the contrary, we may observe, that a genuine and
- hearty pride, or self-esteem, if well concealed and well founded, is
- essential to the character of a man of honour, and that there is no
- quality of the mind which is more indispensably requisite to procure
- the esteem and approbation of mankind. There are certain deferences and
- mutual submissions which custom requires of the different ranks of men
- towards each other; and whoever exceeds in this particular, if through
- interest, is accused of meanness, if through ignorance, of simplicity.
- 'Tis necessary, therefore, to know our rank and station in the world,
- whether it be fixed by our birth, fortune, employments, talents, or
- reputation. 'Tis necessary to feel the sentiment and passion of pride
- in conformity to it, and to regulate our actions accordingly. And
- should it be said, that prudence may suffice to regulate our actions in
- this particular, without any real pride, I would observe, that here the
- object of prudence is to conform our actions to the general usage and
- custom; and that 'tis impossible those tacit airs of superiority should
- ever have been established and authorized by custom, unless men were
- generally proud, and unless that passion were generally approved, when
- well-grounded.
- If we pass from common life and conversation to history, this reasoning
- acquires new force, when we observe, that all those great actions and
- sentiments which have become the admiration of mankind, are founded on
- nothing but pride and self-esteem. 'Go,' says Alexander the Great to
- his soldiers, when they refused to follow him to the Indies, 'go tell
- your countrymen, that you left Alexander completing the conquest of
- the world.' This passage was always particularly admired by the prince
- of Condé, as we learn from St Evremond. 'Alexander,' said that prince,
- 'abandoned by his soldiers, among barbarians not yet fully subdued,
- felt in himself such a dignity and right of empire, that he could not
- believe it possible any one could refuse to obey him. Whether in Europe
- or in Asia, among Greeks or Persians, all was indifferent to him;
- wherever he found men, he fancied he had found subjects.'
- In general, we may observe, that whatever we call _heroic virtue_,
- and admire under the character of greatness and elevation of mind, is
- either nothing but a steady and well-established pride and self-esteem,
- or partakes largely of that passion. Courage, intrepidity, ambition,
- love of glory, magnanimity, and all the other shining virtues of that
- kind, have plainly a strong mixture of self-esteem in them, and derive
- a great part of their merit from that origin. Accordingly we find,
- that many religious declaimers decry those virtues as purely pagan
- and natural, and represent to us the excellency of the _Christian_
- religion, which places humility in the rank of virtues, and corrects
- the judgment of the world, and even of philosophers, who so generally
- admire all the efforts of pride and ambition. Whether this virtue of
- humility has been rightly understood, I shall not pretend to determine.
- I am content with the concession, that the world naturally esteems a
- well-regulated pride, which secretly animates our conduct, without
- breaking out into such indecent expressions of vanity as may offend the
- vanity of others.
- The merit of pride or self-esteem is derived from two circumstances,
- viz. its utility, and its agreeableness to ourselves; by which it
- capacitates us for business, and at the same time gives us an immediate
- satisfaction. When it goes beyond its just bounds, it loses the first
- advantage, and even becomes prejudicial; which is the reason why we
- condemn an extravagant pride and ambition, however regulated by the
- decorums of good-breeding and politeness. But as such a passion is
- still agreeable, and conveys an elevated and sublime sensation to the
- person who is actuated by it, the sympathy with that satisfaction
- diminishes considerably the blame which naturally attends its dangerous
- influence on our conduct and behaviour. Accordingly we may observe,
- that an excessive courage and magnanimity, especially when it displays
- itself under the frowns of fortune, contributes in a great measure to
- the character of a hero, and will render a person the admiration of
- posterity, at the same time that it ruins his affairs, and leads him
- into dangers and difficulties with which otherwise he would never have
- been acquainted.
- Heroism, or military glory, is much admired by the generality of
- mankind. They consider it as the most sublime kind of merit. Men
- of cool reflection are not so sanguine in their praises of it. The
- infinite confusions and disorder which it has caused in the world,
- diminish much of its merit in their eyes. When they would oppose the
- popular notions on this head, they always paint out the evils which
- this supposed virtue has produced in human society; the subversion of
- empires, the devastation of provinces, the sack of cities. As long as
- these are present to us, we are more inclined to hate than admire the
- ambition of heroes. But when we fix our view on the person himself,
- who is the author of all this mischief, there is something so dazzling
- in his character, the mere contemplation of it so elevates the mind,
- that we cannot refuse it our admiration. The pain which we receive from
- its tendency to the prejudice of society, is overpowered by a stronger
- and more immediate sympathy.
- Thus, our explication of the merit or demerit which attends the
- degrees of pride or self-esteem, may serve as a strong argument for
- the preceding hypothesis, by showing the effects of those principles
- above explained in all the variations of our judgments concerning
- that passion. Nor will this reasoning be advantageous to us only by
- showing, that the distinction of vice and virtue arises from the _four_
- principles of the _advantage_ and of the _pleasure_ of the _person
- himself_ and of _others_, but may also afford us a strong proof of some
- under parts of that hypothesis.
- No one who duly considers of this matter will make any scruple of
- allowing, that any piece of ill-breeding, or any expression of pride
- and haughtiness, is displeasing to us, merely because it shocks our
- own pride, and leads us by sympathy into a comparison which causes the
- disagreeable passion of humility. Now, as an insolence of this kind
- is blamed even in a person who has always been civil to ourselves in
- particular, nay, in one whose name is only known to us in history, it
- follows that our disapprobation proceeds from a sympathy with others,
- and from the reflection that such a character is highly displeasing
- and odious to every one who converses or has any intercourse with
- the person possest of it. We sympathize with those people in their
- uneasiness; and as their uneasiness proceeds in part from a sympathy
- with the person who insults them, we may here observe a double rebound
- of the sympathy, which is a principle very similar to what we have
- observed on another occasion.[5]
- [1] Decentior equus cujus astricta sunt ilia; sed idem velocior.
- Pulcher aspectu sit athleta, cujus lacertos exercitatio expressit; idem
- certamini paratior. Nunquam vero _species ab utilitate_ dividitur. Sed
- hoc quidem discernere, modici judicii est.--Quinct. lib. 8.
- [2] Book II. Part II. Sect 8.
- [3]
- Suavi mari magno turbantibus æquora ventis E terra magnum alterius
- spectare laborem; Non quia vexari quenquam est jucunda voluptas, Sed
- quibus ipse malis careas quia cernere suav'est.--_Lucret_.
- [4] Book II. Part II. Sect 10.
- SECTION III.
- OF GOODNESS AND BENEVOLENCE.
- Having thus explained the origin of that praise and approbation which
- attends every thing we call _great_ in human affections, we now proceed
- to give an account of their _goodness_, and show whence its merit is
- derived.
- When experience has once given us a competent knowledge of human
- affairs, and has taught us the proportion they bear to human passion,
- we perceive that the generosity of men is very limited, and that it
- seldom extends beyond their friends and family, or, at most, beyond
- their native country. Being thus acquainted with the nature of man,
- we expect not any impossibilities from him; but confine our view to
- that narrow circle in which any person moves, in order to form a
- judgment of his moral character. When the natural tendency of his
- passions leads him to be serviceable and useful within his sphere,
- we approve of his character, and love his person, by a sympathy with
- the sentiments of those who have a more particular connexion with
- him. We are quickly obliged to forget get our own interest in our
- judgments of this kind, by reason of the perpetual contradictions
- we meet with in society and conversation, from persons that are not
- placed in the same situation, and have not the same interest with
- ourselves. The only point of view in which our sentiments concur with
- those of others, is when we consider the tendency of any passion to
- the advantage or harm of those who have any immediate connexion or
- intercourse with the person possessed of it. And though this advantage
- or harm be often very remote from ourselves, yet sometimes 'tis very
- near us, and interests us strongly by sympathy. This concern we
- readily extend to other cases that are resembling; and when these are
- very remote, our sympathy is proportionably weaker, and our praise or
- blame fainter and more doubtful. The case is here the same as in our
- judgments concerning external bodies. All objects seem to diminish by
- their distance; but though the appearance of objects to our senses
- be the original standard by which we judge of them, yet we do not
- say that they actually diminish by the distance; but, correcting the
- appearance by reflection, arrive at a more constant and established
- judgment concerning them. In like manner, though sympathy be much
- fainter than our concern for ourselves, and a sympathy with persons
- remote from us much fainter than that with persons near and contiguous,
- yet we neglect all these differences in our calm judgments concerning
- the characters of men. Besides that we ourselves often change our
- situation in this particular, we every day meet with persons who are
- in a different situation from ourselves, and who could never converse
- with us on any reasonable terms, were we to remain constantly in that
- situation and point of view which is peculiar to us. The intercourse
- of sentiments, therefore, in society and conversation, makes us form
- some general unalterable standard by which we may approve or disapprove
- of characters and manners. And though the _heart_ does not always take
- part with those general notions, or regulate its love and hatred by
- them, yet are they sufficient for discourse, and serve all our purposes
- in company, in the pulpit, on the theatre, and in the schools.
- From these principles, we may easily account for that merit which is
- commonly ascribed to _generosity, humanity, compassion, gratitude,
- friendship, fidelity, zeal, disinterestedness, liberality_, and all
- those other qualities which form the character of good and benevolent.
- A propensity to the tender passions makes a man agreeable and useful
- in all the parts of life, and gives a just direction to all his other
- qualities, which otherwise may become prejudicial to society. Courage
- and ambition, when not regulated by benevolence, are fit only to make
- a tyrant and public robber. 'Tis the same case with judgment and
- capacity, and all the qualities of that kind. They are indifferent in
- themselves to the interests of society, and have a tendency to the
- good or ill of mankind, according as they are directed by these other
- passions.
- As love is _immediately agreeable_ to the person who is actuated by it,
- and hatred _immediately disagreeable_, this may also be a considerable
- reason why we praise all the passions that partake of the former,
- and blame all those that have any considerable share of the latter.
- 'Tis certain we are infinitely touched with a tender sentiment, as
- well as with a great one. The tears naturally start in our eyes at
- the conception of it; nor can we forbear giving a loose to the same
- tenderness towards the person who exerts it. All this seems to me a
- proof that our approbation has, in these cases, an origin different
- from the prospect of utility and advantage, either to ourselves or
- others. To which we may add, that men naturally, without reflection,
- approve of that character which is most like their own. The man of a
- mild disposition and tender affections, in forming a notion of the
- most perfect virtue, mixes in it more of benevolence and humanity than
- the man of courage and enterprise, who naturally looks upon a certain
- elevation of the mind as the most accomplished character. This must
- evidently proceed from an _immediate_ sympathy, which men have with
- characters similar to their own. They enter with more warmth into such
- sentiments, and feel more sensibly the pleasure which arises from them.
- 'Tis remarkable, that nothing touches a man of humanity more than
- any instance of extraordinary delicacy in love or friendship, where
- a person is attentive to the smallest concerns of his friend, and is
- willing to sacrifice to them the most considerable interest of his own.
- Such delicacies have little influence on society; because they make
- us regard the greatest trifles: but they are the more engaging the
- more minute the concern is, and are a proof of the highest merit in
- any one who is capable of them. The passions are so contagious, that
- they pass with the greatest facility from one person to another, and
- produce correspondent movements in all human breasts. Where friendship
- appears in very signal instances, my heart catches the same passion,
- and is warmed by those warm sentiments that display themselves before
- me. Such agreeable, movements must give me an affection to every one
- that excites them. This is the case with every thing that is agreeable
- in any person. The transition from pleasure to love is easy: but the
- transition must here be still more easy; since the agreeable sentiment
- which is excited by sympathy, is love itself; and there is nothing
- required but to change the object.
- Hence the peculiar merit of benevolence in all its shapes and
- appearances. Hence even its weaknesses are virtuous and amiable; and a
- person, whose grief upon the loss of a friend were excessive, would be
- esteemed upon that account. His tenderness bestows a merit, as it does
- a pleasure, on his melancholy.
- We are not, however, to imagine that all the angry passions are
- vicious, though they are disagreeable. There is a certain indulgence
- due to human nature in this respect. Anger and hatred are passions
- inherent in our very frame and constitution. The want of them, on some
- occasions, may even be a proof of weakness and imbecility. And where
- they appear only in a low degree, we not only excuse them because they
- are natural, but even bestow our applauses on them, because they are
- inferior to what appears in the greatest part of mankind.
- Where these angry passions rise up to cruelty, they form the most
- detested of all vices. All the pity and concern which we have for the
- miserable sufferers by this vice, turns against the person guilty of
- it, and produces a stronger hatred than we are sensible of on any other
- occasion.
- Even when the vice of inhumanity rises not to this extreme degree, our
- sentiments concerning it are very much influenced by reflections on
- the harm that results from it. And we may observe in general, that if
- we can find any quality in a person, which renders him incommodious
- to those who live and converse with him, we always allow it to be a
- fault or blemish, without any farther examination. On the other hand,
- when we enumerate the good qualities of any person, we always mention
- those parts of his character which render him a safe companion, an easy
- friend, a gentle master, an agreeable husband, or an indulgent father.
- We consider him with all his relations in society; and love or hate
- him, according as he affects those who have any immediate intercourse
- with him. And 'tis a most certain rule, that if there be no relation
- of life in which I could not wish to stand to a particular person, his
- character must so far be allowed to be perfect. If he be as little
- wanting to himself as to others, his character is entirely perfect.
- This is the ultimate test of merit and virtue.
- [5] Book II. Part II. Sect. 5.
- SECTION IV.
- OF NATURAL ABILITIES.
- No distinction is more usual in all systems of ethics, than that
- betwixt _natural abilities_ and _moral virtues_; where the former are
- placed on the same footing with bodily endowments, and are supposed
- to have no merit or moral worth annexed to them. Whoever considers
- the matter accurately, will find, that a dispute upon this head would
- be merely a dispute of words, and that, though these qualities are
- not altogether of the same kind, yet they agree in the most material
- circumstances. They are both of them equally mental qualities: and both
- of them equally produce pleasure; and have of course an equal tendency
- to procure the love and esteem of mankind. There are few who are not as
- jealous of their character, with regard to sense and knowledge, as to
- honour and courage; and much more than with regard to temperance and
- sobriety. Men are even afraid of passing for good-natured, lest _that_
- should be taken for want of understanding; and often boast of more
- debauches than they have been really engaged in, to give themselves
- airs of fire and spirit. In short, the figure a man makes in the
- world, the reception he meets with in company, the esteem paid him
- by his acquaintance; all these advantages depend almost as much upon
- his good sense and judgment, as upon any other part of his character.
- Let a man have the best intentions in the world, and be the farthest
- from all injustice and violence, he will never be able to make himself
- be much regarded, without a moderate share, at least, of parts and
- understanding. Since then natural abilities, though perhaps inferior,
- yet are on the same footing, both as to their causes and effects, with
- those qualities which we call moral virtues, why should we make any
- distinction betwixt them?
- Though we refuse to natural abilities the title of virtues, we must
- allow, that they procure the love and esteem of mankind; that they give
- a new lustre to the other virtues; and that a man possessed of them is
- much more entitled to our good will and services than one entirely void
- of them. It may indeed be pretended, that the sentiment of approbation
- which those qualities produce, besides its being _inferior_, is also
- somewhat _different_ from that which attends the other virtues. But
- this, in my opinion, is not a sufficient reason for excluding them
- from the catalogue of virtues. Each of the virtues, even benevolence,
- justice, gratitude, integrity, excites a different sentiment or
- feeling in the spectator. The characters of Cæsar and Cato, as drawn by
- Sallust, are both of them virtuous, in the strictest sense of the word,
- but in a different way: nor are the sentiments entirely the same which
- arise from them. The one produces love, the other esteem; the one is
- amiable, the other awful: we could wish to meet with the one character
- in a friend, the other character we would be ambitious of in ourselves.
- In like manner, the approbation which attends natural abilities, may
- be somewhat different to the feeling from that which arises from the
- other virtues, without making them entirely of a different species. And
- indeed we may observe, that the natural abilities, no more than the
- other virtues, produce not, all of them, the same kind of approbation.
- Good sense and genius beget esteem; wit and humour excite love.[6]
- Those who represent the distinction betwixt natural abilities and
- moral virtues as very material, may say, that the former are entirely
- involuntary, and have therefore no merit attending them, as having no
- dependence on liberty and free will. But to this I answer, _first_,
- That many of those qualities which all moralists, especially the
- ancients, comprehend under the title of moral virtues, are equally
- involuntary and necessary with the qualities of the judgment and
- imagination. Of this nature are constancy, fortitude, magnanimity;
- and, in short, all the qualities which form the _great_ man. I might
- say the same, in some degree, of the others; it being almost impossible
- for the mind to change its character in any considerable article, or
- cure itself of a passionate or splenetic temper, when they are natural
- to it. The greater degree there is of these blameable qualities,
- the more vicious they become, and yet they are the less voluntary.
- _Secondly_, I would have any one give me a reason, why virtue and vice
- may not be involuntary, as well as beauty and deformity. These moral
- distinctions arise from the natural distinctions of pain and pleasure;
- and when we receive those feelings from the general consideration
- of any quality or character, we denominate it vicious or virtuous.
- Now I believe no one will assert, that a quality can never produce
- pleasure or pain to the person who considers it, unless it be perfectly
- voluntary in the person who possesses it. _Thirdly_, As to free will,
- we have shown that it has no place with regard to the actions, no more
- than the qualities of men. It is not a just consequence, that what is
- voluntary is free. Our actions are more voluntary than our judgments;
- but we have not more liberty in the one than in the other.
- But, though this distinction betwixt voluntary and involuntary, be not
- sufficient to justify the distinction betwixt natural abilities and
- moral virtues, yet the former distinction will afford us a plausible
- reason, why moralists have invented the latter. Men have observed,
- that, though natural abilities and moral qualities be in the main on
- the same footing, there is, however, this difference betwixt them,
- that the former are almost invariable by any art or industry; while
- the latter, or at least the actions that proceed from them, may be
- changed by the motives of rewards and punishment, praise and blame.
- Hence legislators and divines and moralists have principally applied
- themselves to the regulating these voluntary actions, and have
- endeavoured to produce additional motives for being virtuous in that
- particular. They knew, that to punish a man for folly, or exhort him to
- be prudent and sagacious, would have but little effect; though the same
- punishments and exhortations, with regard to justice and injustice,
- might have a considerable influence. But as men, in common life and
- conversation, do not carry those ends in view, but naturally praise
- or blame whatever pleases or displeases them, they do not seem much
- to regard this distinction, but consider prudence under the character
- of virtue as well as benevolence, and penetration as well as justice.
- Nay, we find that all moralists, whose judgment is not perverted by a
- strict adherence to a system, enter into the same way of thinking; and
- that the ancient moralists, in particular, made no scruple of placing
- prudence at the head of the cardinal virtues. There is a sentiment
- of esteem and approbation, which may be excited, in some degree, by
- any faculty of the mind, in its perfect state and condition; and to
- account for this sentiment is the business of _philosophers_. It
- belongs to _grammarians_ to examine what qualities are entitled to the
- denomination of _virtue_; nor will they find, upon trial, that this is
- so easy a task as at first sight they may be apt to imagine.
- The principal reason why natural abilities are esteemed, is because
- of their tendency to be useful to the person who is possessed of
- them. 'Tis impossible to execute any design with success, where it is
- not conducted with prudence and discretion; nor will the goodness
- of our intentions alone suffice to procure us a happy issue to our
- enterprises. Men are superior to beasts principally by the superiority
- of their reason; and they are the degrees of the same faculty, which
- set such an infinite difference betwixt one man and another. All the
- advantages of art are owing to human reason; and where fortune is not
- very capricious, the most considerable part of these advantages must
- fall to the share of the prudent and sagacious.
- When it is asked, whether a quick or a slow apprehension be most
- valuable? whether one, that at first view penetrates into a subject,
- but can perform nothing upon study; or a contrary character, which must
- work out every thing by dint of application? whether a clear head, or
- a copious invention? whether a profound genius, or a sure judgment? in
- short, what character, or peculiar understanding, is more excellent
- than another? 'Tis evident we can answer none of these questions,
- without considering which of those qualities capacitates a man best for
- the world, and carries him farthest in any of his undertakings.
- There are many other qualities of the mind, whose merit is derived
- from the same origin. _Industry, perseverance, patience, activity,
- vigilance, application, constancy_, with other virtues of that kind,
- which 'twill be easy to recollect, are esteemed valuable upon no other
- account than their advantage in the conduct of life. 'Tis the same case
- with _temperance, frugality, economy, resolution_; as, on the other
- hand, _prodigality, luxury, irresolution, uncertainty_, are vicious,
- merely because they draw ruin upon us, and incapacitate us for business
- and action.
- As wisdom and good sense are valued because they are _useful_ to the
- person possessed of them, so _wit_ and _eloquence_ are valued because
- they are _immediately agreeable_ to others. On the other hand, _good
- humour_ is loved and esteemed, because it is _immediately agreeable_ to
- the person himself. 'Tis evident, that the conversation of a man of wit
- is very satisfactory; as a cheerful good-humoured companion diffuses
- a joy over the whole company, from a sympathy with his gaiety. These
- qualities, therefore, being agreeable, they naturally beget love and
- esteem, and answer to all the characters of virtue.
- 'Tis difficult to tell, on many occasions, what it is that renders one
- man's conversation so agreeable and entertaining, and another's so
- insipid and distasteful. As conversation is a transcript of the mind as
- well as books, the same qualities which render the one valuable must
- give us an esteem for the other. This we shall consider afterwards.
- In the mean time, it may be affirmed in general, that all the merit
- a man may derive from his conversation (which, no doubt, may be very
- considerable) arises from nothing but the pleasure it conveys to those
- who are present.
- In this view, _cleanliness_ is also to be regarded as a virtue,
- since it naturally renders us agreeable to others, and is a very
- considerable source of love and affection. No one will deny that a
- negligence in this particular is a fault; and as faults are nothing
- but smaller vices, and this fault can have no other origin than the
- uneasy sensation which it excites in others, we may in this instance,
- seemingly so trivial, clearly discover the origin of the moral
- distinction of vice and virtue in other instances.
- Besides all those qualities which render a person lovely or valuable,
- there is also a certain _je-ne-sçai-quoi_ of agreeable and handsome
- that concurs to the same effect. In this case, as well as in that of
- wit and eloquence, we must have recourse to a certain sense, which
- acts without reflection, and regards not the tendencies of qualities
- and characters. Some moralists account for all the sentiments of
- virtue by this sense. Their hypothesis is very plausible. Nothing but
- a particular inquiry can give the preference to any other hypothesis.
- When we find that almost all the virtues have such particular
- tendencies, and also find that these tendencies are sufficient alone to
- give a strong sentiment of approbation, we cannot doubt, after this,
- that qualities are approved of in proportion to the advantage which
- results from them.
- The _decorum_ or _indecorum_ of a quality, with regard to the age,
- or character, or station, contributes also to its praise or blame.
- This decorum depends in a great measure upon experience. 'Tis usual
- to see men lose their levity as they advance in years. Such a degree
- of gravity, therefore, and such years, are connected together in our
- thoughts. When we observe, them separated in any person's character,
- this imposes a kind of violence on our imagination, and is disagreeable.
- That faculty of the soul which, of all others, is of the least
- consequence to the character, and has the least virtue or vice in its
- several degrees, at the same time that it admits of a great variety
- of degrees, is the _memory_. Unless it rise up to that stupendous
- height as to surprise us, or sink so low as in some measure to affect
- the judgment, we commonly take no notice of its variations, nor ever
- mention them to the praise or dispraise of any person. 'Tis so far
- from being a virtue to have a good memory, that men generally affect
- to complain of a bad one; and, endeavouring to persuade the world
- that what they say is entirely of their own invention, sacrifice it
- to the praise of genius and judgment. Yet, to consider the matter
- abstractedly,'twould be difficult to give a reason why the faculty
- of recalling past ideas with truth and clearness, should not have as
- much merit in it as the faculty of placing our present ideas in such
- an order as to form true propositions and opinions. The reason of the
- difference certainly must be, that the memory is exerted without any
- sensation of pleasure or pain, and in all its middling degrees serves
- almost equally well in business and affairs. But the least variations
- in the judgment are sensibly felt in their consequences; while at
- the same time that faculty is never exerted in any eminent degree,
- without an extraordinary delight and satisfaction. The sympathy with
- this utility and pleasure bestows a merit on the understanding; and
- the absence of it makes us consider the memory as a faculty very
- indifferent to blame or praise.
- Before I leave this subject of _natural abilities_, I must observe,
- that perhaps one source of the esteem and affection which attends
- them, is derived from the _importance_ and _weight_ which they bestow
- on the person possessed of them. He becomes of greater consequence
- in life. His resolutions and actions affect a greater number of his
- fellow-creatures. Both his friendship and enmity are of moment. And
- 'tis easy to observe, that whoever is elevated, after this manner,
- above the rest of mankind, must excite in us the sentiments of esteem
- and approbation. Whatever is important engages our attention, fixes
- our thought, and is contemplated with satisfaction. The histories of
- kingdoms are more interesting than domestic stories; the histories of
- great empires more than those of small cities and principalities; and
- the histories of wars and revolutions more than those of peace and
- order. We sympathize with the persons that suffer, in all the various
- sentiments which belong to their fortunes. The mind is occupied by
- the multitude of the objects, and by the strong passions that display
- themselves. And this occupation or agitation of the mind is commonly
- agreeable and amusing. The same theory accounts for the esteem and
- regard we pay to men of extraordinary parts and abilities. The good
- and ill of multitudes are connected with their actions. Whatever they
- undertake is important, and challenges our attention. Nothing is to be
- overlooked and despised that regards them. And where any person can
- excite these sentiments, he soon acquires our esteem, unless other
- circumstances of his character render him odious and disagreeable.
- [6] Love and esteem are at the bottom the same passions, and arise from
- like causes. The qualities that produce both are agreeable, and give
- pleasure. But where this pleasure is severe and serious; or where its
- object is great, and makes a strong impression; or where it produces
- any degree of humility and awe: in all these cases, the passion which
- arises from the pleasure is more properly denominated esteem than love.
- Benevolence attends both; but is connected with love in a more eminent
- degree.
- SECTION V.
- SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING THE NATURAL VIRTUES.
- It has been observed, in treating of the Passions, that pride
- and humility, love and hatred, are excited by any advantages or
- disadvantages of the _mind, body_, or _fortune_; and that these
- advantages or disadvantages have that effect by producing a separate
- impression of pain or pleasure. The pain or pleasure which arises from
- the general survey or view of any action or quality of the _mind_,
- constitutes its vice or virtue, and gives rise to our approbation
- or blame, which is nothing but a fainter and more imperceptible love
- or hatred. We have assigned four different sources of this pain and
- pleasure; and, in order to justify more fully that hypothesis, it may
- here be proper to observe, that the advantages or disadvantages of
- the _body_ and of _fortune_, produce a pain or pleasure from the very
- same principles. The tendency of any object to be _useful_ to the
- person possessed of it, or to others; to convey _pleasure_ to him or
- to others; all these circumstances convey an immediate pleasure to the
- person who considers the object, and command his love and approbation.
- To begin with the advantages of the _body_; we may observe a phenomenon
- which might appear somewhat trivial and ludicrous, if any thing
- could be trivial which fortified a conclusion of such importance, or
- ludicrous, which was employed in a philosophical reasoning. 'Tis a
- general remark, that those we call good _women's men_, who have either
- signalized themselves by their amorous exploits, or whose make of body
- promises any extraordinary vigour of that kind, are well received by
- the fair sex, and naturally engage the affections even of those whose
- virtue prevents any design of ever giving employment to those talents.
- Here 'tis evident that the ability of such a person to give enjoyment,
- is the real source of that love and esteem he meets with among the
- females; at the same time that the women who love and esteem him have
- no prospect of receiving that enjoyment themselves, and can only be
- affected by means of their sympathy with one that has a commerce of
- love with him. This instance is singular, and merits our attention.
- Another source of the pleasure we receive from considering bodily
- advantages, is their utility to the person himself who is possessed of
- them. 'Tis certain, that a considerable part of the beauty of men, as
- well as of other animals, consists in such a conformation of members as
- we find by experience to be attended with strength and agility, and to
- capacitate the creature for any action or exercise. Broad shoulders,
- a lank belly, firm joints, taper legs; all these are beautiful in our
- species, because they are signs of force and vigour, which, being
- advantages we naturally sympathize with, they convey to the beholder a
- share of that satisfaction they produce in the possessor.
- So far as to the _utility_ which may attend any quality of the body.
- As to the immediate _pleasure_, 'tis certain that an air of health, as
- well as of strength and agility, makes a considerable part of beauty;
- and that a sickly air in another is always disagreeable, upon account
- of that idea of pain and uneasiness which it conveys to us. On the
- other hand, we are pleased with the regularity of our own features,
- though it be neither useful to ourselves nor others; and 'tis necessary
- for us in some measure to set ourselves at a distance, to make it
- convey to us any satisfaction. We commonly consider ourselves as we
- appear in the eyes of others, and sympathize with the advantageous
- sentiments they entertain with regard to us.
- How far the advantages of _fortune_ produce esteem and approbation
- from the same principles, we may satisfy ourselves by reflecting on
- our precedent reasoning on that subject. We have observed, that our
- approbation of those who are possessed of the advantages of fortune,
- may be ascribed to three different causes. _First_, To that immediate
- pleasure which a rich man gives us, by the view of the beautiful
- clothes, equipage, gardens, or houses, which he possesses. _Secondly_,
- To the advantage which we hope to reap from him by his generosity and
- liberality. _Thirdly_, To the pleasure and advantage which he himself
- reaps from his possessions, and which produce an agreeable sympathy
- in us. Whether we ascribe our esteem of the rich and great to one or
- all of these causes, we may clearly see the traces of those principles
- which give rise to the sense of vice and virtue. I believe most people,
- at first sight, will be inclined to ascribe our esteem of the rich
- to self-interest and the prospect of advantage. But as 'tis certain
- that our esteem or deference extends beyond any prospect of advantage
- to ourselves, 'tis evident that that sentiment must proceed from a
- sympathy with those who are dependent on the person we esteem and
- respect, and who have an immediate connexion with him. We consider him
- as a person capable of contributing to the happiness or enjoyment of
- his fellow-creatures, whose sentiments with regard to him we naturally
- embrace. And this consideration will serve to justify my hypothesis in
- preferring the _third_ principle to the other two, and ascribing our
- esteem of the rich to a sympathy with the pleasure and advantage which
- they themselves receive from their possessions. For as even the other
- two principles cannot operate to a due extent, or account for all the
- phenomena without having recourse to a sympathy of one kind or other,
- 'tis much more natural to choose that sympathy which is immediate and
- direct, than that which is remote and indirect. To which we may add,
- that where the riches or power are very great, and render the person
- considerable and important, in the world, tire esteem attending them
- may in part be ascribed to another source, distinct from these three,
- viz. their interesting the mind by a prospect of the multitude and
- importance of their consequences; though, in order to account for the
- operation of this principle, we must also have recourse to _sympathy_,
- as we have observed in the preceding section.
- It may not be amiss, on this occasion, to remark the flexibility of
- our sentiments, and the several changes they so readily receive from
- the objects with which they are conjoined. All the sentiments of
- approbation which attend any particular species of objects, have a
- great resemblance to each other, though derived from different sources;
- and, on the other hand, those sentiments, when directed to different
- objects, are different to the feeling, though derived from the same
- source. Thus, the beauty of all visible objects causes a pleasure
- pretty much the same, though it be sometimes derived from the mere
- _species_ and appearance of the objects; sometimes from sympathy,
- and an idea of their utility. In like manner, whenever we survey the
- actions and characters of men, without any particular interest in them,
- the pleasure or pain which arises from the survey (with some minute
- differences) is in the main of the same kind, though perhaps there be
- a great diversity in the causes from which it is derived. On the other
- hand, a convenient house and a virtuous character cause not the same
- feeling of approbation, even though the source of our approbation be
- the same, and flow from sympathy and an idea of their utility. There
- is something very inexplicable in this variation of our feelings; but
- 'tis what we have experience of with regard to all our passions and
- sentiments.
- SECTION VI.
- CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK.
- Thus, upon the whole, I am hopeful that nothing is wanting to an
- accurate proof of this system of ethics. We are certain that sympathy
- is a very powerful principle in human nature. We are also certain
- that it has a great influence on our sense of beauty, when we regard
- external objects, as well as when we judge of morals. We find that
- it has force sufficient to give us the strongest sentiments of
- approbation, when it operates alone, without the concurrence of any
- other principle; as in the cases of justice, allegiance, chastity, and
- good manners. We may observe, that all the circumstances requisite for
- its operation are found in most of the virtues, which have, for the
- most part, a tendency to the good of society, or to that of the person
- possessed of them. If we compare all these circumstances, we shall
- not doubt that sympathy is the chief source of moral distinctions;
- especially when we reflect, that no objection can be raised against
- this hypothesis in one case, which will not extend to all cases.
- Justice is certainly approved of, for no other reason than because it
- has a tendency to the public good; and the public good is indifferent
- to us, except so far as sympathy interests us in it. We may presume the
- like with regard to all the other virtues, which have a like tendency
- to the public good. They must derive all their merit from our sympathy
- with those who reap any advantage from them; as the virtues, which have
- a tendency to the good of the person possessed of them, derive their
- merit from our sympathy with him.
- Most people will readily allow, that the useful qualities of the
- mind are virtuous, because of their utility. This way of thinking is
- so natural, and occurs on so many occasions, that few will make any
- scruple of admitting it. Now, this being once admitted, the force of
- sympathy must necessarily be acknowledged. Virtue is considered as
- means to an end. Means to an end are only valued so far as the end is
- valued. But the happiness of strangers affects us by sympathy alone.
- To that principle, therefore, we are to ascribe the sentiment of
- approbation which arises from the survey of all those virtues that are
- useful to society, or to the person possessed of them. These form the
- most considerable part of morality.
- Were it proper, in such a subject, to bribe the reader's assent, or
- employ any thing but solid argument, we are here abundantly supplied
- with topics to engage the affections. All lovers of virtue (and such
- we all are in speculation, however we may degenerate in practice)
- must certainly be pleased to see moral distinctions derived from so
- noble a source, which gives us a just notion both of the _generosity_
- and _capacity_ of human nature. It requires but very little knowledge
- of human affairs to perceive, that a sense of morals is a principle
- inherent in the soul, and one of the most powerful that enters into
- the composition. But this sense must certainly acquire new force when,
- reflecting on itself, it approves of those principles from whence it is
- derived, and finds nothing but what is great and good in its rise and
- origin. Those who resolve the sense of morals into original instincts
- of the human mind, may defend the cause of virtue with sufficient
- authority, but want the advantage which those possess who account for
- that sense by an extensive sympathy with mankind. According to their
- system, not only virtue must be approved of, but also the sense of
- virtue: and not only that sense, but also the principles from whence
- it is derived. So that nothing is presented on any side but what is
- laudable and good.
- This observation may be extended to justice, and the other virtues of
- that kind. Though justice be artificial, the sense of its morality is
- natural. 'Tis the combination of men in a system of conduct, which
- renders any act of justice beneficial to society. But when once it has
- that tendency, we _naturally_ approve of it; and if we did not so,
- 'tis impossible any combination or convention could ever produce that
- sentiment.
- Most of the inventions of men are subject to change. They depend upon
- humour and caprice. They have a vogue for a time, and then sink into
- oblivion. It may perhaps be apprehended, that if justice were allowed
- to be a human invention, it must be placed on the same footing. But the
- cases are widely different. The interest on which justice is founded is
- the greatest imaginable, and extends to all times and places. It cannot
- possibly be served by any other invention. It is obvious, and discovers
- itself on the very first formation of society. All these causes render
- the rules of justice steadfast and immutable; at least, as immutable
- as human nature. And if they were founded on original instincts, could
- they have any greater stability?
- The same system may help us to form a just notion of the _happiness_,
- as well as of the _dignity_ of virtue, and may interest every principle
- of our nature in the embracing and cherishing that noble quality. Who
- indeed does not feel an accession of alacrity in his pursuits of
- knowledge and ability of every kind, when he considers, that besides
- the advantages which immediately result from these acquisitions, they
- also give him a new lustre in the eyes of mankind, and are universally
- attended with esteem and approbation? And who can think any advantages
- of fortune a sufficient compensation for the least breach of the
- _social_ virtues, when he considers, that not only his character with
- regard to others, but also his peace and inward satisfaction entirely
- depend upon his strict observance of them; and that a mind will never
- be able to bear its own survey, that has been wanting in its parts to
- mankind and society? But I forbear insisting on this subject. Such
- reflections require a work apart, very different from the genius of
- the present. The anatomist ought never to emulate the painter; nor
- in his accurate dissections and portraitures of the smaller parts of
- the human body, pretend to give his figures any graceful and engaging
- attitude or expression. There is even something hideous, or at least
- minute, in the views of things which he presents; and 'tis necessary
- the objects should be set more at a distance, and be more covered
- up from sight, to make them engaging to the eye and imagination. An
- anatomist, however, is admirably fitted to give advice to a painter;
- and 'tis even impracticable to excel in the latter art, without the
- assistance of the former. We must have an exact knowledge of the parts,
- their situation and connection, before we can design with any elegance
- or correctness. And thus the most abstract speculations concerning
- human nature, however cold and unentertaining, become subservient to
- _practical morality_; and may render this latter science more correct
- in its precepts, and more persuasive in its exhortations.
- See Appendix at the end of the volume.
- DIALOGUES
- CONCERNING
- NATURAL RELIGION
- PAMPHILUS TO HERMIPPUS.
- It has been remarked, my Hermippus, that though the ancient
- philosophers conveyed most of their instruction in the form of
- dialogue, this method of composition has been little practised in
- later ages, and has seldom succeeded in the hands of those who have
- attempted it. Accurate and regular argument, indeed, such as is now
- expected of philosophical inquirers, naturally throws a man into the
- methodical and didactic manner; where he can immediately, without
- preparation, explain the point at which he aims; and thence proceed,
- without interruption, to deduce the proofs on which it is established.
- To deliver a *SYSTEM in conversation, scarcely appears natural; and
- while the dialogue-writer desires, by departing from the direct style
- of composition, to give a freer air to his performance, and avoid the
- appearance of _Author_ and _Reader_, he is apt to run into a worse
- inconvenience, and convey the image of _Pedagogue_ and _Pupil_. Or,
- if he carries on the dispute in the natural spirit of good company,
- by throwing in a variety of topics, and preserving a proper balance
- among the speakers, he often loses so much time in preparations and
- transitions, that the reader will scarcely think himself compensated,
- by all the graces of dialogue, for the order, brevity and precision,
- which are sacrificed to them.
- There are some subjects, however, to which dialogue-writing is
- peculiarly adapted, and where it is still preferable to the direct and
- simple method of composition.
- Any point of doctrine, which is so _obvious_ that it scarcely admits
- of dispute, but at the same time so _important_ that it cannot be too
- often inculcated, seems to require some such method of handling it;
- where the novelty of the manner may compensate the triteness of the
- subject; where the vivacity of conversation may enforce the precept;
- and where the variety of lights, presented by various personages and
- characters, may appear neither tedious nor redundant.
- Any question of philosophy, on the other hand, which is so _obscure_
- and _uncertain_, that human reason, can reach no fixed determination
- with regard to it; if it should be treated at all, seems to lead us
- naturally into the style of dialogue and conversation. Reasonable men
- may be allowed to differ, where no one can reasonably be positive:
- Opposite sentiments, even without any decision, afford an agreeable
- amusement; and if the subject be curious and interesting, the book
- carries us, in a manner, into company; and unites the two greatest and
- purest pleasures of human life, study and society.
- Happily, these circumstances are all to be found in the subject of
- NATURAL RELIGION. What truth so obvious, so certain, as the being of a
- God, which the most ignorant ages have acknowledged, for which the most
- refined geniuses have ambitiously striven to produce new proofs and
- arguments? What truth so important as this, which is the ground of all
- our hopes, the surest foundation of morality, the firmest support of
- society, and the only principle which ought never to be a moment absent
- from our thoughts and meditations? But, in treating of this obvious and
- important truth, what obscure questions occur concerning the nature of
- that Divine Being, his attributes, his decrees, his plan of providence?
- These have been always subjected to the disputations of men; concerning
- these human reason has not reached any certain determination. But
- these are topics so interesting, that we cannot restrain our restless
- inquiry with regard to them; though nothing but doubt, uncertainty
- and contradiction, have as yet been the result of our most accurate
- researches.
- This I had lately occasion to observe, while I passed, as usual,
- part of the summer season with Cleanthes, and was present at those
- conversations of his with Philo and Demea, of which I gave you lately
- some imperfect account. Your curiosity, you then told me, was so
- excited, that I must, of necessity, enter into a more exact detail of
- their reasonings, and display those various systems which they advanced
- with regard to so delicate a subject as that of natural religion. The
- remarkable contrast in their characters still farther raised your
- expectations; while you opposed the accurate philosophical turn of
- Cleanthes to the careless scepticism of Philo, or compared either of
- their dispositions with the rigid inflexible orthodoxy of Demea. My
- youth rendered me a mere auditor of their disputes; and that curiosity,
- natural to the early season of life, has so deeply imprinted in my
- memory the whole chain and connexion of their arguments, that, I hope,
- I shall not omit or confound any considerable part of them in the
- recital.
- PART I.
- After I joined the company, whom I found sitting in Cleanthes's
- library, Demea paid Cleanthes some compliments on the great care
- which he took of my education, and on his unwearied perseverance and
- constancy in all his friendships. The father of Pamphilus, said he, was
- your intimate friend: The son is your pupil; and may indeed be regarded
- as your adopted son, were we to judge by the pains which you bestow in
- conveying to him every useful branch of literature and science. You
- are no more wanting, I am persuaded, in prudence than in industry. I
- shall, therefore, communicate to you a maxim, which I have observed
- with regard to my own children, that I may learn how far it agrees with
- your practice. The method I follow in their education is founded on
- the saying of an ancient, 'That students of philosophy ought first to
- learn logics, then ethics, next physics, last of all the nature of the
- gods.'[1] This science of natural theology, according to him, being the
- most profound and abstruse of any, required the maturest judgment in
- its students; and none but a mind enriched with all the other sciences,
- can safely be intrusted with it.
- Are you so late, says Philo, in teaching your children the principles
- of religion? Is there no danger of their neglecting, or rejecting
- altogether those opinions of which they have heard so little during
- the whole course of their education? It is only as a science, replied
- Demea, subjected to human reasoning and disputation, that I postpone
- the study of Natural Theology. To season their minds with early piety,
- is my chief care; and by continual precept and instruction, and I hope
- too by example, I imprint deeply on their tender minds an habitual
- reverence for all the principles of religion. While they pass through
- every other science, I still remark the uncertainty of each part;
- the eternal disputations of men; the obscurity of all philosophy;
- and the strange, ridiculous conclusions, which some of the greatest
- geniuses have derived from the principles of mere human reason. Having
- thus tamed their mind to a proper submission and self-diffidence, I
- have no longer any scruple of opening to them the greatest mysteries
- of religion; nor apprehend any danger from that assuming arrogance
- of philosophy, which may lead them to reject the most established
- doctrines and opinions.
- Your precaution, says, Philo, of seasoning your childrens minds early
- with piety, is certainly very reasonable; and no more than is requisite
- in this profane and irreligious age. But what I chiefly admire in your
- plan of education, is your method of drawing advantage from the very
- principles of philosophy and learning, which, by inspiring pride and
- self-sufficiency, have commonly, in all ages, been found so destructive
- to the principles of religion. The vulgar, indeed, we may remark, who
- are unacquainted with science and profound inquiry, observing the
- endless disputes of the learned, have commonly a thorough contempt for
- philosophy; and rivet themselves the faster, by that means, in the
- great points of theology which have been taught them. Those who enter
- a little into study and inquiry, finding many appearances of evidence
- in doctrines the newest and most extraordinary, think nothing too
- difficult for human reason; and, presumptuously breaking through all
- fences, profane the inmost sanctuaries of the temple. But Cleanthes
- will, I hope, agree with me, that, after we have abandoned ignorance,
- the surest remedy, there is still one expedient left to prevent this
- profane liberty. Let Demea's principles be improved and cultivated:
- Let us become thoroughly sensible of the weakness, blindness, and
- narrow limits of human reason: Let us duly consider its uncertainty and
- endless contrarieties, even in subjects of common life and practice:
- Let the errors and deceits of our very senses be set before us; the
- insuperable difficulties which attend first principles in all systems;
- the contradictions which adhere to the very ideas of matter, cause and
- effect, extension, space, time, motion; and in a word, quantity of all
- kinds, the object of the only science that can fairly pretend to any
- certainty or evidence. When these topics are displayed in their full
- light, as they are by some philosophers and almost all divines; who
- can retain such confidence in this frail faculty of reason as to pay
- any regard to its determinations in points so sublime, so abstruse,
- so remote from common life and experience? When the coherence of the
- parts of a stone, or even that composition of parts which renders it
- extended; when these familiar objects, I say, are so inexplicable,
- and contain circumstances so repugnant and contradictory; with what
- assurance can we decide concerning the origin of worlds, or trace their
- history from eternity to eternity?
- While Philo pronounced these words, I could observe a smile in the
- countenance both of Demea and Cleanthes. That of Demea seemed to
- imply an unreserved satisfaction in the doctrines delivered: But, in
- Cleanthes's features, I could distinguish an air of finesse; as if he
- perceived some raillery or artificial malice in the reasonings of Philo.
- You propose then, Philo, said Cleanthes, to erect religious faith on
- philosophical scepticism; and you think, that if certainty or evidence
- be expelled from every other subject of inquiry, it will all retire to
- these theological doctrines, and there acquire a superior force and
- authority. Whether your scepticism be as absolute and sincere as you
- pretend, we shall learn by and by, when the company breaks up: We shall
- then see, whether you go out at the door or the window; and whether
- you really doubt if your body has gravity, or can be injured by its
- fall; according to popular opinion, derived from our fallacious senses,
- and more fallacious experience. And this consideration, Demea, may, I
- think, fairly serve to abate our ill-will to this humorous sect of the
- sceptics. If they be thoroughly in earnest, they will not long trouble
- the world with their doubts, cavils, and disputes: If they be only in
- jest, they are, perhaps, bad railers; but can never be very dangerous,
- either to the state, to philosophy, or to religion.
- In reality, Philo, continued he, it seems certain, that though a
- man, in a flush of humour, after intense reflection on the many
- contradictions and imperfections of human reason, may entirely renounce
- all belief and opinion, it is impossible for him to persevere in
- this total scepticism, or make it appear in his conduct for a few
- hours. External objects press in upon him; passions solicit him; his
- philosophical melancholy dissipates; and even the utmost violence upon
- his own temper will not be able, during any time, to preserve the poor
- appearance of scepticism. And for what reason impose on himself such
- a violence? This is a point in which it will be impossible for him
- ever to satisfy himself, consistently with his sceptical principles.
- So that, upon the whole, nothing could be more ridiculous than the
- principles of the ancient Pyrrhonians; if in reality they endeavoured,
- as is pretended, to extend, throughout, the same scepticism which they
- had learned from the declamations of their schools, and which they
- ought to have confined to them.
- In this view, there appears a great resemblance between the sects of
- the Stoics and Pyrrhonians, though perpetual antagonists; and both
- of them seem founded on this erroneous maxim, That what a man can
- perform sometimes, and in some dispositions, he can perform always,
- and in every disposition. When the mind, by Stoical reflections, is
- elevated into a sublime enthusiasm of virtue, and strongly smit with
- any _species_ of honour or public good, the utmost bodily pain and
- sufferings will not prevail over such a high sense of duty; and it is
- possible, perhaps, by its means, even to smile and exult in the midst
- of tortures. If this sometimes may be the case in fact and reality,
- much more may a philosopher, in his school, or even in his closet,
- work himself up to such an enthusiasm, and support in imagination the
- acutest pain or most calamitous event which he can possibly conceive.
- But how shall he support this enthusiasm itself? The bent of his mind
- relaxes, and cannot be recalled at pleasure; avocations lead him
- astray; misfortunes attack him unawares; and the _philosopher_ sinks
- by degrees into the _plebeian_.
- I allow of your comparison between the Stoics and Sceptics, replied
- Philo. But you may observe, at the same time, that though the mind
- cannot, in Stoicism, support the highest flights of philosophy, yet,
- even when it sinks lower, it still retains somewhat of its former
- disposition; and the effects of the Stoic's reasoning will appear in
- his conduct in common life, and through the whole tenor of his actions.
- The ancient schools, particularly that of Zeno, produced examples of
- virtue and constancy which seem astonishing to present times.
- Vain Wisdom all and false Philosophy.
- Yet with a pleasing sorcery could charm
- Pain, for a while, or anguish; and excite
- Fallacious Hope, or arm the obdurate breast
- With stubborn Patience, as with triple steel.
- In like manner, if a man has accustomed himself to sceptical
- considerations on the uncertainty and narrow limits of reason, he
- will not entirely forget them when he turns his reflection on other
- subjects; but in all his philosophical principles and reasoning, I dare
- not say in his common conduct, he will be found different from those,
- who either never formed any opinions in the case, or have entertained
- sentiments more favourable to human reason.
- To whatever length any one may push his speculative principles of
- scepticism, he must act, I own, and live, and converse, like other men;
- and for this conduct he is not obliged to give any other reason, than
- the absolute necessity he lies under of so doing. If he ever carries
- his speculations farther than this necessity constrains him, and
- philosophizes either on natural or moral subjects, he is allured by a
- certain pleasure and satisfaction which he finds in employing himself
- after that manner. He considers besides, that every one, even in common
- life, is constrained to have more or less of this philosophy; that
- from our earliest infancy we make continual advances in forming more
- general principles of conduct and reasoning; that the larger experience
- we acquire, and the stronger reason we are endued with, we always
- render our principles the more general and comprehensive; and that
- what we call _philosophy_ is nothing but a more regular and methodical
- operation of the same kind. To philosophize on such subjects, is
- nothing essentially different from reasoning on common life; and we
- may only expect greater stability, if not greater truth, from our
- philosophy, on account of its exacter and more scrupulous method of
- proceeding.
- But when we look beyond human affairs and the properties of the
- surrounding bodies: when we carry our speculations into the two
- eternities, before and after the present state of things; into the
- creation and formation of the universe; the existence and properties of
- spirits; the powers and operations, of one universal Spirit existing
- without beginning and without end; omnipotent, omniscient, immutable,
- infinite and incomprehensible: We must be far removed from the smallest
- tendency to scepticism not to be apprehensive, that we have here got
- quite beyond the reach of our faculties. So long as we confine our
- speculations to trade, or morals, or politics, or criticism, we make
- appeals, every moment, to common sense and experience, which strengthen
- our philosophical conclusions, and remove, at least in part, the
- suspicion which we so justly entertain with regard to every reasoning
- that is very subtile and refined. But, in theological reasonings, we
- have not this advantage; while, at the same time, we are employed upon
- objects, which, we must be sensible, are too large for our grasp, and
- of all others require most to be familiarized to our apprehension. We
- are like foreigners in a strange country, to whom every thing must seem
- suspicious, and who are in danger every moment of transgressing against
- the laws and customs of the people with whom they live and converse. We
- know not how far we ought to trust our vulgar methods of reasoning in
- such a subject; since, even in common life, and in that province which
- is peculiarly appropriated to them, we cannot account for them, and are
- entirely guided by a kind of instinct or necessity in employing them.
- All sceptics pretend, that, if reason be considered in an abstract
- view, it furnishes invincible arguments against itself: and that we
- could never retain any conviction or assurance, on any subject, were
- not the sceptical reasonings so refined and subtile, that they are
- not able to counterpoise the more solid and more natural arguments
- derived from the senses and experience. But it is evident, whenever our
- arguments lose this advantage, and run wide of common life, that the
- most refined scepticism comes to be upon a footing with them, and is
- able to oppose and counterbalance them. The one has no more weight than
- the other. The mind must remain in suspense between them; and it is
- that very suspense or balance, which is the triumph of scepticism.
- But I observe, says Cleanthes, with regard to you, Philo, and all
- speculative sceptics, that your doctrine and practice are as much at
- variance in the most abstruse points of theory as in the conduct of
- common life. Wherever evidence discovers itself, you adhere to it,
- notwithstanding your pretended scepticism; and I can observe, too, some
- of your sect to be as decisive as those who make greater professions of
- certainty and assurance. In reality, would not a man be ridiculous, who
- pretended to reject Newton's explication of the wonderful phenomenon
- of the rainbow, because that explication gives a minute anatomy
- of the rays of light; a subject, forsooth, too refined for human
- comprehension? And what would you say to one, who, having nothing
- particular to object to the arguments of Copernicus and Galilæo for
- the motion of the earth, should withhold his assent, on that general
- principle, that these subjects were too magnificent and remote to be
- explained by the narrow and fallacious reason of mankind?
- There is indeed a kind of brutish and ignorant scepticism, as you well
- observed, which gives the vulgar a general prejudice against what they
- do not easily understand, and makes them reject every principle which
- requires elaborate reasoning to prove and establish it. This species of
- scepticism is fatal to knowledge, not to religion; since we find, that
- those who make greatest profession of it, give often their assent, not
- only to the great truths of Theism and natural theology, but even to
- the most absurd tenets which a traditional superstition has recommended
- to them. They firmly believe in witches, though they will not believe
- nor attend to the most simple proposition of Euclid. But the refined
- and philosophical sceptics fall into an inconsistence of an opposite
- nature. They push their researches into the most abstruse corners of
- science; and their assent attends them in every step, proportioned
- to the evidence which they meet with. They are even obliged to
- acknowledge, that the most abstruse and remote objects are those which
- are best explained by philosophy. Light is in reality anatomized: The
- true system of the heavenly bodies is discovered and ascertained. But
- the nourishment of bodies by food is still an inexplicable mystery:
- The cohesion of the parts of matter is still incomprehensible. These
- sceptics, therefore, are obliged, in every question, to consider
- each particular evidence apart, and proportion their assent to the
- precise degree of evidence which occurs. This is their practice in all
- natural, mathematical, moral, and political science. And why not the
- same, I ask, in the theological and religious? Why must conclusions
- of this nature be alone rejected on the general presumption of the
- insufficiency of human reason, without any particular discussion of the
- evidence? Is not such an unequal conduct a plain proof of prejudice and
- passion?
- Our senses, you say, are fallacious; our understanding erroneous; our
- ideas, even of the most familiar objects, extension, duration, motion,
- full of absurdities and contradictions. You defy me to solve the
- difficulties, or reconcile the repugnancies which you discover in them.
- I have not capacity for so great an undertaking: I have not leisure
- for it: I perceive it to be superfluous. Your own conduct, in every
- circumstance, refutes your principles, and shows the firmest reliance
- on all the received maxims of science, morals, prudence, and behaviour.
- I shall never assent to so harsh an opinion as that of a celebrated
- writer,[2] who says, that the Sceptics are not a sect of philosophers:
- They are only a sect of liars. I may, however, affirm (I hope without
- offence), that they are a sect of jesters or railers. But for my
- part, whenever I find myself disposed to mirth and amusement, I shall
- certainly choose my entertainment of a less perplexing and abstruse
- nature. A comedy, a novel, or at most a history, seems a more natural
- recreation than such metaphysical subtilties and abstractions.
- In vain would the sceptic make a distinction between science and common
- life, or between one science and another. The arguments employed in
- all, if just, are of a similar nature, and contain the same force and
- evidence. Or if there be any difference among them, the advantage lies
- entirely on the side of theology and natural religion. Many principles
- of mechanics are founded on very abstruse reasoning; yet no man who has
- any pretensions to science, even no speculative sceptic, pretends to
- entertain the least doubt with regard to them. The Copernican system
- contains the most surprising paradox, and the most contrary to our
- natural conceptions, to appearances, and to our very senses: yet even
- monks and inquisitors are now constrained to withdraw their opposition
- to it. And shall Philo, a man of so liberal a genius and extensive
- knowledge, entertain any general undistinguished scruples with regard
- to the religious hypothesis, which is founded on the simplest and most
- obvious arguments, and, unless it meets with artificial obstacles, has
- such easy access and admission into the mind of man?
- And here we may observe, continued he, turning himself towards Demea,
- a pretty curious circumstance in the history of the sciences. After
- the union of philosophy with the popular religion, upon the first
- establishment of Christianity, nothing was more usual, among all
- religious teachers, than declamations against reason, against the
- senses, against every principle derived merely from human research
- and inquiry. All the topics of the ancient academics were adopted by
- the fathers; and thence propagated for several ages in every school
- and pulpit throughout Christendom. The Reformers embraced the same
- principles of reasoning, or rather declamation; and all panegyrics on
- the excellency of faith, were sure to be interlarded with some severe
- strokes of satire against natural reason. A celebrated prelate too,[3]
- of the Romish communion, a man of the most extensive learning, who
- wrote a demonstration of Christianity, has also composed a treatise,
- which contains all the cavils of the boldest and most determined
- Pyrrhonism. Locke seems to have been the first Christian who ventured
- openly to assert, that _faith_ was nothing but a species of _reason_;
- that religion was only a branch of philosophy; and that a chain of
- arguments, similar to that which established any truth in morals,
- politics, or physics, was always employed in discovering all the
- principles of theology, natural and revealed. The ill use which Bayle
- and other libertines made of the philosophical scepticism of the
- fathers and first reformers, still farther propagated the judicious
- sentiment of Mr Locke: And it is now in a manner avowed, by all
- pretenders to reasoning and philosophy, that Atheist and Sceptic are
- almost synonymous. And as it is certain that no man is in earnest when
- he professes the latter principle, I would fain hope that there are as
- few who seriously maintain the former.
- Don't you remember, said Philo, the excellent saying of Lord Bacon
- on this head? That a little philosophy, replied Cleanthes, makes a
- man an Atheist: A great deal converts him to religion. That is a very
- judicious remark too, said Philo. But what I have in my eye is another
- passage, where, having mentioned David's fool, who said in his heart
- there is no God, this great philosopher observes, that the Atheists
- now-a-days have a double share of folly; for they are not contented to
- say in their hearts there is no God, but they also utter that impiety
- with their lips, and are thereby guilty of multiplied indiscretion and
- imprudence. Such people, though they were ever so much in earnest,
- cannot, methinks, be very formidable.
- But though you should rank me in this class of fools, I cannot forbear
- communicating a remark that occurs to me, from the history of the
- religious and irreligious scepticism with which you have entertained
- us. It appears to me, that there are strong symptoms of priestcraft in
- the whole progress of this affair. During ignorant ages, such as those
- which followed the dissolution of the ancient schools, the priests
- perceived, that Atheism, Deism, or heresy of any kind, could only
- proceed from the presumptuous questioning of received opinions, and
- from a belief that human reason was equal to every thing. Education had
- then a mighty influence over the minds of men, and was almost equal in
- force to those suggestions of the senses and common understanding, by
- which the most determined sceptic must allow himself to be governed.
- But at present, when the influence of education is much diminished,
- and men, from a more open commerce of the world, have learned to
- compare the popular principles of different nations and ages, our
- sagacious divines have changed their whole system of philosophy, and
- talk the language of Stoics, Platonists, and Peripatetics, not that of
- Pyrrhonians and Academics. If we distrust human reason, we have now no
- other principle to lead us into religion. Thus, sceptics in one age,
- dogmatists in another; whichever system best suits the purpose of these
- reverend gentlemen, in giving them an ascendant over mankind, they are
- sure to make it their favourite principle, and established tenet.
- It is very natural, said Cleanthes, for men to embrace those
- principles, by which they find they can best defend their doctrines;
- nor need we have any recourse to priestcraft to account for so
- reasonable an expedient. And, surely nothing can afford a stronger
- presumption, that any set of principles are true, and ought to be
- embraced, than to observe that they tend to the confirmation of true
- religion, and serve to confound the cavils of Atheists, Libertines, and
- Freethinkers of all denominations.
- [1] Chrysippus apud Plut. de repug. Stoicorum.
- [2] L'art de penser.
- [3] Mons. Huet.
- PART II.
- I must own, Cleanthes, said Demea, that nothing can more surprise
- me, than the light in which you have all along put this argument.
- By the whole tenor of your discourse, one would imagine that you
- were maintaining the Being of a God, against the cavils of Atheists
- and Infidels; and were necessitated to become a champion for that
- fundamental principle of all religion. But this, I hope, is not by any
- means a question among us. No man, no man at least of common sense,
- I am persuaded, ever entertained a serious doubt with regard to a
- truth so certain and self-evident. The question is not concerning the
- *BEING, but the $NATURE of *GOD. This, I affirm, from the infirmities
- of human understanding, to be altogether incomprehensible and unknown
- to us. The essence of that supreme Mind, his attributes, the manner
- of his existence, the very nature of his duration; these, and every
- particular which regards so divine a Being, are mysterious to men.
- Finite, weak, and blind creatures, we ought to humble ourselves in his
- august presence; and, conscious of our frailties, adore in silence his
- infinite perfections, which eye hath not seen, ear hath not heard,
- neither hath it entered into the heart of man to conceive. They are
- covered in a deep cloud from human curiosity: It is profaneness to
- attempt penetrating through these sacred obscurities: And, next to the
- impiety of denying his existence, is the temerity of prying into his
- nature and essence, decrees and attributes.
- But lest you should think that my _piety_ has here got the better of my
- _philosophy_, I shall support my opinion, if it needs any support, by
- a very great authority. I might cite all the divines, almost, from the
- foundation of Christianity, who have ever treated of this or any other
- theological subject: But I shall confine myself, at present, to one
- equally celebrated for piety and philosophy. It is Father Malebranche,
- who, I remember, thus expresses himself.[1] 'One ought not so much,'
- says he, 'to call God a spirit, in order to express positively what
- he is, as in order to signify that he is not matter. He is a Being
- infinitely perfect: Of this we cannot doubt. But in the same manner
- as we ought not to imagine, even supposing him corporeal, that he is
- clothed with a human body, as the Anthropomorphites asserted, under
- colour that that figure was the most perfect of any; so, neither
- ought we to imagine that the spirit of God has human ideas, or bears
- any resemblance to our spirit, under colour that we know nothing
- more perfect than a human mind. We ought rather to believe, that as
- he comprehends the perfections of matter without being material....
- he comprehends also the perfections of created spirits without being
- spirit, in the manner we conceive spirit: That his true name is, _He
- that is_; or, in other words, Being without restriction, All Being, the
- Being infinite and universal.'
- After so great an authority, Demea, replied Philo, as that which
- you have produced, and a thousand more which you might produce, it
- would appear ridiculous in me to add my sentiment, or express my
- approbation of your doctrine. But surely, where reasonable men treat
- these subjects, the question can never be concerning the _Being_,
- but only the _Nature_, of the Deity. The former truth, as you well
- observe, is unquestionable and self-evident. Nothing exists without a
- cause; and the original cause of this universe (whatever it be) we call
- God; and piously ascribe to him every species of perfection. Whoever
- scruples this fundamental truth, deserves every punishment which
- can be inflicted among philosophers, to wit, the greatest ridicule,
- contempt, and disapprobation. But as all perfection is entirely
- relative, we ought never to imagine that we comprehend the attributes
- of this divine Being, or to suppose that his perfections have any
- analogy or likeness to the perfections of a human creature. Wisdom,
- Thought, Design, Knowledge; these we justly ascribe to him; because
- these words are honourable among men, and we have no other language
- or other conceptions by which we can express our adoration of him.
- But let us beware, lest we think that our ideas anywise correspond to
- his perfections, or that his attributes have any resemblance to these
- qualities among men. He is infinitely superior to our limited view and
- comprehension; and is more the object of worship in the temple, than of
- disputation in the schools.
- In reality, Cleanthes, continued he, there is no need of having
- recourse to that affected scepticism so displeasing to you, in order
- to come at this determination. Our ideas reach no farther than our
- experience: We have no experience of divine attributes and operations:
- I need not conclude my syllogism: You can draw the inference yourself.
- And it is a pleasure to me (and I hope to you too) that just reasoning
- and sound piety here concur in the same conclusion, and both of them
- establish the adorably mysterious and incomprehensible nature of the
- Supreme Being.
- Not to lose any time in circumlocutions, said Cleanthes, addressing
- himself to Demea, much less in replying to the pious declamations of
- Philo; I shall briefly explain how I conceive this matter. Look round
- the world: contemplate the whole and every part of it: You will find it
- to be nothing but one great machine, subdivided into an infinite number
- of lesser machines, which again admit of subdivisions to a degree
- beyond what human senses and faculties can trace and explain. All these
- various machines, and even their most minute parts, are adjusted to
- each other with an accuracy which ravishes into admiration all men who
- have ever contemplated them. The curious adapting of means to ends,
- throughout all nature, resembles exactly, though it much exceeds, the
- productions of human contrivance; of human design, thought, wisdom,
- and intelligence. Since therefore the effects resemble each other, we
- are led to infer, by all the rules of analogy, that the causes also
- resemble; and that the Author of Nature is somewhat similar to the
- mind of man, though possessed of much larger faculties, proportioned
- to the grandeur of the work which he has executed. By this argument
- _a posteriori_, and by this argument alone, do we prove at once the
- existence of a Deity, and his similarity to human mind and intelligence.
- I shall be so free, Cleanthes, said Demea, as to tell you, that from
- the beginning I could not approve of your conclusion concerning the
- similarity of the Deity to men; still less can I approve of the mediums
- by which you endeavour to establish it. What! No demonstration of
- the Being of God! No abstract arguments! No proofs _a priori_! Are
- these, which have hitherto been so much insisted on by philosophers,
- all fallacy, all sophism? Can we reach no farther in this subject than
- experience and probability? I will not say that this is betraying
- the cause of a Deity; But surely, by this affected candour, you give
- advantages to Atheists, which they never could obtain by the mere dint
- of argument and reasoning.
- What I chiefly scruple in this subject, said Philo, is not so much
- that all religious arguments are by Cleanthes reduced to experience,
- as that they appear not to be even the most certain and irrefragable
- of that inferior kind. That a stone will fall, that fire will burn,
- that the earth has solidity, we have observed a thousand and a thousand
- times; and when any new instance of this nature is presented, we draw
- without hesitation the accustomed inference. The exact similarity
- of the cases gives us a perfect assurance of a similar event; and a
- stronger evidence is never desired nor sought after. But wherever you
- depart, in the least, from the similarity of the cases, you diminish
- proportionably the evidence; and may at last bring it to a very weak
- _analogy_, which is confessedly liable to error and uncertainty. After
- having experienced the circulation of the blood in human creatures, we
- make no doubt that it takes place in Titius and Mævius: But from its
- circulation in frogs and fishes, it is only a presumption, though a
- strong one, from analogy, that it takes place in men and other animals.
- The analogical reasoning is much weaker, when we infer the circulation
- of the sap in vegetables from our experience that the blood circulates
- in animals; and those, who hastily followed that imperfect analogy, are
- found, by more accurate experiments, to have been mistaken.
- If we see a house, Cleanthes, we conclude, with the greatest certainty,
- that it had an architect or builder; because this is precisely that
- species of effect which we have experienced to proceed from that
- species of cause. But surely you will not affirm, that the universe
- bears such a resemblance to a house, that we can with the same
- certainty infer a similar cause, or that the analogy is here entire and
- perfect. The dissimilitude is so striking, that the utmost you can here
- pretend to is a guess, a conjecture, a presumption concerning a similar
- cause; and how that pretension will be received in the world, I leave
- you to consider.
- It would surely be very ill received, replied Cleanthes; and I should
- be deservedly blamed and detested, did I allow, that the proofs of a
- Deity amounted to no more than a guess or conjecture. But is the whole
- adjustment of means to ends in a house and in the universe so slight a
- resemblance? The economy of final causes? The order, proportion, and
- arrangement of every part? Steps of a stair are plainly contrived, that
- human legs may use them in mounting; and this inference is certain and
- infallible. Human legs are also contrived for walking and mounting; and
- this inference, I allow, is not altogether so certain, because of the
- dissimilarity which you remark; but does it, therefore, deserve the
- name only of presumption or conjecture?
- Good God! cried Demea, interrupting him, where are we? Zealous
- defenders of religion allow, that the proofs of a Deity fall short
- of perfect evidence! And you, Philo, on whose assistance I depended
- in proving the adorable mysteriousness of the Divine Nature, do you
- assent to all these extravagant opinions of Cleanthes? For what other
- name can I give them? or, why spare my censure, when such principles
- are advanced, supported by such an authority, before so young a man as
- Pamphilus?
- You seem not to apprehend, replied Philo, that I argue with Cleanthes
- in his own way; and, by showing him the dangerous consequences of his
- tenets, hope at last to reduce him to our opinion. But what sticks most
- with you, I observe, is the representation which Cleanthes has made of
- the argument _a posteriori_; and finding that that argument is likely
- to escape your hold and vanish into air, you think it so disguised,
- that you can scarcely believe it to be set in its true light. Now,
- however much I may dissent, in other respects, from the dangerous
- principles of Cleanthes, I must allow that he has fairly represented
- that argument; and I shall endeavour so to state the matter to you,
- that you will entertain no farther scruples with regard to it.
- Were a man to abstract from every thing which he knows or has seen, he
- would be altogether incapable, merely from his own ideas, to determine
- what kind of scene the universe must be, or to give the preference
- to one state or situation of things above another. For as nothing
- which he clearly conceives could be esteemed impossible or implying
- a contradiction, every chimera of his fancy would be upon an equal
- footing; nor could he assign any just reason why he adheres to one idea
- or system, and rejects the others which are equally possible.
- Again; after he opens his eyes, and contemplates the world as it really
- is, it would be impossible for him at first to assign the cause of
- any one event, much less of the whole of things, or of the universe.
- He might set his fancy a rambling; and she might bring him in an
- infinite variety of reports and representations. These would all be
- possible; but being all equally possible, he would never of himself
- give a satisfactory account for his preferring one of them to the rest.
- Experience alone can point out to him the true cause of any phenomenon.
- Now, according to this method of reasoning, Demea, it follows, (and is,
- indeed, tacitly allowed by Cleanthes himself), that order, arrangement,
- or the adjustment of final causes, is not of itself any proof of
- design; but only so far as it has been experienced to proceed from
- that principle. For aught we can know _a priori_, matter may contain
- the source or spring of order originally within itself, as well as
- mind does; and there is no more difficulty in conceiving, that the
- several elements, from an internal unknown cause, may fall into the
- most exquisite arrangement, than to conceive that their ideas, in the
- great universal mind, from a like internal unknown cause, fall into
- that arrangement. The equal possibility of both these suppositions is
- allowed. But, by experience, we find, (according to Cleanthes), that
- there is a difference between them. Throw several pieces of steel
- together, without shape or form; they will never arrange themselves
- so as to compose a watch. Stone, and mortar, and wood, without an
- architect, never erect a house. But the ideas in a human mind, we see,
- by an unknown, inexplicable economy, arrange themselves so as to form
- the plan of a watch or house. Experience, therefore, proves, that there
- is an original principle of order in mind, not in matter. From similar
- effects we infer similar causes. The adjustment of means to ends is
- alike in the universe, as in a machine of human contrivance. The
- causes, therefore, must be resembling.
- I was from the beginning scandalized, I must own, with this
- resemblance, which is asserted, between the Deity and human creatures;
- and must conceive it to imply such a degradation of the Supreme Being
- as no sound Theist could endure. With your assistance, therefore,
- Demea, I shall endeavour to defend what you justly call the adorable
- mysteriousness of the Divine Nature, and shall refute this reasoning of
- Cleanthes, provided he allows that I have made a fair representation of
- it.
- When Cleanthes had assented, Philo, after a short pause, proceeded in
- the following manner.
- That all inferences, Cleanthes, concerning fact, are founded on
- experience; and that all experimental reasonings are founded on the
- supposition that similar causes prove similar effects, and similar
- effects similar causes; I shall not at present much dispute with
- you. But observe, I entreat you, with what extreme caution all just
- reasoners proceed in the transferring of experiments to similar cases.
- Unless the cases be exactly similar, they repose no perfect confidence
- in applying their past observation to any particular phenomenon.
- Every alteration of circumstances occasions a doubt concerning the
- event; and it requires new experiments to prove certainly, that the
- new circumstances are of no moment or importance. A change in bulk,
- situation, arrangement, age, disposition of the air, or surrounding
- bodies; any of these particulars may be attended with the most
- unexpected consequences: And unless the objects be quite familiar to
- us, it is the highest temerity to expect with assurance, after any of
- these changes, an event similar to that which before fell under our
- observation. The slow and deliberate steps of philosophers here, if
- any where, are distinguished from the precipitate march of the vulgar,
- who, hurried on by the smallest similitude, are incapable of all
- discernment or consideration.
- But can you think, Cleanthes, that your usual phlegm and philosophy
- have been preserved in so wide a step as you have taken, when you
- compared to the universe houses, ships, furniture, machines, and, from
- their similarity in some circumstances, inferred a similarity in their
- causes? Thought, design, intelligence, such as we discover in men
- and other animals, is no more than one of the springs and principles
- of the universe, as well as heat or cold, attraction or repulsion,
- and a hundred others, which fall under daily observation. It is an
- active cause, by which some particular parts of nature, we find,
- produce alterations on other parts. But can a conclusion, with any
- propriety, be transferred from parts to the whole? Does not the great
- disproportion bar all comparison and inference? From observing the
- growth of a hair, can we learn any thing concerning the generation of a
- man? Would the manner of a leaf's blowing, even though perfectly known,
- afford us any instruction concerning the vegetation of a tree?
- But, allowing that we were to take the _operations_ of one part of
- nature upon another, for the foundation of our judgment concerning the
- _origin_ of the whole, (which never can be admitted), yet why select
- so minute, so weak, so bounded a principle, as the reason and design
- of animals is found to be upon this planet? What peculiar privilege
- has this little agitation of the brain which we call _thought_, that
- we must thus make it the model of the whole universe? Our partiality
- in our own favour does indeed present it on all occasions; but sound
- philosophy ought carefully to guard against so natural an illusion.
- So far from admitting, continued Philo, that the operations of a part
- can afford us any just conclusion concerning the origin of the whole,
- I will not allow any one part to form a rule for another part, if the
- latter be very remote from the former. Is there any reasonable ground
- to conclude, that the inhabitants of other planets possess thought,
- intelligence, reason, or any thing similar to these faculties in men?
- When nature has so extremely diversified her manner of operation in
- this small globe, can we imagine that she incessantly copies herself
- throughout so immense a universe? And if thought, as we may well
- suppose, be confined merely to this narrow corner, and has even there
- so limited a sphere of action, with what propriety can we assign it for
- the original cause of all things? The narrow views of a peasant, who
- makes his domestic economy the rule for the government of kingdoms, is
- in comparison a pardonable sophism.
- But were we ever so much assured, that a thought and reason, resembling
- the human, were to be found throughout the whole universe, and were
- its activity elsewhere vastly greater and more commanding than it
- appears in this globe; yet I cannot see, why the operations of a world
- constituted, arranged, adjusted, can with any propriety be extended
- to a world which is in its embryo-state, and is advancing towards
- that constitution and arrangement. By observation, we know somewhat
- of the economy, action, and nourishment of a finished animal; but we
- must transfer with great caution that observation to the growth of a
- foetus in the womb, and still more to the formation of an animalcule in
- the loins of its male parent. Nature, we find, even from our limited
- experience, possesses an infinite number of springs and principles,
- which incessantly discover themselves on every change of her position
- and situation. And what new and unknown principles would actuate her in
- so new and unknown a situation as that of the formation of a universe,
- we cannot, without the utmost temerity, pretend to determine.
- A very small part of this great system, during a very short time,
- is very imperfectly discovered to us; and do we thence pronounce
- decisively concerning the origin of the whole?
- Admirable conclusion! Stone, wood, brick, iron, brass, have not, at
- this time, in this minute globe of earth, an order or arrangement
- without human art and contrivance; therefore the universe could not
- originally attain its order and arrangement, without something similar
- to human art. But is a part of nature a rule for another part very wide
- of the former? Is it a rule for the whole? Is a very small part a rule
- for the universe? Is nature in one situation, a certain rule for nature
- in another situation vastly different from the former?
- And can you blame me, Cleanthes, if I here imitate the prudent reserve
- of Simonides, who, according to the noted story, being asked by Hiero,
- _What God was_? desired a day to think of it, and then two days more;
- and after that manner continually prolonged the term, without ever
- bringing in his definition or description? Could you even blame me, if
- I had answered at first, _that I did not know_, and was sensible that
- this subject lay vastly beyond the reach of my faculties? You might cry
- out sceptic and rallier, as much as you pleased: but having found, in
- so many other subjects much more familiar, the imperfections and even
- contradictions of human reason, I never should expect any success from
- its feeble conjectures, in a subject so sublime, and so remote from the
- sphere of our observation. When two _species_ of objects have always
- been observed to be conjoined together, I can _infer_, by custom, the
- existence of one wherever I _see_ the existence of the other; and
- this I call an argument from experience. But how this argument can
- have place, where the objects, as in the present case, are single,
- individual, without parallel, or specific resemblance, may be difficult
- to explain. And will any man tell me with a serious countenance, that
- an orderly universe must arise from some thought and art like the
- human, because we have experience of it? To ascertain this reasoning,
- it were requisite that we had experience of the origin of worlds; and
- it is not sufficient, surely, that we have seen ships and cities arise
- from human art and contrivance.
- Philo was proceeding in this vehement manner, somewhat between jest
- and earnest, as it appeared to me, when he observed some signs of
- impatience in Cleanthes, and then immediately stopped short. What I had
- to suggest, said Cleanthes, is only that you would not abuse terms, or
- make use of popular expressions to subvert philosophical reasonings.
- You know, that the vulgar often distinguish reason from experience,
- even where the question relates only to matter of fact and existence;
- though it is found, where that _reason_ is properly analyzed, that
- it is nothing but a species of experience. To prove by experience
- the origin of the universe from mind, is not more contrary to common
- speech, than to prove the motion of the earth from the same principle.
- And a caviller might raise all the same objections to the Copernican
- system, which you have urged against my reasonings. Have you other
- earths, might he say, which you have seen to move? Have....
- Yes! cried Philo, interrupting him, we have other earths. Is not the
- moon another earth, which we see to turn round its centre? Is not
- Venus another earth, where we observe the same phenomenon? Are not the
- revolutions of the sun also a confirmation, from analogy, of the same
- theory? All the planets, are they not earths, which revolve about the
- sun? Are not the satellites moons, which move round Jupiter and Saturn,
- and along with these primary planets round the sun? These analogies
- and resemblances, with others which I have not mentioned, are the sole
- proofs of the Copernican system; and to you it belongs to consider,
- whether you have any analogies of the same kind to support your theory.
- In reality, Cleanthes, continued he, the modern system of astronomy
- is now so much received by all inquirers, and has become so essential
- a part even of our earliest education, that we are not commonly very
- scrupulous in examining the reasons upon which it is founded. It is now
- become a matter of mere curiosity to study the first writers on that
- subject, who had the full force of prejudice to encounter, and were
- obliged to turn their arguments on every side in order to render them
- popular and convincing. But if we peruse Galilæo's famous Dialogues
- concerning the system of the world, we shall find, that that great
- genius, one of the sublimest that ever existed, first bent all his
- endeavours to prove, that there was no foundation for the distinction
- commonly made between elementary and celestial substances. The schools,
- proceeding from the illusions of sense, had carried this distinction
- very far; and had established the latter substances to be ingenerable,
- incorruptible, unalterable, impassible; and had assigned all the
- opposite qualities to the former. But Galilæo, beginning with the moon,
- proved its similarity in every particular to the earth; its convex
- figure, its natural darkness when not illuminated, its density, its
- distinction into solid and liquid, the variations of its phases, the
- mutual illuminations of the earth and moon, their mutual eclipses, the
- inequalities of the lunar surface, &c. After many instances of this
- kind, with regard to all the planets, men plainly saw that these bodies
- became proper objects of experience; and that the similarity of their
- nature enabled us to extend the same arguments and phenomena from one
- to the other.
- In this cautious proceeding of the astronomers, you may read your
- own condemnation, Cleanthes; or rather may see, that the subject in
- which you are engaged exceeds all human reason and inquiry. Can you
- pretend to show any such similarity between the fabric of a house, find
- the generation of a universe? Have you ever seen nature in any such
- situation as resembles the first arrangement of the elements? Have
- worlds ever been formed under your eye; and have you had leisure to
- observe the whole progress of the phenomenon, from the first appearance
- of order to its final consummation? If you have, then cite your
- experience, and deliver your theory.
- [1] Recherche de la Verité, liv. 3, cap. 9.
- PART III.
- How the most absurd argument, replied Cleanthes, in the hands of a
- man of ingenuity and invention, may acquire an air of probability!
- Are you not aware, Philo, that it became necessary for Copernicus
- and his first disciples to prove the similarity of the terrestrial
- and celestial matter; because several philosophers, blinded by old
- systems, and supported by some sensible appearances, had denied this
- similarity? but that it is by no means necessary, that Theists should
- prove the similarity of the works of Nature to those of Art; because
- this similarity is self-evident and undeniable? The same matter, a
- like form; what more is requisite to show an analogy between their
- causes, and to ascertain the origin of all things from a divine purpose
- and intention? Your objections, I must freely tell you, are no better
- than the abstruse cavils of those philosophers who denied motion; and
- ought to be refuted in the same manner, by illustrations, examples and
- instances, rather than by serious argument and philosophy.
- Suppose, therefore, that an articulate voice were heard, in the clouds,
- much louder and more melodious than any which human art could ever
- reach: Suppose, that this voice were extended in the same instant
- over all nations, and spoke to each nation in its own language and
- dialect: Suppose, that the words delivered not only contain a just
- sense and meaning, but convey some instruction altogether worthy of a
- benevolent Being, superior to mankind: Could you possibly hesitate a
- moment concerning the cause of this voice? and must you not instantly
- ascribe it to some design or purpose? Yet I cannot see but all the
- same objections (if they merit that appellation) which lie against the
- system of Theism, may also be produced against this inference.
- Might you not say, that all conclusions concerning fact were founded
- on experience: that when we hear an articulate voice in the dark,
- and thence infer a man, it is only the resemblance of the effects
- which leads us to conclude that there is a like resemblance in the
- cause: but that this extraordinary voice, by its loudness, extent, and
- flexibility to all languages, bears so little analogy to any human
- voice, that we have no reason to suppose any analogy in their causes:
- and consequently, that a rational, wise, coherent speech proceeded, you
- know not whence, from some accidental whistling of the winds, not from
- any divine reason or intelligence? You see clearly your own objections
- in these cavils, and I hope too you see clearly, that they cannot
- possibly have more force in the one case than in the other.
- But to bring the case still nearer the present one of the universe,
- I shall make two suppositions, which imply not any absurdity or
- impossibility. Suppose that there is a natural, universal, invariable
- language, common to every individual of human race; and that books
- are natural productions, which perpetuate themselves in the same
- manner with animals and vegetables, by descent and propagation.
- Several expressions of our passions contain a universal language: all
- brute animals have a natural speech, which, however limited, is very
- intelligible to their own species. And as there are infinitely fewer
- parts and less contrivance in the finest composition of eloquence, than
- in the coarsest organized body, the propagation of an Iliad or Æneid is
- an easier supposition than that of any plant or animal.
- Suppose, therefore, that you enter into your library, thus peopled by
- natural volumes, containing the most refined reason and most exquisite
- beauty; could you possibly open one of them, and doubt, that its
- original cause bore the strongest analogy to mind and intelligence?
- When it reasons and discourses; when it expostulates, argues, and
- enforces its views and topics; when it applies sometimes to the pure
- intellect, sometimes to the affections; when it collects, disposes, and
- adorns every consideration suited to the subject; could you persist in
- asserting, that all this, at the bottom, had really no meaning; and
- that the first formation of this volume in the loins of its original
- parent proceeded not from thought and design? Your obstinacy, I know,
- reaches not that degree of firmness: even your sceptical play and
- wantonness would be abashed at so glaring an absurdity.
- But if there be any difference, Philo, between this supposed case and
- the real one of the universe, it is all to the advantage of the latter.
- The anatomy of an animal affords many stronger instances of design than
- the perusal of Livy or Tacitus; and any objection which you start in
- the former case, by carrying me back to so unusual and extraordinary a
- scene as the first formation of worlds, the same objection has place on
- the supposition of our vegetating library. Choose, then, your party,
- Philo, without ambiguity or evasion; assert either that a rational
- volume is no proof of a rational cause, or admit of a similar cause to
- all the works of nature.
- Let me here observe too, continued Cleanthes, that this religious
- argument, instead of being weakened by that scepticism so much
- affected by you, rather acquires force from it, and becomes more firm
- and undisputed. To exclude all argument or reasoning of every kind,
- is either affectation or madness. The declared profession of every
- reasonable sceptic is only to reject abstruse, remote, and refined
- arguments; to adhere to common sense and the plain instincts of
- nature; and to assent, wherever any reasons strike him with so full
- a force that he cannot, without the greatest violence, prevent it.
- Now the arguments for Natural Religion are plainly of this kind; and
- nothing but the most perverse, obstinate metaphysics can reject them.
- Consider, anatomize the eye; survey its structure and contrivance;
- and tell me, from your own feeling, if the idea of a contriver does
- not immediately flow in upon you with a force like that of sensation.
- The most obvious conclusion, surely, is in favour of design; and it
- requires time, reflection, and study, to summon up those frivolous,
- though abstruse objections, which can support Infidelity. Who can
- behold the male and female of each species, the correspondence of
- their parts and instincts, their passions, and whole course of life
- before and after generation, but must be sensible, that the propagation
- of the species is intended by Nature? Millions and millions of such
- instances present themselves through every part of the universe; and
- no language can convey a more intelligible irresistible meaning, than
- the curious adjustment of final causes. To what degree, therefore, of
- blind dogmatism must one have attained, to reject such natural and such
- convincing arguments?
- Some beauties in writing we may meet with, which seem contrary to
- rules, and which gain the affections, and animate the imagination, in
- opposition to all the precepts of criticism, and to the authority of
- the established masters of art. And if the argument for Theism be, as
- you pretend, contradictory to the principles of logic; its universal,
- its irresistible influence proves clearly, that there may be arguments
- of a like irregular nature. Whatever cavils may be urged, an orderly
- world, as well as a coherent, articulate speech, will still be received
- as an incontestable proof of design and intention.
- It sometimes happens, I own, that the religious arguments have not
- their due influence on an ignorant savage and barbarian; not because
- they are obscure and difficult, but because he never asks himself any
- question with regard to them. Whence arises the curious structure of
- an animal? From the copulation of its parents. And these whence? From
- _their_ parents? A few removes set the objects at such a distance, that
- to him they are lost in darkness and confusion; nor is he actuated by
- any curiosity to trace them farther. But this is neither dogmatism
- nor scepticism, but stupidity: a state of mind very different from
- your sifting, inquisitive disposition, my ingenious friend. You can
- trace causes from effects: You can compare the most distant and
- remote objects: and your greatest errors proceed not from barrenness
- of thought and invention, but from too luxuriant a fertility, which
- suppresses your natural good sense, by a profusion of unnecessary
- scruples and objections.
- Here I could observe, Hermippus, that Philo was a little embarrassed
- and confounded: But while he hesitated in delivering an answer, luckily
- for him, Demea broke in upon the discourse, and saved his countenance.
- Your instance, Cleanthes, said he, drawn from books and language, being
- familiar, has, I confess, so much more force on that account: but is
- there not some danger too in this very circumstance; and may it not
- render us presumptuous, by making us imagine we comprehend the Deity,
- and have some adequate idea of his nature and attributes? When I read
- a volume, I enter into the mind and intention of the author: I become
- him, in a manner, for the instant; and have an immediate feeling and
- conception of those ideas which revolved in his imagination while
- employed in that composition. But so near an approach we never surely
- can make to the Deity. His ways are not our ways. His attributes are
- perfect, but incomprehensible. And this volume of nature contains a
- great and inexplicable riddle, more than any intelligible discourse or
- reasoning.
- The ancient Platonists, you know, were the most religious and devout
- of all the Pagan philosophers; yet many of them, particularly
- Plotinus, expressly declare, that intellect or understanding is not
- to be ascribed to the Deity; and that our most perfect worship of him
- consists, not in acts of veneration, reverence, gratitude, or love;
- but in a certain mysterious self-annihilation, or total extinction of
- all our faculties. These ideas are, perhaps, too far stretched; but
- still it must be acknowledged, that, by representing the Deity as so
- intelligible and comprehensible, and so similar to a human mind, we are
- guilty of the grossest and most narrow partiality, and make ourselves
- the model of the whole universe.
- All the _sentiments_ of the human mind, gratitude, resentment, love,
- friendship, approbation, blame, pity, emulation, envy, have a plain
- reference to the state and situation of man, and are calculated for
- preserving the existence and promoting the activity of such a being
- in such circumstances. It seems, therefore, unreasonable to transfer
- such sentiments to a supreme existence, or to suppose him actuated by
- them; and the phenomena besides of the universe will not support us in
- such a theory. All our _ideas_ derived from the senses are confessedly
- false and illusive; and cannot therefore be supposed to have place in
- a supreme intelligence: And as the ideas of internal sentiment, added
- to those of the external senses, compose the whole furniture of human
- understanding, we may conclude, that none of the _materials_ of thought
- are in any respect similar in the human and in the divine intelligence.
- Now, as to the _manner_ of thinking; how can we make any comparison
- between them, or suppose them any wise resembling? Our thought is
- fluctuating, uncertain, fleeting, successive, and compounded; and
- were we to remove these circumstances, we absolutely annihilate its
- essence, and it would in such a case be an abuse of terms to apply to
- it the name of thought or reason. At least if it appear more pious
- and respectful (as it really is) still to retain these terms, when we
- mention the Supreme Being, we ought to acknowledge, that their meaning,
- in that case, is totally incomprehensible; and that the infirmities
- of our nature do not permit us to reach any ideas which in the least
- correspond to the ineffable sublimity of the Divine attributes.
- PART IV.
- It seems strange to me, said Cleanthes, that you, Demea, who are so
- sincere in the cause of religion, should still maintain the mysterious,
- incomprehensible nature of the Deity, and should insist so strenuously
- that he has no manner of likeness or resemblance to human creatures.
- The Deity, I can readily allow, possesses many powers and attributes of
- which we can have no comprehension: But if our ideas, so far as they
- go, be not just, and adequate, and correspondent to his real nature,
- I know not what there is in this subject worth insisting on. Is the
- name, without any meaning, of such mighty importance? Or how do you
- mystics, who maintain the absolute incomprehensibility of the Deity,
- differ from Sceptics or Atheists, who assert, that the first cause of
- all is unknown and unintelligible? Their temerity must be very great,
- if, after rejecting the production by a mind, I mean a mind resembling
- the human, (for I know of no other), they pretend to assign, with
- certainty, any other specific intelligible cause: And their conscience
- must be very scrupulous indeed, if they refuse to call the universal
- unknown cause a God or Deity; and to bestow on him as many sublime
- eulogies and unmeaning epithets as you shall please to require of them.
- Who could imagine, replied Demea, that Cleanthes, the calm
- philosophical Cleanthes, would attempt to refute his antagonists
- by affixing a nickname to them; and, like the common bigots and
- inquisitors of the age, have recourse to invective and declamation,
- instead of reasoning? Or does he not perceive, that these topics
- are easily retorted, and that Anthropomorphite is an appellation as
- invidious, and implies as dangerous consequences, as the epithet of
- Mystic, with which he has honoured us? In reality, Cleanthes, consider
- what it is you assert when you represent the Deity as similar to a
- human mind and understanding. What is the soul of man? A composition
- of various faculties, passions, sentiments, ideas; united, indeed,
- into one self or person, but still distinct from each other. When it
- reasons, the ideas, which are the parts of its discourse, arrange
- themselves in a certain form or order; which is not preserved entire
- for a moment, but immediately gives place to another arrangement. New
- opinions, new passions, new affections, new feelings arise, which
- continually diversify the mental scene, and produce in it the greatest
- variety and most rapid succession imaginable. How is this compatible
- with that perfect immutability and simplicity which all true Theists
- ascribe to the Deity? By the same act, say they, he sees past,
- present, and future: His love and hatred, his mercy and justice, are
- one individual operation: He is entire in every point of space; and
- complete in every instant of duration. No succession, no change, no
- acquisition, no diminution. What he is implies not in it any shadow of
- distinction or diversity. And what he is this moment he ever has been,
- and ever will be, without any new judgment, sentiment, or operation. He
- stands fixed in one simple, perfect state: nor can you ever gay, with
- any propriety, that this act of his is different from that other; or
- that this judgment or idea has been lately formed, and will give place,
- by succession, to any different judgment or idea.
- I can readily allow, said Cleanthes, that those who maintain the
- perfect simplicity of the Supreme Being, to the extent in which you
- have explained it, are complete Mystics, and chargeable with all the
- consequences which I have drawn from their opinion. They are, in a
- word, Atheists, without knowing it For though it be allowed, that the
- Deity possesses attributes of which we have no comprehension, yet
- ought we never to ascribe to him any attributes which are absolutely
- incompatible with that intelligent nature essential to him. A mind,
- whose acts and sentiments and ideas are not distinct and successive;
- one, that is wholly simple, and totally immutable, is a mind which has
- no thought, no reason, no will, no sentiment, no love, no hatred; or,
- in a word, is no mind at all. It is an abuse of terms to give it that
- appellation; and we may as well speak of limited extension without
- figure, or of number without composition.
- Pray consider, said Philo, whom you are at present inveighing against.
- You are honouring with the appellation of _Atheist_ all the sound,
- orthodox divines, almost, who have treated of this subject; and you
- will at last be, yourself, found, according to your reckoning, the
- only sound Theist in the world. But if idolaters be Atheists, as, I
- think, may justly be asserted, and Christian Theologians the same, what
- becomes of the argument, so much celebrated, derived from the universal
- consent of mankind?
- But because I know you are not much swayed by names and authorities,
- I shall endeavour to show you, a little more distinctly, the
- inconveniences of that Anthropomorphism, which you have embraced; and
- shall prove, that there is no ground to suppose a plan of the world to
- be formed in the Divine mind, consisting of distinct ideas, differently
- arranged, in the same manner as an architect forms in his head the plan
- of a house which he intends to execute.
- It is not easy, I own, to see what is gained by this supposition,
- whether we judge of the matter by _Reason_ or by _Experience_. We are
- still obliged to mount higher, in order to find the cause of this
- cause, which you had assigned as satisfactory and conclusive.
- If _Reason_ (I mean abstract reason, derived from inquiries _a priori_)
- be not alike mute with regard to all questions concerning cause and
- effect, this sentence at least it will venture to pronounce, That
- a mental world, or universe of ideas, requires a cause as much, as
- does a material world, or universe of objects; and, if similar in its
- arrangement, must require a similar cause. For what is there in this
- subject, which should occasion a different conclusion or inference? In
- an abstract view, they are entirely alike; and no difficulty attends
- the one supposition, which is not common to both of them.
- Again, when we will needs force _Experience_ to pronounce some
- sentence, even on these subjects which lie beyond her sphere, neither
- can she perceive any material difference in this particular, between
- these two kinds of worlds; but finds them to be governed by similar
- principles, and to depend upon an equal variety of causes in their
- operations. We have specimens in miniature of both of them. Our own
- mind resembles the one; a vegetable or animal body the other. Let
- experience, therefore, judge from these samples. Nothing seems more
- delicate, with regard to its causes, than thought; and as these causes
- never operate in two persons after the same manner, so we never find
- two persons who think exactly alike. Nor indeed does the same person
- think exactly alike at any two different periods of time. A difference
- of age, of the disposition of his body, of weather, of food, of
- company, of books, of passions; any of these particulars, or others
- more minute, are sufficient to alter the curious machinery of thought,
- and communicate to it very different movements and operations. As far
- as we can judge, vegetables and animal bodies are not more delicate
- in their motions, nor depend upon a greater variety or more curious
- adjustment of springs and principles.
- How, therefore, shall we satisfy ourselves concerning the cause of that
- Being whom you suppose the Author of Nature, or, according to your
- system of Anthropomorphism, the ideal world, into which you trace the
- material? Have we not the same reason to trace that ideal world into
- another ideal world, or new intelligent principle? But if we stop, and
- go no farther; why go so far? why not stop at the material world? How
- can we satisfy ourselves without going on _in infinitum_? And, after
- all, what satisfaction is there in that infinite progression? Let us
- remember the story of the Indian philosopher and his elephant. It was
- never more applicable than to the present subject. If the material
- world rests upon a similar ideal world, this ideal world must rest upon
- some other; and so on, without end. It were better, therefore, never
- to look beyond the present material world. By supposing it to contain
- the principle of its order within itself, we really assert it to be
- God; and the sooner we arrive at that Divine Being, so much the better.
- When you go one step beyond the mundane system, you only excite an
- inquisitive humour which it is impossible ever to satisfy.
- To say, that the different ideas which compose the reason of the
- Supreme Being, fall into order of themselves, and by their own nature,
- is really to talk without any precise meaning. If it has a meaning, I
- would fain know, why it is not as good sense to say, that the parts
- of the material world fall into order of themselves and by their own
- nature. Can the one opinion be intelligible, while the other is not so?
- We have, indeed, experience of ideas which fall into order of
- themselves, and without any _known_ cause. But, I am sure, we have
- a much larger experience of matter which does the same; as, in all
- instances of generation and vegetation, where the accurate analysis of
- the cause exceeds all human comprehension. We have also experience of
- particular systems of thought and of matter which have no order; of the
- first in madness, of the second in corruption. Why, then, should we
- think, that order is more essential to one than the other? And if it
- requires a cause in both, what do we gain by your system, in tracing
- the universe of objects into a similar universe of ideas? The first
- step which we make leads us on for ever. It were, therefore, wise in
- us to limit all our inquiries to the present world, without looking
- farther. No satisfaction can ever be attained by these speculations,
- which so far exceed the narrow bounds of human understanding.
- It was usual with the Peripatetics, you know, Cleanthes, when the cause
- of any phenomenon was demanded, to have recourse to their _faculties_,
- or _occult qualities_; and to say, for instance, that bread, nourished
- by its nutritive faculty, and senna purged by its purgative. But it
- has been discovered, that this subterfuge was nothing but the disguise
- of ignorance; and that these philosophers, though less ingenuous,
- really said the same thing with the sceptics or the vulgar, who
- fairly confessed that they knew not the cause of these phenomena.
- In like manner, when it is asked, what cause produces order in the
- ideas of the Supreme Being; can any other reason be assigned by you,
- Anthropomorphites, than that it is a _rational_ faculty, and that
- such is the nature of the Deity? But why a similar answer will not be
- equally satisfactory in accounting for the order of the world, without
- having recourse to any such intelligent creator as you insist on, may
- be difficult to determine. It is only to say, that _such_ is the nature
- of material objects, and that they are all originally possessed of a
- _faculty_ of order and proportion. These are only more learned and
- elaborate ways of confessing our ignorance; nor has the one hypothesis
- any real advantage above the other, except in its greater conformity to
- vulgar prejudices.
- You have displayed this argument with great emphasis, replied
- Cleanthes: You seem not sensible how easy it is to answer it. Even in
- common life, if I assign a cause for any event, is it any objection,
- Philo, that I cannot assign the cause of that cause, and answer every
- new question which may incessantly be started? And what philosophers
- could possibly submit to so rigid a rule? philosophers, who confess
- ultimate causes to be totally unknown; and are sensible, that the most
- refined principles into which they trace the phenomena, are still to
- them as inexplicable as these phenomena themselves are to the vulgar.
- The order and arrangement of nature, the curious adjustment of final
- causes, the plain use and intention of every part and organ; all these
- bespeak in the clearest language an intelligent cause or author. The
- heavens and the earth join in the same testimony: The whole chorus of
- Nature raises one hymn to the praises of its Creator. You alone, or
- almost alone, disturb this general harmony. You start abstruse doubts,
- cavils, and objections: You ask me, what is the cause of this cause? I
- know not; I care not; that concerns not me. I have found a Deity; and
- here I stop my inquiry. Let those go farther, who are wiser or more
- enterprising.
- I pretend to be neither, replied Philo: And for that very reason, I
- should never perhaps have attempted to go so tar; especially when I
- am sensible, that I must at last be contented to sit down with the
- same answer, which, without farther trouble, might have satisfied me
- from the beginning. If I am still to remain in utter ignorance of
- causes, and can absolutely give an explication of nothing, I shall
- never esteem it any advantage to shove off for a moment a difficulty,
- which, you acknowledge, must immediately, in its full force, recur
- upon me. Naturalists indeed very justly explain particular effects by
- more general causes, though these general causes themselves should
- remain in the end totally inexplicable; but they never surely thought
- it satisfactory to explain a particular effect by a particular cause,
- which was no more to be accounted for than the effect itself. An ideal
- system, arranged of itself, without a precedent design, is not a whit
- more explicable than a material one, which attains its order in a like
- manner; nor is there any more difficulty in the latter supposition than
- in the former.
- PART V.
- But to show you still more inconveniences, continued Philo, in your
- Anthropomorphism, please to take a new survey of your principles.
- _Like effects prove like causes_. This is the experimental argument;
- and this, you say too, is the sole theological argument. Now, it is
- certain, that the liker the effects are which are seen, and the liker
- the causes which are inferred, the stronger is the argument. Every
- departure on either side diminishes the probability, and renders the
- experiment less conclusive. You cannot doubt of the principle; neither
- ought you to reject its consequences.
- All the new discoveries in astronomy, which prove the immense grandeur
- and magnificence of the works of Nature, are so many additional
- arguments for a Deity, according to the true system of Theism; but,
- according to your hypothesis of experimental Theism, they become
- so many objections, by removing the effect still farther from all
- resemblance to the effects of human art and contrivance. For, if
- Lucretius,[1] even following the old system of the world, could exclaim,
- Quis regere immensi summam, quis habere profundi
- Indu manu validas potis est moderanter habenas?
- Quis pariter coelos omnes convertere? et omnes
- Ignibus ætheriis terras suffire feraces?
- Omnibus inque locis esse omni tempore præsto?
- If Tully[2] esteemed this reasoning so natural, as to put it into
- the mouth of his Epicurean: 'Quibus enim oculis animi intueri potuit
- vester Plato fabricam illam tanti operis, qua construi a Deo atque
- ædificari mundum facit? quæ molito? quæ ferramenta? qui vectes? quæ
- machinæ? qui minstri tanti muneris fuerunt? quemadmodum autem obedire
- et parere voluntati architecti aer, ignis, aqua, terra potuerunt?' If
- this argument, I say, had any force in former ages, how much greater
- must it have at present, when the bounds of Nature are so infinitely
- enlarged, and such a magnificent scene is opened to us? It is still
- more unreasonable to form our idea of so unlimited a cause from our
- experience of the narrow productions of human design and invention.
- The discoveries by microscopes, as they open a new universe in
- miniature, are still objections, according to you, arguments, according
- to me. The farther we push our researches of this kind, we are still
- led to infer the universal cause of all to be vastly different from
- mankind, or from any object of human experience and observation.
- And what say you to the discoveries in anatomy, chemistry, botany?...
- These surely are no objections, replied Cleanthes; they only discover
- new instances of art and contrivance. It is still the image of mind
- reflected on us from innumerable objects. Add, a mind _like the human_,
- said Philo. I know of no other, replied Cleanthes. And the liker the
- better, insisted Philo. To be sure, said Cleanthes.
- Now, Cleanthes, said Philo, with an air of alacrity and triumph, mark
- the consequences. _First_, By this method of reasoning, you renounce
- all claim to infinity in any of the attributes of the Deity. For,
- as the cause ought only to be proportioned to the effect, and the
- effect, so far as it falls under our cognizance, is not infinite; what
- pretensions have we, upon your suppositions, to ascribe that attribute
- to the Divine Being? You will still insist, that, by removing him so
- much from all similarity to human creatures, we give in to the most
- arbitrary hypothesis, and at the same time weaken all proofs of his
- existence.
- _Secondly_, You have no reason, on your theory, for ascribing
- perfection to the Deity, even in his finite capacity, or for
- supposing him free from every error, mistake, or incoherence, in his
- undertakings. There are many inexplicable difficulties in the works of
- Nature, which, if we allow a perfect author to be proved _a priori_,
- are easily solved, and become only seeming difficulties, from the
- narrow capacity of man, who cannot trace infinite relations. But
- according to your method of reasoning, these difficulties become all
- real; and perhaps will be insisted on, as new instances of likeness to
- human art and contrivance. At least, you must acknowledge, that it is
- impossible for us to tell, from our limited views, whether this system
- contains any great faults, or deserves any considerable praise, if
- compared to other possible, and even real systems. Could a peasant,
- if the Æneid were read to him, pronounce that poem to be absolutely
- faultless, or even assign to it its proper rank among the productions
- of human wit, he, who had never seen any other production?
- But were this world ever so perfect a production, it must still remain
- uncertain, whether all the excellences of the work can justly be
- ascribed to the workman. If we survey a ship, what an exalted idea must
- we form of the ingenuity of the carpenter who framed so complicated,
- useful, and beautiful a machine? And what surprise must we feel, when
- we find him a stupid mechanic, who imitated others, and copied an art,
- which, through a long succession of ages, after multiplied trials,
- mistakes, corrections, deliberations, and controversies, had been
- gradually improving? Many worlds might have been botched and bungled,
- throughout an eternity, ere this system was struck out; much labour
- lost, many fruitless trials made; and a slow, but continued improvement
- carried on during infinite ages in the art of world-making. In such
- subjects, who can determine, where the truth; nay, who can conjecture
- where the probability lies, amidst a great number of hypotheses which
- may be proposed, and a still greater which may be imagined?
- And what shadow of an argument, continued Philo, can you produce, from
- your hypothesis, to prove the unity of the Deity? A great number of
- men join in building a house or ship, in rearing a city, in framing a
- commonwealth; why may not several deities combine in contriving and
- framing a world? This is only so much greater similarity to human
- affairs. By sharing the work among several, we may so much farther
- limit the attributes of each, and get rid of that extensive power and
- knowledge, which must be supposed in one deity, and which, according to
- you, can only serve to weaken the proof of his existence. And if such
- foolish, such vicious creatures as man, can yet often unite in framing
- and executing one plan, how much more those deities or demons, whom we
- may suppose several degrees more perfect!
- To multiply causes without necessity, is indeed contrary to true
- philosophy: but this principle applies not to the present case. Were
- one deity antecedently proved by your theory, who were possessed
- of every attribute requisite to the production of the universe; it
- would be needless, I own, (though not absurd), to suppose any other
- deity existent. But while it is still a question, Whether all these
- attributes are united in one subject, or dispersed among several
- independent beings, by what phenomena in nature can we pretend to
- decide the controversy? Where we see a body raised in a scale, we
- are sure that there is in the opposite scale, however concealed from
- sight, some counterpoising weight equal to it; but it is still allowed
- to doubt, whether that weight be an aggregate of several distinct
- bodies, or one uniform united mass. And if the weight requisite very
- much exceeds any thing which we have ever seen conjoined in any single
- body, the former supposition becomes still more probable and natural.
- An intelligent being of such vast power and capacity as is necessary
- to produce the universe, or, to speak in the language of ancient
- philosophy, so prodigious an animal exceeds all analogy, and even
- comprehension.
- But farther, Cleanthes: Men are mortal, and renew their species by
- generation; and this is common to all living creatures. The two great
- sexes of male and female, says Milton, animate the world. Why must
- this circumstance, so universal, so essential, be excluded from those
- numerous and limited deities? Behold, then, the theogony of ancient
- times brought back upon us.
- And why not become a perfect Anthropomorphite? Why not assert the deity
- or deities to be corporeal, and to have eyes, a nose, mouth, ears, &c.?
- Epicurus maintained, that no man had ever seen reason but in a human
- figure; therefore the gods must have a human figure. And this argument,
- which is deservedly so much ridiculed by Cicero, becomes, according to
- you, solid and philosophical.
- In a word, Cleanthes, a man who follows your hypothesis is able perhaps
- to assert, or conjecture, that the universe, sometime, arose from
- something like design: but beyond that position he cannot ascertain one
- single circumstance; and is left afterwards to fix every point of his
- theology by the utmost license of fancy and hypothesis. This world, for
- aught he knows, is very faulty and imperfect, compared to a superior
- standard; and was only the first rude essay of some infant deity, who
- afterwards abandoned it, ashamed of his lame performance: it is the
- work only of some dependent, inferior deity; and is the object of
- derision to his superiors: it is the production of old age and dotage
- in some superannuated deity; and ever since his death, has run on at
- adventures, from the first impulse and active force which it received
- from him. You justly give signs of horror, Demea, at these strange
- suppositions; but these, and a thousand more of the same kind, are
- Cleanthes's suppositions, not mine. From the moment the attributes of
- the Deity are supposed finite, all these have place. And I cannot, for
- my part, think that so wild and unsettled a system of theology is, in
- any respect, preferable to none at all.
- These suppositions I absolutely disown, cried Cleanthes: they strike
- me, however, with no horror, especially when proposed in that
- rambling way in which they drop from you. On the contrary, they give
- me pleasure, when I see, that, by the utmost indulgence of your
- imagination, you never get rid of the hypothesis of design in the
- universe, but are obliged at every turn to have recourse to it. To
- this concession I adhere steadily; and this I regard as a sufficient
- foundation for religion.
- [1] Lib. xi. 1094.
- [2] De Nat Deor. lib. i.
- PART VI.
- It must be a slight fabric, indeed, said Demea, which can be erected
- on so tottering a foundation. While we are uncertain whether there is
- one deity or many; whether the deity or deities, to whom we owe our
- existence, be perfect or imperfect, subordinate or supreme, dead or
- alive, what trust or confidence can we repose in them? What devotion or
- worship address to them? What veneration or obedience pay them? To all
- the purposes of life the theory of religion becomes altogether useless:
- and even with regard to speculative consequences, its uncertainty,
- according to you, must render it totally precarious and unsatisfactory.
- To render it still more unsatisfactory, said Philo, there occurs to me
- another hypothesis, which must acquire an air of probability from the
- method of reasoning so much insisted on by Cleanthes. That like effects
- arise from like causes: this principle he supposes the foundation of
- all religion. But there is another principle of the same kind, no less
- certain, and derived from the same source of experience; that where
- several known circumstances are observed to be similar, the unknown
- will also be found similar. Thus, if we see the limbs of a human body,
- we conclude that it is also attended with a human head, though hid from
- us. Thus, if we see, through a chink in a wall, a small part of the
- sun, we conclude, that, were the wall removed, we should see the whole
- body. In short, this method of reasoning is so obvious and familiar,
- that no scruple can ever be made with regard to its solidity.
- Now, if we survey the universe, so far as it falls under our knowledge,
- it bears a great resemblance to an animal or organized body, and
- seems actuated with a like principle of life and motion. A continual
- circulation of matter in it produces no disorder: a continual waste in
- every part is incessantly repaired: the closest sympathy is perceived
- throughout the entire system: and each part or member, in performing
- its proper offices, operates both to its own preservation and to that
- of the whole. The world, therefore, I infer, is an animal; and the
- Deity is the soul of the world, actuating it, and actuated by it.
- You have too much learning, Cleanthes, to be at all surprised at this
- opinion, which, you know, was maintained by almost all the Theists of
- antiquity, and chiefly prevails in their discourses and reasonings.
- For though, sometimes, the ancient philosophers reason from final
- causes, as if they thought the world the workmanship of God; yet it
- appears rather their favourite notion to consider it as his body, whose
- organization renders it subservient to him. And it must be confessed,
- that, as the universe resembles more a human body than it does the
- works of human art and contrivance, if our limited analogy could ever,
- with any propriety, be extended to the whole of nature, the inference
- seems juster in favour of the ancient than the modern theory.
- There are many other advantages, too, in the former theory, which
- recommended it to the ancient theologians. Nothing more repugnant
- to all their notions, because nothing more repugnant to common
- experience, than mind without body; a mere spiritual substance,
- which fell not under their senses nor comprehension, and of which
- they had not observed one single instance throughout all nature. Mind
- and body they knew, because they felt both: an order, arrangement,
- organization, or internal machinery, in both, they likewise knew, after
- the same manner: and it could not but seem reasonable to transfer this
- experience to the universe; and to suppose the divine mind and body
- to be also coeval, and to have, both of them, order and arrangement
- naturally inherent in them, and inseparable from them.
- Here, therefore, is a new species of _Anthropomorphism_, Cleanthes,
- on which you may deliberate; and a theory which seems not liable to
- any considerable difficulties. You are too much superior, surely, to
- _systematical prejudices_, to find any more difficulty in supposing
- an animal body to be, originally, of itself, or from unknown causes,
- possessed of order and organization, than in supposing a similar order
- to belong to mind. But the _vulgar prejudice_, that body and mind
- ought always to accompany each other, ought not, one should think, to
- be entirely neglected; since it is founded on _vulgar experience_,
- the only guide which you profess to follow in all these theological
- inquiries. And if you assert, that our limited experience is an
- unequal standard, by which to judge of the unlimited extent of nature;
- you entirely abandon your own hypothesis, and must thenceforward
- adopt our Mysticism, as you call it, and admit of the absolute
- incomprehensibility of the Divine Nature.
- This theory, I own, replied Cleanthes, has never before occurred to me,
- though a pretty natural one; and I cannot readily, upon so short an
- examination and reflection, deliver any opinion with regard to it. You
- are very scrupulous, indeed, said Philo: were I to examine any system
- of yours, I should not have acted with half that caution and reserve,
- in starting objections and difficulties to it. However, if any thing
- occur to you, you will oblige us by proposing it.
- Why then, replied Cleanthes, it seems to me, that, though the world
- does, in many circumstances, resemble an animal body; yet is the
- analogy also defective in many circumstances the most material: no
- organs of sense; no seat of thought or reason; no one precise origin of
- motion and action. In short, it seems to bear a stronger resemblance
- to a vegetable than to an animal, and your inference would be so far
- inconclusive in favour of the soul of the world.
- But, in the next place, your theory seems to imply the eternity of
- the world; and that is a principle, which, I think, can be refuted by
- the strongest reasons and probabilities. I shall suggest an argument
- to this purpose, which, I believe, has not been insisted on by any
- writer. Those, who reason from the late origin of arts and sciences,
- though their inference wants not force, may perhaps be refuted by
- considerations derived from the nature of human society, which is in
- continual revolution, between ignorance and knowledge, liberty and
- slavery, riches and poverty; so that it is impossible for us, from
- our limited experience, to foretel with assurance what events may or
- may not be expected. Ancient learning and history seem to have been
- in great danger of entirely perishing after the inundation of the
- barbarous nations; and had these convulsions continued a little longer,
- or been a little more violent, we should not probably have now known
- what passed in the world a few centuries before us. Nay, were it not
- for the superstition of the Popes, who preserved a little jargon of
- Latin, in order to support the appearance of an ancient and universal
- church, that tongue must have been utterly lost; in which case, the
- Western world, being totally barbarous, would not have been in a fit
- disposition for receiving the Greek language and learning, which was
- conveyed to them after the sacking of Constantinople. When learning
- and books had been extinguished, even the mechanical arts would have
- fallen considerably to decay; and it is easily imagined, that fable or
- tradition might ascribe to them a much later origin than the true one.
- This vulgar argument, therefore, against the eternity of the world,
- seems a little precarious.
- But here appears to be the foundation of a better argument. Lucullus
- was the first that brought cherry-trees from Asia to Europe; though
- that tree thrives so well in many European climates, that it grows
- in the woods without any culture. Is it possible, that throughout a
- whole eternity, no European had ever passed into Asia, and thought of
- transplanting so delicious a fruit into his own country? Or if the tree
- was once transplanted and propagated, how could it ever afterwards
- perish? Empires may rise and fall, liberty and slavery succeed
- alternately, ignorance and knowledge give place to each other; but the
- cherry-tree will still remain in the woods of Greece, Spain and Italy,
- and will never be affected by the revolutions of human society.
- It is not two thousand years since vines were transplanted into France,
- though there is no climate in the world more favourable to them. It
- is not three centuries since horses, cows, sheep, swine, dogs, corn,
- were known in America. Is it possible, that during the revolutions
- of a whole eternity, there never arose a Columbus, who might open
- the communication between Europe and that continent? We may as well
- imagine, that all men would wear stockings for ten thousand years, and
- never have the sense to think of garters to tie them. All these seem
- convincing proofs of the youth, or rather infancy, of the world; as
- being founded on the operation of principles more constant and steady
- than those by which human society is governed and directed. Nothing
- less than a total convulsion of the elements will ever destroy all
- the European animals and vegetables which are now to be found in the
- Western world.
- And what argument have you against such convulsions? replied Philo.
- Strong and almost incontestable proofs may be traced over the whole
- earth, that every part of this globe has continued for many ages
- entirely covered with water. And though order were supposed inseparable
- from matter, and inherent in it; yet may matter be susceptible of many
- and great revolutions, through the endless periods of eternal duration.
- The incessant changes, to which every part of it is subject, seem to
- intimate some such general transformations; though, at the same time,
- it is observable, that all the changes and corruptions of which we
- have ever had experience, are but passages from one state of order to
- another; nor can matter ever rest in total deformity and confusion.
- What we see in the parts, we may infer in the whole; at least, that
- is the method of reasoning on which you rest your whole theory. And
- were I obliged to defend any particular system of this nature, which I
- never willingly should do, I esteem none more plausible than that which
- ascribes an eternal inherent principle of order to the world, though
- attended with great and continual revolutions and alterations. This at
- once solves all difficulties; and if the solution, by being so general,
- is not entirely complete and satisfactory, it is at least a theory that
- we must sooner or later have recourse to, whatever system we embrace.
- How could things have been as they are, were there not an original
- inherent principle of order somewhere, in thought or in matter? And it
- is very indifferent to which of these we give the preference. Chance
- has no place, on any hypothesis, sceptical or religious. Every thing
- is surely governed by steady, inviolable laws. And were the inmost
- essence of things laid open to us, we should then discover a scene,
- of which, at present, we can have no idea. Instead of admiring the
- order of natural beings, we should clearly see that it was absolutely
- impossible for them, in the smallest article, ever to admit of any
- other disposition.
- Were any one inclined to revive the ancient Pagan Theology, which
- maintained, as we learn from Hesiod, that this globe was governed
- by 30,000 deities, who arose from the unknown powers of nature: you
- would naturally object, Cleanthes, that nothing is gained by this
- hypothesis; and that it is as easy to suppose all men animals, beings
- more numerous, but less perfect, to have sprung immediately from a
- like origin. Push the same inference a step farther, and you will find
- a numerous society of deities as explicable as one universal deity,
- who possesses within himself the powers and perfections of the whole
- society. All these systems, then, of Scepticism, Polytheism, and
- Theism, you must allow, on your principles, to be on a like footing,
- and that no one of them has any advantage over the others. You may
- thence learn the fallacy of your principles.
- PART VII.
- But here, continued Philo, in examining the ancient system of the soul
- of the world, there strikes me, all on a sudden, a new idea, which, if
- just, must go near to subvert all your reasoning, and destroy even your
- first inferences, on which you repose such confidence. If the universe
- bears a greater likeness to animal bodies and to vegetables, than to
- the works of human art, it is more probable that its cause resembles
- the cause of the former than that of the latter, and its origin ought
- rather to be ascribed to generation or vegetation, than to reason or
- design. Your conclusion, even according to your own principles, is
- therefore lame and defective.
- Pray open up this argument a little farther, said Demea, for I do not
- rightly apprehend it in that concise manner in which you have expressed
- it.
- Our friend Cleanthes, replied Philo, as you have heard, asserts, that
- since no question of fact can be proved otherwise than by experience,
- the existence of a Deity admits not of proof from any other medium. The
- world, says he, resembles the works of human contrivance; therefore
- its cause must also resemble that of the other. Here we may remark,
- that the operation of one very small part of nature, to wit man, upon
- another very small part, to wit that inanimate matter lying within
- his reach, is the rule by which Cleanthes judges of the origin of
- the whole; and he measures objects, so widely disproportioned, by the
- same individual standard. But to waive all objections drawn from this
- topic, I affirm, that there are other parts of the universe (besides
- the machines of human invention) which bear still a greater resemblance
- to the fabric of the world, and which, therefore, afford a better
- conjecture concerning the universal origin of this system. These parts
- are animals and vegetables. The world plainly resembles more an animal
- or a vegetable, than it does a watch or a knitting-loom. Its cause,
- therefore, it is more probable, resembles the cause of the former. The
- cause of the former is generation or vegetation. The cause, therefore,
- of the world, we may infer to be something similar or analogous to
- generation or vegetation.
- But how is it conceivable, said Demea, that the world can arise from
- any thing similar to vegetation or generation?
- Very easily, replied Philo. In like manner as a tree sheds its seed
- into the neighbouring fields, and produces other trees; so the great
- vegetable, the world, or this planetary system, produces within itself
- certain seeds, which, being scattered into the surrounding chaos,
- vegetate into new worlds. A comet, for instance, is the seed of a
- world; and after it has been fully ripened, by passing from sun to sun,
- and star to star, it is at last tossed into the unformed elements which
- every where surround this universe, and immediately sprouts up into a
- new system.
- Or if, for the sake of variety (for I see no other advantage), we
- should suppose this world to be an animal; a comet is the egg of this
- animal: and in like manner as an ostrich lays its egg in the sand,
- which, without any farther care, hatches the egg, and produces a new
- animal; so ... I understand you, says Demea: But what wild, arbitrary
- suppositions are these! What _data_ have you for such extraordinary
- conclusions? And is the slight, imaginary resemblance of the world to
- a vegetable or an animal sufficient to establish the same inference
- with regard to both? Objects, which are in general so widely different,
- ought they to be a standard for each other?
- Right, cries Philo: This is the topic on which I have all along
- insisted. I have still asserted, that we have no _data_ to establish
- any system of cosmogony. Our experience, so imperfect in itself, and
- so limited both in extent and duration, can afford us no probable
- conjecture concerning the whole of things. But if we must needs fix
- on some hypothesis; by what rule, pray, ought we to determine our
- choice? Is there any other rule than the greater similarity of the
- objects compared? And does not a plant or an animal, which springs from
- vegetation or generation, bear a stronger resemblance to the world,
- than does any artificial machine, which arises from reason and design?
- But what is this vegetation and generation of which you talk, said
- Demea? Can you explain their operations, and anatomize that fine
- internal structure on which they depend?
- As much, at least, replied Philo, as Cleanthes can explain the
- operations of reason, or anatomize that internal structure on which
- _it_ depends. But without any such elaborate disquisitions, when I
- see an animal, I infer, that it sprang from generation; and that with
- as great certainty as you conclude a house to have been reared by
- design. These words, _generation, reason_, mark only certain powers
- and energies in nature, whose effects are known, but whose essence is
- incomprehensible; and one of these principles, more than the other, has
- no privilege for being made a standard to the whole of nature.
- In reality, Demea, it may reasonably be expected, that the larger the
- views are which we take of things, the better will they conduct us in
- our conclusions concerning such extraordinary and such magnificent
- subjects. In this little corner of the world alone, there are four
- principles, _reason, instinct, generation, vegetation_, which are
- similar to each other, and are the causes of similar effects. What a
- number of other principles may we naturally suppose in the immense
- extent and variety of the universe, could we travel from planet to
- planet, and from system to system, in order to examine each part of
- this mighty fabric? Any one of these four principles above mentioned,
- (and a hundred others which lie open to our conjecture), may afford
- us a theory by which to judge of the origin of the world; and it is
- a palpable and egregious partiality to confine our view entirely to
- that principle by which our own minds operate. Were this principle
- more intelligible on that account, such a partiality might be somewhat
- excuseable: But reason, in its internal fabric and structure, is
- really as little known to us as instinct or vegetation; and, perhaps,
- even that vague, undeterminate word, _Nature_, to which the vulgar
- refer every thing, is not at the bottom more inexplicable. The
- effects of these principles are all known to us from experience;
- but the principles themselves, and their manner of operation, are
- totally unknown; nor is it less intelligible, or less conformable to
- experience, to say, that the world arose by vegetation, from a seed
- shed by another world, than to say that it arose from a divine reason
- or contrivance, according to the sense in which Cleanthes understands
- it.
- But methinks, said Demea, if the world had a vegetative quality, and
- could sow the seeds of new worlds into the infinite chaos, this power
- would be still an additional argument for design in its author. For
- whence could arise so wonderful a faculty but from design? Or how can
- order spring from any thing which perceives not that order which it
- bestows?
- You need only look around you, replied Philo, to satisfy yourself with
- regard to this question. A tree bestows order and organization on that
- tree which springs from it, without knowing the order; an animal in
- the same manner on its offspring; a bird on its nest; and instances
- of this kind are even more frequent in the world than those of order,
- which arise from reason and contrivance. To say, that all this order
- in animals and vegetables proceeds ultimately from design, is begging
- the question; nor can that great point be ascertained otherwise than by
- proving, _a priori_, both that order is, from its nature, inseparably
- attached to thought; and that it can never of itself, or from original
- unknown principles, belong to matter.
- But farther, Demea; this objection which you urge can never be made
- use of by Cleanthes, without renouncing a defence which he has already
- made against one of my objections. When I inquired concerning the
- cause of that supreme reason and intelligence into which he resolves
- every thing; he told me, that the impossibility of satisfying such
- inquiries could never be admitted as an objection in any species of
- philosophy. _We must stop somewhere_, says he; _nor is it ever within
- the reach of human capacity to explain ultimate causes, of show the
- last connections of any objects. It is sufficient, if any steps, so
- far as we go, are supported by experience and observation_. Now, that
- vegetation and generation, as well as reason, are experienced to be
- principles of order in nature, is undeniable. If I rest my system of
- cosmogony on the former, preferably to the latter, it is at my choice.
- The matter seems entirely arbitrary. And when Cleanthes asks me what is
- the cause of my great vegetative or generative faculty, I am equally
- entitled to ask him the cause of his great reasoning principle. These
- questions we have agreed to forbear on both sides; and it is chiefly
- his interest on the present occasion to stick to this agreement.
- Judging by our limited and imperfect experience, generation has some
- privileges above reason: for we see every day the latter arise from the
- former, never the former from the latter.
- Compare, I beseech you, the consequences on both sides. The world, say
- I, resembles an animal; therefore it is an animal, therefore it arose
- from generation. The steps, I confess, are wide; yet there is some
- small appearance of analogy in each step. The world, says Cleanthes,
- resembles a machine; therefore it is a machine, therefore it arose from
- design. The steps are here equally wide, and the analogy less striking.
- And if he pretends to carry on _my_ hypothesis a step farther, and
- to infer design or reason from the great principle of generation, on
- which I insist; I may, with better authority, use the same freedom
- to push farther _his_ hypothesis, and infer a divine generation or
- theogony from his principle of reason. I have at least some faint
- shadow of experience, which is the utmost that can ever be attained in
- the present subject. Reason, in innumerable instances, is observed to
- arise from the principle of generation, and never to arise from any
- other principle.
- Hesiod, and all the ancient mythologists, were so struck with this
- analogy, that they universally explained the origin of nature from an
- animal birth, and copulation. Plato too, so far as he is intelligible,
- seems to have adopted some such notion in his Timæus.
- The Brahmins assert, that the world arose from an infinite spider,
- who spun this whole complicated mass from his bowels, and annihilates
- afterwards the whole or any part of it, by absorbing it again, and
- resolving it into his own essence. Here is a species of cosmogony,
- which appears to us ridiculous; because a spider is a little
- contemptible animal, whose operations we are never likely to take for
- a model of the whole universe. But still here is a new species of
- analogy, even in our globe. And were there a planet wholly inhabited by
- spiders, (which is very possible), this inference would there appear
- as natural and irrefragable as that which in our planet ascribes the
- origin of all things to design and intelligence, as explained by
- Cleanthes. Why an orderly system may not be spun from the belly as well
- as from the brain, it will be difficult for him to give a satisfactory
- reason.
- I must confess, Philo, replied Cleanthes, that of all men living, the
- task which you have undertaken, of raising doubts and objections,
- suits you best, and seems, in a manner, natural and unavoidable to
- you. So great is your fertility of invention, that I am not ashamed
- to acknowledge myself unable, on a sudden, to solve regularly such
- out-of-the-way difficulties as you incessantly start upon me: though
- I clearly see, in general, their fallacy and error. And I question
- not, but you are yourself, at present, in the same case, and have not
- the solution so ready as the objection: while you must be sensible,
- that common sense and reason are entirely against you; and that such
- whimsies as you have delivered, may puzzle, but never can convince us.
- PART VIII.
- What you ascribe to the fertility of my invention, replied Philo,
- is entirely owing to the nature of the subject. In subjects adapted
- to the narrow compass of human reason, there is commonly but one
- determination, which carries probability or conviction with it; and to
- a man of sound judgment, all other suppositions, but that one, appear
- entirely absurd and chimerical. But in such questions as the present, a
- hundred contradictory views may preserve a kind of imperfect analogy;
- and invention has here full scope to exert itself. Without any great
- effort of thought, I believe that I could, in an instant, propose other
- systems of cosmogony, which would have some faint appearance of truth;
- though it is a thousand, a million to one, if either yours or any one
- of mine be the true system.
- For instance, what if I should revive the old Epicurean hypothesis?
- This is commonly, and I believe justly, esteemed the most absurd
- system that has yet been proposed; yet I know not whether, with a few
- alterations, it might not be brought to bear a faint appearance of
- probability. Instead of supposing matter infinite, as Epicurus did, let
- us suppose it finite. A finite number of particles is only susceptible
- of finite transpositions: and it must happen, in an eternal duration,
- that every possible order or position must be tried an infinite number
- of times. This world, therefore, with all its events, even the most
- minute, has before been produced and destroyed, and will again be
- produced and destroyed, without any bounds and limitations. No one, who
- has a conception of the powers of infinite, in comparison of finite,
- will ever scruple this determination.
- But this supposes, said Demea, that matter can acquire motion, without
- any voluntary agent or first mover.
- And where is the difficulty, replied Philo, of that supposition? Every
- event, before experience, is equally difficult and incomprehensible;
- and every event, after experience, is equally easy and intelligible.
- Motion, in many instances, from gravity, from elasticity, from
- electricity, begins in matter, without any known voluntary agent:
- and to suppose always, in these cases, an unknown voluntary agent,
- is mere hypothesis; and hypothesis attended with no advantages. The
- beginning of motion in matter itself is as conceivable _a priori_ as
- its communication from mind and intelligence.
- Besides, why may not motion have been propagated by impulse through all
- eternity, and the same stock of it, or nearly the same, be still upheld
- in the universe? As much is lost by the composition of motion, as much
- is gained by its resolution. And whatever the causes are, the fact is
- certain, that matter is, and always has been, in continual agitation,
- as far as human experience or tradition reaches. There is not probably,
- at present, in the whole universe, one particle of matter at absolute
- rest.
- And this very consideration too, continued Philo, which we have
- stumbled on in the course of the argument, suggests a new hypothesis
- of cosmogony, that is not absolutely absurd and improbable. Is there a
- system, an order, an economy of things, by which matter can preserve
- that perpetual agitation which seems essential to it, and yet maintain
- a constancy in the forms which it produces? There certainly is such
- an economy; for this is actually the case with the present world.
- The continual motion of matter, therefore, in less than infinite
- transpositions, must produce this economy or order; and by its very
- nature, that order, when once established, supports itself, for many
- ages, if not to eternity. But wherever matter is so poized, arranged,
- and adjusted, as to continue in perpetual motion, and yet preserve a
- constancy in the forms, its situation must, of necessity, have all the
- same appearance of art and contrivance which we observe at present. All
- the parts of each form must have a relation to each other, and to the
- whole; and the whole itself must have a relation to the other parts
- of the universe; to the element in which the form subsists; to the
- materials with which it repairs its waste and decay; and to every other
- form which is hostile or friendly. A defect in any of these particulars
- destroys the form; and the matter of which it is composed is again set
- loose, and is thrown into irregular motions and fermentations, till it
- unite itself to some other regular form. If no such form be prepared
- to receive it, and if there be a great quantity of this corrupted
- matter in the universe, the universe itself is entirely disordered;
- whether it be the feeble embryo of a world in its first beginnings
- that is thus destroyed, or the rotten carcase of one languishing in
- old age and infirmity. In either case, a chaos ensues; till finite,
- though innumerable revolutions produce at last some forms, whose parts
- and organs are so adjusted as to support the forms amidst a continued
- succession of matter.
- Suppose (for we shall endeavour to vary the expression), that matter
- were thrown into any position, by a blind, unguided force; it is
- evident that this first position must, in all probability, be the
- most confused and most disorderly imaginable, without any resemblance
- to those works of human contrivance, which, along with a symmetry of
- parts, discover an adjustment of means to ends, and a tendency to
- self-preservation. If the actuating force cease after this operation,
- matter must remain for ever in disorder, and continue an immense chaos,
- without any proportion or activity. But suppose that the actuating
- force, whatever it be, still continues in matter, this first position
- will immediately give place to a second, which will likewise in all
- probability be as disorderly as the first, and so on through many
- successions of changes and revolutions. No particular order or position
- ever continues a moment unaltered. The original force, still remaining
- in activity, gives a perpetual restlessness to matter. Every possible
- situation is produced, and instantly destroyed. If a glimpse or dawn
- of order appears for a moment, it is instantly hurried away, and
- confounded, by that never-ceasing force which actuates every part of
- matter.
- Thus the universe goes on for many ages in a continued succession
- of chaos and disorder. But is it not possible that it may settle at
- last, so as not to lose its motion and active force (for that we
- have supposed inherent in it), yet so as to preserve an uniformity
- of appearance, amidst the continual motion and fluctuation of its
- parts? This we find to be the case with the universe at present.
- Every individual is perpetually changing, and every part of every
- individual; and yet the whole remains, in appearance, the same. May we
- not hope for such a position, or rather be assured of it, from the
- eternal revolutions of unguided matter; and may not this account for
- all the appearing wisdom and contrivance which is in the universe?
- Let us contemplate the subject a little, and we shall find, that this
- adjustment, if attained by matter of a seeming stability in the forms,
- with a real and perpetual revolution or motion of parts, affords a
- plausible, if not a true solution of the difficulty.
- It is in vain, therefore, to insist upon the uses of the parts in
- animals or vegetables, and their curious adjustment to each other. I
- would fain know, how an animal could subsist, unless its parts were so
- adjusted? Do we not find, that it immediately perishes whenever this
- adjustment ceases, and that its matter corrupting tries some new form?
- It happens indeed, that the parts of the world are so well adjusted,
- that some regular form immediately lays claim to this corrupted matter:
- and if it were not so, could the world subsist? Must it not dissolve as
- well as the animal, and pass through new positions and situations, till
- in great, but finite succession, it fall at last into the present or
- some such order?
- It is well, replied Cleanthes, you told us, that this hypothesis
- was suggested on a sudden, in the course of the argument. Had
- you had leisure to examine it, you would soon have perceived the
- insuperable objections to which it is exposed. No form, you say, can
- subsist, unless it possess those powers and organs requisite for its
- subsistence: some new order or economy must be tried, and so on,
- without intermission; till at last some order, which can support and
- maintain itself, is fallen upon. But according to this hypothesis,
- whence arise the many conveniences and advantages which men and all
- animals possess? Two eyes, two ears, are not absolutely necessary for
- the subsistence of the species. Human race might have been propagated
- and preserved, without horses, dogs, cows, sheep, and those innumerable
- fruits and products which serve to our satisfaction and enjoyment. If
- no camels had been created for the use of man in the sandy deserts of
- Africa and Arabia, would the world have been dissolved? If no loadstone
- had been framed to give that wonderful and useful direction to the
- needle, would human society and the human kind have been immediately
- extinguished? Though the maxims of Nature be in general very frugal,
- yet instances of this kind are far from being rare; and any one of them
- is a sufficient proof of design, and of a benevolent design, which gave
- rise to the order and arrangement of the universe.
- At least, you may safely infer, said Philo, that the foregoing
- hypothesis is so far incomplete and imperfect, which I shall not
- scruple to allow. But can we ever reasonably expect greater success
- in any attempts of this nature? Or can we ever hope to erect a system
- of cosmogony, that will be liable to no exceptions, and will contain
- no circumstance repugnant to our limited and imperfect experience of
- the analogy of Nature? Your theory itself cannot surely pretend to any
- such advantage, even though you have run into _Anthropomorphism_, the
- better to preserve a conformity to common experience. Let us once more
- put into trial. In all instances which we have ever seen, ideas are
- copied from real objects, and are ectypal, not archetypal, to express
- myself in learned terms: You reverse this order, and give thought the
- precedence. In all instances which we have ever seen, thought has no
- influence upon matter, except where that matter is so conjoined with
- it as to have an equal reciprocal influence upon it. No animal can move
- immediately any thing but the members of its own body; and indeed,
- the equality of action and re-action seems to be an universal law of
- nature: But your theory implies a contradiction to this experience.
- These instances, with many more, which it were easy to collect,
- (particularly the supposition of a mind or system of thought that is
- eternal, or, in other words, an animal ingenerable and immortal); these
- instances, I say, may teach all of us sobriety in condemning each
- other, and let us see, that as no system of this kind ought ever to be
- received from a slight analogy, so neither ought any to be rejected on
- account of a small incongruity. For that is an inconvenience from which
- we can justly pronounce no one to be exempted.
- All religious systems, it is confessed, are subject to great and
- insuperable difficulties. Each disputant triumphs in his turn; while he
- carries on an offensive war, and exposes the absurdities, barbarities,
- and pernicious tenets of his antagonist. But all of them, on the whole,
- prepare a complete triumph for the _Sceptic_; who tells them, that no
- system ought ever to be embraced with regard to such subjects: For
- this plain reason, that no absurdity ought ever to be assented to with
- regard to any subject. A total suspense of judgment is here our only
- reasonable resource. And if every attack, as is commonly observed, and
- no defence, among Theologians, is successful; how complete must be
- _his_ victory, who remains always, with all mankind, on the offensive,
- and has himself no fixed station or abiding city, which he is ever, on
- any occasion, obliged to defend?
- PART IX.
- But if so many difficulties attend the argument _a posteriori_, said
- Demea, had we not better adhere to that simple and sublime argument _a
- priori_, which, by offering to us infallible demonstration, cuts off
- at once all doubt and difficulty? By this argument, too, we may prove
- the INFINITY of the Divine attributes, which, I am afraid, can never be
- ascertained with certainty from any other topic. For how can an effect,
- which either is finite, or, for aught we know, may be so; how can such
- an effect, I say, prove an infinite cause? The unity too of the Divine
- Nature, it is very difficult, if not absolutely impossible, to deduce
- merely from contemplating the works of nature; nor will the uniformity
- alone of the plan, even were it allowed, give us any assurance of that
- attribute. Whereas the argument _a priori_....
- You seem to reason, Demea, interposed Cleanthes, as if those
- advantages and conveniences in the abstract argument were full proofs
- of its solidity. But it is first proper, in my opinion, to determine
- what argument of this nature you choose to insist on; and we shall
- afterwards, from itself, better than from its _useful_ consequences,
- endeavour to determine what value we ought to put upon it.
- The argument, replied Demea, which I would insist on, is the common
- one. Whatever exists must have a cause or reason of its existence; it
- being absolutely impossible for any thing to produce itself, or be the
- cause of its own existence. In mounting up, therefore, from effects
- to causes, we must either go on in tracing an infinite succession,
- without any ultimate cause at all; or must at last have recourse to
- some ultimate cause, that is _necessarily_ existent: Now, that the
- first supposition is absurd, may be thus proved. In the infinite chain
- or succession of causes and effects, each single effect is determined
- to exist by the power and efficacy of that cause which immediately
- preceded; but the whole eternal chain or succession, taken together,
- is not determined or caused by any thing; and yet it is evident that
- it requires a cause or reason, as much as any particular object
- which begins to exist in time. The question is still reasonable,
- why this particular succession of causes existed from eternity, and
- not any other succession, or no succession at all. If there be no
- necessarily existent being, any supposition which can be formed is
- equally possible; nor is there any more absurdity in Nothing's having
- existed from eternity, than there is in that succession of causes
- which constitutes the universe. What was it, then, which determined
- Something to exist rather than Nothing, and bestowed being on a
- particular possibility, exclusive of the rest? _External causes_, there
- are supposed to be none. _Chance_ is a word without a meaning. Was it
- _Nothing_? But that can never produce any thing. We must, therefore,
- have recourse to a necessarily existent Being, who carries the REASON
- of his existence in himself, and who cannot be supposed not to exist,
- without an express contradiction. There is, consequently, such a Being;
- that is, there is a Deity.
- I shall not leave it to Philo, said Cleanthes, though I know that the
- starting objections is his chief delight, to point out the weakness of
- this metaphysical reasoning. It seems to me so obviously ill-grounded,
- and at the same time of so little consequence to the cause of true
- piety and religion, that I shall myself venture to show the fallacy of
- it.
- I shall begin with observing, that there is an evident absurdity in
- pretending to demonstrate a matter of fact, or to prove it by any
- arguments _a priori_. Nothing is demonstrable, unless the contrary
- implies a contradiction. Nothing, that is distinctly conceivable,
- implies a contradiction. Whatever we conceive as existent, we can
- also conceive as non-existent. There is no being, therefore, whose
- non-existence implies a contradiction. Consequently there is no being,
- whose existence is demonstrable. I propose this argument as entirely
- decisive, and am willing to rest the whole controversy upon it.
- It is pretended that the Deity is a necessarily existent being; and
- this necessity of his existence is attempted to be explained by
- asserting, that if we knew his whole essence or nature, we should
- perceive it to be as impossible for him not to exist, as for twice two
- not to be four. But it is evident that this can never happen, while
- our faculties remain the same as at present. It will still be possible
- for us, at any time, to conceive the non-existence of what we formerly
- conceived to exist; nor can the mind ever lie under a necessity of
- supposing any object to remain always in being; in the same manner as
- we lie under a necessity of always conceiving twice two to be four. The
- words, therefore, _necessary existence_, have no meaning; or, which is
- the same thing, none that is consistent.
- But farther, why may not die material universe be the necessarily
- existent Being, according to this pretended explication of necessity?
- We dare not affirm that we know all the qualities of matter; and for
- aught we can determine, it may contain some qualities, which, were they
- known, would make its non-existence appear as great a contradiction as
- that twice two is five. I find only one argument employed to prove,
- that the material world is not the necessarily existent Being; and
- this argument is derived from the contingency both of the matter and
- the form of the world. 'Any particle of matter,' it is said,[1] 'may
- be _conceived_ to be annihilated; and any form may be _conceived_ to
- be altered. Such an annihilation or alteration, therefore, is not
- impossible.' But it seems a great partiality not to perceive, that
- the same argument extends equally to the Deity, so far as we have
- any conception of him; and that the mind can at least imagine him to
- be non-existent, or his attributes to be altered. It must be some
- unknown, inconceivable qualities, which can make his non-existence
- appear impossible, or his attributes unalterable: And no reason can
- be assigned, why these qualities may not belong to matter. As they
- are altogether unknown and inconceivable, they can never be proved
- incompatible with it.
- Add to this, that in tracing an eternal succession of objects, it seems
- absurd to inquire for a general cause or first author. How can any
- thing, that exists from eternity, have a cause, since that relation
- implies a priority in time, and a beginning of existence?
- In such a chain, too, or succession of objects, each part is caused
- by that which preceded it, and causes that which succeeds it. Where
- then is the difficulty? But the WHOLE, you say, wants a cause. I
- answer, that the uniting of these parts into a whole, like the uniting
- of several distinct countries into one kingdom, or several distinct
- members into one body, is performed merely by an arbitrary act of the
- mind, and has no influence on the nature of things. Did I show you
- the particular causes of each individual in a collection of twenty
- particles of matter, I should think it very unreasonable, should you
- afterwards ask me, what was the cause of the whole twenty. This is
- sufficiently explained in explaining the cause of the parts.
- Though the reasonings which you have urged, Cleanthes, may well
- excuse me, said Philo, from starting any farther difficulties, yet
- I cannot forbear insisting still upon another topic. It is observed
- by arithmeticians, that the products of 9 compose always either 9,
- or some lesser product of 9, if you add together all the characters
- of which any of the former products is composed. Thus, of 18, 27,
- 36, which are products of 9, you make 9 by adding 1 to 8, 2 to 7, 3
- to 6. Thus, 369 is a product also of 9; and if you add 3, 6, and 9,
- you make 18, a lesser product of 9.[2] To a superficial observer, so
- wonderful a regularity may be admired as the effect either of chance
- or design: but a skilful algebraist immediately concludes it to be
- the work of necessity, and demonstrates, that it must for ever result
- from the nature of these numbers. Is it not probable, I ask, that the
- whole economy of the universe is conducted by a like necessity, though
- no human algebra can furnish a key which solves the difficulty? And
- instead of admiring the order of natural beings, may it not happen,
- that, could we penetrate into the intimate nature of bodies, we should
- clearly see why it was absolutely impossible they could ever admit of
- any other disposition? So dangerous is it to introduce this idea of
- necessity into the present question! and so naturally does it afford an
- inference directly opposite to the religious hypothesis!
- But dropping all these abstractions, continued Philo, and confining
- ourselves to more familiar topics, I shall venture to add an
- observation, that the argument _a priori_ has seldom been found
- very convincing, except to people of a metaphysical head, who have
- accustomed themselves to abstract reasoning, and who, finding from
- mathematics, that the understanding frequently leads to truth through
- obscurity, and, contrary to first appearances, have transferred the
- same habit of thinking to subjects where it ought not to have place.
- Other people, even of good sense and the best inclined to religion,
- feel always some deficiency in such arguments, though they are not
- perhaps able to explain distinctly where it lies; a certain proof that
- men ever did, and ever will derive their religion from other sources
- than from this species of reasoning.
- [1] Dr Clarke.
- [2] République des Lettres, Août 1685.
- PART X.
- It is my opinion, I own, replied Demea, that each man feels, in a
- manner, the truth of religion within his own breast, and, from a
- consciousness of his imbecility and misery, rather than from any
- reasoning, is led to seek protection from that Being, on whom he and
- all nature is dependent. So anxious or so tedious are even the best
- scenes of life, that futurity is still the object of all our hopes
- and fears. We incessantly look forward, and endeavour, by prayers,
- adoration, and sacrifice, to appease those unknown powers, whom we
- find, by experience, so able to afflict and oppress us. Wretched
- creatures that we are! what resource for us amidst the innumerable
- ills of life, did not religion, suggest some methods of atonement,
- and appease those terrors with which we are incessantly agitated and
- tormented?
- I am indeed persuaded, said Philo, that the best, and indeed the only
- method of bringing every one to a due sense of religion, is by just
- representations of the misery and wickedness of men. And for that
- purpose a talent of eloquence and strong imagery is more requisite than
- that of reasoning and argument. For is it necessary to prove what every
- one feels within himself? It is only necessary to make us feel it, if
- possible, more intimately and sensibly.
- The people, indeed, replied Demea, are sufficiently convinced of this
- great and melancholy truth. The miseries of life; the unhappiness
- of man; the general corruptions of our nature; the unsatisfactory
- enjoyment of pleasures, riches, honours; these phrases have become
- almost proverbial in all languages. And who can doubt of what all men
- declare from their own immediate feeling and experience?
- In this point, said Philo, the learned are perfectly agreed with the
- vulgar; and in all letters, _sacred_ and _profane_, the topic of
- human misery has been insisted on with the most pathetic eloquence
- that sorrow and melancholy could inspire. The poets, who speak from
- sentiment, without a system, and whose testimony has therefore the
- more authority, abound in images of this nature. From Homer down to Dr
- Young, the whole inspired tribe have ever been sensible, that no other
- representation of things would suit the feeling and observation of each
- individual.
- As to authorities, replied Demea, you need not seek them. Look round
- this library of Cleanthes. I shall venture to affirm, that, except
- authors of particular sciences, such as chemistry or botany, who have
- no occasion to treat of human life, there is scarce one of those
- innumerable writers, from whom the sense of human misery has not, in
- some passage or other, extorted a complaint and confession of it. At
- least, the chance is entirely on that side; and no one author has ever,
- so far as I can recollect, been so extravagant as to deny it.
- There you must excuse me, said Philo: Leibnitz has denied it; and is
- perhaps the first[1] who ventured upon so bold and paradoxical an
- opinion; at least, the first who made it essential to his philosophical
- system.
- And by being the first, replied Demea, might he not have been sensible
- of his error? For is this a subject in which philosophers can propose
- to make discoveries especially in so late an age? And can any man hope
- by a simple denial (for the subject scarcely admits of reasoning),
- to bear down the united testimony of mankind, founded on sense and
- consciousness?
- And why should man, added he, pretend to an exemption from the lot of
- all other animals? The whole earth, believe me, Philo, is cursed and
- polluted. A perpetual war is kindled amongst all living creatures.
- Necessity, hunger, want, stimulate the strong and courageous: Fear,
- anxiety, terror, agitate the weak and infirm. The first entrance into
- life gives anguish to the new-born infant and to its wretched parent:
- Weakness, impotence, distress, attend each stage of that life: and it
- is at last finished in agony and horror.
- Observe too, says Philo, the curious artifices of Nature, in order
- to embitter the life of every living being. The stronger prey upon
- the weaker, and keep them in perpetual terror and anxiety. The weaker
- too, in their turn, often prey upon the stronger, and vex and molest
- them without relaxation. Consider that innumerable race of insects,
- which either are bred on the body of each animal, or, flying about,
- infix their stings in him. These insects have others still less than
- themselves, which torment them. And thus on each hand, before and
- behind, above and below, every animal is surrounded with enemies, which
- incessantly seek his misery and destruction.
- Man alone, said Demea, seems to be, in part, an exception to this rule.
- For by combination in society, he can easily master lions, tigers, and
- bears, whose greater strength and agility naturally enable them to prey
- upon him.
- On the contrary, it is here chiefly, cried Philo, that the uniform
- and equal maxims of Nature are most apparent. Man, it is true, can,
- by combination, surmount all his _real_ enemies, and become master of
- the whole animal creation: but does he not immediately raise up to
- himself _imaginary_ enemies, the demons of his fancy, who haunt him
- with superstitious terrors, and blast every enjoyment of life? His
- pleasure, as he imagines, becomes, in their eyes, a crime: his food and
- repose give them umbrage and offence: his very sleep and dreams furnish
- new materials to anxious fear: and even death, his refuge from every
- other ill, presents only the dread of endless and innumerable woes. Nor
- does the wolf molest more the timid flock, than superstition does the
- anxious breast of wretched mortals.
- Besides, consider, Demea: This very society, by which we surmount those
- wild beasts, our natural enemies; what new enemies does it not raise to
- us? What wo and misery does it not occasion? Man is the greatest enemy
- of man. Oppression, injustice, contempt, contumely, violence, sedition,
- war, calumny, treachery, fraud; by these they mutually torment each
- other; and they would soon dissolve that society which they had formed,
- were it not for the dread of still greater ills, which must attend
- their separation.
- But though these external insults, said Demea, from animals, from men,
- from all the elements, which assault us, form a frightful catalogue
- of woes, they are nothing in comparison of those which arise within
- ourselves, from the distempered condition of our mind and body. How
- many lie under the lingering torment of diseases? Hear the pathetic
- enumeration of the great poet.
- Intestine stone and ulcer, colic-pangs,
- Demoniac frenzy, moping melancholy,
- And moon-struck madness, pining atrophy,
- Marasmus, and wide-wasting pestilence.
- Dire was the tossing, deep the groans: *DESPAIR
- Tended the sick, busiest from couch to couch.
- And over them triumphant *DEATH his dart
- Shook: but delay'd to strike, though oft invok'd
- With vows, as their chief good and final hope.
- The disorders of the mind, continued Demea, though more secret, are
- not perhaps less dismal and vexatious. Remorse, shame, anguish, rage,
- disappointment, anxiety, fear, dejection, despair; who has ever passed
- through life without cruel inroads from these tormentors? How many
- have scarcely ever felt any better sensations? Labour and poverty, so
- abhorred by every one, are the certain lot of the far greater number;
- and those few privileged persons, who enjoy ease and opulence, never
- reach contentment or true felicity. All the goods of life united would
- not make a very happy man; but all the ills united would make a wretch
- indeed; and any one of them almost (and who can be free from every
- one?) nay often the absence of one good (and who can possess all?) is
- sufficient to render life ineligible.
- Were a stranger to drop on a sudden into this world, I would show him,
- as a specimen of its ills, an hospital full of diseases, a prison
- crowded with malefactors and debtors, a field of battle strewed with
- carcases, a fleet foundering in the ocean, a nation languishing under
- tyranny, famine, or pestilence. To turn the gay side of life to him,
- and give him a notion of its pleasures; whether should I conduct him?
- to a ball, to an opera, to court? He might justly think, that I was
- only showing him a diversity of distress and sorrow.
- There is no evading such striking instances, said Philo, but by
- apologies, which still farther aggravate the charge. Why have all men,
- I ask, in all ages, complained incessantly of the miseries of life?....
- They have no just reason, says one: these complaints proceed only from
- their discontented, repining, anxious disposition.... And can there
- possibly, I reply, be a more certain foundation of misery, than such a
- wretched temper?
- But if they were really as unhappy as they pretend, says my antagonist,
- why do they remain in life?....
- Not satisfied with life, afraid of death.
- This is the secret chain, say I, that holds us. We are terrified, not
- bribed to the continuance of our existence.
- It is only a false delicacy, he may insist, which a few refined spirits
- indulge, and which has, spread these complaints among the whole, nice
- of mankinds.... And what is this delicacy, I ask, which you blame? Is
- it any thing but a greater sensibility to all the pleasures and pains
- of life? and if the man of a delicate, refined temper, by being so much
- more alive than the rest of the world, is only so much more unhappy,
- what judgment must we form in general of human life?
- Let men remain at rest, says our adversary, and they will be easy. They
- are willing artificers of their own misery.... No! reply I: an anxious
- languor follows their repose; disappointment, vexation, trouble, their
- activity and ambition.
- I can observe something like what you mention in some others, replied
- Cleanthes: but I confess I feel little or nothing of it in myself, and
- hope that it is not so common as you represent it.
- If you feel not human misery yourself, cried Demea, I congratulate
- you on so happy a singularity. Others, seemingly the most prosperous,
- have not been ashamed to vent their complaints in the most melancholy
- strains. Let us attend to the great, the fortunate emperor, Charles
- V., when, tired with human grandeur, he resigned all his extensive
- dominions into the hands of his son. In the last harangue which
- he made on that memorable occasion, he publicly avowed, _that the
- greatest prosperities which he had ever enjoyed, had been mixed with
- so many adversities, that he might truly say he had never enjoyed
- any satisfaction or contentment_. But did the retired life, in which
- he sought for shelter, afford him any greater happiness? If we may
- credit his son's account, his repentance commenced the very day of his
- resignation.
- Cicero's fortune, from small beginnings, rose to the greatest lustre
- and renown; yet what pathetic complaints of the ills of life do his
- familiar letters, as well as philosophical discourses, contain? And
- suitably to his own experience, he introduces Cato, the great, the
- fortunate Cato, protesting in his old age, that had he a new life in
- his offer, he would reject the present.
- Ask yourself, ask any of your acquaintance, whether they would live
- over again the last ten or twenty years of their life. No! but the next
- twenty, they say, will be better:
- And from the dregs of life, hope to receive
- What the first sprightly running could not give.
- Thus at last they find (such is the greatness of human misery, it
- reconciles even contradictions), that they complain at once of the
- shortness of life, and of its vanity and sorrow.
- And is it possible, Cleanthes, said Philo, that after all these
- reflections, and infinitely more, which might be suggested, you
- can still persevere in your Anthropomorphism, and assert the moral
- attributes of the Deity, his justice, benevolence, mercy, and
- rectitude, to be of the same nature with these virtues in human
- creatures? His power we allow is infinite: whatever he wills is
- executed: but neither man nor any other animal is happy: therefore he
- does not will their happiness. His wisdom is infinite: he is never
- mistaken in choosing the means to any end: but the course of Nature
- tends not to human or animal felicity: therefore it is not established
- for that purpose. Through the whole compass of human knowledge, there
- are no inferences more certain and infallible than these. In what
- respect, then, do his benevolence and mercy resemble the benevolence
- and mercy of men?
- Epicurus's old questions are yet unanswered.
- Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is
- he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent Is he both able and
- willing? whence then is evil?
- You ascribe, Cleanthes (and I believe justly), a purpose and intention
- to Nature. But what, I beseech you, is the object of that curious
- artifice and machinery, which she has displayed in all animals? The
- preservation alone of individuals, and propagation of the species. It
- seems enough for her purpose, if such a rank be barely upheld in the
- universe, without any care or concern for the happiness of the members
- that compose it. No resource for this purpose: no machinery, in order
- merely to give pleasure or ease: no fund of pure joy and contentment:
- no indulgence, without some want or necessity accompanying it. At
- least, the few phenomena of this nature are overbalanced by opposite
- phenomena of still greater importance.
- Our sense of music, harmony, and indeed beauty of all kinds, gives
- satisfaction, without being absolutely necessary to the preservation
- and propagation of the species. But what racking pains, on the other
- hand, arise from gouts, gravels, megrims, toothaches, rheumatisms,
- where the injury to the animal machinery is either small or incurable?
- Mirth, laughter, play, frolic, seem gratuitous satisfactions, which
- have no farther tendency: spleen, melancholy, discontent, superstition,
- are pains of the same nature. How then does the Divine benevolence
- display itself, in the sense of you Anthropomorphites? None but we
- Mystics, as you were pleased to call us, can account for this strange
- mixture of phenomena, by deriving it from attributes, infinitely
- perfect, but incomprehensible.
- And have you at last, said Cleanthes smiling, betrayed your intentions,
- Philo? Your long agreement with Demea did indeed a little surprise me;
- but I find you were all the while erecting a concealed battery against
- me. And I must confess, that you have now fallen upon a subject worthy
- of your noble spirit of opposition and controversy. If you can make out
- the present point, and prove mankind to be unhappy or corrupted, there
- is an end at once of all religion. For to what purpose establish the
- natural attributes of the Deity, while the moral are still doubtful and
- uncertain?
- You take umbrage very easily, replied Demea, at opinions the most
- innocent, and the most generally received, even amongst the religious
- and devout themselves: and nothing can be more surprising than to
- find a topic like this, concerning the wickedness and misery of man,
- charged with no less than Atheism and profaneness. Have not all
- pious divines and preachers, who have indulged their rhetoric on so
- fertile a subject; have they not easily, I say, given a solution of
- any difficulties which may attend it? This world is but a point in
- comparison of the universe; this life but a moment in comparison of
- eternity. The present evil phenomena, therefore, are rectified in
- other regions, and in some future period of existence. And the eyes
- of men, being then opened to larger views of things, see the whole
- connection of general laws; and trace with adoration, the benevolence
- and rectitude of the Deity, through all the mazes and intricacies of
- his providence.
- No! replied Cleanthes, No! These arbitrary suppositions can never be
- admitted, contrary to matter of fact, visible and uncontroverted.
- Whence can any cause be known but from its known effects? Whence can
- any hypothesis be proved but from the apparent phenomena? To establish
- one hypothesis upon another, is building entirely in the air; and
- the utmost we ever attain, by these conjectures and fictions, is to
- ascertain the bare possibility of our opinion; but never can we, upon
- such terms, establish its reality.
- The only method of supporting Divine benevolence, and it is what I
- willingly embrace, is to deny absolutely the misery and wickedness of
- man. Your representations are exaggerated; your melancholy views mostly
- fictitious; your inferences contrary to fact and experience. Health is
- more common than sickness; pleasure than pain; happiness than misery.
- And for one vexation which we meet with, we attain, upon computation, a
- hundred enjoyments.
- Admitting your position, replied Philo, which yet is extremely
- doubtful, you must at the same time allow, that if pain be less
- frequent than pleasure, it is infinitely more violent and durable.
- One hour of it is often able to outweigh a day, a week, a month of
- our common insipid enjoyments; and how many days, weeks, and months,
- are passed by several in the most acute torments? Pleasure, scarcely
- in one instance, is ever able to reach ecstasy and rapture; and in
- no one instance can it continue for any time at its highest pitch
- and altitude. The spirits evaporate, the nerves relax, the fabric is
- disordered, and the enjoyment quickly degenerates into fatigue and
- uneasiness. But pain often, good God, how often! rises to torture and
- agony; and the longer it continues, it becomes still more genuine agony
- and torture. Patience is exhausted, courage languishes, melancholy
- seizes us, and nothing terminates our misery but the removal of its
- cause, or another event, which is the sole cure of all evil, but
- which, from our natural folly, we regard with still greater horror and
- consternation.
- But not to insist upon these topics, continued Philo, though most
- obvious, certain, and important; I must use the freedom to admonish
- you, Cleanthes, that you have put the controversy upon a most dangerous
- issue, and are unawares introducing a total scepticism into the most
- essential articles of natural and revealed theology. What! no method of
- fixing a just foundation for religion, unless we allow the happiness
- of human life, and maintain a continued existence even in this world,
- with all our present pains, infirmities, vexations, and follies, to be
- eligible and desirable! But this is contrary to every one's feeling and
- experience: It is contrary to an authority so established as nothing
- can subvert.
- No decisive proofs can ever be produced against this authority; nor is
- it possible for you to compute, estimate and compare, all the pains and
- all the pleasures in the lives of all men and of all animals: And thus,
- by your resting the whole system of religion on a point, which, from
- its very nature, must for ever be uncertain, you tacitly confess, that
- that system is equally uncertain.
- But allowing you what never will be believed, at least what you never
- possibly can prove, that animal, or at least human happiness, in this
- life, exceeds its misery, you have yet done nothing: For this is not,
- by any means, what we expect from infinite power, infinite wisdom, and
- infinite goodness. Why is there any misery at all in the world? Not by
- chance surely. From some cause then. Is it from the intention of the
- Deity? But he is perfectly benevolent. Is it contrary to his intention?
- But he is almighty. Nothing can shake the solidity of this reasoning,
- so short, so clear, so decisive; except we assert, that these subjects
- exceed all human capacity, and that our common measures of truth and
- falsehood are not applicable to them; a topic which I have all along
- insisted on, but which you have, from the beginning, rejected with
- scorn and indignation.
- But I will be contented to retire still from this intrenchment, for
- I deny that you can ever force me in it. I will allow, that pain or
- misery in man is _compatible_ with infinite power and goodness in the
- Deity, even in your sense of these attributes: What are you advanced by
- all these concessions? A mere possible compatibility is not sufficient.
- You must _prove_ these pure, unmixt, and uncontrollable attributes
- from the present mixt and confused phenomena, and from these alone. A
- hopeful undertaking! Were the phenomena ever so pure and unmixt, yet
- being finite, they would be insufficient for that purpose. How much
- more, where they are also so jarring and discordant!
- Here, Cleanthes, I find myself at ease in my argument. Here I triumph.
- Formerly, when we argued concerning the natural attributes of
- intelligence and design, I needed all my sceptical and metaphysical
- subtilty to elude your grasp. In many views of the universe, and of its
- parts, particularly the latter, the beauty and fitness of final causes
- strike us with such irresistible force, that all objections appear
- (what I believe they really are) mere cavils and sophisms; nor can
- we then imagine how it was ever possible for us to repose any weight
- on them. But there is no view of human life, or of the condition of
- mankind, from which, without the greatest violence, we can infer the
- moral attributes, or learn that infinite benevolence, conjoined with
- infinite power and infinite wisdom, which we must discover by the eyes
- of faith alone. It is your turn now to tug the labouring oar, and to
- support your philosophical subtilties against the dictates of plain
- reason and experience.
- [1] That sentiment had been maintained by Dr King, and some few others,
- before Leibnitz, though by none of so great fame as that German
- philosopher.
- PART XI.
- I scruple not to allow, said Cleanthes, that I have been apt to
- suspect the frequent repetition of the word _infinite_, which we meet
- with in all theological writers, to savour more of panegyric than of
- philosophy; and that any purposes of reasoning, and even of religion,
- would be better served, were we to rest contented with more accurate
- and more moderate expressions. The terms, _admirable, excellent,
- superlatively great, wise_, and _holy_; these sufficiently fill the
- imaginations of men; and any thing beyond, besides that it leads into
- absurdities, has no influence on the affections or sentiments. Thus,
- in the present subject, if we abandon all human analogy, as seems your
- intention, Demea, I am afraid we abandon all religion, and retain no
- conception of the great object of our adoration. If we preserve human
- analogy, we must for ever find it impossible to reconcile any mixture
- of evil in the universe with infinite attributes; much less can we ever
- prove the latter from the former. But supposing the Author of Nature
- to be finitely perfect, though far exceeding mankind, a satisfactory
- account may then be given of natural and moral evil, and every untoward
- phenomenon be explained and adjusted. A less evil may then be chosen,
- in order to avoid a greater; inconveniences be submitted to, in order
- to reach a desirable end; and in a word, benevolence, regulated by
- wisdom, and limited by necessity, may produce just such a world as
- the present. You, Philo, who are so prompt at starting views, and
- reflections, and analogies, I would gladly hear, at length, without
- interruption, your opinion of this new theory; and if it deserve our
- attention, we may afterwards, at more leisure, reduce it into form.
- My sentiments, replied Philo, are not worth being made a mystery of;
- and therefore, without any ceremony, I shall deliver what occurs to
- me with regard to the present subject. It must, I think, be allowed,
- that if a very limited intelligence, whom we shall suppose utterly
- unacquainted with the universe, were assured, that it were the
- production of a very good, wise, and powerful Being, however finite, he
- would, from his conjectures, form _beforehand_ a different notion of it
- from what we find it to be by experience; nor would he ever imagine,
- merely from these attributes of the cause, of which he is informed,
- that the effect could be so full of vice and misery and disorder, as
- it appears in this life. Supposing now, that this person were brought
- into the world, still assured that it was the workmanship of such a
- sublime and benevolent Being; he might, perhaps, be surprised at the
- disappointment; but would never retract his former belief, if founded
- on any very solid argument; since such a limited intelligence must
- be sensible of his own blindness and ignorance, and must allow, that
- there may be many solutions of those phenomena, which will for ever
- escape his comprehension. But supposing, which is the real case with
- regard to man, that this creature is not antecedently convinced of a
- supreme intelligence, benevolent, and powerful, but is left to gather
- such a belief from the appearances of things; this entirely alters
- the case, nor will he ever find any reason for such a conclusion. He
- may be fully convinced of the narrow limits of his understanding; but
- this will not help him in forming an inference concerning the goodness
- of superior powers, since he must form that inference from what he
- knows, not from what he is ignorant of. The more you exaggerate his
- weakness and ignorance, the more diffident you render him, and give
- him the greater suspicion that such subjects are beyond the reach of
- his faculties. You are obliged, therefore, to reason with him merely
- from the known phenomena, and to drop every arbitrary supposition or
- conjecture.
- Did I show you a house or palace, where there was not one apartment
- convenient or agreeable; where the windows, doors, fires passages,
- stairs, and the whole economy of the building, were the source of
- noise, confusion, fatigue, darkness, and the extremes of heat and
- cold; you would certainly blame the contrivance, without any farther
- examination. The architect would in vain display his subtilty, and
- prove to you, that if this door or that window were altered, greater
- ills would ensue. What he says may be strictly true: The alteration
- of one particular, while the other parts of the building remain, may
- only augment the inconveniences. But still you would assert in general,
- that, if the architect had had skill and good intentions, he might
- have formed such a plan of the whole, and might have adjusted the
- parts in such a manner, as would have remedied all or most of these
- inconveniences. His ignorance, or even your own ignorance of such a
- plan, will never convince you of the impossibility of it. If you find
- any inconveniences and deformities in the building, you will always,
- without entering into any detail, condemn the architect.
- In short, I repeat the question: Is the world, considered in general,
- and as it appears to us in this life, different from what a man, or
- such a limited being, would, _beforehand_, expect from a very powerful,
- wise, and benevolent Deity? It must be strange prejudice to assert
- the contrary. And from thence I conclude, that however consistent the
- world may be, allowing certain suppositions and conjectures, with the
- idea of such a Deity, it can never afford us an inference concerning
- his existence. The consistence is not absolutely denied, only the
- inference. Conjectures, especially where infinity is excluded from the
- Divine attributes, may perhaps be sufficient to prove a consistence,
- but can never be foundations for any inference.
- There seem to be _four_ circumstances, on which depend all, or the
- greatest part of the ills, that molest sensible creatures; and it
- is not impossible but all these circumstances may be necessary
- and unavoidable. We know so little beyond common life, or even of
- common life, that, with regard to the economy of a universe, there
- is no conjecture, however wild, which may not be just; nor any one,
- however plausible, which may not be erroneous. All that belongs to
- human understanding, in this deep ignorance and obscurity, is to be
- sceptical, or at least cautious, and not to admit of any hypothesis
- whatever, much less of any which is supported by no appearance of
- probability. Now, this I assert to be the case with regard to all the
- causes of evil, and the circumstances on which it depends. None of them
- appear to human reason in the least degree necessary or unavoidable;
- nor can we suppose them such, without the utmost license of imagination.
- The _first_ circumstance which introduces evil, is that contrivance or
- economy of the animal creation, by which pains, as well as pleasures,
- are employed to excite all creatures to action, and make them vigilant
- in the great work of self-preservation. Now pleasure alone, in its
- various degrees, seems to human understanding sufficient for this
- purpose. All animals might be constantly in a state of enjoyment:
- but when urged by any of the necessities of nature, such as thirst,
- hunger, weariness; instead of pain, they might feel a diminution of
- pleasure, by which they might be prompted to seek that object which
- is necessary to their subsistence. Men pursue pleasure as eagerly as
- they avoid pain; at least, they might have been so constituted. It
- seems, therefore, plainly possible to carry on the business of life
- without any pain. Why then is any animal ever rendered susceptible of
- such a sensation? If animals can be free from it an hour, they might
- enjoy a perpetual exemption from it; and it required as particular a
- contrivance of their organs to produce that feeling, as to endow them
- with sight, hearing, or any of the senses. Shall we conjecture, that
- such a contrivance was necessary, without any appearance of reason? and
- shall we build on that conjecture as on the most certain truth?
- But a capacity of pain would not alone produce pain, were it not for
- the _second_ circumstance, viz. the conducting of the world by general
- laws; and this seems nowise necessary to a very perfect Being. It is
- true, if every thing were conducted by particular volitions, the course
- of nature would be perpetually broken, and no man could employ his
- reason in the conduct of life. But might not other particular volitions
- remedy this inconvenience? In short, might not the Deity exterminate
- all ill, wherever it were to be found; and produce all good, without
- any preparation, or long progress of causes and effects?
- Besides, we must consider, that, according to the present economy of
- the world, the course of nature, though supposed exactly regular,
- yet to us appears not so, and many events are uncertain, and many
- disappoint our expectations. Health and sickness, calm and tempest,
- with an infinite number of other accidents, whose causes are unknown
- and variable, have a great influence both on the fortunes of particular
- persons and on the prosperity of public societies; and indeed all human
- life, in a manner, depends on such accidents. A being, therefore, who
- knows the secret springs of the universe, might easily, by particular
- volitions, turn all these accidents to the good of mankind, and render
- the whole world happy, without discovering himself in any operation.
- A fleet, whose purposes were salutary to society, might always meet
- with a fair wind. Good princes enjoy sound health and long life.
- Persons born to power and authority, be framed with good tempers and
- virtuous dispositions. A few such events as these, regularly and
- wisely conducted, would change the face of the world; and yet would no
- more seem to disturb the course of nature, or confound human conduct,
- than the present economy of things, where the causes are secret, and
- variable, and compounded. Some small touches given to Caligula's brain
- in his infancy, might have converted him into a Trajan. One wave, a
- little higher than the rest, by burying Cæsar and his fortune in the
- bottom of the ocean, might have restored liberty to a considerable
- part of mankind. There may, for aught we know, be good reasons why
- Providence interposes not in this manner; but they are unknown to
- us; and though the mere supposition, that such reasons exist, may be
- sufficient to _save_ the conclusion concerning the Divine attributes,
- yet surely it can never be sufficient to _establish_ that conclusion.
- If every thing in the universe be conducted by general laws, and if
- animals be rendered susceptible of pain, it scarcely seems possible
- but some ill must arise in the various shocks of matter, and the
- various concurrence and opposition of general laws; but this ill
- would be very rare, were it not for the _third_ circumstance, which I
- proposed to mention, viz. the great frugality with which all powers
- and faculties are distributed to every particular being. So well
- adjusted are the organs and capacities of all animals, and so well
- fitted to their preservation, that, as far as history or tradition
- reaches, there appears not to be any single species which has yet
- been extinguished in the universe. Every animal has the requisite
- endowments; but these endowments are bestowed with so scrupulous an
- economy, that any considerable diminution must entirely destroy the
- creature. Wherever one power is increased, there is a proportional
- abatement in the others. Animals which excel in swiftness are commonly
- defective in force. Those which possess both are either imperfect in
- some of their senses, or are oppressed with the most craving wants.
- The human species, whose chief excellency is reason and sagacity, is
- of all others the most necessitous, and the most deficient in bodily
- advantages; without clothes, without arms, without food, without
- lodging, without any convenience of life, except what they owe to
- their own skill and industry. In short, nature seems to have formed
- an exact calculation of the necessities of her creatures; and, like
- a _rigid master_, has afforded them little more powers or endowments
- than what are strictly sufficient to supply those necessities. An
- _indulgent parent_ would have bestowed a large stock, in order to
- guard against accidents, and secure the happiness and welfare of the
- creature in the most unfortunate concurrence of circumstances. Every
- course of life would not have been so surrounded with precipices, that
- the least departure from the true path, by mistake or necessity, must
- involve us in misery and ruin. Some reserve, some fund, would have been
- provided to ensure happiness; nor would the powers and the necessities
- have been adjusted with so rigid an economy. The Author of Nature is
- inconceivably powerful: his force is supposed great, if not altogether
- inexhaustible: nor is there any reason, as far as we can judge, to make
- him observe this strict frugality in his dealings with his creatures.
- It would have been better, were his power extremely limited, to have
- created fewer animals, and to have endowed these with more faculties
- for their happiness and preservation. A builder is never esteemed
- prudent, who undertakes a plan beyond what his stock will enable him to
- finish.
- In order to cure most of the ills of human life, I require not that
- man should have the wings of the eagle, the swiftness of the stag, the
- force of the ox, the arms of the lion, the scales of the crocodile
- or rhinoceros; much less do I demand the sagacity of an angel or
- cherubim. I am contented to take an increase in one single power or
- faculty of his soul. Let him be endowed with a greater propensity to
- industry and labour; a more vigorous spring and activity of mind; a
- more constant bent to business and application. Let the whole species
- possess naturally an equal diligence with that which many individuals
- are able to attain by habit and reflection; and the most beneficial
- consequences, without any allay of ill, is the immediate and necessary
- result of this endowment. Almost all the moral, as well as natural
- evils of human life, arise from idleness; and were our species, by
- the original constitution of their frame, exempt from this vice or
- infirmity, the perfect cultivation of land, the improvement of arts and
- manufactures, the exact execution of every office and duty, immediately
- follow; and men at once may fully reach that state of society, which
- is so imperfectly attained by the best regulated government. But
- as industry is a power, and the most valuable of any, Nature seems
- determined, suitably to her usual maxims, to bestow it on men with a
- very sparing hand; and rather to punish him severely for his deficiency
- in it, than to reward him for his attainments. She has so contrived
- his frame, that nothing but the most violent necessity can oblige him
- to labour; and she employs all his other wants to overcome, at least
- in part, the want of diligence, and to endow him with some share of a
- faculty of which she has thought fit naturally to bereave him. Here our
- demands may be allowed very humble, and therefore the more reasonable.
- If we required the endowments of superior penetration and judgment, of
- a more delicate taste of beauty, of a nicer sensibility to benevolence
- and friendship; we might be told, that we impiously pretend to break
- the order of Nature; that we want to exalt ourselves into a higher rank
- of being; that the presents which we require, not being suitable to our
- state and condition, would only be pernicious to us. But it is hard; I
- dare to repeat it, it is hard, that being placed in a world so full of
- wants and necessities, where almost every being and element is either
- our foe or refuses its assistance ... we should also have our own
- temper to struggle with, and should be deprived of that faculty which
- can alone fence against these multiplied evils.
- The _fourth_ circumstance, whence arises the misery and ill of
- the universe, is the inaccurate workmanship of all the springs and
- principles of the great machine of nature. It must be acknowledged,
- that there are few parts of the universe, which seem not to serve
- some purpose, and whose removal would not produce a visible defect
- and disorder in the whole. The parts hang all together; nor can one
- be touched without affecting the rest, in a greater or less degree.
- But at the same time, it must be observed, that none of these parts
- or principles, however useful, are so accurately adjusted, as to keep
- precisely within those bounds in which their utility consists; but
- they are, all of them, apt, on every occasion, to run into the one
- extreme or the other. One would imagine, that this grand production
- had not received the last hand of the maker; so little finished is
- every part, and so coarse are the strokes with which it is executed.
- Thus, the winds are requisite to convey the vapours along the surface
- of the globe, and to assist men in navigation: but how oft, rising
- up to tempests and hurricanes, do they become pernicious? Rains are
- necessary to nourish all the plants and animals of the earth: but how
- often are they defective? how often excessive? Heat is requisite to all
- life and vegetation; but is not always found in the due proportion.
- On the mixture and secretion of the humours and juices of the body
- depend the health and prosperity of the animal: but the parts perform
- not regularly their proper function. What more useful than all the
- passions of the mind, ambition, vanity love, anger? But how oft do they
- break their bounds, and cause the greatest convulsions in society?
- There is nothing so advantageous in the universe, but what frequently
- becomes pernicious, by its excess or defect; nor has Nature guarded,
- with the requisite accuracy, against all disorder or confusion. The
- irregularity is never perhaps so great as to destroy any species; but
- is often sufficient to involve the individuals in ruin and misery.
- On the concurrence, then, of these _four_ circumstances, does all or
- the greatest part of natural evil depend. Were all living creatures
- incapable of pain, or were the world administered by particular
- volitions, evil never could have found access into the universe: and
- were animals endowed with a large stock of powers and faculties,
- beyond what strict necessity requires; or were the several springs
- and principles of the universe so accurately framed as to preserve
- always the just temperament and medium; there must have been very
- little ill in comparison of what we feel at present. What then shall
- we pronounce on this occasion? Shall we say that these circumstances
- are not necessary, and that they might easily have been altered in
- the contrivance of the universe? This decision seems too presumptuous
- for creatures so blind and ignorant. Let us be more modest in our
- conclusions. Let us allow, that, if the goodness of the Diety (I mean
- a goodness like the human) could be established on any tolerable
- reasons _a priori_, these phenomena, however untoward, would not be
- sufficient to subvert that principle; but might easily, in some unknown
- manner, be reconcileable to it. But let us still assert, that as this
- goodness is not antecedently established, but must be inferred from the
- phenomena, there can be no grounds for such an inference, while there
- are so many ills in the universe, and while these ills might so easily
- have been remedied, as far as human understanding can be allowed to
- judge on such a subject. I am Sceptic enough to allow, that the bad
- appearances, notwithstanding all my reasonings, may be compatible with
- such attributes as you suppose; but surely they can never prove these
- attributes. Such a conclusion cannot result from Scepticism, but must
- arise from the phenomena, and from our confidence in the reasonings
- which we deduce from these phenomena.
- Look round this universe. What an immense profusion of beings, animated
- and organized, sensible and active! You admire this prodigious
- variety and fecundity. But inspect a little more narrowly these
- living existences, the only beings worth regarding. How hostile and
- destructive to each other! How insufficient all of them for their own
- happiness! How contemptible or odious to the spectator! The whole
- presents nothing but the idea of a blind Nature, impregnated by a
- great vivifying principle, and pouring forth from her lap, without
- discernment or parental care, her maimed and abortive children!
- Here the Manichæan system occurs as a proper hypothesis to solve the
- difficulty: and no doubt, in some respects, it is very specious, and
- has more probability than the common hypothesis, by giving a plausible
- account of the strange mixture of good and ill which appears in life.
- But if we consider, on the other hand, the perfect uniformity and
- agreement of the parts of the universe, we shall not discover in it any
- marks of the combat of a malevolent with a benevolent being. There is
- indeed an opposition of pains and pleasures in the feelings of sensible
- creatures: but are not all the operations of Nature carried on by an
- opposition of principles, of hot and cold, moist and dry, light and
- heavy? The true conclusion is, that the original Source of all things
- is entirely indifferent to all these principles; and has no more regard
- to good above ill, than to heat above cold, or to drought above
- moisture, or to light above heavy.
- There may _four_ hypotheses be framed concerning the first causes of
- the universe: _that_ they are endowed with perfect goodness; _that_
- they have perfect malice; _that_ they are opposite, and have both
- goodness and malice; _that_ they have neither goodness nor malice. Mixt
- phenomena can never prove the two former unmixt principles; and the
- uniformity and steadiness of general laws seem to oppose the third. The
- fourth, therefore, seems by far the most probable.
- What I have said concerning natural evil will apply to moral, with
- little or no variation; and we have no more reason to infer, that the
- rectitude of the Supreme Being resembles human rectitude, than that
- his benevolence resembles the human. Nay, it will be thought, that we
- have still greater cause to exclude from him moral sentiments, such as
- we feel them; since moral evil, in the opinion of many, is much more
- predominant above moral good than natural evil above natural good.
- But even though this should not be allowed, and though the virtue which
- is in mankind should be acknowledged much superior to the vice, yet so
- long as there is any vice at all in the universe, it will very much
- puzzle you Anthropomorphites, how to account for it. You must assign a
- cause for it, without having recourse to the first cause. But as every
- effect must have a cause, and that cause another, you must either carry
- on the progression _in infinitum_, or rest on that original principle,
- who is the ultimate cause of all things....
- Hold! hold! cried Demea: Whither does your imagination hurry you? I
- joined in alliance with you, in order to prove the incomprehensible
- nature of the Divine Being, and refute the principles of Cleanthes,
- who would measure every thing by human rule and standard. But I now
- find you running into all the topics of the greatest libertines and
- infidels, and betraying that holy cause which you seemingly espoused.
- Are you secretly, then, a more dangerous enemy than Cleanthes himself?
- And are you so late in perceiving it? replied Cleanthes. Believe me,
- Demea, your friend Philo, from the beginning, has been amusing himself
- at both our expense; and it must be confessed, that the injudicious
- reasoning of our vulgar theology has given him but too just a handle
- of ridicule. The total infirmity of human reason, the absolute
- incomprehensibility of the Divine Nature, the great and universal
- misery, and still greater wickedness of men; these are strange topics,
- surely, to be so fondly cherished by orthodox divines and doctors.
- In ages of stupidity and ignorance, indeed, these principles may
- safely be espoused; and perhaps no views of things are more proper to
- promote superstition, than such as encourage the blind amazement, the
- diffidence, and melancholy of mankind. But at present....
- Blame not so much, interposed Philo, the ignorance of these reverend
- gentlemen. They know how to change their style with the times. Formerly
- it was a most popular theological topic to maintain, that human life
- was vanity and misery, and to exaggerate all the ills and pains which
- are incident to men. But of late years, divines, we find, begin to
- retract this position; and maintain, though still with some hesitation,
- that there are more goods than evils, more pleasures than pains, even
- in this life. When religion stood entirely upon temper and education,
- it was thought proper to encourage melancholy; as indeed mankind never
- have recourse to superior powers so readily as in that disposition. But
- as men have now learned to form principles, and to draw consequences,
- it is necessary to change the batteries, and to make use of such
- arguments as will endure at least some scrutiny and examination. This
- variation is the same (and from the same causes) with that which I
- formerly remarked with regard to Scepticism.
- Thus Philo continued to the last his spirit of opposition, and his
- censure of established opinions. But I could observe that Demea did not
- at all relish the latter part of the discourse; and he took occasion
- soon after, on some pretence or other, to leave the company.
- PART XII.
- After Demea's departure, Cleanthes and Philo continued the conversation
- in the following manner. Our friend, I am afraid, said Cleanthes,
- will have little inclination to revive this topic of discourse,
- while you are in company; and to tell truth, Philo, I should rather
- wish to reason with either of you apart on a subject so sublime and
- interesting. Your spirit of controversy, joined to your abhorence of
- vulgar superstition, carries you strange lengths, when engaged in an
- argument; and there is nothing so sacred and venerable, even in your
- own eyes, which you spare on that occasion.
- I must confess, replied Philo, that I am less cautious on the subject
- of Natural Religion than on any other; both because I know that I can
- never, on that head, corrupt the principles of any man of common sense;
- and because no one, I am confident, in whose eyes I appear a man of
- common sense, will ever mistake my intentions. You, in particular,
- Cleanthes, with whom I live in unreserved intimacy; you are sensible,
- that notwithstanding the freedom of my conversation, and my love of
- singular arguments, no one has a deeper sense of religion impressed
- on his mind, or pays more profound adoration to the Divine Being,
- as he discovers himself to reason, in the inexplicable contrivance
- and artifice of nature. A purpose, an intention, a design, strikes
- every where the most careless, the most stupid thinker; and no man
- can be so hardened in absurd systems, as at all times to reject it.
- _That Nature does nothing in vain_, is a maxim established in all
- the schools, merely from the contemplation of the works of Nature,
- without any religious purpose; and, from a firm conviction of its
- truth, an anatomist, who had observed a new organ or canal, would never
- be satisfied till he had also discovered its use and intention. One
- great foundation of the Copernican system is the maxim, _That Nature
- acts by the simplest methods, and chooses the most proper means to
- any end_; and astronomers often, without thinking of it, lay this
- strong foundation of piety and religion. The same thing is observable
- in other parts of philosophy: And thus all the sciences almost lead
- us insensibly to acknowledge a first intelligent Author; and their
- authority is often so much the greater, as they do not directly profess
- that intention.
- It is with pleasure I hear Galen reason concerning the structure of
- the human body. The anatomy of a man, says he,[1] discovers above 600
- different muscles; and whoever duly considers these, will find, that,
- in each of them, Nature must have adjusted at least ten different
- circumstances, in order to attain the end which she proposed; proper
- figure, just magnitude, right disposition of the several ends, upper
- and lower position of the whole, the due insertion of the several
- nerves, veins, and arteries: So that, in the muscles alone, above 6000
- several views and intentions must have been formed and executed. The
- bones he calculates to be 284: The distinct purposes aimed at in the
- structure of each, above forty. What a prodigious display of artifice,
- even in these simple and homogeneous parts! But if we consider the
- skin, ligaments, vessels, glandules, humours, the several limbs and
- members of the body; how must our astonishment rise upon us, in
- proportion to the number and intricacy of the parts so artificially
- adjusted! The farther we advance in these researches, we discover new
- scenes of art and wisdom: But descry still, at a distance, farther
- scenes beyond our reach; in the fine internal structure of the parts,
- in the economy of the brain, in the fabric of the seminal vessels. All
- these artifices are repeated in every different species of animal, with
- wonderful variety, and with exact propriety, suited to the different
- intentions of Nature in framing each species. And if the infidelity of
- Galen, even when these natural sciences were still imperfect, could
- not withstand such striking appearances, to what pitch of pertinacious
- obstinacy must a philosopher in this age have attained, who can now
- doubt of a Supreme Intelligence!
- Could I meet with one of this species (who, I thank God, are very
- rare), I would ask him: Supposing there were a God, who did not
- discover himself immediately to our senses, were it possible for him
- to give stronger proofs of his existence, than what appear on the
- whole face of Nature? What indeed could such a Divine Being do, but
- copy the present economy of things; render many of his artifices so
- plain, that no stupidity could mistake them; afford glimpses of still
- greater artifices, which demonstrate his prodigious superiority above
- our narrow apprehensions; and conceal altogether a great many from such
- imperfect creatures? Now, according to all rules of just reasoning,
- every fact must pass for undisputed, when it is supported by all the
- arguments which its nature admits of; even though these arguments be
- not, in themselves, very numerous or forcible: How much more, in the
- present case, where no human imagination can compute their number, and
- no understanding estimate their cogency!
- I shall farther add, said Cleanthes, to what you have so well urged,
- that one great advantage of the principle of Theism, is, that it is
- the only system of cosmogony which can be rendered intelligible and
- complete, and yet can throughout preserve a strong analogy to what
- we every day see and experience in the world. The comparison of the
- universe to a machine of human contrivance, is so obvious and natural,
- and is justified by so many instances of order and design in Nature,
- that it must immediately strike all unprejudiced apprehensions,
- and procure universal approbation. Whoever attempts to weaken this
- theory, cannot pretend to succeed by establishing in its place any
- other that is precise and determinate: It is sufficient for him if
- he start doubts and difficulties; and by remote and abstract views
- of things, reach that suspense of judgment, which is here the utmost
- boundary of his wishes. But, besides that this state of mind is in
- itself unsatisfactory, it can never be steadily maintained against
- such striking appearances as continually engage us into the religious
- hypothesis. A false, absurd system, human nature, from the force of
- prejudice, is capable of adhering to with obstinacy and perseverance:
- But no system at all, in opposition to a theory supported by strong and
- obvious reason, by natural propensity, and by early education, I think
- it absolutely impossible to maintain or defend.
- So little, replied Philo, do I esteem this suspense of judgment in the
- present case to be possible, that I am apt to suspect there enters
- somewhat of a dispute of words into this controversy; more than is
- usually imagined. That the works of Nature bear a great analogy to
- the productions of art, is evident; and according to all the rules of
- good reasoning, we ought to infer, if we argue at all concerning them,
- that their causes have a proportional analogy. But as there are also
- considerable differences, we have reason to suppose a proportional
- difference in the causes; and in particular, ought to attribute a much
- higher degree of power and energy to the supreme cause, than any we
- have ever observed in mankind. Here then the existence of a *DEITY is
- plainly ascertained by reason: and if we make it a question, whether,
- on account of these analogies, we can properly call him a _mind_
- or _intelligence_, notwithstanding the vast difference which may
- reasonably be supposed between him and human minds; what is this but
- a mere verbal controversy? No man can deny the analogies between the
- effects: To restrain ourselves from inquiring concerning the causes is
- scarcely possible. From this inquiry, the legitimate conclusion is,
- that the causes have also an analogy: And if we are not contented with
- calling the first and supreme cause a *GOD or *DEITY, but desire to
- vary the expression; what can we call him but *MIND or $THOUGHT, to
- which he is justly supposed to bear a considerable resemblance?
- All men of sound reason are disgusted with verbal disputes, which
- abound so much in philosophical and theological inquiries; and it
- is found, that the only remedy for this abuse must arise from clear
- definitions, from the precision of those ideas which enter into any
- argument, and from the strict and uniform use of those terms which
- are employed. But there is a species of controversy, which, from the
- very nature of language and of human ideas, is involved in perpetual
- ambiguity, and can never, by any precaution or any definitions, be
- able to reach a reasonable certainty or precision. These are the
- controversies concerning the degrees of any quality or circumstance.
- Men may argue to all eternity, whether Hannibal be a great, or a very
- great, or a superlatively great man, what degree of beauty Cleopatra
- possessed, what epithet of praise Livy or Thucydides is entitled to,
- without bringing the controversy to any determination. The disputants
- may here agree in their sense, and differ in the terms, or _vice
- versa_; yet never be able to define their terms, so as to enter into
- each other's meaning: Because the degrees of these qualities are not,
- like quantity or number, susceptible of any exact mensuration, which
- may be the standard in the controversy. That the dispute concerning
- Theism is of this nature, and consequently is merely verbal, or
- perhaps, if possible, still more incurably ambiguous, will appear upon
- the slightest inquiry. I ask the Theist, if he does not allow, that
- there is a great and immeasurable, because incomprehensible difference
- between the _human_ and the _divine_ mind: The more pious he is, the
- more readily will he assent to the affirmative, and the more will he
- be disposed to magnify the difference: He will even assert, that the
- difference is of a nature which cannot be too much magnified. I next
- turn to the Atheist, who, I assert, is only nominally so, and can never
- possibly be in earnest; and I ask him, whether, from the coherence
- and apparent sympathy in all the parts of this world, there be not
- a certain degree of analogy among all the operations of Nature, in
- every situation and in every age; whether the rotting of a turnip, the
- generation of an animal, and the structure of human thought, be not
- energies that probably bear some remote analogy to each other: It
- is impossible he can deny it: He will readily acknowledge it. Having
- obtained this concession, I push him still farther in his retreat;
- and I ask him, if it be not probable, that the principle which first
- arranged, and still maintains order in this universe, bears not also
- some remote inconceivable analogy to the other operations of Nature,
- and, among the rest, to the economy of human mind and thought. However
- reluctant, he must give his assent. Where then, cry I to both these
- antagonists, is the subject of your dispute? The Theist allows, that
- the original intelligence is very different from human reason: The
- Atheist allows, that the original principle of order bears some remote
- analogy to it. Will you quarrel, Gentlemen, about the degrees, and
- enter into a controversy, which admits not of any precise meaning,
- nor consequently of any determination? If you should be so obstinate,
- I should not be surprised to find you insensibly change sides; while
- the Theist, on the one hand, exaggerates the dissimilarity between the
- Supreme Being, and frail, imperfect, variable, fleeting, and mortal
- creatures; and the Atheist, on the other, magnifies the analogy among
- all the operations of Nature, in every period, every situation, and
- every position. Consider then, where the real point of controversy
- lies; and if you cannot lay aside your disputes, endeavour, at least,
- to cure yourselves of your animosity.
- And here I must also acknowledge, Cleanthes, that as the works of
- Nature have a much greater analogy to the effects of _our_ art and
- contrivance, than to those of _our_ benevolence and justice, we have
- reason to infer, that the natural attributes of the Deity have a
- greater resemblance to those of men, than his moral have to human
- virtues. But what is the consequence? Nothing but this, that the moral
- qualities of man are more defective in their kind than his natural
- abilities. For, as the Supreme Being is allowed to be absolutely and
- entirely perfect, whatever differs most from him, departs the farthest
- from the supreme standard of rectitude and perfection.[2]
- These, Cleanthes, are my unfeigned sentiments on this subject; and
- these sentiments, you know, I have ever cherished and maintained. But
- in proportion to my veneration for true religion, is my abhorrence of
- vulgar superstitions; and I indulge a peculiar pleasure, I confess,
- in pushing such principles, sometimes into absurdity, sometimes into
- impiety. And you are sensible, that all bigots, notwithstanding their
- great aversion to the latter above the former, are commonly equally
- guilty of both.
- My inclination, replied Cleanthes, lies, I own, a contrary way.
- Religion, however corrupted, is still better than no religion at all.
- The doctrine of a future state is so strong and necessary a security
- to morals, that we never ought to abandon or neglect it. For if and
- temporary rewards and punishments have so great an effect, as we daily
- find; how much greater must be expected from such as are infinite and
- eternal?
- How happens it then, said Philo, if vulgar superstition be so salutary
- to society, that all history abounds so much with accounts of its
- pernicious consequences on public affairs? Factions, civil wars,
- persecutions, subversions of government, oppression, slavery; these
- are the dismal consequences which always attend its prevalency over
- the minds of men. If the religious spirit be ever mentioned in any
- historical narration, we are sure to meet afterwards with a detail of
- the miseries which attend it. And no period of time can be happier or
- more prosperous, than those in which it is never regarded or heard of.
- The reason of this observation, replied Cleanthes, is obvious. The
- proper office of religion is to regulate the heart of men, humanize
- their conduct, infuse the spirit of temperance, order, and obedience;
- and as its operation is silent, and only enforces the motives of
- morality and justice, it is in danger of being overlooked, and
- confounded with these other motives. When it distinguishes itself, and
- acts as a separate principle over men, it has departed from its proper
- sphere, and has become only a cover to faction and ambition.
- And so will all religion, said Philo, except the philosophical and
- rational kind. Your reasonings are more easily eluded than my facts.
- The inference is not just, because finite and temporary rewards and
- punishments have so great influence, that therefore such as are
- infinite and eternal must have so much greater. Consider, I beseech
- you, the attachment which we have to present things, and the little
- concern which we discover for objects so remote and uncertain. When
- divines are declaiming against the common behaviour and conduct of
- the world, they always represent this principle as the strongest
- imaginable (which indeed it is); and describe almost all human kind as
- lying under the influence of it, and sunk into the deepest lethargy
- and unconcern about their religious interests. Yet these same divines,
- when they refute their speculative antagonists, suppose the motives
- of religion to be so powerful, that, without them, it were impossible
- for civil society to subsist; nor are they ashamed of so palpable a
- contradiction. It is certain, from experience, that the smallest grain
- of natural honesty and benevolence has more effect on men's conduct,
- than the most pompous views suggested by theological theories and
- systems. A man's natural inclination works incessantly upon him; it
- is for ever present to the mind, and mingles itself with every view
- and consideration: whereas religious motives, where they act at all,
- operate only by starts and bounds; and it is scarcely possible for them
- to become altogether habitual to the mind. The force of the greatest
- gravity, say the philosophers, is infinitely small, in comparison of
- that of the least impulse: yet it is certain, that the smallest gravity
- will, in the end, prevail above a great impulse; because no strokes or
- blows can be repeated with such constancy as attraction and gravitation.
- Another advantage of inclination: It engages on its side all the wit
- and ingenuity of the mind; and when set in opposition to religious
- principles, seeks every method and art of eluding them: In which it
- is almost always successful. Who can explain the heart of man, or
- account for those strange salvos and excuses, with which people satisfy
- themselves, when they follow their inclinations in opposition to their
- religious duty? This is well understood in the world; and none but
- fools ever repose less trust in a man, because they hear, that from
- study and philosophy, he has entertained some speculative doubts with
- regard to theological subjects. And when we have to do with a man, who
- makes a great profession of religion and devotion, has this any other
- effect upon several, who pass for prudent, than to put them on their
- guard, lest they be cheated and deceived by him?
- We must farther consider, that philosophers, who cultivate reason and
- reflection, stand less in need of such motives to keep them under
- the restraint of morals; and that the vulgar, who alone may need
- them, are utterly incapable of so pure a religion as represents the
- Deity to be pleased with nothing but virtue in human behaviour. The
- recommendations to the Divinity are generally supposed to be either
- frivolous observances, or rapturous ecstasies, or a bigotted credulity.
- We need not run back into antiquity, or wander into remote regions,
- to find instances of this degeneracy. Amongst ourselves, some have
- been guilty of that atrociousness, unknown to the Egyptian and Grecian
- superstitions, of declaiming in express terms, against morality; and
- representing it as a sure forfeiture of the Divine favour, if the least
- trust or reliance be laid upon it.
- But even though superstition or enthusiasm should not put itself in
- direct opposition to morality; the very diverting of the attention,
- the raising up a new and frivolous species of merit, the preposterous
- distribution which it makes of praise and blame, must have the most
- pernicious consequences, and weaken extremely men's attachment to the
- natural motives of justice and humanity.
- Such a principle of action likewise, not being any of the familiar
- motives of human conduct, acts only by intervals on the temper;
- and must be roused by continual efforts, in order to render the
- pious zealot satisfied with his own conduct, and make him fulfil
- his devotional task. Many religious exercises are entered into with
- seeming fervour, where the heart, at the time, feels cold and languid:
- A habit of dissimulation is by degrees contracted; and fraud and
- falsehood become the predominant principle. Hence the reason of that
- vulgar observation, that the highest zeal in religion and the deepest
- hypocrisy, so far from being inconsistent, are often or commonly united
- in the same individual character.
- The bad effects of such habits, even in common life, are easily
- imagined; but where the interests of religion are concerned, no
- morality can be forcible enough to bind the enthusiastic zealot. The
- sacredness of the cause sanctifies every measure which can be made use
- of to promote it.
- The steady attention alone to so important an interest as that of
- eternal salvation, is apt to extinguish the benevolent affections,
- and beget a narrow, contracted selfishness. And when such a temper is
- encouraged, it easily eludes all the general precepts of charity and
- benevolence.
- Thus, the motives of vulgar superstition have no great influence on
- general conduct; nor is their operation favourable to morality, in the
- instances where they predominate.
- Is there any maxim in politics more certain and infallible, than that
- both the number and authority of priests should be confined within very
- narrow limits; and that the civil magistrate ought, for ever, to keep
- his _fasces_ and _axes_ from such dangerous hands? But if the spirit of
- popular religion were so salutary to society, a contrary maxim ought
- to prevail. The greater number of priests, and their greater authority
- and riches, will always augment the religious spirit. And though the
- priests have the guidance of this spirit, why may we not expect a
- superior sanctity of life, and greater benevolence and moderation, from
- persons who are set apart for religion, who are continually inculcating
- it upon others, and who must themselves imbibe a greater share of it?
- Whence comes it then, that, in fact, the utmost a wise magistrate can
- propose with regard to popular religions, is, as far as possible, to
- make a saving game of it, and to prevent their pernicious consequences
- with regard to society? Every expedient which he tries for so humble
- a purpose is surrounded with inconveniences. If he admits only one
- religion among his subjects, he must sacrifice, to an uncertain
- prospect of tranquillity, every consideration of public liberty,
- science, reason, industry, and even his own independency. If he gives
- indulgence to several sects, which is the wiser maxim, he must preserve
- a very philosophical indifference to all of them, and carefully
- restrain the pretensions of the prevailing sect; otherwise he can
- expect nothing but endless disputes, quarrels, factions, persecutions,
- and civil commotions.
- True religion, I allow, has no such pernicious consequences: but we
- must treat of religion, as it has commonly been found in the world;
- nor have I any thing to do with that speculative tenet of Theism,
- which, as it is a species of philosophy, must partake of the beneficial
- influence of that principle, and at the same time must lie under a like
- inconvenience, of being always confined to very few persons.
- Oaths are requisite in all courts of judicature; but it is a question
- whether their authority arises from any popular religion. It is the
- solemnity and importance of the occasion, the regard to reputation,
- and the reflecting on the general interests of society, which are the
- chief restraints upon mankind. Customhouse oaths and political oaths
- are but little regarded even by some who pretend to principles of
- honesty and religion; and a Quaker's asseveration is with us justly put
- upon the same footing with the oath of any other person. I know, that
- Polybius[3] ascribes the infamy of Greek faith to the prevalency of the
- Epicurean philosophy: but I know also, that Punic faith had as bad a
- reputation in ancient times as Irish evidence has in modern; though we
- cannot account for these vulgar observations by the same reason. Not to
- mention that Greek faith was infamous before the rise of the Epicurean
- philosophy; and Euripides,[4] in a passage which I shall point out to
- you, has glanced a remarkable stroke of satire against his nation, with
- regard to this circumstance.
- Take care, Philo, replied Cleanthes, take care: push not matters too
- far: allow not your zeal against false religion to undermine your
- veneration for the true. Forfeit not this principle, the chief, the
- only great comfort in life; and our principal support amidst all the
- attacks of adverse fortune. The most agreeable reflection, which it is
- possible for human imagination to suggest, is that of genuine Theism,
- which represents us as the workmanship of a Being perfectly good, wise,
- and powerful; who created us for happiness; and who, having implanted
- in us immeasurable desires of good, will prolong our existence to all
- eternity, and will transfer us into an infinite variety of scenes, in
- order to satisfy those desires, and render our felicity complete and
- durable. Next to such a Being himself (if the comparison be allowed),
- the happiest lot which we can imagine, is that of being under his
- guardianship and protection.
- These appearances, said Philo, are most engaging and alluring; and with
- regard to the true philosopher, they are more than appearances. But it
- happens here, as in the former case, that, with regard to the greater
- part of mankind, the appearances are deceitful, and that the terrors of
- religion commonly prevail above its comforts.
- It is allowed, that men never have recourse to devotion so readily as
- when dejected with grief or depressed with sickness. Is not this a
- proof, that the religious spirit is not so nearly allied to joy as to
- sorrow?
- But men, when afflicted, find consolation in religion, replied
- Cleanthes. Sometimes, said Philo: but it is natural to imagine,
- that they will form a notion of those unknown beings, suitably to
- the present gloom and melancholy of their temper, when they betake
- themselves to the contemplation of them. Accordingly, we find the
- tremendous images to predominate in all religions; and we ourselves,
- after having employed the most exalted expression in our descriptions
- of the Deity, fall into the flattest contradiction in affirming that
- the damned are infinitely superior in number to the elect.
- I shall venture to affirm, that there never was a popular religion,
- which represented the state of departed souls in such a light, as would
- render it eligible for human kind that there should be such a state.
- These fine models of religion are the mere product of philosophy. For
- as death lies between the eye and the prospect of futurity, that event
- is so shocking to Nature, that it must throw a gloom on all the regions
- which lie beyond it; and suggest to the generality of mankind the idea
- of Cerberus and Furies; devils, and torrents of fire and brimstone.
- It is true, both fear and hope enter into religion; because both these
- passions, at different times, agitate the human mind, and each of
- them forms a species of divinity suitable to itself. But when a man
- is in a cheerful disposition, he is fit for business, or company, or
- entertainment of any kind; and he naturally applies himself to these,
- and thinks not of religion. When melancholy and dejected, he has
- nothing to do but brood upon the terrors of the invisible world, and
- to plunge himself still deeper in affliction. It may indeed happen,
- that after he has, in this manner, engraved the religious opinions deep
- into his thought and imagination, there may arrive a change of health
- or circumstances, which may restore his good humour, and, raising
- cheerful prospects of futurity, make him run into the other extreme of
- joy and triumph. But still it must be acknowledged, that, as terror
- is the primary principle of religion, it is the passion which always
- predominates in it, and admits but of short intervals of pleasure.
- Not to mention, that these fits of excessive, enthusiastic joy, by
- exhausting the spirits, always prepare the way for equal fits of
- superstitious terror and dejection; nor is there any state of mind
- so happy as the calm and equable. But this state it is impossible to
- support, where a man thinks that he lies in such profound darkness
- and uncertainty, between an eternity of happiness and an eternity of
- misery. No wonder that such an opinion disjoints the ordinary frame
- of the mind, and throws it into the utmost confusion. And though that
- opinion is seldom so steady in its operation as to influence all the
- actions; yet it is apt to make a considerable breach in the temper, and
- to produce that gloom and melancholy so remarkable in all devout people.
- It is contrary to common sense to entertain apprehensions or terrors
- upon account of any opinion whatsoever, or to imagine that we run any
- risk hereafter, by the freest use of our reason. Such a sentiment
- implies both an _absurdity_ and an _inconsistency_. It is an absurdity
- to believe that the Deity has human passions, and one of the lowest
- of human passions, a restless appetite for applause. It is an
- inconsistency to believe, that, since the Deity has this human passion,
- he has not others also; and, in particular, a disregard to the opinions
- of creatures so much inferior.
- _To know God_, says Seneca, _is to worship him_. All other worship
- is indeed absurd, superstitious, and even impious. It degrades him
- to the low condition of mankind, who are delighted with entreaty,
- solicitation, presents, and flattery. Yet is this impiety the smallest
- of which superstition is guilty. Commonly, it depresses the Deity far
- below the condition of mankind; and represents him as a capricious
- demon, who exercises his power without reason and without humanity! And
- were that Divine Being disposed to be offended at the vices and follies
- of silly mortals, who are his own workmanship, ill would it surely fare
- with the votaries of most popular superstitions. Nor would any of human
- race merit his _favour_, but a very few, the philosophical Theists,
- who entertain, or rather indeed endeavour to entertain, suitable
- notions of his Divine perfections: As the only persons entitled to his
- _compassion_ and _indulgence_ would be the philosophical Sceptics, a
- sect almost equally rare, who, from a natural diffidence of their own
- capacity, suspend, or endeavour to suspend, all judgment with regard to
- such sublime and such extraordinary subjects.
- If the whole of Natural Theology, as some people seem to maintain,
- resolves itself into one simple, though somewhat ambiguous, at least
- undefined proposition, _That the cause or causes of order in the
- universe probably bear some remote analogy to human intelligence_:
- If this proposition be not capable of extension, variation, or more
- particular explication: If it affords no inference that affects human
- life, or can be the source of any action or forbearance: And if the
- analogy, imperfect as it is, can be carried no farther than to the
- human intelligence, and cannot be transferred, with any appearance of
- probability, to the other qualities of the mind; if this really be the
- case, what can the most inquisitive, contemplative, and religious man
- do more than give a plain, philosophical assent to the proposition,
- as often as it occurs, and believe that the arguments on which it
- is established exceed the objections which lie against it? Some
- astonishment, indeed, will naturally arise from the greatness of the
- object; some melancholy from its obscurity; some contempt of human
- reason, that it can give no solution more satisfactory with regard to
- so extraordinary and magnificent a question. But believe me, Cleanthes,
- the most natural sentiment which a well-disposed mind will feel on
- this occasion, is a longing desire and expectation that Heaven would
- be pleased to dissipate, at least alleviate, this profound ignorance,
- by affording some more particular revelation to mankind, and making
- discoveries of the nature, attributes, and operations of the Divine
- object of our faith. A person, seasoned with a just sense of the
- imperfections of natural reason, will fly to revealed truth with the
- greatest avidity: While the haughty Dogmatist, persuaded that he can
- erect a complete system of Theology by the mere help of philosophy,
- disdains any further aid, and rejects this adventitious instructor.
- To be a philosophical Sceptic is, in a man of letters, the first and
- most essential step towards being a sound, believing Christian; a
- proposition which I would willingly recommend to the attention of
- Pamphilus: And I hope Cleanthes will forgive me for interposing so far
- in the education and instruction of his pupil.
- Cleanthes and Philo pursued not this conversation much farther: and as
- nothing ever made greater impression on me, than all the reasonings
- of that day, so I confess, that, upon a serious review of the whole,
- I cannot but think, that Philo's principles are more probable than
- Demea's; but that those of Cleanthes approach still nearer to the truth.
- [1] De Formatione Foetus.
- [2] It seems evident that the dispute between the Sceptics and
- Dogmatists is entirely verbal, or at least regards only the degrees
- of doubt and assurance which we ought to indulge with regard to all
- reasoning; and such disputes are commonly, at the bottom, verbal, and
- admit not of any precise determination. No philosophical Dogmatist
- denies that there are difficulties both with regard to the senses and
- to all science, and that these difficulties are in a regular, logical
- method, absolutely insolvable. No Sceptic denies that we lie under an
- absolute necessity, notwithstanding these difficulties, of thinking,
- and believing, and reasoning, with regard to all kinds of subjects, and
- even of frequently assenting with confidence and security. The only
- difference, then, between these sects, if they merit that name, is,
- that the Sceptic, from habit, caprice, or inclination, insists most on
- the difficulties; the Dogmatist, for like reasons, on the necessity.
- [3] Lib. vi. cap. 54.
- [4] Iphigenia in Tauride.
- APPENDIX
- TO THE
- TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE.
- There is nothing I would more willingly lay hold of, than an
- opportunity of confessing my errors; and should esteem such a return to
- truth and reason to be more honourable than the most unerring judgment.
- A man who is free from mistakes can pretend to no praises, except from
- the justness of his understanding; but a man who corrects his mistakes
- shows at once the justness of his understanding, and the candour
- and ingenuity of his temper. I have not yet been so fortunate as to
- discover any very considerable mistakes in the reasonings delivered
- in the preceding volumes, except on one article; but I have found by
- experience, that some of my expressions have not been so well chosen
- as to guard against all mistakes in the readers; and 'tis chiefly to
- remedy this defect I have subjoined the following Appendix.
- We can never be induced to believe any matter of fact except where
- its cause or its effect is present to us; but what the nature is of
- that belief which arises from the relation of cause and effect, few
- have had the curiosity to ask themselves. In my opinion this dilemma
- is inevitable. Either the belief is some new idea, such as that of
- _reality_ or _existence_, which we join to the simple conception
- of an object, or it is merely a peculiar _feeling_ or _sentiment_.
- That it is not a new idea, annexed to the simple conception, may be
- evinced from these two arguments. _First_, We have no abstract idea of
- existence, distinguishable and separable from the idea of particular
- objects. 'Tis impossible, therefore, that this idea of existence can
- be annexed to the idea of any object, or form the difference betwixt
- a simple conception and belief. _Secondly_, The mind has the command
- over all its ideas, and can separate, unite, mix, and vary them, as
- it pleases; so that, if belief consisted merely in a new idea annexed
- to the conception, it would be in a man's power to believe what he
- pleased. We may therefore conclude, that belief consists merely in a
- certain feeling or sentiment; in something that depends not on the
- will, but must arise from certain determinate causes and principles
- of which we are not masters. When we are convinced of any matter of
- fact, we do nothing but conceive it, along with a certain feeling,
- different from what attends the mere _reveries_ of the imagination.
- And when we express our incredulity concerning any fact, we mean,
- that the arguments for the fact produce not that feeling. Did not the
- belief consist in a sentiment different from our mere conception,
- whatever objects were presented by the wildest imagination would be on
- an equal footing with the most established truths founded on history
- and experience. There is nothing but the feeling or sentiment to
- distinguish the one from the other.
- This, therefore, being regarded as an undoubted truth, that _belief is
- nothing but a peculiar feeling, different from the simple conception_,
- the next question that naturally occurs is, _what is the nature of
- this feeling or sentiment, and whether it be analogous to any other
- sentiment of the human mind_? This question is important. For if it be
- not analogous to any other sentiment, we must despair of explaining
- its causes, and must consider it as an original principle of the human
- mind. If it be analogous, we may hope to explain its causes from
- analogy, and trace it up to more general principles. Now, that there
- is a greater firmness and solidity in the conceptions, which are the
- objects of conviction and assurance, than in the loose and indolent
- reveries of a castle-builder, every one will readily own. They strike
- upon us with more force; they are more present to us; the mind has
- a firmer hold of them, and is more actuated and moved by them. It
- acquiesces in them; and, in a manner, fixes and reposes itself on
- them. In short, they approach nearer to the impressions, which are
- immediately present to us; and are therefore analogous to many other
- operations of the mind.
- There is not, in my opinion, any possibility of evading this
- conclusion, but by asserting that belief, beside the simple conception,
- consists in some impression or feeling, distinguishable from the
- conception. It does not modify the conception, and render it more
- present and intense: it is only annexed to it, after the same manner
- that _will_ and _desire_ are annexed to particular conceptions of
- good and pleasure. But the following considerations will, I hope,
- be sufficient to remove this hypothesis. _First_, It is directly
- contrary to experience, and our immediate consciousness? All men have
- ever allowed reasoning to be merely an operation of our thoughts or
- ideas; and however those ideas may be varied to the feeling, there is
- nothing ever enters into our _conclusions_ but ideas, or our fainter
- conceptions. For instance, I hear at present a person's voice with
- whom I am acquainted, and this sound comes from the next room. This
- impression of my senses immediately conveys my thoughts to the person,
- along with all the surrounding objects. I paint them out to myself
- as existent at present, with the same qualities and relations that I
- formerly knew them possessed of. These ideas take faster hold of my
- mind, than the ideas of an enchanted castle. They are different to the
- feeling; but there is no distinct or separate impression attending
- them. 'Tis the same case when I recollect the several incidents of a
- journey, or the events of any history. Every particular fact is there
- the object of belief. Its idea is modified differently from the loose
- reveries of a castle-builder: but no distinct impression attends
- every distinct idea, or conception of matter of fact. This is the
- subject of plain experience. If ever this experience can be disputed
- on any occasion, 'tis when the mind has been agitated with doubts and
- difficulties; and afterwards, upon taking the object in a new point of
- view, or being presented with a new argument, fixes and reposes itself
- in one settled conclusion and belief. In this case there is a feeling
- distinct and separate from the conception. The passage from doubt
- and agitation to tranquillity and repose, conveys a satisfaction and
- pleasure to the mind. But take any other case. Suppose I see the legs
- and thighs of a person in motion, while some interposed object conceals
- the rest of his body. Here 'tis certain, the imagination spreads out
- the whole figure. I give him a head and shoulders, and breast and neck.
- These members I conceive and believe him to be possessed of. Nothing
- can be more evident, than that this whole operation is performed
- by the thought or imagination alone. The transition is immediate.
- The ideas presently strike us. Their customary connexion with the
- present impression varies them and modifies them in a certain manner,
- but produces no act of the mind, distinct from this peculiarity of
- conception. Let any one examine his own mind, and he will evidently
- find this to be the truth.
- _Secondly_, Whatever may be the case, with regard to this distinct
- impression, it must be allowed that the mind has a firmer hold, or
- more steady conception of what it takes to be matter of fact than of
- fictions. Why then look any farther, or multiply suppositions without
- necessity?
- _Thirdly_, We can explain the _causes_ of the firm conception, but not
- those of any separate impression. And not only so, but the causes of
- the firm conception exhaust the whole subject, and nothing is left to
- produce any other effect. An inference concerning a matter of fact is
- nothing but the idea of an object that is frequently conjoined, or is
- associated with a present impression. This is the whole of it. Every
- part is requisite to explain, from analogy, the more steady conception;
- and nothing remains capable of producing any distinct impression.
- _Fourthly_, The _effects_ of belief, in influencing the passions
- and imagination, can all be explained from the firm conception; and
- there is no occasion to have recourse to any other principle. These
- arguments, with many others, enumerated in the foregoing volumes,
- sufficiently prove, that belief only modifies the idea or conception;
- and renders it different to the feeling, without producing any distinct
- impression.
- Thus, upon a general view of the subject, there appear to be two
- questions of importance, which we may venture to recommend to
- the consideration of philosophers, _Whether there be any thing to
- distinguish belief from the simple conception, beside the feeling
- or sentiment_? And, _Whether this feeling be any thing but a firmer
- conception, or a faster hold, that we take of the object_?
- If, upon impartial inquiry, the same conclusion that I have formed
- be assented to by philosophers, the next business is to examine the
- analogy which there is betwixt belief and other acts of the mind,
- and find the cause of the firmness and strength of conception; and
- this I do not esteem a difficult task. The transition from a present
- impression, always enlivens and strengthens any idea. When any object
- is presented, the idea of its usual attendant immediately strikes us,
- as something real and solid. 'Tis _felt_ rather than conceived, and
- approaches the impression, from which it is derived, in its force
- and influence. This I have proved at large, and cannot add any new
- arguments.
- I had entertained some hopes, that however deficient our theory of the
- intellectual world might be, it would be free from those contradictions
- and absurdities, which seem to attend every explication, that human
- reason can give of the material world. But upon a more strict review of
- the section concerning _personal identity_, I find myself involved in
- such a labyrinth, that, I must confess, I neither know how to correct
- my former opinions, nor how to render them consistent. If this be not
- a good _general_ reason for scepticism, 'tis at least a sufficient
- one (if I were not already abundantly supplied) for me to entertain
- a diffidence and modesty in all my decisions. I shall propose the
- arguments on both sides, beginning with those that induced me to deny
- the strict and proper identity and simplicity of a self or thinking
- being.
- When we talk of _self_ or _subsistence_, we must have an idea annexed
- to these terms, otherwise they are altogether unintelligible. Every
- idea is derived from preceding impressions; and we have no impression
- of self or substance, as something simple and individual. We have,
- therefore, no idea of them in that sense.
- Whatever is distinct, is distinguishable, and whatever is
- distinguishable, is separable by the thought or imagination. All
- perceptions are distinct. They are, therefore, distinguishable, and
- separable, and may be conceived, as separately existent, and may exist
- separately, without any contradiction or absurdity.
- When I view this table and that chimney, nothing is present to me but
- particular perceptions, which are of a like nature with all the other
- perceptions. This is the doctrine of philosophers. But this table,
- which is present to me, and that chimney, may, and do exist separately.
- This is the doctrine of the vulgar, and implies no contradiction.
- There, is no contradiction, therefore, in extending the same doctrine
- to all the perceptions.
- In general, the following reasoning seems satisfactory. All ideas are
- borrowed from preceding perceptions. Our ideas of objects, therefore,
- are derived from that source. Consequently no proposition can be
- intelligible or consistent with regard to objects, which is not so
- with regard to perceptions. But 'tis intelligible and consistent to
- say, that objects exist distinct and independent, without any common
- _simple_ substance or subject of inhesion. This proposition, therefore,
- can never be absurd with regard to perceptions.
- When I turn my reflection on _myself_, I never can perceive this _self_
- without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing
- but the perceptions. 'Tis the composition of these, therefore, which
- forms the self.
- We can conceive a thinking being to have either many or few
- perceptions. Suppose the mind to be reduced even below the life of an
- oyster. Suppose it to have only one perception, as of thirst or hunger.
- Consider it in that situation. Do you conceive any thing but merely
- that perception? Have you any notion of _self_ or _substance_? If not,
- the addition of other perceptions can never give you that notion.
- The annihilation which some people suppose to follow upon death, and
- which entirely destroys this self, is nothing but an extinction of all
- particular perceptions; love and hatred, pain and pleasure, thought and
- sensation. These, therefore, must be the same with self, since the one
- cannot survive the other.
- Is _self_ the same with _substance_? If it be, how can that question
- have place, concerning the subsistence of self, under a change of
- substance? If they be distinct, what is the difference betwixt them?
- For my part, I have a notion of neither, when conceived distinct from
- particular perceptions.
- Philosophers begin to be reconciled to the principle, _that we have
- no idea of external substance, distinct from the ideas of particular
- qualities_. This must pave the way for a like principle with regard to
- the mind, _that we have no notion of it, distinct from the particular
- perception_.
- So far I seem to be attended with sufficient evidence. But having thus
- loosened all our particular perceptions, when I proceed to explain
- the principle of connexion, which binds them together, and makes us
- attribute to them a real simplicity and identity, I am sensible that my
- account is very defective, and that nothing but the seeming evidence
- of the precedent reasonings could have induced me to receive it. If
- perceptions are distinct existences, they form a whole only by being
- connected together. But no connexions among distinct existences are
- ever discoverable by human understanding. We only _feel_ a connexion
- or determination of the thought to pass from one object to another. It
- follows, therefore, that the thought alone feels personal identity,
- when reflecting on the train of past perceptions that compose a mind,
- the ideas of them are felt to be connected together, and naturally
- introduce each other. However extraordinary this conclusion may seem,
- it need not surprise us. Most philosophers seem inclined to think, that
- personal identity _arises_ from consciousness, and consciousness is
- nothing but a reflected thought or perception. The present philosophy,
- therefore, has so far a promising aspect. But all my hopes vanish, when
- I come to explain the principles that unite our successive perceptions
- in our thought or consciousness. I cannot discover any theory, which
- gives me satisfaction on this head.
- In short, there are two principles which I cannot render consistent,
- nor is it in my power to renounce either of them, viz. _that all
- our distinct perceptions are distinct existences, and that the mind
- never perceives any real connexion among distinct existences_. Did
- our perceptions either inhere in something simple and individual, or
- did the mind perceive some real connexion among them, there would be
- no difficulty in the case. For my part, I must plead the privilege
- of a sceptic, and confess, that this difficulty is too hard for my
- understanding. I pretend not, however, to pronounce it absolutely
- insuperable. Others, perhaps, or myself, upon more mature reflections,
- may discover some hypothesis that will reconcile those contradictions.
- I shall also take this opportunity of confessing two other errors of
- less importance, which more mature reflection has discovered to me in
- my reasoning. The first may be found in Vol. I. page 85, where I say,
- that the distance betwixt two bodies is known, among other things, by
- the angles which the rays of light flowing from the bodies make with
- each other. 'Tis certain, that these angles are not known to the mind,
- and consequently can never discover the distance. The second error may
- be found in Vol. I. p. 132, where I say, that two ideas of the same
- object can only be different by their different degrees of force and
- vivacity. I believe there are other differences among ideas, which
- cannot properly be comprehended under these terms. Had I said, that
- two ideas of the same object can only be different by their different
- _feeling_, I should have been nearer the truth.
- END OF VOLUME SECOND.
- End of Project Gutenberg's Philosophical Works, v. 2 (of 4), by David Hume
- *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS, V. 2 (OF 4) ***
- ***** This file should be named 53792-8.txt or 53792-8.zip *****
- This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
- http://www.gutenberg.org/5/3/7/9/53792/
- Produced by Madelaine Kilsby and Marc D'Hooghe at Free
- Literature (back online soon in an extended version, also
- linking to free sources for education worldwide ... MOOC's,
- educational materials,...) Images generously made available
- by the Bodleian Library, Oxford.
- Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will
- be renamed.
- Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
- law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
- so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
- States without permission and without paying copyright
- royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
- of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm
- concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
- and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive
- specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this
- eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook
- for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports,
- performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given
- away--you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks
- not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the
- trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
- START: FULL LICENSE
- THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
- PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
- To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
- distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
- (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
- Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at
- www.gutenberg.org/license.
- Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works
- 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
- and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
- (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
- the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
- destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your
- possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
- Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
- by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the
- person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph
- 1.E.8.
- 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
- used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
- agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
- things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
- even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
- paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this
- agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
- 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the
- Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
- of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual
- works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
- States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
- United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
- claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
- displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
- all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
- that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting
- free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm
- works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
- Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily
- comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
- same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when
- you share it without charge with others.
- 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
- what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
- in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
- check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
- agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
- distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
- other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no
- representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
- country outside the United States.
- 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
- 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
- immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear
- prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work
- on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the
- phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed,
- performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
- most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no
- restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it
- under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this
- eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the
- United States, you'll have to check the laws of the country where you
- are located before using this ebook.
- 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is
- derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
- contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
- copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
- the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
- redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
- either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
- obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm
- trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
- with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
- must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
- additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
- will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works
- posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
- beginning of this work.
- 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
- work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
- 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
- electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
- prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
- active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm License.
- 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
- compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
- any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
- to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format
- other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official
- version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site
- (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
- to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
- of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain
- Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the
- full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
- 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
- performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
- unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
- access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
- provided that
- * You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
- the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
- you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
- to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has
- agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
- within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
- legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
- payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
- Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation."
- * You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
- you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
- does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
- copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
- all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm
- works.
- * You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
- any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
- electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
- receipt of the work.
- * You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
- distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than
- are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
- from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and The
- Project Gutenberg Trademark LLC, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm
- trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
- 1.F.
- 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
- effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
- works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
- Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
- contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
- or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
- intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
- other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
- cannot be read by your equipment.
- 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
- of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
- liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
- fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
- LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
- PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
- TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
- LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
- INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
- DAMAGE.
- 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
- defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
- receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
- written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
- received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
- with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
- with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
- lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
- or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
- opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
- the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
- without further opportunities to fix the problem.
- 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
- in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO
- OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
- LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
- 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
- warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
- damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
- violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
- agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
- limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
- unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
- remaining provisions.
- 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
- trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
- providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in
- accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
- production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
- including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
- the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
- or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or
- additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any
- Defect you cause.
- Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
- Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
- electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
- computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
- exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
- from people in all walks of life.
- Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
- assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
- goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
- remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
- and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future
- generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
- Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
- www.gutenberg.org Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation
- The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
- 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
- state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
- Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
- number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
- U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
- The Foundation's principal office is in Fairbanks, Alaska, with the
- mailing address: PO Box 750175, Fairbanks, AK 99775, but its
- volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous
- locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt
- Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to
- date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and
- official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact
- For additional contact information:
- Dr. Gregory B. Newby
- Chief Executive and Director
- gbnewby@pglaf.org
- Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation
- Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
- spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
- increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
- freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
- array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
- ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
- status with the IRS.
- The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
- charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
- States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
- considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
- with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
- where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
- DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular
- state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate
- While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
- have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
- against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
- approach us with offers to donate.
- International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
- any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
- outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
- Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
- methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
- ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
- donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate
- Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works.
- Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be
- freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
- distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of
- volunteer support.
- Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
- editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
- the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
- necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
- edition.
- Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search
- facility: www.gutenberg.org
- This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
- including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
- subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.