- The Project Gutenberg EBook of A Treatise of Human Nature, by David Hume
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
- almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
- re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
- with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
- Title: A Treatise of Human Nature
- Author: David Hume
- Release Date: December, 2003 [Etext #4705]
- Posting Date: February 13, 2010
- [This file last updated: March 31, 2012]
- Language: English
- *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE ***
- Produced by Col Choat
- A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE
- By David Hume
- CONTENTS
- VOLUME I
- INTRODUCTION BY THE AUTHOR.
- BOOK I OF THE UNDERSTANDING
- PART I OF IDEAS, THEIR ORIGIN, COMPOSITION, CONNEXION,
- ABSTRACTION, ETC.
- SECT. I OF THE ORIGIN OF OUR IDEAS.
- SECT. II. DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT.
- SECT. III. OF THE IDEAS OF THE MEMORY AND IMAGINATION.
- SECT. IV. OF THE CONNECTION OR ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS.
- SECT. V. OF RELATIONS.
- SECT. VI. OF MODES AND SUBSTANCES
- SECT. VII. OF ABSTRACT IDEAS.
- PART II. OF THE IDEAS OF SPACE AND TIME.
- SECT. I. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF OUR IDEAS OF SPACE AND TIME.
- SECT. II. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF SPACE AND TIME.
- SECT. III. OF THE OTHER QUALITIES OF OUR IDEA OF SPACE AND TIME.
- SECT. IV. OBJECTIONS ANSWERED.
- SECT. V. THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.
- SECT. VI. OF THE IDEA OF EXISTENCE, AND OF EXTERNAL EXISTENCE.
- PART III. OF KNOWLEDGE AND PROBABILITY.
- SECT. I. OF KNOWLEDGE.
- SECT. II. OF PROBABILITY, AND OF THE IDEA OF CAUSE AND EFFECT.
- SECT. III. WHY A CAUSE IS ALWAYS NECESSARY.
- SECT. IV. OF THE COMPONENT PARTS OF OUR REASONINGS CONCERNING CAUSE
- AND EFFECT.
- SECT. V. OF THE IMPRESSIONS OF THE SENSES AND MEMORY.
- SECT. VI. OF THE INFERENCE FROM THE IMPRESSION TO THE IDEA.
- SECT. VII. OF THE NATURE OF THE IDEA OR BELIEF.
- SECT. VIII. OF THE CAUSES OF BELIEF.
- SECT. IX. OF THE EFFECTS OF OTHER RELATIONS AND OTHER HABITS.
- SECT. X. OF THE INFLUENCE OF BELIEF.
- SECT. XI. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CHANCES.
- SECT. XII. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CAUSES.
- SECT. XIII. OF UNPHILOSOPHICAL PROBABILITY.
- SECT. XIV. OF THE IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNECTION.
- SECT. XV. RULES BY WHICH TO JUDGE OF CAUSES AND EFFECTS.
- SECT. XVI OF THE REASON OF ANIMALS
- PART IV. OF THE SCEPTICAL AND OTHER SYSTEMS OF PHILOSOPHY.
- SECT. I. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO REASON.
- SECT. II. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO THE SENSES.
- SECT. III. OF THE ANTIENT PHILOSOPHY.
- SECT. IV. OF THE MODERN PHILOSOPHY.
- SECT. V. OF THE IMMATERIALITY OF THE SOUL.
- SECT. VI. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY
- SECT. VII. CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK.
- VOLUME II
- BOOK II OF THE PASSIONS
- PART I OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY
- SECT. I DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT
- SECT. II OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY, THEIR OBJECTS AND CAUSES
- SECT. III WHENCE THESE OBJECTS AND CAUSES ARE DERIVED
- SECT. IV OF THE RELATIONS OF IMPRESSIONS AND IDEAS
- SECT. V OF THE INFLUENCE OF THESE RELATIONS ON PRIDE AND HUMILITY
- SECT. VI LIMITATIONS OF THIS SYSTEM
- SECT. VII OF VICE AND VIRTUE
- SECT. VIII OF BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY
- SECT. IX OF EXTERNAL ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES
- SECT. X OF PROPERTY AND RICHES
- SECT. XI OF THE LOVE OF FAME
- SECT. XII OF THE PRIDE AND HUMILITY OF ANIMALS
- PART II OF LOVE AND HATRED
- SECT. I OF THE OBJECT AND CAUSES OF LOVE AND HATRED
- SECT. II EXPERIMENTS TO CONFIRM THIS SYSTEM
- SECT. III DIFFICULTIES SOLVED
- SECT. IV OF THE LOVE OF RELATIONS
- SECT. V OF OUR ESTEEM FOR THE RICH AND POWERFUL
- SECT. VI OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER
- SECT. VII OF COMPASSION
- SECT. VIII OF MALICE AND ENVY
- SECT. IX OF THE MIXTURE OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER WITH COMPASSION
- AND MALICE
- SECT. X OF RESPECT AND CONTEMPT
- SECT. XI OF THE AMOROUS PASSION, OR LOVE BETWIXT THE SEXES
- SECT. XII OF THE LOVE AND HATRED OF ANIMALS
- PART III OF THE WILL AND DIRECT PASSIONS
- SECT. I OF LIBERTY AND NECESSITY
- SECT. II THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED
- SECT. III OF THE INFLUENCING MOTIVES OF THE WILL
- SECT. IV OF THE CAUSES OF THE VIOLENT PASSIONS
- SECT. V OF THE EFFECTS OF CUSTOM
- SECT. VI OF THE INFLUENCE OF THE IMAGINATION ON THE PASSIONS
- SECT. VII OF CONTIGUITY AND DISTANCE IN SPACE AND TIME
- SECT. VIII THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED
- SECT. IX OF THE DIRECT PASSIONS
- SECT. X OF CURIOSITY, OR THE LOVE OF TRUTH
- BOOK III OF MORALS
- PART I OF VIRTUE AND VICE IN GENERAL
- SECT. I MORAL DISTINCTIONS NOT DERIVED FROM REASON
- SECT. II MORAL DISTINCTIONS DERIVED FROM A MORAL SENSE
- PART II OF JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE
- SECT. I JUSTICE, WHETHER A NATURAL OR ARTIFICIAL VIRTUE?
- SECT. II OF THE ORIGIN OF JUSTICE AND PROPERTY
- SECT. III OF THE RULES WHICH DETERMINE PROPERTY
- SECT. IV OF THE TRANSFERENCE OF PROPERTY BY CONSENT
- SECT. V OF THE OBLIGATION OF PROMISES
- SECT. VI SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE
- SECT. VII OF THE ORIGIN OF GOVERNMENT
- SECT. VIII OF THE SOURCE OF ALLEGIANCE
- SECT. IX OF THE MEASURES OF ALLEGIANCE
- SECT. X OF THE OBJECTS OF ALLEGIANCE
- SECT. XI OF THE LAWS OF NATIONS
- SECT. XII OF CHASTITY AND MODESTY
- PART III OF THE OTHER VIRTUES AND VICES
- SECT. I OF THE ORIGIN OF THE NATURAL VIRTUES AND VICES
- SECT. II OF GREATNESS OF MIND
- SECT. III OF GOODNESS AND BENEVOLENCE
- SECT. IV OF NATURAL ABILITIES
- SECT. V SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING THE NATURAL VIRTUES
- SECT. VI CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK
- APPENDIX TO THE TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE
- * * * * *
- VOL. I OF THE UNDERSTANDING.
- ADVERTISEMENT.
- My design in the present work is sufficiently explained in the
- Introduction. The reader must only observe, that all the subjects I have
- there planned out to myself, are not treated of in these two volumes.
- The subjects of the Understanding and Passions make a compleat chain
- of reasoning by themselves; and I was willing to take advantage of this
- natural division, in order to try the taste of the public. If I have the
- good fortune to meet with success, I shall proceed to the examination
- of Morals, Politics, and Criticism; which will compleat this Treatise of
- Human Nature. The approbation of the public I consider as the greatest
- reward of my labours; but am determined to regard its judgment, whatever
- it be, as my best instruction.
- INTRODUCTION.
- Nothing is more usual and more natural for those, who pretend to
- discover anything new to the world in philosophy and the sciences, than
- to insinuate the praises of their own systems, by decrying all those,
- which have been advanced before them. And indeed were they content with
- lamenting that ignorance, which we still lie under in the most important
- questions, that can come before the tribunal of human reason, there are
- few, who have an acquaintance with the sciences, that would not readily
- agree with them. It is easy for one of judgment and learning, to
- perceive the weak foundation even of those systems, which have obtained
- the greatest credit, and have carried their pretensions highest
- to accurate and profound reasoning. Principles taken upon trust,
- consequences lamely deduced from them, want of coherence in the parts,
- and of evidence in the whole, these are every where to be met with in
- the systems of the most eminent philosophers, and seem to have drawn
- disgrace upon philosophy itself.
- Nor is there required such profound knowledge to discover the present
- imperfect condition of the sciences, but even the rabble without doors
- may, judge from the noise and clamour, which they hear, that all goes
- not well within. There is nothing which is not the subject of debate,
- and in which men of learning are not of contrary opinions. The most
- trivial question escapes not our controversy, and in the most momentous
- we are not able to give any certain decision. Disputes are multiplied,
- as if every thing was uncertain; and these disputes are managed with the
- greatest warmth, as if every thing was certain. Amidst all this bustle
- it is not reason, which carries the prize, but eloquence; and no
- man needs ever despair of gaining proselytes to the most extravagant
- hypothesis, who has art enough to represent it in any favourable
- colours. The victory is not gained by the men at arms, who manage the
- pike and the sword; but by the trumpeters, drummers, and musicians of
- the army.
- From hence in my opinion arises that common prejudice against
- metaphysical reasonings of all kinds, even amongst those, who profess
- themselves scholars, and have a just value for every other part of
- literature. By metaphysical reasonings, they do not understand those on
- any particular branch of science, but every kind of argument, which is
- any way abstruse, and requires some attention to be comprehended. We
- have so often lost our labour in such researches, that we commonly
- reject them without hesitation, and resolve, if we must for ever be a
- prey to errors and delusions, that they shall at least be natural and
- entertaining. And indeed nothing but the most determined scepticism,
- along with a great degree of indolence, can justify this aversion to
- metaphysics. For if truth be at all within the reach of human capacity,
- it is certain it must lie very deep and abstruse: and to hope we shall
- arrive at it without pains, while the greatest geniuses have failed
- with the utmost pains, must certainly be esteemed sufficiently vain
- and presumptuous. I pretend to no such advantage in the philosophy I am
- going to unfold, and would esteem it a strong presumption against it,
- were it so very easy and obvious.
- It is evident, that all the sciences have a relation, greater or less,
- to human nature: and that however wide any of them may seem to run from
- it, they still return back by one passage or another. Even. Mathematics,
- Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, are in some measure dependent
- on the science of MAN; since the lie under the cognizance of men, and
- are judged of by their powers and faculties. It is impossible to tell
- what changes and improvements we might make in these sciences were we
- thoroughly acquainted with the extent and force of human understanding,
- and could explain the nature of the ideas we employ, and of the
- operations we perform in our reasonings. And these improvements are
- the more to be hoped for in natural religion, as it is not content with
- instructing us in the nature of superior powers, but carries its views
- farther, to their disposition towards us, and our duties towards them;
- and consequently we ourselves are not only the beings, that reason, but
- also one of the objects, concerning which we reason.
- If therefore the sciences of Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and
- Natural Religion, have such a dependence on the knowledge of man, what
- may be expected in the other sciences, whose connexion with human nature
- is more close and intimate? The sole end of logic is to explain the
- principles and operations of our reasoning faculty, and the nature of
- our ideas: morals and criticism regard our tastes and sentiments: and
- politics consider men as united in society, and dependent on each other.
- In these four sciences of Logic, Morals, Criticism, and Politics, is
- comprehended almost everything, which it can any way import us to be
- acquainted with, or which can tend either to the improvement or ornament
- of the human mind.
- Here then is the only expedient, from which we can hope for success in
- our philosophical researches, to leave the tedious lingering method,
- which we have hitherto followed, and instead of taking now and then a
- castle or village on the frontier, to march up directly to the capital
- or center of these sciences, to human nature itself; which being once
- masters of, we may every where else hope for an easy victory. From this
- station we may extend our conquests over all those sciences, which more
- intimately concern human life, and may afterwards proceed at leisure
- to discover more fully those, which are the objects of pore curiosity.
- There is no question of importance, whose decision is not comprised in
- the science of man; and there is none, which can be decided with any
- certainty, before we become acquainted with that science. In pretending,
- therefore, to explain the principles of human nature, we in effect
- propose a compleat system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost
- entirely new, and the only one upon which they can stand with any
- security.
- And as the science of man is the-only solid foundation for the other
- sciences, so the only solid foundation we can give to this science
- itself must be laid on experience and observation. It is no astonishing
- reflection to consider, that the application of experimental philosophy
- to moral subjects should come after that to natural at the distance of
- above a whole century; since we find in fact, that there was about the
- same interval betwixt the origins of these sciences; and that reckoning
- from THALES to SOCRATES, the space of time is nearly equal to that
- betwixt, my Lord Bacon and some late philosophers [Mr. Locke, my Lord
- Shaftesbury, Dr. Mandeville, Mr. Hutchinson, Dr. Butler, etc.] in
- England, who have begun to put the science of man on a new footing, and
- have engaged the attention, and excited the curiosity of the public. So
- true it is, that however other nations may rival us in poetry, and
- excel us in some other agreeable arts, the improvements in reason and
- philosophy can only be owing to a land of toleration and of liberty.
- Nor ought we to think, that this latter improvement in the science of
- man will do less honour to our native country than the former in natural
- philosophy, but ought rather to esteem it a greater glory, upon account
- of the greater importance of that science, as well as the necessity it
- lay under of such a reformation. For to me it seems evident, that the
- essence of the mind being equally unknown to us with that of external
- bodies, it must be equally impossible to form any notion of its powers
- and qualities otherwise than from careful and exact experiments, and the
- observation of those particular effects, which result from its different
- circumstances and situations. And though we must endeavour to render all
- our principles as universal as possible, by tracing up our experiments
- to the utmost, and explaining all effects from the simplest and fewest
- causes, it is still certain we cannot go beyond experience; and any
- hypothesis, that pretends to discover the ultimate original qualities
- of human nature, ought at first to be rejected as presumptuous and
- chimerical.
- I do not think a philosopher, who would apply himself so earnestly to
- the explaining the ultimate principles of the soul, would show himself a
- great master in that very science of human nature, which he pretends to
- explain, or very knowing in what is naturally satisfactory to the mind
- of man. For nothing is more certain, than that despair has almost the
- same effect upon us with enjoyment, and that we are no sooner acquainted
- with the impossibility of satisfying any desire, than the desire itself
- vanishes. When we see, that we have arrived at the utmost extent of
- human reason, we sit down contented, though we be perfectly satisfied in
- the main of our ignorance, and perceive that we can give no reason for
- our most general and most refined principles, beside our experience
- of their reality; which is the reason of the mere vulgar, and what it
- required no study at first to have discovered for the most particular
- and most extraordinary phaenomenon. And as this impossibility of making
- any farther progress is enough to satisfy the reader, so the writer
- may derive a more delicate satisfaction from the free confession of his
- ignorance, and from his prudence in avoiding that error, into which so
- many have fallen, of imposing their conjectures and hypotheses on the
- world for the most certain principles. When this mutual contentment and
- satisfaction can be obtained betwixt the master and scholar, I know not
- what more we can require of our philosophy.
- But if this impossibility of explaining ultimate principles should be
- esteemed a defect in the science of man, I will venture to affirm, that
- it is a defect common to it with all the sciences, and all the arts, in
- which we can employ ourselves, whether they be such as are cultivated
- in the schools of the philosophers, or practised in the shops of the
- meanest artizans. None of them can go beyond experience, or establish
- any principles which are not founded on that authority. Moral philosophy
- has, indeed, this peculiar disadvantage, which is not found in natural,
- that in collecting its experiments, it cannot make them purposely, with
- premeditation, and after such a manner as to satisfy itself concerning
- every particular difficulty which may be. When I am at a loss to know
- the effects of one body upon another in any situation, I need only put
- them in that situation, and observe what results from it. But should
- I endeavour to clear up after the same manner any doubt in moral
- philosophy, by placing myself in the same case with that which I
- consider, it is evident this reflection and premeditation would so
- disturb the operation of my natural principles, as must render it
- impossible to form any just conclusion from the phenomenon. We must
- therefore glean up our experiments in this science from a cautious
- observation of human life, and take them as they appear in the common
- course of the world, by men's behaviour in company, in affairs, and
- in their pleasures. Where experiments of this kind are judiciously
- collected and compared, we may hope to establish on them a science which
- will not be inferior in certainty, and will be much superior in utility
- to any other of human comprehension.
- BOOK I. OF THE UNDERSTANDING
- PART I. OF IDEAS, THEIR ORIGIN, COMPOSITION, CONNEXION, ABSTRACTION,
- ETC.
- SECT. I. OF THE ORIGIN OF OUR IDEAS.
- All the perceptions of the human mind resolve themselves into two
- distinct kinds, which I shall call IMPRESSIONS and IDEAS. The difference
- betwixt these consists in the degrees of force and liveliness, with
- which they strike upon the mind, and make their way into our thought
- or consciousness. Those perceptions, which enter with most force and
- violence, we may name impressions: and under this name I comprehend
- all our sensations, passions and emotions, as they make their first
- appearance in the soul. By ideas I mean the faint images of these in
- thinking and reasoning; such as, for instance, are all the perceptions
- excited by the present discourse, excepting only those which arise from
- the sight and touch, and excepting the immediate pleasure or uneasiness
- it may occasion. I believe it will not be very necessary to employ many
- words in explaining this distinction. Every one of himself will readily
- perceive the difference betwixt feeling and thinking. The common degrees
- of these are easily distinguished; though it is not impossible but in
- particular instances they may very nearly approach to each other. Thus
- in sleep, in a fever, in madness, or in any very violent emotions of
- soul, our ideas may approach to our impressions, As on the other hand
- it sometimes happens, that our impressions are so faint and low, that
- we cannot distinguish them from our ideas. But notwithstanding this near
- resemblance in a few instances, they are in general so very different,
- that no-one can make a scruple to rank them under distinct heads, and
- assign to each a peculiar name to mark the difference [Footnote 1.].
- [Footnote 1. I here make use of these terms, impression and
- idea, in a sense different from what is usual, and I hope
- this liberty will be allowed me. Perhaps I rather restore
- the word, idea, to its original sense, from which Mr LOCKE
- had perverted it, in making it stand for all our
- perceptions. By the terms of impression I would not be
- understood to express the manner, in which our lively
- perceptions are produced in the soul, but merely the
- perceptions themselves; for which there is no particular
- name either in the English or any other language, that I
- know of.]
- There is another division of our perceptions, which it will be
- convenient to observe, and which extends itself both to our impressions
- and ideas. This division is into SIMPLE and COMPLEX. Simple perceptions
- or impressions and ideas are such as admit of no distinction nor
- separation. The complex are the contrary to these, and may be
- distinguished into parts. Though a particular colour, taste, and smell,
- are qualities all united together in this apple, it is easy to perceive
- they are not the same, but are at least distinguishable from each other.
- Having by these divisions given an order and arrangement to our objects,
- we may now apply ourselves to consider with the more accuracy their
- qualities and relations. The first circumstance, that strikes my eye, is
- the great resemblance betwixt our impressions and ideas in every other
- particular, except their degree of force and vivacity. The one seem to
- be in a manner the reflexion of the other; so that all the perceptions
- of the mind are double, and appear both as impressions and ideas. When
- I shut my eyes and think of my chamber, the ideas I form are exact
- representations of the impressions I felt; nor is there any circumstance
- of the one, which is not to be found in the other. In running over my
- other perceptions, I find still the same resemblance and representation.
- Ideas and impressions appear always to correspond to each other. This
- circumstance seems to me remarkable, and engages my attention for a
- moment.
- Upon a more accurate survey I find I have been carried away too far by
- the first appearance, and that I must make use of the distinction of
- perceptions into simple and complex, to limit this general decision,
- that all our ideas and impressions are resembling. I observe, that many
- of our complex ideas never had impressions, that corresponded to them,
- and that many of our complex impressions never are exactly copied in
- ideas. I can imagine to myself such a city as the New Jerusalem, whose
- pavement is gold and walls are rubies, though I never saw any such.
- I have seen Paris; but shall I affirm I can form such an idea of that
- city, as will perfectly represent all its streets and houses in their
- real and just proportions?
- I perceive, therefore, that though there is in general a great,
- resemblance betwixt our complex impressions and ideas, yet the rule is
- not universally true, that they are exact copies of each other. We may
- next consider how the case stands with our simple, perceptions. After
- the most accurate examination, of which I am capable, I venture to
- affirm, that the rule here holds without any exception, and that every
- simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it, and every
- simple impression a correspondent idea. That idea of red, which we form
- in the dark, and that impression which strikes our eyes in sun-shine,
- differ only in degree, not in nature. That the case is the same with
- all our simple impressions and ideas, it is impossible to prove by a
- particular enumeration of them. Every one may satisfy himself in this
- point by running over as many as he pleases. But if any one should deny
- this universal resemblance, I know no way of convincing him, but by
- desiring him to shew a simple impression, that has not a correspondent
- idea, or a simple idea, that has not a correspondent impression. If he
- does not answer this challenge, as it is certain he cannot, we may from
- his silence and our own observation establish our conclusion.
- Thus we find, that all simple ideas and impressions resemble each other;
- and as the complex are formed from them, we may affirm in general,
- that these two species of perception are exactly correspondent. Having
- discovered this relation, which requires no farther examination, I am
- curious to find some other of their qualities. Let us consider how they
- stand with regard to their existence, and which of the impressions and
- ideas are causes, and which effects.
- The full examination of this question is the subject of the present
- treatise; and therefore we shall here content ourselves with
- establishing one general proposition, THAT ALL OUR SIMPLE IDEAS IN
- THEIR FIRST APPEARANCE ARE DERIVED FROM SIMPLE IMPRESSIONS, WHICH ARE
- CORRESPONDENT TO THEM, AND WHICH THEY EXACTLY REPRESENT.
- In seeking for phenomena to prove this proposition, I find only those
- of two kinds; but in each kind the phenomena are obvious, numerous, and
- conclusive. I first make myself certain, by a new, review, of what I
- have already asserted, that every simple impression is attended with
- a correspondent idea, and every simple idea with a correspondent
- impression. From this constant conjunction of resembling perceptions
- I immediately conclude, that there is a great connexion betwixt our
- correspondent impressions and ideas, and that the existence of the one
- has a considerable influence upon that of the other. Such a constant
- conjunction, in such an infinite number of instances, can never arise
- from chance; but clearly proves a dependence of the impressions on the
- ideas, or of the ideas on the impressions. That I may know on which side
- this dependence lies, I consider the order of their first appearance;
- and find by constant experience, that the simple impressions always take
- the precedence of their correspondent ideas, but never appear in the
- contrary order. To give a child an idea of scarlet or orange, of sweet
- or bitter, I present the objects, or in other words, convey to him these
- impressions; but proceed not so absurdly, as to endeavour to produce
- the impressions by exciting the ideas. Our ideas upon their appearance
- produce not their correspondent impressions, nor do we perceive any
- colour, or feel any sensation merely upon thinking of them. On the
- other hand we find, that any impression either of the mind or body
- is constantly followed by an idea, which resembles it, and is only
- different in the degrees of force and liveliness, The constant
- conjunction of our resembling perceptions, is a convincing proof,
- that the one are the causes of the other; and this priority of the
- impressions is an equal proof, that our impressions are the causes of
- our ideas, not our ideas of our impressions.
- To confirm this I consider Another plain and convincing phaenomenon;
- which is, that, where-ever by any accident the faculties, which give
- rise to any impressions, are obstructed in their operations, as when one
- is born blind or deaf; not only the impressions are lost, but also their
- correspondent ideas; so that there never appear in the mind the least
- traces of either of them. Nor is this only true, where the organs of
- sensation are entirely destroyed, but likewise where they have never
- been put in action to produce a particular impression. We cannot form
- to ourselves a just idea of the taste of a pine apple, without having
- actually tasted it.
- There is however one contradictory phaenomenon, which may prove, that it
- is not absolutely impossible for ideas to go before their correspondent
- impressions. I believe it will readily be allowed that the several
- distinct ideas of colours, which enter by the eyes, or those of sounds,
- which are conveyed by the hearing, are really different from each other,
- though at the same time resembling. Now if this be true of different
- colours, it must be no less so of the different shades of the same
- colour, that each of them produces a distinct idea, independent of the
- rest. For if this should be denied, it is possible, by the continual
- gradation of shades, to run a colour insensibly into what is most remote
- from it; and if you will not allow any of the means to be different,
- you cannot without absurdity deny the extremes to be the same. Suppose
- therefore a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and
- to have become perfectly well acquainted with colours of all kinds,
- excepting one particular shade of blue, for instance, which it never
- has been his fortune to meet with. Let all the different shades of
- that colour, except that single one, be placed before him, descending
- gradually from the deepest to the lightest; it is plain, that he will
- perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting, said will be sensible,
- that there is a greater distance in that place betwixt the contiguous
- colours, than in any other. Now I ask, whether it is possible for him,
- from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency, and raise up to
- himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been
- conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are few but will be
- of opinion that he can; and this may serve as a proof, that the simple
- ideas are not always derived from the correspondent impressions; though
- the instance is so particular and singular, that it is scarce worth
- our observing, and does not merit that for it alone we should alter our
- general maxim.
- But besides this exception, it may not be amiss to remark on this head,
- that the principle of the priority of impressions to ideas must be
- understood with another limitation, viz., that as our ideas are images
- of our impressions, so we can form secondary ideas, which are images of
- the primary; as appears from this very reasoning concerning them.
- This is not, properly speaking, an exception to the rule so much as
- an explanation of it. Ideas produce the images of themselves in
- new ideas; but as the first ideas are supposed to be derived from
- impressions, it still remains true, that all our simple ideas proceed
- either mediately or immediately, from their correspondent impressions.
- This then is the first principle I establish in the science of human
- nature; nor ought we to despise it because of the simplicity of its
- appearance. For it is remarkable, that the present question concerning
- the precedency of our impressions or ideas, is the same with what has
- made so much noise in other terms, when it has been disputed whether
- there be any INNATE IDEAS, or whether all ideas be derived from
- sensation and reflexion. We may observe, that in order to prove the
- ideas of extension and colour not to be innate, philosophers do nothing
- but shew that they are conveyed by our senses. To prove the ideas
- of passion and desire not to be innate, they observe that we have a
- preceding experience of these emotions in ourselves. Now if we carefully
- examine these arguments, we shall find that they prove nothing but that
- ideas are preceded by other more lively perceptions, from which the
- are derived, and which they represent. I hope this clear stating of the
- question will remove all disputes concerning it, and win render this
- principle of more use in our reasonings, than it seems hitherto to have
- been.
- SECT. II. DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT.
- Since it appears, that our simple impressions are prior to their
- correspondent ideas, and that the exceptions are very rare, method seems
- to require we should examine our impressions, before we consider our
- ideas. Impressions way be divided into two kinds, those Of SENSATION and
- those of REFLEXION. The first kind arises in the soul originally, from
- unknown causes. The second is derived in a great measure from our ideas,
- and that in the following order. An impression first strikes upon the
- senses, and makes us perceive heat or cold, thirst or hunger, pleasure
- or pain of some kind or other. Of this impression there is a copy taken
- by the mind, which remains after the impression ceases; and this we call
- an idea. This idea of pleasure or pain, when it returns upon the soul,
- produces the new impressions of desire and aversion, hope and fear,
- which may properly be called impressions of reflexion, because derived
- from it. These again are copied by the memory and imagination, and
- become ideas; which perhaps in their turn give rise to other impressions
- and ideas. So that the impressions of reflexion are only antecedent
- to their correspondent ideas; but posterior to those of sensation, and
- derived from them. The examination of our sensations belongs more to
- anatomists and natural philosophers than to moral; and therefore shall
- not at present be entered upon. And as the impressions of reflexion,
- viz. passions, desires, and emotions, which principally deserve our
- attention, arise mostly from ideas, it will be necessary to reverse that
- method, which at first sight seems most natural; and in order to explain
- the nature and principles of the human mind, give a particular account
- of ideas, before we proceed to impressions. For this reason I have here
- chosen to begin with ideas.
- SECT. III. OF THE IDEAS OF THE MEMORY AND IMAGINATION.
- We find by experience, that when any impression has been present with
- the mind, it again makes its appearance there as an idea; and this it
- may do after two different ways: either when in its new appearance it
- retains a considerable degree of its first vivacity, and is somewhat
- intermediate betwixt an impression and an idea: or when it entirely
- loses that vivacity, and is a perfect idea. The faculty, by which we
- repeat our impressions in the first manner, is called the MEMORY, and
- the other the IMAGINATION. It is evident at first sight, that the
- ideas of the memory are much more lively and strong than those of the
- imagination, and that the former faculty paints its objects in more
- distinct colours, than any which are employed by the latter. When we
- remember any past event, the idea of it flows in upon the mind in a
- forcible manner; whereas in the imagination the perception is faint and
- languid, and cannot without difficulty be preserved by the mind
- steddy and uniform for any considerable time. Here then is a sensible
- difference betwixt one species of ideas and another. But of this more
- fully hereafter.[Part II, Sect. 5.]
- There is another difference betwixt these two kinds of ideas, which is
- no less evident, namely that though neither the ideas, of the memory
- nor imagination, neither the lively nor faint ideas can make their
- appearance in the mind, unless their correspondent impressions have
- gone before to prepare the way for them, yet the imagination is not
- restrained to the same order and form with the original impressions;
- while the memory is in a manner tied down in that respect, without any
- power of variation.
- It is evident, that the memory preserves the original form, in which
- its objects were presented, and that where-ever we depart from it in
- recollecting any thing, it proceeds from some defect or imperfection
- in that faculty. An historian may, perhaps, for the more convenient
- Carrying on of his narration, relate an event before another, to which
- it was in fact posterior; but then he takes notice of this disorder, if
- he be exact; and by that means replaces the idea in its due position. It
- is the same case in our recollection of those places and persons, with
- which we were formerly acquainted. The chief exercise of the memory
- is not to preserve the simple ideas, but their order and position. In
- short, this principle is supported by such a number of common and vulgar
- phaenomena, that we may spare ourselves the trouble of insisting on it
- any farther.
- The same evidence follows us in our second principle, OF THE LIBERTY OF
- THE IMAGINATION TO TRANSPOSE AND CHANGE ITS IDEAS. The fables we meet
- with in poems and romances put this entirely out of the question. Nature
- there is totally confounded, and nothing mentioned but winged horses,
- fiery dragons, and monstrous giants. Nor will this liberty of the fancy
- appear strange, when we consider, that all our ideas are copyed from
- our impressions, and that there are not any two impressions which
- are perfectly inseparable. Not to mention, that this is an evident
- consequence of the division of ideas into simple and complex. Where-ever
- the imagination perceives a difference among ideas, it can easily
- produce a separation.
- SECT. IV. OF THE CONNEXION OR ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS.
- As all simple ideas may be separated by the imagination, and may
- be united again in what form it pleases, nothing would be more
- unaccountable than the operations of that faculty, were it not guided
- by some universal principles, which render it, in some measure, uniform
- with itself in all times and places. Were ideas entirely loose and
- unconnected, chance alone would join them; and it is impossible the same
- simple ideas should fall regularly into complex ones (as they Commonly
- do) without some bond of union among them, some associating quality,
- by which one idea naturally introduces another. This uniting principle
- among ideas is not to be considered as an inseparable connexion; for
- that has been already excluded from the imagination: Nor yet are we to
- conclude, that without it the mind cannot join two ideas; for nothing
- is more free than that faculty: but we are only to regard it as a
- gentle force, which commonly prevails, and is the cause why, among other
- things, languages so nearly correspond to each other; nature in a manner
- pointing out to every one those simple ideas, which are most proper to
- be united in a complex one. The qualities, from which this association
- arises, and by which the mind is after this manner conveyed from one
- idea to another, are three, viz. RESEMBLANCE, CONTIGUITY in time or
- place, and CAUSE and EFFECT.
- I believe it will not be very necessary to prove, that these qualities
- produce an association among ideas, and upon the appearance of one idea
- naturally introduce another. It is plain, that in the course of our
- thinking, and in the constant revolution of our ideas, our imagination
- runs easily from one idea to any other that resembles it, and that this
- quality alone is to the fancy a sufficient bond and association. It
- is likewise evident that as the senses, in changing their objects,
- are necessitated to change them regularly, and take them as they lie
- CONTIGUOUS to each other, the imagination must by long custom acquire
- the same method of thinking, and run along the parts of space and time
- in conceiving its objects. As to the connexion, that is made by the
- relation of cause and effect, we shall have occasion afterwards to
- examine it to the bottom, and therefore shall not at present insist
- upon it. It is sufficient to observe, that there is no relation, which
- produces a stronger connexion in the fancy, and makes one idea more
- readily recall another, than the relation of cause and effect betwixt
- their objects.
- That we may understand the full extent of these relations, we must
- consider, that two objects are connected together in the imagination,
- not only when the one is immediately resembling, contiguous to, or the
- cause of the other, but also when there is interposed betwixt them a
- third object, which bears to both of them any of these relations. This
- may be carried on to a great length; though at the same time we may
- observe, that each remove considerably weakens the relation. Cousins in
- the fourth degree are connected by causation, if I may be allowed to
- use that term; but not so closely as brothers, much less as child and
- parent. In general we may observe, that all the relations of blood
- depend upon cause and effect, and are esteemed near or remote, according
- to the number of connecting causes interposed betwixt the persons.
- Of the three relations above-mentioned this of causation is the most
- extensive. Two objects may be considered as placed in this relation,
- as well when one is the cause of any of the actions or motions of the
- other, as when the former is the cause of the existence of the
- latter. For as that action or motion is nothing but the object itself,
- considered in a certain light, and as the object continues the same
- in all its different situations, it is easy to imagine how such
- an influence of objects upon one another may connect them in the
- imagination.
- We may carry this farther, and remark, not only that two objects are
- connected by the relation of cause and effect, when the one produces
- a motion or any action in the other, but also when it has a power
- of producing it. And this we may observe to be the source of all the
- relation, of interest and duty, by which men influence each other in
- society, and are placed in the ties of government and subordination. A
- master is such-a-one as by his situation, arising either from force or
- agreement, has a power of directing in certain particulars the actions
- of another, whom we call servant. A judge is one, who in all disputed
- cases can fix by his opinion the possession or property of any thing
- betwixt any members of the society. When a person is possessed of any
- power, there is no more required to convert it into action, but the
- exertion of the will; and that in every case is considered as possible,
- and in many as probable; especially in the case of authority, where the
- obedience of the subject is a pleasure and advantage to the superior.
- These are therefore the principles of union or cohesion among our simple
- ideas, and in the imagination supply the place of that inseparable
- connexion, by which they are united in our memory. Here is a kind
- of ATTRACTION, which in the mental world will be found to have as
- extraordinary effects as in the natural, and to shew itself in as many
- and as various forms. Its effects are every where conspicuous; but as to
- its causes, they are mostly unknown, and must be resolved into original
- qualities of human nature, which I pretend not to explain. Nothing is
- more requisite for a true philosopher, than to restrain the intemperate
- desire of searching into causes, and having established any doctrine
- upon a sufficient number of experiments, rest contented with that, when
- he sees a farther examination would lead him into obscure and uncertain
- speculations. In that case his enquiry would be much better employed in
- examining the effects than the causes of his principle.
- Amongst the effects of this union or association of ideas, there are
- none more remarkable, than those complex ideas, which are the common
- subjects of our thoughts and reasoning, and generally arise from some
- principle of union among our simple ideas. These complex ideas may be
- divided into Relations, Modes, and Substances. We shall briefly examine
- each of these in order, and shall subjoin some considerations concerning
- our general and particular ideas, before we leave the present subject,
- which may be considered as the elements of this philosophy.
- SECT. V. OF RELATIONS.
- The word RELATION is commonly used in two senses considerably different
- from each other. Either for that quality, by which two ideas are
- connected together in the imagination, and the one naturally introduces
- the other, after the manner above-explained: or for that particular
- circumstance, in which, even upon the arbitrary union of two ideas in
- the fancy, we may think proper to compare them. In common language the
- former is always the sense, in which we use the word, relation; and it
- is only in philosophy, that we extend it to mean any particular subject
- of comparison, without a connecting principle. Thus distance will be
- allowed by philosophers to be a true relation, because we acquire an
- idea of it by the comparing of objects: But in a common way we say, THAT
- NOTHING CAN BE MORE DISTANT THAN SUCH OR SUCH THINGS FROM EACH OTHER,
- NOTHING CAN HAVE LESS RELATION: as if distance and relation were
- incompatible.
- It may perhaps be esteemed an endless task to enumerate all those
- qualities, which make objects admit of comparison, and by which the
- ideas of philosophical relation are produced. But if we diligently
- consider them, we shall find that without difficulty they may be
- comprised under seven general heads, which may be considered as the
- sources of all philosophical relation.
- (1) The first is RESEMBLANCE: And this is a relation, without which
- no philosophical relation can exist; since no objects will admit
- of comparison, but what have some degree of resemblance. But though
- resemblance be necessary to all philosophical relation, it does not
- follow, that it always produces a connexion or association of ideas.
- When a quality becomes very general, and is common to a great many
- individuals, it leads not the mind directly to any one of them; but
- by presenting at once too great a choice, does thereby prevent the
- imagination from fixing on any single object.
- (2) IDENTITY may be esteemed a second species of relation. This relation
- I here consider as applied in its strictest sense to constant and
- unchangeable objects; without examining the nature and foundation
- of personal identity, which shall find its place afterwards. Of all
- relations the most universal is that of identity, being common to every
- being whose existence has any duration.
- (3) After identity the most universal and comprehensive relations are
- those of SPACE and TIME, which are the sources of an infinite number of
- comparisons, such as distant, contiguous, above, below, before, after,
- etc.
- (4) All those objects, which admit of QUANTITY, or NUMBER, may be
- compared in that particular; which is another very fertile source of
- relation.
- (5) When any two objects possess the same QUALITY in common, the
- DEGREES, in which they possess it, form a fifth species of relation.
- Thus of two objects, which are both heavy, the one may be either of
- greater, or less weight than the other. Two colours, that are of the
- same kind, may yet be of different shades, and in that respect admit of
- comparison.
- (6) The relation of CONTRARIETY may at first sight be regarded as an
- exception to the rule, THAT NO RELATION OF ANY KIND CAN SUBSIST WITHOUT
- SOME DEGREE OF RESEMBLANCE. But let us consider, that no two ideas are
- in themselves contrary, except those of existence and non-existence,
- which are plainly resembling, as implying both of them an idea of the
- object; though the latter excludes the object from all times and places,
- in which it is supposed not to exist.
- (7) All other objects, such as fire and water, heat and cold, are only
- found to be contrary from experience, and from the contrariety of their
- causes or effects; which relation of cause and effect is a seventh
- philosophical relation, as well as a natural one. The resemblance
- implied in this relation, shall be explained afterwards.
- It might naturally be expected, that I should join DIFFERENCE to the
- other relations. But that I consider rather as a negation of relation,
- than as anything real or positive. Difference is of two kinds as opposed
- either to identity or resemblance. The first is called a difference of
- number; the other of KIND.
- SECT. VI. OF MODES AND SUBSTANCES
- I would fain ask those philosophers, who found so much of their
- reasonings on the distinction of substance and accident, and imagine we
- have clear ideas of each, whether the idea of substance be derived from
- the impressions of sensation or of reflection? If it be conveyed to us
- by our senses, I ask, which of them; and after what manner? If it be
- perceived by the eyes, it must be a colour; if by the ears, a sound; if
- by the palate, a taste; and so of the other senses. But I believe none
- will assert, that substance is either a colour, or sound, or a taste.
- The idea, of substance must therefore be derived from an impression
- of reflection, if it really exist. But the impressions of reflection
- resolve themselves into our passions and emotions: none of which can
- possibly represent a substance. We have therefore no idea of substance,
- distinct from that of a collection of particular qualities, nor have we
- any other meaning when we either talk or reason concerning it.
- The idea of a substance as well as that of a mode, is nothing but a
- collection of Simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, and have
- a particular name assigned them, by which we are able to recall, either
- to ourselves or others, that collection. But the difference betwixt
- these ideas consists in this, that the particular qualities, which form
- a substance, are commonly referred to an unknown something, in which
- they are supposed to inhere; or granting this fiction should not take
- place, are at least supposed to be closely and inseparably connected by
- the relations of contiguity and causation. The effect of this is, that
- whatever new simple quality we discover to have the same connexion with
- the rest, we immediately comprehend it among them, even though it did
- not enter into the first conception of the substance. Thus our idea of
- gold may at first be a yellow colour, weight, malleableness, fusibility;
- but upon the discovery of its dissolubility in aqua regia, we join that
- to the other qualities, and suppose it to belong to the substance as
- much as if its idea had from the beginning made a part of the compound
- one. The principal of union being regarded as the chief part of the
- complex idea, gives entrance to whatever quality afterwards occurs, and
- is equally comprehended by it, as are the others, which first presented
- themselves.
- That this cannot take place in modes, is evident from considering their
- mature. The simple ideas of which modes are formed, either represent
- qualities, which are not united by contiguity and causation, but are
- dispersed in different subjects; or if they be all united together, the
- uniting principle is not regarded as the foundation of the complex idea.
- The idea of a dance is an instance of the first kind of modes; that
- of beauty of the second. The reason is obvious, why such complex
- ideas cannot receive any new idea, without changing the name, which
- distinguishes the mode.
- SECT. VII. OF ABSTRACT IDEAS.
- A very material question has been started concerning ABSTRACT or GENERAL
- ideas, WHETHER THEY BE GENERAL OR PARTICULAR IN THE MIND'S CONCEPTION
- OF THEM. A great philosopher [Dr. Berkeley.] has disputed the received
- opinion in this particular, and has asserted, that all general ideas are
- nothing but particular ones, annexed to a certain term, which gives
- them a more extensive signification, and makes them recall upon occasion
- other individuals, which are similar to them. As I look upon this to be
- one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of
- late years in the republic of letters, I shall here endeavour to confirm
- it by some arguments, which I hope will put it beyond all doubt and
- controversy.
- It is evident, that in forming most of our general ideas, if not all of
- them, we abstract from every particular degree of quantity and quality,
- and that an object ceases not to be of any particular species on
- account of every small alteration in its extension, duration and other
- properties. It may therefore be thought, that here is a plain dilemma,
- that decides concerning the nature of those abstract ideas, which have
- afforded so much speculation to philosophers. The abstract idea of a man
- represents men of all sizes and all qualities; which it is concluded it
- cannot do, but either by representing at once all possible sizes and all
- possible qualities, or by, representing no particular one at all. Now
- it having been esteemed absurd to defend the former proposition, as
- implying an infinite capacity in the mind, it has been commonly inferred
- in favour of the latter: and our abstract ideas have been supposed to
- represent no particular degree either of quantity or quality. But that
- this inference is erroneous, I shall endeavour to make appear, first,
- by proving, that it is utterly impossible to conceive any quantity or
- quality, without forming a precise notion of its degrees: And secondly
- by showing, that though the capacity of the mind be not infinite, yet
- we can at once form a notion of all possible degrees of quantity and
- quality, in such a manner at least, as, however imperfect, may serve all
- the purposes of reflection and conversation.
- To begin with the first proposition, THAT THE MIND CANNOT FORM ANY
- NOTION OF QUANTITY OR QUALITY WITHOUT FORMING A PRECISE NOTION OF
- DEGREES OF EACH; we may prove this by the three following arguments.
- First, We have observed, that whatever objects are different are
- distinguishable, and that whatever objects are distinguishable are
- separable by the thought and imagination. And we may here add, that
- these propositions are equally true in the inverse, and that whatever
- objects are separable are also distinguishable, and that whatever
- objects are distinguishable, are also different. For how is it possible
- we can separate what is not distinguishable, or distinguish what is not
- different? In order therefore to know, whether abstraction implies a
- separation, we need only consider it in this view, and examine, whether
- all the circumstances, which we abstract from in our general ideas, be
- such as are distinguishable and different from those, which we retain
- as essential parts of them. But it is evident at first sight, that the
- precise length of a line is not different nor distinguishable from the
- line itself nor the precise degree of any quality from the quality.
- These ideas, therefore, admit no more of separation than they do of
- distinction and difference. They are consequently conjoined with
- each other in the conception; and the general idea of a line,
- notwithstanding all our abstractions and refinements, has in its
- appearance in the mind a precise degree of quantity and quality; however
- it may be made to represent others, which have different degrees of
- both.
- Secondly, it is contest, that no object can appear to the senses; or in
- other words, that no impression can become present to the mind, without
- being determined in its degrees both of quantity and quality. The
- confusion, in which impressions are sometimes involved, proceeds only
- from their faintness and unsteadiness, not from any capacity in the mind
- to receive any impression, which in its real existence has no particular
- degree nor proportion. That is a contradiction in terms; and even
- implies the flattest of all contradictions, viz. that it is possible for
- the same thing both to be and not to be.
- Now since all ideas are derived from impressions, and are nothing but
- copies and representations of them, whatever is true of the one must be
- acknowledged concerning the other. Impressions and ideas differ only in
- their strength and vivacity. The foregoing conclusion is not founded on
- any particular degree of vivacity. It cannot therefore be affected by
- any variation in that particular. An idea is a weaker impression; and
- as a strong impression must necessarily have a determinate quantity and
- quality, the case must be the same with its copy or representative.
- Thirdly, it is a principle generally received in philosophy that
- everything in nature is individual, and that it is utterly absurd to
- suppose a triangle really existent, which has no precise proportion of
- sides and angles. If this therefore be absurd in fact and reality, it
- must also be absurd in idea; since nothing of which we can form a clear
- and distinct idea is absurd and impossible. But to form the idea of an
- object, and to form an idea simply, is the same thing; the reference
- of the idea to an object being an extraneous denomination, of which in
- itself it bears no mark or character. Now as it is impossible to form an
- idea of an object, that is possest of quantity and quality, and yet
- is possest of no precise degree of either; it follows that there is an
- equal impossibility of forming an idea, that is not limited and confined
- in both these particulars. Abstract ideas are therefore in themselves
- individual, however they may become general in their representation.
- The image in the mind is only that of a particular object, though the
- application of it in our reasoning be the same, as if it were universal.
- This application of ideas beyond their nature proceeds from our
- collecting all their possible degrees of quantity and quality in such an
- imperfect manner as may serve the purposes of life, which is the second
- proposition I proposed to explain. When we have found a resemblance
- [Footnote 2.] among several objects, that often occur to us, we apply
- the same name to all of them, whatever differences we may observe in the
- degrees of their quantity and quality, and whatever other differences
- may appear among them. After we have acquired a custom of this kind, the
- hearing of that name revives the idea of one of these objects, and makes
- the imagination conceive it with all its particular circumstances and
- proportions. But as the same word is supposed to have been frequently
- applied to other individuals, that are different in many respects from
- that idea, which is immediately present to the mind; the word not being
- able to revive the idea of all these individuals, but only touches the
- soul, if I may be allowed so to speak, and revives that custom, which we
- have acquired by surveying them. They are not really and in fact present
- to the mind, but only in power; nor do we draw them all out distinctly
- in the imagination, but keep ourselves in a readiness to survey any of
- them, as we may be prompted by a present design or necessity. The word
- raises up an individual idea, along with a certain custom; and that
- custom produces any other individual one, for which we may have
- occasion. But as the production of all the ideas, to which the name may
- be applied, is in most eases impossible, we abridge that work by a more
- partial consideration, and find but few inconveniences to arise in our
- reasoning from that abridgment.
- [Footnote 2. It is evident, that even different simple ideas
- may have a similarity or resemblance to each other; nor is
- it necessary, that the point or circumstance of resemblance
- shoud be distinct or separable from that in which they
- differ. BLUE and GREEN are different simple ideas, but are
- more resembling than BLUE and SCARLET; tho their perfect
- simplicity excludes all possibility of separation or
- distinction. It is the same case with particular sounds, and
- tastes and smells. These admit of infinite resemblances upon
- the general appearance and comparison, without having any
- common circumstance the same. And of this we may be certain,
- even from the very abstract terms SIMPLE IDEA. They
- comprehend all simple ideas under them. These resemble each
- other in their simplicity. And yet from their very nature,
- which excludes all composition, this circumstance, In which
- they resemble, Is not distinguishable nor separable from the
- rest. It is the same case with all the degrees In any
- quality. They are all resembling and yet the quality, In any
- individual, Is not distinct from the degree.]
- For this is one of the most extraordinary circumstances in the present
- affair, that after the mind has produced an individual idea, upon which
- we reason, the attendant custom, revived by the general or abstract
- term, readily suggests any other individual, if by chance we form any
- reasoning, that agrees not with it. Thus should we mention the
- word triangle, and form the idea of a particular equilateral one to
- correspond to it, and should we afterwards assert, that the three
- angles of a triangle are equal to each other, the other individuals of a
- scalenum and isosceles, which we overlooked at first, immediately crowd
- in upon us, and make us perceive the falshood of this proposition,
- though it be true with relation to that idea, which we had formed. If
- the mind suggests not always these ideas upon occasion, it proceeds
- from some imperfection in its faculties; and such a one as is often the
- source of false reasoning and sophistry. But this is principally the
- case with those ideas which are abstruse and compounded. On other
- occasions the custom is more entire, and it is seldom we run into such
- errors.
- Nay so entire is the custom, that the very same idea may be annext to
- several different words, and may be employed in different reasonings,
- without any danger of mistake. Thus the idea of an equilateral triangle
- of an inch perpendicular may serve us in talking of a figure, of a
- rectilinear figure, of a regular figure, of a triangle, and of an
- equilateral triangle. All these terms, therefore, are in this case
- attended with the same idea; but as they are wont to be applied in a
- greater or lesser compass, they excite their particular habits, and
- thereby keep the mind in a readiness to observe, that no conclusion be
- formed contrary to any ideas, which are usually comprized under them.
- Before those habits have become entirely perfect, perhaps the mind may
- not be content with forming the idea of only one individual, but may run
- over several, in order to make itself comprehend its own meaning, and
- the compass of that collection, which it intends to express by the
- general term. That we may fix the meaning of the word, figure, we may
- revolve in our mind the ideas of circles, squares, parallelograms,
- triangles of different sizes and proportions, and may not rest on one
- image or idea. However this may be, it is certain that we form the idea
- of individuals, whenever we use any general term; that we seldom or
- never can exhaust these individuals; and that those, which remain,
- are only represented by means of that habit, by which we recall them,
- whenever any present occasion requires it. This then is the nature of
- our abstract ideas and general terms; and it is after this manner we
- account for the foregoing paradox, THAT SOME IDEAS ARE PARTICULAR IN
- THEIR NATURE, BUT GENERAL IN THEIR REPRESENTATION. A particular idea
- becomes general by being annexed to a general term; that is, to a
- term, which from a customary conjunction has a relation to many other
- particular ideas, and readily recalls them in the imagination.
- The only difficulty, that can remain on this subject, must be with
- regard to that custom, which so readily recalls every particular idea,
- for which we may have occasion, and is excited by any word or sound, to
- which we commonly annex it. The most proper method, in my opinion,
- of giving a satisfactory explication of this act of the mind, is
- by producing other instances, which are analogous to it, and other
- principles, which facilitate its operation. To explain the ultimate
- causes of our mental actions is impossible. It is sufficient, if we can
- give any satisfactory account of them from experience and analogy.
- First then I observe, that when we mention any great number, such as
- a thousand, the mind has generally no adequate idea of it, but only a
- power of producing such an idea, by its adequate idea of the decimals,
- under which the number is comprehended. This imperfection, however,
- in our ideas, is never felt in our reasonings; which seems to be an
- instance parallel to the present one of universal ideas.
- Secondly, we have several instances of habits, which may be revived
- by one single word; as when a person, who has by rote any periods of a
- discourse, or any number of verses, will be put in remembrance of
- the whole, which he is at a loss to recollect, by that single word or
- expression, with which they begin.
- Thirdly, I believe every one, who examines the situation of his mind in
- reasoning will agree with me, that we do not annex distinct and compleat
- ideas to every term we make use of, and that in talking of government,
- church, negotiation, conquest, we seldom spread out in our minds all the
- simple ideas, of which these complex ones are composed. It is however
- observable, that notwithstanding this imperfection we may avoid talking
- nonsense on these subjects, and may perceive any repugnance among
- the ideas, as well as if we had a fall comprehension of them. Thus
- if instead of saying, that in war the weaker have always recourse to
- negotiation, we should say, that they have always recourse to conquest,
- the custom, which we have acquired of attributing certain relations to
- ideas, still follows the words, and makes us immediately perceive the
- absurdity of that proposition; in the same manner as one particular idea
- may serve us in reasoning concerning other ideas, however different from
- it in several circumstances.
- Fourthly, As the individuals are collected together, said placed under
- a general term with a view to that resemblance, which they bear to each
- other, this relation must facilitate their entrance in the imagination,
- and make them be suggested more readily upon occasion. And indeed if
- we consider the common progress of the thought, either in reflection
- or conversation, we shall find great reason to be satisfyed in this
- particular. Nothing is more admirable, than the readiness, with which
- the imagination suggests its ideas, and presents them at the very
- instant, in which they become necessary or useful. The fancy runs from
- one end of the universe to the other in collecting those ideas, which
- belong to any subject. One would think the whole intellectual world of
- ideas was at once subjected to our view, and that we did nothing but
- pick out such as were most proper for our purpose. There may not,
- however, be any present, beside those very ideas, that are thus
- collected by a kind of magical faculty in the soul, which, though it be
- always most perfect in the greatest geniuses, and is properly what we
- call a genius, is however inexplicable by the utmost efforts of human
- understanding.
- Perhaps these four reflections may help to remove an difficulties to
- the hypothesis I have proposed concerning abstract ideas, so contrary to
- that, which has hitherto prevailed in philosophy, But, to tell the truth
- I place my chief confidence in what I have already proved concerning
- the impossibility of general ideas, according to the common method of
- explaining them. We must certainly seek some new system on this head,
- and there plainly is none beside what I have proposed. If ideas be
- particular in their nature, and at the same time finite in their number,
- it is only by custom they can become general in their representation,
- and contain an infinite number of other ideas under them.
- Before I leave this subject I shall employ the same principles to
- explain that distinction of reason, which is so much talked of, and is
- so little understood, in the schools. Of this kind is the distinction
- betwixt figure and the body figured; motion and the body moved. The
- difficulty of explaining this distinction arises from the principle
- above explained, that all ideas, which are different, are separable. For
- it follows from thence, that if the figure be different from the body,
- their ideas must be separable as well as distinguishable: if they be
- not different, their ideas can neither be separable nor distinguishable.
- What then is meant by a distinction of reason, since it implies neither
- a difference nor separation.
- To remove this difficulty we must have recourse to the foregoing
- explication of abstract ideas. It is certain that the mind would never
- have dreamed of distinguishing a figure from the body figured, as being
- in reality neither distinguishable, nor different, nor separable; did it
- not observe, that even in this simplicity there might be contained many
- different resemblances and relations. Thus when a globe of white marble
- is presented, we receive only the impression of a white colour disposed
- in a certain form, nor are we able to separate and distinguish the
- colour from the form. But observing afterwards a globe of black marble
- and a cube of white, and comparing them with our former object, we
- find two separate resemblances, in what formerly seemed, and really is,
- perfectly inseparable. After a little more practice of this kind, we
- begin to distinguish the figure from the colour by a distinction of
- reason; that is, we consider the figure and colour together, since they
- are in effect the same and undistinguishable; but still view them in
- different aspects, according to the resemblances, of which they are
- susceptible. When we would consider only the figure of the globe of
- white marble, we form in reality an idea both of the figure and colour,
- but tacitly carry our eye to its resemblance with the globe of black
- marble: And in the same manner, when we would consider its colour only,
- we turn our view to its resemblance with the cube of white marble. By
- this means we accompany our ideas with a kind of reflection, of which
- custom renders us, in a great measure, insensible. A person, who desires
- us to consider the figure of a globe of white marble without thinking on
- its colour, desires an impossibility but his meaning is, that we should
- consider the figure and colour together, but still keep in our eye the
- resemblance to the globe of black marble, or that to any other globe of
- whatever colour or substance.
- PART II. OF THE IDEAS OF SPACE AND TIME.
- SECT. I. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF OUR IDEAS OF SPACE AND TIME.
- Whatever has the air of a paradox, and is contrary to the first and
- most unprejudiced notions of mankind, is often greedily embraced by
- philosophers, as shewing the superiority of their science, which coued
- discover opinions so remote from vulgar conception. On the other hand,
- anything proposed to us, which causes surprize and admiration, gives
- such a satisfaction to the mind, that it indulges itself in those
- agreeable emotions, and will never be persuaded that its pleasure is
- entirely without foundation. From these dispositions in philosophers and
- their disciples arises that mutual complaisance betwixt them; while the
- former furnish such plenty of strange and unaccountable opinions, and
- the latter so readily believe them. Of this mutual complaisance I
- cannot give a more evident instance than in the doctrine of infinite
- divisibility, with the examination of which I shall begin this subject
- of the ideas of space and time.
- It is universally allowed, that the capacity of the mind is limited, and
- can never attain a full and adequate conception of infinity: And though
- it were not allowed, it would be sufficiently evident from the plainest
- observation and experience. It is also obvious, that whatever is capable
- of being divided in infinitum, must consist of an infinite number of
- parts, and that it is impossible to set any bounds to the number of
- parts, without setting bounds at the same time to the division. It
- requires scarce any, induction to conclude from hence, that the idea,
- which we form of any finite quality, is not infinitely divisible, but
- that by proper distinctions and separations we may run up this idea
- to inferior ones, which will be perfectly simple and indivisible. In
- rejecting the infinite capacity of the mind, we suppose it may arrive at
- an end in the division of its ideas; nor are there any possible means of
- evading the evidence of this conclusion.
- It is therefore certain, that the imagination reaches a minimum, and
- may raise up to itself an idea, of which it cannot conceive any
- sub-division, and which cannot be diminished without a total
- annihilation. When you tell me of the thousandth and ten thousandth
- part of a grain of sand, I have a distinct idea of these numbers and of
- their different proportions; but the images, which I form in my mind to
- represent the things themselves, are nothing different from each other,
- nor inferior to that image, by which I represent the grain of sand
- itself, which is supposed so vastly to exceed them. What consists of
- parts is distinguishable into them, and what is distinguishable is
- separable. But whatever we may imagine of the thing, the idea of a grain
- of sand is not distinguishable, nor separable into twenty, much less
- into a thousand, ten thousand, or an infinite number of different ideas.
- It is the same case with the impressions of the senses as with the ideas
- of the imagination. Put a spot of ink upon paper, fix your eye upon that
- spot, and retire to such a distance, that, at last you lose sight of it;
- it is plain, that the moment before it vanished the image or impression
- was perfectly indivisible. It is not for want of rays of light striking
- on our eyes, that the minute parts of distant bodies convey not any
- sensible impression; but because they are removed beyond that distance,
- at which their impressions were reduced to a minimum, and were incapable
- of any farther diminution. A microscope or telescope, which renders them
- visible, produces not any new rays of light, but only spreads those,
- which always flowed from them; and by that means both gives parts to
- impressions, which to the naked eye appear simple and uncompounded, and
- advances to a minimum, what was formerly imperceptible.
- We may hence discover the error of the common opinion, that the capacity
- of the mind is limited on both sides, and that it is impossible for
- the imagination to form an adequate idea, of what goes beyond a certain
- degree of minuteness as well as of greatness. Nothing can be more
- minute, than some ideas, which we form in the fancy; and images, which
- appear to the senses; since there are ideas and images perfectly simple
- and indivisible. The only defect of our senses is, that they give
- us disproportioned images of things, and represent as minute and
- uncompounded what is really great and composed of a vast number of
- parts. This mistake we are not sensible of: but taking the impressions
- of those minute objects, which appear to the senses, to be equal or
- nearly equal to the objects, and finding by reason, that there are other
- objects vastly more minute, we too hastily conclude, that these are
- inferior to any idea of our imagination or impression of our senses.
- This however is certain, that we can form ideas, which shall be no
- greater than the smallest atom of the animal spirits of an insect a
- thousand times less than a mite: And we ought rather to conclude, that
- the difficulty lies in enlarging our conceptions so much as to form a
- just notion of a mite, or even of an insect a thousand times less than a
- mite. For in order to form a just notion of these animals, we must have
- a distinct idea representing every part of them, which, according to the
- system of infinite divisibility, is utterly impossible, and, recording
- to that of indivisible parts or atoms, is extremely difficult, by reason
- of the vast number and multiplicity of these parts.
- SECT. II. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF SPACE AND TIME.
- Wherever ideas are adequate representations of objects, the relations,
- contradictions and agreements of the ideas are all applicable to the
- objects; and this we may in general observe to be the foundation of all
- human knowledge. But our ideas are adequate representations of the
- most minute parts of extension; and through whatever divisions and
- subdivisions we may suppose these parts to be arrived at, they can never
- become inferior to some ideas, which we form. The plain consequence is,
- that whatever appears impossible and contradictory upon the comparison
- of these ideas, must be really impossible and contradictory, without any
- farther excuse or evasion.
- Every thing capable of being infinitely divided contains an infinite
- number of parts; otherwise the division would be stopt short by the
- indivisible parts, which we should immediately arrive at. If therefore
- any finite extension be infinitely divisible, it can be no contradiction
- to suppose, that a finite extension contains an infinite number of
- parts: And vice versa, if it be a contradiction to suppose, that
- a finite extension contains an infinite number of parts, no finite
- extension can be infinitely divisible. But that this latter supposition
- is absurd, I easily convince myself by the consideration of my clear
- ideas. I first take the least idea I can form of a part of extension,
- and being certain that there is nothing more minute than this idea, I
- conclude, that whatever I discover by its means must be a real quality
- of extension. I then repeat this idea once, twice, thrice, &c., and find
- the compound idea of extension, arising from its repetition, always
- to augment, and become double, triple, quadruple, &c., till at last it
- swells up to a considerable bulk, greater or smaller, in proportion as I
- repeat more or less the same idea. When I stop in the addition of parts,
- the idea of extension ceases to augment; and were I to carry on the
- addition in infinitum, I clearly perceive, that the idea of extension
- must also become infinite. Upon the whole, I conclude, that the idea of
- all infinite number of parts is individually the same idea with that of
- an infinite extension; that no finite extension is capable of containing
- an infinite number of parts; and consequently that no finite extension
- is infinitely divisible [Footnote 3.].
- [Footnote 3. It has been objected to me, that infinite
- divisibility supposes only an infinite number of
- PROPORTIONAL not of ALIQIOT parts, and that an infinite
- number of proportional parts does not form an infinite
- extension. But this distinction is entirely frivolous.
- Whether these parts be calld ALIQUOT or PROPORTIONAL, they
- cannot be inferior to those minute parts we conceive; and
- therefore cannot form a less extension by their
- conjunction.]
- I may subjoin another argument proposed by a noted author [Mons.
- MALEZIEU], which seems to me very strong and beautiful. It is evident,
- that existence in itself belongs only to unity, and is never applicable
- to number, but on account of the unites, of which the number is
- composed. Twenty men may be said to exist; but it is only because one,
- two, three, four, &c. are existent, and if you deny the existence of
- the latter, that of the former falls of course. It is therefore utterly
- absurd to suppose any number to exist, and yet deny the existence of
- unites; and as extension is always a number, according to the common
- sentiment of metaphysicians, and never resolves itself into any unite or
- indivisible quantity, it follows, that extension can never at all exist.
- It is in vain to reply, that any determinate quantity of extension is an
- unite; but such-a-one as admits of an infinite number of fractions, and
- is inexhaustible in its sub-divisions. For by the same rule these twenty
- men may be considered as a unit. The whole globe of the earth, nay
- the whole universe, may be considered as a unit. That term of unity
- is merely a fictitious denomination, which the mind may apply to any
- quantity of objects it collects together; nor can such an unity any more
- exist alone than number can, as being in reality a true number. But the
- unity, which can exist alone, and whose existence is necessary to that
- of all number, is of another kind, and must be perfectly indivisible,
- and incapable of being resolved into any lesser unity.
- All this reasoning takes place with regard to time; along with an
- additional argument, which it may be proper to take notice of. It is a
- property inseparable from time, and which in a manner constitutes its
- essence, that each of its parts succeeds another, and that none of them,
- however contiguous, can ever be co-existent. For the same reason, that
- the year 1737 cannot concur with the present year 1738 every moment must
- be distinct from, and posterior or antecedent to another. It is certain
- then, that time, as it exists, must be composed of indivisible moments.
- For if in time we could never arrive at an end of division, and if
- each moment, as it succeeds another, were not perfectly single and
- indivisible, there would be an infinite number of co-existent moments,
- or parts of time; which I believe will be allowed to be an arrant
- contradiction.
- The infinite divisibility of space implies that of time, as is evident
- from the nature of motion. If the latter, therefore, be impossible, the
- former must be equally so.
- I doubt not but, it will readily be allowed by the most obstinate
- defender of the doctrine of infinite divisibility, that these arguments
- are difficulties, and that it is impossible to give any answer to them
- which will be perfectly clear and satisfactory. But here we may
- observe, that nothing can be more absurd, than this custom of calling a
- difficulty what pretends to be a demonstration, and endeavouring by that
- means to elude its force and evidence. It is not in demonstrations as
- in probabilities, that difficulties can take place, and one argument
- counter-ballance another, and diminish its authority. A demonstration,
- if just, admits of no opposite difficulty; and if not just, it is a
- mere sophism, and consequently can never be a difficulty. It is either
- irresistible, or has no manner of force. To talk therefore of objections
- and replies, and ballancing of arguments in such a question as this, is
- to confess, either that human reason is nothing but a play of words, or
- that the person himself, who talks so, has not a Capacity equal to such
- subjects. Demonstrations may be difficult to be comprehended, because of
- abstractedness of the subject; but can never have such difficulties as
- will weaken their authority, when once they are comprehended.
- It is true, mathematicians are wont to say, that there are here equally
- strong arguments on the other side of the question, and that the
- doctrine of indivisible points is also liable to unanswerable
- objections. Before I examine these arguments and objections in detail,
- I will here take them in a body, and endeavour by a short and decisive
- reason to prove at once, that it is utterly impossible they can have any
- just foundation.
- It is an established maxim in metaphysics, That whatever the mind
- clearly conceives, includes the idea of possible existence, or in other
- words, that nothing we imagine is absolutely impossible. We can form the
- idea of a golden mountain, and from thence conclude that such a mountain
- may actually exist. We can form no idea of a mountain without a valley,
- and therefore regard it as impossible.
- Now it is certain we have an idea of extension; for otherwise why do we
- talk and reason concerning it? It is likewise certain that this idea,
- as conceived by the imagination, though divisible into parts or inferior
- ideas, is not infinitely divisible, nor consists of an infinite number
- of parts: For that exceeds the comprehension of our limited capacities.
- Here then is an idea of extension, which consists of parts or inferior
- ideas, that are perfectly, indivisible: consequently this idea implies
- no contradiction: consequently it is possible for extension really to
- exist conformable to it: and consequently all the arguments employed
- against the possibility of mathematical points are mere scholastick
- quibbles, and unworthy of our attention.
- These consequences we may carry one step farther, and conclude that all
- the pretended demonstrations for the infinite divisibility of extension
- are equally sophistical; since it is certain these demonstrations cannot
- be just without proving the impossibility of mathematical points; which
- it is an evident absurdity to pretend to.
- SECT. III. OF THE OTHER QUALITIES OF OUR IDEA OF SPACE AND TIME.
- No discovery coued have been made more happily for deciding all
- controversies concerning ideas, than that abovementioned, that
- impressions always take the precedency of them, and that every idea,
- with which the imagination is furnished, first makes its appearance in a
- correspondent impression. These latter perceptions are all so clear and
- evident, that they admit of no controversy; though many of our ideas are
- so obscure, that it is almost impossible even for the mind, which forms
- them, to tell exactly their nature and composition. Let us apply this
- principle, in order to discover farther the nature of our ideas of space
- and time.
- Upon opening my eyes, and turning them to the surrounding objects,
- I perceive many visible bodies; and upon shutting them again, and
- considering the distance betwixt these bodies, I acquire the idea of
- extension. As every idea is derived from some impression, which
- is exactly similar to it, the impressions similar to this idea of
- extension, must either be some sensations derived from the sight, or
- some internal impressions arising from these sensations.
- Our internal impressions are our passions, emotions, desires and
- aversions; none of which, I believe, will ever be asserted to be the
- model, from which the idea of space is derived. There remains therefore
- nothing but the senses, which can convey to us this original impression.
- Now what impression do oar senses here convey to us? This is the
- principal question, and decides without appeal concerning the nature of
- the idea.
- The table before me is alone sufficient by its view to give me the idea
- of extension. This idea, then, is borrowed from, and represents some
- impression, which this moment appears to the senses. But my senses
- convey to me only the impressions of coloured points, disposed in a
- certain manner. If the eye is sensible of any thing farther, I desire
- it may be pointed out to me. But if it be impossible to shew any thing
- farther, we may conclude with certainty, that the idea of extension is
- nothing but a copy of these coloured points, and of the manner of their
- appearance.
- Suppose that in the extended object, or composition of coloured points,
- from which we first received the idea of extension, the points were of
- a purple colour; it follows, that in every repetition of that idea we
- would not only place the points in the same order with respect to each
- other, but also bestow on them that precise colour, with which alone we
- are acquainted. But afterwards having experience of the other colours of
- violet, green, red, white, black, and of all the different compositions
- of these, and finding a resemblance in the disposition of coloured
- points, of which they are composed, we omit the peculiarities of
- colour, as far as possible, and found an abstract idea merely on that
- disposition of points, or manner of appearance, in which they agree. Nay
- even when the resemblance is carryed beyond the objects of one sense,
- and the impressions of touch are found to be Similar to those of sight
- in the disposition of their parts; this does not hinder the abstract
- idea from representing both, upon account of their resemblance. All
- abstract ideas are really nothing but particular ones, considered in
- a certain light; but being annexed to general terms, they are able to
- represent a vast variety, and to comprehend objects, which, as they are
- alike in some particulars, are in others vastly wide of each other.
- The idea of time, being derived from the succession of our perceptions
- of every kind, ideas as well as impressions, and impressions of
- reflection as well as of sensations will afford us an instance of an
- abstract idea, which comprehends a still greater variety than that of
- space, and yet is represented in the fancy by some particular individual
- idea of a determinate quantity and quality.
- As it is from the disposition of visible and tangible objects we receive
- the idea of space, so from the succession of ideas and impressions we
- form the idea of time, nor is it possible for time alone ever to make
- its appearance, or be taken notice of by the mind. A man in a sound
- sleep, or strongly occupyed with one thought, is insensible of time;
- and according as his perceptions succeed each other with greater or
- less rapidity, the same duration appears longer or shorter to his
- imagination. It has been remarked by a great philosopher, that our
- perceptions have certain bounds in this particular, which are fixed by
- the original nature and constitution of the mind, and beyond which no
- influence of external objects on the senses is ever able to hasten or
- retard our thought. If you wheel about a burning coal with rapidity, it
- will present to the senses an image of a circle of fire; nor will there
- seem to be any interval of time betwixt its revolutions; meerly because
- it is impossible for our perceptions to succeed each other with the same
- rapidity, that motion may be communicated to external objects. Wherever
- we have no successive perceptions, we have no notion of time, even
- though there be a real succession in the objects. From these phenomena,
- as well as from many others, we may conclude, that time cannot make
- its appearance to the mind, either alone, or attended with a steady
- unchangeable object, but is always discovered some PERCEIVABLE
- succession of changeable objects.
- To confirm this we may add the following argument, which to me seems
- perfectly decisive and convincing. It is evident, that time or duration
- consists of different parts: For otherwise we coued not conceive a
- longer or shorter duration. It is also evident, that these parts are not
- co-existent: For that quality of the co-existence of parts belongs to
- extension, and is what distinguishes it from duration. Now as time is
- composed of parts, that are not coexistent: an unchangeable object,
- since it produces none but coexistent impressions, produces none that
- can give us the idea of time; and consequently that idea must be
- derived from a succession of changeable objects, and time in its first
- appearance can never be severed from such a succession.
- Having therefore found, that time in its first appearance to the mind
- is always conjoined with a succession of changeable objects, and that
- otherwise it can never fall under our notice, we must now examine
- whether it can be conceived without our conceiving any succession
- of objects, and whether it can alone form a distinct idea in the
- imagination.
- In order to know whether any objects, which are joined in impression,
- be inseparable in idea, we need only consider, if they be different
- from each other; in which case, it is plain they may be conceived apart.
- Every thing, that is different is distinguishable: and everything,
- that is distinguishable, may be separated, according to the maxims
- above-explained. If on the contrary they be not different, they are
- not distinguishable: and if they be not distinguishable, they cannot be
- separated. But this is precisely the case with respect to time, compared
- with our successive perceptions. The idea of time is not derived from a
- particular impression mixed up with others, and plainly distinguishable
- from them; but arises altogether from the manner, in which impressions
- appear to the mind, without making one of the number. Five notes played
- on a flute give us the impression and idea of time; though time be not
- a sixth impression, which presents itself to the hearing or any other of
- the senses. Nor is it a sixth impression, which the mind by reflection
- finds in itself. These five sounds making their appearance in this
- particular manner, excite no emotion in the mind, nor produce an
- affection of any kind, which being observed by it can give rise to a new
- idea. For that is necessary to produce a new idea of reflection, nor can
- the mind, by revolving over a thousand times all its ideas of sensation,
- ever extract from them any new original idea, unless nature has so
- framed its faculties, that it feels some new original impression arise
- from such a contemplation. But here it only takes notice of the manner,
- in which the different sounds make their appearance; and that it may
- afterwards consider without considering these particular sounds, but
- may conjoin it with any other objects. The ideas of some objects it
- certainly must have, nor is it possible for it without these ideas ever
- to arrive at any conception of time; which since it, appears not as any
- primary distinct impression, can plainly be nothing but different
- ideas, or impressions, or objects disposed in a certain manner, that is,
- succeeding each other.
- I know there are some who pretend, that the idea of duration
- is applicable in a proper sense to objects, which are perfectly
- unchangeable; and this I take to be the common opinion of philosophers
- as well as of the vulgar. But to be convinced of its falsehood we need
- but reflect on the foregoing conclusion, that the idea of duration is
- always derived from a succession of changeable objects, and can never
- be conveyed to the mind by any thing stedfast and unchangeable. For it
- inevitably follows from thence, that since the idea of duration cannot
- be derived from such an object, it can never-in any propriety or
- exactness be applied to it, nor can any thing unchangeable be ever said
- to have duration. Ideas always represent the Objects or impressions,
- from which they are derived, and can never without a fiction represent
- or be applied to any other. By what fiction we apply the idea of time,
- even to what is unchangeable, and suppose, as is common, that duration
- is a measure of rest as well as of motion, we shall consider [Sect 5.]
- afterwards.
- There is another very decisive argument, which establishes the present
- doctrine concerning our ideas of space and time, and is founded only on
- that simple principle, that our ideas of them are compounded of parts,
- which are indivisible. This argument may be worth the examining.
- Every idea, that is distinguishable, being also separable, let us take
- one of those simple indivisible ideas, of which the compound one of
- extension is formed, and separating it from all others, and considering
- it apart, let us form a judgment of its nature and qualities.
- It is plain it is not the idea of extension. For the idea of extension
- consists of parts; and this idea, according to t-he supposition, is
- perfectly simple and indivisible. Is it therefore nothing? That is
- absolutely impossible. For as the compound idea of extension, which is
- real, is composed of such ideas; were these so many non-entities, there
- would be a real existence composed of non-entities; which is absurd.
- Here therefore I must ask, What is our idea of a simple and indivisible
- point? No wonder if my answer appear somewhat new, since the question
- itself has scarce ever yet been thought of. We are wont to dispute
- concerning the nature of mathematical points, but seldom concerning the
- nature of their ideas.
- The idea of space is conveyed to the mind by two senses, the sight
- and touch; nor does anything ever appear extended, that is not either
- visible or tangible. That compound impression, which represents
- extension, consists of several lesser impressions, that are indivisible
- to the eye or feeling, and may be called impressions of atoms or
- corpuscles endowed with colour and solidity. But this is not all. It is
- not only requisite, that these atoms should be coloured or tangible,
- in order to discover themselves to our senses; it is also necessary
- we should preserve the idea of their colour or tangibility in order to
- comprehend them by our imagination. There is nothing but the idea of
- their colour or tangibility, which can render them conceivable by the
- mind. Upon the removal of the ideas of these sensible qualities, they
- are utterly annihilated to the thought or imagination.
- Now such as the parts are, such is the whole. If a point be not
- considered as coloured or tangible, it can convey to us no idea; and
- consequently the idea of extension, which is composed of the ideas of
- these points, can never possibly exist. But if the idea of extension
- really can exist, as we are conscious it does, its parts must also
- exist; and in order to that, must be considered as coloured or tangible.
- We have therefore no idea of space or extension, but when we regard it
- as an object either of our sight or feeling.
- The same reasoning will prove, that the indivisible moments of time must
- be filled with some real object or existence, whose succession forms the
- duration, and makes it be conceivable by the mind.
- SECT. IV. OBJECTIONS ANSWERED.
- Our system concerning space and time consists of two parts, which
- are intimately connected together. The first depends on this chain of
- reasoning. The capacity of the mind is not infinite; consequently no
- idea of extension or duration consists of an infinite number of parts
- or inferior ideas, but of a finite number, and these simple and
- indivisible: It is therefore possible for space and time to exist
- conformable to this idea: And if it be possible, it is certain they
- actually do exist conformable to it; since their infinite divisibility
- is utterly impossible and contradictory.
- The other part of our system is a consequence of this. The parts, into
- which the ideas of space and time resolve themselves, become at last
- indivisible; and these indivisible parts, being nothing in themselves,
- are inconceivable when not filled with something real and existent. The
- ideas of space and time are therefore no separate or distinct ideas, but
- merely those of the manner or order, in which objects exist: Or in
- other words, it is impossible to conceive either a vacuum and extension
- without matter, or a time, when there was no succession or change in any
- real existence. The intimate connexion betwixt these parts of our system
- is the reason why we shall examine together the objections, which have
- been urged against both of them, beginning with those against the finite
- divisibility of extension.
- I. The first of these objections, which I shall take notice of, is more
- proper to prove this connexion and dependence of the one part upon the
- other, than to destroy either of them. It has often been maintained in
- the schools, that extension must be divisible, in infinitum, because
- the system of mathematical points is absurd; and that system is absurd,
- because a mathematical point is a non-entity, and consequently can never
- by its conjunction with others form a real existence. This would
- be perfectly decisive, were there no medium betwixt the infinite
- divisibility of matter, and the non-entity of mathematical points. But
- there is evidently a medium, viz. the bestowing a colour or solidity on
- these points; and the absurdity of both the extremes is a demonstration
- of the truth and reality of this medium. The system of physical points,
- which is another medium, is too absurd to need a refutation. A real
- extension, such as a physical point is supposed to be, can never exist
- without parts, different from each other; and wherever objects are
- different, they are distinguishable and separable by the imagination.
- II. The second objection is derived from the necessity there would be of
- PENETRATION, if extension consisted of mathematical points. A simple and
- indivisible atom, that touches another, must necessarily penetrate it;
- for it is impossible it can touch it by its external parts, from the
- very supposition of its perfect simplicity, which excludes all parts. It
- must therefore touch it intimately, and in its whole essence, SECUNDUM
- SE, TOTA, ET TOTALITER; which is the very definition of penetration.
- But penetration is impossible: Mathematical points are of consequence
- equally impossible.
- I answer this objection by substituting a juster idea of penetration.
- Suppose two bodies containing no void within their circumference, to
- approach each other, and to unite in such a manner that the body, which
- results from their union, is no more extended than either of them; it
- is this we must mean when we talk of penetration. But it is evident this
- penetration is nothing but the annihilation of one of these bodies, and
- the preservation of the other, without our being able to distinguish
- particularly which is preserved and which annihilated. Before the
- approach we have the idea of two bodies. After it we have the idea
- only of one. It is impossible for the mind to preserve any notion of
- difference betwixt two bodies of the same nature existing in the same
- place at the same time.
- Taking then penetration in this sense, for the annihilation of one body
- upon its approach to another, I ask any one, if he sees a necessity,
- that a coloured or tangible point should be annihilated upon the
- approach of another coloured or tangible point? On the contrary, does
- he not evidently perceive, that from the union of these points there
- results an object, which is compounded and divisible, and may be
- distinguished into two parts, of which each preserves its existence
- distinct and separate, notwithstanding its contiguity to the other? Let
- him aid his fancy by conceiving these points to be of different colours,
- the better to prevent their coalition and confusion. A blue and a red
- point may surely lie contiguous without any penetration or annihilation.
- For if they cannot, what possibly can become of them? Whether shall the
- red or the blue be annihilated? Or if these colours unite into one, what
- new colour will they produce by their union?
- What chiefly gives rise to these objections, and at the same time
- renders it so difficult to give a satisfactory answer to them, is the
- natural infirmity and unsteadiness both of our imagination and senses,
- when employed on such minute objects. Put a spot of ink upon paper, and
- retire to such a distance, that the spot becomes altogether invisible;
- you will find, that upon your return and nearer approach the spot
- first becomes visible by short intervals; and afterwards becomes always
- visible; and afterwards acquires only a new force in its colouring
- without augmenting its bulk; and afterwards, when it has encreased to
- such a degree as to be really extended, it is still difficult for
- the imagination to break it into its component parts, because of the
- uneasiness it finds in the conception of such a minute object as a
- single point. This infirmity affects most of our reasonings on the
- present subject, and makes it almost impossible to answer in an
- intelligible manner, and in proper expressions, many questions which may
- arise concerning it.
- III. There have been many objections drawn from the mathematics against
- the indivisibility of the parts of extension: though at first sight that
- science seems rather favourable to the present doctrine; and if it
- be contrary in its DEMONSTRATIONS, it is perfectly conformable in its
- definitions. My present business then must be to defend the definitions,
- and refute the demonstrations.
- A surface is DEFINed to be length and breadth without depth: A line
- to be length without breadth or depth: A point to be what has neither
- length, breadth nor depth. It is evident that all this is perfectly
- unintelligible upon any other supposition than that of the composition
- of extension by indivisible points or atoms. How else coued any thing
- exist without length, without breadth, or without depth?
- Two different answers, I find, have been made to this argument; neither
- of which is in my opinion satisfactory. The first is, that the objects
- of geometry, those surfaces, lines and points, whose proportions and
- positions it examines, are mere ideas in the mind; I and not only never
- did, but never can exist in nature. They never did exist; for no one
- will pretend to draw a line or make a surface entirely conformable to
- the definition: They never can exist; for we may produce demonstrations
- from these very ideas to prove, that they are impossible.
- But can anything be imagined more absurd and contradictory than this
- reasoning? Whatever can be conceived by a clear and distinct idea
- necessarily implies the possibility of existence; and he who pretends
- to prove the impossibility of its existence by any argument derived from
- the clear idea, in reality asserts, that we have no clear idea of
- it, because we have a clear idea. It is in vain to search for a
- contradiction in any thing that is distinctly conceived by the mind. Did
- it imply any contradiction, it is impossible it coued ever be conceived.
- There is therefore no medium betwixt allowing at least the possibility
- of indivisible points, and denying their idea; and it is on this latter
- principle, that the second answer to the foregoing argument is founded.
- It has been pretended [L'Art de penser.], that though it be impossible
- to conceive a length without any breadth, yet by an abstraction without
- a separation, we can consider the one without regarding the other; in
- the same manner as we may think of the length of the way betwixt two
- towns, and overlook its breadth. The length is inseparable from the
- breadth both in nature and in our minds; but this excludes not a partial
- consideration, and a distinction of reason, after the manner above
- explained.
- In refuting this answer I shall not insist on the argument, which I have
- already sufficiently explained, that if it be impossible for the mind
- to arrive at a minimum in its ideas, its capacity must be infinite, in
- order to comprehend the infinite number of parts, of which its idea of
- any extension would be composed. I shall here endeavour to find some new
- absurdities in this reasoning.
- A surface terminates a solid; a line terminates a surface; a point
- terminates a line; but I assert, that if the ideas of a point, line or
- surface were not indivisible, it is impossible we should ever conceive
- these terminations: For let these ideas be supposed infinitely
- divisible; and then let the fancy endeavour to fix itself on the idea of
- the last surface, line or point; it immediately finds this idea to break
- into parts; and upon its seizing the last of these parts, it loses its
- hold by a new division, and so on in infinitum, without any possibility
- of its arriving at a concluding idea. The number of fractions bring
- it no nearer the last division, than the first idea it formed. Every
- particle eludes the grasp by a new fraction; like quicksilver, when we
- endeavour to seize it. But as in fact there must be something, which
- terminates the idea of every finite quantity; and as this terminating
- idea cannot itself consist of parts or inferior ideas; otherwise it
- would be the last of its parts, which finished the idea, and so on; this
- is a clear proof, that the ideas of surfaces, lines and points admit
- not of any division; those of surfaces in depth; of lines in breadth and
- depth; and of points in any dimension.
- The school were so sensible of the force of this argument, that some of
- them maintained, that nature has mixed among those particles of matter,
- which are divisible in infinitum, a number of mathematical points, in
- order to give a termination to bodies; and others eluded the force of
- this reasoning by a heap of unintelligible cavils and distinctions. Both
- these adversaries equally yield the victory. A man who hides himself,
- confesses as evidently the superiority of his enemy, as another, who
- fairly delivers his arms.
- Thus it appears, that the definitions of mathematics destroy the
- pretended demonstrations; and that if we have the idea of indivisible
- points, lines and surfaces conformable to the definition, their
- existence is certainly possible: but if we have no such idea, it is
- impossible we can ever conceive the termination of any figure; without
- which conception there can be no geometrical demonstration.
- But I go farther, and maintain, that none of these demonstrations
- can have sufficient weight to establish such a principle, as this of
- infinite divisibility; and that because with regard to such minute
- objects, they are not properly demonstrations, being built on ideas,
- which are not exact, and maxims, which are not precisely true. When
- geometry decides anything concerning the proportions of quantity, we
- ought not to look for the utmost precision and exactness. None of its
- proofs extend so far. It takes the dimensions and proportions of
- figures justly; but roughly, and with some liberty. Its errors are never
- considerable; nor would it err at all, did it not aspire to such an
- absolute perfection.
- I first ask mathematicians, what they mean when they say one line or
- surface is EQUAL to, or GREATER or LESS than another? Let any of them
- give an answer, to whatever sect he belongs, and whether he maintains
- the composition of extension by indivisible points, or by quantities
- divisible in infinitum. This question will embarrass both of them.
- There are few or no mathematicians, who defend the hypothesis of
- indivisible points; and yet these have the readiest and justest answer
- to the present question. They need only reply, that lines or surfaces
- are equal, when the numbers of points in each are equal; and that as
- the proportion of the numbers varies, the proportion of the lines and
- surfaces is also varyed. But though this answer be just, as well as
- obvious; yet I may affirm, that this standard of equality is entirely
- useless, and that it never is from such a comparison we determine
- objects to be equal or unequal with respect to each other. For as the
- points, which enter into the composition of any line or surface, whether
- perceived by the sight or touch, are so minute and so confounded with
- each other, that it is utterly impossible for the mind to compute their
- number, such a computation will Never afford us a standard by which we
- may judge of proportions. No one will ever be able to determine by an
- exact numeration, that an inch has fewer points than a foot, or a foot
- fewer than an ell or any greater measure: for which reason we seldom or
- never consider this as the standard of equality or inequality.
- As to those, who imagine, that extension is divisible in infinitum, it
- is impossible they can make use of this answer, or fix the equality of
- any line or surface by a numeration of its component parts. For since,
- according to their hypothesis, the least as well as greatest figures
- contain an infinite number of parts; and since infinite numbers,
- properly speaking, can neither be equal nor unequal with respect to each
- other; the equality or inequality of any portions of space can never
- depend on any proportion in the number of their parts. It is true, it
- may be said, that the inequality of an ell and a yard consists in the
- different numbers of the feet, of which they are composed; and that of
- a foot and a yard in the number of the inches. But as that quantity we
- call an inch in the one is supposed equal to what we call an inch in
- the other, and as it is impossible for the mind to find this equality by
- proceeding in infinitum with these references to inferior quantities: it
- is evident, that at last we must fix some standard of equality different
- from an enumeration of the parts.
- There are some [See Dr. Barrow's mathematical lectures.], who pretend,
- that equality is best defined by congruity, and that any two figures
- are equal, when upon the placing of one upon the other, all their parts
- correspond to and touch each other. In order to judge of this definition
- let us consider, that since equality is a relation, it is not, strictly
- speaking, a property in the figures themselves, but arises merely from
- the comparison, which the mind makes betwixt them. If it consists,
- therefore, in this imaginary application and mutual contact of parts, we
- must at least have a distinct notion of these parts, and must conceive
- their contact. Now it is plain, that in this conception we would run up
- these parts to the greatest minuteness, which can possibly be conceived;
- since the contact of large parts would never render the figures equal.
- But the minutest parts we can conceive are mathematical points; and
- consequently this standard of equality is the same with that derived
- from the equality of the number of points; which we have already
- determined to be a just but an useless standard. We must therefore look
- to some other quarter for a solution of the present difficulty.
- There are many philosophers, who refuse to assign any standard of
- equality, but assert, that it is sufficient to present two objects, that
- are equal, in order to give us a just notion of this proportion. All
- definitions, say they, are fruitless, without the perception of such
- objects; and where we perceive such objects, we no longer stand in need
- of any definition. To this reasoning, I entirely agree; and assert, that
- the only useful notion of equality, or inequality, is derived from the
- whole united appearance and the comparison of particular objects.
- It is evident, that the eye, or rather the mind is often able at one
- view to determine the proportions of bodies, and pronounce them equal
- to, or greater or less than each other, without examining or comparing
- the number of their minute parts. Such judgments are not only common,
- but in many cases certain and infallible. When the measure of a yard and
- that of a foot are presented, the mind can no more question, that the
- first is longer than the second, than it can doubt of those principles,
- which are the most clear and self-evident.
- There are therefore three proportions, which the mind distinguishes
- in the general appearance of its objects, and calls by the names of
- greater, less and equal. But though its decisions concerning these
- proportions be sometimes infallible, they are not always so; nor are our
- judgments of this kind more exempt from doubt and error than those on
- any other subject. We frequently correct our first opinion by a review
- and reflection; and pronounce those objects to be equal, which at first
- we esteemed unequal; and regard an object as less, though before it
- appeared greater than another. Nor is this the only correction, which
- these judgments of our senses undergo; but we often discover our error
- by a juxtaposition of the objects; or where that is impracticable, by
- the use of some common and invariable measure, which being successively
- applied to each, informs us of their different proportions. And even
- this correction is susceptible of a new correction, and of different
- degrees of exactness, according to the nature of the instrument,
- by which we measure the bodies, and the care which we employ in the
- comparison.
- When therefore the mind is accustomed to these judgments and their
- corrections, and finds that the same proportion which makes two figures
- have in the eye that appearance, which we call equality, makes them also
- correspond to each other, and to any common measure, with which they
- are compared, we form a mixed notion of equality derived both from the
- looser and stricter methods of comparison. But we are not content with
- this. For as sound reason convinces us that there are bodies vastly more
- minute than those, which appear to the senses; and as a false reason
- would perswade us, that there are bodies infinitely more minute; we
- clearly perceive, that we are not possessed of any instrument or art of
- measuring, which can secure us from ill error and uncertainty. We are
- sensible, that the addition or removal of one of these minute parts,
- is not discernible either in the appearance or measuring; and as we
- imagine, that two figures, which were equal before, cannot be equal
- after this removal or addition, we therefore suppose some imaginary
- standard of equality, by which the appearances and measuring are exactly
- corrected, and the figures reduced entirely to that proportion. This
- standard is plainly imaginary. For as the very idea of equality is that
- of such a particular appearance corrected by juxtaposition or a common
- measure. The notion of any correction beyond what we have instruments
- and art to make, is a mere fiction of the mind, and useless as well
- as incomprehensible. But though this standard be only imaginary, the
- fiction however is very natural; nor is anything more usual, than for
- the mind to proceed after this manner with any action, even after the
- reason has ceased, which first determined it to begin. This appears very
- conspicuously with regard to time; where though it is evident we have no
- exact method of determining the proportions of parts, not even so exact
- as in extension, yet the various corrections of our measures, and their
- different degrees of exactness, have given as an obscure and implicit
- notion of a perfect and entire equality. The case is the same in many
- other subjects. A musician finding his ear becoming every day more
- delicate, and correcting himself by reflection and attention, proceeds
- with the same act of the mind, even when the subject fails him, and
- entertains a notion of a compleat TIERCE or OCTAVE, without being able
- to tell whence he derives his standard. A painter forms the same fiction
- with regard to colours. A mechanic with regard to motion. To the one
- light and shade; to the other swift and slow are imagined to be capable
- of an exact comparison and equality beyond the judgments of the senses.
- We may apply the same reasoning to CURVE and RIGHT lines. Nothing is
- more apparent to the senses, than the distinction betwixt a curve and a
- right line; nor are there any ideas we more easily form than the ideas
- of these objects. But however easily we may form these ideas, it is
- impossible to produce any definition of them, which will fix the precise
- boundaries betwixt them. When we draw lines upon paper, or any continued
- surface, there is a certain order, by which the lines run along from one
- point to another, that they may produce the entire impression of a
- curve or right line; but this order is perfectly unknown, and nothing
- is observed but the united appearance. Thus even upon the system of
- indivisible points, we can only form a distant notion of some unknown
- standard to these objects. Upon that of infinite divisibility we cannot
- go even this length; but are reduced meerly to the general appearance,
- as the rule by which we determine lines to be either curve or right
- ones. But though we can give no perfect definition of these lines, nor
- produce any very exact method of distinguishing the one from the other;
- yet this hinders us not from correcting the first appearance by a more
- accurate consideration, and by a comparison with some rule, of whose
- rectitude from repeated trials we have a greater assurance. And it is
- from these corrections, and by carrying on the same action of the mind,
- even when its reason fails us, that we form the loose idea of a perfect
- standard to these figures, without being able to explain or comprehend
- it.
- It is true, mathematicians pretend they give an exact definition of a
- right line, when they say, it is the shortest way betwixt two points.
- But in the first place I observe, that this is more properly the
- discovery of one of the properties of a right line, than a just
- deflation of it. For I ask any one, if upon mention of a right line he
- thinks not immediately on such a particular appearance, and if it is not
- by accident only that he considers this property? A right line can be
- comprehended alone; but this definition is unintelligible without a
- comparison with other lines, which we conceive to be more extended. In
- common life it is established as a maxim, that the straightest way is
- always the shortest; which would be as absurd as to say, the shortest
- way is always the shortest, if our idea of a right line was not
- different from that of the shortest way betwixt two points.
- Secondly, I repeat what I have already established, that we have no
- precise idea of equality and inequality, shorter and longer, more than
- of a right line or a curve; and consequently that the one can never
- afford us a perfect standard for the other. An exact idea can never be
- built on such as are loose and undetermined.
- The idea of a plain surface is as little susceptible of a precise
- standard as that of a right line; nor have we any other means of
- distinguishing such a surface, than its general appearance. It is in
- vain, that mathematicians represent a plain surface as produced by the
- flowing of a right line. It will immediately be objected, that our idea
- of a surface is as independent of this method of forming a surface, as
- our idea of an ellipse is of that of a cone; that the idea of a right
- line is no more precise than that of a plain surface; that a right line
- may flow irregularly, and by that means form a figure quite different
- from a plane; and that therefore we must suppose it to flow along two
- right lines, parallel to each other, and on the same plane; which is a
- description, that explains a thing by itself, and returns in a circle.
- It appears, then, that the ideas which are most essential to geometry,
- viz. those of equality and inequality, of a right line and a plain
- surface, are far from being exact and determinate, according to our
- common method of conceiving them. Not only we are incapable of telling,
- if the case be in any degree doubtful, when such particular figures are
- equal; when such a line is a right one, and such a surface a plain one;
- but we can form no idea of that proportion, or of these figures, which
- is firm and invariable. Our appeal is still to the weak and fallible
- judgment, which we make from the appearance of the objects, and correct
- by a compass or common measure; and if we join the supposition of
- any farther correction, it is of such-a-one as is either useless or
- imaginary. In vain should we have recourse to the common topic, and
- employ the supposition of a deity, whose omnipotence may enable him to
- form a perfect geometrical figure, and describe a right line without any
- curve or inflexion. As the ultimate standard of these figures is derived
- from nothing but the senses and imagination, it is absurd to talk of
- any perfection beyond what these faculties can judge of; since the true
- perfection of any thing consists in its conformity to its standard.
- Now since these ideas are so loose and uncertain, I would fain ask any
- mathematician what infallible assurance he has, not only of the more
- intricate, and obscure propositions of his science, but of the most
- vulgar and obvious principles? How can he prove to me, for instance,
- that two right lines cannot have one common segment? Or that it is
- impossible to draw more than one right line betwixt any two points?
- should he tell me, that these opinions are obviously absurd, and
- repugnant to our clear ideas; I would answer, that I do not deny, where
- two right lines incline upon each other with a sensible angle, but it is
- absurd to imagine them to have a common segment. But supposing these two
- lines to approach at the rate of an inch in twenty leagues, I perceive
- no absurdity in asserting, that upon their contact they become one. For,
- I beseech you, by what rule or standard do you judge, when you assert,
- that the line, in which I have supposed them to concur, cannot make
- the same right line with those two, that form so small an angle betwixt
- them? You must surely have some idea of a right line, to which this line
- does not agree. Do you therefore mean that it takes not the points in
- the same order and by the same rule, as is peculiar and essential to a
- right line? If so, I must inform you, that besides that in judging after
- this manner you allow, that extension is composed of indivisible points
- (which, perhaps, is more than you intend) besides this, I say, I must
- inform you, that neither is this the standard from which we form the
- idea of a right line; nor, if it were, is there any such firmness in our
- senses or imagination, as to determine when such an order is violated or
- preserved. The original standard of a right line is in reality nothing
- but a certain general appearance; and it is evident right lines may be
- made to concur with each other, and yet correspond to this standard,
- though corrected by all the means either practicable or imaginable.
- To whatever side mathematicians turn, this dilemma still meets them.
- If they judge of equality, or any other proportion, by the accurate and
- exact standard, viz. the enumeration of the minute indivisible parts,
- they both employ a standard, which is useless in practice, and actually
- establish the indivisibility of extension, which they endeavour to
- explode. Or if they employ, as is usual, the inaccurate standard,
- derived from a comparison of objects, upon their general appearance,
- corrected by measuring and juxtaposition; their first principles,
- though certain and infallible, are too coarse to afford any such subtile
- inferences as they commonly draw from them. The first principles are
- founded on the imagination and senses: The conclusion, therefore, can
- never go beyond, much less contradict these faculties.
- This may open our eyes a little, and let us see, that no geometrical
- demonstration for the infinite divisibility of extension can have so
- much force as what we naturally attribute to every argument, which is
- supported by such magnificent pretensions. At the same time we may learn
- the reason, why geometry falls of evidence in this single point, while
- all its other reasonings command our fullest assent and approbation.
- And indeed it seems more requisite to give the reason of this exception,
- than to shew, that we really must make such an exception, and regard
- all the mathematical arguments for infinite divisibility as utterly
- sophistical. For it is evident, that as no idea of quantity is
- infinitely divisible, there cannot be imagined a more glaring absurdity,
- than to endeavour to prove, that quantity itself admits of such a
- division; and to prove this by means of ideas, which are directly
- opposite in that particular. And as this absurdity is very glaring in
- itself, so there is no argument founded on it which is not attended
- with a new absurdity, and involves not an evident contradiction.
- I might give as instances those arguments for infinite divisibility,
- which are derived from the point of contact. I know there is no
- mathematician, who will not refuse to be judged by the diagrams he
- describes upon paper, these being loose draughts, as he will tell us,
- and serving only to convey with greater facility certain ideas, which
- are the true foundation of all our reasoning. This I am satisfyed with,
- and am willing to rest the controversy merely upon these ideas. I desire
- therefore our mathematician to form, as accurately as possible,
- the ideas of a circle and a right line; and I then ask, if upon the
- conception of their contact he can conceive them as touching in a
- mathematical point, or if he must necessarily imagine them to concur
- for some space. Whichever side he chuses, he runs himself into equal
- difficulties. If he affirms, that in tracing these figures in his
- imagination, he can imagine them to touch only in a point, he allows
- the possibility of that idea, and consequently of the thing. If he says,
- that in his conception of the contact of those lines he must make
- them concur, he thereby acknowledges the fallacy of geometrical
- demonstrations, when carryed beyond a certain degree of minuteness;
- since it is certain he has such demonstrations against the concurrence
- of a circle and a right line; that is, in other words, he can prove an
- idea, viz. that of concurrence, to be INCOMPATIBLE with two other
- ideas, those of a circle and right line; though at the same time he
- acknowledges these ideas to be inseparable.
- SECT. V. THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.
- If the second part of my system be true, that the idea of space
- or extension is nothing but the idea of visible or tangible points
- distributed in a certain order; it follows, that we can form no idea
- of a vacuum, or space, where there is nothing visible or tangible. This
- gives rise to three objections, which I shall examine together, because
- the answer I shall give to one is a consequence of that which I shall
- make use of for the others.
- First, It may be said, that men have disputed for many ages concerning
- a vacuum and a plenum, without being able to bring the affair to a
- final decision; and philosophers, even at this day, think themselves
- at liberty to take part on either side, as their fancy leads them. But
- whatever foundation there may be for a controversy concerning the things
- themselves, it may be pretended, that the very dispute is decisive
- concerning the idea, and that it is impossible men coued so long reason
- about a vacuum, and either refute or defend it, without having a notion
- of what they refuted or defended.
- Secondly, If this argument should be contested, the reality or at least
- the possibility of the idea of a vacuum may be proved by the following
- reasoning. Every idea is possible, which is a necessary and infallible
- consequence of such as are possible. Now though we allow the world to be
- at present a plenum, we may easily conceive it to be deprived of motion;
- and this idea will certainly be allowed possible. It must also be
- allowed possible, to conceive the annihilation of any part of matter by
- the omnipotence of the deity, while the other parts remain at rest. For
- as every idea, that is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination;
- and as every idea, that is separable by the imagination, may be
- conceived to be separately existent; it is evident, that the existence
- of one particle of matter, no more implies the existence of another,
- than a square figure in one body implies a square figure in every one.
- This being granted, I now demand what results from the concurrence of
- these two possible ideas of rest and annihilation, and what must we
- conceive to follow upon the annihilation of all the air and subtile
- matter in the chamber, supposing the walls to remain the same, without
- any motion or alteration? There are some metaphysicians, who answer,
- that since matter and extension are the same, the annihilation of one
- necessarily implies that of the other; and there being now no distance
- betwixt the walls of the chamber, they touch each other; in the same
- manner as my hand touches the paper, which is immediately before me.
- But though this answer be very common, I defy these metaphysicians to
- conceive the matter according to their hypothesis, or imagine the floor
- and roof, with all the opposite sides of the chamber, to touch each
- other, while they continue in rest, and preserve the same position. For
- how can the two walls, that run from south to north, touch each other,
- while they touch the opposite ends of two walls, that run from east
- to west? And how can the floor and roof ever meet, while they are
- separated by the four walls, that lie in a contrary position? If you
- change their position, you suppose a motion. If you conceive any thing
- betwixt them, you suppose a new creation. But keeping strictly to the
- two ideas of rest and annihilation, it is evident, that the idea, which
- results from them, is not that of a contact of parts, but something
- else; which is concluded to be the idea of a vacuum.
- The third objection carries the matter still farther, and not only
- asserts, that the idea of a vacuum is real and possible, but also
- necessary and unavoidable. This assertion is founded on the motion we
- observe in bodies, which, it is maintained, would be impossible and
- inconceivable without a vacuum, into which one body must move in order
- to make way for another.. I shall not enlarge upon this objection,
- because it principally belongs to natural philosophy, which lies without
- our present sphere.
- In order to answer these objections, we must take the matter pretty
- deep, and consider the nature and origin of several ideas, lest we
- dispute without understanding perfectly the subject of the controversy.
- It is evident the idea of darkness is no positive idea, but merely the
- negation of light, or more properly speaking, of coloured and visible
- objects. A man, who enjoys his sight, receives no other perception from
- turning his eyes on every side, when entirely deprived of light, than
- what is common to him with one born blind; and it is certain such-a-one
- has no idea either of light or darkness. The consequence of this is,
- that it is not from the mere removal of visible objects we receive
- the impression of extension without matter; and that the idea of utter
- darkness can never be the same with that of vacuum.
- Suppose again a man to be supported in the air, and to be softly
- conveyed along by some invisible power; it is evident he is sensible of
- nothing, and never receives the idea of extension, nor indeed any idea,
- from this invariable motion. Even supposing he moves his limbs to
- and fro, this cannot convey to him that idea. He feels in that case a
- certain sensation or impression, the parts of which are successive to
- each other, and may give him the idea of time: But certainly are not
- disposed in such a manner, as is necessary to convey the idea of space
- or the idea of space or extension.
- Since then it appears, that darkness and motion, with the utter removal
- of every thing visible and tangible, can never give us the idea of
- extension without matter, or of a vacuum; the next question is, whether
- they can convey this idea, when mixed with something visible and
- tangible?
- It is commonly allowed by philosophers, that all bodies, which discover
- themselves to the eye, appear as if painted on a plain surface, and that
- their different degrees of remoteness from ourselves are discovered
- more by reason than by the senses. When I hold up my hand before me, and
- spread my fingers, they are separated as perfectly by the blue colour
- of the firmament, as they coued be by any visible object, which I coued
- place betwixt them. In order, therefore, to know whether the sight can
- convey the impression and idea of a vacuum, we must suppose, that amidst
- an entire darkness, there are luminous bodies presented to us, whose
- light discovers only these bodies themselves, without giving us any
- impression of the surrounding objects.
- We must form a parallel supposition concerning the objects of our
- feeling. It is not proper to suppose a perfect removal of all tangible
- objects: we must allow something to be perceived by the feeling; and
- after an interval and motion of the hand or other organ of sensation,
- another object of the touch to be met with; and upon leaving that,
- another; and so on, as often as we please. The question is, whether
- these intervals do not afford us the idea of extension without body?
- To begin with the first case; it is evident, that when only two luminous
- bodies appear to the eye, we can perceive, whether they be conjoined or
- separate: whether they be separated by a great or small distance; and if
- this distance varies, we can perceive its increase or diminution, with
- the motion of the bodies. But as the distance is not in this case any
- thing coloured or visible, it may be thought that there is here a vacuum
- or pure extension, not only intelligible to the mind, but obvious to the
- very senses.
- This is our natural and most familiar way of thinking; but which we
- shall learn to correct by a little reflection. We may observe, that
- when two bodies present themselves, where there was formerly an entire
- darkness, the only change, that is discoverable, is in the appearance
- of these two objects, and that all the rest continues to be as before, a
- perfect negation of light, and of every coloured or visible object. This
- is not only true of what may be said to be remote from these bodies, but
- also of the very distance; which is interposed betwixt them; that being
- nothing but darkness, or the negation of light; without parts, without
- composition, invariable and indivisible. Now since this distance causes
- no perception different from what a blind man receives from his eyes, or
- what is conveyed to us in the darkest night, it must partake of the
- same properties: And as blindness and darkness afford us no ideas of
- extension, it is impossible that the dark and undistinguishable distance
- betwixt two bodies can ever produce that idea.
- The sole difference betwixt an absolute darkness and the appearance of
- two or more visible luminous objects consists, as I said, in the objects
- themselves, and in the manner they affect our senses. The angles, which
- the rays of light flowing from them, form with each other; the motion
- that is required in the eye, in its passage from one to the other; and
- the different parts of the organs, which are affected by them; these
- produce the only perceptions, from which we can judge of the distance.
- But as these perceptions are each of them simple and indivisible, they
- can never give us the idea of extension.
- We may illustrate this by considering the sense of feeling, and the
- imaginary distance or interval interposed betwixt tangible or solid
- objects. I suppose two cases, viz. that of a man supported in the air,
- and moving his limbs to and fro, without meeting any thing tangible; and
- that of a man, who feeling something tangible, leaves it, and after a
- motion, of which he is sensible, perceives another tangible object; and
- I then ask, wherein consists the difference betwixt these two cases?
- No one will make any scruple to affirm, that it consists meerly in the
- perceiving those objects, and that the sensation, which arises from the
- motion, is in both cases the same: And as that sensation is not capable
- of conveying to us an idea of extension, when unaccompanyed with some
- other perception, it can no more give us that idea, when mixed with
- the impressions of tangible objects; since that mixture produces no
- alteration upon it.
- But though motion and darkness, either alone, or attended with tangible
- and visible objects, convey no idea of a vacuum or extension without
- matter, yet they are the causes why we falsly imagine we can form such
- an idea. For there is a close relation betwixt that motion and darkness,
- and a real extension, or composition of visible and tangible objects.
- First, We may observe, that two visible objects appearing in the midst
- of utter darkness, affect the senses in the same manner, and form the
- same angle by the rays, which flow from them, and meet in the eye, as if
- the distance betwixt them were find with visible objects, that give us
- a true idea of extension. The sensation of motion is likewise the same,
- when there is nothing tangible interposed betwixt two bodies, as when
- we feel a compounded body, whose different parts are placed beyond each
- other.
- Secondly, We find by experience, that two bodies, which are so placed
- as to affect the senses in the same manner with two others, that have a
- certain extent of visible objects interposed betwixt them, are
- capable of receiving the same extent, without any sensible impulse or
- penetration, and without any change on that angle, under which they
- appear to the senses. In like manner, where there is one object, which
- we cannot feel after another without an interval, and the perceiving
- of that sensation we call motion in our hand or organ of sensation;
- experience shews us, that it is possible the same object may be felt
- with the same sensation of motion, along with the interposed impression
- of solid and tangible objects, attending the sensation. That is, in
- other words, an invisible and intangible distance may be converted into
- a visible and tangible one, without any change on the distant objects.
- Thirdly, We may observe, as another relation betwixt these two kinds
- of distance, that they have nearly the same effects on every natural
- phaenomenon. For as all qualities, such as heat, cold, light,
- attraction, &c. diminish in proportion to the distance; there is but
- little difference observed, whether this distance be marled out by
- compounded and sensible objects, or be known only by the manner, in
- which the distant objects affect the senses.
- Here then are three relations betwixt that distance, which conveys the
- idea of extension, and that other, which is not filled with any coloured
- or solid object. The distant objects affect the senses in the same
- manner, whether separated by the one distance or the other; the second
- species of distance is found capable of receiving the first; and they
- both equally diminish the force of every quality.
- These relations betwixt the two kinds of distance will afford us an easy
- reason, why the one has so often been taken for the other, and why we
- imagine we have an idea of extension without the idea of any object
- either of the sight or feeling. For we may establish it as a general
- maxim in this science of human nature, that wherever there is a close
- relation betwixt two ideas, the mind is very apt to mistake them, and
- in all its discourses and reasonings to use the one for the other. This
- phaenomenon occurs on so many occasions, and is of such consequence,
- that I cannot forbear stopping a moment to examine its causes. I shall
- only premise, that we must distinguish exactly betwixt the phaenomenon
- itself, and the causes, which I shall assign for it; and must not
- imagine from any uncertainty in the latter, that the former is also
- uncertain. The phaenomenon may be real, though my explication be
- chimerical. The falshood of the one is no consequence of that of the
- other; though at the same time we may observe, that it is very natural
- for us to draw such a consequence; which is an evident instance of that
- very principle, which I endeavour to explain.
- When I received the relations of resemblance, contiguity and causation,
- as principles of union among ideas, without examining into their causes,
- it was more in prosecution of my first maxim, that we must in the end
- rest contented with experience, than for want of something specious and
- plausible, which I might have displayed on that subject. It would have
- been easy to have made an imaginary dissection of the brain, and have
- shewn, why upon our conception of any idea, the animal spirits run
- into all the contiguous traces, and rouze up the other ideas, that are
- related to it. But though I have neglected any advantage, which I might
- have drawn from this topic in explaining the relations of ideas, I am
- afraid I must here have recourse to it, in order to account for the
- mistakes that arise from these relations. I shall therefore observe,
- that as the mind is endowed with a power of exciting any idea it
- pleases; whenever it dispatches the spirits into that region of the
- brain, in which the idea is placed; these spirits always excite the
- idea, when they run precisely into the proper traces, and rummage that
- cell, which belongs to the idea. But as their motion is seldom direct,
- and naturally turns a little to the one side or the other; for this
- reason the animal spirits, falling into the contiguous traces, present
- other related ideas in lieu of that, which the mind desired at first to
- survey. This change we are not always sensible of; but continuing
- still the same train of thought, make use of the related idea, which is
- presented to us, and employ it in our reasoning, as if it were the same
- with what we demanded. This is the cause of many mistakes and sophisms
- in philosophy; as will naturally be imagined, and as it would be easy to
- show, if there was occasion.
- Of the three relations above-mentioned that of resemblance is the most
- fertile source of error; and indeed there are few mistakes in reasoning,
- which do not borrow largely from that origin. Resembling ideas are not
- only related together, but the actions of the mind, which we employ
- in considering them, are so little different, that we are not able to
- distinguish them. This last circumstance is of great consequence, and we
- may in general observe, that wherever the actions of the mind in forming
- any two ideas are the same or resembling, we are very apt to confound
- these ideas, and take the one for the other. Of this we shall see many
- instances in the progress of this treatise. But though resemblance be
- the relation, which most readily produces a mistake in ideas, yet
- the others of causation and contiguity may also concur in the same
- influence. We might produce the figures of poets and orators, as
- sufficient proofs of this, were it as usual, as it is reasonable, in
- metaphysical subjects to draw our arguments from that quarter. But lest
- metaphysicians should esteem this below their dignity, I shall borrow
- a proof from an observation, which may be made on most of their own
- discourses, viz. that it is usual for men to use words for ideas, and
- to talk instead of thinking in their reasonings. We use words for ideas,
- because they are commonly so closely connected that the mind easily
- mistakes them. And this likewise is the reason, why we substitute
- the idea of a distance, which is not considered either as visible or
- tangible, in the room of extension, which is nothing but a composition
- of visible or tangible points disposed in a certain order. In
- causing this mistake there concur both the relations of causation and
- resemblance. As the first species of distance is found to be convertible
- into the second, it is in this respect a kind of cause; and the
- similarity of their manner of affecting the senses, and diminishing
- every quality, forms the relation of resemblance.
- After this chain of reasoning and explication of my principles, I am now
- prepared to answer all the objections that have been offered, whether
- derived from metaphysics or mechanics. The frequent disputes concerning
- a vacuum, or extension without matter prove not the reality of the idea,
- upon which the dispute turns; there being nothing more common, than to
- see men deceive themselves in this particular; especially when by means
- of any close relation, there is another idea presented, which may be the
- occasion of their mistake.
- We may make almost the same answer to the second objection, derived from
- the conjunction of the ideas of rest and annihilation. When every thing
- is annihilated in the chamber, and the walls continue immoveable, the
- chamber must be conceived much in the same manner as at present, when
- the air that fills it, is not an object of the senses. This annihilation
- leaves to the eye, that fictitious distance, which is discovered by the
- different parts of the organ, that are affected, and by the degrees of
- light and shade;--and to the feeling, that which consists in a sensation
- of motion in the hand, or other member of the body. In vain should we.
- search any farther. On whichever side we turn this subject, we shall
- find that these are the only impressions such an object can produce
- after the supposed annihilation; and it has already been remarked, that
- impressions can give rise to no ideas, but to such as resemble them.
- Since a body interposed betwixt two others may be supposed to be
- annihilated, without producing any change upon such as lie on each
- hand of it, it is easily conceived, how it may be created anew, and yet
- produce as little alteration. Now the motion of a body has much the same
- effect as its creation. The distant bodies are no more affected in the
- one case, than in the other. This suffices to satisfy the imagination,
- and proves there is no repugnance in such a motion. Afterwards
- experience comes in play to persuade us that two bodies, situated in the
- manner above-described, have really such a capacity of receiving body
- betwixt them, and that there is no obstacle to the conversion of the
- invisible and intangible distance into one that is visible and tangible.
- However natural that conversion may seem, we cannot be sure it is
- practicable, before we have had experience of it.
- Thus I seem to have answered the three objections above-mentioned;
- though at the same time I am sensible, that few will be satisfyed
- with these answers, but will immediately propose new objections and
- difficulties. It will probably be said, that my reasoning makes nothing
- to the matter in hands and that I explain only the manner in which
- objects affect the senses, without endeavouring to account for their
- real nature and operations. Though there be nothing visible or tangible
- interposed betwixt two bodies, yet we find BY EXPERIENCE, that the
- bodies may be placed in the same manner, with regard to the eye, and
- require the same motion of the hand in passing from one to the other,
- as if divided by something visible and tangible. This invisible and
- intangible distance is also found by experience to contain a capacity of
- receiving body, or of becoming visible and tangible. Here is the whole
- of my system; and in no part of it have I endeavoured to explain the
- cause, which separates bodies after this manner, and gives them a
- capacity of receiving others betwixt them, without any impulse or
- penetration.
- I answer this objection, by pleading guilty, and by confessing that my
- intention never was to penetrate into the nature of bodies, or explain
- the secret causes of their operations. For besides that this belongs not
- to my present purpose, I am afraid, that such an enterprise is beyond
- the reach of human understanding, and that we can never pretend to
- know body otherwise than by those external properties, which discover
- themselves to the senses. As to those who attempt any thing farther, I
- cannot approve of their ambition, till I see, in some one instance at
- least, that they have met with success. But at present I content myself
- with knowing perfectly the manner in which objects affect my senses, and
- their connections with each other, as far as experience informs me of
- them. This suffices for the conduct of life; and this also suffices for
- my philosophy, which pretends only to explain the nature and causes of
- our perceptions, or impressions and ideas [Footnote 4.].
- [Footnote 4. As long as we confine our speculations to the
- appearances of objects to our senses, without entering into
- disquisitions concerning their real nature and operations,
- we are safe from all difficulties, and can never be
- embarrassed by any question. Thus, if it be asked, if the
- invisible and intangible distance, interposed betwixt two
- objects, be something or nothing: It is easy to answer, that
- it is SOMETHING, VIZ. a property of the objects, which
- affect the SENSES after such a particular manner. If it be
- asked whether two objects, having such a distance betwixt
- them, touch or not: it may be answered, that this depends
- upon the definition of the word, TOUCH. If objects be said
- to touch, when there is nothing SENSIBLE interposed betwixt
- them, these objects touch: it objects be said to touch, when
- their IMAGES strike contiguous parts of the eye, and when
- the hand FEELS both objects successively, without any
- interposed motion, these objects do not touch. The
- appearances of objects to our senses are all consistent; and
- no difficulties can ever arise, but from the obscurity of
- the terms we make use of.
- If we carry our enquiry beyond the appearances of objects to
- the senses, I am afraid, that most of our conclusions will
- be full of scepticism and uncertainty. Thus if it be asked,
- whether or not the invisible and intangible distance be
- always full of body, or of something that by an improvement
- of our organs might become visible or tangible, I must
- acknowledge, that I find no very decisive arguments on
- either side; though I am inclined to the contrary opinion,
- as being more suitable to vulgar and popular notions. If THE
- NEWTONIAN philosophy be rightly understood, it will be found
- to mean no more. A vacuum is asserted: That is, bodies are
- said to be placed after such a manner, is to receive bodies
- betwixt them, without impulsion or penetration. The real
- nature of this position of bodies is unknown. We are only
- acquainted with its effects on the senses, and its power of
- receiving body. Nothing is more suitable to that philosophy,
- than a modest scepticism to a certain degree, and a fair
- confession of ignorance in subjects, that exceed all human
- capacity.]
- I shall conclude this subject of extension with a paradox, which will
- easily be explained from the foregoing reasoning. This paradox is, that
- if you are pleased to give to the in-visible and intangible distance,
- or in other words, to the capacity of becoming a visible and tangible
- distance, the name of a vacuum, extension and matter are the same, and
- yet there is a vacuum. If you will not give it that name, motion
- is possible in a plenum, without any impulse in infinitum, without
- returning in a circle, and without penetration. But however we may
- express ourselves, we must always confess, that we have no idea of any
- real extension without filling it with sensible objects, and conceiving
- its parts as visible or tangible.
- As to the doctrine, that time is nothing but the manner, in which
- some real objects exist; we may observe, that it is liable to the same
- objections as the similar doctrine with regard to extension. If it be a
- sufficient proof, that we have the idea of a vacuum, because we dispute
- and reason concerning it; we must for the same reason have the idea
- of time without any changeable existence; since there is no subject of
- dispute more frequent and common. But that we really have no such idea,
- is certain. For whence should it be derived? Does it arise from an
- impression of sensation or of reflection? Point it out distinctly to us,
- that we may know its nature and qualities. But if you cannot point
- out any such impression, you may be certain you are mistaken, when you
- imagine you have any such idea.
- But though it be impossible to shew the impression, from which the idea
- of time without a changeable existence is derived; yet we can easily
- point out those appearances, which make us fancy we have that idea. For
- we may observe, that there is a continual succession of perceptions in
- our mind; so that the idea of time being for ever present with us; when
- we consider a stedfast object at five-a-clock, and regard the same at
- six; we are apt to apply to it that idea in the same manner as if every
- moment were distinguished by a different position, or an alteration
- of the object. The first and second appearances of the object, being
- compared with the succession of our perceptions, seem equally removed as
- if the object had really changed. To which we may add, what experience
- shews us, that the object was susceptible of such a number of changes
- betwixt these appearances; as also that the unchangeable or rather
- fictitious duration has the same effect upon every quality, by
- encreasing or diminishing it, as that succession, which is obvious to
- the senses. From these three relations we are apt to confound our ideas,
- and imagine we can form the idea of a time and duration, without any
- change or succession.
- SECT. VI. OF THE IDEA OF EXISTENCE, AND OF EXTERNAL EXISTENCE.
- It may not be amiss, before we leave this subject, to explain the ideas
- of existence and of external existence; which have their difficulties,
- as well as the ideas of space and time. By this means we shall be the
- better prepared for the examination of knowledge and probability, when
- we understand perfectly all those particular ideas, which may enter into
- our reasoning.
- There is no impression nor idea of any kind, of which we have any
- consciousness or memory, that is not conceived as existent; and it
- is evident, that from this consciousness the most perfect idea and
- assurance of being is derived. From hence we may form a dilemma, the
- most clear and conclusive that can be imagined, viz. that since we never
- remember any idea or impression without attributing existence to it,
- the idea of existence must either be derived from a distinct impression,
- conjoined with every perception or object of our thought, or must be the
- very same with the idea of the perception or object.
- As this dilemma is an evident consequence of the principle, that every
- idea arises from a similar impression, so our decision betwixt the
- propositions of the dilemma is no more doubtful. So far from there being
- any distinct impression, attending every impression and every idea,
- that I do not think there are any two distinct impressions, which are
- inseparably conjoined. Though certain sensations may at one time be
- united, we quickly find they admit of a separation, and may be presented
- apart. And thus, though every impression and idea we remember be
- considered as existent, the idea of existence is not derived from any
- particular impression.
- The idea of existence, then, is the very same with the idea of what we
- conceive to be existent. To reflect on any thing simply, and to reflect
- on it as existent, are nothing different from each other. That idea,
- when conjoined with the idea of any object, makes no addition to it.
- Whatever we conceive, we conceive to be existent. Any idea we please
- to form is the idea of a being; and the idea of a being is any idea we
- please to form.
- Whoever opposes this, must necessarily point out that distinct
- impression, from which the idea of entity is derived, and must prove,
- that this impression is inseparable from every perception we believe to
- be existent. This we may without hesitation conclude to be impossible.
- Our foregoing reasoning [Part I. Sect. 7.] concerning the distinction of
- ideas without any real difference will not here serve us in any stead.
- That kind of distinction is founded on the different resemblances, which
- the same simple idea may have to several different ideas. But no object
- can be presented resembling some object with respect to its existence,
- and different from others in the same particular; since every object,
- that is presented, must necessarily be existent.
- A like reasoning will account for the idea of external existence. We may
- observe, that it is universally allowed by philosophers, and is besides
- pretty obvious of itself, that nothing is ever really present with the
- mind but its perceptions or impressions and ideas, and that external
- objects become known to us only by those perceptions they occasion. To
- hate, to love, to think, to feel, to see; all this is nothing but to
- perceive.
- Now since nothing is ever present to the mind but perceptions, and since
- all ideas are derived from something antecedently present to the mind;
- it follows, that it is impossible for us so much as to conceive or form
- an idea of any thing specifically different from ideas and impressions.
- Let us fix our attention out of ourselves as much as possible: Let us
- chase our imagination to the heavens, or to the utmost limits of the
- universe; we never really advance a step beyond ourselves, nor can
- conceive any kind of existence, but those perceptions, which
- have appeared in that narrow compass. This is the universe of the
- imagination, nor have we any idea but what is there produced.
- The farthest we can go towards a conception of external objects, when
- supposed SPECIFICALLY different from our perceptions, is to form a
- relative idea of them, without pretending to comprehend the related
- objects. Generally speaking we do not suppose them specifically
- different; but only attribute to them different relations, connections
- and durations. But of this more fully hereafter.[Part IV, Sect. 2.]
- PART III. OF KNOWLEDGE AND PROBABILITY.
- SECT. I. OF KNOWLEDGE.
- There are seven [Part I. Sect. 5.] different kinds of philosophical
- relation, viz. RESEMBLANCE, IDENTITY, RELATIONS OF TIME AND PLACE,
- PROPORTION IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER, DEGREES IN ANY QUALITY, CONTRARIETY
- and CAUSATION. These relations may be divided into two classes; into
- such as depend entirely on the ideas, which we compare together, and
- such as may be changed without any change in the ideas. It is from the
- idea of a triangle, that we discover the relation of equality, which its
- three angles bear to two right ones; and this relation is invariable,
- as long as our idea remains the same. On the contrary, the relations of
- contiguity and distance betwixt two objects may be changed merely by an
- alteration of their place, without any change on the objects themselves
- or on their ideas; and the place depends on a hundred different
- accidents, which cannot be foreseen by the mind. It is the same case
- with identity and causation. Two objects, though perfectly resembling
- each other, and even appearing in the same place at different times, may
- be numerically different: And as the power, by which one object produces
- another, is never discoverable merely from their idea, it is evident
- cause and effect are relations, of which we receive information from
- experience, and not from any abstract reasoning or reflection. There is
- no single phaenomenon, even the most simple, which can be accounted for
- from the qualities of the objects, as they appear to us; or which we
- coued foresee without the help of our memory and experience.
- It appears, therefore, that of these seven philosophical relations,
- there remain only four, which depending solely upon ideas, can be
- the objects of knowledge and certainty. These four are RESEMBLANCE,
- CONTRARIETY, DEGREES IN QUALITY, and PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER.
- Three of these relations are discoverable at first sight, and fall more
- properly under the province of intuition than demonstration. When any
- objects resemble each other, the resemblance will at first strike the
- eye, or rather the mind; and seldom requires a second examination. The
- case is the same with contrariety, and with the degrees of any quality.
- No one can once doubt but existence and non-existence destroy each
- other, and are perfectly incompatible and contrary. And though it be
- impossible to judge exactly of the degrees of any quality, such as
- colour, taste, heat, cold, when the difference betwixt them is very
- small: yet it is easy to decide, that any of them is superior or
- inferior to another, when their difference is considerable. And this
- decision we always pronounce at first sight, without any enquiry or
- reasoning.
- We might proceed, after the same manner, in fixing the proportions
- of quantity or number, and might at one view observe a superiority
- or inferiority betwixt any numbers, or figures; especially where the
- difference is very great and remarkable. As to equality or any exact
- proportion, we can only guess at it from a single consideration; except
- in very short numbers, or very limited portions of extension; which are
- comprehended in an instant, and where we perceive an impossibility of
- falling into any considerable error. In all other cases we must settle
- the proportions with some liberty, or proceed in a more artificial
- manner.
- I have already observed, that geometry, or the art, by which we fix
- the proportions of figures; though it much excels both in universality
- and exactness, the loose judgments of the senses and imagination; yet
- never attains a perfect precision and exactness. It's first principles
- are still drawn from the general appearance of the objects; and that
- appearance can never afford us any security, when we examine, the
- prodigious minuteness of which nature is susceptible. Our ideas seem
- to give a perfect assurance, that no two right lines can have a common
- segment; but if we consider these ideas, we shall find, that they always
- suppose a sensible inclination of the two lines, and that where the
- angle they form is extremely small, we have no standard of a I @ right
- line so precise as to assure us of the truth of this proposition. It is
- the same case with most of the primary decisions of the mathematics.
- There remain, therefore, algebra and arithmetic as the only sciences, in
- which we can carry on a chain of reasoning to any degree of intricacy,
- and yet preserve a perfect exactness and certainty. We are possest of a
- precise standard, by which we can judge of the equality and proportion
- of numbers; and according as they correspond or not to that standard,
- we determine their relations, without any possibility of error. When two
- numbers are so combined, as that the one has always an unite answering
- to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal; and it is for want
- of such a standard of equality in extension, that geometry can scarce be
- esteemed a perfect and infallible science.
- But here it may not be amiss to obviate a difficulty, which may arise
- from my asserting, that though geometry falls short of that perfect
- precision and certainty, which are peculiar to arithmetic and algebra,
- yet it excels the imperfect judgments of our senses and imagination. The
- reason why I impute any defect to geometry, is, because its original and
- fundamental principles are derived merely from appearances; and it may
- perhaps be imagined, that this defect must always attend it, and keep it
- from ever reaching a greater exactness in the comparison of objects or
- ideas, than what our eye or imagination alone is able to attain. I own
- that this defect so far attends it, as to keep it from ever aspiring to
- a full certainty: But since these fundamental principles depend on
- the easiest and least deceitful appearances, they bestow on their
- consequences a degree of exactness, of which these consequences are
- singly incapable. It is impossible for the eye to determine the angles
- of a chiliagon to be equal to 1996 right angles, or make any conjecture,
- that approaches this proportion; but when it determines, that right
- lines cannot concur; that we cannot draw more than one right line
- between two given points; it's mistakes can never be of any consequence.
- And this is the nature and use of geometry, to run us up to such
- appearances, as, by reason of their simplicity, cannot lead us into any
- considerable error.
- I shall here take occasion to propose a second observation concerning
- our demonstrative reasonings, which is suggested by the same subject of
- the mathematics. It is usual with mathematicians, to pretend, that
- those ideas, which are their objects, are of so refined and spiritual a
- nature, that they fall not under the conception of the fancy, but must
- be comprehended by a pure and intellectual view, of which the superior
- faculties of the soul are alone capable. The same notion runs through
- most parts of philosophy, and is principally made use of to explain oar
- abstract ideas, and to shew how we can form an idea of a triangle,
- for instance, which shall neither be an isoceles nor scalenum, nor be
- confined to any particular length and proportion of sides. It is easy to
- see, why philosophers are so fond of this notion of some spiritual
- and refined perceptions; since by that means they cover many of their
- absurdities, and may refuse to submit to the decisions of clear ideas,
- by appealing to such as are obscure and uncertain. But to destroy this
- artifice, we need but reflect on that principle so oft insisted on, that
- all our ideas are copyed from our impressions. For from thence we may
- immediately conclude, that since all impressions are clear and precise,
- the ideas, which are copyed from them, must be of the same nature, and
- can never, but from our fault, contain any thing so dark and intricate.
- An idea is by its very nature weaker and fainter than an impression;
- but being in every other respect the same, cannot imply any very great
- mystery. If its weakness render it obscure, it is our business to
- remedy that defect, as much as possible, by keeping the idea steady and
- precise; and till we have done so, it is in vain to pretend to reasoning
- and philosophy.
- SECT. II. OF PROBABILITY, AND OF THE IDEA OF CAUSE AND EFFECT.
- This is all I think necessary to observe concerning those four
- relations, which are the foundation of science; but as to the other
- three, which depend not upon the idea, and may be absent or present
- even while that remains the same, it will be proper to explain them more
- particularly. These three relations are identity, the situations in time
- and place, and causation.
- All kinds of reasoning consist in nothing but a comparison, and a
- discovery of those relations, either constant or inconstant, which two
- or more objects bear to each other. This comparison we may make, either
- when both the objects are present to the senses, or when neither of them
- is present, or when only one. When both the objects are present to the
- senses along with the relation, we call this perception rather than
- reasoning; nor is there in this case any exercise of the thought, or
- any action, properly speaking, but a mere passive admission of the
- impressions through the organs of sensation. According to this way of
- thinking, we ought not to receive as reasoning any of the observations
- we may make concerning identity, and the relations of time and place;
- since in none of them the mind can go beyond what is immediately present
- to the senses, either to discover the real existence or the relations
- of objects. It is only causation, which produces such a connexion, as
- to give us assurance from the existence or action of one object, that it
- was followed or preceded by any other existence or action; nor can the
- other two relations be ever made use of in reasoning, except so far
- as they either affect or are affected by it. There is nothing in any
- objects to perswade us, that they are either always remote or always
- contiguous; and when from experience and observation we discover, that
- their relation in this particular is invariable, we, always conclude
- there is some secret cause, which separates or unites them. The same
- reasoning extends to identity. We readily suppose an object may continue
- individually the same, though several times absent from and present
- to the senses; and ascribe to it an identity, notwithstanding the
- interruption of the perception, whenever we conclude, that if we had
- kept our eye or hand constantly upon it, it would have conveyed an
- invariable and uninterrupted perception. But this conclusion beyond the
- impressions of our senses can be founded only on the connexion of cause
- and effect; nor can we otherwise have any security, that the object is
- not changed upon us, however much the new object may resemble that which
- was formerly present to the senses. Whenever we discover such a perfect
- resemblance, we consider, whether it be common in that species of
- objects; whether possibly or probably any cause coued operate in
- producing the change and resemblance; and according as we determine
- concerning these causes and effects, we form our judgment concerning the
- identity of the object.
- Here then it appears, that of those three relations, which depend not
- upon the mere ideas, the only one, that can be traced beyond our senses
- and informs us of existences and objects, which we do not see or feel,
- is causation. This relation, therefore, we shall endeavour to explain
- fully before we leave the subject of the understanding.
- To begin regularly, we must consider the idea of causation, and see from
- what origin it is derived. It is impossible to reason justly, without
- understanding perfectly the idea concerning which we reason; and it is
- impossible perfectly to understand any idea, without tracing it up to
- its origin, and examining that primary impression, from which it arises.
- The examination of the impression bestows a clearness on the idea;
- and the examination of the idea bestows a like clearness on all our
- reasoning.
- Let us therefore cast our eye on any two objects, which we call
- cause and effect, and turn them on all sides, in order to find that
- impression, which produces an idea, of such prodigious consequence.
- At first sight I perceive, that I must not search for it in any of
- the particular qualities of the objects; since which-ever of these
- qualities I pitch on, I find some object, that is not possessed of it,
- and yet falls under the denomination of cause or effect. And indeed
- there is nothing existent, either externally or internally, which is
- not to be considered either as a cause or an effect; though it is plain
- there is no one quality, which universally belongs to all beings, and
- gives them a title to that denomination.
- The idea, then, of causation must be derived from some relation among
- objects; and that relation we must now endeavour to discover. I find
- in the first place, that whatever objects are considered as causes
- or effects, are contiguous; and that nothing can operate in a time or
- place, which is ever so little removed from those of its existence.
- Though distant objects may sometimes seem productive of each other, they
- are commonly found upon examination to be linked by a chain of causes,
- which are contiguous among themselves, and to the distant objects; and
- when in any particular instance we cannot discover this connexion, we
- still presume it to exist. We may therefore consider the relation of
- CONTIGUITY as essential to that of causation; at least may suppose it
- such, according to the general opinion, till we can find a more [Part
- IV. Sect. 5.] proper occasion to clear up this matter, by examining what
- objects are or are not susceptible of juxtaposition and conjunction.
- The second relation I shall observe as essential to causes and effects,
- is not so universally acknowledged, but is liable to some controversy.
- It is that of PRIORITY Of time in the cause before the effect. Some
- pretend that it is not absolutely necessary a cause should precede its
- effect; but that any object or action, in the very first moment of its
- existence, may exert its productive quality, and give rise to another
- object or action, perfectly co-temporary with itself. But beside that
- experience in most instances seems to contradict this opinion, we may
- establish the relation of priority by a kind of inference or reasoning.
- It is an established maxim both in natural and moral philosophy, that
- an object, which exists for any time in its full perfection without
- producing another, is not its sole cause; but is assisted by some other
- principle, which pushes it from its state of inactivity, and makes it
- exert that energy, of which it was secretly possest. Now if any cause
- may be perfectly co-temporary with its effect, it is certain, according
- to this maxim, that they must all of them be so; since any one of them,
- which retards its operation for a single moment, exerts not itself
- at that very individual time, in which it might have operated; and
- therefore is no proper cause. The consequence of this would be no less
- than the destruction of that succession of causes, which we observe in
- the world; and indeed, the utter annihilation of time. For if one cause
- were co-temporary with its effect, and this effect with its effect, and
- so on, it is plain there would be no such thing as succession, and all
- objects must be co-existent.
- If this argument appear satisfactory, it is well. If not, I beg the
- reader to allow me the same liberty, which I have used in the preceding
- case, of supposing it such. For he shall find, that the affair is of no
- great importance.
- Having thus discovered or supposed the two relations of contiguity and
- succession to be essential to causes and effects, I find I am stopt
- short, and can proceed no farther in considering any single instance
- of cause and effect. Motion in one body is regarded upon impulse as the
- cause of motion in another. When we consider these objects with utmost
- attention, we find only that the one body approaches the other; and that
- the motion of it precedes that of the other, but without any, sensible
- interval. It is in vain to rack ourselves with farther thought and
- reflection upon this subject. We can go no farther in considering this
- particular instance.
- Should any one leave this instance, and pretend to define a cause, by
- saying it is something productive of another, it is evident he would say
- nothing. For what does he mean by production? Can he give any definition
- of it, that will not be the same with that of causation? If he can; I
- desire it may be produced. If he cannot; he here runs in a circle, and
- gives a synonimous term instead of a definition.
- Shall we then rest contented with these two relations of contiguity and
- succession, as affording a complete idea of causation? By, no means. An
- object may be contiguous and prior to another, without being considered
- as its cause. There is a NECESSARY CONNEXION to be taken into
- consideration; and that relation is of much greater importance, than any
- of the other two above-mentioned.
- Here again I turn the object on all sides, in order to discover
- the nature of this necessary connexion, and find the impression, or
- impressions, from which its idea may be derived. When I cast my eye on
- the known Qualities of objects, I immediately discover that the relation
- of cause and effect depends not in the least on them. When I consider
- their relations, I can find none but those of contiguity and succession;
- which I have already regarded as imperfect and unsatisfactory. Shall the
- despair of success make me assert, that I am here possest of an idea,
- which is not preceded by any similar impression? This would be too
- strong a proof of levity and inconstancy; since the contrary principle
- has been already so firmly established, as to admit of no farther doubt;
- at least, till we have more fully examined the present difficulty.
- We must, therefore, proceed like those, who being in search of any
- thing, that lies concealed from them, and not finding it in the place
- they expected, beat about all the neighbouring fields, without any
- certain view or design, in hopes their good fortune will at last guide
- them to what they search for. It is necessary for us to leave the
- direct survey of this question concerning the nature of that necessary
- connexion, which enters into our idea of cause and effect; and endeavour
- to find some other questions, the examination of which will perhaps
- afford a hint, that may serve to clear up the present difficulty. Of
- these questions there occur two, which I shall proceed to examine, viz.
- First, For what reason we pronounce it necessary, that every thing whose
- existence has a beginning, should also have a cause.
- Secondly, Why we conclude, that such particular causes must necessarily
- have such particular effects; and what is the nature of that inference
- we draw from the one to the other, and of the belief we repose in it?
- I shall only observe before I proceed any farther, that though the ideas
- of cause and effect be derived from the impressions of reflection as
- well as from those of sensation, yet for brevity's sake, I commonly
- mention only the latter as the origin of these ideas; though I desire
- that whatever I say of them may also extend to the former. Passions are
- connected with their objects and with one another; no less than external
- bodies are connected together. The same relation, then, of cause and
- effect, which belongs to one, must be common to all of them.
- SECT. III. WHY A CAUSE IS ALWAYS NECESSARY.
- To begin with the first question concerning the necessity of a cause:
- It is a general maxim in philosophy, that whatever begins to exist, must
- have a cause of existence. This is commonly taken for granted in all
- reasonings, without any proof given or demanded. It is supposed to be
- founded on intuition, and to be one of those maxims, which though they
- may be denyed with the lips, it is impossible for men in their hearts
- really to doubt of. But if we examine this maxim by the idea of
- knowledge above-explained, we shall discover in it no mark of any such
- intuitive certainty; but on the contrary shall find, that it is of a
- nature quite foreign to that species of conviction.
- All certainty arises from the comparison of ideas, and from the
- discovery of such relations as are unalterable, so long as the ideas
- continue the same. These relations are RESEMBLANCE, PROPORTIONS IN
- QUANTITY AND NUMBER, DEGREES OF ANY QUALITY, and CONTRARIETY; none of
- which are implyed in this proposition, Whatever has a beginning has
- also a cause of existence. That proposition therefore is not intuitively
- certain. At least any one, who would assert it to be intuitively
- certain, must deny these to be the only infallible relations, and must
- find some other relation of that kind to be implyed in it; which it will
- then be time enough to examine.
- But here is an argument, which proves at once, that the foregoing
- proposition is neither intuitively nor demonstrably certain. We can
- never demonstrate the necessity of a cause to every new existence, or
- new modification of existence, without shewing at the same time the
- impossibility there is, that any thing can ever begin to exist without
- some productive principle; and where the latter proposition cannot be
- proved, we must despair of ever being able to prove the former. Now that
- the latter proposition is utterly incapable of a demonstrative proof,
- we may satisfy ourselves by considering that as all distinct ideas are
- separable from each other, and as the ideas of cause and effect are
- evidently distinct, it will be easy for us to conceive any object to be
- non-existent this moment, and existent the next, without conjoining to
- it the distinct idea of a cause or productive principle. The separation,
- therefore, of the idea of a cause from that of a beginning of existence,
- is plainly possible for the imagination; and consequently the actual
- separation of these objects is so far possible, that it implies no
- contradiction nor absurdity; and is therefore incapable of being refuted
- by any reasoning from mere ideas; without which it is impossible to
- demonstrate the necessity of a cause.
- Accordingly we shall find upon examination, that every demonstration,
- which has been produced for the necessity of a cause, is fallacious and
- sophistical. All the points of time and place, say some philosophers
- [Mr. Hobbes.], in which we can suppose any object to begin to exist, are
- in themselves equal; and unless there be some cause, which is peculiar
- to one time and to one place, and which by that means determines and
- fixes the existence, it must remain in eternal suspence; and the object
- can never begin to be, for want of something to fix its beginning. But I
- ask; Is there any more difficulty in supposing the time and place to be
- fixed without a cause, than to suppose the existence to be determined in
- that manner? The first question that occurs on this subject is always,
- whether the object shall exist or not: The next, when and where it shall
- begin to exist. If the removal of a cause be intuitively absurd in the
- one case, it must be so in the other: And if that absurdity be not clear
- without a proof in the one case, it will equally require one in the
- other. The absurdity, then, of the one supposition can never be a proof
- of that of the other; since they are both upon the same footing, and
- must stand or fall by the same reasoning.
- The second argument [Dr. Clarke and others.], which I find used on this
- head, labours under an equal difficulty. Every thing, it is said, must
- have a cause; for if any thing wanted a cause, it would produce
- ITSELF; that is, exist before it existed; which is impossible. But this
- reasoning is plainly unconclusive; because it supposes, that in our
- denial of a cause we still grant what we expressly deny, viz. that there
- must be a cause; which therefore is taken to be the object itself; and
- that, no doubt, is an evident contradiction. But to say that any thing
- is produced, or to express myself more properly, comes into existence,
- without a cause, is not to affirm, that it is itself its own cause; but
- on the contrary in excluding all external causes, excludes a fortiori
- the thing itself, which is created. An object, that exists absolutely
- without any cause, certainly is not its own cause; and when you assert,
- that the one follows from the other, you suppose the very point in
- questions and take it for granted, that it is utterly impossible any
- thing can ever begin to exist without a cause, but that, upon the
- exclusion of one productive principle, we must still have recourse to
- another.
- It is exactly the same case with the third argument [Mr. Locke.], which
- has been employed to demonstrate the necessity of a cause. Whatever is
- produced without any cause, is produced by nothing; or in other words,
- has nothing for its cause. But nothing can never be a cause, no more
- than it can be something, or equal to two right angles. By the same
- intuition, that we perceive nothing not to be equal to two right angles,
- or not to be something, we perceive, that it can never be a cause; and
- consequently must perceive, that every object has a real cause of its
- existence.
- I believe it will not be necessary to employ many words in shewing the
- weakness of this argument, after what I have said of the foregoing. They
- are all of them founded on the same fallacy, and are derived from the
- same turn of thought. It is sufficient only to observe, that when
- we exclude all causes we really do exclude them, and neither suppose
- nothing nor the object itself to be the causes of the existence;
- and consequently can draw no argument from the absurdity of these
- suppositions to prove the absurdity of that exclusion. If every thing
- must have a cause, it follows, that upon the exclusion of other causes
- we must accept of the object itself or of nothing as causes. But it is
- the very point in question, whether every thing must have a cause or
- not; and therefore, according to all just reasoning, it ought never to
- be taken for granted.
- They are still more frivolous, who say, that every effect must have a
- cause, because it is implyed in the very idea of effect. Every effect
- necessarily pre-supposes a cause; effect being a relative term, of which
- cause is the correlative. But this does not prove, that every being must
- be preceded by a cause; no more than it follows, because every husband
- must have a wife, that therefore every man must be marryed. The true
- state of the question is, whether every object, which begins to exist,
- must owe its existence to a cause: and this I assert neither to be
- intuitively nor demonstratively certain, and hope to have proved it
- sufficiently by the foregoing arguments.
- Since it is not from knowledge or any scientific reasoning, that we
- derive the opinion of the necessity of a cause to every new production,
- that opinion must necessarily arise from observation and experience. The
- next question, then, should naturally be, how experience gives rise to
- such a principle? But as I find it will be more convenient to sink this
- question in the following, Why we conclude, that such particular
- causes must necessarily have such particular erects, and why we form
- an inference from one to another? we shall make that the subject of our
- future enquiry. It will, perhaps, be found in the end, that the same
- answer will serve for both questions.
- SECT. IV. OF THE COMPONENT PARTS OF OUR REASONINGS CONCERNING CAUSE AND EFFECT.
- Though the mind in its reasonings from causes or effects carries its
- view beyond those objects, which it sees or remembers, it must never
- lose sight of them entirely, nor reason merely upon its own ideas,
- without some mixture of impressions, or at least of ideas of the memory,
- which are equivalent to impressions. When we infer effects from causes,
- we must establish the existence of these causes; which we have only
- two ways of doing, either by an immediate perception of our memory or
- senses, or by an inference from other causes; which causes again we must
- ascertain in the same manner, either by a present impression, or by an
- inference from their causes, and so on, till we arrive at some object,
- which we see or remember. It is impossible for us to carry on our
- inferences IN INFINITUM; and the only thing, that can stop them, is an
- impression of the memory or senses, beyond which there is no room for
- doubt or enquiry.
- To give an instance of this, we may chuse any point of history, and
- consider for what reason we either believe or reject it. Thus we believe
- that Caesar was killed in the senate-house on the ides of March; and
- that because this fact is established on the unanimous testimony of
- historians, who agree to assign this precise time and place to that
- event. Here are certain characters and letters present either to our
- memory or senses; which characters we likewise remember to have been
- used as the signs of certain ideas; and these ideas were either in the
- minds of such as were immediately present at that action, and received
- the ideas directly from its existence; or they were derived from the
- testimony of others, and that again from another testimony, by a
- visible gradation, it will we arrive at those who were eyewitnesses and
- spectators of the event. It is obvious all this chain of argument or
- connexion of causes and effects, is at first founded on those characters
- or letters, which are seen or remembered, and that without the authority
- either of the memory or senses our whole reasoning would be chimerical
- and without foundation. Every link of the chain would in that case hang
- upon another; but there would not be any thing fixed to one end of it,
- capable of sustaining the whole; and consequently there would be no
- belief nor evidence. And this actually is the case with all hypothetical
- arguments, or reasonings upon a supposition; there being in them,
- neither any present impression, nor belief of a real existence.
- I need not observe, that it is no just objection to the present
- doctrine, that we can reason upon our past conclusions or principles,
- without having recourse to those impressions, from which they first
- arose. For even supposing these impressions should be entirely effaced
- from the memory, the conviction they produced may still remain; and it
- is equally true, that all reasonings concerning causes and effects are
- originally derived from some impression; in the same manner, as the
- assurance of a demonstration proceeds always from a comparison of ideas,
- though it may continue after the comparison is forgot.
- SECT. V. OF THE IMPRESSIONS OF THE SENSES AND MEMORY.
- In this kind of reasoning, then, from causation, we employ materials,
- which are of a mixed and heterogeneous nature, and which, however
- connected, are yet essentially different from each other. All our
- arguments concerning causes and effects consist both of an impression of
- the memory or, senses, and of the idea of that existence, which produces
- the object of the impression, or is produced by it. Here therefore
- we have three things to explain, viz. First, The original impression.
- Secondly, The transition to the idea of the connected cause or effect.
- Thirdly, The nature and qualities of that idea.
- As to those impressions, which arise from the senses, their ultimate
- cause is, in my opinion, perfectly inexplicable by human reason, and it
- will always be impossible to decide with certainty, whether they arise
- immediately from the object, or are produced by the creative power of
- the mind, or are derived from the author of our being. Nor is such a
- question any way material to our present purpose. We may draw inferences
- from the coherence of our perceptions, whether they be true or false;
- whether they represent nature justly, or be mere illusions of the
- senses.
- When we search for the characteristic, which distinguishes the memory
- from the imagination, we must immediately perceive, that it cannot lie
- in the simple ideas it presents to us; since both these faculties borrow
- their simple ideas from the impressions, and can never go beyond these
- original perceptions. These faculties are as little distinguished from
- each other by the arrangement of their complex ideas. For though it be
- a peculiar property of the memory to preserve the original order and
- position of its ideas, while the imagination transposes and changes
- them, as it pleases; yet this difference is not sufficient to
- distinguish them in their operation, or make us know the one from the
- other; it being impossible to recal the past impressions, in order to
- compare them with our present ideas, and see whether their arrangement
- be exactly similar. Since therefore the memory, is known, neither by
- the order of its complex ideas, nor the nature of its simple ones; it
- follows, that the difference betwixt it and the imagination lies in its
- superior force and vivacity. A man may indulge his fancy in feigning
- any past scene of adventures; nor would there be any possibility of
- distinguishing this from a remembrance of a like kind, were not the
- ideas of the imagination fainter and more obscure.
- It frequently happens, that when two men have been engaged in any scene
- of action, the one shall remember it much better than the other,
- and shall have all the difficulty in the world to make his companion
- recollect it. He runs over several circumstances in vain; mentions the
- time, the place, the company, what was said, what was done on all sides;
- till at last he hits on some lucky circumstance, that revives the whole,
- and gives his friend a perfect memory of every thing. Here the person
- that forgets receives at first all the ideas from the discourse of
- the other, with the same circumstances of time and place; though he
- considers them as mere fictions of the imagination. But as soon as the
- circumstance is mentioned, that touches the memory, the very same ideas
- now appear in a new light, and have, in a manner, a different feeling
- from what they had before. Without any other alteration, beside that
- of the feeling, they become immediately ideas of the memory, and are
- assented to.
- Since, therefore, the imagination can represent all the same objects
- that the memory can offer to us, and since those faculties are only
- distinguished by the different feeling of the ideas they present, it
- may be proper to consider what is the nature of that feeling. And here
- I believe every one will readily agree with me, that the ideas of the
- memory are more strong and lively than those of the fancy.
- A painter, who intended to represent a passion or emotion of any kind,
- would endeavour to get a sight of a person actuated by a like emotion,
- in order to enliven his ideas, and give them a force and vivacity
- superior to what is found in those, which are mere fictions of the
- imagination. The more recent this memory is, the clearer is the idea;
- and when after a long interval he would return to the contemplation of
- his object, he always finds its idea to be much decayed, if not wholly
- obliterated. We are frequently in doubt concerning the ideas of the
- memory, as they become very weak and feeble; and are at a loss to
- determine whether any image proceeds from the fancy or the memory,
- when it is not drawn in such lively colours as distinguish that latter
- faculty. I think, I remember such an event, says one; but am not sure.
- A long tract of time has almost worn it out of my memory, and leaves me
- uncertain whether or not it be the pure offspring of my fancy.
- And as an idea of the memory, by losing its force and vivacity,
- may degenerate to such a degree, as to be taken for an idea of the
- imagination; so on the other hand an idea of the imagination may acquire
- such a force and vivacity, as to pass for an idea of the memory, and
- counterfeit its effects on the belief and judgment. This is noted in
- the case of liars; who by the frequent repetition of their lies, come at
- last to believe and remember them, as realities; custom and habit having
- in this case, as in many others, the same influence on the mind as
- nature, and infixing the idea with equal force and vigour.
- Thus it appears, that the belief or assent, which always attends the
- memory and senses, is nothing but the vivacity of those perceptions they
- present; and that this alone distinguishes them from the imagination. To
- believe is in this case to feel an immediate impression of the senses,
- or a repetition of that impression in the memory. It is merely the force
- and liveliness of the perception, which constitutes the first act of the
- judgment, and lays the foundation of that reasoning, which we build upon
- it, when we trace the relation of cause and effect.
- SECT. VI. OF THE INFERENCE FROM THE IMPRESSION TO THE IDEA.
- It is easy to observe, that in tracing this relation, the inference we
- draw from cause to effect, is not derived merely from a survey of these
- particular objects, and from such a penetration into their essences
- as may discover the dependance of the one upon the other. There is no
- object, which implies the existence of any other if we consider these
- objects in themselves, and never look beyond the ideas which we form of
- them. Such an inference would amount to knowledge, and would imply
- the absolute contradiction and impossibility of conceiving any thing
- different. But as all distinct ideas are separable, it is evident
- there can be no impossibility of that kind. When we pass from a present
- impression to the idea of any object, we might possibly have separated
- the idea from the impression, and have substituted any other idea in its
- room.
- It is therefore by EXPERIENCE only, that we can infer the existence of
- one object from that of another. The nature of experience is this. We
- remember to have had frequent instances of the existence of one species
- of objects; and also remember, that the individuals of another species
- of objects have always attended them, and have existed in a regular
- order of contiguity and succession with regard to them. Thus we
- remember, to have seen that species of object we call flame, and to have
- felt that species of sensation we call heat. We likewise call to mind
- their constant conjunction in all past instances. Without any farther
- ceremony, we call the one cause and the other effect, and infer the
- existence of the one from that of the other. In all those instances,
- from which we learn the conjunction of particular causes and effects,
- both the causes and effects have been perceived by the senses, and are
- remembered But in all cases, wherein we reason concerning them, there
- is only one perceived or remembered, and the other is supplyed in
- conformity to our past experience.
- Thus in advancing we have insensibly discovered a new relation betwixt
- cause and effect, when we least expected it, and were entirely employed
- upon another subject. This relation is their CONSTANT CONJUNCTION.
- Contiguity and succession are not sufficient to make us pronounce any
- two objects to be cause and effect, unless we perceive, that these
- two relations are preserved in several instances. We may now see the
- advantage of quitting the direct survey of this relation, in order
- to discover the nature of that necessary connexion, which makes so
- essential a part of it. There are hopes, that by this means we may
- at last arrive at our proposed end; though to tell the truth, this
- new-discovered relation of a constant conjunction seems to advance us
- but very little in our way. For it implies no more than this, that like
- objects have always been placed in like relations of contiguity and
- succession; and it seems evident, at least at first sight, that by this
- means we can never discover any new idea, and can only multiply, but not
- enlarge the objects of our mind. It may be thought, that what we learn
- not from one object, we can never learn from a hundred, which are all
- of the same kind, and are perfectly resembling in every circumstance. As
- our senses shew us in one instance two bodies, or motions, or qualities
- in certain relations of success and contiguity; so our memory presents
- us only with a multitude of instances, wherein we always find like
- bodies, motions, or qualities in like relations. From the mere
- repetition of any past impression, even to infinity, there never will
- arise any new original idea, such as that of a necessary connexion; and
- the number of impressions has in this case no more effect than if we
- confined ourselves to one only. But though this reasoning seems just and
- obvious; yet as it would be folly to despair too soon, we shall continue
- the thread of our discourse; and having found, that after the discovery
- of the constant conjunction of any objects, we always draw an inference
- from one object to another, we shall now examine the nature of that
- inference, and of the transition from the impression to the idea.
- Perhaps it will appear in the end, that the necessary connexion depends
- on the inference, instead of the inference's depending on the necessary
- connexion.
- Since it appears, that the transition from an impression present to
- the memory or senses to the idea of an object, which we call cause or
- effect, is founded on past experience, and on our remembrance of their
- constant conjunction, the next question is, Whether experience produces
- the idea by means of the understanding or imagination; whether we are
- determined by reason to make the transition, or by a certain association
- and relation of perceptions. If reason determined us, it would proceed
- upon that principle, that instances, of which we have had no experience,
- must resemble those, of which we have had experience, and that the
- course of nature continues always uniformly the same. In order therefore
- to clear up this matter, let us consider all the arguments, upon which
- such a proposition may be supposed to be founded; and as these must be
- derived either from knowledge or probability, let us cast our eye on
- each of these degrees of evidence, and see whether they afford any just
- conclusion of this nature.
- Our foregoing method of reasoning will easily convince us, that there
- can be no demonstrative arguments to prove, that those instances, of
- which we have, had no experience, resemble those, of which we have had
- experience. We can at least conceive a change in the course of nature;
- which sufficiently proves, that such a change is not absolutely
- impossible. To form a clear idea of any thing, is an undeniable
- argument for its possibility, and is alone a refutation of any pretended
- demonstration against it.
- Probability, as it discovers not the relations of ideas, considered as
- such, but only those of objects, must in some respects be founded on the
- impressions of our memory and senses, and in some respects on our ideas.
- Were there no mixture of any impression in our probable reasonings, the
- conclusion would be entirely chimerical: And were there no mixture
- of ideas, the action of the mind, in observing the relation, would,
- properly speaking, be sensation, not reasoning. It is therefore
- necessary, that in all probable reasonings there be something present
- to the mind, either seen or remembered; and that from this we infer
- something connected with it, which is not seen nor remembered.
- The only connexion or relation of objects, which can lead us beyond the
- immediate impressions of our memory and senses, is that of cause and
- effect; and that because it is the only one, on which we can found a
- just inference from one object to another. The idea of cause and effect
- is derived from experience, which informs us, that such particular
- objects, in all past instances, have been constantly conjoined with
- each other: And as an object similar to one of these is supposed to
- be immediately present in its impression, we thence presume on the
- existence of one similar to its usual attendant. According to this
- account of things, which is, I think, in every point unquestionable,
- probability is founded on the presumption of a resemblance betwixt those
- objects, of which we have had experience, and those, of which we have
- had none; and therefore it is impossible this presumption can arise from
- probability. The same principle cannot be both the cause and effect
- of another; and this is, perhaps, the only proposition concerning that
- relation, which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain.
- Should any one think to elude this argument; and without determining
- whether our reasoning on this subject be derived from demonstration or
- probability, pretend that all conclusions from causes and effects are
- built on solid reasoning: I can only desire, that this reasoning may be
- produced, in order to be exposed to our examination. It may, perhaps,
- be said, that after experience of the constant conjunction of certain
- objects, we reason in the following manner. Such an object is always
- found to produce another. It is impossible it coued have this effect,
- if it was not endowed with a power of production. The power necessarily
- implies the effect; and therefore there is a just foundation for drawing
- a conclusion from the existence of one object to that of its usual
- attendant. The past production implies a power: The power implies a new
- production: And the new production is what we infer from the power and
- the past production.
- It were easy for me to shew the weakness of this reasoning, were I
- willing to make use of those observations, I have already made, that
- the idea of production is the same with that of causation, and that no
- existence certainly and demonstratively implies a power in any other
- object; or were it proper to anticipate what I shall have occasion to
- remark afterwards concerning the idea we form of power and efficacy. But
- as such a method of proceeding may seem either to weaken my system,
- by resting one part of it on another, or to breed a confusion in my
- reasoning, I shall endeavour to maintain my present assertion without
- any such assistance.
- It shall therefore be allowed for a moment, that the production of one
- object by another in any one instance implies a power; and that this
- power is connected with its effect. But it having been already proved,
- that the power lies not in the sensible qualities of the cause; and
- there being nothing but the sensible qualities present to us; I ask, why
- in other instances you presume that the same power still exists, merely
- upon the appearance of these qualities? Your appeal to past experience
- decides nothing in the present case; and at the utmost can only prove,
- that that very object, which produced any other, was at that very
- instant endowed with such a power; but can never prove, that the
- same power must continue in the same object or collection of sensible
- qualities; much less, that a like power is always conjoined with like
- sensible qualities, should it be said, that we have experience, that the
- same power continues united with the same object, and that like objects
- are endowed with like powers, I would renew my question, why from this
- experience we form any conclusion beyond those past instances, of which
- we have had experience. If you answer this question in, the same manner
- as the preceding, your answer gives still occasion to a new question
- of the same kind, even in infinitum; which clearly proves, that the
- foregoing reasoning had no just foundation.
- Thus not only our reason fails us in the discovery of the ultimate
- connexion of causes and effects, but even after experience has informed
- us of their constant conjunction, it is impossible for us to satisfy
- ourselves by our reason, why we should extend that experience beyond
- those particular instances, which have fallen under our observation. We
- suppose, but are never able to prove, that there must be a resemblance
- betwixt those objects, of which we have had experience, and those which
- lie beyond the reach of our discovery.
- We have already taken notice of certain relations, which make us pass
- from one object to another, even though there be no reason to determine
- us to that transition; and this we may establish for a general rule,
- that wherever the mind constantly and uniformly makes a transition
- without any reason, it is influenced by these relations. Now this is
- exactly the present case. Reason can never shew us the connexion of one
- object with another, though aided by experience, and the observation
- of their constant conjunction in all past instances. When the mind,
- therefore, passes from the idea or impression of one object to the idea
- or belief of another, it is not determined by reason, but by certain
- principles, which associate together the ideas of these objects, and
- unite them in the imagination. Had ideas no more union in the fancy
- than objects seem to have to the understanding, we coued never draw any
- inference from causes to effects, nor repose belief in any matter of
- fact. The inference, therefore, depends solely on the union of ideas.
- The principles of union among ideas, I have reduced to three general
- ones, and have asserted, that the idea or impression of any object
- naturally introduces the idea of any other object, that is resembling,
- contiguous to, or connected with it. These principles I allow to be
- neither the infallible nor the sole causes of an union among ideas.
- They are not the infallible causes. For one may fix his attention during
- Sometime on any one object without looking farther. They are not the
- sole causes. For the thought has evidently a very irregular motion in
- running along its objects, and may leap from the heavens to the earth,
- from one end of the creation to the other, without any certain method
- or order. But though I allow this weakness in these three relations, and
- this irregularity in the imagination; yet I assert that the only general
- principles, which associate ideas, are resemblance, contiguity and
- causation.
- There is indeed a principle of union among ideas, which at first sight
- may be esteemed different from any of these, but will be found at
- the bottom to depend on the same origin. When every individual of any
- species of objects is found by experience to be constantly united with
- an individual of another species, the appearance of any new individual
- of either species naturally conveys the thought to its usual attendant.
- Thus because such a particular idea is commonly annexed to such a
- particular word, nothing is required but the hearing of that word to
- produce the correspondent idea; and it will scarce be possible for the
- mind, by its utmost efforts, to prevent that transition. In this case it
- is not absolutely necessary, that upon hearing such a particular sound
- we should reflect on any past experience, and consider what idea
- has been usually connected with the sound. The imagination of itself
- supplies the place of this reflection, and is so accustomed to pass from
- the word to the idea, that it interposes not a moment's delay betwixt
- the hearing of the one, and the conception of the other.
- But though I acknowledge this to be a true principle of association
- among ideas, I assert it to be the very same with that betwixt the ideas
- of cause and effects and to be an essential part in all our reasonings
- from that relation. We have no other notion of cause and effect, but
- that of certain objects, which have been always conjoined together,
- and which in all past instances have been found inseparable. We cannot
- penetrate into the reason of the conjunction. We only observe the thing
- itself, and always find that from the constant conjunction the objects
- acquire an union in the imagination. When the impression of one becomes
- present to us, we immediately form an idea of its usual attendant; and
- consequently we may establish this as one part of the definition of an
- opinion or belief, that it is an idea related to or associated with a
- present impression.
- Thus though causation be a philosophical relation, as implying
- contiguity, succession, and constant conjunction, yet it is only so far
- as it is a natural relation, and produces an union among our ideas, that
- we are able to reason upon it, or draw any inference from it.
- SECT. VII. OF THE NATURE OF THE IDEA OR BELIEF.
- The idea of an object is an essential part of the belief of it, but not
- the whole. We conceive many things, which we do not believe. In order
- then to discover more fully the nature of belief, or the qualities of
- those ideas we assent to, let us weigh the following considerations.
- It is evident, that all reasonings from causes or effects terminate
- in conclusions, concerning matter of fact; that is, concerning the
- existence of objects or of their qualities. It is also evident, that the
- idea, of existence is nothing different from the idea of any object, and
- that when after the simple conception of any thing we would conceive
- it as existent, we in reality make no addition to or alteration on our
- first idea. Thus when we affirm, that God is existent, we simply
- form the idea of such a being, as he is represented to us; nor is the
- existence, which we attribute to him, conceived by a particular idea,
- which we join to the idea of his other qualities, and can again separate
- and distinguish from them. But I go farther; and not content with
- asserting, that the conception of the existence of any object is no
- addition to the simple conception of it, I likewise maintain, that the
- belief of the existence joins no new ideas to those which compose
- the idea of the object. When I think of God, when I think of him as
- existent, and when I believe him to be existent, my idea of him
- neither encreases nor diminishes. But as it is certain there is a great
- difference betwixt the simple conception of the existence of an object,
- and the belief of it, and as this difference lies not in the parts or
- composition of the idea, which we conceive; it follows, that it must lie
- in the manner, in which we conceive it.
- Suppose a person present with me, who advances propositions, to which I
- do not assent, that Caesar dyed in his bed, that silver is more
- fusible, than lead, or mercury heavier than gold; it is evident, that
- notwithstanding my incredulity, I clearly understand his meaning, and
- form all the same ideas, which he forms. My imagination is endowed with
- the same powers as his; nor is it possible for him to conceive any idea,
- which I cannot conceive; nor conjoin any, which I cannot conjoin. I
- therefore ask, Wherein consists the difference betwixt believing
- and disbelieving any proposition? The answer is easy with regard to
- propositions, that are proved by intuition or demonstration. In that
- case, the person, who assents, not only conceives the ideas according to
- the proposition, but is necessarily determined to conceive them in that
- particular manner, either immediately or by the interposition of other
- ideas. Whatever is absurd is unintelligible; nor is it possible for the
- imagination to conceive any thing contrary to a demonstration. But as in
- reasonings from causation, and concerning matters of fact, this absolute
- necessity cannot take place, and the imagination is free to conceive
- both sides of the question, I still ask, Wherein consists the deference
- betwixt incredulity and belief? since in both cases the conception of
- the idea is equally possible and requisite.
- It will not be a satisfactory answer to say, that a person, who does not
- assent to a proposition you advance; after having conceived the object
- in the same manner with you; immediately conceives it in a different
- manner, and has different ideas of it. This answer is unsatisfactory;
- not because it contains any falshood, but because it discovers not all
- the truth. It is contest, that in all cases, wherein we dissent from any
- person, we conceive both sides of the question; but as we can believe
- only one, it evidently follows, that the belief must make some
- difference betwixt that conception to which we assent, and that from
- which we dissent. We may mingle, and unite, and separate, and confound,
- and vary our ideas in a hundred different ways; but until there appears
- some principle, which fixes one of these different situations, we
- have in reality no opinion: And this principle, as it plainly makes
- no addition to our precedent ideas, can only change the manner of our
- conceiving them.
- All the perceptions of the mind are of two kinds, viz. impressions and
- ideas, which differ from each other only in their different degrees
- of force and vivacity. Our ideas are copyed from our impressions, and
- represent them in all their parts. When you would any way vary the idea
- of a particular object, you can only encrease or diminish its force and
- vivacity. If you make any other change on it, it represents a different
- object or impression. The case is the same as in colours. A particular
- shade of any colour may acquire a new degree of liveliness or brightness
- without any other variation. But when you produce any other variation,
- it is no longer the same shade or colour. So that as belief does nothing
- but vary the manner, in which we conceive any object, it can only bestow
- on our ideas an additional force and vivacity. An opinion, therefore,
- or belief may be most accurately defined, a lively idea related to or
- associated with a present impression.
- We may here take occasion to observe a very remarkable error, which
- being frequently inculcated in the schools, has become a kind of
- establishd maxim, and is universally received by all logicians. This
- error consists in the vulgar division of the acts of the understanding,
- into CONCEPTION, JUDGMENT and REASONING, and in the definitions we give
- of them. Conception is defind to be the simple survey of one or more
- ideas: Judgment to be the separating or uniting of different ideas:
- Reasoning to be the separating or uniting of different ideas by the
- interposition of others, which show the relation they bear to each
- other. But these distinctions and definitions are faulty in very
- considerable articles. For FIRST, it is far from being true, that in
- every judgment, which we form, we unite two different ideas; since in
- that proposition, GOD IS, or indeed any other, which regards existence,
- the idea of existence is no distinct idea, which we unite with that
- of the object, and which is capable of forming a compound idea by the
- union. SECONDLY, As we can thus form a proposition, which contains only
- one idea, so we may exert our reason without employing more than two
- ideas, and without having recourse to a third to serve as a medium
- betwixt them. We infer a cause immediately from its effect; and this
- inference is not only a true species of reasoning, but the strongest of
- all others, and more convincing than when we interpose another idea to
- connect the two extremes. What we may in general affirm concerning these
- three acts of the understanding is, that taking them in a proper
- light, they all resolve themselves into the first, and are nothing but
- particular ways of conceiving our objects. Whether we consider a single
- object, or several; whether we dwell on these objects, or run from them
- to others; and in whatever form or order we survey them, the act of
- the mind exceeds not a simple conception; and the only remarkable
- difference, which occurs on this occasion, is, when we join belief to
- the conception, and are persuaded of the truth of what we conceive.
- This act of the mind has never yet been explaind by any philosopher; and
- therefore I am at liberty to propose my hypothesis concerning it; which
- is, that it is only a strong and steady conception of any idea, and such
- as approaches in some measure to an immediate impression. [Footnote 5.]
- [Footnote 5. Here are the heads of those arguments, which
- lead us to this conclusion. When we infer the existence of
- an object from that of others, some object must always be
- present either to the memory or senses, in order to be the
- foundation of our reasoning; since the mind cannot run up
- with its inferences IN INFINITUM. Reason can never satisfy
- us that the existence of any one object does ever imply that
- of another; so that when we pass from the impression of one
- to the idea or belief of another, we are not determined by
- reason, but by custom or a principle of association. But
- belief is somewhat more than a simple idea. It is a
- particular manner of forming an idea: And as the same idea
- can only be varyed by a variation of its degrees of force
- and vivacity; it follows upon the whole, that belief is a
- lively idea produced by a relation to a present impression,
- according to the foregoing definition.]
- This operation of the mind, which forms the belief of any matter of
- fact, seems hitherto to have been one of the greatest mysteries of
- philosophy; though no one has so much as suspected, that there was
- any difficulty in explaining it. For my part I must own, that I find
- a considerable difficulty in the case; and that even when I think I
- understand the subject perfectly, I am at a loss for terms to express
- my meaning. I conclude, by an induction which seems to me very evident,
- that an opinion or belief is nothing but an idea, that is different
- from a fiction, not in the nature or the order of its parts, but in the
- manner of its being conceived. But when I would explain this manner, I
- scarce find any word that fully answers the case, but am obliged to have
- recourse to every one's feeling, in order to give him a perfect notion
- of this operation of the mind. An idea assented to FEELS different
- from a fictitious idea, that the fancy alone presents to us: And this
- different feeling I endeavour to explain by calling it a superior force,
- or vivacity, or solidity, or FIRMNESS, or steadiness. This variety of
- terms, which may seem so unphilosophical, is intended only to express
- that act of the mind, which renders realities more present to us than
- fictions, causes them to weigh more in the thought, and gives them a
- superior influence on the passions and imagination. Provided we
- agree about the thing, it is needless to dispute about the terms. The
- imagination has the command over all its ideas, and can join, and mix,
- and vary them in all the ways possible. It may conceive objects with
- all the circumstances of place and time. It may set them, in a manner,
- before our eyes in their true colours, just as they might have existed.
- But as it is impossible, that that faculty can ever, of itself, reach
- belief, it is evident, that belief consists not in the nature and
- order of our ideas, but in the manner of their conception, and in
- their feeling to the mind. T confess, that it is impossible to explain
- perfectly this feeling or manner of conception. We may make use of
- words, that express something near it. But its true and proper name
- is belief, which is a term that every one sufficiently understands in
- common life. And in philosophy we can go no farther, than assert, that
- it is something felt by the mind, which distinguishes the ideas of the
- judgment from the fictions of the imagination. It gives them more force
- and influence; makes them appear of greater importance; infixes them in
- the mind; and renders them the governing principles of all our actions.
- This definition will also be found to be entirely conformable to every
- one's feeling and experience. Nothing is more evident, than that those
- ideas, to which we assent, are more strong, firm and vivid, than the
- loose reveries of a castle-builder. If one person sits down to read a
- book as a romance, and another as a true history, they plainly receive
- the same ideas, and in the same order; nor does the incredulity of the
- one, and the belief of the other hinder them from putting the very
- same sense upon their author. His words produce the same ideas in both;
- though his testimony has not the same influence on them. The latter has
- a more lively conception of all the incidents. He enters deeper into
- the concerns of the persons: represents to himself their actions, and
- characters, and friendships, and enmities: He even goes so far as to
- form a notion of their features, and air, and person. While the former,
- who gives no credit to the testimony of the author, has a more faint and
- languid conception of all these particulars; and except on account
- of the style and ingenuity of the composition, can receive little
- entertainment from it.
- SECT. VIII. OF THE CAUSES OF BELIEF.
- Having thus explained the nature of belief, and shewn that it consists
- in a lively idea related to a present impression; let us now proceed
- to examine from what principles it is derived, and what bestows the
- vivacity on the idea.
- I would willingly establish it as a general maxim in the science of
- human nature, that when any impression becomes present to us, it
- not only transports the mind to such ideas as are related to it, but
- likewise communicates to them a share of its force and vivacity. All
- the operations of the mind depend in a great measure on its disposition,
- when it performs them; and according as the spirits are more or less
- elevated, and the attention more or less fixed, the action will always
- have more or less vigour and vivacity. When therefore any object is
- presented, which elevates and enlivens the thought, every action, to
- which the mind applies itself, will be more strong and vivid, as Tong
- as that disposition continues, Now it is evident the continuance of the
- disposition depends entirely on the objects, about which the mind is
- employed; and that any new object naturally gives a new direction to the
- spirits, and changes the disposition; as on the contrary, when the mind
- fixes constantly on the same object, or passes easily and insensibly
- along related objects, the disposition has a much longer duration.
- Hence it happens, that when the mind is once inlivened by a present
- impression, it proceeds to form a more lively idea of the related
- objects, by a natural transition of the disposition from the one to the
- other. The change of the objects is so easy, that the mind is scarce
- sensible of it, but applies itself to the conception of the related idea
- with all the force and vivacity it acquired from the present impression.
- If in considering the nature of relation, and that facility of
- transition, which is essential to it, we can satisfy ourselves
- concerning the reality of this phaenomenon, it is well: But I must
- confess I place my chief confidence in experience to prove so material
- a principle. We may, therefore, observe, as the first experiment to our
- present purpose, that upon the appearance of the picture of an absent
- friend, our idea of him is evidently inlivened by the resemblance, and
- that every passion, which that idea occasions, whether of joy or sorrow,
- acquires new force and vigour. In producing this effect there concur
- both a relation and a present impression. Where the picture bears him no
- resemblance, or at least was not intended for him, it never so much
- as conveys our thought to him: And where it is absent, as well as the
- person; though the mind may pass from the thought of the one to that of
- the other; it feels its idea to be rather weekend than inlivened by that
- transition. We take a pleasure in viewing the picture of a friend, when
- it is set before us; but when it is removed, rather choose to consider
- him directly, than by reflexion in an image, which is equally distinct
- and obscure.
- The ceremonies of the Roman Catholic religion may be considered
- as experiments of the same nature. The devotees of that strange
- superstition usually plead in excuse of the mummeries, with which they
- are upbraided, that they feel the good effect of those external motions,
- and postures, and actions, in enlivening their devotion, and quickening
- their fervour, which otherwise would decay away, if directed entirely to
- distant and immaterial objects. We shadow out the objects of our faith,
- say they, in sensible types and images, and render them more present to
- us by the immediate presence of these types, than it is possible for
- us to do, merely by an intellectual view and contemplation. Sensible
- objects have always a greater influence on the fancy than any other;
- and this influence they readily convey to those ideas, to which they
- are related, and which they Resemble. I shall only infer from these
- practices, and this reasoning, that the effect of resemblance in
- inlivening the idea is very common; and as in every case a resemblance
- and a present impression must concur, we are abundantly supplyed with
- experiments to prove the reality of the foregoing principle.
- We may add force to these experiments by others of a different kind, in
- considering the effects of contiguity, as well as of resemblance. It is
- certain, that distance diminishes the force of every idea, and that upon
- our approach to any object; though it does not discover itself to our
- senses; it operates upon the mind with an influence that imitates an
- immediate impression. The thinking on any object readily transports the
- mind to what is contiguous; but it is only the actual presence of an
- object, that transports it with a superior vivacity. When I am a few
- miles from home, whatever relates to it touches me more nearly than
- when I am two hundred leagues distant; though even at that distance the
- reflecting on any thing in the neighbourhood of my friends and family
- naturally produces an idea of them. But as in this latter case, both
- the objects of the mind are ideas; notwithstanding there is an easy
- transition betwixt them; that transition alone is not able to give
- a superior vivacity to any of the ideas, for want of some immediate
- impression. [Footnote 6.]
- [Footnote 6. NATURANE NOBIS, IN QUIT, DATUM DICAM, AN ERRORE
- QUODAM, UT, CUM EA LOCA VIDEAMUS, IN QUIBUS MEMORIA DIGNOS
- VIROS ACCEPERIMUS MULTURN ESSE VERSATOS, MAGIS MOVEAMUR,
- QUAM SIQUANDO EORUM IPSORUM AUT JACTA AUDIAMUS, AUT SCRIPTUM
- ALIQUOD LEGAMUS? VELUT EGO NUNC MOVEOR. VENIT ENIM MIHI
- PLATONIS IN MENTEM: QUEM ACCIPIMUS PRIMURN HIC DISPUTARE
- SOLITUM: CUJUS ETIAM ILLI HORTULI PROPINQUI NON MEMORIAM
- SOLUM MIHI AFFERUNT, SED IPSUM VIDENTUR IN CONSPECTU MEO HIC
- PONERE. HIC SPEUSIPPUS, HIC XENOCRATES, HIC EJUS AUDITOR
- POLEMO; CUJUS IPSA ILLA SESSIO FUIT, QUAM VIDEAMUS. EQUIDEM
- ETIAM CURIAM NOSTRAM, HOSTILIAM DICO, NON HANC NOVAM, QUAE
- MIHI MINOR ESSE VIDETUR POST QUAM EST MAJOR, SOLE BARN
- INTUENS SCIPIONEM, CATONEM, LACLIUM, NOSTRUM VERO IN PRIMIS
- AVUM COGITARE. TANTA VIS ADMONITIONIS INEST IN LOCIS; UT NON
- SINE CAUSA EX HIS MEMORIAE DUCTA SIT DISCIPLINA. Cicero de
- Finibus, lib. 5.
- {"Should I, he said, "attribute to instinct or to some kind
- of illusion the fact that when we see those places in which
- we are told notable men spent much of their time, we are
- more powerfully affected than when we hear of the exploits
- of the men themselves or read something written? This is
- just what is happening to me now; for I am reminded of Plato
- who, we are told, was the first to make a practice of
- holding discussions here. Those gardens of his near by do
- not merely put me in mind of him; they seem to set the man
- himself before my very eyes. Speusippus was here; so was
- Xenocrates; so was his pupil, Polemo, and that very seat
- which we may view was his.
- "Then again, when I looked at our Senate-house (I mean the
- old building of Hostilius, not this new one; when it was
- enlarged, it diminished in my estimation), I used to think
- of Scipio, Cato, Laelius and in particular of my own
- grandfather.
- "Such is the power of places to evoke associations; so it is
- with good reason that they are used as a basis for memory
- training."}]
- No one can doubt but causation has the same influence as the other two
- relations; of resemblance and contiguity. Superstitious people are fond
- of the relicks of saints and holy men, for the same reason that they
- seek after types and images, in order to enliven their devotion, and
- give them a more intimate and strong conception of those exemplary
- lives, which they desire to imitate. Now it is evident, one of the best
- relicks a devotee coued procure, would be the handywork of a saint; and
- if his cloaths and furniture are ever to be considered in this light, it
- is because they were once at his disposal, and were moved and affected
- by him; in which respect they are to be considered as imperfect effects,
- and as connected with him by a shorter chain of consequences than any
- of those, from which we learn the reality of his existence. This
- phaenomenon clearly proves, that a present impression with a relation
- of causation may, inliven any idea, and consequently produce belief or
- assent, according to the precedent definition of it.
- But why need we seek for other arguments to prove, that a present
- impression with a relation or transition of the fancy may inliven any
- idea, when this very instance of our reasonings from cause and effect
- will alone suffice to that purpose? It is certain we must have an idea
- of every matter of fact, which we believe. It is certain, that this idea
- arises only from a relation to a present impression. It is certain, that
- the belief super-adds nothing to the idea, but only changes our manner
- of conceiving it, and renders it more strong and lively. The present
- conclusion concerning the influence of relation is the immediate
- consequence of all these steps; and every step appears to me sure end
- infallible. There enters nothing into this operation of the mind but a
- present impression, a lively idea, and a relation or association in the
- fancy betwixt the impression and idea; so that there can be no suspicion
- of mistake.
- In order to put this whole affair in a fuller light, let us consider
- it as a question in natural philosophy, which we must determine by
- experience and observation. I suppose there is an object presented, from
- which I draw a certain conclusion, and form to myself ideas, which I
- am said to believe or assent to. Here it is evident, that however that
- object, which is present to my senses, and that other, whose existence
- I infer by reasoning, may be thought to influence each other by their
- particular powers or qualities; yet as the phenomenon of belief, which
- we at present examine, is merely internal, these powers and qualities,
- being entirely unknown, can have no hand in producing it. It is the
- present impression, which is to be considered as the true and real
- cause of the idea, and of the belief which attends it. We must therefore
- endeavour to discover by experiments the particular qualities, by which
- it is enabled to produce so extraordinary an effect.
- First then I observe, that the present impression has not this effect
- by its own proper power and efficacy, and when considered alone, as
- a single perception, limited to the present moment. I find, that
- an impression, from which, on its first appearance, I can draw no
- conclusion, may afterwards become the foundation of belief, when I have
- had experience of its usual consequences. We must in every case have
- observed the same impression in past instances, and have found it to be
- constantly conjoined with some other impression. This is confirmed by
- such a multitude of experiments, that it admits not of the smallest
- doubt.
- From a second observation I conclude, that the belief, which attends the
- present impression, and is produced by a number of past impressions and
- conjunctions; that this belief, I say, arises immediately, without any
- new operation of the reason or imagination. Of this I can be certain,
- because I never am conscious of any such operation, and find nothing
- in the subject, on which it can be founded. Now as we call every thing
- CUSTOM, which proceeds from a past repetition, without any new reasoning
- or conclusion, we-may establish it as a certain truth, that all the
- belief, which follows upon any present impression, is derived solely
- from that origin. When we are accustomed to see two impressions
- conjoined together, the appearance or idea of the one immediately
- carries us to the idea of the other.
- Being fully satisfyed on this head, I make a third set of experiments,
- in order to know, whether any thing be requisite, beside the customary
- transition, towards the production of this phaenomenon of belief. I
- therefore change the first impression into an idea; and observe, that
- though the customary transition to the correlative idea still remains,
- yet there is in reality no belief nor perswasion. A present impression,
- then, is absolutely requisite to this whole operation; and when after
- this I compare an impression with an idea, and find that their only
- difference consists in their different degrees of force and vivacity,
- I conclude upon the whole, that belief is a more vivid and intense
- conception of an idea, proceeding from its relation to a present
- impression.
- Thus all probable reasoning is nothing but a species of sensation. It is
- not solely in poetry and music, we must follow our taste and sentiment,
- but likewise in philosophy. When I am convinced of any principle, it
- is only an idea, which strikes more strongly upon me. When I give the
- preference to one set of arguments above another, I do nothing but
- decide from my feeling concerning the superiority of their influence.
- Objects have no discoverable connexion together; nor is it from any
- other principle but custom operating upon the imagination, that we
- can draw any inference from the appearance of one to the existence of
- another.
- It will here be worth our observation, that the past experience, on
- which all our judgments concerning cause and effect depend, may operate
- on our mind in such an insensible manner as never to be taken notice of,
- and may even in some measure be unknown to us. A person, who stops
- short in his journey upon meeting a river in his way, foresees the
- consequences of his proceeding forward; and his knowledge of these
- consequences is conveyed to him by past experience, which informs him of
- such certain conjunctions of causes and effects. But can we think,
- that on this occasion he reflects on any past experience, and calls
- to remembrance instances, that he has seen or heard of, in order to
- discover the effects of water on animal bodies? No surely; this is not
- the method, in which he proceeds in his reasoning. The idea of sinking
- is so closely connected with that of water, and the idea of suffocating
- with that of sinking, that the mind makes the transition without the
- assistance of the memory. The custom operates before we have time for
- reflection. The objects seem so inseparable, that we interpose not
- a moment's delay in passing from the one to the other. But as this
- transition proceeds from experience, and not from any primary connexion
- betwixt the ideas, we must necessarily acknowledge, that experience
- may produce a belief and a judgment of causes and effects by a secret
- operation, and without being once thought of. This removes all pretext,
- if there yet remains any, for asserting that the mind is convinced
- by reasoning of that principle, that instances of which we have no
- experience, must necessarily resemble those, of which we have. For we
- here find, that the understanding or imagination can draw inferences
- from past experience, without reflecting on it; much more without
- forming any principle concerning it, or reasoning upon that principle.
- In general we may observe, that in all the most established and uniform
- conjunctions of causes and effects, such as those of gravity, impulse,
- solidity, &c. the mind never carries its view expressly to consider any
- past experience: Though in other associations of objects, which are more
- rare and unusual, it may assist the custom and transition of ideas by
- this reflection. Nay we find in some cases, that the reflection produces
- the belief without the custom; or more properly speaking, that the
- reflection produces the custom in an oblique and artificial manner. I
- explain myself. It is certain, that not only in philosophy, but even in
- common life, we may attain the knowledge of a particular cause merely by
- one experiment, provided it be made with judgment, and after a careful
- removal of all foreign and superfluous circumstances. Now as after one
- experiment of this kind, the mind, upon the appearance either of the
- cause or the effect, can draw an inference concerning the existence
- of its correlative; and as a habit can never be acquired merely by one
- instance; it may be thought, that belief cannot in this case be esteemed
- the effect of custom. But this difficulty will vanish, if we consider,
- that though we are here supposed to have had only one experiment of
- a particular effect, yet we have many millions to convince us of this
- principle; that like objects placed in like circumstances, will always
- produce like effects; and as this principle has established itself by a
- sufficient custom, it bestows an evidence and firmness on any opinion,
- to which it can be applied. The connexion of the ideas is not habitual
- after one experiment: but this connexion is comprehended under another
- principle, that is habitual; which brings us back to our hypothesis. In
- all cases we transfer our experience to instances, of which we have no
- experience, either expressly or tacitly, either directly or indirectly.
- I must not conclude this subject without observing, that it is very
- difficult to talk of the operations of the mind with perfect propriety
- and exactness; because common language has seldom made any very nice
- distinctions among them, but has generally called by the same term
- all such as nearly resemble each other. And as this is a source
- almost inevitable of obscurity and confusion in the author; so it may
- frequently give rise to doubts and objections in the reader, which
- otherwise he would never have dreamed of. Thus my general position, that
- an opinion or belief is nothing but a strong and lively idea derived
- from a present impression related to it, maybe liable to the following
- objection, by reason of a little ambiguity in those words strong and
- lively. It may be said, that not only an impression may give rise to
- reasoning, but that an idea may also have the same influence; especially
- upon my principle, that all our ideas are derived from correspondent
- impressions. For suppose I form at present an idea, of which I have
- forgot the correspondent impression, I am able to conclude from this
- idea, that such an impression did once exist; and as this conclusion is
- attended with belief, it may be asked, from whence are the qualities of
- force and vivacity derived, which constitute this belief? And to this I
- answer very readily, from the present idea. For as this idea is not here
- considered, as the representation of any absent object, but as a real
- perception in the mind, of which we are intimately conscious, it must
- be able to bestow on whatever is related to it the same quality, call
- it firmness, or solidity, or force, or vivacity, with which the mind
- reflects upon it, and is assured of its present existence. The idea here
- supplies the place of an impression, and is entirely the same, so far as
- regards our present purpose.
- Upon the same principles we need not be surprized to hear of the
- remembrance of an idea: that is, of the idea of an idea, and of its
- force and vivacity superior to the loose conceptions of the imagination.
- In thinking of our past thoughts we not only delineate out the objects,
- of which we were thinking, but also conceive the action of the mind in
- the meditation, that certain JE-NE-SCAI-QUOI, of which it is impossible
- to give any definition or description, but which every one sufficiently
- understands. When the memory offers an idea of this, and represents it
- as past, it is easily conceived how that idea may have more vigour and
- firmness, than when we think of a past thought, of which we have no
- remembrance.
- After this any one will understand how we may form the idea of an
- impression and of an idea, and how we way believe the existence of an
- impression and of an idea.
- SECT. IX. OF THE EFFECTS OF OTHER RELATIONS AND OTHER HABITS.
- However convincing the foregoing arguments may appear, we must not rest
- contented with them, but must turn the subject on every side, in order
- to find some new points of view, from which we may illustrate and
- confirm such extraordinary, and such fundamental principles. A
- scrupulous hesitation to receive any new hypothesis is so laudable a
- disposition in philosophers, and so necessary to the examination of
- truth, that it deserves to be complyed with, and requires that every
- argument be produced, which may tend to their satisfaction, and every
- objection removed, which may stop them in their reasoning.
- I have often observed, that, beside cause and effect, the two relations
- of resemblance and contiguity, are to be considered as associating
- principles of thought, and as capable of conveying the imagination from
- one idea to another. I have also observed, that when of two objects
- connected to-ether by any of these relations, one is immediately
- present to the memory or senses, not only the mind is conveyed to
- its co-relative by means of the associating principle; but likewise
- conceives it with an additional force and vigour, by the united
- operation of that principle, and of the present impression. All this
- I have observed, in order to confirm by analogy, my explication of
- our judgments concerning cause and effect. But this very argument may,
- perhaps, be turned against me, and instead of a confirmation of my
- hypothesis, may become an objection to it. For it may be said, that if
- all the parts of that hypothesis be true, viz. that these three species
- of relation are derived from the same principles; that their effects
- in informing and enlivening our ideas are the same; and that belief is
- nothing but a more forcible and vivid conception of an idea; it should
- follow, that that action of the mind may not only be derived from the
- relation of cause and effect, but also from those of contiguity and
- resemblance. But as we find by experience, that belief arises only from
- causation, and that we can draw no inference from one object to another,
- except they be connected by this relation, we may conclude, that there
- is some error in that reasoning, which leads us into such difficulties.
- This is the objection; let us now consider its solution. It is evident,
- that whatever is present to the memory, striking upon the mind with
- a vivacity, which resembles an immediate impression, must become of
- considerable moment in all the operations of the mind, and must easily
- distinguish itself above the mere fictions of the imagination. Of
- these impressions or ideas of the memory we form a kind of system,
- comprehending whatever we remember to have been present, either to our
- internal perception or senses; and every particular of that system,
- joined to the present impressions, we are pleased to call a reality.
- But the mind stops not here. For finding, that with this system of
- perceptions, there is another connected by custom, or if you will, by
- the relation of cause or effect, it proceeds to the consideration
- of their ideas; and as it feels that it is in a manner necessarily
- determined to view these particular ideas, and that the custom or
- relation, by which it is determined, admits not of the least change, it
- forms them into a new system, which it likewise dignifies with the title
- of realities. The first of these systems is the object of the memory and
- senses; the second of the judgment.
- It is this latter principle, which peoples the world, and brings us
- acquainted with such existences, as by their removal in time and place,
- lie beyond the reach of the senses and memory. By means of it I paint
- the universe in my imagination, and fix my attention on any part of it
- I please. I form an idea of ROME, which I neither see nor remember; but
- which is connected with such impressions as I remember to have received
- from the conversation and books of travellers and historians. This idea
- of Rome I place in a certain situation on the idea of an object, which I
- call the globe. I join to it the conception of a particular government,
- and religion, and manners. I look backward and consider its first
- foundation; its several revolutions, successes, and misfortunes. All
- this, and everything else, which I believe, are nothing but ideas;
- though by their force and settled order, arising from custom and the
- relation of cause and effect, they distinguish themselves from the other
- ideas, which are merely the offspring of the imagination.
- As to the influence of contiguity and resemblance, we may observe, that
- if the contiguous and resembling object be comprehended in this system
- of realities, there is no doubt but these two relations will assist that
- of cause and effect, and infix the related idea with more force in the
- imagination. This I shall enlarge upon presently. Mean while I shall
- carry my observation a step farther, and assert, that even where the
- related object is but feigned, the relation will serve to enliven the
- idea, and encrease its influence. A poet, no doubt, will be the better
- able to form a strong description of the Elysian fields, that he prompts
- his imagination by the view of a beautiful meadow or garden; as at
- another time he may by his fancy place himself in the midst of these
- fabulous regions, that by the feigned contiguity he may enliven his
- imagination.
- But though I cannot altogether exclude the relations of resemblance and
- contiguity from operating on the fancy in this manner, it is observable
- that, when single, their influence is very feeble and uncertain. As the
- relation of cause and effect is requisite to persuade us of any real
- existence, so is this persuasion requisite to give force to these other
- relations. For where upon the appearance of an impression we not
- only feign another object, but likewise arbitrarily, and of our mere
- good-will and pleasure give it a particular relation to the impression,
- this can have but a small effect upon the mind; nor is there any reason,
- why, upon the return of the same impression, we should be determined to
- place the same object in the same relation to it. There is no manner of
- necessity for the mind to feign any resembling and contiguous objects;
- and if it feigns such, there is as little necessity for it always to
- confine itself to the same, without any difference or variation. And
- indeed such a fiction is founded on so little reason, that nothing but
- pure caprice can determine the mind to form it; and that principle being
- fluctuating and uncertain, it is impossible it can ever operate with
- any considerable degree of force and constancy. The mind forsees and
- anticipates the change; and even from the very first instant feels the
- looseness of its actions, and the weak hold it has of its objects. And
- as this imperfection is very sensible in every single instance, it still
- encreases by experience and observation, when we compare the several
- instances we may remember, and form a general rule against the reposing
- any assurance in those momentary glimpses of light, which arise in the
- imagination from a feigned resemblance and contiguity.
- The relation of cause and effect has all the opposite advantages. The
- objects it presents are fixt and unalterable. The impressions of the
- memory never change in any considerable degree; and each impression
- draws along with it a precise idea, which takes its place in the
- imagination as something solid and real, certain and invariable. The
- thought is always determined to pass from the impression to the idea,
- and from that particular impression to that particular idea, without any
- choice or hesitation.
- But not content with removing this objection, I shall endeavour
- to extract from it a proof of the present doctrine. Contiguity and
- resemblance have an effect much inferior to causation; but still have
- some effect, and augment the conviction of any opinion, and the vivacity
- of any conception. If this can be proved in several new instances,
- beside what we have already observed, it will be allowed no
- inconsiderable argument, that belief is nothing but a lively idea
- related to a present impression.
- To begin with contiguity; it has been remarked among the Mahometans as
- well as Christians, that those pilgrims, who have seen MECCA or the HOLY
- LAND, are ever after more faithful and zealous believers, than those
- who have not had that advantage. A man, whose memory presents him with a
- lively image of the Red-Sea, and the Desert, and Jerusalem, and Galilee,
- can never doubt of any miraculous events, which are related either by
- Moses or the Evangelists. The lively idea of the places passes by an
- easy transition to the facts, which are supposed to have been related to
- them by contiguity, and encreases the belief by encreasing the vivacity
- of the conception. The remembrance of these fields and rivers has
- the same influence on the vulgar as a new argument; and from the same
- causes.
- We may form a like observation concerning resemblance. We have remarked,
- that the conclusion, which we draw from a present object to its absent
- cause or effect, is never founded on any qualities, which we observe
- in that object, considered in itself, or, in other words, that it is
- impossible to determine, otherwise than by experience, what will result
- from any phenomenon, or what has preceded it. But though this be so
- evident in itself, that it seemed not to require any, proof; yet some
- philosophers have imagined that there is an apparent cause for the
- communication of motion, and that a reasonable man might immediately
- infer the motion of one body from the impulse of another, without having
- recourse to any past observation. That this opinion is false will admit
- of an easy proof. For if such an inference may be drawn merely from
- the ideas of body, of motion, and of impulse, it must amount to a
- demonstration, and must imply the absolute impossibility of any contrary
- supposition. Every effect, then, beside the communication of motion,
- implies a formal contradiction; and it is impossible not only that it
- can exist, but also that it can be conceived. But we may soon satisfy
- ourselves of the contrary, by forming a clear and consistent idea of
- one body's moving upon another, and of its rest immediately upon the
- contact, or of its returning back in the same line in which it came; or
- of its annihilation; or circular or elliptical motion: and in short, of
- an infinite number of other changes, which we may suppose it to undergo.
- These suppositions are all consistent and natural; and the reason, Why
- we imagine the communication of motion to be more consistent and natural
- not only than those suppositions, but also than any other natural
- effect, is founded on the relation of resemblance betwixt the cause and
- effect, which is here united to experience, and binds the objects in the
- closest and most intimate manner to each other, so as to make us imagine
- them to be absolutely inseparable. Resemblance, then, has the same or a
- parallel influence with experience; and as the only immediate effect
- of experience is to associate our ideas together, it follows, that all
- belief arises from the association of ideas, according to my hypothesis.
- It is universally allowed by the writers on optics, that the eye at all
- times sees an equal number of physical points, and that a man on the top
- of a mountain has no larger an image presented to his senses, than
- when he is cooped up in the narrowest court or chamber. It is only by
- experience that he infers the greatness of the object from some peculiar
- qualities of the image; and this inference of the judgment he confounds
- with sensation, as is common on other occasions. Now it is evident,
- that the inference of the judgment is here much more lively than what
- is usual in our common reasonings, and that a man has a more vivid
- conception of the vast extent of the ocean from the image he receives by
- the eye, when he stands on the top of the high promontory, than merely
- from hearing the roaring of the waters. He feels a more sensible
- pleasure from its magnificence; which is a proof of a more lively idea:
- And he confounds his judgment with sensation, which is another proof of
- it. But as the inference is equally certain and immediate in both cases,
- this superior vivacity of our conception in one case can proceed from
- nothing but this, that in drawing an inference from the sight, beside
- the customary conjunction, there is also a resemblance betwixt the image
- and the object we infer; which strengthens the relation, and conveys the
- vivacity of the impression to the related idea with an easier and more
- natural movement.
- No weakness of human nature is more universal and conspicuous than what
- we commonly call CREDULITY, or a too easy faith in the testimony of
- others; and this weakness is also very naturally accounted for from the
- influence of resemblance. When we receive any matter of fact upon human
- testimony, our faith arises from the very same origin as our inferences
- from causes to effects, and from effects to causes; nor is there
- anything but our experience of the governing principles of human nature,
- which can give us any assurance of the veracity of men. But though
- experience be the true standard of this, as well as of all other
- judgments, we seldom regulate ourselves entirely by it; but have a
- remarkable propensity to believe whatever is reported, even concerning
- apparitions, enchantments, and prodigies, however contrary to daily
- experience and observation. The words or discourses of others have an
- intimate connexion with certain ideas in their mind; and these ideas
- have also a connexion with the facts or objects, which they represent.
- This latter connexion is generally much over-rated, and commands our
- assent beyond what experience will justify; which can proceed from
- nothing beside the resemblance betwixt the ideas and the facts. Other
- effects only point out their causes in an oblique manner; but the
- testimony of men does it directly, and is to be considered as an image
- as well as an effect. No wonder, therefore, we are so rash in drawing
- our inferences from it, and are less guided by experience in our
- judgments concerning it, than in those upon any other subject.
- As resemblance, when conjoined with causation, fortifies our reasonings;
- so the want of it in any very great degree is able almost entirely to
- destroy them. Of this there is a remarkable instance in the universal
- carelessness and stupidity of men with regard to a future state, where
- they show as obstinate an incredulity, as they do a blind credulity on
- other occasions. There is not indeed a more ample matter of wonder
- to the studious, and of regret to the pious man, than to observe
- the negligence of the bulk of mankind concerning their approaching
- condition; and it is with reason, that many eminent theologians have not
- scrupled to affirm, that though the vulgar have no formal principles
- of infidelity, yet they are really infidels in their hearts, and have
- nothing like what we can call a belief of the eternal duration of their
- souls. For let us consider on the one hand what divines have displayed
- with such eloquence concerning the importance of eternity; and at the
- same time reflect, that though in matters of rhetoric we ought to lay
- our account with some exaggeration, we must in this case allow, that the
- strongest figures are infinitely inferior to the subject: And after this
- let us view on the other hand, the prodigious security of men in this
- particular: I ask, if these people really believe what is inculcated on
- them, and what they pretend to affirm; and the answer is obviously in
- the negative. As belief is an act of the mind arising from custom, it
- is not strange the want of resemblance should overthrow what custom has
- established, and diminish the force of the idea, as much as that latter
- principle encreases it. A future state is so far removed from our
- comprehension, and we have so obscure an idea of the manner, in which we
- shall exist after the dissolution of the body, that all the reasons we
- can invent, however strong in themselves, and however much assisted
- by education, are never able with slow imaginations to surmount this
- difficulty, or bestow a sufficient authority and force on the idea. I
- rather choose to ascribe this incredulity to the faint idea we form
- of our future condition, derived from its want of resemblance to the
- present life, than to that derived from its remoteness. For I observe,
- that men are everywhere concerned about what may happen after their
- death, provided it regard this world; and that there are few to whom
- their name, their family, their friends, and their country are in any
- period of time entirely indifferent.
- And indeed the want of resemblance in this case so entirely destroys
- belief, that except those few, who upon cool reflection on the
- importance of the subject, have taken care by repeated meditation to
- imprint in their minds the arguments for a future state, there scarce
- are any, who believe the immortality of the soul with a true and
- established judgment; such as is derived from the testimony of
- travellers and historians. This appears very conspicuously wherever
- men have occasion to compare the pleasures and pains, the rewards and
- punishments of this life with those of a future; even though the case
- does not concern themselves, and there is no violent passion to disturb
- their judgment. The Roman Clatholicks are certainly the most zealous of
- any sect in the Christian world; and yet you'll find few among the
- more sensible people of that communion who do not blame the
- Gunpowder-treason, and the massacre of St. Bartholomew, as cruel and
- barbarous, though projected or executed against those very people, whom
- without any scruple they condemn to eternal and infinite punishments.
- All we can say in excuse for this inconsistency is, that they really do
- not believe what they affirm concerning a future state; nor is there any
- better proof of it than the very inconsistency.
- We may add to this a remark; that in matters of religion men take a
- pleasure in being terrifyed, and that no preachers are so popular, as
- those who excite the most dismal and gloomy passions. In the common
- affairs of life, where we feel and are penetrated with the solidity of
- the subject, nothing can be more disagreeable than fear and terror; and
- it is only in dramatic performances and in religious discourses, that
- they ever give pleasure. In these latter cases the imagination reposes
- itself indolently on the idea; and the passion, being softened by the
- want of belief in the subject, has no more than the agreeable effect of
- enlivening the mind, and fixing the attention.
- The present hypothesis will receive additional confirmation, if we
- examine the effects of other kinds of custom, as well as of other
- relations. To understand this we must consider, that custom, to which
- I attribute all belief and reasoning, may operate upon the mind in
- invigorating an idea after two several ways. For supposing that in all
- past experience we have found two objects to have been always conjoined
- together, it is evident, that upon the appearance of one of these
- objects in an impression, we must from custom make an easy transition to
- the idea of that object, which usually attends it; and by means of the
- present impression and easy transition must conceive that idea in a
- stronger and more lively manner, than we do any loose floating image of
- the fancy. But let us next suppose, that a mere idea alone, without any
- of this curious and almost artificial preparation, should frequently
- make its appearance in the mind, this idea must by degrees acquire a
- facility and force; and both by its firm hold and easy introduction
- distinguish itself from any new and unusual idea. This is the only
- particular, in which these two kinds of custom agree; and if it appear,
- that their effects on the judgment, are similar and proportionable, we
- may certainly conclude, that the foregoing explication of that faculty
- is satisfactory. But can we doubt of this agreement in their influence
- on the judgment, when we consider the nature and effects Of EDUCATION?
- All those opinions and notions of things, to which we have been
- accustomed from our infancy, take such deep root, that it is impossible
- for us, by all the powers of reason and experience, to eradicate them;
- and this habit not only approaches in its influence, but even on
- many occasions prevails over that which a-rises from the constant and
- inseparable union of causes and effects. Here we most not be contented
- with saying, that the vividness of the idea produces the belief: We must
- maintain that they are individually the same. The frequent repetition
- of any idea infixes it in the imagination; but coued never possibly
- of itself produce belief, if that act of the mind was, by the original
- constitution of our natures, annexed only to a reasoning and comparison
- of ideas. Custom may lead us into some false comparison of ideas. This
- is the utmost effect we can conceive of it. But it is certain it coued
- never supply the place of that comparison, nor produce any act of the
- mind, which naturally belonged to that principle.
- A person, that has lost a leg or an arm by amputation, endeavours for a
- long time afterwards to serve himself with them. After the death of any
- one, it is a common remark of the whole family, but especially of the
- servants, that they can scarce believe him to be dead, but still
- imagine him to be in his chamber or in any other place, where they
- were accustomed to find him. I have often heard in conversation, after
- talking of a person, that is any way celebrated, that one, who has
- no acquaintance with him, will say, I have never seen such-a-one, but
- almost fancy I have; so often have I heard talk of him. All these are
- parallel instances.
- If we consider this argument from EDUCATION in a proper light, it will
- appear very convincing; and the more so, that it is founded on one
- of the most common phaenomena, that is any where to be met with. I am
- persuaded, that upon examination we shall find more than one half of
- those opinions, that prevail among mankind, to be owing to education,
- and that the principles, which are thus implicitely embraced,
- overballance those, which are owing either to abstract reasoning or
- experience. As liars, by the frequent repetition of their lies, come at
- last to remember them; so the judgment, or rather the imagination, by
- the like means, may have ideas so strongly imprinted on it, and conceive
- them in so full a light, that they may operate upon the mind in the same
- manner with those, which the senses, memory or reason present to us. But
- as education is an artificial and not a natural cause, and as its maxims
- are frequently contrary to reason, and even to themselves in different
- times and places, it is never upon that account recognized by
- philosophers; though in reality it be built almost on the same
- foundation of custom and repetition as our reasonings from causes and
- effects.
- [Footnote 7. In general we may observe, that as our assent
- to all probable reasonings is founded on the vivacity of
- ideas, It resembles many of those whimsies and prejudices,
- which are rejected under the opprobrious character of being
- the offspring of the imagination. By this expression it
- appears that the word, imagination, is commonly usd in two
- different senses; and tho nothing be more contrary to true
- philosophy, than this inaccuracy, yet in the following
- reasonings I have often been obligd to fall into it. When I
- oppose the Imagination to the memory, I mean the faculty, by
- which we form our fainter ideas. When I oppose it to reason,
- I mean the same faculty, excluding only our demonstrative
- and probable reasonings. When I oppose it to neither, it is
- indifferent whether it be taken in the larger or more
- limited sense, or at least the context will sufficiently
- explain the meaning.]
- SECT. X. OF THE INFLUENCE OF BELIEF.
- But though education be disclaimed by philosophy, as a fallacious ground
- of assent to any opinion, it prevails nevertheless in the world, and
- is the cause why all systems are apt to be rejected at first as new
- and unusual. This perhaps will be the fate of what I have here advanced
- concerning belief, and though the proofs I have produced appear to
- me perfectly conclusive, I expect not to make many proselytes to
- my opinion. Men will scarce ever be persuaded, that effects of
- such consequence can flow from principles, which are seemingly so
- inconsiderable, and that the far greatest part of our reasonings with
- all our actions and passions, can be derived from nothing but custom and
- habit. To obviate this objection, I shall here anticipate a little what
- would more properly fall under our consideration afterwards, when we
- come to treat of the passions and the sense of beauty.
- There is implanted in the human mind a perception of pain and pleasure,
- as the chief spring and moving principle of all its actions. But pain
- and pleasure have two ways of making their appearance in the mind; of
- which the one has effects very different from the other. They may either
- appear in impression to the actual feeling, or only in idea, as at
- present when I mention them. It is evident the influence of these upon
- our actions is far from being equal. Impressions always actuate the
- soul, and that in the highest degree; but it is not every idea which
- has the same effect. Nature has proceeded with caution in this came, and
- seems to have carefully avoided the inconveniences of two extremes.
- Did impressions alone influence the will, we should every moment of our
- lives be subject to the greatest calamities; because, though we foresaw
- their approach, we should not be provided by nature with any principle
- of action, which might impel us to avoid them. On the other hand,
- did every idea influence our actions, our condition would not be much
- mended. For such is the unsteadiness and activity of thought, that
- the images of every thing, especially of goods and evils, are always
- wandering in the mind; and were it moved by every idle conception of
- this kind, it would never enjoy a moment's peace and tranquillity.
- Nature has, therefore, chosen a medium, and has neither bestowed on
- every idea of good and evil the power of actuating the will, nor yet has
- entirely excluded them from this influence. Though an idle fiction has
- no efficacy, yet we find by experience, that the ideas of those objects,
- which we believe either are or will be existent, produce in a lesser
- degree the same effect with those impressions, which are immediately
- present to the senses and perception. The effect, then, of belief is to
- raise up a simple idea to an equality with our impressions, and bestow
- on it a like influence on the passions. This effect it can only have by
- making an idea approach an impression in force and vivacity. For as the
- different degrees of force make all the original difference betwixt an
- impression and an idea, they must of consequence be the source of all
- the differences in the effects of these perceptions, and their removal,
- in whole or in part, the cause of every new resemblance they acquire.
- Wherever we can make an idea approach the impressions in force and
- vivacity, it will likewise imitate them in its influence on the mind;
- and vice versa, where it imitates them in that influence, as in the
- present case, this must proceed from its approaching them in force and
- vivacity. Belief, therefore, since it causes an idea to imitate
- the effects of the impressions, must make it resemble them in these
- qualities, and is nothing but A MORE VIVID AND INTENSE CONCEPTION OF
- ANY IDEA. This, then, may both serve as an additional argument for
- the present system, and may give us a notion after what manner our
- reasonings from causation are able to operate on the will and passions.
- As belief is almost absolutely requisite to the exciting our passions,
- so the passions in their turn are very favourable to belief; and not
- only such facts as convey agreeable emotions, but very often such as
- give pain, do upon that account become more readily the objects of faith
- and opinion. A coward, whose fears are easily awakened, readily assents
- to every account of danger he meets with; as a person of a sorrowful and
- melancholy disposition is very credulous of every thing, that nourishes
- his prevailing passion. When any affecting object is presented, it
- gives the alarm, and excites immediately a degree of its proper passion;
- especially in persons who are naturally inclined to that passion. This
- emotion passes by an easy transition to the imagination; and diffusing
- itself over our idea of the affecting object, makes us form that
- idea with greater force and vivacity, and consequently assent to it,
- according to the precedent system. Admiration and surprize have the same
- effect as the other passions; and accordingly we may observe, that
- among the vulgar, quacks and projectors meet with a more easy faith upon
- account of their magnificent pretensions, than if they kept themselves
- within the bounds of moderation. The first astonishment, which naturally
- attends their miraculous relations, spreads itself over the whole soul,
- and so vivifies and enlivens the idea, that it resembles the inferences
- we draw from experience. This is a mystery, with which we may be already
- a little acquainted, and which we shall have farther occasion to be let
- into in the progress of this treatise.
- After this account of the influence of belief on the passions, we shall
- find less difficulty in explaining its effects on the imagination,
- however extraordinary they may appear. It is certain we cannot take
- pleasure in any discourse, where our judgment gives no assent to those
- images which are presented to our fancy. The conversation of those who
- have acquired a habit of lying, though in affairs of no moment, never
- gives any satisfaction; and that because those ideas they present to us,
- not being attended with belief, make no impression upon the mind. Poets
- themselves, though liars by profession, always endeavour to give an air
- of truth to their fictions; and where that is totally neglected, their
- performances, however ingenious, will never be able to afford much
- pleasure. In short, we may observe, that even when ideas have no manner
- of influence on the will and passions, truth and reality are still
- requisite, in order to make them entertaining to the imagination.
- But if we compare together all the phenomena that occur on this head,
- we shall find, that truth, however necessary it may seem in all works
- of genius, has no other effect than to procure an easy reception for the
- ideas, and to make the mind acquiesce in them with satisfaction, or at
- least without reluctance. But as this is an effect, which may easily be
- supposed to flow from that solidity and force, which, according to
- my system, attend those ideas that are established by reasonings from
- causation; it follows, that all the influence of belief upon the fancy
- may be explained from that system. Accordingly we may observe, that
- wherever that influence arises from any other principles beside truth or
- reality, they supply its place, and give an equal entertainment to
- the imagination. Poets have formed what they call a poetical system of
- things, which though it be believed neither by themselves nor readers,
- is commonly esteemed a sufficient foundation for any fiction. We have
- been so much accustomed to the names of MARS, JUPITER, VENUS, that
- in the same manner as education infixes any opinion, the constant
- repetition of these ideas makes them enter into the mind with facility,
- and prevail upon the fancy, without influencing the judgment. In like
- manner tragedians always borrow their fable, or at least the names of
- their principal actors, from some known passage in history; and that not
- in order to deceive the spectators; for they will frankly confess, that
- truth is not in any circumstance inviolably observed: but in order
- to procure a more easy reception into the imagination for those
- extraordinary events, which they represent. But this is a precaution,
- which is not required of comic poets, whose personages and incidents,
- being of a more familiar kind, enter easily into the conception, and are
- received without any such formality, even though at first night they be
- known to be fictitious, and the pure offspring of the fancy.
- This mixture of truth and falshood in the fables of tragic poets not
- only serves our present purpose, by shewing, that the imagination can be
- satisfyed without any absolute belief or assurance; but may in another
- view be regarded as a very strong confirmation of this system. It is
- evident, that poets make use of this artifice of borrowing the names
- of their persons, and the chief events of their poems, from history, in
- order to procure a more easy reception for the whole, and cause it
- to make a deeper impression on the fancy and affections. The several
- incidents of the piece acquire a kind of relation by being united into
- one poem or representation; and if any of these incidents be an object
- of belief, it bestows a force and vivacity on the others, which are
- related to it. The vividness of the first conception diffuses itself
- along the relations, and is conveyed, as by so many pipes or canals,
- to every idea that has any communication with the primary one. This,
- indeed, can never amount to a perfect assurance; and that because
- the union among the ideas is, in a manner, accidental: But still it
- approaches so near, in its influence, as may convince us, that they
- are derived from the same origin. Belief must please the imagination
- by means of the force and vivacity which attends it; since every idea,
- which has force and vivacity, is found to be agreeable to that faculty.
- To confirm this we may observe, that the assistance is mutual betwixt
- the judgment and fancy, as well as betwixt the judgment and passion;
- and that belief not only gives vigour to the imagination, but that a
- vigorous and strong imagination is of all talents the most proper to
- procure belief and authority. It is difficult for us to withhold our
- assent from what is painted out to us in all the colours of eloquence;
- and the vivacity produced by the fancy is in many cases greater than
- that which arises from custom and experience. We are hurried away by the
- lively imagination of our author or companion; and even he himself is
- often a victim to his own fire and genius.
- Nor will it be amiss to remark, that as a lively imagination very often
- degenerates into madness or folly, and bears it a great resemblance in
- its operations; so they influence the judgment after the same manner,
- and produce belief from the very same principles. When the imagination,
- from any extraordinary ferment of the blood and spirits, acquires such a
- vivacity as disorders all its powers and faculties, there is no means
- of distinguishing betwixt truth and falshood; but every loose fiction or
- idea, having the same influence as the impressions of the memory, or
- the conclusions of the judgment, is received on the same footing, and
- operates with equal force on the passions. A present impression and a
- customary transition are now no longer necessary to enliven our ideas.
- Every chimera of the brain is as vivid and intense as any of those
- inferences, which we formerly dignifyed with the name of conclusions
- concerning matters of fact, and sometimes as the present impressions of
- the senses.
- We may observe the same effect of poetry in a lesser degree; and this is
- common both to poetry and madness, that the vivacity they bestow on the
- ideas is not derived from the particular situations or connexions of the
- objects of these ideas, but from the present temper and disposition
- of the person. But how great soever the pitch may be, to which this
- vivacity rises, it is evident, that in poetry it never has the same
- feeling with that which arises in the mind, when we reason, though even
- upon the lowest species of probability. The mind can easily distinguish
- betwixt the one and the other; and whatever emotion the poetical
- enthusiasm may give to the spirits, it is still the mere phantom of
- belief or persuasion. The case is the same with the idea, as with the
- passion it occasions. There is no passion of the human mind but what may
- arise from poetry; though at the same time the feelings of the passions
- are very different when excited by poetical fictions, from what they are
- when they are from belief and reality. A passion, which is disagreeable
- in real life, may afford the highest entertainment in a tragedy, or epic
- poem. In the latter case, it lies not with that weight upon us: It
- feels less firm and solid: And has no other than the agreeable effect of
- exciting the spirits, and rouzing the attention. The difference in the
- passions is a clear proof of a like difference in those ideas, from
- which the passions are derived. Where the vivacity arises from a
- customary conjunction with a present impression; though the imagination
- may not, in appearance, be so much moved; yet there is always something
- more forcible and real in its actions, than in the fervors of poetry and
- eloquence. The force of our mental actions in this case, no more than in
- any other, is not to be measured by the apparent agitation of the mind.
- A poetical description may have a more sensible effect on the
- fancy, than an historical narration. It may collect more of those
- circumstances, that form a compleat image or picture. It may seem to
- set the object before us in more lively colours. But still the ideas it
- presents are different to the feeling from those, which arise from the
- memory and the judgment. There is something weak and imperfect amidst
- all that seeming vehemence of thought and sentiment, which attends the
- fictions of poetry.
- We shall afterwards have occasion to remark both the resemblance and
- differences betwixt a poetical enthusiasm, and a serious conviction. In
- the mean time I cannot forbear observing, that the great difference
- in their feeling proceeds in some measure from reflection and GENERAL
- RULES. We observe, that the vigour of conception, which fictions receive
- from poetry and eloquence, is a circumstance merely accidental, of which
- every idea is equally susceptible; and that such fictions are connected
- with nothing that is real. This observation makes us only lend
- ourselves, so to speak, to the fiction: But causes the idea to feel very
- different from the eternal established persuasions founded on memory and
- custom. They are somewhat of the same kind: But the one is much inferior
- to the other, both in its causes and effects.
- A like reflection on general rules keeps us from augmenting our belief
- upon every encrease of the force and vivacity of our ideas. Where an
- opinion admits of no doubt, or opposite probability, we attribute to it
- a full conviction: though the want of resemblance, or contiguity, may
- render its force inferior to that of other opinions. It is thus the
- understanding corrects the appearances of the senses, and makes us
- imagine, that an object at twenty foot distance seems even to the eye as
- large as one of the same dimensions at ten.
- We may observe the same effect of poetry in a lesser degree; only with
- this difference, that the least reflection dissipates the illusions
- of poetry, and Places the objects in their proper light. It is however
- certain, that in the warmth of a poetical enthusiasm, a poet has a
- counterfeit belief, and even a kind of vision of his objects: And
- if there be any shadow of argument to support this belief, nothing
- contributes more to his full conviction than a blaze of poetical figures
- and images, which have their effect upon the poet himself, as well as
- upon his readers.
- SECT. XI. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CHANCES.
- But in order to bestow on this system its full force and evidence, we
- must carry our eye from it a moment to consider its consequences, and
- explain from the same principles some other species of reasoning, which
- are derived from the same origin.
- Those philosophers, who have divided human reason into knowledge and
- probability, and have defined the first to be that evidence, which
- arises from the comparison of ideas, are obliged to comprehend all our
- arguments from causes or effects under the general term of probability.
- But though every one be free to use his terms in what sense he pleases;
- and accordingly in the precedent part of this discourse, I have followed
- this method of expression; it is however certain, that in common
- discourse we readily affirm, that many arguments from causation exceed
- probability, and may be received as a superior kind of evidence. One
- would appear ridiculous, who would say, that it is only probable the
- sun will rise to-morrow, or that all men must dye; though it is plain we
- have no further assurance of these facts, than what experience affords
- us. For this reason, it would perhaps be more convenient, in order at
- once to preserve the common signification of words, and mark the several
- degrees of evidence, to distinguish human reason into three kinds, viz.
- THAT FROM KNOWLEDGE, FROM PROOFS, AND FROM PROBABILITIES. By knowledge,
- I mean the assurance arising from the comparison of ideas. By proofs,
- those arguments, which are derived from the relation of cause and
- effect, and which are entirely free from doubt and uncertainty. By
- probability, that evidence, which is still attended with uncertainty. It
- is this last species of reasoning, I proceed to examine.
- Probability or reasoning from conjecture may be divided into two kinds,
- viz. that which is founded on chance, and that which arises from causes.
- We shall consider each of these in order.
- The idea of cause and effect is derived from experience, which
- presenting us with certain objects constantly conjoined with each other,
- produces such a habit of surveying them in that relation, that we cannot
- without a sensible violence survey them iii any other. On the other
- hand, as chance is nothing real in itself, and, properly speaking, is
- merely the negation of a cause, its influence on the mind is contrary to
- that of causation; and it is essential to it, to leave the imagination
- perfectly indifferent, either to consider the existence or non-existence
- of that object, which is regarded as contingent. A cause traces the
- way to our thought, and in a manner forces us to survey such certain
- objects, in such certain relations. Chance can only destroy this
- determination of the thought, and leave the mind in its native situation
- of indifference; in which, upon the absence of a cause, it is instantly
- re-instated.
- Since therefore an entire indifference is essential to chance, no one
- chance can possibly be superior to another, otherwise than as it is
- composed of a superior number of equal chances. For if we affirm that
- one chance can, after any other manner, be superior to another, we must
- at the same time affirm, that there is something, which gives it the
- superiority, and determines the event rather to that side than the
- other: That is, in other words, we must allow of a cause, and destroy
- the supposition of chance; which we had before established. A
- perfect and total indifference is essential to chance, and one total
- indifference can never in itself be either superior or inferior to
- another. This truth is not peculiar to my system, but is acknowledged by
- every one, that forms calculations concerning chances.
- And here it is remarkable, that though chance and causation be directly
- contrary, yet it is impossible for us to conceive this combination of
- chances, which is requisite to render one hazard superior to another,
- without supposing a mixture of causes among the chances, and a
- conjunction of necessity in some particulars, with a total indifference
- in others. Where nothing limits the chances, every notion, that the most
- extravagant fancy can form, is upon a footing of equality; nor can there
- be any circumstance to give one the advantage above another. Thus unless
- we allow, that there are some causes to make the dice fall, and preserve
- their form in their fall, and lie upon some one of their sides, we can
- form no calculation concerning the laws of hazard. But supposing these
- causes to operate, and supposing likewise all the rest to be indifferent
- and to be determined by chance, it is easy to arrive at a notion of a
- superior combination of chances. A dye that has four sides marked with
- a certain number of spots, and only two with another, affords us an
- obvious and easy instance of this superiority. The mind is here limited
- by the causes to such a precise number and quality of the events; and at
- the same time is undetermined in its choice of any particular event.
- Proceeding then in that reasoning, wherein we have advanced three steps;
- that chance is merely the negation of a cause, and produces a total
- indifference in the mind; that one negation of a cause and one total
- indifference can never be superior or inferior to another; and that
- there must always be a mixture of causes among the chances, in order to
- be the foundation of any reasoning: We are next to consider what effect
- a superior combination of chances can have upon the mind, and after what
- manner it influences our judgment and opinion. Here we may repeat all
- the same arguments we employed in examining that belief, which arises
- from causes; and may prove, after the same manner, that a superior
- number of chances produces our assent neither by demonstration nor
- probability. It is indeed evident that we can never by the comparison
- of mere ideas make any discovery, which can be of consequence in this
- affairs and that it is impossible to prove with certainty, that any
- event must fall on that side where there is a superior number of
- chances. To, suppose in this case any certainty, were to overthrow what
- we have established concerning the opposition of chances, and their
- perfect equality and indifference.
- Should it be said, that though in an opposition of chances it is
- impossible to determine with certainty, on which side the event will
- fall, yet we can pronounce with certainty, that it is more likely and
- probable, it will be on that side where there is a superior number of
- chances, than where there is an inferior: should this be said, I would
- ask, what is here meant by likelihood and probability? The likelihood
- and probability of chances is a superior number of equal chances; and
- consequently when we say it is likely the event win fall on the side,
- which is superior, rather than on the inferior, we do no more than
- affirm, that where there is a superior number of chances there is
- actually a superior, and where there is an inferior there is an
- inferior; which are identical propositions, and of no consequence. The
- question is, by what means a superior number of equal chances operates
- upon the mind, and produces belief or assent; since it appears, that
- it is neither by arguments derived from demonstration, nor from
- probability.
- In order to clear up this difficulty, we shall suppose a person to take
- a dye, formed after such a manner as that four of its sides are marked
- with one figure, or one number of spots, and two with another; and to
- put this dye into the box with an intention of throwing it: It is plain,
- he must conclude the one figure to be more probable than the other, and
- give the preference to that which is inscribed on the greatest number
- of sides. He in a manner believes, that this will lie uppermost; though
- still with hesitation and doubt, in proportion to the number of chances,
- which are contrary: And according as these contrary chances diminish,
- and the superiority encreases on the other side, his belief acquires new
- degrees of stability and assurance. This belief arises from an operation
- of the mind upon the simple and limited object before us; and therefore
- its nature will be the more easily discovered and explained. We have
- nothing but one single dye to contemplate, in order to comprehend one of
- the most curious operations of the understanding.
- This dye, formed as above, contains three circumstances worthy of our
- attention. First, Certain causes, such as gravity, solidity, a cubical
- figure, &c. which determine it to fall, to preserve its form in its
- fall, and to turn up one of its sides. Secondly, A certain number
- of sides, which are supposed indifferent. Thirdly, A certain figure
- inscribed on each side. These three particulars form the whole nature of
- the dye, so far as relates to our present purpose; and consequently are
- the only circumstances regarded by the mind in its forming a judgment
- concerning the result of such a throw. Let us, therefore, consider
- gradually and carefully what must be the influence of these
- circumstances on the thought and imagination.
- First, We have already observed, that the mind is determined by custom
- to pass from any cause to its effect, and that upon the appearance
- of the one, it is almost impossible for it not to form an idea of the
- other. Their constant conjunction in past instances has produced such
- a habit in the mind, that it always conjoins them in its thought, and
- infers the existence of the one from that of its usual attendant. When
- it considers the dye as no longer supported by the box, it can not
- without violence regard it as suspended in the air; but naturally places
- it on the table, and views it as turning up one of its sides. This
- is the effect of the intermingled causes, which are requisite to our
- forming any calculation concerning chances.
- Secondly, It is supposed, that though the dye be necessarily determined
- to fall, and turn up one of its sides, yet there is nothing to fix the
- particular side, but that this is determined entirely by chance. The
- very nature and essence of chance is a negation of causes, and the
- leaving the mind in a perfect indifference among those events, which
- are supposed contingent. When therefore the thought is determined by the
- causes to consider the dye as falling and turning up one of its sides,
- the chances present all these sides as equal, and make us consider every
- one of them, one after another, as alike probable and possible. The
- imagination passes from the cause, viz. the throwing of the dye, to the
- effect, viz. the turning up one of the six sides; and feels a kind of
- impossibility both of stopping short in the way, and of forming any
- other idea. But as all these six sides are incompatible, and the dye
- cannot turn up above one at once, this principle directs us not to
- consider all of them at once as lying uppermost; which we look upon
- as impossible: Neither does it direct us with its entire force to any
- particular side; for in that case this side would be considered as
- certain and inevitable; but it directs us to the whole six sides after
- such a manner as to divide its force equally among them. We conclude in
- general, that some one of them must result from the throw: We run all
- of them over in our minds: The determination of the thought is common to
- all; but no more of its force falls to the share of any one, than what
- is suitable to its proportion with the rest. It is after this manner the
- original impulse, and consequently the vivacity of thought, arising from
- the causes, is divided and split in pieces by the intermingled chances.
- We have already seen the influence of the two first qualities of the
- dye, viz. the causes, and the number and indifference of the sides, and
- have learned how they give an impulse to the thought, and divide that
- impulse into as many parts as there are unites in the number of sides.
- We must now consider the effects of the third particular, viz. the
- figures inscribed on each side. It is evident that where several
- sides have the same figure inscribe on them, they must concur in their
- influence on the mind, and must unite upon one image or idea of a figure
- all those divided impulses, that were dispersed over the several sides,
- upon which that figure is inscribed. Were the question only what side
- will be turned up, these are all perfectly equal, and no one coued ever
- have any advantage above another. But as the question is concerning the
- figure, and as the same figure is presented by more than one side: it is
- evident, that the impulses belonging to all these sides must re-unite
- in that one figure, and become stronger and more forcible by the union.
- Four sides are supposed in the present case to have the same figure
- inscribed on them, and two to have another figure. The impulses of
- the former are, therefore, superior to those of the latter. But as the
- events are contrary, and it is impossible both these figures can be
- turned up; the impulses likewise become contrary, and the inferior
- destroys the superior, as far as its strength goes. The vivacity of the
- idea is always proportionable to the degrees of the impulse or tendency
- to the transition; and belief is the same with the vivacity of the idea,
- according to the precedent doctrine.
- SECT. XII. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CAUSES.
- What I have said concerning the probability of chances can serve to
- no other purpose, than to assist us in explaining the probability of
- causes; since it is commonly allowed by philosophers, that what the
- vulgar call chance is nothing but a secret and concealed cause. That
- species of probability, therefore, is what we must chiefly examine.
- The probabilities of causes are of several kinds; but are all derived
- from the same origin, viz. THE ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS TO A PRESENT
- IMPRESSION. As the habit, which produces the association, arises from
- the frequent conjunction of objects, it must arrive at its perfection by
- degrees, and must acquire new force from each instance, that falls under
- our observation. The first instance has little or no force: The second
- makes some addition to it: The third becomes still more sensible; and it
- is by these slow steps, that our judgment arrives at a full assurance.
- But before it attains this pitch of perfection, it passes through
- several inferior degrees, and in all of them is only to be esteemed a
- presumption or probability. The gradation, therefore, from probabilities
- to proofs is in many cases insensible; and the difference betwixt these
- kinds of evidence is more easily perceived in the remote degrees, than
- in the near and contiguous.
- It is worthy of remark on this occasion, that though the species of
- probability here explained be the first in order, and naturally takes
- place before any entire proof can exist, yet no one, who is arrived at
- the age of maturity, can any longer be acquainted with it. It is true,
- nothing is more common than for people of the most advanced knowledge
- to have attained only an imperfect experience of many particular events;
- which naturally produces only an imperfect habit and transition: But
- then we must consider, that the mind, having formed another observation
- concerning the connexion of causes and effects, gives new force to
- its reasoning from that observation; and by means of it can build an
- argument on one single experiment, when duly prepared and examined. What
- we have found once to follow from any object, we conclude will for ever
- follow from it; and if this maxim be not always built upon as certain,
- it is not for want of a sufficient number of experiments, but because
- we frequently meet with instances to the contrary; which leads us to
- the second species of probability, where there is a contrariety in our
- experience and observation.
- It would be very happy for men in the conduct of their lives and
- actions, were the same objects always conjoined together, and, we had
- nothing to fear but the mistakes of our own judgment, without having any
- reason to apprehend the uncertainty of nature. But as it is frequently
- found, that one observation is contrary to another, and that causes and
- effects follow not in the same order, of which we have I had experience,
- we are obliged to vary our reasoning on, account of this uncertainty,
- and take into consideration the contrariety of events. The first
- question, that occurs on this head, is concerning the nature and causes
- of the contrariety.
- The vulgar, who take things according to their first appearance,
- attribute the uncertainty of events to such an uncertainty in the
- causes, as makes them often fail of their usual influence, though
- they meet with no obstacle nor impediment in their operation. But
- philosophers observing, that almost in every part of nature there is
- contained a vast variety of springs and principles, which are hid,
- by reason of their minuteness or remoteness, find that it is at least
- possible the contrariety of events may not proceed from any contingency
- in the cause, but from the secret operation of contrary causes. This
- possibility is converted into certainty by farther observation, when
- they remark, that upon an exact scrutiny, a contrariety of effects
- always betrays a contrariety of causes, and proceeds from their mutual
- hindrance and opposition. A peasant can give no better reason for the
- stopping of any clock or watch than to say, that commonly it does not
- go right: But an artizan easily perceives, that the same force in the
- spring or pendulum has always the same influence on the wheels; but
- fails of its usual effect, perhaps by reason of a grain of dust, which
- puts a stop to the whole movement. From the observation of several
- parallel instances, philosophers form a maxim, that the connexion
- betwixt all causes and effects is equally necessary, and that its
- seeming uncertainty in some instances proceeds from the secret
- opposition of contrary causes.
- But however philosophers and the vulgar may differ in their explication
- of the contrariety of events, their inferences from it are always of the
- same kind, and founded on the same principles. A contrariety of events
- in the past may give us a kind of hesitating belief for the future after
- two several ways. First, By producing an imperfect habit and transition
- from the present impression to the related idea. When the conjunction of
- any two objects is frequent, without being entirely constant, the mind
- is determined to pass from one object to the other; but not with
- so entire a habit, as when the union is uninterrupted, and all the
- instances we have ever met with are uniform and of a piece-.. We find
- from common experience, in our actions as well as reasonings, that
- a constant perseverance in any course of life produces a strong
- inclination and tendency to continue for the future; though there
- are habits of inferior degrees of force, proportioned to the inferior
- degrees of steadiness and uniformity in our conduct.
- There is no doubt but this principle sometimes takes place, and
- produces those inferences we draw from contrary phaenomena: though I
- am perswaded, that upon examination we shall not find it to be the
- principle, that most commonly influences the mind in this species of
- reasoning. When we follow only the habitual determination of the mind,
- we make the transition without any reflection, and interpose not a
- moment's delay betwixt the view of one object and the belief of that,
- which is often found to attend it. As the custom depends not upon any
- deliberation, it operates immediately, without allowing any time for
- reflection. But this method of proceeding we have but few instances
- of in our probable reasonings; and even fewer than in those, which are
- derived from the uninterrupted conjunction of objects. In the former
- species of reasoning we commonly take knowingly into consideration
- the contrariety of past events; we compare the different sides of the
- contrariety, and carefully weigh the experiments, which we have on each
- side: Whence we may conclude, that our reasonings of this kind arise
- not directly from the habit, but in an oblique manner; which we must now
- endeavour to explain.
- It is evident, that when an object is attended with contrary effects, we
- judge of them only by our past experience, and always consider those
- as possible, which we have observed to follow from it. And as past
- experience regulates our judgment concerning the possibility of these
- effects, so it does that concerning their probability; and that effect,
- which has been the most common, we always esteem the most likely. Here
- then are two things to be considered, viz. the reasons which determine
- us to make the past a standard for the future, and the manner how we
- extract a single judgment from a contrariety of past events.
- First we may observe, that the supposition, that the future resembles
- the past, is not founded on arguments of any kind, but is derived
- entirely from habit, by which we are determined to expect for the future
- the same train of objects, to which we have been accustomed. This habit
- or determination to transfer the past to the future is full and perfect;
- and consequently the first impulse of the imagination in this species of
- reasoning is endowed with the same qualities.
- But, secondly, when in considering past experiments we find them of a
- contrary nature, this determination, though full and perfect in itself,
- presents us with no steady object, but offers us a number of disagreeing
- images in a certain order and proportion. The first impulse, therefore,
- is here broke into pieces, and diffuses itself over all those images, of
- which each partakes an equal share of that force and vivacity, that is
- derived from the impulse. Any of these past events may again happen;
- and we judge, that when they do happen, they will be mixed in the same
- proportion as in the past.
- If our intention, therefore, be to consider the proportions of contrary
- events in a great number of instances, the images presented by our past
- experience must remain in their FIRST FORM, and preserve their first
- proportions. Suppose, for instance, I have found by long observation,
- that of twenty ships, which go to sea, only nineteen return. Suppose
- I see at present twenty ships that leave the port: I transfer my past
- experience to the future, and represent to myself nineteen of these
- ships as returning in safety, and one as perishing. Concerning this
- there can be no difficulty. But as we frequently run over those several
- ideas of past events, in order to form a judgment concerning one single
- event, which appears uncertain; this consideration must change the FIRST
- FORM of our ideas, and draw together the divided images presented
- by experience; since it is to it we refer the determination of that
- particular event, upon which we reason. Many of these images are
- supposed to concur, and a superior number to concur on one side. These
- agreeing images unite together, and render the idea more strong and
- lively, not only than a mere fiction of the imagination, but also than
- any idea, which is supported by a lesser number of experiments. Each new
- experiment is as a new stroke of the pencil, which bestows an additional
- vivacity on the colours without either multiplying or enlarging the
- figure. This operation of the mind has been so fully explained in
- treating of the probability of chance, that I need not here endeavour to
- render it more intelligible. Every past experiment may be considered as
- a kind of chance; I it being uncertain to us, whether the object will
- exist conformable to one experiment or another. And for this reason
- every thing that has been said on the one subject is applicable to both.
- Thus upon the whole, contrary experiments produce an imperfect belief,
- either by weakening the habit, or by dividing and afterwards joining in
- different parts, that perfect habit, which makes us conclude in general,
- that instances, of which we have no experience, must necessarily
- resemble those of which we have.
- To justify still farther this account of the second species of
- probability, where we reason with knowledge and reflection from
- a contrariety of past experiments, I shall propose the following
- considerations, without fearing to give offence by that air of subtilty,
- which attends them. Just reasoning ought still, perhaps, to retain
- its force, however subtile; in the same manner as matter preserves its
- solidity in the air, and fire, and animal spirits, as well as in the
- grosser and more sensible forms.
- First, We may observe, that there is no probability so great as not to
- allow of a contrary possibility; because otherwise it would cease to be
- a probability, and would become a certainty. That probability of causes,
- which is most extensive, and which we at present examine, depends on a
- contrariety of experiments: and it is evident An experiment in the past
- proves at least a possibility for the future.
- Secondly, The component parts of this possibility and probability are of
- the same nature, and differ in number only, but not in kind. It has been
- observed, that all single chances are entirely equal, and that the
- only circumstance, which can give any event, that is contingent, a
- superiority over another is a superior number of chances. In like
- manner, as the uncertainty of causes is discovery by experience, which
- presents us with a view of contrary events, it is plain, that when we
- transfer the past to the future, the known to the unknown, every past
- experiment has the same weight, and that it is only a superior number
- of them, which can throw the ballance on any side. The possibility,
- therefore, which enters into every reasoning of this kind, is composed
- of parts, which are of the same nature both among themselves, and with
- those, that compose the opposite probability.
- Thirdly, We may establish it as a certain maxim, that in all moral as
- well as natural phaenomena, wherever any cause consists of a number
- of parts, and the effect encreases or diminishes, according to the
- variation of that number, the effects properly speaking, is a compounded
- one, and arises from the union of the several effects, that proceed from
- each part of the cause. Thus, because the gravity of a body encreases or
- diminishes by the encrease or diminution of its parts, we conclude that
- each part contains this quality and contributes to the gravity of the
- whole. The absence or presence of a part of the cause is attended with
- that of a proportionable part of the effect. This connexion or constant
- conjunction sufficiently proves the one part to be the cause of the
- other. As the belief which we have of any event, encreases or diminishes
- according to the number of chances or past experiments, it is to be
- considered as a compounded effect, of which each part arises from a
- proportionable number of chances or experiments.
- Let us now join these three observations, and see what conclusion we can
- draw from them. To every probability there is an opposite possibility.
- This possibility is composed of parts, that are entirely of the same
- nature with those of the probability; and consequently have the same
- influence on the mind and understanding. The belief, which attends the
- probability, is a compounded effect, and is formed by the concurrence
- of the several effects, which proceed from each part of the probability.
- Since therefore each part of the probability contributes to the
- production of the belief, each part of the possibility must have the
- same influence on the opposite side; the nature of these parts being
- entirely the same. The contrary belief, attending the possibility,
- implies a view of a certain object, as well as the probability does
- an opposite view. In this particular both these degrees of belief are
- alike. The only manner then, in which the superior number of similar
- component parts in the one can exert its influence, and prevail above
- the inferior in the other, is by producing a stronger and more lively
- view of its object. Each part presents a particular view; and all these
- views uniting together produce one general view, which is fuller and
- more distinct by the greater number of causes or principles, from which
- it is derived.
- The component parts of the probability and possibility, being alike
- in their nature, must produce like effects; and the likeness of their
- effects consists in this, that each of them presents a view of a
- particular object. But though these parts be alike in their nature, they
- are very different in their quantity and number; and this difference
- must appear in the effect as well as the similarity. Now as the view
- they present is in both cases full and entire, and comprehends the
- object in all its parts, it is impossible that in this particular there
- can be any difference; nor is there any thing but a superior vivacity
- in the probability, arising from the concurrence of a superior number of
- views, which can distinguish these effects.
- Here is almost the same argument in a different light. All our
- reasonings concerning the probability of causes are founded on the
- transferring of past to future. The transferring of any past experiment
- to the future is sufficient to give us a view of the object; whether
- that experiment be single or combined with others of the same kind;
- whether it be entire, or opposed by others of a contrary kind. Suppose,
- then, it acquires both these qualities of combination and opposition, it
- loses not upon that account its former power of presenting a view of the
- object, but only concurs with and opposes other experiments, that have
- a like influence. A question, therefore, may arise concerning the manner
- both of the concurrence and opposition. As to the concurrence, there is
- only the choice left betwixt these two hypotheses. First, That the view
- of the object, occasioned by the transference of each past experiment,
- preserves itself entire, and only multiplies the number of views. Or,
- SECONDLY, That it runs into the other similar and correspondent views,
- and gives them a superior degree of force and vivacity. But that the
- first hypothesis is erroneous, is evident from experience, which
- informs us, that the belief, attending any reasoning, consists in
- one conclusion, not in a multitude of similar ones, which would only
- distract the mind, and in many cases would be too numerous to be
- comprehended distinctly by any finite capacity. It remains, therefore,
- as the only reasonable opinion, that these similar views run into each
- other, and unite their forces; so as to produce a stronger and clearer
- view, than what arises from any one alone. This is the manner, in which
- past experiments concur, when they are transfered to any future event.
- As to the manner of their opposition, it is evident, that as the
- contrary views are incompatible with each other, and it is impossible
- the object can at once exist conformable to both of them, their
- influence becomes mutually destructive, and the mind is determined to
- the superior only with that force, which remains, after subtracting the
- inferior.
- I am sensible how abstruse all this reasoning must appear to the
- generality of readers, who not being accustomed to such profound
- reflections on the intellectual faculties of the mind, will be apt to
- reject as chimerical whatever strikes not in with the common received
- notions, and with the easiest and most obvious principles of philosophy.
- And no doubt there are some pains required to enter into these
- arguments; though perhaps very little are necessary to perceive the
- imperfection of every vulgar hypothesis on this subject, and the little
- light, which philosophy can yet afford us in such sublime and such
- curious speculations. Let men be once fully perswaded of these two
- principles, THAT THERE, IS NOTHING IN ANY OBJECT, CONSIDERed IN ITSELF,
- WHICH CAN AFFORD US A REASON FOR DRAWING A CONCLUSION BEYOND it; and,
- THAT EVEN AFTER THE OBSERVATION OF THE FREQUENT OR CONSTANT CONJUNCTION
- OF OBJECTS, WE HAVE NO REASON TO DRAW ANY INFERENCE CONCERNING ANY
- OBJECT BEYOND THOSE OF WHICH WE HAVE HAD EXPERIENCE; I say, let men be
- once fully convinced of these two principles, and this will throw them
- so loose from all common systems, that they will make no difficulty of
- receiving any, which may appear the most extraordinary. These principles
- we have found to be sufficiently convincing, even with regard to our
- most certain reasonings from causation: But I shall venture to affirm,
- that with regard to these conjectural or probable reasonings they still
- acquire a new degree of evidence.
- First, It is obvious, that in reasonings of this kind, it is not the
- object presented to us, which, considered in itself, affords us any
- reason to draw a conclusion concerning any other object or event. For
- as this latter object is supposed uncertain, and as the uncertainty is
- derived from a concealed contrariety of causes in the former, were any
- of the causes placed in the known qualities of that object, they would
- no longer be concealed, nor would our conclusion be uncertain.
- But, secondly, it is equally obvious in this species of reasoning, that
- if the transference of the past to the future were founded merely on a
- conclusion of the understanding, it coued never occasion any belief or
- assurance. When we transfer contrary experiments to the future, we
- can only repeat these contrary experiments with their particular
- proportions; which coued not produce assurance in any single event, upon
- which we reason, unless the fancy melted together all those images
- that concur, and extracted from them one single idea or image, which is
- intense and lively in proportion to the number of experiments from which
- it is derived, and their superiority above their antagonists. Our past
- experience presents no determinate object; and as our belief, however
- faint, fixes itself on a determinate object, it is evident that the
- belief arises not merely from the transference of past to future, but
- from some operation of the fancy conjoined with it. This may lead us
- to conceive the manner, in which that faculty enters into all our
- reasonings.
- I shall conclude this subject with two reflections, which may deserve
- our attention. The FIRST may be explained after this manner. When the
- mind forms a reasoning concerning any matter of fact, which is
- only probable, it casts its eye backward upon past experience, and
- transferring it to the future, is presented with so many contrary
- views of its object, of which those that are of the same kind uniting
- together, and running into one act of the mind, serve to fortify and
- inliven it. But suppose that this multitude of views or glimpses of an
- object proceeds not from experience, but from a voluntary act of the
- imagination; this effect does not follow, or at least, follows not in
- the same degree. For though custom and education produce belief by such
- a repetition, as is not derived from experience, yet this requires
- a long tract of time, along with a very frequent and undesigned
- repetition. In general we may pronounce, that a person who would
- voluntarily repeat any idea in his mind, though supported by one past
- experience, would be no more inclined to believe the existence of its
- object, than if he had contented himself with one survey of it.
- Beside the effect of design; each act of the mind, being separate and
- independent, has a separate influence, and joins not its force with that
- of its fellows. Not being united by any common object, producing them,
- they have no relation to each other; and consequently make no transition
- or union of forces. This phaenomenon we shall understand better
- afterwards.
- My second reflection is founded on those large probabilities, which the
- mind can judge of, and the minute differences it can observe betwixt
- them. When the chances or experiments on one side amount to ten
- thousand, and on the other to ten thousand and one, the judgment gives
- the preference to the latter, upon account of that superiority; though
- it is plainly impossible for the mind to run over every particular view,
- and distinguish the superior vivacity of the image arising from the
- superior number, where the difference is so inconsiderable. We have a
- parallel instance in the affections. It is evident, according to the
- principles above-mentioned, that when an object produces any passion in
- us, which varies according to the different quantity of the object; I
- say, it is evident, that the passion, properly speaking, is not a simple
- emotion, but a compounded one, of a great number of weaker passions,
- derived from a view of each part of the object. For otherwise it were
- impossible the passion should encrease by the encrease of these parts.
- Thus a man, who desires a thousand pound, has in reality a thousand
- or more desires which uniting together, seem to make only one passion;
- though the composition evidently betrays itself upon every alteration of
- the object, by the preference he gives to the larger number, if superior
- only by an unite. Yet nothing can be more certain, than that so small
- a difference would not be discernible in the passions, nor coued render
- them distinguishable from each other. The difference, therefore, of our
- conduct in preferring the greater number depends not upon our passions,
- but upon custom, and general rules. We have found in a multitude of
- instances, that the augmenting the numbers of any sum augments the
- passion, where the numbers are precise and the difference sensible. The
- mind can perceive from its immediate feeling, that three guineas produce
- a greater passion than two; and this it transfers to larger numbers,
- because of the resemblance; and by a general rule assigns to a thousand
- guineas, a stronger passion than to nine hundred and ninety nine. These
- general rules we shall explain presently.
- But beside these two species of probability, which a-re derived from an
- imperfect experience and from contrary causes, there is a third arising
- from ANALOGY, which differs from them in some material circumstances.
- According to the hypothesis above explained all kinds of reasoning from
- causes or effects are founded on two particulars, viz., the constant
- conjunction of any two objects in all past experience, and the
- resemblance of a present object to any one of them. The effect of these
- two particulars is, that the present object invigorates and inlivens the
- imagination; and the resemblance, along with the constant union, conveys
- this force and vivacity to the related idea; which we are therefore said
- to believe, or assent to. If you weaken either the union or resemblance,
- you weaken the principle of transition, and of consequence that belief,
- which arises from it. The vivacity of the first impression cannot be
- fully conveyed to the related idea, either where the conjunction of
- their objects is not constant, or where the present impression does
- not perfectly resemble any of those, whose union we are accustomed to
- observe. In those probabilities of chance and causes above-explained,
- it is the constancy of the union, which is diminished; and in the
- probability derived from analogy, it is the resemblance only, which is
- affected. Without some degree of resemblance, as well as union, it is
- impossible there can be any reasoning: but as this resemblance admits
- of many different degrees, the reasoning becomes proportionably more
- or less firm and certain. An experiment loses of its force, when
- transferred to instances, which are not exactly resembling; though it
- is evident it may still retain as much as may be the foundation of
- probability, as long as there is any resemblance remaining.
- SECT. XIII. OF UNPHILOSOPHICAL PROBABILITY.
- All these kinds of probability are received by philosophers, and allowed
- to be reasonable foundations of belief and opinion. But there are
- others, that are derived from the same principles, though they have not
- had the good fortune to obtain the same sanction. The first probability
- of this kind may be accounted for thus. The diminution of the union, and
- of the resemblance, as above explained, diminishes the facility of the
- transition, and by that means weakens the evidence; and we may farther
- observe, that the same diminution of the evidence will follow from a
- diminution of the impression, and from the shading of those colours,
- under which it appears to the memory or senses. The argument, which
- we found on any matter of fact we remember, is more or less convincing
- according as the fact is recent or remote; and though the difference
- in these degrees of evidence be not received by philosophy as solid and
- legitimate; because in that case an argument must have a different force
- to day, from what it shall have a month hence; yet notwithstanding
- the opposition of philosophy, it is certain, this circumstance has a
- considerable influence on the understanding, and secretly changes the
- authority of the same argument, according to the different times,
- in which it is proposed to us. A greater force and vivacity in the
- impression naturally conveys a greater to the related idea; and it is on
- the degrees of force and vivacity, that the belief depends, according to
- the foregoing system.
- There is a second difference, which we may frequently observe in our
- degrees of belief and assurance, and which never fails to take place,
- though disclaimed by philosophers. An experiment, that is recent and
- fresh in the memory, affects us more than one that is in some measure
- obliterated; and has a superior influence on the judgment, as well as on
- the passions. A lively impression produces more assurance than a faint
- one; because it has more original force to communicate to the related
- idea, which thereby acquires a greater force and vivacity. A recent
- observation has a like effect; because the custom and transition is
- there more entire, and preserves better the original force in the
- communication. Thus a drunkard, who has seen his companion die of a
- debauch, is struck with that instance for some time, and dreads a like
- accident for himself: But as the memory of it decays away by degrees,
- his former security returns, and the danger seems less certain and real.
- I add, as a third instance of this kind, that though our reasonings from
- proofs and from probabilities be considerably different from each other,
- yet the former species of reasoning often degenerates insensibly into
- the latter, by nothing but the multitude of connected arguments. It is
- certain, that when an inference is drawn immediately from an object,
- without any intermediate cause or effect, the conviction is much
- stronger, and the persuasion more lively, than when the imagination is
- carryed through a long chain of connected arguments, however infallible
- the connexion of each link may be esteemed. It is from the original
- impression, that the vivacity of all the ideas is derived, by means
- of the customary transition of the imagination; and it is evident this
- vivacity must gradually decay in proportion to the distance, and must
- lose somewhat in each transition. Sometimes this distance has a greater
- influence than even contrary experiments would have; and a man may
- receive a more lively conviction from a probable reasoning, which is
- close and immediate, than from a long chain of consequences, though just
- and conclusive in each part. Nay it is seldom such reasonings produce
- any conviction; and one must have a very strong and firm imagination
- to preserve the evidence to the end, where it passes through so many,
- stages.
- But here it may not be amiss to remark a very curious phaenomenon, which
- the present subject suggests to us. It is evident there is no point
- of ancient history, of which we can have any assurance, but by passing
- through many millions of causes and effects, and through a chain of
- arguments of almost an immeasurable length. Before the knowledge of the
- fact coued come to the first historian, it must be conveyed through many
- mouths; and after it is committed to writing, each new copy is a new
- object, of which the connexion with the foregoing is known only by
- experience and observation. Perhaps, therefore, it may be concluded from
- the precedent reasoning, that the evidence of all ancient history must
- now be lost; or at least, will be lost in time, as the chain of causes
- encreases, and runs on to a greater length. But as it seems contrary to
- common sense to think, that if the republic of letters, and the art of
- printing continue on the same footing as at present, our posterity, even
- after a thousand ages, can ever doubt if there has been such a man as
- JULIUS CAESAR; this may be considered as an objection to the present
- system. If belief consisted only in a certain vivacity, conveyed from an
- original impression, it would decay by the length of the transition, and
- must at last be utterly extinguished: And vice versa, if belief on some
- occasions be not capable of such an extinction; it must be something
- different from that vivacity.
- Before I answer this objection I shall observe, that from this topic
- there has been borrowed a very celebrated argument against the Christian
- Religion; but with this difference, that the connexion betwixt each link
- of the chain in human testimony has been there supposed not to go beyond
- probability, and to be liable to a degree of doubt and uncertainty.
- And indeed it must be confest, that in this manner of considering
- the subject, (which however is not a true one) there is no history or
- tradition, but what must in the end lose all its force and evidence.
- Every new probability diminishes the original conviction; and however
- great that conviction may be supposed, it is impossible it can subsist
- under such re-iterated diminutions. This is true in general; though
- we shall find [Part IV. Sect. 1.] afterwards, that there is one very
- memorable exception, which is of vast consequence in the present subject
- of the understanding.
- Mean while to give a solution of the preceding objection upon the
- supposition, that historical evidence amounts at first to an entire
- proof; let us consider, that though the links are innumerable, that
- connect any original fact with the present impression, which is the
- foundation of belief; yet they are all of the same kind, and depend on
- the fidelity of Printers and Copyists. One edition passes into another,
- and that into a third, and so on, till we come to that volume we peruse
- at present. There is no variation in the steps. After we know one we
- know all of them; and after we have made one, we can have no scruple as
- to the rest. This circumstance alone preserves the evidence of history,
- and will perpetuate the memory of the present age to the latest
- posterity. If all the long chain of causes and effects, which connect
- any past event with any volume of history, were composed of parts
- different from each other, and which it were necessary for the mind
- distinctly to conceive, it is impossible we should preserve to the
- end any belief or evidence. But as most of these proofs are perfectly
- resembling, the mind runs easily along them, jumps from one part to
- another with facility, and forms but a confused and general notion of
- each link. By this means a long chain of argument, has as little effect
- in diminishing the original vivacity, as a much shorter would have, if
- composed of parts, which were different from each other, and of which
- each required a distinct consideration.
- A fourth unphilosophical species of probability is that derived from
- general rules, which we rashly form to ourselves, and which are the
- source of what we properly call PREJUDICE. An IRISHMAN cannot have
- wit, and a Frenchman cannot have solidity; for which reason, though the
- conversation of the former in any instance be visibly very agreeable,
- and of the latter very judicious, we have entertained such a prejudice
- against them, that they must be dunces or fops in spite of sense and
- reason. Human nature is very subject to errors of this kind; and perhaps
- this nation as much as any other.
- Should it be demanded why men form general rules, and allow them to
- influence their judgment, even contrary to present observation and
- experience, I should reply, that in my opinion it proceeds from those
- very principles, on which all judgments concerning causes and effects
- depend. Our judgments concerning cause and effect are derived from
- habit and experience; and when we have been accustomed to see one object
- united to another, our imagination passes from the first to the second,
- by a natural transition, which precedes reflection, and which cannot be
- prevented by it. Now it is the nature of custom not only to operate with
- its full force, when objects are presented, that are exactly the same
- with those to which we have been accustomed; but also to operate in an
- inferior degree, when we discover such as are similar; and though the
- habit loses somewhat of its force by every difference, yet it is seldom
- entirely destroyed, where any considerable circumstances remain the
- same. A man, who has contracted a custom of eating fruit by the use of
- pears or peaches, will satisfy himself with melons, where he cannot find
- his favourite fruit; as one, who has become a drunkard by the use of
- red wines, will be carried almost with the same violence to white, if
- presented to him. From this principle I have accounted for that species
- of probability, derived from analogy, where we transfer our experience
- in past instances to objects which are resembling, but are not exactly
- the same with those concerning which we have had experience. In
- proportion as the resemblance decays, the probability diminishes;
- but still has some force as long as there remain any traces of the
- resemblance.
- This observation we may carry farther; and may remark, that though
- custom be the foundation of all our judgments, yet sometimes it has an
- effect on the imagination in opposition to the judgment, and produces
- a contrariety in our sentiments concerning the same object. I explain
- myself. In almost all kinds of causes there is a complication of
- circumstances, of which some are essential, and others superfluous; some
- are absolutely requisite to the production of the effect, and others
- are only conjoined by accident. Now we may observe, that when these
- superfluous circumstances are numerous, and remarkable, and frequently
- conjoined with the essential, they have such an influence on the
- imagination, that even in the absence of the latter they carry us on to
- t-he conception of the usual effect, and give to that conception a force
- and vivacity, which make it superior to the mere fictions of the fancy.
- We may correct this propensity by a reflection on the nature of those
- circumstances: but it is still certain, that custom takes the start, and
- gives a biass to the imagination.
- To illustrate this by a familiar instance, let us consider the case of
- a man, who, being hung out from a high tower in a cage of iron cannot
- forbear trembling, when he surveys the precipice below him, though he
- knows himself to be perfectly secure from falling, by his experience of
- the solidity of the iron, which supports him; and though the ideas of
- fall and descent, and harm and death, be derived solely from custom and
- experience. The same custom goes beyond the instances, from which it is
- derived, and to which it perfectly corresponds; and influences his
- ideas of such objects as are in some respect resembling, but fall not
- precisely under the same rule. The circumstances of depth and descent
- strike so strongly upon him, that their influence can-not be destroyed
- by the contrary circumstances of support and solidity, which ought to
- give him a perfect security. His imagination runs away with its object,
- and excites a passion proportioned to it. That passion returns back
- upon the imagination and inlivens the idea; which lively idea has a
- new influence on the passion, and in its turn augments its force and
- violence; and both his fancy and affections, thus mutually supporting
- each other, cause the whole to have a very great influence upon him.
- But why need we seek for other instances, while the present subject
- of philosophical probabilities offers us so obvious an one, in the
- opposition betwixt the judgment and imagination arising from these
- effects of custom? According to my system, all reasonings are nothing
- but the effects of custom; and custom has no influence, but by
- inlivening the imagination, and giving us a strong conception of
- any object. It may, therefore, be concluded, that our judgment and
- imagination can never be contrary, and that custom cannot operate on
- the latter faculty after such a manner, as to render it opposite to the
- former. This difficulty we can remove after no other manner, than by
- supposing the influence of general rules. We shall afterwards take
- [Sect. 15.] notice of some general rules, by which we ought to regulate
- our judgment concerning causes and effects; and these rules are formed
- on the nature of our understanding, and on our experience of its
- operations in the judgments we form concerning objects. By them we learn
- to distinguish the accidental circumstances from the efficacious causes;
- and when we find that an effect can be produced without the concurrence
- of any particular circumstance, we conclude that that circumstance makes
- not a part of the efficacious cause, however frequently conjoined with
- it. But as this frequent conjunction necessity makes it have some effect
- on the imagination, in spite of the opposite conclusion from general
- rules, the opposition of these two principles produces a contrariety
- in our thoughts, and causes us to ascribe the one inference to our
- judgment, and the other to our imagination. The general rule is
- attributed to our judgment; as being more extensive and constant. The
- exception to the imagination, as being more capricious and uncertain.
- Thus our general rules are in a manner set in opposition to each other.
- When an object appears, that resembles any cause in very considerable
- circumstances, the imagination naturally carries us to a lively
- conception of the usual effect, Though the object be different in the
- most material and most efficacious circumstances from that cause. Here
- is the first influence of general rules. But when we take a review of
- this act of the mind, and compare it with the more general and authentic
- operations of the understanding, we find it to be of an irregular
- nature, and destructive of all the most established principles of
- reasonings; which is the cause of our rejecting it. This is a second
- influence of general rules, and implies the condemnation of the former.
- Sometimes the one, sometimes the other prevails, according to the
- disposition and character of the person. The vulgar are commonly guided
- by the first, and wise men by the second. Mean while the sceptics may
- here have the pleasure of observing a new and signal contradiction in
- our reason, and of seeing all philosophy ready to be subverted by a
- principle of human nature, and again saved by a new direction of
- the very same principle. The following of general rules is a very
- unphilosophical species of probability; and yet it is only by
- following them that we can correct this, and all other unphilosophical
- probabilities.
- Since we have instances, where general rules operate on the imagination
- even contrary to the judgment, we need not be surprized to see their
- effects encrease, when conjoined with that latter faculty, and to
- observe that they bestow on the ideas they present to us a force
- superior to what attends any other. Every one knows, there is an
- indirect manner of insinuating praise or blame, which is much less
- shocking than the open flattery or censure of any person. However he may
- communicate his sentiments by such secret insinuations, and make them
- known with equal certainty as by the open discovery of them, it is
- certain that their influence is not equally strong and powerful. One who
- lashes me with concealed strokes of satire, moves not my indignation to
- such a degree, as if he flatly told me I was a fool and coxcomb; though
- I equally understand his meaning, as if he did. This difference is to be
- attributed to the influence of general rules.
- Whether a person openly, abuses me, or slyly intimates his contempt, in
- neither case do I immediately perceive his sentiment or opinion; and it
- is only by signs, that is, by its effects, I become sensible of it. The
- only difference, then, betwixt these two cases consists in this, that
- in the open discovery of his sentiments he makes use of signs, which are
- general and universal; and in the secret intimation employs such as are
- more singular and uncommon. The effect of this circumstance is, that the
- imagination, in running from the present impression to the absent idea,
- makes the transition with greater facility, and consequently conceives
- the object with greater force, where the connexion is common and
- universal, than where it is more rare and particular. Accordingly we
- may observe, that the open declaration of our sentiments is called the
- taking off the mask, as the secret intimation of our opinions is said
- to be the veiling of them. The difference betwixt an idea produced by
- a general connexion, and that arising from a particular one is here
- compared to the difference betwixt an impression and an idea. This
- difference in the imagination has a suitable effect on the passions; and
- this effect is augmented by another circumstance. A secret intimation
- of anger or contempt shews that we still have some consideration for
- the person, and avoid the directly abusing him. This makes a concealed
- satire less disagreeable; but still this depends on the same principle.
- For if an idea were not more feeble, when only intimated, it would never
- be esteemed a mark of greater respect to proceed in this method than in
- the other.
- Sometimes scurrility is less displeasing than delicate satire, because
- it revenges us in a manner for the injury at the very time it is
- committed, by affording us a just reason to blame and contemn the
- person, who injures us. But this phaenomenon likewise depends upon the
- same principle. For why do we blame all gross and injurious language,
- unless it be, because we esteem it contrary to good breeding and
- humanity? And why is it contrary, unless it be more shocking than any
- delicate satire? The rules of good breeding condemn whatever is openly
- disobliging, and gives a sensible pain and confusion to those, with
- whom we converse. After this is once established, abusive language is
- universally blamed, and gives less pain upon account of its coarseness
- and incivility, which render the person despicable, that employs it. It
- becomes less disagreeable, merely because originally it is more so; and
- it is more disagreeable, because it affords an inference by general and
- common rules, that are palpable and undeniable.
- To this explication of the different influence of open and concealed
- flattery or satire, I shall add the consideration of another phenomenon,
- which is analogous to it. There are many particulars in the point of
- honour both of men and women, whose violations, when open and avowed,
- the world never excuses, but which it is more apt to overlook, when the
- appearances are saved, and the transgression is secret and concealed.
- Even those, who know with equal certainty, that the fault is committed,
- pardon it more easily, when the proofs seem in some measure oblique and
- equivocal, than when they are direct and undeniable. The same idea is
- presented in both cases, and, properly speaking, is equally assented
- to by the judgment; and yet its influence is different, because of the
- different manner, in which it is presented.
- Now if we compare these two cases, of the open and concealed violations
- of the laws of honour, we shall find, that the difference betwixt them
- consists in this, that in the first ease the sign, from which we infer
- the blameable action, is single, and suffices alone to be the foundation
- of our reasoning and judgment; whereas in the latter the signs are
- numerous, and decide little or nothing when alone and unaccompanyed with
- many minute circumstances, which are almost imperceptible. But it is
- certainly true, that any reasoning is always the more convincing, the
- more single and united it is to the eye, and the less exercise it gives
- to the imagination to collect all its parts, and run from them to the
- correlative idea, which forms the conclusion. The labour of the thought
- disturbs the regular progress of the sentiments, as we shall observe
- presently.[Part IV. Sect. 1.] The idea strikes not on us with ouch
- vivacity; and consequently has no such influence on the passion and
- imagination.
- From the same principles we may account for those observations of the
- CARDINAL DE RETZ, that there are many things, in which the world wishes
- to be deceived; and that it more easily excuses a person in acting than
- in talking contrary to the decorum of his profession and character. A
- fault in words is commonly more open and distinct than one in actions,
- which admit of many palliating excuses, and decide not so clearly
- concerning the intention and views of the actor.
- Thus it appears upon the whole, that every kind of opinion or judgment,
- which amounts not to knowledge, is derived entirely from the force and
- vivacity of the perception, and that these qualities constitute in the
- mind, what we call the BELIEF Of the existence of any object. This force
- and this vivacity are most conspicuous in the memory; and therefore our
- confidence in the veracity of that faculty is the greatest imaginable,
- and equals in many respects the assurance of a demonstration. The next
- degree of these qualities is that derived from the relation of cause and
- effect; and this too is very great, especially when the conjunction is
- found by experience to be perfectly constant, and when the object,
- which is present to us, exactly resembles those, of which we have had
- experience. But below this degree of evidence there are many others,
- which have an influence on the passions and imagination, proportioned to
- that degree of force and vivacity, which they communicate to the ideas.
- It is by habit we make the transition from cause to effect; and it is
- from some present impression we borrow that vivacity, which we diffuse
- over the correlative idea. But when we have not observed a sufficient
- number of instances, to produce a strong habit; or when these instances
- are contrary to each other; or when the resemblance is not exact; or
- the present impression is faint and obscure; or the experience in some
- measure obliterated from the memory; or the connexion dependent on a
- long chain of objects; or the inference derived from general rules, and
- yet not conformable to them: In all these cases the evidence diminishes
- by the diminution of the force and intenseness of the idea. This
- therefore is the nature of the judgment and probability.
- What principally gives authority to this system is, beside the undoubted
- arguments, upon which each part is founded, the agreement of these
- parts, and the necessity of one to explain another. The belief, which
- attends our memory, is of the same nature with that, which is derived
- from our judgments: Nor is there any difference betwixt that judgment,
- which is derived from a constant and uniform connexion of causes and
- effects, and that which depends upon an interrupted and uncertain. It is
- indeed evident, that in all determinations, where the mind decides from
- contrary experiments, it is first divided within itself, and has an
- inclination to either side in proportion to the number of experiments
- we have seen and remember. This contest is at last determined to the
- advantage of that side, where we observe a superior number of these
- experiments; but still with a diminution of force in the evidence
- correspondent to the number of the opposite experiments. Each
- possibility, of which the probability is composed, operates separately
- upon the imagination; and it is the larger collection of possibilities,
- which at last prevails, and that with a force proportionable to its
- superiority. All these phenomena lead directly to the precedent system;
- nor will it ever be possible upon any other principles to give a
- satisfactory and consistent explication of them. Without considering
- these judgments as the effects of custom on the imagination, we shall
- lose ourselves in perpetual contradiction and absurdity.
- SECT. XIV. OF THE IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNEXION.
- Having thus explained the manner, in which we reason beyond our
- immediate impressions, and conclude that such particular causes must
- have such particular effects; we must now return upon our footsteps to
- examine that question, which [Sect. 2.] first occured to us, and which
- we dropt in our way, viz. What is our idea of necessity, when we say
- that two objects are necessarily connected together. Upon this head I
- repeat what I have often had occasion to observe, that as we have
- no idea, that is not derived from an impression, we must find some
- impression, that gives rise to this idea of necessity, if we assert we
- have really such an idea. In order to this I consider, in what objects
- necessity is commonly supposed to lie; and finding that it is always
- ascribed to causes and effects, I turn my eye to two objects supposed to
- be placed in that relation; and examine them in all the situations,
- of which they are susceptible. I immediately perceive, that they are
- contiguous in time and place, and that the object we call cause precedes
- the other we call effect. In no one instance can I go any farther,
- nor is it possible for me to discover any third relation betwixt these
- objects. I therefore enlarge my view to comprehend several instances;
- where I find like objects always existing in like relations of
- contiguity and succession. At first sight this seems to serve but little
- to my purpose. The reflection on several instances only repeats the
- same objects; and therefore can never give rise to a new idea. But upon
- farther enquiry I find, that the repetition is not in every particular
- the same, but produces a new impression, and by that means the idea,
- which I at present examine. For after a frequent repetition, I find,
- that upon the appearance of one of the objects, the mind is determined
- by custom to consider its usual attendant, and to consider it in a
- stronger light upon account of its relation to the first object. It is
- this impression, then, or determination, which affords me the idea of
- necessity.
- I doubt not but these consequences will at first sight be received
- without difficulty, as being evident deductions from principles, which
- we have already established, and which we have often employed in our
- reasonings. This evidence both in the first principles, and in the
- deductions, may seduce us unwarily into the conclusion, and make us
- imagine it contains nothing extraordinary, nor worthy of our curiosity.
- But though such an inadvertence may facilitate the reception of this
- reasoning, it will make it be the more easily forgot; for which reason
- I think it proper to give warning, that I have just now examined one of
- the most sublime questions in philosophy, viz. that concerning the power
- and efficacy of causes; where all the sciences seem so much interested.
- Such a warning will naturally rouze up the attention of the reader, and
- make him desire a more full account of my doctrine, as well as of the
- arguments, on which it is founded. This request is so reasonable, that
- I cannot refuse complying with it; especially as I am hopeful that these
- principles, the more they are examined, will acquire the more force and
- evidence.
- There is no question, which on account of its importance, as well as
- difficulty, has caused more disputes both among antient and modern
- philosophers, than this concerning the efficacy of causes, or that
- quality which makes them be followed by their effects. But before they
- entered upon these disputes, methinks it would not have been improper to
- have examined what idea we have of that efficacy, which is the subject
- of the controversy. This is what I find principally wanting in their
- reasonings, and what I shall here endeavour to supply.
- I begin with observing that the terms of EFFICACY, AGENCY, POWER, FORCE,
- ENERGY, NECESSITY, CONNEXION, and PRODUCTIVE QUALITY, are all nearly
- synonymous; and therefore it is an absurdity to employ any of them in
- defining the rest. By this observation we reject at once all the vulgar
- definitions, which philosophers have given of power and efficacy; and
- instead of searching for the idea in these definitions, must look for
- it in the impressions, from which it is originally derived. If it be a
- compound idea, it must arise from compound impressions. If simple, from
- simple impressions.
- I believe the most general and most popular explication of this
- matter, is to say [See Mr. Locke, chapter of power.], that finding from
- experience, that there are several new productions in matter, such
- as the motions and variations of body, and concluding that there must
- somewhere be a power capable of producing them, we arrive at last by
- this reasoning at the idea of power and efficacy. But to be convinced
- that this explication is more popular than philosophical, we need but
- reflect on two very obvious principles. First, That reason alone can
- never give rise to any original idea, and secondly, that reason, as
- distinguished from experience, can never make us conclude, that a cause
- or productive quality is absolutely requisite to every beginning of
- existence. Both these considerations have been sufficiently explained:
- and therefore shall not at present be any farther insisted on.
- I shall only infer from them, that since reason can never give rise to
- the idea of efficacy, that idea must be derived from experience, and
- from some particular instances of this efficacy, which make their
- passage into the mind by the common channels of sensation or reflection.
- Ideas always represent their objects or impressions; and vice versa,
- there are some objects necessary to give rise to every idea. If we
- pretend, therefore, to have any just idea of this efficacy, we must
- produce some instance, wherein the efficacy is plainly discoverable to
- the mind, and its operations obvious to our consciousness or sensation.
- By the refusal of this, we acknowledge, that the idea is impossible and
- imaginary, since the principle of innate ideas, which alone can save
- us from this dilemma, has been already refuted, and is now almost
- universally rejected in the learned world. Our present business,
- then, must be to find some natural production, where the operation and
- efficacy of a cause can be clearly conceived and comprehended by the
- mind, without any danger of obscurity or mistake.
- In this research we meet with very little encouragement from that
- prodigious diversity, which is found in the opinions of those
- philosophers, who have pretended to explain the secret force and energy
- of causes. [See Father Malbranche, Book vi. Part 2, chap. 3. And the
- illustrations upon it.] There are some, who maintain, that bodies
- operate by their substantial form; others, by their accidents or
- qualities; several, by their matter and form; some, by their form and
- accidents; others, by certain virtues and faculties distinct from all
- this. All these sentiments again are mixed and varyed in a thousand
- different ways; and form a strong presumption, that none of them have
- any solidity or evidence, and that the supposition of an efficacy in any
- of the known qualities of matter is entirely without foundation.
- This presumption must encrease upon us, when we consider, that these
- principles of substantial forms, and accidents, and faculties, are not
- in reality any of the known properties of bodies, but are perfectly
- unintelligible and inexplicable. For it is evident philosophers would
- never have had recourse to such obscure and uncertain principles, had
- they met with any satisfaction in such as are clear and intelligible;
- especially in such an affair as this, which must be an object of the
- simplest understanding, if not of the senses. Upon the whole, we
- may conclude, that it is impossible in any one instance to shew the
- principle, in which the force and agency of a cause is placed; and that
- the most refined and most vulgar understandings are equally at a loss
- in this particular. If any one think proper to refute this assertion,
- he need not put himself to the trouble of inventing any long reasonings:
- but may at once shew us an instance of a cause, where we discover the
- power or operating principle. This defiance we are obliged frequently
- to make use of, as being almost the only means of proving a negative in
- philosophy.
- The small success, which has been met with in all the attempts to fix
- this power, has at last obliged philosophers to conclude, that the
- ultimate force and efficacy of nature is perfectly unknown to us,
- and that it is in vain we search for it in all the known qualities of
- matter. In this opinion they are almost unanimous; and it is only in the
- inference they draw from it, that they discover any difference in their
- sentiments. For some of them, as the CARTESIANS in particular, having
- established it as a principle, that we are perfectly acquainted with the
- essence of matter, have very naturally inferred, that it is endowed with
- no efficacy, and that it is impossible for it of itself to communicate
- motion, or produce any of those effects, which we ascribe to it. As the
- essence of matter consists in extension, and as extension implies not
- actual motion, but only mobility; they conclude, that the energy, which
- produces the motion, cannot lie in the extension.
- This conclusion leads them into another, which they regard as perfectly
- unavoidable. Matter, say they, is in itself entirely unactive, and
- deprived of any power, by which it may produce, or continue, or
- communicate motion: But since these effects are evident to our senses,
- and since the power, that produces them, must be placed somewhere, it
- must lie in the DEITY, or that divine being, who contains in his nature
- all excellency and perfection. It is the deity, therefore, who is the
- prime mover of the universe, and who not only first created matter, and
- gave it it's original impulse, but likewise by a continued exertion of
- omnipotence, supports its existence, and successively bestows on it
- all those motions, and configurations, and qualities, with which it is
- endowed.
- This opinion is certainly very curious, and well worth our attention;
- but it will appear superfluous to examine it in this place, if we
- reflect a moment on our present purpose in taking notice of it. We
- have established it as a principle, that as all ideas are derived from
- impressions, or some precedent perceptions, it is impossible we can have
- any idea of power and efficacy, unless some instances can be produced,
- wherein this power is perceived to exert itself. Now, as these instances
- can never be discovered in body, the Cartesians, proceeding upon their
- principle of innate ideas, have had recourse to a supreme spirit or
- deity, whom they consider as the only active being in the universe, and
- as the immediate cause of every alteration in matter. But the principle
- of innate ideas being allowed to be false, it follows, that the
- supposition of a deity can serve us in no stead, in accounting for that
- idea of agency, which we search for in vain in all the objects, which
- are presented to our senses, or which we are internally conscious of in
- our own minds. For if every idea be derived from an impression, the idea
- of a deity proceeds from the same origin; and if no impression, either
- of sensation or reflection, implies any force or efficacy, it is equally
- impossible to discover or even imagine any such active principle in the
- deity. Since these philosophers, therefore, have concluded, that
- matter cannot be endowed with any efficacious principle, because it
- is impossible to discover in it such a principle; the same course of
- reasoning should determine them to exclude it from the supreme being. Or
- if they esteem that opinion absurd and impious, as it really is, I shall
- tell them how they may avoid it; and that is, by concluding from the
- very first, that they have no adequate idea of power or efficacy in
- any object; since neither in body nor spirit, neither in superior nor
- inferior natures, are they able to discover one single instance of it.
- The same conclusion is unavoidable upon the hypothesis of those, who
- maintain the efficacy of second causes, and attribute a derivative, but
- a real power and energy to matter. For as they confess, that this energy
- lies not in any of the known qualities of matter, the difficulty still
- remains concerning the origin of its idea. If we have really an idea
- of power, we may attribute power to an unknown quality: But as it is
- impossible, that that idea can be derived from such a quality, and as
- there is nothing in known qualities, which can produce it; it follows
- that we deceive ourselves, when we imagine we are possest of any idea
- of this kind, after the manner we commonly understand it. All ideas are
- derived from, and represent impressions. We never have any impression,
- that contains any power or efficacy. We never therefore have any idea of
- power.
- Some have asserted, that we feel an energy, or power, in our own mind;
- and that having in this manner acquired the idea of power, we transfer
- that quality to matter, where we are not able immediately to discover
- it. The motions of our body, and the thoughts and sentiments of our
- mind, (say they) obey the will; nor do we seek any farther to acquire
- a just notion of force or power. But to convince us how fallacious this
- reasoning is, we need only consider, that the will being here considered
- as a cause, has no more a discoverable connexion with its effects, than
- any material cause has with its proper effect. So far from perceiving
- the connexion betwixt an act of volition, and a motion of the body;
- it is allowed that no effect is more inexplicable from the powers and
- essence of thought and matter. Nor is the empire of the will over
- our mind more intelligible. The effect is there distinguishable
- and separable from the cause, and coued not be foreseen without the
- experience of their constant conjunction. We have command over our mind
- to a certain degree, but beyond that, lose all empire over it: And it is
- evidently impossible to fix any precise bounds to our authority, where
- we consult not experience. In short, the actions of the mind are, in
- this respect, the same with those of matter. We perceive only their
- constant conjunction; nor can we ever reason beyond it. No internal
- impression has an apparent energy, more than external objects have.
- Since, therefore, matter is confessed by philosophers to operate by
- an unknown force, we should in vain hope to attain an idea of force by
- consulting our own minds. [Footnote 8.]
- [Footnote 8. The same imperfection attends our ideas of the
- Deity; but this can have no effect either on religion or
- morals. The order of the universe proves an omnipotent mind;
- that is, a mind whose wili is CONSTANTLY ATTENDED with the
- obedience of every creature and being. Nothing more is
- requisite to give a foundation to all the articles of
- religion, nor is It necessary we shoud form a distinct idea
- of the force and energy of the supreme Being.]
- It has been established as a certain principle, that general or abstract
- ideas are nothing but individual ones taken in a certain light, and
- that, in reflecting on any object, it is as impossible to exclude from
- our thought all particular degrees of quantity and quality as from the
- real nature of things. If we be possest, therefore, of any idea of power
- in general, we must also be able to conceive some particular species
- of it; and as power cannot subsist alone, but is always regarded as an
- attribute of some being or existence, we must be able to place this
- power in some particular being, and conceive that being as endowed with
- a real force and energy, by which such a particular effect necessarily
- results from its operation. We must distinctly and particularly conceive
- the connexion betwixt the cause and effect, and be able to pronounce,
- from a simple view of the one, that it must be followed or preceded by
- the other. This is the true manner of conceiving a particular power in
- a particular body: and a general idea being impossible without an
- individual; where the latter is impossible, it is certain the former
- can never exist. Now nothing is more evident, than that the human mind
- cannot form such an idea of two objects, as to conceive any connexion
- betwixt them, or comprehend distinctly that power or efficacy, by which
- they are united. Such a connexion would amount to a demonstration, and
- would imply the absolute impossibility for the one object not to follow,
- or to be conceived not to follow upon the other: Which kind of connexion
- has already been rejected in all cases. If any one is of a contrary
- opinion, and thinks he has attained a notion of power in any particular
- object, I desire he may point out to me that object. But till I meet
- with such-a-one, which I despair of, I cannot forbear concluding, that
- since we can never distinctly conceive how any particular power can
- possibly reside in any particular object, we deceive ourselves in
- imagining we can form any such general idea.
- Thus upon the whole we may infer, that when we talk of any being,
- whether of a superior or inferior nature, as endowed with a power
- or force, proportioned to any effect; when we speak of a necessary
- connexion betwixt objects, and suppose, that this connexion depends upon
- an efficacy or energy, with which any of these objects are endowed; in
- all these expressions, so applied, we have really no distinct meaning,
- and make use only of common words, without any clear and determinate
- ideas. But as it is more probable, that these expressions do here lose
- their true meaning by being wrong applied, than that they never have
- any meaning; it will be proper to bestow another consideration on this
- subject, to see if possibly we can discover the nature and origin of
- those ideas, we annex to them.
- Suppose two objects to be presented to us, of which the one is the
- cause and the other the effect; it is plain, that from the simple
- consideration of one, or both these objects we never shall perceive the
- tie by which they are united, or be able certainly to pronounce, that
- there is a connexion betwixt them. It is not, therefore, from any one
- instance, that we arrive at the idea of cause and effect, of a necessary
- connexion of power, of force, of energy, and of efficacy. Did we never
- see any but particular conjunctions of objects, entirely different from
- each other, we should never be able to form any such ideas.
- But again; suppose we observe several instances, in which the same
- objects are always conjoined together, we immediately conceive a
- connexion betwixt them, and begin to draw an inference from one
- to another. This multiplicity of resembling instances, therefore,
- constitutes the very essence of power or connexion, and is the source
- from which the idea of it arises. In order, then, to understand the idea
- of power, we must consider that multiplicity; nor do I ask more to give
- a solution of that difficulty, which has so long perplexed us. For thus
- I reason. The repetition of perfectly similar instances can never alone
- give rise to an original idea, different from what is to be found in any
- particular instance, as has been observed, and as evidently follows from
- our fundamental principle, that all ideas are copyed from impressions.
- Since therefore the idea of power is a new original idea, not to be
- found in any one instance, and which yet arises from the repetition of
- several instances, it follows, that the repetition alone has not that
- effect, but must either discover or produce something new, which is the
- source of that idea. Did the repetition neither discover nor produce
- anything new, our ideas might be multiplyed by it, but would not
- be enlarged above what they are upon the observation of one single
- instance. Every enlargement, therefore, (such as the idea of power or
- connexion) which arises from the multiplicity of similar instances,
- is copyed from some effects of the multiplicity, and will be perfectly
- understood by understanding these effects. Wherever we find anything new
- to be discovered or produced by the repetition, there we must place the
- power, and must never look for it in any other object.
- But it is evident, in the first place, that the repetition of like
- objects in like relations of succession and contiguity discovers nothing
- new in any one of them: since we can draw no inference from it, nor make
- it a subject either of our demonstrative or probable reasonings;[Sect.
- 6.] as has been already proved. Nay suppose we coued draw an inference,
- it would be of no consequence in the present case; since no kind of
- reasoning can give rise to a new idea, such as this of power is; but
- wherever we reason, we must antecedently be possest of clear ideas,
- which may be the objects of our reasoning. The conception always
- precedes the understanding; and where the one is obscure, the other is
- uncertain; where the one fails, the other must fail also.
- Secondly, It is certain that this repetition of similar objects in
- similar situations produces nothing new either in these objects, or
- in any external body. For it will readily be allowed, that the several
- instances we have of the conjunction of resembling causes and effects
- are in themselves entirely independent, and that the communication
- of motion, which I see result at present from the shock of two
- billiard-balls, is totally distinct from that which I saw result from
- such an impulse a twelve-month ago. These impulses have no influence
- on each other. They are entirely divided by time and place; and the one
- might have existed and communicated motion, though the other never had
- been in being.
- There is, then, nothing new either discovered or produced in any objects
- by their constant conjunction, and by the uninterrupted resemblance
- of their relations of succession and contiguity. But it is from this
- resemblance, that the ideas of necessity, of power, and of efficacy, are
- derived. These ideas, therefore, represent not anything, that does or
- can belong to the objects, which are constantly conjoined. This is
- an argument, which, in every view we can examine it, will be found
- perfectly unanswerable. Similar instances are still the first source
- of our idea of power or necessity; at the same time that they have no
- influence by their similarity either on each other, or on any external
- object. We must, therefore, turn ourselves to some other quarter to seek
- the origin of that idea.
- Though the several resembling instances, which give rise to the idea of
- power, have no influence on each other, and can never produce any new
- quality in the object, which can be the model of that idea, yet the
- observation of this resemblance produces a new impression in the mind,
- which is its real model. For after we have observed the resemblance in
- a sufficient number of instances, we immediately feel a determination of
- the mind to pass from one object to its usual attendant, and to conceive
- it in a stronger light upon account of that relation. This determination
- is the only effect of the resemblance; and therefore must be the same
- with power or efficacy, whose idea is derived from the resemblance. The
- several instances of resembling conjunctions lead us into the notion of
- power and necessity. These instances are in themselves totally distinct
- from each other, and have no union but in the mind, which observes
- them, and collects their ideas. Necessity, then, is the effect of this
- observation, and is nothing but an internal impression of the mind,
- or a determination to carry our thoughts from one object to another.
- Without considering it in this view, we can never arrive at the most
- distant notion of it, or be able to attribute it either to external or
- internal objects, to spirit or body, to causes or effects.
- The necessary connexion betwixt causes and effects is the foundation of
- our inference from one to the other. The foundation of our inference is
- the transition arising from the accustomed union. These are, therefore,
- the same.
- The idea of necessity arises from some impression. There is no
- impression conveyed by our senses, which can give rise to that idea. It
- must, therefore, be derived from some internal impression, or impression
- of reflection. There is no internal impression, which has any relation
- to the present business, but that propensity, which custom produces, to
- pass from an object to the idea of its usual attendant. This therefore
- is the essence of necessity. Upon the whole, necessity is something,
- that exists in the mind, not in objects; nor is it possible for us ever
- to form the most distant idea of it, considered as a quality in bodies.
- Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is nothing but that
- determination of the thought to pass from causes to effects, and from
- effects to causes, according to their experienced union.
- Thus as the necessity, which makes two times two equal to four, or three
- angles of a triangle equal to two right ones, lies only in the act of
- the understanding, by which we consider and compare these ideas; in like
- manner the necessity or power, which unites causes and effects, lies
- in the determination of the mind to pass from the one to the other. The
- efficacy or energy of causes is neither placed in the causes themselves,
- nor in the deity, nor in the concurrence of these two principles; but
- belongs entirely to the soul, which considers the union of two or more
- objects in all past instances. It is here that the real power of causes
- is placed along with their connexion and necessity.
- I am sensible, that of all the paradoxes, which I, have had, or shall
- hereafter have occasion to advance in the course of this treatise, the
- present one is the most violent, and that it is merely by dint of solid
- proof and reasoning I can ever hope it will have admission, and overcome
- the inveterate prejudices of mankind. Before we are reconciled to this
- doctrine, how often must we repeat to ourselves, that the simple view of
- any two objects or actions, however related, can never give us any idea,
- of power, or of a connexion betwixt them: that this idea arises from
- the repetition of their union: that the repetition neither discovers nor
- causes any thing in the objects, but has an influence only on the mind,
- by that customary transition it produces: that this customary transition
- is, therefore, the same with the power and necessity; which are
- consequently qualities of perceptions, not of objects, and are
- internally felt by the soul, and not perceivd externally in bodies?
- There is commonly an astonishment attending every thing extraordinary;
- and this astonishment changes immediately into the highest degree
- of esteem or contempt, according as we approve or disapprove of the
- subject. I am much afraid, that though the foregoing reasoning appears
- to me the shortest and most decisive imaginable; yet with the generality
- of readers the biass of the mind will prevail, and give them a prejudice
- against the present doctrine.
- This contrary biass is easily accounted for. It is a common observation,
- that the mind has a great propensity to spread itself on external
- objects, and to conjoin with them any internal impressions, which they
- occasion, and which always make their appearance at the same time that
- these objects discover themselves to the senses. Thus as certain sounds
- and smells are always found to attend certain visible objects, we
- naturally imagine a conjunction, even in place, betwixt the objects and
- qualities, though the qualities be of such a nature as to admit of no
- such conjunction, and really exist no where. But of this more fully
- hereafter [Part IV, Sect. 5.]. Mean while it is sufficient to observe,
- that the same propensity is the reason, why we suppose necessity and
- power to lie in the objects we consider, not in our mind that considers
- them; notwithstanding it is not possible for us to form the most distant
- idea of that quality, when it is not taken for the determination of the
- mind, to pass from the idea of an object to that of its usual attendant.
- But though this be the only reasonable account we can give of necessity,
- the contrary notion if; so riveted in the mind from the principles
- above-mentioned, that I doubt not but my sentiments will be treated by
- many as extravagant and ridiculous. What! the efficacy of causes lie
- in the determination of the mind! As if causes did not operate entirely
- independent of the mind, and would not continue their operation,
- even though there was no mind existent to contemplate them, or reason
- concerning them. Thought may well depend on causes for its operation,
- but not causes on thought. This is to reverse the order of nature, and
- make that secondary, which is really primary, To every operation there
- is a power proportioned; and this power must be placed on the body, that
- operates. If we remove the power from one cause, we must ascribe it to
- another: But to remove it from all causes, and bestow it on a being,
- that is no ways related to the cause or effect, but by perceiving them,
- is a gross absurdity, and contrary to the most certain principles of
- human reason.
- I can only reply to all these arguments, that the case is here much the
- same, as if a blind man should pretend to find a great many absurdities
- in the supposition, that the colour of scarlet is not the same with the
- sound of a trumpet, nor light the same with solidity. If we have really
- no idea of a power or efficacy in any object, or of any real connexion
- betwixt causes and effects, it will be to little purpose to prove, that
- an efficacy is necessary in all operations. We do not understand our own
- meaning in talking so, but ignorantly confound ideas, which are entirely
- distinct from each other. I am, indeed, ready to allow, that there may
- be several qualities both in material and immaterial objects, with which
- we are utterly unacquainted; and if we please to call these POWER or
- EFFICACY, it will be of little consequence to the world. But when,
- instead of meaning these unknown qualities, we make the terms of power
- and efficacy signify something, of which we have a clear idea, and which
- is incompatible with those objects, to which we apply it, obscurity
- and error begin then to take place, and we are led astray by a false
- philosophy. This is the case, when we transfer the determination of the
- thought to external objects, and suppose any real intelligible connexion
- betwixt them; that being a quality, which can only belong to the mind
- that considers them.
- As to what may be said, that the operations of nature are independent
- of our thought and reasoning, I allow it; and accordingly have observed,
- that objects bear to each other the relations of contiguity and
- succession: that like objects may be observed in several instances to
- have like relations; and that all this is independent of, and antecedent
- to the operations of the understanding. But if we go any farther, and
- ascribe a power or necessary connexion to these objects; this is what
- we can never observe in them, but must draw the idea of it from what we
- feel internally in contemplating them. And this I carry so far, that I
- am ready to convert my present reasoning into an instance of it, by a
- subtility, which it will not be difficult to comprehend.
- When any object is presented to us, it immediately conveys to the mind
- a lively idea of that object, which is usually found to attend it; and
- this determination of the mind forms the necessary connexion of these
- objects. But when we change the point of view, from the objects to the
- perceptions; in that case the impression is to be considered as the
- cause, and the lively idea as the effect; and their necessary connexion
- is that new determination, which we feel to pass from the idea of the
- one to that of the other. The uniting principle among our internal
- perceptions is as unintelligible as that among external objects, and
- is not known to us any other way than by experience. Now the nature
- and effects of experience have been already sufficiently examined and
- explained. It never gives us any insight into the internal structure or
- operating principle of objects, but only accustoms the mind to pass from
- one to another.
- It is now time to collect all the different parts of this reasoning,
- and by joining them together form an exact definition of the relation of
- cause and effect, which makes the subject of the present enquiry. This
- order would not have been excusable, of first examining our inference
- from the relation before we had explained the relation itself, had it
- been possible to proceed in a different method. But as the nature of the
- relation depends so much on that of the inference, we have been obliged
- to advance in this seemingly preposterous manner, and make use of terms
- before we were able exactly to define them, or fix their meaning. We
- shall now correct this fault by giving a precise definition of cause and
- effect.
- There may two definitions be given of this relation, which are only
- different, by their presenting a different view of the same object,
- and making us consider it either as a philosophical or as a natural
- relation; either as a comparison of two ideas, or as an association
- betwixt them. We may define a CAUSE to be An object precedent and
- contiguous to another, and where all the objects resembling the former
- are placed in like relations of precedency and contiguity to those
- objects that resemble the latter. I If this definition be esteemed
- defective, because drawn from objects foreign to the cause, we may
- substitute this other definition in its place, viz. A CAUSE is an object
- precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it, that the
- idea, of the one determines the mind to form the idea of the other, and
- the impression of the one to form a more lively idea of the other. 2
- should this definition also be rejected for the same reason, I know no
- other remedy, than that the persons, who express this delicacy, should
- substitute a juster definition in its place. But for my part I must own
- my incapacity for such an undertaking. When I examine with the utmost
- accuracy those objects, which are commonly denominated causes and
- effects, I find, in considering a single instance, that the one object
- is precedent and contiguous to the other; and in inlarging my view
- to consider several instances, I find only, that like objects are
- constantly placed in like relations of succession and contiguity. Again,
- when I consider the influence of this constant conjunction, I perceive,
- that such a relation can never be an object of reasoning, and can never
- operate upon the mind, but by means of custom, which determines the
- imagination to make a transition from the idea of one object to that
- of its usual attendant, and from the impression of one to a more lively
- idea of the other. However extraordinary these sentiments may appear,
- I think it fruitless to trouble myself with any farther enquiry or
- reasoning upon the subject, but shall repose myself on them as on
- established maxims.
- It will only be proper, before we leave this subject, to draw some
- corrollaries from it, by which we may remove several prejudices and
- popular errors, that have very much prevailed in philosophy. First, We
- may learn from the foregoing, doctrine, that all causes are of the
- same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that
- distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes and causes
- sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and
- exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is derived
- from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observed,
- the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause
- of any kind. For the same reason we must reject the distinction betwixt
- cause and occasion, when supposed to signify any thing essentially
- different from each other. If constant conjunction be implyed in what we
- call occasion, it is a real cause. If not, it is no relation at all, and
- cannot give rise to any argument or reasoning.
- Secondly, The same course of reasoning will make us conclude, that there
- is but one kind of necessity, as there is but one kind of cause, and
- that the common distinction betwixt moral and physical necessity
- is without any foundation in nature. This clearly appears from the
- precedent explication of necessity. It is the constant conjunction of
- objects, along with the determination of the mind, which constitutes
- a physical necessity: And the removal of these is the same thing with
- chance. As objects must either be conjoined or not, and as the mind must
- either be determined or not to pass from one object to another, it
- is impossible to admit of any medium betwixt chance and an absolute
- necessity. In weakening this conjunction and determination you do not
- change the nature of the necessity; since even in the operation of
- bodies, these have different degrees of constancy and force, without
- producing a different species of that relation.
- The distinction, which we often make betwixt POWER and the EXERCISE of
- it, is equally without foundation.
- Thirdly, We may now be able fully to overcome all that repugnance, which
- it is so natural for us to entertain against the foregoing reasoning,
- by which we endeavoured to prove, that the necessity of a cause to
- every beginning of existence is not founded on any arguments either
- demonstrative or intuitive. Such an opinion will not appear strange
- after the foregoing definitions. If we define a cause to be an
- object precedent and contiguous to another, and where all the objects
- resembling the farmer are placed in a like relation of priority and
- contiguity to those objects, that resemble the latter; we may easily
- conceive, that there is no absolute nor metaphysical necessity, that
- every beginning of existence should be attended with such an object. If
- we define a cause to be, AN OBJECT PRECEDENT AND CONTIGUOUS TO ANOTHER,
- AND SO UNITED WITH IT IN THE IMAGINATION, THAT THE IDEA OF THE ONE
- DETERMINES THE MIND TO FORM THE IDEA OF THE OTHER, AND THE IMPRESSION
- OF THE ONE TO FORM A MORE LIVELY IDEA OF THE OTHER; we shall make still
- less difficulty of assenting to this opinion. Such an influence on the
- mind is in itself perfectly extraordinary and incomprehensible; nor can
- we be certain of its reality, but from experience and observation.
- I shall add as a fourth corrollary that we can never have reason to
- believe that any object exists, of which we cannot form an idea. For as
- all our reasonings concerning existence are derived from causation,
- and as all our reasonings concerning causation are derived from
- the experienced conjunction of objects, not from any reasoning or
- reflection, the same experience must give us a notion of these objects,
- and must remove all mystery from our conclusions. This is so evident,
- that it would scarce have merited our attention, were it not to obviate
- certain objections of this kind, which might arise against the following
- reasonings concerning matter and substance. I need not observe, that
- a full knowledge of the object is not requisite, but only of those
- qualities of it, which we believe to exist.
- SECT. XV. RULES BY WHICH TO JUDGE OF CAUSES AND EFFECTS.
- According to the precedent doctrine, there are no objects which by the
- mere survey, without consulting experience, we can determine to be the
- causes of any other; and no objects, which we can certainly determine in
- the same manner not to be the causes. Any thing may produce any thing.
- Creation, annihilation, motion, reason, volition; all these may arise
- from one another, or from any other object we can imagine. Nor will this
- appear strange, if we compare two principles explained above, THAT THE
- CONSTANT CONJUNCTION OF OBJECTS DETERMINES THEIR CAUSATION, AND [Part I.
- Sect. 5.] THAT, PROPERTY SPEAKING, NO OBJECTS ARE CONTRARY TO EACH OTHER
- BUT EXISTENCE AND NON-EXISTENCE. Where objects are not contrary,
- nothing hinders them from having that constant conjunction, on which the
- relation of cause and effect totally depends.
- Since therefore it is possible for all objects to become causes or
- effects to each other, it may be proper to fix some general rules, by
- which we may know when they really are so.
- (1) The cause and effect must be contiguous in space and time.
- (2) The cause must be prior to the effect.
- (3) There must be a constant union betwixt the cause and effect. It is
- chiefly this quality, that constitutes the relation.
- (4) The same cause always produces the same effect, and the same effect
- never arises but from the same cause. This principle we derive from
- experience, and is the source of most of our philosophical reasonings.
- For when by any clear experiment we have discovered the causes or
- effects of any phaenomenon, we immediately extend our observation to
- every phenomenon of the same kind, without waiting for that constant
- repetition, from which the first idea of this relation is derived.
- (5) There is another principle, which hangs upon this, viz. that where
- several different objects produce the same effect, it must be by means
- of some quality, which we discover to be common amongst them. For as
- like effects imply like causes, we must always ascribe the causation to
- the circumstance, wherein we discover the resemblance.
- (6) The following principle is founded on the same reason. The
- difference in the effects of two resembling objects must proceed from
- that particular, in which they differ. For as like causes always
- produce like effects, when in any instance we find our expectation to be
- disappointed, we must conclude that this irregularity proceeds from some
- difference in the causes.
- (7) When any object encreases or diminishes with the encrease or
- diminution of its cause, it is to be regarded as a compounded effect,
- derived from the union of the several different effects, which arise
- from the several different parts of the cause. The absence or presence
- of one part of the cause is here supposed to be always attended with
- the absence or presence of a proportionable part of the effect. This
- constant conjunction sufficiently proves, that the one part is the cause
- of the other. We must, however, beware not to draw such a conclusion
- from a few experiments. A certain degree of heat gives pleasure; if you
- diminish that heat, the pleasure diminishes; but it does not follow,
- that if you augment it beyond a certain degree, the pleasure will
- likewise augment; for we find that it degenerates into pain.
- (8) The eighth and last rule I shall take notice of is, that an object,
- which exists for any time in its full perfection without any effect, is
- not the sole cause of that effect, but requires to be assisted by some
- other principle, which may forward its influence and operation. For as
- like effects necessarily follow from like causes, and in a contiguous
- time and place, their separation for a moment shews, that these causes
- are not compleat ones.
- Here is all the LOGIC I think proper to employ in my reasoning; and
- perhaps even this was not very necessary, but might have been supplyd by
- the natural principles of our understanding. Our scholastic head-pieces
- and logicians shew no such superiority above the mere vulgar in their
- reason and ability, as to give us any inclination to imitate them in
- delivering a long system of rules and precepts to direct our judgment,
- in philosophy. All the rules of this nature are very easy in their
- invention, but extremely difficult in their application; and even
- experimental philosophy, which seems the most natural and simple of any,
- requires the utmost stretch of human judgment. There is no phaenomenon
- in nature, but what is compounded and modifyd by so many different
- circumstances, that in order to arrive at the decisive point, we
- must carefully separate whatever is superfluous, and enquire by new
- experiments, if every particular circumstance of the first experiment
- was essential to it. These new experiments are liable to a discussion
- of the same kind; so that the utmost constancy is requird to make us
- persevere in our enquiry, and the utmost sagacity to choose the right
- way among so many that present themselves. If this be the case even
- in natural philosophy, how much more in moral, where there is a much
- greater complication of circumstances, and where those views and
- sentiments, which are essential to any action of the mind, are so
- implicit and obscure, that they often escape our strictest attention,
- and are not only unaccountable in their causes, but even unknown in
- their existence? I am much afraid lest the small success I meet with
- in my enquiries will make this observation bear the air of an apology
- rather than of boasting.
- If any thing can give me security in this particular, it will be the
- enlarging of the sphere of my experiments as much as possible; for which
- reason it may be proper in this place to examine the reasoning faculty
- of brutes, as well as that of human creatures.
- SECT. XVI OF THE REASON OF ANIMALS
- Next to the ridicule of denying an evident truth, is that of taking much
- pains to defend it; and no truth appears to me more evident, than that
- beasts are endowd with thought and reason as well as men. The arguments
- are in this case so obvious, that they never escape the most stupid and
- ignorant.
- We are conscious, that we ourselves, in adapting means to ends, are
- guided by reason and design, and that it is not ignorantly nor casually
- we perform those actions, which tend to self-preservation, to the
- obtaining pleasure, and avoiding pain. When therefore we see other
- creatures, in millions of instances, perform like actions, and direct
- them to the ends, all our principles of reason and probability carry us
- with an invincible force to believe the existence of a like cause. It is
- needless in my opinion to illustrate this argument by the enumeration
- of particulars. The smallest attention will supply us with more than are
- requisite. The resemblance betwixt the actions of animals and those
- of men is so entire in this respect, that the very first action of
- the first animal we shall please to pitch on, will afford us an
- incontestable argument for the present doctrine.
- This doctrine is as useful as it is obvious, and furnishes us with a
- kind of touchstone, by which we may try every system in this species
- of philosophy. It is from the resemblance of the external actions of
- animals to those we ourselves perform, that we judge their internal
- likewise to resemble ours; and the same principle of reasoning, carryd
- one step farther, will make us conclude that since our internal actions
- resemble each other, the causes, from which they are derivd, must also
- be resembling. When any hypothesis, therefore, is advancd to explain a
- mental operation, which is common to men and beasts, we must apply the
- same hypothesis to both; and as every true hypothesis will abide this
- trial, so I may venture to affirm, that no false one will ever be able
- to endure it. The common defect of those systems, which philosophers
- have employd to account for the actions of the mind, is, that they
- suppose such a subtility and refinement of thought, as not only exceeds
- the capacity of mere animals, but even of children and the common people
- in our own species; who are notwithstanding susceptible of the same
- emotions and affections as persons of the most accomplishd genius and
- understanding. Such a subtility is a dear proof of the falshood, as the
- contrary simplicity of the truth, of any system.
- Let us therefore put our present system concerning the nature of the
- understanding to this decisive trial, and see whether it will equally
- account for the reasonings of beasts as for these of the human species.
- Here we must make a distinction betwixt those actions of animals, which
- are of a vulgar nature, and seem to be on a level with their common
- capacities, and those more extraordinary instances of sagacity, which
- they sometimes discover for their own preservation, and the propagation
- of their species. A dog, that avoids fire and precipices, that shuns
- strangers, and caresses his master, affords us an instance of the first
- kind. A bird, that chooses with such care and nicety the place and
- materials of her nest, and sits upon her eggs for a due time, and in
- suitable season, with all the precaution that a chymist is capable of in
- the most delicate projection, furnishes us with a lively instance of the
- second.
- As to the former actions, I assert they proceed from a reasoning, that
- is not in itself different, nor founded on different principles, from
- that which appears in human nature. It is necessary in the first place,
- that there be some impression immediately present to their memory or
- senses, in order to be the foundation of their judgment. From the
- tone of voice the dog infers his masters anger, and foresees his own
- punishment. From a certain sensation affecting his smell, he judges his
- game not to be far distant from him.
- Secondly, The inference he draws from the present impression is built on
- experience, and on his observation of the conjunction of objects in past
- instances. As you vary this experience, he varies his reasoning. Make
- a beating follow upon one sign or motion for some time, and afterwards
- upon another; and he will successively draw different conclusions,
- according to his most recent experience.
- Now let any philosopher make a trial, and endeavour to explain that
- act of the mind, which we call BELIEF, and give an account of the
- principles, from which it is derivd, independent of the influence of
- custom on the imagination, and let his hypothesis be equally applicable
- to beasts as to the human species; and after he has done this, I promise
- to embrace his opinion. But at the same time I demand as an equitable
- condition, that if my system be the only one, which can answer to all
- these terms, it may be receivd as entirely satisfactory and convincing.
- And that it is the only one, is evident almost without any reasoning.
- Beasts certainly never perceive any real connexion among objects. It is
- therefore by experience they infer one from another. They can never by
- any arguments form a general conclusion, that those objects, of which
- they have had no experience, resemble those of which they have. It is
- therefore by means of custom alone, that experience operates upon them.
- All this was sufficiently evident with respect to man. But with respect
- to beasts there cannot be the least suspicion of mistake; which must be
- ownd to be a strong confirmation, or rather an invincible proof of my
- system.
- Nothing shews more the force of habit in reconciling us to any
- phaenomenoun, than this, that men are not astonished at the operations
- of their own reason, at the same time, that they admire the instinct
- of animals, and find a difficulty in explaining it, merely because it
- cannot be reducd tothe very same principles. To consider the matter
- aright, reason is nothing but a wonderful and unintelligible instinct in
- our souls, which carries us along a certain train of ideas, and endows
- them with particular qualities, according to their particular situations
- and relations. This instinct, it is true, arises from past observation
- and experience; but can any one give the ultimate reason, why past
- experience and observation produces such an effect, any more than why
- nature alone shoud produce it? Nature may certainly produce whatever
- can arise from habit: Nay, habit is nothing but one of the principles of
- nature, and derives all its force from that origin.
- PART IV. OF THE SCEPTICAL AND OTHER SYSTEMS OF PHILOSOPHY.
- SECT. I. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO REASON.
- In all demonstrative sciences the rules are certain and infallible; but
- when we apply them, our fallible said uncertain faculties are very apt
- to depart from them, and fall into error. We must, therefore, in every
- reasoning form a new judgment, as a check or controul on our first
- judgment or belief; and must enlarge our view to comprehend a kind of
- history of all the instances, wherein our understanding has deceived us,
- compared with those, wherein its testimony was just and true. Our reason
- must be considered as a kind of cause, of which truth is the natural
- effect; but such-a-one as by the irruption of other causes, and by the
- inconstancy of our mental powers, may frequently be prevented. By this
- means all knowledge degenerates into probability; and this probability
- is greater or less, according to our experience of the veracity or
- deceitfulness of our understanding, and according to the simplicity or
- intricacy of the question.
- There is no Algebraist nor Mathematician so expert in his science, as to
- place entire confidence in any truth immediately upon his discovery of
- it, or regard it as any thing, but a mere probability. Every time he
- runs over his proofs, his confidence encreases; but still more by the
- approbation of his friends; and is raised to its utmost perfection by
- the universal assent and applauses of the learned world. Now it is
- evident, that this gradual encrease of assurance is nothing but the
- addition of new probabilities, and is derived from the constant union of
- causes and effects, according to past experience and observation.
- In accompts of any length or importance, Merchants seldom trust to
- the infallible certainty of numbers for their security; but by the
- artificial structure of the accompts, produce a probability beyond what
- is derived from the skill and experience of the accomptant. For that
- is plainly of itself some degree of probability; though uncertain and
- variable, according to the degrees of his experience and length of
- the accompt. Now as none will maintain, that our assurance in a long
- numeration exceeds probability, I may safely affirm, that there scarce
- is any proposition concerning numbers, of which we can have a fuller
- security. For it is easily possible, by gradually diminishing the
- numbers, to reduce the longest series of addition to the most simple
- question, which can be formed, to an addition of two single numbers; and
- upon this supposition we shall find it impracticable to shew the precise
- limits of knowledge and of probability, or discover that particular
- number, at which the one ends and the other begins. But knowledge and
- probability are of such contrary and disagreeing natures, that they
- cannot well run insensibly into each other, and that because they will
- not divide, but must be either entirely present, or entirely absent.
- Besides, if any single addition were certain, every one would be so, and
- consequently the whole or total sum; unless the whole can be different
- from all its parts. I had almost said, that this was certain; but I
- reflect that it must reduce itself, as well as every other reasoning,
- and from knowledge degenerate into probability.
- Since therefore all knowledge resolves itself into probability, and
- becomes at last of the same nature with that evidence, which we employ
- in common life, we must now examine this latter species of reasoning,
- and see on what foundation it stands.
- In every judgment, which we can form concerning probability, as well
- as concerning knowledge, we ought always to correct the first judgment,
- derived from the nature of the object, by another judgment, derived from
- the nature of the understanding. It is certain a man of solid sense and
- long experience ought to have, and usually has, a greater assurance
- in his opinions, than one that is foolish and ignorant, and that our
- sentiments have different degrees of authority, even with ourselves, in
- proportion to the degrees of our reason and experience. In the man of
- the best sense and longest experience, this authority is never entire;
- since even such-a-one must be conscious of many errors in the past, and
- must still dread the like for the future. Here then arises a new species
- of probability to correct and regulate the first, and fix its just
- standard and proportion. As demonstration is subject to the controul of
- probability, so is probability liable to a new correction by a reflex
- act of the mind, wherein the nature of our understanding, and our
- reasoning from the first probability become our objects.
- Having thus found in every probability, beside the original uncertainty
- inherent in the subject, a new uncertainty derived from the weakness of
- that faculty, which judges, and having adjusted these two together,
- we are obliged by our reason to add a new doubt derived from the
- possibility of error in the estimation we make of the truth and fidelity
- of our faculties. This is a doubt, which immediately occurs to us, and
- of which, if we would closely pursue our reason, we cannot avoid giving
- a decision. But this decision, though it should be favourable to our
- preceding judgment, being founded only on probability, must weaken still
- further our first evidence, and must itself be weakened by a fourth
- doubt of the same kind, and so on in infinitum: till at last there
- remain nothing of the original probability, however great we may
- suppose it to have been, and however small the diminution by every new
- uncertainty. No finite object can subsist under a decrease repeated IN
- INFINITUM; and even the vastest quantity, which can enter into human
- imagination, must in this manner be reduced to nothing. Let our first
- belief be never so strong, it must infallibly perish by passing through
- so many new examinations, of which each diminishes somewhat of its force
- and vigour. When I reflect on the natural fallibility of my judgment,
- I have less confidence in my opinions, than when I only consider the
- objects concerning which I reason; and when I proceed still farther,
- to turn the scrutiny against every successive estimation I make of my
- faculties, all the rules of logic require a continual diminution, and at
- last a total extinction of belief and evidence.
- Should it here be asked me, whether I sincerely assent to this argument,
- which I seem to take such pains to inculcate, and whether I be really
- one of those sceptics, who hold that all is uncertain, and that our
- judgment is not in any thing possest of any measures of truth and
- falshood; I should reply, that this question is entirely superfluous,
- and that neither I, nor any other person was ever sincerely and
- constantly of that opinion. Nature, by an absolute and uncontroulable
- necessity has determined us to judge as well as to breathe and feel; nor
- can we any more forbear viewing certain objects in a stronger and
- fuller light, upon account of their customary connexion with a present
- impression, than we can hinder ourselves from thinking as long, as
- we are awake, or seeing the surrounding bodies, when we turn our eyes
- towards them in broad sunshine. Whoever has taken the pains to refute
- the cavils of this total scepticism, has really disputed without an
- antagonist, and endeavoured by arguments to establish a faculty, which
- nature has antecedently implanted in the mind, and rendered unavoidable.
- My intention then in displaying so carefully the arguments of that
- fantastic sect, is only to make the reader sensible of the truth of my
- hypothesis, that all our reasonings concerning causes and effects are
- derived from nothing but custom; and that belief is more properly an act
- of the sensitive, than of the cogitative part of our natures. I
- have here proved, that the very same principles, which make us form
- a decision upon any subject, and correct that decision by the
- consideration of our genius and capacity, and of the situation of our
- mind, when we examined that subject; I say, I have proved, that these
- same principles, when carryed farther, and applied to every new reflex
- judgment, must, by continually diminishing the original evidence, at
- last reduce it to nothing, and utterly subvert all belief and opinion.
- If belief, therefore, were a simple act of the thought, without any
- peculiar manner of conception, or the addition of a force and vivacity,
- it must infallibly destroy itself, and in every case terminate in a
- total suspense of judgment. But as experience will sufficiently convince
- any one, who thinks it worth while to try, that though he can find no
- error in the foregoing arguments, yet he still continues to believe, and
- think, and reason as usual, he may safely conclude, that his reasoning
- and belief is some sensation or peculiar manner of conception, which it
- is impossible for mere ideas and reflections to destroy.
- But here, perhaps, it may be demanded, how it happens, even upon my
- hypothesis, that these arguments above-explained produce not a total
- suspense of judgment, and after what manner the mind ever retains a
- degree of assurance in any subject? For as these new probabilities,
- which by their repetition perpetually diminish the original evidence,
- are founded on the very same principles, whether of thought or
- sensation, as the primary judgment, it may seem unavoidable, that in
- either case they must equally subvert it, and by the opposition,
- either of contrary thoughts or sensations, reduce the mind to a total
- uncertainty. I suppose, there is some question proposed to me, and
- that after revolving over the impressions of my memory and senses,
- and carrying my thoughts from them to such objects, as are commonly
- conjoined with them, I feel a stronger and more forcible conception on
- the one side, than on the other. This strong conception forms my first
- decision. I suppose, that afterwards I examine my judgment itself,
- and observing from experience, that it is sometimes just and sometimes
- erroneous, I consider it as regulated by contrary principles or causes,
- of which some lead to truth, and some to error; and in ballancing these
- contrary causes, I diminish by a new probability the assurance of my
- first decision. This new probability is liable to the same diminution as
- the foregoing, and so on, IN INFINITUM. It is therefore demanded, how
- it happens, that even after all we retain a degree of belief, which is
- sufficient for our purpose, either in philosophy or common life.
- I answer, that after the first and second decision; as the action of
- the mind becomes forced and unnatural, and the ideas faint and obscure;
- though the principles of judgment, and the ballancing of opposite
- causes be the same as at the very beginning; yet their influence on the
- imagination, and the vigour they add to, or diminish from the thought,
- is by no means equal. Where the mind reaches not its objects with
- easiness and facility, the same principles have not the same effect as
- in a more natural conception of the ideas; nor does the imagination feel
- a sensation, which holds any proportion with that which arises from
- its common judgments and opinions. The attention is on the stretch: The
- posture of the mind is uneasy; and the spirits being diverted from their
- natural course, are not governed in their movements by the same laws, at
- least not to the same degree, as when they flow in their usual channel.
- If we desire similar instances, it will not be very difficult to find
- them. The present subject of metaphysics will supply us abundantly. The
- same argument, which would have been esteemed convincing in a reasoning
- concerning history or politics, has little or no influence in these
- abstruser subjects, even though it be perfectly comprehended; and that
- because there is required a study and an effort of thought, in order
- to its being comprehended: And this effort of thought disturbs the
- operation of our sentiments, on which the belief depends. The case is
- the same in other subjects. The straining of the imagination always
- hinders the regular flowing of the passions and sentiments. A tragic
- poet, that would represent his heroes as very ingenious and witty in
- their misfortunes, would never touch the passions. As the emotions of
- the soul prevent any subtile reasoning and reflection, so these latter
- actions of the mind are equally prejudicial to the former. The mind, as
- well as the body, seems to be endowed with a certain precise degree of
- force and activity, which it never employs in one action, but at the
- expense of all the rest. This is more evidently true, where the actions
- are of quite different natures; since in that case the force of the mind
- is not only diverted, but even the disposition changed, so as to render
- us incapable of a sudden transition from one action to the other, and
- still more of performing both at once. No wonder, then, the conviction,
- which arises from a subtile reasoning, diminishes in proportion to the
- efforts, which the imagination makes to enter into the reasoning, and
- to conceive it in all its parts. Belief, being a lively conception, can
- never be entire, where it is not founded on something natural and easy.
- This I take to be the true state of the question, and cannot approve of
- that expeditious way, which some take with the sceptics, to reject
- at once all their arguments without enquiry or examination. If the
- sceptical reasonings be strong, say they, it is a proof, that reason may
- have some force and authority: if weak, they can never be sufficient to
- invalidate all the conclusions of our understanding. This argument is
- not just; because the sceptical reasonings, were it possible for them
- to exist, and were they not destroyed by their subtility, would
- be successively both strong and weak, according to the successive
- dispositions of the mind. Reason first appears in possession of the
- throne, prescribing laws, and imposing maxims, with an absolute sway and
- authority. Her enemy, therefore, is obliged to take shelter under
- her protection, and by making use of rational arguments to prove the
- fallaciousness and imbecility of reason, produces, in a manner, a
- patent under her hand and seal. This patent has at first an authority,
- proportioned to the present and immediate authority of reason, from
- which it is derived. But as it is supposed to be contradictory to
- reason, it gradually diminishes the force of that governing power
- and its own at the same time; till at last they both vanish away into
- nothing, by a regulax and just diminution. The sceptical and dogmatical
- reasons are of the same kind, though contrary in their operation and
- tendency; so that where the latter is strong, it has an enemy of equal
- force in the former to encounter; and as their forces were at first
- equal, they still continue so, as long as either of them subsists; nor
- does one of them lose any force in the contest, without taking as much
- from its antagonist. It is happy, therefore, that nature breaks the
- force of all sceptical arguments in time, and keeps them from having any
- considerable influence on the understanding. Were we to trust entirely
- to their self-destruction, that can never take place, until they have
- first subverted all conviction, and have totally destroyed human reason.
- SECT. II. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO THE SENSES.
- Thus the sceptic still continues to reason and believe, even though be
- asserts, that he cannot defend his reason by reason; and by the same
- rule he must assent to the principle concerning the existence of body,
- though he cannot pretend by any arguments of philosophy to maintain its
- veracity. Nature has not left this to his choice, and has doubtless,
- esteemed it an affair of too great importance to be trusted to our
- uncertain reasonings and speculations. We may well ask, What causes
- induce us to believe in the existence of body? but it is in vain to ask,
- Whether there be body or not? That is a point, which we must take for
- granted in all our reasonings.
- The subject, then, of our present enquiry is concerning the causes which
- induce us to believe in the existence of body: And my reasonings on this
- head I shall begin with a distinction, which at first sight may
- seem superfluous, but which will contribute very much to the perfect
- understanding of what follows. We ought to examine apart those two
- questions, which are commonly confounded together, viz. Why we attribute
- a continued existence to objects, even when they are not present to the
- senses; and why we suppose them to have an existence DISTINCT from the
- mind and perception. Under this last head I comprehend their
- situation as well as relations, their external position as well as
- the independence of their existence and operation. These two questions
- concerning the continued and distinct existence of body are intimately
- connected together. For if the objects of our senses continue to
- exist, even when they are not perceived, their existence is of course
- independent of and distinct from the perception: and vice versa, if
- their existence be independent of the perception and distinct from it,
- they must continue to exist, even though they be not perceived. But
- though the decision of the one question decides the other; yet that we
- may the more easily discover the principles of human nature, from whence
- the decision arises, we shall carry along with us this distinction, and
- shall consider, whether it be the senses, reason, or the imagination,
- that produces the opinion of a continued or of a distinct existence.
- These are the only questions, that are intelligible on the present
- subject. For as to the notion of external existence, when taken for
- something specially different from our perceptions [Part. II. Sect. 6.],
- we have already shewn its absurdity.
- To begin with the SENSES, it is evident these faculties are incapable of
- giving rise to the notion of the continued existence of their objects,
- after they no longer appear to the senses. For that is a contradiction
- in terms, and suppose that the senses continue to operate, even after
- they have ceased all manner of operation. These faculties, therefore, if
- they have any influence in the present case, must produce the opinion
- of a distinct, not of a continued existence; and in order to that, must
- present their impressions either as images and representations, or as
- these very distinct and external existences.
- That our senses offer not their impressions as the images of something
- distinct, or independent, and external, is evident; because they convey
- to us nothing but a single perception, and never give us the least
- intimation of any thing beyond. A single perception can never produce
- the idea of a double existence, but by some inference either of the
- reason or imagination. When the mind looks farther than what immediately
- appears to it, its conclusions can never be put to the account of the
- senses; and it certainly looks farther, when from a single perception it
- infers a double existence, and supposes the relations of resemblance and
- causation betwixt them.
- If our senses, therefore, suggest any idea of distinct existences,
- they must convey the impressions as those very existences, by a kind of
- fallacy and illusion. Upon this bead we may observe, that all sensations
- are felt by the mind, such as they really are, and that when we
- doubt, whether they present themselves as distinct objects, or as
- mere impressions, the difficulty is not concerning their nature, but
- concerning their relations and situation. Now if the senses presented
- our impressions as external to, and independent of ourselves, both the
- objects and ourselves must be obvious to our senses, otherwise they
- coued not be compared by these faculties. The difficulty, then, is how
- fax we are ourselves the objects of our senses.
- It is certain there is no question in philosophy more abstruse than
- that concerning identity, and the nature of the uniting principle, which
- constitutes a person. So far from being able by our senses merely to
- determine this question, we must have recourse to the most profound
- metaphysics to give a satisfactory answer to it; and in common life
- it is evident these ideas of self and person are never very fixed nor
- determinate. It is absurd, therefore, to imagine the senses can ever
- distinguish betwixt ourselves and external objects.
- Add to this, that every impression, external and internal, passions,
- affections, sensations, pains and pleasures, are originally on the same
- footing; and that whatever other differences we may observe among them,
- they appear, all of them, in their true colours, as impressions or
- perceptions. And indeed, if we consider the matter aright, it is scarce
- possible it should be otherwise, nor is it conceivable that our senses
- should be more capable of deceiving us in the situation and relations,
- than in the nature of our impressions. For since all actions and
- sensations of the mind are known to us by consciousness, they must
- necessarily appear in every particular what they are, and be what they
- appear. Every thing that enters the mind, being in reality a perception,
- it is impossible any thing should to feeling appear different. This were
- to suppose, that even where we are most intimately conscious, we might
- be mistaken.
- But not to lose time in examining, whether it is possible for our senses
- to deceive us, and represent our perceptions as distinct from ourselves,
- that is as external to and independent of us; let us consider whether
- they really do so, and whether this error proceeds from an immediate
- sensation, or from some other causes.
- To begin with the question concerning EXTERNAL existence, it may perhaps
- be said, that setting aside the metaphysical question of the identity
- of a thinking substance, our own body evidently belongs to us; and as
- several impressions appear exterior to the body, we suppose them also
- exterior to ourselves. The paper, on which I write at present, is beyond
- my hand. The table is beyond the paper. The walls of the chamber beyond
- the table. And in casting my eye towards the window, I perceive a great
- extent of fields and buildings beyond my chamber. From all this it may
- be infered, that no other faculty is required, beside the senses, to
- convince us of the external existence of body. But to prevent this
- inference, we need only weigh the three following considerations. First,
- That, properly speaking, it is not our body we perceive, when we regard
- our limbs and members, but certain impressions, which enter by the
- senses; so that the ascribing a real and corporeal existence to these
- impressions, or to their objects, is an act of the mind as difficult
- to explain, as that which we examine at present. Secondly, Sounds, and
- tastes, and smelts, though commonly regarded by the mind as continued
- independent qualities, appear not to have any existence in extension,
- and consequently cannot appear to the senses as situated externally
- to the body. The reason, why we ascribe a place to them, shall be:
- considered afterwards. Thirdly, Even our sight informs us not of
- distance or outness (so to speak) immediately and without a certain
- reasoning and experience, as is acknowledged by the most rational
- philosophers.
- As to the independency of our perceptions on ourselves, this can never
- be an object of the senses; but any opinion we form concerning it, must
- be derived from experience and observation: And we shall see afterwards,
- that our conclusions from experience are far from being favourable to
- the doctrine of the independency of our perceptions. Mean while we may
- observe that when we talk of real distinct existences, we have commonly
- more in our eye their independency than external situation in place,
- and think an object has a sufficient reality, when its Being is
- uninterrupted, and independent of the incessant revolutions, which we
- are conscious of in ourselves.
- Thus to resume what I have said concerning the senses; they give us no
- notion of continued existence, because they cannot operate beyond the
- extent, in which they really operate. They as little produce the opinion
- of a distinct existence, because they neither can offer it to the mind
- as represented, nor as original. To offer it as represented, they must
- present both an object and an image. To make it appear as original, they
- must convey a falshood; and this falshood must lie in the relations and
- situation: In order to which they must be able to compare the object
- with ourselves; and even in that case they do not, nor is it possible
- they should, deceive us. We may, therefore, conclude with certainty,
- that the opinion of a continued and of a distinct existence never arises
- from the senses.
- To confirm this we may observe, that there are three different kinds of
- impressions conveyed by the senses. The first are those of the figure,
- bulk, motion and solidity of bodies. The second those of colours,
- tastes, smells, sounds, heat and cold. The third are the pains and
- pleasures, that arise from the application of objects to our bodies, as
- by the cutting of our flesh with steel, and such like. Both philosophers
- and the vulgar suppose the first of these to have a distinct continued
- existence. The vulgar only regard the second as on the same footing.
- Both philosophers and the vulgar, again, esteem the third to be merely
- perceptions and consequently interrupted and dependent beings.
- Now it is evident, that, whatever may be our philosophical opinion,
- colours, Sounds, heat and cold, as far as appears to the senses, exist
- after the same manner with motion and solidity, and that the difference
- we make betwixt them in this respect, arises not from the mere
- perception. So strong the prejudice for the distinct continued existence
- Of the former qualities, that when the contrary opinion is advanced by
- modern philosophers, people imagine they can almost refute it from
- their feeling and experience, and that their very senses contradict this
- philosophy. It is also evident, that colours, sounds, &c. are originally
- on the same footing with the pain that arises from steel, and pleasure
- that proceeds from a fire; and that the difference betwixt them is
- founded neither on perception nor reason, but on the imagination. For
- as they are confest to be, both of them, nothing but perceptions arising
- from the particular configurations and motions of the parts of body,
- wherein possibly can their difference consist? Upon the whole, then, we
- may conclude, that as far as the senses are judges, all perceptions are
- the same in the manner of their existence.
- We may also observe in this instance of sounds and colours, that we
- can attribute a distinct continued existence to objects without ever
- consulting REASON, or weighing our opinions by any philosophical
- principles. And indeed, whatever convincing arguments philosophers may
- fancy they can produce to establish the belief of objects independent of
- the mind, it is obvious these arguments are known but to very few, and
- that it is not by them, that children, peasants, and the greatest part
- of mankind are induced to attribute objects to some impressions, and
- deny them to others. Accordingly we find, that all the conclusions,
- which the vulgar form on this head, are directly contrary to those,
- which are confirmed by philosophy. For philosophy informs us, that every
- thing, which appears to the mind, is nothing but a perception, and is
- interrupted, and dependent on the mind: whereas the vulgar confound
- perceptions and objects, and attribute a distinct continued existence
- to the very things they feel or see. This sentiment, then, as it is
- entirely unreasonable, must proceed from some other faculty than
- the understanding. To which we may add, that as long as we take our
- perceptions and objects to be the same, we can never infer the existence
- of the one from that of the other, nor form any argument from the
- relation of cause and effect; which is the only one that earl assure us
- of matter of fact. Even after we distinguish our perceptions from
- our objects, it will appear presently, that we are still incapable of
- reasoning from the existence of one to that of the other: So that upon
- the whole our reason neither does, nor is it possible it ever should,
- upon any supposition, give us an assurance of the continued and
- distinct existence of body. That opinion must be entirely owing to the
- IMAGINATION: which must now be the subject of our enquiry.
- Since all impressions are internal and perishing existences, and appear
- as such, the notion of their distinct and continued existence must arise
- from a concurrence of some of their qualities with the qualities of the
- imagination, and since this notion does not extend to all of them, it
- must arise from certain qualities peculiar to some impressions. It will
- therefore be easy for us to discover these qualities by a comparison
- of the impressions, to which we attribute a distinct and continued
- existence, with those, which we regard as internal and perishing.
- We may observe, then, that it is neither upon account of the
- involuntariness of certain impressions, as is commonly supposed, nor of
- their superior force and violence, that we attribute to them a reality,
- and continued existence, which we refuse to others, that are voluntary
- or feeble. For it is evident our pains and pleasures, our passions and
- affections, which we never suppose to have any existence beyond our
- perception, operate with greater violence, and are equally involuntary,
- as the impressions of figure and extension, colour and sound, which we
- suppose to be permanent beings. The heat of a fire, when moderate, is
- supposed to exist in the fire; but the pain, which it causes upon a near
- approach, is not taken to have any being, except in the perception.
- These vulgar opinions, then, being rejected, we must search for some
- other hypothesis, by which we may discover those peculiar qualities
- in our impressions, which makes us attribute to them a distinct and
- continued existence.
- After a little examination, we shall find, that all those objects, to
- which we attribute a continued existence, have a peculiar constancy,
- which distinguishes them from the impressions, whose existence depends
- upon our perception. Those mountains, and houses, and trees, which lie
- at present under my eye, have always appeared to me in the same order;
- and when I lose sight of them by shutting my eyes or turning my head, I
- soon after find them return upon me without the least alteration. My bed
- and table, my books and papers, present themselves in the same uniform
- manner, and change not upon account of any interruption in my seeing
- or perceivilng them. This is the case with all the impressions, whose
- objects are supposed to have an external existence; and is the case
- with no other impressions, whether gentle or violent, voluntary or
- involuntary.
- This constancy, however, is not so perfect as not to admit of very
- considerable exceptions. Bodies often change their position and
- qualities, and after a little absence or interruption may become hardly
- knowable. But here it is observable, that even in these changes they
- preserve a coherence, and have a regular dependence on each other; which
- is the foundation of a kind of reasoning from causation, and produces
- the opinion of their continued existence. When I return to my chamber
- after an hour's absence, I find not my fire in the same situation, in
- which I left it: But then I am accustomed in other instances to see a
- like alteration produced in a like time, whether I am present or absent,
- near or remote. This coherence, therefore, in their changes is one of
- the characteristics of external objects, as well as their constancy.
- Having found that the opinion of the continued existence of body depends
- on the COHERENCE, and CONSTANCY of certain impressions, I now proceed to
- examine after what manner these qualities give rise to so extraordinary
- an opinion. To begin with the coherence; we may observe, that though
- those internal impressions, which we regard as fleeting and perishing,
- have also a certain coherence or regularity in their appearances, yet
- it is of somewhat a different nature, from that which we discover in
- bodies. Our passions are found by experience to have a mutual connexion
- with and dependence on each other; but on no occasion is it necessary
- to suppose, that they have existed and operated, when they were not
- perceived, in order to preserve the same dependence and connexion, of
- which we have had experience. The case is not the same with relation
- to external objects. Those require a continued existence, or otherwise
- lose, in a great measure, the regularity of their operation. I am here
- seated in my chamber with my face to the fire; and all the objects, that
- strike my senses, are contained in a few yards around me. My memory,
- indeed, informs me of the existence of many objects; but then this
- information extends not beyond their past existence, nor do either my
- senses or memory give any testimony to the continuance of their being.
- When therefore I am thus seated, and revolve over these thoughts, I hear
- on a sudden a noise as of a door turning upon its hinges; and a little
- after see a porter, who advances towards me. This gives occasion to many
- new reflections and reasonings. First, I never have observed, that
- this noise coued proceed from any thing but the motion of a door; and
- therefore conclude, that the present phaenomenon is a contradiction to
- all past experience, unless the door, which I remember on the other side
- the chamber, be still in being. Again, I have always found, that a human
- body was possest of a quality, which I call gravity, and which hinders
- it from mounting in the air, as this porter must have done to arrive
- at my chamber, unless the stairs I remember be not annihilated by my
- absence. But this is not all. I receive a letter, which upon, opening
- it I perceive by the hand-writing and subscription to have come from a
- friend, who says he is two hundred leagues distant. It is evident I can
- never account for this phenomenon, conformable to my experience in other
- instances, without spreading out in my mind the whole sea and continent
- between us, and supposing the effects and continued existence of posts
- and ferries, according to my Memory and observation. To consider
- these phaenomena of the porter and letter in a certain light, they are
- contradictions to common experience, and may be regarded as objections
- to those maxims, which we form concerning the connexions of causes and
- effects. I am accustomed to hear such a sound, and see such an object in
- motion at the same time. I have not received in this particular instance
- both these perceptions. These observations are contrary, unless I
- suppose that the door still remains, and that it was opened without
- my perceiving it: And this supposition, which was at first entirely
- arbitrary and hypothetical, acquires a force and evidence by its being
- the only one, upon which I can reconcile these contradictions. There
- is scarce a moment of my life, wherein there is not a similar instance
- presented to me, and I have not occasion to suppose the continued
- existence of objects, in order to connect their past and present
- appearances, and give them such an union with each other, as I have
- found by experience to be suitable to their particular natures and
- circumstances. Here then I am naturally led to regard the world, as
- something real and durable, and as preserving its existence, even when
- it is no longer present to my perception.
- But though this conclusion from the coherence of appearances may seem to
- be of the same nature with our reasonings concerning causes and effects;
- as being derived from custom, and regulated by past experience; we
- shall find upon examination, that they are at the bottom considerably
- different from each other, and that this inference arises from the
- understanding, and from custom in an indirect and oblique manner. For
- it will readily be allowed, that since nothing is ever really present to
- the mind, besides its own perceptions, it is not only impossible,
- that any habit should ever be acquired otherwise than by the regular
- succession of these perceptions, but also that any habit should ever
- exceed that degree of regularity. Any degree, therefore, of regularity
- in our perceptions, can never be a foundation for us to infer a greater
- degree of regularity in some objects, which are not perceived; since
- this supposes a contradiction, viz. a habit acquired by what was never
- present to the mind. But it is evident, that whenever we infer the
- continued existence of the objects of sense from their coherence, and
- the frequency of their union, it is in order to bestow on the objects
- a greater regularity than what is observed in our mere perceptions. We
- remark a connexion betwixt two kinds of objects in their past appearance
- to the senses, but are not able to observe this connexion to be
- perfectly constant, since the turning about of our head or the shutting
- of our eyes is able to break it. What then do we suppose in this
- case, but that these objects still continue their usual connexion,
- notwithstanding their apparent interruption, and that the irregular
- appearances are joined by something, of which we are insensible? But as
- all reasoning concerning matters of fact arises only from custom, and
- custom can only be the effect of repeated perceptions, the extending of
- custom and reasoning beyond the perceptions can never be the direct and
- natural effect of the constant repetition and connexion, but must arise
- from the co-operation of some other principles.
- I have already observed [Part II, Sect. 4.], in examining the foundation
- of mathematics, that the imagination, when set into any train of
- thinking, is apt to continue, even when its object fails it, and like a
- galley put in motion by the oars, carries on its course without any new
- impulse. This I have assigned for the reason, why, after considering
- several loose standards of equality, and correcting them by each other,
- we proceed to imagine so correct and exact a standard of that relation,
- as is not liable to the least error or variation. The same principle
- makes us easily entertain this opinion of the continued existence
- of body. Objects have a certain coherence even as they appear to our
- senses; but this coherence is much greater and more uniform, if we
- suppose the object.% to have a continued existence; and as the mind is
- once in the train of observing an uniformity among objects, it naturally
- continues, till it renders the uniformity as compleat as possible.
- The simple supposition of their continued existence suffices for this
- purpose, and gives us a notion of a much greater regularity among
- objects, than what they have when we look no farther than our senses.
- But whatever force we may ascribe to this principle, I am afraid it
- is too weak to support alone so vast an edifice, as is that of the
- continued existence of all external bodies; and that we must join the
- constancy of their appearance to the coherence, in order to give a
- satisfactory account of that opinion. As the explication of this will
- lead me into a considerable compass of very profound reasoning; I
- think it proper, in order to avoid confusion, to give a short sketch or
- abridgment of my system, and afterwards draw out all its parts in their
- full compass. This inference from the constancy of our perceptions, like
- the precedent from their coherence, gives rise to the opinion of the
- continued existence of body, which is prior to that of its distinct
- existence, and produces that latter principle.
- When we have been accustomed to observe a constancy in certain
- impressions, and have found, that the perception of the sun or ocean,
- for instance, returns upon us after an absence or annihilation with like
- parts and in a like order, as at its first appearance, we are not apt
- to regard these interrupted perceptions as different, (which they really
- are) but on the contrary consider them as individually the same,
- upon account of their resemblance. But as this interruption of their
- existence is contrary to their perfect identity, and makes us regard
- the first impression as annihilated, and the second as newly created,
- we find ourselves somewhat at a loss, and are involved in a kind of
- contradiction. In order to free ourselves from this difficulty, we
- disguise, as much as possible, the interruption, or rather remove it
- entirely, by supposing that these interrupted perceptions are connected
- by a real existence, of which we are insensible. This supposition, or
- idea of continued existence, acquires a force and vivacity from the
- memory of these broken impressions, and from that propensity, which
- they give us, to suppose them the same; and according to the precedent
- reasoning, the very essence of belief consists in the force and vivacity
- of the conception.
- In order to justify this system, there are four things requisite. First,
- To explain the PRINCIPIUM INDIVIDUATIONIS, or principle of identity.
- Secondly, Give a reason, why the resemblance of our broken and
- interrupted perceptions induces us to attribute an identity to them.
- Thirdly, Account for that propensity, which this illusion gives, to
- unite these broken appearances by a continued existence. Fourthly and
- lastly, Explain that force and vivacity of conception, which arises from
- the propensity.
- First, As to the principle of individuation; we may observe, that the
- view of any one object is not sufficient to convey the idea of identity.
- For in that proposition, an object is the same with itself, if the idea
- expressed by the word, object, were no ways distinguished from
- that meant by itself; we really should mean nothing, nor would the
- proposition contain a predicate and a subject, which however are implyed
- in this affirmation. One single object conveys the idea of unity, not
- that of identity.
- On the other hand, a multiplicity of objects can never convey this idea,
- however resembling they may be supposed. The mind always pronounces the
- one not to be the other, and considers them as forming two, three,
- or any determinate number of objects, whose existences are entirely
- distinct and independent.
- Since then both number and unity are incompatible with the relation of
- identity, it must lie in something that is neither of them. But to tell
- the truth, at first sight this seems utterly impossible. Betwixt unity
- and number there can be no medium; no more than betwixt existence and
- nonexistence. After one object is supposed to exist, we must either
- suppose another also to exist; in which case we have the idea of number:
- Or we must suppose it not to exist; in which case the first object
- remains at unity.
- To remove this difficulty, let us have recourse to the idea of time or
- duration. I have already observd [Part II, Sect. 5.], that time, in a
- strict sense, implies succession, and that when we apply its idea to
- any unchangeable object, it is only by a fiction of the imagination, by
- which the unchangeable object is supposd to participate of the
- changes of the co-existent objects, and in particular of that of our
- perceptions. This fiction of the imagination almost universally takes
- place; and it is by means of it, that a single object, placd before us,
- and surveyd for any time without our discovering in it any interruption
- or variation, is able to give us a notion of identity. For when we
- consider any two points of this time, we may place them in different
- lights: We may either survey them at the very same instant; in which
- case they give us the idea of number, both by themselves and by the
- object; which must be multiplyd, in order to be conceivd at once, as
- existent in these two different points of time: Or on the other hand,
- we may trace the succession of time by a like succession of ideas,
- and conceiving first one moment, along with the object then existent,
- imagine afterwards a change in the time without any VARIATION or
- INTERRUPTION in the object; in which case it gives us the idea of unity.
- Here then is an idea, which is a medium betwixt unity and number; or
- more properly speaking, is either of them, according to the view, in
- which we take it: And this idea we call that of identity. We cannot, in
- any propriety of speech, say, that an object is the same with itself,
- unless we mean, that the object existent at one time is the same with
- itself existent at another. By this means we make a difference, betwixt
- the idea meant by the word, OBJECT, and that meant by ITSELF, without
- going the length of number, and at the same time without restraining
- ourselves to a strict and absolute unity.
- Thus the principle of individuation is nothing but the INVARIABLENESS
- and UNINTERRUPTEDNESS of any object, thro a supposd variation of
- time, by which the mind can trace it in the different periods of its
- existence, without any break of the view, and without being obligd to
- form the idea of multiplicity or number.
- I now proceed to explain the SECOND part of my system, and shew why
- the constancy of our perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect
- numerical identity, tho there be very long intervals betwixt their
- appearance, and they have only one of the essential qualities of
- identity, VIZ, INVARIABLENESS. That I may avoid all ambiguity and
- confusion on this head, I shall observe, that I here account for the
- opinions and belief of the vulgar with regard to the existence of body;
- and therefore must entirely conform myself to their manner of thinking
- and of expressing themselves. Now we have already observd, that however
- philosophers may distinguish betwixt the objects and perceptions of the
- senses; which they suppose co-existent and resembling; yet this is a
- distinction, which is not comprehended by the generality of mankind, who
- as they perceive only one being, can never assent to the opinion of a
- double existence and representation. Those very sensations, which enter
- by the eye or ear, are with them the true objects, nor can they
- readily conceive that this pen or paper, which is immediately perceivd,
- represents another, which is different from, but resembling it. In
- order, therefore, to accommodate myself to their notions, I shall at
- first suppose; that there is only a single existence, which I shall call
- indifferently OBJECT or PERCEPTION, according as it shall seem best to
- suit my purpose, understanding by both of them what any common man means
- by a hat, or shoe, or stone, or any other impression, conveyd to him
- by his senses. I shall be sure to give warning, when I return to a more
- philosophical way of speaking and thinking.
- To enter, therefore, upon the question concerning the source of the
- error and deception with regard to identity, when we attribute it to our
- resembling perceptions, notwithstanding their interruption; I must here
- recal an observation, which I have already provd and explaind [Part II.
- Sect. 5.]. Nothing is more apt to make us mistake one idea for another,
- than any relation betwixt them, which associates them together in the
- imagination, and makes it pass with facility from one to the other.
- Of all relations, that of resemblance is in this respect the most
- efficacious; and that because it not only causes an association of
- ideas, but also of dispositions, and makes us conceive the one idea by
- an act or operation of the mind, similar to that by which we conceive
- the other. This circumstance I have observd to be of great moment; and
- we may establish it for a general rule, that whatever ideas place the
- mind in the same disposition or in similar ones, are very apt to be
- confounded. The mind readily passes from one to the other, and perceives
- not the change without a strict attention, of which, generally speaking,
- it is wholly incapable.
- In order to apply this general maxim, we must first examine the
- disposition of the mind in viewing any object which preserves a perfect
- identity, and then find some other object, that is confounded with it,
- by causing a similar disposition. When we fix our thought on any object,
- and suppose it to continue the same for some time; it is evident we
- suppose the change to lie only in the time, and never exert ourselves to
- produce any new image or idea of the object. The faculties of the mind
- repose themselves in a manner, and take no more exercise, than what is
- necessary to continue that idea, of which we were formerly possest, and
- which subsists without variation or interruption. The passage from one
- moment to another is scarce felt, and distinguishes not itself by a
- different perception or idea, which may require a different direction of
- the spirits, in order to its conception.
- Now what other objects, beside identical ones, are capable of placing
- the mind in the same disposition, when it considers them, and of causing
- the same uninterrupted passage of the imagination from one idea to
- another? This question is of the last importance. For if we can find any
- such objects, we may certainly conclude, from the foregoing principle,
- that they are very naturally confounded with identical ones, and are
- taken for them in most of our reasonings. But though this question be
- very important, it is not very difficult nor doubtful. For I immediately
- reply, that a succession of related objects places the mind in this
- disposition, and is considered with the same smooth and uninterrupted
- progress of the imagination, as attends the view of the same invariable
- object. The very nature and essence of relation is to connect our ideas
- with each other, and upon the appearance of one, to facilitate the
- transition to its correlative. The passage betwixt related ideas is,
- therefore, so smooth and easy, that it produces little alteration on
- the mind, and seems like the continuation of the same action; and as the
- continuation of the same action is an effect of the continued view of
- the same object, it is for this reason we attribute sameness to every
- succession of related objects. The thought slides along the succession
- with equal facility, as if it considered only one object; and therefore
- confounds the succession with the identity.
- We shall afterwards see many instances of this tendency of relation to
- make us ascribe an identity to different objects; but shall here confine
- ourselves to the present subject. We find by experience, that there is
- such a constancy in almost all the impressions of the senses, that their
- interruption produces no alteration on them, and hinders them not from
- returning the same in appearance and in situation as at their first
- existence. I survey the furniture of my chamber; I shut my eyes, and
- afterwards open them; and find the new perceptions to resemble perfectly
- those, which formerly struck my senses. This resemblance is observed in
- a thousand instances, and naturally connects together our ideas of these
- interrupted perceptions by the strongest relation, and conveys the
- mind with an easy transition from one to another. An easy transition
- or passage of the imagination, along the ideas of these different and
- interrupted perceptions, is almost the same disposition of mind with
- that in which we consider one constant and uninterrupted perception. It
- is therefore very natural for us to mistake the one for the other.
- [Footnote 9 This reasoning, it must be confest, is somewhat
- abstruse, and difficult to be comprehended; but it is
- remarkable, that this very difficulty may be converted into
- a proof of the reasoning. We may observe, that there are two
- relations, and both of them resemblances, which contribute
- to our mistaking the succession of our interrupted
- perceptions for an identical object. The first is, the
- resemblance of the perceptions: The second is the
- resemblance, which the act of the mind in surveying a
- succession of resembling objects bears to that in surveying
- an identical object. Now these resemblances we are apt to
- confound with each other; and it is natural we shoud,
- according to this very reasoning. But let us keep them
- distinct, and we shall find no difficulty in conceiving the
- precedent argument.]
- The persons, who entertain this opinion concerning the identity of
- our resembling perceptions, are in general an the unthinking and
- unphilosophical part of mankind, (that is, all of us, at one time or
- other) and consequently such as suppose their perceptions to be their
- only objects, and never think of a double existence internal and
- external, representing and represented. The very image, which is present
- to the senses, is with us the real body; and it is to these interrupted
- images we ascribe a perfect identity. But as the interruption of the
- appearance seems contrary to the identity, and naturally leads us to
- regard these resembling perceptions as different from each other, we
- here find ourselves at a loss how to reconcile such opposite opinions.
- The smooth passage of the imagination along the ideas of the resembling
- perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect identity. The interrupted
- manner of their appearance makes us consider them as so many resembling,
- but still distinct beings, which appear after certain intervals. The
- perplexity arising from this contradiction produces a propension to
- unite these broken appearances by the fiction of a continued existence,
- which is the third part of that hypothesis I proposed to explain.
- Nothing is more certain from experience, than that any contradiction
- either to the sentiments or passions gives a sensible uneasiness,
- whether it proceeds from without or from within; from the opposition
- of external objects, or from the combat of internal principles. On the
- contrary, whatever strikes in with the natural propensities, and either
- externally forwards their satisfaction, or internally concurs with their
- movements, is sure to give a sensible pleasure. Now there being here an
- opposition betwixt the notion of the identity of resembling perceptions,
- and the interruption of their appearance, the mind must be uneasy in
- that situation, and will naturally seek relief from the uneasiness.
- Since the uneasiness arises from the opposition of two contrary
- principles, it must look for relief by sacrificing the one to the
- other. But as the smooth passage of our thought along our resembling
- perceptions makes us ascribe to them an identity, we can never without
- reluctance yield up that opinion. We must, therefore, turn to the other
- side, and suppose that our perceptions are no longer interrupted, but
- preserve a continued as well as an invariable existence, and are by that
- means entirely the same. But here the interruptions in the appearance
- of these perceptions are so long and frequent, that it is impossible to
- overlook them; and as the appearance of a perception in the mind and
- its existence seem at first sight entirely the same, it may be doubted,
- whether we can ever assent to so palpable a contradiction, and suppose a
- perception to exist without being present to the mind. In order to clear
- up this matter, and learn how the interruption in the appearance of a
- perception implies not necessarily an interruption in its existence,
- it will be proper to touch upon some principles, which we shall have
- occasion to explain more fully afterwards. [Sect. 6.]
- We may begin with observing, that the difficulty in the present case
- is not concerning the matter of fact, or whether the mind forms such a
- conclusion concerning the continued existence of its perceptions,
- but only concerning the manner in which the conclusion is formed, and
- principles from which it is derived. It is certain, that almost all
- mankind, and even philosophers themselves, for the greatest part of
- their lives, take their perceptions to be their only objects, and
- suppose, that the very being, which is intimately present to the mind,
- is the real body or material existence. It is also certain, that this
- very perception or object is supposed to have a continued uninterrupted
- being, and neither to be annihilated by our absence, nor to be brought
- into existence by our presence. When we are absent from it, we say it
- still exists, but that we do not feel, we do not see it. When we are
- present, we say we feel, or see it. Here then may arise two questions;
- First, How we can satisfy ourselves in supposing a perception to be
- absent from the mind without being annihilated. Secondly, After what
- manner we conceive an object to become present to the mind, without some
- new creation of a perception or image; and what we mean by this seeing,
- and feeling, and perceiving.
- As to the first question; we may observe, that what we call a mind,
- is nothing but a heap or collection of different perceptions, united
- together by certain relations, and supposed, though falsely, to be
- endowed with a perfect simplicity and identity. Now as every perception
- is distinguishable from another, and may be considered as separately
- existent; it evidently follows, that there is no absurdity in separating
- any particular perception from the mind; that is, in breaking off all
- its relations, with that connected mass of perceptions, which constitute
- a thinking being.
- The same reasoning affords us an answer to the second question. If the
- name of perception renders not this separation from a mind absurd and
- contradictory, the name of object, standing for the very same thing, can
- never render their conjunction impossible. External objects are seen,
- and felt, and become present to the mind; that is, they acquire such a
- relation to a connected heap of perceptions, as to influence them very
- considerably in augmenting their number by present reflections and
- passions, and in storing the memory with ideas. The same continued and
- uninterrupted Being may, therefore, be sometimes present to the mind,
- and sometimes absent from it, without any real or essential change in
- the Being itself. An interrupted appearance to the senses implies not
- necessarily an interruption in the existence. The supposition of the
- continued existence of sensible objects or perceptions involves
- no contradiction. We may easily indulge our inclination to that
- supposition. When the exact resemblance of our perceptions makes us
- ascribe to them an identity, we may remove the seeming interruption by
- feigning a continued being, which may fill those intervals, and preserve
- a perfect and entire identity to our perceptions.
- But as we here not only feign but believe this continued existence, the
- question is, from whence arises such a belief; and this question leads
- us to the fourth member of this system. It has been proved already, that
- belief in general consists in nothing, but the vivacity of an idea; and
- that an idea may acquire this vivacity by its relation to some present
- impression. Impressions are naturally the most vivid perceptions of
- the mind; and this quality is in part conveyed by the relation to every
- connected idea. The relation causes a smooth passage from the impression
- to the idea, and even gives a propensity to that passage. The mind falls
- so easily from the one perception to the other, that it scarce perceives
- the change, but retains in the second a considerable share of the
- vivacity of the first. It is excited by the lively impression; and this
- vivacity is conveyed to the related idea, without any great diminution
- in the passage, by reason of the smooth transition and the propensity of
- the imagination.
- But suppose, that this propensity arises from some other principle,
- besides that of relation; it is evident it must still have the same
- effect, and convey the vivacity from the impression to the idea. Now
- this is exactly the present case. Our memory presents us with a vast
- number of instances of perceptions perfectly resembling each other,
- that return at different distances of time, and after considerable
- interruptions. This resemblance gives us a propension to consider these
- interrupted perceptions as the same; and also a propension to connect
- them by a continued existence, in order to justify this identity, and
- avoid the contradiction, in which the interrupted appearance of these
- perceptions seems necessarily to involve us. Here then we have a
- propensity to feign the continued existence of all sensible objects; and
- as this propensity arises from some lively impressions of the memory, it
- bestows a vivacity on that fiction: or in other words, makes us believe
- the continued existence of body. If sometimes we ascribe a continued
- existence to objects, which are perfectly new to us, and of whose
- constancy and coherence we have no experience, it is because the manner,
- in which they present themselves to our senses, resembles that of
- constant and coherent objects; and this resemblance is a source of
- reasoning and analogy, and leads us to attribute the same qualities to
- similar objects.
- I believe an intelligent reader will find less difficulty to assent to
- this system, than to comprehend it fully and distinctly, and will allow,
- after a little reflection, that every part carries its own proof
- along with it. It is indeed evident, that as the vulgar suppose their
- perceptions to be their only objects, and at the same time believe the
- continued existence of matter, we must account for the origin of the
- belief upon that supposition. Now upon that supposition, it is a false
- opinion that any of our objects, or perceptions, are identically the
- same after an interruption; and consequently the opinion of their
- identity can never arise from reason, but must arise from the
- imagination. The imagination is seduced into such an opinion only by
- means of the resemblance of certain perceptions; since we find they are
- only our resembling perceptions, which we have a propension to suppose
- the same. This propension to bestow an identity on our resembling
- perceptions, produces the fiction of a continued existence; since that
- fiction, as well as the identity, is really false, as is acknowledged
- by all philosophers, and has no other effect than to remedy the
- interruption of our perceptions, which is the only circumstance that
- is contrary to their identity. In the last place this propension causes
- belief by means of the present impressions of the memory; since without
- the remembrance of former sensations, it is plain we never should have
- any belief of the continued existence of body. Thus in examining all
- these parts, we find that each of them is supported by the strongest
- proofs: and that all of them together form a consistent system, which is
- perfectly convincing. A strong propensity or inclination alone, without
- any present impression, will sometimes cause a belief or opinion. How
- much more when aided by that circumstance?
- But though we are led after this manner, by the natural propensity of
- the imagination, to ascribe a continued existence to those sensible
- objects or perceptions, which we find to resemble each other in their
- interrupted appearance; yet a very little reflection and philosophy
- is sufficient to make us perceive the fallacy of that opinion. I have
- already observed, that there is an intimate connexion betwixt those two
- principles, of a continued and of a distinct or independent existence,
- and that we no sooner establish the one than the other follows, as a
- necessary consequence. It is the opinion of a continued existence, which
- first takes place, and without much study or reflection draws the other
- along with it, wherever the mind follows its first and most natural
- tendency. But when we compare experiments, and reason a little upon
- them, we quickly perceive, that the doctrine of the independent
- existence of our sensible perceptions is contrary to the plainest
- experience. This leads us backward upon our footsteps to perceive our
- error in attributing a continued existence to our perceptions, and is
- the origin of many very curious opinions, which we shall here endeavour
- to account for.
- It will first be proper to observe a few of those experiments, which
- convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any independent
- existence. When we press one eye with a finger, we immediately perceive
- all the objects to become double, and one half of them to be removed
- from their common and natural position. But as we do not attribute to
- continued existence to both these perceptions, and as they are both
- of the same nature, we clearly perceive, that all our perceptions are
- dependent on our organs, and the disposition of our nerves and
- animal spirits. This opinion is confirmed by the seeming encrease and
- diminution of objects, according to their distance; by the apparent
- alterations in their figure; by the changes in their colour and other
- qualities from our sickness and distempers: and by an infinite number
- of other experiments of the same kind; from all which we learn, that
- our sensible perceptions are not possest of any distinct or independent
- existence.
- The natural consequence of this reasoning should be, that our
- perceptions have no more a continued than an independent existence; and
- indeed philosophers have so far run into this opinion, that they change
- their system, and distinguish, (as we shall do for the future) betwixt
- perceptions and objects, of which the former are supposed to be
- interrupted, and perishing, and different at every different return; the
- latter to be uninterrupted, and to preserve a continued existence and
- identity. But however philosophical this new system may be esteemed, I
- assert that it is only a palliative remedy, and that it contains all the
- difficulties of the vulgar system, with some others, that are peculiar
- to itself. There are no principles either of the understanding or fancy,
- which lead us directly to embrace this opinion of the double existence
- of perceptions and objects, nor can we arrive at it but by passing
- through the common hypothesis of the identity and continuance of
- our interrupted perceptions. Were we not first perswaded, that our
- perceptions are our only objects, and continue to exist even when they
- no longer make their appearance to the senses, we should never be led
- to think, that our perceptions and objects are different, and that our
- objects alone preserve a continued existence. The latter hypothesis
- has no primary recommendation either to reason or the imagination, but
- acquires all its influence on the imagination from the former. This
- proposition contains two parts, which we shall endeavour to prove as
- distinctly and clearly, as such abstruse subjects will permit.
- As to the first part of the proposition, that this philosophical
- hypothesis has no primary recommendation, either to reason, or the
- imagination, we may soon satisfy ourselves with regard to reason by the
- following reflections. The only existences, of which we are certain,
- are perceptions, which being immediately present to us by consciousness,
- command our strongest assent, and are the first foundation of all our
- conclusions. The only conclusion we can draw from the existence of
- one thing to that of another, is by means of the relation of cause and
- effect, which shews, that there is a connexion betwixt them, and that
- the existence of one is dependent on that of the other. The idea of this
- relation is derived from past experience, by which we find, that two
- beings are constantly conjoined together, and are always present at
- once to the mind. But as no beings are ever present to the mind but
- perceptions; it follows that we may observe a conjunction or a relation
- of cause and effect between different perceptions, but can never observe
- it between perceptions and objects. It is impossible, therefore, that
- from the existence or any of the qualities of the former, we can ever
- form any conclusion concerning the existence of the latter, or ever
- satisfy our reason in this particular.
- It is no less certain, that this philosophical system has no primary
- recommendation to the imagination, and that that faculty would never, of
- itself, and by its original tendency, have fallen upon such a principle.
- I confess it will be somewhat difficult to prove this to the fall
- satisfaction of the reader; because it implies a negative, which in many
- cases will not admit of any positive proof. If any one would take the
- pains to examine this question, and would invent a system, to account
- for the direct origin of this opinion from the imagination, we should be
- able, by the examination of that system, to pronounce a certain
- judgment in the present subject. Let it be taken for granted, that our
- perceptions are broken, and interrupted, and however like, are still
- different from each other; and let any one upon this supposition shew
- why the fancy, directly and immediately, proceeds to the belief of
- another existence, resembling these perceptions in their nature, but yet
- continued, and uninterrupted, and identical; and after he has done this
- to my satisfaction, I promise to renounce my present opinion. Mean while
- I cannot forbear concluding, from the very abstractedness and difficulty
- of the first supposition, that it is an improper subject for the fancy
- to work upon. Whoever would explain the origin of the common opinion
- concerning the continued and distinct existence of body, must take the
- mind in its common situation, and must proceed upon the supposition,
- that our perceptions are our only objects, and continue to exist even
- when they are not perceived. Though this opinion be false, it is the
- most natural of any, and has alone any primary recommendation to the
- fancy.
- As to the second part of the proposition, that the philosophical system
- acquires all its influence on the imagination from the vulgar one; we
- may observe, that this is a natural and unavoidable consequence of the
- foregoing conclusion, that it has no primary recommendation to reason or
- the imagination. For as the philosophical system is found by experience
- to take hold of many minds, and in particular of all those, who reflect
- ever so little on this subject, it must derive all its authority from
- the vulgar system; since it has no original authority of its own.
- The manner, in which these two systems, though directly contrary, are
- connected together, may be explains, as follows.
- The imagination naturally runs on in this train of thinking. Our
- perceptions are our only objects: Resembling perceptions are the same,
- however broken or uninterrupted in their appearance: This appealing
- interruption is contrary to the identity: The interruption consequently
- extends not beyond the appearance, and the perception or object really
- continues to exist, even when absent from us: Our sensible perception
- s have, therefore, a continued and uninterrupted existence. But as a
- little reflection destroys this conclusion, that our perceptions have a
- continued existence, by shewing that they have a dependent one, it would
- naturally be expected, that we must altogether reject the opinion,
- that there is such a thing in nature as a continued existence, which
- is preserved even when it no longer appears to the senses. The case,
- however, is otherwise. Philosophers are so far from rejecting the
- opinion of a continued existence upon rejecting that of the independence
- and continuance of our sensible perceptions, that though all sects
- agree in the latter sentiment, the former, which is, in a manner, its
- necessary consequence, has been peculiar to a few extravagant sceptics;
- who after all maintained that opinion in words only, and were never able
- to bring themselves sincerely to believe it.
- There is a great difference betwixt such opinions as we form after
- a calm and profound reflection, and such as we embrace by a kind of
- instinct or natural impulse, on account of their suitableness and
- conformity to the mind. If these opinions become contrary, it is not
- difficult to foresee which of them will have the advantage. As long as
- our attention is bent upon the subject, the philosophical and studyed
- principle may prevail; but the moment we relax our thoughts, nature will
- display herself, and draw us back to our former opinion. Nay she has
- sometimes such an influence, that she can stop our progress, even in the
- midst of our most profound reflections, and keep us from running on
- with all the consequences of any philosophical opinion. Thus though we
- clearly perceive the dependence and interruption of our perceptions, we
- stop short in our career, and never upon that account reject the notion
- of an independent and continued existence. That opinion has taken such
- deep root in the imagination, that it is impossible ever to eradicate
- it, nor will any strained metaphysical conviction of the dependence of
- our perceptions be sufficient for that purpose.
- But though our natural and obvious principles here prevail above our
- studied reflections, it is certain there must be sonic struggle and
- opposition in the case: at least so long as these rejections retain any
- force or vivacity. In order to set ourselves at ease in this particular,
- we contrive a new hypothesis, which seems to comprehend both
- these principles of reason and imagination. This hypothesis is the
- philosophical, one of the double existence of perceptions and objects;
- which pleases our reason, in allowing, that our dependent perceptions
- are interrupted and different; and at the same time is agreeable to the
- imagination, in attributing a continued existence to something else,
- which we call objects. This philosophical system, therefore, is the
- monstrous offspring of two principles, which are contrary to each
- other, which are both at once embraced by the mind, and which are unable
- mutually to destroy each other. The imagination tells us, that our
- resembling perceptions have a continued and uninterrupted existence, and
- are not annihilated by their absence. Reflection tells us, that even our
- resembling perceptions are interrupted in their existence, and different
- from each other. The contradiction betwixt these opinions we elude by a
- new fiction, which is conformable to the hypotheses both of reflection
- and fancy, by ascribing these contrary qualities to different
- existences; the interruption to perceptions, and the continuance to
- objects. Nature is obstinate, and will not quit the field, however
- strongly attacked by reason; and at the same time reason is so clear
- in the point, that there is no possibility of disguising her. Not being
- able to reconcile these two enemies, we endeavour to set ourselves at
- ease as much as possible, by successively granting to each whatever
- it demands, and by feigning a double existence, where each may find
- something, that has all the conditions it desires. Were we fully
- convinced, that our resembling perceptions are continued, and identical,
- and independent, we should never run into this opinion of a double
- existence, since we should find satisfaction in our first supposition,
- and would not look beyond. Again, were we fully convinced, that our
- perceptions are dependent, and interrupted, and different, we should be
- as little inclined to embrace the opinion of a double existence;
- since in that case we should clearly perceive the error of our first
- supposition of a continued existence, and would never regard it any
- farther. It is therefore from the intermediate situation of the mind,
- that this opinion arises, and from such an adherence to these two
- contrary principles, as makes us seek some pretext to justify our
- receiving both; which happily at last is found in the system of a double
- existence.
- Another advantage of this philosophical system is its similarity to the
- vulgar one; by which means we can humour our reason for a moment,
- when it becomes troublesome and sollicitous; and yet upon its least
- negligence or inattention, can easily return to our vulgar and natural
- notions. Accordingly we find, that philosophers neglect not this
- advantage; but immediately upon leaving their closets, mingle with the
- rest of mankind in those exploded opinions, that our perceptions are our
- only objects, and continue identically and uninterruptedly the same in
- all their interrupted appearances.
- There are other particulars of this system, wherein we may remark its
- dependence on the fancy, in a very conspicuous manner. Of these, I
- shall observe the two following. First, We suppose external objects to
- resemble internal perceptions. I have already shewn, that the relation
- of cause and effect can never afford us any just conclusion from the
- existence or qualities of our perceptions to the existence of external
- continued objects: And I shall farther add, that even though they coued
- afford such a conclusion, we should never have any reason to infer,
- that our objects resemble our perceptions. That opinion, therefore, is
- derived from nothing but the quality of the fancy above-explained,
- it borrows all its ideas from some precedent perception>. We never can
- conceive any thing but perceptions, and therefore must make every thing
- resemble them.
- Secondly, As we suppose our objects in general to resemble our
- perceptions, so we take it for granted, that every particular object
- resembles that perception, which it causes. The relation of cause and
- effect determines us to join the other of resemblance; and the ideas
- of these existences being already united together in the fancy by the
- former relation, we naturally add the latter to compleat the union.
- We have a strong propensity to compleat every union by joining new
- relations to those which we have before observed betwixt any ideas, as
- we shall have occasion to observe presently. [Sect. 5.]
- Having thus given an account of all the systems both popular and
- philosophical, with regard to external existences, I cannot forbear
- giving vent to a certain sentiment, which arises upon reviewing those
- systems. I begun this subject with premising, that we ought to have an
- implicit faith in our senses, and that this would be the conclusion, I
- should draw from the whole of my reasoning. But to be ingenuous, I feel
- myself at present of a quite contrary sentiment, and am more inclined
- to repose no faith at all in my senses, or rather imagination, than
- to place in it such an implicit confidence. I cannot conceive how such
- trivial qualities of the fancy, conducted by such false suppositions,
- can ever lead to any solid and rational system. They are the coherence
- and constancy of our perceptions, which produce the opinion of their
- continued existence; though these qualities of perceptions have no
- perceivable connexion with such an existence. The constancy of our
- perceptions has the most considerable effect, and yet is attended with
- the greatest difficulties. It is a gross illusion to suppose, that
- our resembling perceptions are numerically the same; and it is this
- illusion, which leads us into the opinion, that these perceptions are
- uninterrupted, and are still existent, even when they are not present
- to the senses. This is the case with our popular system. And as to
- our philosophical one, it is liable to the same difficulties; and is
- over-and-above loaded with this absurdity, that it at once denies and
- establishes the vulgar supposition. Philosophers deny our resembling
- perceptions to be identically the same, and uninterrupted; and yet have
- so great a propensity to believe them such, that they arbitrarily invent
- a new set of perceptions, to which they attribute these qualities. I
- say, a new set of perceptions: For we may well suppose in general, but
- it is impossible for us distinctly to conceive, objects to be in their
- nature any thing but exactly the same with perceptions. What then can
- we look for from this confusion of groundless and extraordinary opinions
- but error and falshood? And how can we justify to ourselves any belief
- we repose in them?
- This sceptical doubt, both with respect to reason and the senses, is
- a malady, which can never be radically cured, but must return upon
- us every moment, however we may chace it away, and sometimes may seem
- entirely free from it. It is impossible upon any system to defend either
- our understanding or senses; and we but expose them farther when we
- endeavour to justify them in that manner. As the sceptical doubt arises
- naturally from a profound and intense reflection on those subjects,
- it always encreases, the farther we carry our reflections, whether in
- opposition or conformity to it. Carelessness and in-attention alone can
- afford us any remedy. For this reason I rely entirely upon them; and
- take it for granted, whatever may be the reader's opinion at this
- present moment, that an hour hence he will be persuaded there is both an
- external and internal world; and going upon that supposition, I intend
- to examine some general systems both ancient and modern, which have
- been proposed of both, before I proceed to a more particular enquiry
- concerning our impressions. This will not, perhaps, in the end be found
- foreign to our present purpose.
- SECT. III. OF THE ANTIENT PHILOSOPHY.
- Several moralists have recommended it as an excellent method of becoming
- acquainted with our own hearts, and knowing our progress in virtue,
- to recollect our dreams in a morning, and examine them with the same
- rigour, that we would our most serious and most deliberate actions.
- Our character is the same throughout, say they, and appears best
- where artifice, fear, and policy have no place, and men can neither be
- hypocrites with themselves nor others. The generosity, or baseness
- of our temper, our meekness or cruelty, our courage or pusilanimity,
- influence the fictions of the imagination with the most unbounded
- liberty, and discover themselves in the most glaring colours. In like
- manner, I am persuaded, there might be several useful discoveries made
- from a criticism of the fictions of the antient philosophy, concerning
- substances, and substantial form, and accidents, and occult qualities;
- which, however unreasonable and capricious, have a very intimate
- connexion with the principles of human nature.
- It is confest by the most judicious philosophers, that our ideas of
- bodies are nothing but collections formed by the mind of the ideas of
- the several distinct sensible qualities, of which objects are composed,
- and which we find to have a constant union with each other. But however
- these qualities may in themselves be entirely distinct, it is certain
- we commonly regard the compound, which they form, as ONE thing, and
- as continuing the SAME under very considerable alterations. The
- acknowledged composition is evidently contrary to this supposed
- simplicity, and the variation to the identity. It may, therefore, be
- worth while to consider the causes, which make us almost universally
- fall into such evident contradictions, as well as the means by which we
- endeavour to conceal them.
- It is evident, that as the ideas of the several distinct, successive
- qualities of objects are united together by a very close relation, the
- mind, in looking along the succession, must be carryed from one part
- of it to another by an easy transition, and will no more perceive the
- change, than if it contemplated the same unchangeable object. This easy
- transition is the effect, or rather essence of relation; I and as the
- imagination readily takes one idea for another, where their influence
- on the mind is similar; hence it proceeds, that any such succession
- of related qualities is readily considered as one continued object,
- existing without any variation. The smooth and uninterrupted progress of
- the thought, being alike in both cases, readily deceives the mind, and
- makes us ascribe an identity to the changeable succession of connected
- qualities.
- But when we alter our method of considering the succession, and instead
- of traceing it gradually through the successive points of time, survey
- at once Any two distinct periods of its duration, and compare the
- different conditions of the successive qualities; in that case the
- variations, which were insensible when they arose gradually, do now
- appear of consequence, and seem entirely to destroy the identity. By
- this means there arises a kind of contrariety in our method of thinking,
- from the different points of view, in which we survey the object, and
- from the nearness or remoteness of those instants of time, which we
- compare together. When we gradually follow an object in its successive
- changes, the smooth progress of the thought makes us ascribe an identity
- to the succession; because it is by a similar act of the mind we
- consider an unchangeable object. When we compare its situation after
- a considerable change the progress of the thought is broke; and
- consequently we are presented with the idea of diversity: In order to
- reconcile which contradictions the imagination is apt to feign something
- unknown and invisible, which it supposes to continue the same under
- all these variations; and this unintelligible something it calls a
- substance, or original and first matter.
- We entertain a like notion with regard to the simplicity of substances,
- and from like causes. Suppose an object perfectly simple and indivisible
- to be presented, along with another object, whose co-existent parts are
- connected together by a strong relation, it is evident the actions of
- the mind, in considering these two objects, are not very different. The
- imagination conceives the simple object at once, with facility, by a
- single effort of thought, without change or variation. The connexion of
- parts in the compound object has almost the same effect, and so unites
- the object within itself, that the fancy feels not the transition in
- passing from one part to another. Hence the colour, taste, figure,
- solidity, and other qualities, combined in a peach or melon, are
- conceived to form one thing; and that on account of their close
- relation, which makes them affect the thought in the same manner, as if
- perfectly uncompounded. But the mind rests not here. Whenever it views
- the object in another light, it finds that all these qualities are
- different, and distinguishable, and separable from each other; which
- view of things being destructive of its primary and more natural
- notions, obliges the imagination to feign an unknown something, or
- original substance and matter, as a principle of union or cohesion among
- these qualities, and as what may give the compound object a title to be
- called one thing, notwithstanding its diversity and composition.
- The peripatetic philosophy asserts the original matter to be perfectly
- homogeneous in all bodies, and considers fire, water, earth, and air, as
- of the very same substance; on account of their gradual revolutions and
- changes into each other. At the same time it assigns to each of these
- species of objects a distinct substantial form, which it supposes to be
- the source of all those different qualities they possess, and to be a
- new foundation of simplicity and identity to each particular species.
- All depends on our manner of viewing the objects. When we look along the
- insensible changes of bodies, we suppose all of them to be of the same
- substance or essence. When we consider their sensible differences, we
- attribute to each of them a substantial and essential difference. And
- in order to indulge ourselves in both these ways of considering our
- objects, we suppose all bodies to have at once a substance and a
- substantial form.
- The notion of accidents is an unavoidable consequence of this method
- of thinking with regard to substances and substantial forms; nor can
- we forbear looking upon colours, sounds, tastes, figures, and other
- properties of bodies, as existences, which cannot subsist apart, but
- require a subject of inhesion to sustain and support them. For having
- never discovered any of these sensible qualities, where, for the reasons
- above-mentioned, we did not likewise fancy a substance to exist; the
- same habit, which makes us infer a connexion betwixt cause and effect,
- makes us here infer a dependence of every quality on the unknown
- substance. The custom of imagining a dependence has the same effect as
- the custom of observing it would have. This conceit, however, is no more
- reasonable than any of the foregoing. Every quality being a distinct
- thing from another, may be conceived to exist apart, and may exist
- apart, not only from every other quality, but from that unintelligible
- chimera of a substance.
- But these philosophers carry their fictions still farther in their
- sentiments concerning occult qualities, and both suppose a substance
- supporting, which they do not understand, and an accident supported, of
- which they have as imperfect an idea. The whole system, therefore, is
- entirely incomprehensible, and yet is derived from principles as natural
- as any of these above-explained.
- In considering this subject we may observe a gradation of three
- opinions, that rise above each other, according as the persons, who form
- them, acquire new degrees of reason and knowledge. These opinions are
- that of the vulgar, that of a false philosophy, and that of the true;
- where we shall find upon enquiry, that the true philosophy approaches
- nearer to the sentiments of the vulgar, than to those of a mistaken
- knowledge. It is natural for men, in their common and care, less way of
- thinking, to imagine they perceive a connexion betwixt such objects
- as they have constantly found united together; and because custom has
- rendered it difficult to separate the ideas, they are apt to fancy such
- a separation to be in itself impossible and absurd. But philosophers,
- who abstract from the effects of custom, and compare the ideas of
- objects, immediately perceive the falshood of these vulgar sentiments,
- and discover that there is no known connexion among objects. Every
- different object appears to them entirely distinct and separate; and
- they perceive, that it is not from a view of the nature and qualities of
- objects we infer one from another, but only when in several instances we
- observe them to have been constantly conjoined. But these philosophers,
- instead of drawing a just inference from this observation, and
- concluding, that we have no idea of power or agency, separate from
- the mind, and belonging to causes; I say, instead of drawing this
- conclusion, they frequently search for the qualities, in which this
- agency consists, and are displeased with every system, which their
- reason suggests to them, in order to explain it. They have sufficient
- force of genius to free them from the vulgar error, that there is a
- natural and perceivable connexion betwixt the several sensible qualities
- and actions of matter; but not sufficient to keep them from ever
- seeking for this connexion in matter, or causes. Had they fallen upon
- the just conclusion, they would have returned back to the situation
- of the vulgar, and would have regarded all these disquisitions with
- indolence and indifference. At present they seem to be in a very
- lamentable condition, and such as the poets have given us but a faint
- notion of in their descriptions of the punishment of Sisyphus and
- Tantalus. For what can be imagined more tormenting, than to seek with
- eagerness, what for ever flies us; and seek for it in a place, where it
- is impossible it can ever exist?
- But as nature seems to have observed a kind of justice and compensation
- in every thing, she has not neglected philosophers more than the rest
- of the creation; but has reserved them a consolation amid all their
- disappointments and afflictions. This consolation principally consists
- in their invention of the words: faculty and occult quality. For
- it being usual, after the frequent use of terms, which are really
- significant and intelligible, to omit the idea, which we would express
- by them, and to preserve only the custom, by which we recal the idea at
- pleasure; so it naturally happens, that after the frequent use of terms,
- which are wholly insignificant and unintelligible, we fancy them to be
- on the same footing with the precedent, and to have a secret meaning,
- which we might discover by reflection. The resemblance of their
- appearance deceives the mind, as is usual, and makes us imagine a
- thorough resemblance and conformity. By this means these philosophers
- set themselves at ease, and arrive at last, by an illusion, at the
- same indifference, which the people attain by their stupidity, and true
- philosophers by their moderate scepticism. They need only say, that
- any phenomenon, which puzzles them, arises from a faculty or an occult
- quality, and there is an end of all dispute and enquiry upon the matter.
- But among all the instances, wherein the Peripatetics have shewn they
- were guided by every trivial propensity of the imagination, no one is
- more-remarkable than their sympathies, antipathies, and horrors of
- a vacuum. There is a very remarkable inclination in human nature, to
- bestow on external objects the same emotions, which it observes in
- itself; and to find every where those ideas, which are most present to
- it. This inclination, it is true, is suppressed by a little reflection,
- and only takes place in children, poets, and the antient philosophers.
- It appears in children, by their desire of beating the stones, which
- hurt them: In poets, by their readiness to personify every thing: And in
- the antient philosophers, by these fictions of sympathy and antipathy.
- We must pardon children, because of their age; poets, because they
- profess to follow implicitly the suggestions of their fancy: But
- what excuse shall we find to justify our philosophers in so signal a
- weakness?
- SECT. IV. OF THE MODERN PHILOSOPHY.
- But here it may be objected, that the imagination, according to my own
- confession, being the ultimate judge of all systems of philosophy, I
- am unjust in blaming the antient philosophers for making use of that
- faculty, and allowing themselves to be entirely guided by it in their
- reasonings. In order to justify myself, I must distinguish in the
- imagination betwixt the principles which are permanent, irresistible,
- and universal; such as the customary transition from causes to effects,
- and from effects to causes: And the principles, which are changeable,
- weak, and irregular; such as those I have just now taken notice of. The
- former are the foundation of all our thoughts and actions, so that upon
- their removal human nature must immediately perish and go to ruin. The
- latter are neither unavoidable to mankind, nor necessary, or so much as
- useful in the conduct of life; but on the contrary are observed only to
- take place in weak minds, and being opposite to the other principles
- of custom and reasoning, may easily be subverted by a due contrast and
- opposition. For this reason the former are received by philosophy, and
- the latter rejected. One who concludes somebody to be near him, when
- he hears an articulate voice in the dark, reasons justly and naturally;
- though that conclusion be derived from nothing but custom, which infixes
- and inlivens the idea of a human creature, on account of his usual
- conjunction with the present impression. But one, who is tormented
- he knows not why, with the apprehension of spectres in the dark, may,
- perhaps, be said to reason, and to reason naturally too: But then it
- must be in the same sense, that a malady is said to be natural; as
- arising from natural causes, though it be contrary to health, the most
- agreeable and most natural situation of man.
- The opinions of the antient philosophers, their fictions of substance
- and accident, and their reasonings concerning substantial forms and
- occult qualities, are like the spectres in the dark, and are derived
- from principles, which, however common, are neither universal nor
- unavoidable in human nature. The modern philosophy pretends to be
- entirely free from this defect, and to arise only from the solid,
- permanent, and consistent principles of the imagination. Upon what
- grounds this pretension is founded must now be the subject of our
- enquiry.
- The fundamental principle of that philosophy is the opinion concerning
- colours, sounds, tastes, smells, heat and cold; which it asserts to
- be nothing but impressions in the mind, derived from the operation of
- external objects, and without any resemblance to the qualities of the
- objects. Upon examination, I find only one of the reasons commonly
- produced for this opinion to be satisfactory, viz. that derived from the
- variations of those impressions, even while the external object, to all
- appearance, continues the same. These variations depend upon several
- circumstances. Upon the different situations of our health: A man in a
- malady feels a disagreeable taste in meats, which before pleased him the
- most. Upon the different complexions and constitutions of men That seems
- bitter to one, which is sweet to another. Upon the difference of their
- external situation and position: Colours reflected from the clouds
- change according to the distance of the clouds, and according to the
- angle they make with the eye and luminous body. Fire also communicates
- the sensation of pleasure at one distance, and that of pain at another.
- Instances of this kind are very numerous and frequent.
- The conclusion drawn from them, is likewise as satisfactory as can
- possibly be imagined. It is certain, that when different impressions of
- the same sense arise from any object, every one of these impressions has
- not a resembling quality existent in the object. For as the same object
- cannot, at the same time, be endowed with different qualities of the
- same sense, and as the same quality cannot resemble impressions entirely
- different; it evidently follows, that many of our impressions have
- no external model or archetype. Now from like effects we presume like
- causes. Many of the impressions of colour, sound, &c. are confest to be
- nothing but internal existences, and to arise from causes, which no ways
- resemble them. These impressions are in appearance nothing different
- from the other impressions of colour, sound, &c. We conclude, therefore,
- that they are, all of them, derived from a like origin.
- This principle being once admitted, all the other doctrines of that
- philosophy seem to follow by an easy consequence. For upon the removal
- of sounds, colours, beat, cold, and other sensible qualities, from the
- rank of continued independent existences, we are reduced merely to what
- are called primary qualities, as the only real ones, of which we have
- any adequate notion. These primary qualities are extension and solidity,
- with their different mixtures and modifications; figure, motion,
- gravity, and cohesion. The generation, encrease, decay, and corruption
- of animals and vegetables, are nothing but changes of figure and motion;
- as also the operations of all bodies on each other; of fire, of light,
- water, air, earth, and of all the elements and powers of nature. One
- figure and motion produces another figure and motion; nor does there
- remain in the material universe any other principle, either active or
- passive, of which we can form the most distant idea.
- I believe many objections might be made to this system But at present
- I shall confine myself to one, which is in my opinion very decisive. I
- assert, that instead of explaining the operations of external objects by
- its means, we utterly annihilate all these objects, and reduce ourselves
- to the opinions of the most extravagant scepticism concerning them. If
- colours, sounds, tastes, and smells be merely perceptions, nothing we
- can conceive is possest of a real, continued, and independent existence;
- not even motion, extension and solidity, which are the primary qualities
- chiefly insisted on.
- To begin with the examination of motion; it is evident this is a quality
- altogether inconceivable alone, and without a reference to some other
- object. The idea of motion necessarily supposes that of a body moving.
- Now what is our idea of the moving body, without which motion is
- incomprehensible? It must resolve itself into the idea of extension or
- of solidity; and consequently the reality of motion depends upon that of
- these other qualities.
- This opinion, which is universally acknowledged concerning motion, I
- have proved to be true with regard to extension; and have shewn that it
- is impossible to conceive extension, but as composed of parts, endowed
- with colour or solidity. The idea of extension is a compound idea;
- but as it is not compounded of an infinite number of parts or inferior
- ideas, it must at last resolve itself into such as are perfectly simple
- and indivisible. These simple and indivisible parts, not being ideas of
- extension, must be non entities, unless conceived as coloured or solid.
- Colour is excluded from any real existence. The reality, therefore, of
- our idea of extension depends upon the reality of that of solidity, nor
- can the former be just while the latter is chimerical. Let us, then,
- lend our attention to the examination of the idea of solidity.
- The idea of solidity is that of two objects, which being impelled by the
- utmost force, cannot penetrate each other; but still maintain a
- separate and distinct existence. Solidity, therefore, is perfectly
- incomprehensible alone, and without the conception of some bodies, which
- are solid, and maintain this separate and distinct existence. Now what
- idea have we of these bodies? The ideas of colours, sounds, and other
- secondary qualities are excluded. The idea of motion depends on that
- of extension, and the idea of extension on that of solidity. It is
- impossible, therefore, that the idea of solidity can depend on either of
- them. For that would be to run in a circle, and make one idea depend on
- another, while at the same time the latter depends on the former. Our
- modern philosophy, therefore, leaves us no just nor satisfactory idea of
- solidity; nor consequently of matter.
- This argument will appear entirely conclusive to every one that
- comprehends it; but because it may seem abstruse and intricate to the
- generality of readers, I hope to be excused, if I endeavour to render
- it more obvious by some variation of the expression. In order to form
- an idea of solidity, we must conceive two bodies pressing on each other
- without any penetration; and it is impossible to arrive at this idea,
- when we confine ourselves to one object, much more without conceiving
- any. Two non-entities cannot exclude each other from their places;
- because they never possess any place, nor can be endowed with any
- quality. Now I ask, what idea do we form of these bodies or objects,
- to which we suppose solidity to belong? To say, that we conceive them
- merely as solid, is to run on in infinitum. To affirm, that we paint
- them out to ourselves as extended, either resolves all into a false
- idea, or returns in a circle. Extension must necessarily be considered
- either as coloured, which is a false idea; I or as solid, which
- brings us back to the first question. We may make the same observation
- concerning mobility and figure; and upon the whole must conclude, that
- after the exclusion of colours, sounds, heat and cold from the rank of
- external existences, there remains nothing, which can afford us a just
- and constituent idea of body.
- Add to this, that, properly speaking, solidity or impenetrability is
- nothing, but an impossibility of annihilation, as [Part II. Sect. 4.]
- has been already observed: For which reason it is the more necessary
- for us to form some distinct idea of that object, whose annihilation we
- suppose impossible. An impossibility of being annihilated cannot exist,
- and can never be conceived to exist, by itself: but necessarily
- requires some object or real existence, to which it may belong. Now
- the difficulty still remains, how to form an idea of this object
- or existence, without having recourse to the secondary and sensible
- qualities.
- Nor must we omit on this occasion our accustomed method of examining
- ideas by considering those impressions, from which they are derived. The
- impressions, which enter by the sight and hearing, the smell and taste,
- are affirmed by modern philosophy to be without any resembling objects;
- and consequently the idea of solidity, which is supposed to be real, can
- never be derived from any of these senses. There remains, therefore,
- the feeling as the only sense, that can convey the impression, which is
- original to the idea of solidity; and indeed we naturally imagine, that
- we feel the solidity of bodies, and need but touch any object in order
- to perceive this quality. But this method of thinking is more popular
- than philosophical; as will appear from the following reflections.
- First, It is easy to observe, that though bodies are felt by means of
- their solidity, yet the feeling is a quite different thing from the
- solidity; and that they have not the least resemblance to each other.
- A man, who has the palsey in one hand, has as perfect an idea of
- impenetrability, when he observes that hand to be supported by the
- table, as when he feels the same table with the other hand. An object,
- that presses upon any of our members, meets with resistance; and that
- resistance, by the motion it gives to the nerves and animal spirits,
- conveys a certain sensation to the mind; but it does not follow, that
- the sensation, motion, and resistance are any ways resembling.
- Secondly, The impressions of touch are simple impressions, except when
- considered with regard to their extension; which makes nothing to the
- present purpose: And from this simplicity I infer, that they neither
- represent solidity, nor any real object. For let us put two cases, viz.
- that of a man, who presses a stone, or any solid body, with his hand,
- and that of two stones, which press each other; it will readily be
- allowed, that these two cases are not in every respect alike, but
- that in the former there is conjoined with the solidity, a feeling or
- sensation, of which there is no appearance in the latter. In order,
- therefore, to make these two cases alike, it is necessary to remove some
- part of the impression, which the man feels by his hand, or organ of
- sensation; and that being impossible in a simple impression, obliges
- us to remove the whole, and proves that this whole impression has
- no archetype or model in external objects. To which we may add, that
- solidity necessarily supposes two bodies, along with contiguity and
- impulse; which being a compound object, can never be represented by a
- simple impression. Not to mention, that though solidity continues always
- invariably the same, the impressions of touch change every moment upon
- us; which is a clear proof that the latter are not representations of
- the former.
- Thus there is a direct and total opposition betwixt our reason and our
- senses; or more properly speaking, betwixt those conclusions we form
- from cause and effect, and those that persuade us of the continued and
- independent existence of body. When we reason from cause and effect, we
- conclude, that neither colour, sound, taste, nor smell have a continued
- and independent existence. When we exclude these sensible qualities
- there remains nothing in the universe, which has such an existence.
- SECT. V. OF THE IMMATERIALITY OF THE SOUL.
- Having found such contradictions and difficulties in every system
- concerning external objects, and in the idea of matter, which we fancy
- so clear and determinate, We shall naturally expect still greater
- difficulties and contradictions in every hypothesis concerning our
- internal perceptions, and the nature of the mind, which we are apt
- to imagine so much more obscure, and uncertain. But in this we should
- deceive ourselves. The intellectual world, though involved in infinite
- obscurities, is not perplexed with any such contradictions, as those we
- have discovered in the natural. What is known concerning it, agrees with
- itself; and what is unknown, we must be contented to leave so.
- It is true, would we hearken to certain philosophers, they promise to
- diminish our ignorance; but I am afraid it is at the hazard of running
- us into contradictions, from which the subject is of itself exempted.
- These philosophers are the curious reasoners concerning the material or
- immaterial substances, in which they suppose our perceptions to inhere.
- In order to put a stop to these endless cavils on both sides, I know no
- better method, than to ask these philosophers in a few words, What
- they mean by substance and inhesion? And after they have answered
- this question, it will then be reasonable, and not till then, to enter
- seriously into the dispute.
- This question we have found impossible to be answered with regard to
- matter and body: But besides that in the case of the mind, it labours
- under all the same difficulties, it is burthened with some additional
- ones, which are peculiar to that subject. As every idea is derived from
- a precedent impression, had we any idea of the substance of our minds,
- we must also have an impression of it; which is very difficult, if
- not impossible, to be conceived. For how can an impression represent a
- substance, otherwise than by resembling it? And how can an impression
- resemble a substance, since, according to this philosophy, it is not a
- substance, and has none of the peculiar qualities or characteristics of
- a substance?
- But leaving the question of what may or may not be, for that other what
- actually is, I desire those philosophers, who pretend that we have an
- idea of the substance of our minds, to point out the impression that
- produces it, and tell distinctly after what manner that impression
- operates, and from what object it is derived. Is it an impression of
- sensation or of reflection? Is it pleasant, or painful, or indifferent?
- I Does it attend us at all times, or does it only return at intervals?
- If at intervals, at what times principally does it return, and by what
- causes is it produced?
- If instead of answering these questions, any one should evade the
- difficulty, by saying, that the definition of a substance is something
- which may exist by itself; and that this definition ought to satisfy us:
- should this be said, I should observe, that this definition agrees to
- every thing, that can possibly be conceived; and never will serve to
- distinguish substance from accident, or the soul from its perceptions.
- For thus I reason. Whatever is clearly conceived may exist; and whatever
- is clearly conceived, after any manner, may exist after the same manner.
- This is one principle, which has been already acknowledged. Again, every
- thing, which is different, is distinguishable, and every thing which
- is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination. This is another
- principle. My conclusion from both is, that since all our perceptions
- are different from each other, and from every thing else in the
- universe, they are also distinct and separable, and may be considered as
- separately existent, and may exist separately, and have no need of any
- thing else to support their existence. They are, therefore, substances,
- as far as this definition explains a substance.
- Thus neither by considering the first origin of ideas, nor by means of
- a definition are we able to arrive at any satisfactory notion of
- substance; which seems to me a sufficient reason for abandoning utterly
- that dispute concerning the materiality and immateriality of the soul,
- and makes me absolutely condemn even the question itself. We have no
- perfect idea of any thing but of a perception. A substance is entirely
- different from a perception. We have, therefore, no idea of a substance.
- Inhesion in something is supposed to be requisite to support the
- existence of our perceptions. Nothing appears requisite to support the
- existence of a perception. We have, therefore, no idea of inhesion. What
- possibility then of answering that question, Whether perceptions
- inhere in a material or immaterial substance, when we do not so much as
- understand the meaning of the question?
- There is one argument commonly employed for the immateriality of the
- soul, which seems to me remarkable. Whatever is extended consists of
- parts; and whatever consists of parts is divisible, if not in reality,
- at least in the imagination. But it is impossible anything divisible
- can be conjoined to a thought or perception, which is a being altogether
- inseparable and indivisible. For supposing such a conjunction, would
- the indivisible thought exist on the left or on the right hand of this
- extended divisible body? On the surface or in the middle? On the back
- or fore side of it? If it be conjoined with the extension, it must exist
- somewhere within its dimensions. If it exist within its dimensions, it
- must either exist in one particular part; and then that particular part
- is indivisible, and the perception is conjoined only with it, not with
- the extension: Or if the thought exists in every part, it must also be
- extended, and separable, and divisible, as well as the body; which is
- utterly absurd and contradictory. For can any one conceive a passion of
- a yard in length, a foot in breadth, and an inch in thickness? Thought,
- therefore, and extension are qualities wholly incompatible, and never
- can incorporate together into one subject.
- This argument affects not the question concerning the substance of the
- soul, but only that concerning its local conjunction with matter; and
- therefore it may not be improper to consider in general what objects
- are, or are not susceptible of a local conjunction. This is a curious
- question, and may lead us to some discoveries of considerable moment.
- The first notion of space and extension is derived solely from the
- senses of sight and feeling; nor is there any thing, but what is
- coloured or tangible, that has parts disposed after such a manner, as to
- convey that idea. When we diminish or encrease a relish, it is not after
- the same manner that we diminish or encrease any visible object; and
- when several sounds strike our hearing at once, custom and reflection
- alone make us form an idea of the degrees of the distance and contiguity
- of those bodies, from which they are derived. Whatever marks the place
- of its existence either must be extended, or must be a mathematical
- point, without parts or composition. What is extended must have a
- particular figure, as square, round, triangular; none of which will
- agree to a desire, or indeed to any impression or idea, except to these
- two senses above-mentioned. Neither ought a desire, though indivisible,
- to be considered as a mathematical point. For in that case it would be
- possible, by the addition of others, to make two, three, four desires,
- and these disposed and situated in such a manner, as to have a
- determinate length, breadth and thickness; which is evidently absurd.
- It will not be surprising after this, if I deliver a maxim, which is
- condemned by several metaphysicians, and is esteemed contrary to the
- most certain principles of hum reason. This maxim is that an object
- may exist, and yet be no where: and I assert, that this is not only
- possible, but that the greatest part of beings do and must exist after
- this manner. An object may be said to be no where, when its parts are
- not so situated with respect to each other, as to form any figure or
- quantity; nor the whole with respect to other bodies so as to answer to
- our notions of contiguity or distance. Now this is evidently the case
- with all our perceptions and objects, except those of the sight and
- feeling. A moral reflection cannot be placed on the right or on the left
- hand of a passion, nor can a smell or sound be either of a circular or a
- square figure. These objects and perceptions, so far from requiring
- any particular place, are absolutely incompatible with it, and even
- the imagination cannot attribute it to them. And as to the absurdity of
- supposing them to be no where, we may consider, that if the passions and
- sentiments appear to the perception to have any particular place, the
- idea of extension might be derived from them, as well as from the sight
- and touch; contrary to what we have already established. If they APPEAR
- not to have any particular place, they may possibly exist in the same
- manner; since whatever we conceive is possible.
- It will not now be necessary to prove, that those perceptions, which are
- simple, and exist no where, are incapable of any conjunction in place
- with matter or body, which is extended and divisible; since it is
- impossible to found a relation but on some common quality. It may
- be better worth our while to remark, that this question of the local
- conjunction of objects does not only occur in metaphysical disputes
- concerning the nature of the soul, but that even in common life we have
- every moment occasion to examine it. Thus supposing we consider a fig at
- one end of the table, and an olive at the other, it is evident, that in
- forming the complex ideas of these substances, one of the most obvious
- is that of their different relishes; and it is as evident, that we
- incorporate and conjoin these qualities with such as are coloured
- and tangible. The bitter taste of the one, and sweet of the other are
- supposed to lie in the very visible body, and to be separated from
- each other by the whole length of the table. This is so notable and so
- natural an illusion, that it may be proper to consider the principles,
- from which it is derived.
- Though an extended object be incapable of a conjunction in place with
- another, that exists without any place or extension, yet are they
- susceptible of many other relations. Thus the taste and smell of
- any fruit are inseparable from its other qualities of colour and
- tangibility; and whichever of them be the cause or effect, it is certain
- they are always co-existent. Nor are they only co-existent in general,
- but also co-temporary in their appearance in the mind; and it is upon
- the application of the extended body to our senses we perceive its
- particular taste and smell. These relations, then, of causation, and
- contiguity in the time of their appearance, betwixt the extended object
- and the quality, which exists without any particular place, must have
- such an effect on the mind, that upon the appearance of one it will
- immediately turn its thought to the conception of the other. Nor is this
- all. We not only turn our thought from one to the other upon account of
- their relation, but likewise endeavour to give them a new relation, viz.
- that of a CONJUNCTION IN PLACE, that we may render the transition more
- easy and natural. For it is a quality, which I shall often have occasion
- to remark in human nature, and shall explain more fully in its proper
- place, that when objects are united by any relation, we have a strong
- propensity to add some new relation to them, in order to compleat the
- union. In our arrangement of bodies we never fail to place such as are
- resembling, in contiguity to each other, or at least in correspondent
- points of view: Why? but because we feel a satisfaction in joining the
- relation of contiguity to that of resemblance, or the resemblance of
- situation to that of qualities. The effects this propensity have been
- [Sect. 2, towards the end.] already observed in that resemblance, which
- we so readily suppose betwixt particular impressions and their external
- causes. But we shall not find a more evident effect of it, than in the
- present instance, where from the relations of causation and contiguity
- in time betwixt two objects, we feign likewise that of a conjunction in
- place, in order to strengthen the connexion.
- But whatever confused notions we may form of an union in place betwixt
- an extended body, as a fig, and its particular taste, it is certain
- that upon reflection we must observe this union something altogether
- unintelligible and contradictory. For should we ask ourselves one
- obvious question, viz. if the taste, which we conceive to be contained
- in the circumference of the body, is in every part of it or in one only,
- we must quickly find ourselves at a loss, and perceive the impossibility
- of ever giving a satisfactory answer. We cannot rely, that it is only
- in one part: For experience convinces us, that every part has the same
- relish. We can as little reply, that it exists in every part: For
- then we must suppose it figured and extended; which is absurd and
- incomprehensible. Here then we are influenced by two principles directly
- contrary to each other, viz. that inclination of our fancy by which we
- are determined to incorporate the taste with the extended object, and
- our reason, which shows us the impossibility of such an union. Being
- divided betwixt these opposite principles, we renounce neither one nor
- the other, but involve the subject in such confusion and obscurity, that
- we no longer perceive the opposition. We suppose, that the taste exists
- within the circumference of the body, but in such a manner, that it
- fills the whole without extension, and exists entire in every part
- without separation. In short, we use in our most familiar way of
- thinking, that scholastic principle, which, when crudely proposed,
- appears so shocking, of TOTUM IN TOTO & TOLUM IN QUALIBET PARTE: Which
- is much the same, as if we should say, that a thing is in a certain
- place, and yet is not there.
- All this absurdity proceeds from our endeavouring to bestow a place on
- what is utterly incapable of it; and that endeavour again arises from
- our inclination to compleat an union, which is founded on causation,
- and a contiguity of time, by attributing to the objects a conjunction in
- place. But if ever reason be of sufficient force to overcome prejudice,
- it is certain, that in the present case it must prevail. For we have
- only this choice left, either to suppose that some beings exist without
- any place; or that they are figured and extended; or that when they are
- incorporated with extended objects, the whole is in the whole, and the
- whole in every part. The absurdity of the two last suppositions proves
- sufficiently the veracity of the first. Nor is there any fourth
- opinion. For as to the supposition of their existence in the manner of
- mathematical points, it resolves itself into the second opinion, and
- supposes, that several passions may be placed in a circular figure,
- and that a certain number of smells, conjoined with a certain number of
- sounds, may make a body of twelve cubic inches; which appears ridiculous
- upon the bare mentioning of it.
- But though in this view of things we cannot refuse to condemn the
- materialists, who conjoin all thought with extension; yet a little
- reflection will show us equal reason for blaming their antagonists, who
- conjoin all thought with a simple and indivisible substance. The most
- vulgar philosophy informs us, that no external object can make itself
- known to the mind immediately, and without the interposition of an
- image or perception. That table, which just now appears to me, is only a
- perception, and all its qualities are qualities of a perception. Now the
- most obvious of all its qualities is extension. The perception consists
- of parts. These parts are so situated, as to afford us the notion
- of distance and contiguity; of length, breadth, and thickness. The
- termination of these three dimensions is what we call figure. This
- figure is moveable, separable, and divisible. Mobility, and separability
- are the distinguishing properties of extended objects. And to cut short
- all disputes, the very idea of extension is copyed from nothing but an
- impression, and consequently must perfectly agree to it. To say the idea
- of extension agrees to any thing, is to say it is extended.
- The free-thinker may now triumph in his turn; and having found there are
- impressions and ideas really extended, may ask his antagonists, how
- they can incorporate a simple and indivisible subject with an extended
- perception? All the arguments of Theologians may here be retorted upon
- them. Is the indivisible subject, or immaterial substance, if you
- will, on the left or on the right hand of the perception? Is it in this
- particular part, or in that other? Is it in every part without being
- extended? Or is it entire in any one part without deserting the rest? It
- is impossible to give any answer to these questions, but what will both
- be absurd in itself, and will account for the union of our indivisible
- perceptions with an extended substance.
- This gives me an occasion to take a-new into consideration the question
- concerning the substance of the soul; and though I have condemned that
- question as utterly unintelligible, yet I cannot forbear proposing some
- farther reflections concerning it. I assert, that the doctrine of the
- immateriality, simplicity, and indivisibility of a thinking substance
- is a true atheism, and will serve to justify all those sentiments, for
- which Spinoza is so universally infamous. From this topic, I hope at
- least to reap one advantage, that my adversaries will not have any
- pretext to render the present doctrine odious by their declamations,
- when they see that they can be so easily retorted on them.
- The fundamental principle of the atheism of Spinoza is the doctrine
- of the simplicity of the universe, and the unity of that substance, in
- which he supposes both thought and matter to inhere. There is only one
- substance, says he, in the world; and that substance is perfectly simple
- and indivisible, and exists every where, without any local presence.
- Whatever we discover externally by sensation; whatever we feel
- internally by reflection; all these are nothing but modifications of
- that one, simple, and necessarily existent being, and are not possest
- of any separate or distinct existence. Every passion of the soul; every
- configuration of matter, however different and various, inhere in
- the same substance, and preserve in themselves their characters of
- distinction, without communicating them to that subject, in which
- they inhere. The same substratum, if I may so speak, supports the most
- different modifications, without any difference in itself; and varies
- them, without any variation. Neither time, nor place, nor all the
- diversity of nature are able to produce any composition or change in its
- perfect simplicity and identity.
- I believe this brief exposition of the principles of that famous atheist
- will be sufficient for the present purpose, and that without entering
- farther into these gloomy and obscure regions, I shall be able to
- shew, that this hideous hypothesis is almost the same with that of the
- immateriality of the soul, which has become so popular. To make this
- evident, let us [Part II, Sect. 6.] remember, that as every idea is
- derived from a preceding perception, it is impossible our idea of
- a perception, and that of an object or external existence can ever
- represent what are specifically different from each other. Whatever
- difference we may suppose betwixt them, it is still incomprehensible to
- us; and we are obliged either to conceive an external object merely as
- a relation without a relative, or to make it the very same with a
- perception or impression.
- The consequence I shall draw from this may, at first sight, appear a
- mere sophism; but upon the least examination will be found solid and
- satisfactory. I say then, that since we may suppose, but never can
- conceive a specific deference betwixt an object and impression;
- any conclusion we form concerning the connexion and repugnance of
- impressions, will not be known certainly to be applicable to objects;
- but that on the other hand, whatever conclusions of this kind we form
- concerning objects, will most certainly be applicable to impressions.
- The reason is not difficult. As an object is supposed to be different
- from an impression, we cannot be sure, that the circumstance, upon
- which we found our reasoning, is common to both, supposing we form the
- reasoning upon the impression. It is still possible, that the object may
- differ from it in that particular. But when we first form our reasoning
- concerning the object, it is beyond doubt, that the same reasoning must
- extend to the impression: And that because the quality of the object,
- upon which the argument is founded, must at least be conceived by
- the mind; and coued not be conceived, unless it were common to an
- impression; since we have no idea but what is derived from that origin.
- Thus we may establish it as a certain maxim, that we can never, by any
- principle, but by an irregular kind [Such as that of Sect. 2, form the
- coherence of our perceptions.] of reasoning from experience, discover
- a connexion or repugnance betwixt objects, which extends not to
- impressions; though the inverse proposition may not be equally true,
- that all the discoverable relations of impressions are common to
- objects.
- To apply this to the present case; there are two different systems
- of being presented, to which I suppose myself under necessity of
- assigning some substance, or ground of inhesion. I observe first the
- universe of objects or of body: The sun, moon and stars; the earth,
- seas, plants, animals, men, ships, houses, and other productions either
- of art or nature. Here Spinoza appears, and tells me, that these are
- only modifications; and that the subject, in which they inhere, is
- simple, incompounded, and indivisible. After this I consider the other
- system of beings, viz. the universe of thought, or my impressions and
- ideas. There I observe another sun, moon and stars; an earth, and seas,
- covered and inhabited by plants and animals; towns, houses, mountains,
- rivers; and in short every thing I can discover or conceive in the
- first system. Upon my enquiring concerning these, Theologians present
- themselves, and tell me, that these also are modifications, and
- modifications of one simple, uncompounded, and indivisible substance.
- Immediately upon which I am deafened with the noise of a hundred voices,
- that treat the first hypothesis with detestation and scorn, and the
- second with applause and veneration. I turn my attention to these
- hypotheses to see what may be the reason of so great a partiality; and
- find that they have the same fault of being unintelligible, and that
- as far as we can understand them, they are so much alike, that it is
- impossible to discover any absurdity in one, which is not common to both
- of them. We have no idea of any quality in an object, which does not
- agree to, and may not represent a quality in an impression; and that
- because all our ideas are derived from our impressions. We can
- never, therefore, find any repugnance betwixt an extended object as
- a modification, and a simple uncompounded essence, as its substance,
- unless that repugnance takes place equally betwixt the perception or
- impression of that extended object, and the same uncompounded essence.
- Every idea of a quality in an object passes through an impression;
- and therefore every perceivable relation, whether of connexion or
- repugnance, must be common both to objects and impressions.
- But though this argument, considered in general, seems evident beyond
- all doubt and contradiction, yet to make it more clear and sensible, let
- us survey it in detail; and see whether all the absurdities, which have
- been found in the system of Spinoza, may not likewise be discovered in
- that of Theologians. [See Bayle's dictionary, article of Spinoza.]
- First, It has been said against Spinoza, according to the scholastic way
- of talking, rather than thinking, that a mode, not being any distinct
- or separate existence, must be the very same with its substance,
- and consequently the extension of the universe, must be in a manner
- identifyed with that, simple, uncompounded essence, in which the
- universe is supposed to inhere. But this, it may be pretended, is
- utterly impossible and inconceivable unless the indivisible substance
- expand itself, so as to correspond to the extension, or the extension
- contract itself, so as to answer to the indivisible substance. This
- argument seems just, as far as we can understand it; and it is plain
- nothing is required, but a change in the terms, to apply the same
- argument to our extended perceptions, and the simple essence of the
- soul; the ideas of objects and perceptions being in every respect
- the same, only attended with the supposition of a difference, that is
- unknown and incomprehensible.
- Secondly, It has been said, that we have no idea of substance, which is
- not applicable to matter; nor any idea of a distinct substance, which is
- not applicable to every distinct portion of matter. Matter, therefore,
- is not a mode but a substance, and each part of matter is not a distinct
- mode, but a distinct substance. I have already proved, that we have no
- perfect idea of substance; but that taking it for something, that can
- exist by itself, it is evident every perception is a substance,
- and every distinct part of a perception a distinct substance: And
- consequently the one hypothesis labours under the same difficulties in
- this respect with the other.
- Thirdly, It has been objected to the system of one simple substance in
- the universe, that this substance being the support or substratum of
- every thing, must at the very same instant be modifyed into forms,
- which are contrary and incompatible. The round and square figures are
- incompatible in the same substance at the same time. How then is it
- possible, that the same substance can at once be modifyed into
- that square table, and into this round one? I ask the same question
- concerning the impressions of these tables; and find that the answer is
- no more satisfactory in one case than in the other.
- It appears, then, that to whatever side we turn, the same difficulties
- follow us, and that we cannot advance one step towards the establishing
- the simplicity and immateriality o the soul, without preparing the
- way for a dangerous and irrecoverable atheism. It is the same case, if
- instead o calling thought a modification of the soul, we should give it
- the more antient, and yet more modish name of an action. By an action we
- mean much the same thing, as what is commonly called an abstract
- mode; that is, something, which, properly speaking, is neither
- distinguishable, nor separable from its substance, and is only conceived
- by a distinction of reason, or an abstraction. But nothing is gained by
- this change of the term of modification, for that of action; nor do we
- free ourselves from one single difficulty by its means; as will appear
- from the two following reflexions.
- First, I observe, that the word, action, according to this explication
- of it, can never justly be applied to any perception, as derived from
- a mind or thinking substance. Our perceptions are all really different,
- and separable, and distinguishable from each other, and from everything
- else, which we can imagine: and therefore it is impossible to conceive,
- how they can be the action or abstract mode of any substance. The
- instance of motion, which is commonly made use of to shew after what
- manner perception depends, as an action, upon its substance, rather
- confounds than instructs us. Motion to all appearance induces no real
- nor essential change on the body, but only varies its relation to other
- objects. But betwixt a person in the morning walking a garden with
- company, agreeable to him; and a person in the afternoon inclosed in a
- dungeon, and full of terror, despair, and resentment, there seems to be
- a radical difference, and of quite another kind, than what is produced
- on a body by the change of its situation. As we conclude from the
- distinction and separability of their ideas, that external objects
- have a separate existence from each other; so when we make these ideas
- themselves our objects, we must draw the same conclusion concerning
- them, according to the precedent reasoning. At least it must be confest,
- that having idea of the substance of the soul, it is impossible for us
- to tell how it can admit of such differences, and even contrarieties of
- perception without any fundamental change; and consequently can never
- tell in what sense perceptions are actions of that substance. The use,
- therefore, of the word, action, unaccompanyed with any meaning, instead
- of that of modification, makes no addition to our knowledge, nor is of
- any advantage to the doctrine of the immateriality of the soul.
- I add in the second place, that if it brings any advantage to that
- cause, it must bring an equal to the cause of atheism. For do our
- Theologians pretend to make a monopoly of the word, action, and may not
- the atheists likewise take possession of it, and affirm that plants,
- animals, men, &c. are nothing but particular actions of one simple
- universal substance, which exerts itself from a blind and
- absolute necessity? This you'll say is utterly absurd. I own it is
- unintelligible; but at the same time assert, according to the principles
- above-explained, that it is impossible to discover any absurdity in the
- supposition, that all the various objects in nature are actions of
- one simple substance, which absurdity will not be applicable to a like
- supposition concerning impressions and ideas.
- From these hypotheses concerning the substance and local conjunction of
- our perceptions, we may pass to another, which is more intelligible
- than the former, and more important than the latter, viz. concerning the
- cause of our perceptions. Matter and motion, it is commonly said in the
- schools, however varyed, are still matter and motion, and produce only
- a difference in the position and situation of objects. Divide a body as
- often as you please, it is still body. Place it in any figure, nothing
- ever results but figure, or the relation of parts. Move it in any
- manner, you still find motion or a change of relation. It is absurd to
- imagine, that motion in a circle, for instance, should be nothing but
- merely motion in a circle; while motion in another direction, as in an
- ellipse, should also be a passion or moral reflection: That the shocking
- of two globular particles should become a sensation of pain, and that
- the meeting of two triangular ones should afford a pleasure. Now as
- these different shocks, and variations, and mixtures are the only
- changes, of which matter is susceptible, and as these never afford us
- any idea of thought or perception, it is concluded to be impossible,
- that thought can ever be caused by matter.
- Few have been able to withstand the seeming evidence of this argument;
- and yet nothing in the world is more easy than to refute it. We need
- only reflect on what has been proved at large, that we are never
- sensible of any connexion betwixt causes and effects, and that it is
- only by our experience of their constant conjunction, we can arrive
- at any knowledge of this relation. Now as all objects, which are not
- contrary, are susceptible of a constant conjunction, and as no real
- objects are contrary [Part III. Sect. 15.]; I have inferred from these
- principles, that to consider the matter A PRIORI, any thing may produce
- any thing, and that we shall never discover a reason, why any object may
- or may not be the cause of any other, however great, or however little
- the resemblance may be betwixt them. This evidently destroys the
- precedent reasoning concerning the cause of thought or perception. For
- though there appear no manner of connexion betwixt motion or thought,
- the case is the same with all other causes and effects. Place one body
- of a pound weight on one end of a lever, and another body of the same
- weight on another end; you will never find in these bodies any principle
- of motion dependent on their distances from the center, more than of
- thought and perception. If you pretend, therefore, to prove a priori,
- that such a position of bodies can never cause thought; because turn it
- which way you will, it is nothing but a position of bodies; you must by
- the same course of reasoning conclude, that it can never produce motion;
- since there is no more apparent connexion in the one case than in the
- other. But as this latter conclusion is contrary to evident experience,
- and as it is possible we may have a like experience in the operations of
- the mind, and may perceive a constant conjunction of thought and motion;
- you reason too hastily, when from the mere consideration of the ideas,
- you conclude that it is impossible motion can ever produce thought, or
- a different position of parts give rise to a different passion or
- reflection. Nay it is not only possible we may have such an experience,
- but it is certain we have it; since every one may perceive, that the
- different dispositions of his body change his thoughts and sentiments.
- And should it be said, that this depends on the union of soul and
- body; I would answer, that we must separate the question concerning the
- substance of the mind from that concerning the cause of its thought; and
- that confining ourselves to the latter question we find by the comparing
- their ideas, that thought and motion are different from each other,
- and by experience, that they are constantly united; which being all
- the circumstances, that enter into the idea of cause and effect, when
- applied to the operations of matter, we may certainly conclude, that
- motion may be, and actually is, the cause of thought and perception.
- There seems only this dilemma left us in the present case; either to
- assert, that nothing can be the cause of another, but where the mind can
- perceive the connexion in its idea of the objects: Or to maintain, that
- all objects, which we find constantly conjoined, are upon that account
- to be regarded as causes and effects. If we choose the first part of the
- dilemma, these are the consequences. First, We in reality affirm,
- that there is no such thing in the universe as a cause or productive
- principle, not even the deity himself; since our idea of that supreme
- Being is derived from particular impressions, none of which contain any
- efficacy, nor seem to have any connexion with any other existence. As to
- what may be said, that the connexion betwixt the idea of an infinitely
- powerful being, and that of any effect, which he wills, is necessary and
- unavoidable; I answer, that we have no idea of a being endowed with
- any power, much less of one endowed with infinite power. But if we will
- change expressions, we can only define power by connexion; and then in
- saying, that the idea, of an infinitely powerful being is connected with
- that of every effect, which he wills, we really do no more than
- assert, that a being, whose volition is connected with every effect,
- is connected with every effect: which is an identical proposition, and
- gives us no insight into the nature of this power or connexion. But,
- secondly, supposing, that the deity were the great and efficacious
- principle, which supplies the deficiency of all causes, this leads us
- into the grossest impieties and absurdities. For upon the same account,
- that we have recourse to him in natural operations, and assert that
- matter cannot of itself communicate motion, or produce thought, viz.
- because there is no apparent connexion betwixt these objects; I say,
- upon the very same account, we must acknowledge that the deity is the
- author of all our volitions and perceptions; since they have no more
- apparent connexion either with one another, or with the supposed but
- unknown substance of the soul. This agency of the supreme Being we know
- to have been asserted by [As father Malebranche and other Cartesians.]
- several philosophers with relation to all the actions of the mind,
- except volition, or rather an inconsiderable part of volition; though it
- is easy to perceive, that this exception is a mere pretext, to avoid the
- dangerous consequences of that doctrine. If nothing be active but
- what has an apparent power, thought is in no case any more active than
- matter; and if this inactivity must make us have recourse to a deity,
- the supreme being is the real cause of all our actions, bad as well as
- good, vicious as well as virtuous.
- Thus we are necessarily reduced to the other side of the dilemma, viz..
- that all objects, which are found to be constantly conjoined, are upon
- that account only to be regarded as causes and effects. Now as
- all objects, which are not contrary, are susceptible of a constant
- conjunction, and as no real objects are contrary: it follows, that for
- ought we can determine by the mere ideas, any thing may be the cause
- or effect of any thing; which evidently gives the advantage to the
- materialists above their antagonists.
- To pronounce, then, the final decision upon the whole; the question
- concerning the substance of the soul is absolutely unintelligible: All
- our perceptions are not susceptible of a local union, either with what
- is extended or unextended: there being some of them of the one kind,
- and some of the other: And as the constant conjunction of objects
- constitutes the very essence of cause and effect, matter and motion may
- often be regarded as the causes of thought, as far as we have any notion
- of that relation.
- It is certainly a kind of indignity to philosophy, whose sovereign
- authority ought every where to be acknowledged, to oblige her on every
- occasion to make apologies for her conclusions, and justify herself to
- every particular art and science, which may be offended at her. This
- puts one in mind of a king arrainged for high-treason against his
- subjects. There is only one occasion, when philosophy will think it
- necessary and even honourable to justify herself, and that is, when
- religion may seem to be in the least offended; whose rights are as
- dear to her as her own, and are indeed the same. If any one, therefore,
- should imagine that the foregoing arguments are any ways dangerous to
- religion, I hope the following apology will remove his apprehensions.
- There is no foundation for any conclusion a priori, either concerning
- the operations or duration of any object, of which it is possible for
- the human mind to form a conception. Any object may be imagined to
- become entirely inactive, or to be annihilated in a moment; and it is an
- evident principle, that whatever we can imagine, is possible. Now this
- is no more true of matter, than of spirit; of an extended compounded
- substance, than of a simple and unextended. In both cases the
- metaphysical arguments for the immortality of the soul are equally
- inconclusive: and in both cases the moral arguments and those derived
- from the analogy of nature are equally strong and convincing. If my
- philosophy, therefore, makes no addition to the arguments for religion,
- I have at least the satisfaction to think it takes nothing from them,
- but that every thing remains precisely as before.
- SECT. VI. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY
- There are some philosophers who imagine we are every moment intimately
- conscious of what we call our SELF; that we feel its existence and its
- continuance in existence; and are certain, beyond the evidence of a
- demonstration, both o its perfect identity and simplicity. The strongest
- sensation, the most violent passion, say they, instead of distracting
- us from this view, only fix it the more intensely, and make us consider
- their influence on self either by their pain or pleasure. To attempt a
- farther proof of this were to weaken its evidence; since no proof can be
- derived from any fact, of which we are so intimately conscious; nor is
- there any thing, of which we can be certain, if we doubt of this.
- Unluckily all these positive assertions are contrary to that very
- experience, which is pleaded for them, nor have we any idea of self,
- after the manner it is here explained. For from what impression coued
- this idea be derived? This question it is impossible to answer without
- a manifest contradiction and absurdity; and yet it is a question, which
- must necessarily be answered, if we would have the idea of self pass for
- clear and intelligible, It must be some one impression, that gives rise
- to every real idea. But self or person is not any one impression, but
- that to which our several impressions and ideas are supposed to have
- a reference. If any impression gives rise to the idea of self, that
- impression must continue invariably the same, through the whole course
- of our lives; since self is supposed to exist after that manner. But
- there is no impression constant and invariable. Pain and pleasure, grief
- and joy, passions and sensations succeed each other, and never all
- exist at the same time. It cannot, therefore, be from any of these
- impressions, or from any other, that the idea of self is derived; and
- consequently there is no such idea.
- But farther, what must become of all our particular perceptions upon
- this hypothesis? All these are different, and distinguishable, and
- separable from each other, and may be separately considered, and may
- exist separately, and have no Deed of tiny thing to support their
- existence. After what manner, therefore, do they belong to self; and how
- are they connected with it? For my part, when I enter most intimately
- into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception
- or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or
- pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and
- never can observe any thing but the perception. When my perceptions
- are removed for any time, as by sound sleep; so long am I insensible of
- myself, and may truly be said not to exist. And were all my perceptions
- removed by death, and coued I neither think, nor feel, nor see, nor
- love, nor hate after the dissolution of my body, I should be entirely
- annihilated, nor do I conceive what is farther requisite to make me a
- perfect non-entity. If any one, upon serious and unprejudiced reflection
- thinks he has a different notion of himself, I must confess I call
- reason no longer with him. All I can allow him is, that he may be in
- the right as well as I, and that we are essentially different in this
- particular. He may, perhaps, perceive something simple and continued,
- which he calls himself; though I am certain there is no such principle
- in me.
- But setting aside some metaphysicians of this kind, I may venture to
- affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but a bundle or
- collection of different perceptions, which succeed each other with an
- inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement. Our
- eyes cannot turn in their sockets without varying our perceptions. Our
- thought is still more variable than our sight; and all our other senses
- and faculties contribute to this change; nor is there any single power
- of the soul, which remains unalterably the same, perhaps for one moment.
- The mind is a kind of theatre, where several perceptions successively
- make their appearance; pass, re-pass, glide away, and mingle in an
- infinite variety of postures and situations. There is properly no
- simplicity in it at one time, nor identity in different; whatever
- natural propension we may have to imagine that simplicity and identity.
- The comparison of the theatre must not mislead us. They are the
- successive perceptions only, that constitute the mind; nor have we the
- most distant notion of the place, where these scenes are represented, or
- of the materials, of which it is composed.
- What then gives us so great a propension to ascribe an identity to
- these successive perceptions, and to suppose ourselves possest of an
- invariable and uninterrupted existence through the whole course of our
- lives? In order to answer this question, we must distinguish betwixt
- personal identity, as it regards our thought or imagination, and as it
- regards our passions or the concern we take in ourselves. The first is
- our present subject; and to explain it perfectly we must take the matter
- pretty deep, and account for that identity, which we attribute to plants
- and animals; there being a great analogy betwixt it, and the identity of
- a self or person.
- We have a distinct idea of an object, that remains invariable and
- uninterrupted through a supposed variation of time; and this idea we
- call that of identity or sameness. We have also a distinct idea of
- several different objects existing in succession, and connected together
- by a close relation; and this to an accurate view affords as perfect
- a notion of diversity, as if there was no manner of relation among the
- objects. But though these two ideas of identity, and a succession of
- related objects be in themselves perfectly distinct, and even contrary,
- yet it is certain, that in our common way of thinking they are generally
- confounded with each other. That action of the imagination, by which we
- consider the uninterrupted and invariable object, and that by which we
- reflect on the succession of related objects, are almost the same to the
- feeling, nor is there much more effort of thought required in the latter
- case than in the former. The relation facilitates the transition of the
- mind from one object to another, and renders its passage as smooth as if
- it contemplated one continued object. This resemblance is the cause
- of the confusion and mistake, and makes us substitute the notion of
- identity, instead of that of related objects. However at one instant we
- may consider the related succession as variable or interrupted, we are
- sure the next to ascribe to it a perfect identity, and regard it as
- enviable and uninterrupted. Our propensity to this mistake is so great
- from the resemblance above-mentioned, that we fall into it before we are
- aware; and though we incessantly correct ourselves by reflection, and
- return to a more accurate method of thinking, yet we cannot long sustain
- our philosophy, or take off this biass from the imagination. Our last
- resource is to yield to it, and boldly assert that these different
- related objects are in effect the same, however interrupted and
- variable. In order to justify to ourselves this absurdity, we often
- feign some new and unintelligible principle, that connects the objects
- together, and prevents their interruption or variation. Thus we feign
- the continued existence of the perceptions of our senses, to remove
- the interruption: and run into the notion of a soul, and self, and
- substance, to disguise the variation. But we may farther observe, that
- where we do not give rise to such a fiction, our propension to confound
- identity with relation is so great, that we are apt to imagine [Footnote
- 10] something unknown and mysterious, connecting the parts, beside their
- relation; and this I take to be the case with regard to the identity
- we ascribe to plants and vegetables. And even when this does not take
- place, we still feel a propensity to confound these ideas, though we
- a-re not able fully to satisfy ourselves in that particular, nor
- find any thing invariable and uninterrupted to justify our notion of
- identity.
- [Footnote 10 If the reader is desirous to see how a great
- genius may be influencd by these seemingly trivial
- principles of the imagination, as well as the mere vulgar,
- let him read my Lord SHAFTSBURYS reasonings concerning the
- uniting principle of the universe, and the identity of
- plants and animals. See his MORALISTS: or, PHILOSOPHICAL
- RHAPSODY.]
- Thus the controversy concerning identity is not merely a dispute of
- words. For when we attribute identity, in an improper sense, to variable
- or interrupted objects, our mistake is not confined to the expression,
- but is commonly attended with a fiction, either of something invariable
- and uninterrupted, or of something mysterious and inexplicable, or at
- least with a propensity to such fictions. What will suffice to prove
- this hypothesis to the satisfaction of every fair enquirer, is to shew
- from daily experience and observation, that the objects, which are
- variable or interrupted, and yet are supposed to continue the same, are
- such only as consist of a succession of parts, connected together by
- resemblance, contiguity, or causation. For as such a succession answers
- evidently to our notion of diversity, it can only be by mistake we
- ascribe to it an identity; and as the relation of parts, which leads us
- into this mistake, is really nothing but a quality, which produces an
- association of ideas, and an easy transition of the imagination from one
- to another, it can only be from the resemblance, which this act of the
- mind bears to that, by which we contemplate one continued object, that
- the error arises. Our chief business, then, must be to prove, that
- all objects, to which we ascribe identity, without observing their
- invariableness and uninterruptedness, are such as consist of a
- succession of related objects.
- In order to this, suppose any mass of matter, of which the parts are
- contiguous and connected, to be placed before us; it is plain we must
- attribute a perfect identity to this mass, provided all the parts
- continue uninterruptedly and invariably the same, whatever motion or
- change of place we may observe either in the whole or in any of the
- parts. But supposing some very small or inconsiderable part to be added
- to the mass, or subtracted from it; though this absolutely destroys
- the identity of the whole, strictly speaking; yet as we seldom think so
- accurately, we scruple not to pronounce a mass of matter the same, where
- we find so trivial an alteration. The passage of the thought from the
- object before the change to the object after it, is so smooth and easy,
- that we scarce perceive the transition, and are apt to imagine, that it
- is nothing but a continued survey of the same object.
- There is a very remarkable circumstance, that attends this experiment;
- which is, that though the change of any considerable part in a mass
- of matter destroys the identity of the whole, let we must measure the
- greatness of the part, not absolutely, but by its proportion to the
- whole. The addition or diminution of a mountain would not be sufficient
- to produce a diversity in a planet: though the change of a very few
- inches would be able to destroy the identity of some bodies. It will be
- impossible to account for this, but by reflecting that objects operate
- upon the mind, and break or interrupt the continuity of its actions not
- according to their real greatness, but according to their proportion to
- each other: And therefore, since this interruption makes an object cease
- to appear the same, it must be the uninterrupted progress o the thought,
- which constitutes the imperfect identity.
- This may be confirmed by another phenomenon. A change in any
- considerable part of a body destroys its identity; but it is remarkable,
- that where the change is produced gradually and insensibly we are less
- apt to ascribe to it the same effect. The reason can plainly be no
- other, than that the mind, in following the successive changes of the
- body, feels an easy passage from the surveying its condition in one
- moment to the viewing of it in another, and at no particular time
- perceives any interruption in its actions. From which continued
- perception, it ascribes a continued existence and identity to the
- object.
- But whatever precaution we may use in introducing the changes gradually,
- and making them proportionable to the whole, it is certain, that where
- the changes are at last observed to become considerable, we make a
- scruple of ascribing identity to such different objects. There is,
- however, another artifice, by which we may induce the imagination to
- advance a step farther; and that is, by producing a reference of the
- parts to each other, and a combination to some common end or purpose.
- A ship, of which a considerable part has been changed by frequent
- reparations, is still considered as the same; nor does the difference
- of the materials hinder us from ascribing an identity to it. The
- common end, in which the parts conspire, is the same under all their
- variations, and affords an easy transition of the imagination from one
- situation of the body to another.
- But this is still more remarkable, when we add a sympathy of parts
- to their common end, and suppose that they bear to each other, the
- reciprocal relation of cause and effect in all their actions and
- operations. This is the case with all animals and vegetables; where not
- only the several parts have a reference to some general purpose, but
- also a mutual dependence on, and connexion with each other. The effect
- of so strong a relation is, that though every one must allow, that in a
- very few years both vegetables and animals endure a total change, yet we
- still attribute identity to them, while their form, size, and substance
- are entirely altered. An oak, that grows from a small plant to a large
- tree, is still the same oak; though there be not one particle of matter,
- or figure of its parts the same. An infant becomes a man-, and is
- sometimes fat, sometimes lean, without any change in his identity.
- We may also consider the two following phaenomena, which are remarkable
- in their kind. The first is, that though we commonly be able to
- distinguish pretty exactly betwixt numerical and specific identity, yet
- it sometimes happens, that we confound them, and in our thinking and
- reasoning employ the one for the other. Thus a man, who bears a noise,
- that is frequently interrupted and renewed, says, it is still the same
- noise; though it is evident the sounds have only a specific identity or
- resemblance, and there is nothing numerically the same, but the cause,
- which produced them. In like manner it may be said without breach of the
- propriety of language, that such a church, which was formerly of brick,
- fell to ruin, and that the parish rebuilt the same church of free-stone,
- and according to modern architecture. Here neither the form nor
- materials are the same, nor is there any thing common to the two
- objects, but their relation to the inhabitants of the parish; and yet
- this alone is sufficient to make us denominate them the same. But
- we must observe, that in these cases the first object is in a manner
- annihilated before the second comes into existence; by which means, we
- are never presented in any one point of time with the idea of difference
- and multiplicity: and for that reason are less scrupulous in calling
- them the same.
- Secondly, We may remark, that though in a succession of related objects,
- it be in a manner requisite, that the change of parts be not sudden nor
- entire, in order to preserve the identity, yet where the objects are
- in their nature changeable and inconstant, we admit of a more sudden
- transition, than would otherwise be consistent with that relation. Thus
- as the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts;
- though in less than four and twenty hours these be totally altered; this
- hinders not the river from continuing the same during several ages. What
- is natural and essential to any thing is, in a manner, expected; and
- what is expected makes less impression, and appears of less moment, than
- what is unusual and extraordinary. A considerable change of the former
- kind seems really less to the imagination, than the most trivial
- alteration of the latter; and by breaking less the continuity of the
- thought, has less influence in destroying the identity.
- We now proceed to explain the nature of personal identity, which has
- become so great a question ill philosophy, especially of late years in
- England, where all the abstruser sciences are studyed with a peculiar
- ardour and application. And here it is evident, the same method of
- reasoning must be continued which has so successfully explained the
- identity of plants, and animals, and ships, and houses, and of all
- the compounded and changeable productions either of art or nature. The
- identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one,
- and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal
- bodies. It cannot, therefore, have a different origin, but must proceed
- from a like operation of the imagination upon like objects.
- But lest this argument should not convince the reader; though in my
- opinion perfectly decisive; let him weigh the following reasoning, which
- is still closer and more immediate. It is evident, that the identity,
- which we attribute to the human mind, however perfect we may imagine it
- to be, is not able to run the several different perceptions into one,
- and make them lose their characters of distinction and difference, which
- are essential to them. It is still true, that every distinct perception,
- which enters into the composition of the mind, is a distinct existence,
- and is different, and distinguishable, and separable from every other
- perception, either contemporary or successive. But, as, notwithstanding
- this distinction and separability, we suppose the whole train of
- perceptions to be united by identity, a question naturally arises
- concerning this relation of identity; whether it be something that
- really binds our several perceptions together, or only associates
- their ideas in the imagination. That is, in other words, whether in
- pronouncing concerning the identity of a person, we observe some real
- bond among his perceptions, or only feel one among the ideas we form of
- them. This question we might easily decide, if we would recollect what
- has been already proud at large, that the understanding never observes
- any real connexion among objects, and that even the union of cause
- and effect, when strictly examined, resolves itself into a customary
- association of ideas. For from thence it evidently follows, that
- identity is nothing really belonging to these different perceptions, and
- uniting them together; but is merely a quality, which we attribute to
- them, because of the union of their ideas in the imagination, when we
- reflect upon them. Now the only qualities, which can give ideas an union
- in the imagination, are these three relations above-mentioned. There
- are the uniting principles in the ideal world, and without them
- every distinct object is separable by the mind, and may be separately
- considered, and appears not to have any more connexion with any other
- object, than if disjoined by the greatest difference and remoteness.
- It is, therefore, on some of these three relations of resemblance,
- contiguity and causation, that identity depends; and as the very essence
- of these relations consists in their producing an easy transition
- of ideas; it follows, that our notions of personal identity, proceed
- entirely from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along
- a train of connected ideas, according to the principles above-explained.
- The only question, therefore, which remains, is, by what relations this
- uninterrupted progress of our thought is produced, when we consider
- the successive existence of a mind or thinking person. And here it is
- evident we must confine ourselves to resemblance and causation, and must
- drop contiguity, which has little or no influence in the present case.
- To begin with resemblance; suppose we coued see clearly into the
- breast of another, and observe that succession of perceptions, which
- constitutes his mind or thinking principle, and suppose that he always
- preserves the memory of a considerable part of past perceptions; it is
- evident that nothing coued more contribute to the bestowing a relation
- on this succession amidst all its variations. For what is the memory but
- a faculty, by which we raise up the images of past perceptions? And
- as an image necessarily resembles its object, must not. The frequent
- placing of these resembling perceptions in the chain of thought, convey
- the imagination more easily from one link to another, and make the whole
- seem like the continuance of one object? In this particular, then, the
- memory not only discovers the identity, but also contributes to
- its production, by producing the relation of resemblance among the
- perceptions. The case is the same whether we consider ourselves or
- others.
- As to causation; we may observe, that the true idea of the human mind,
- is to consider it as a system of different perceptions or different
- existences, which are linked together by the relation of cause and
- effect, and mutually produce, destroy, influence, and modify each other.
- Our impressions give rise to their correspondent ideas; said these ideas
- in their turn produce other impressions. One thought chaces another,
- and draws after it a third, by which it is expelled in its turn. In this
- respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a
- republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the
- reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other
- persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of
- its parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its
- members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the
- same person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his
- impressions and ideas, without losing his identity. Whatever changes
- he endures, his several parts are still connected by the relation of
- causation. And in this view our identity with regard to the passions
- serves to corroborate that with regard to the imagination, by the making
- our distant perceptions influence each other, and by giving us a present
- concern for our past or future pains or pleasures.
- As a memory alone acquaints us with the continuance and extent of this
- succession of perceptions, it is to be considered, upon that account
- chiefly, as the source of personal identity. Had we no memory, we never
- should have any notion of causation, nor consequently of that chain of
- causes and effects, which constitute our self or person. But having once
- acquired this notion of causation from the memory, we can extend the
- same chain of causes, and consequently the identity of car persons
- beyond our memory, and can comprehend times, and circumstances, and
- actions, which we have entirely forgot, but suppose in general to have
- existed. For how few of our past actions are there, of which we have
- any memory? Who can tell me, for instance, what were his thoughts and
- actions on the 1st of January 1715, the 11th of March 1719, and the 3rd
- of August 1733? Or will he affirm, because he has entirely forgot the
- incidents of these days, that the present self is not the same person
- with the self of that time; and by that means overturn all the most
- established notions of personal identity? In this view, therefore,
- memory does not so much produce as discover personal identity, by
- shewing us the relation of cause and effect among our different
- perceptions. It will be incumbent on those, who affirm that memory
- produces entirely our personal identity, to give a reason why we cm thus
- extend our identity beyond our memory.
- The whole of this doctrine leads us to a conclusion, which is of great
- importance in the present affair, viz. that all the nice and subtile
- questions concerning personal identity can never possibly be decided,
- and are to be regarded rather as gramatical than as philosophical
- difficulties. Identity depends on the relations of ideas; and these
- relations produce identity, by means of that easy transition they
- occasion. But as the relations, and the easiness of the transition may
- diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we
- can decide any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a
- title to the name of identity. All the disputes concerning the identity
- of connected objects are merely verbal, except so fax as the relation of
- parts gives rise to some fiction or imaginary principle of union, as we
- have already observed.
- What I have said concerning the first origin and uncertainty of our
- notion of identity, as applied to the human mind, may be extended with
- little or no variation to that of simplicity. An object, whose different
- co-existent parts are bound together by a close relation, operates upon
- the imagination after much the same manner as one perfectly simple and
- indivisible and requires not a much greater stretch of thought in order
- to its conception. From this similarity of operation we attribute a
- simplicity to it, and feign a principle of union as the support of this
- simplicity, and the center of all the different parts and qualities of
- the object.
- Thus we have finished our examination of the several systems of
- philosophy, both of the intellectual and natural world; and in our
- miscellaneous way of reasoning have been led into several topics;
- which will either illustrate and confirm some preceding part of this
- discourse, or prepare the way for our following opinions. It is now time
- to return to a more close examination of our subject, and to proceed in
- the accurate anatomy of human nature, having fully explained the nature
- of our judgment and understandings.
- SECT. VII. CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK.
- But before I launch out into those immense depths of philosophy, which
- lie before me, I find myself inclined to stop a moment in my present
- station, and to ponder that voyage, which I have undertaken, and which
- undoubtedly requires the utmost art and industry to be brought to a
- happy conclusion. Methinks I am like a man, who having struck on many
- shoals, and having narrowly escaped shipwreck in passing a small frith,
- has yet the temerity to put out to sea in the same leaky weather-beaten
- vessel, and even carries his ambition so far as to think of compassing
- the globe under these disadvantageous circumstances. My memory of past
- errors and perplexities, makes me diffident for the future. The wretched
- condition, weakness, and disorder of the faculties, I must employ in my
- enquiries, encrease my apprehensions. And the impossibility of amending
- or correcting these faculties, reduces me almost to despair, and makes
- me resolve to perish on the barren rock, on which I am at present,
- rather than venture myself upon that boundless ocean, which runs
- out into immensity. This sudden view of my danger strikes me with
- melancholy; and as it is usual for that passion, above all others, to
- indulge itself; I cannot forbear feeding my despair, with all those
- desponding reflections, which the present subject furnishes me with in
- such abundance.
- I am first affrighted and confounded with that forelorn solitude,
- in which I am placed in my philosophy, and fancy myself some strange
- uncouth monster, who not being able to mingle and unite in society,
- has been expelled all human commerce, and left utterly abandoned and
- disconsolate. Fain would I run into the crowd for shelter and warmth;
- but cannot prevail with myself to mix with such deformity. I call upon
- others to join me, in order to make a company apart; but no one will
- hearken to me. Every one keeps at a distance, and dreads that storm,
- which beats upon me from every side. I have exposed myself to the enmity
- of all metaphysicians, logicians, mathematicians, and even theologians;
- and can I wonder at the insults I must suffer? I have declared my
- disapprobation of their systems; and can I be surprized, if they should
- express a hatred of mine and of my person? When I look abroad, I foresee
- on every side, dispute, contradiction, anger, calumny and detraction.
- When I turn my eye inward, I find nothing but doubt and ignorance.
- All the world conspires to oppose and contradict me; though such is my
- weakness, that I feel all my opinions loosen and fall of themselves,
- when unsupported by the approbation of others. Every step I take is
- with hesitation, and every new reflection makes me dread an error and
- absurdity in my reasoning.
- For with what confidence can I venture upon such bold enterprises, when
- beside those numberless infirmities peculiar to myself, I find so many
- which are common to human nature? Can I be sure, that in leaving all
- established opinions I am following truth; and by what criterion shall
- I distinguish her, even if fortune should at last guide me on her
- foot-steps? After the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can
- give no reason why I should assent to it; and feel nothing but a strong
- propensity to consider objects strongly in that view, under which they
- appear to me. Experience is a principle, which instructs me in
- the several conjunctions of objects for the past. Habit is another
- principle, which determines me to expect the same for the future; and
- both of them conspiring to operate upon the imagination, make me form
- certain ideas in a more intense and lively manner, than others, which
- are not attended with the same advantages. Without this quality, by
- which the mind enlivens some ideas beyond others (which seemingly is so
- trivial, and so little founded on reason) we coued never assent to any
- argument, nor carry our view beyond those few objects, which are present
- to our senses. Nay, even to these objects we coued never attribute any
- existence, but what was dependent on the senses; and must comprehend
- them entirely in that succession of perceptions, which constitutes our
- self or person. Nay farther, even with relation to that succession, we
- coued only admit of those perceptions, which are immediately present to
- our consciousness, nor coued those lively images, with which the memory
- presents us, be ever received as true pictures of past perceptions. The
- memory, senses, and understanding are, therefore, all of them founded on
- the imagination, or the vivacity of our ideas.
- No wonder a principle so inconstant and fallacious should lead us into
- errors, when implicitly followed (as it must be) in all its variations.
- It is this principle, which makes us reason from causes and effects; and
- it is the same principle, which convinces us of the continued existence
- of external objects, when absent from the senses. But though these two
- operations be equally natural and necessary in the human mind, yet in
- some circumstances they are [Sect. 4.] directly contrary, nor is it
- possible for us to reason justly and regularly from causes and effects,
- and at the same time believe the continued existence of matter. How
- then shall we adjust those principles together? Which of them shall we
- prefer? Or in case we prefer neither of them, but successively assent
- to both, as is usual among philosophers, with what confidence can we
- afterwards usurp that glorious title, when we thus knowingly embrace a
- manifest contradiction?
- This contradiction [Part III. Sect. 14.] would be more excusable, were
- it compensated by any degree of solidity and satisfaction in the other
- parts of our reasoning. But the case is quite contrary. When we trace up
- the human understanding to its first principles, we find it to lead us
- into such sentiments, as seem to turn into ridicule all our past pains
- and industry, and to discourage us from future enquiries. Nothing is
- more curiously enquired after by the mind of man, than the causes of
- every phenomenon; nor are we content with knowing the immediate causes,
- but push on our enquiries, till we arrive at the original and ultimate
- principle. We would not willingly stop before we are acquainted with
- that energy in the cause, by which it operates on its effect; that tie,
- which connects them together; and that efficacious quality, on which the
- tie depends. This is our aim in all our studies and reflections: And
- how must we be disappointed, when we learn, that this connexion, tie, or
- energy lies merely in ourselves, and is nothing but that determination
- of the mind, which is acquired by custom, and causes us to make
- a transition from an object to its usual attendant, and from the
- impression of one to the lively idea of the other? Such a discovery not
- only cuts off all hope of ever attaining satisfaction, but even prevents
- our very wishes; since it appears, that when we say we desire to know
- the ultimate and operating principle, as something, which resides in
- the external object, we either contradict ourselves, or talk without a
- meaning.
- This deficiency in our ideas is not, indeed, perceived in common life,
- nor are we sensible, that in the most usual conjunctions of cause and
- effect we are as ignorant of the ultimate principle, which binds them
- together, as in the most unusual and extraordinary. But this proceeds
- merely from an illusion of the imagination; and the question is, how far
- we ought to yield to these illusions. This question is very difficult,
- and reduces us to a very dangerous dilemma, whichever way we answer it.
- For if we assent to every trivial suggestion of the fancy; beside that
- these suggestions are often contrary to each other; they lead us into
- such errors, absurdities, and obscurities, that we must at last become
- ashamed of our credulity. Nothing is more dangerous to reason than the
- flights of the imagination, and nothing has been the occasion of more
- mistakes among philosophers. Men of bright fancies may in this respect
- be compared to those angels, whom the scripture represents as covering
- their eyes with their wings. This has already appeared in so many
- instances, that we may spare ourselves the trouble of enlarging upon it
- any farther.
- But on the other hand, if the consideration of these instances makes us
- take a resolution to reject all the trivial suggestions of the fancy,
- and adhere to the understanding, that is, to the general and more
- established properties of the imagination; even this resolution, if
- steadily executed, would be dangerous, and attended with the most
- fatal consequences. For I have already shewn [Sect. 1.], that the
- understanding, when it acts alone, and according to its most general
- principles, entirely subverts itself, and leaves not the lowest degree
- of evidence in any proposition, either in philosophy or common life. We
- save ourselves from this total scepticism only by means of that singular
- and seemingly trivial property of the fancy, by which we enter with
- difficulty into remote views of things, and are not able to accompany
- them with so sensible an impression, as we do those, which are more easy
- and natural. Shall we, then, establish it for a general maxim, that no
- refined or elaborate reasoning is ever to be received? Consider well the
- consequences of such a principle. By this means you cut off entirely
- all science and philosophy: You proceed upon one singular quality of the
- imagination, and by a parity of reason must embrace all of them: And
- you expressly contradict yourself; since this maxim must be built on the
- preceding reasoning, which will be allowed to be sufficiently refined
- and metaphysical. What party, then, shall we choose among these
- difficulties? If we embrace this principle, and condemn all refined
- reasoning, we run into the most manifest absurdities. If we reject it
- in favour of these reasonings, we subvert entirely the human
- understanding. We have, therefore, no choice left but betwixt a false
- reason and none at all. For my part, know not what ought to be done in
- the present case. I can only observe what is commonly done; which is,
- that this difficulty is seldom or never thought of; and even where it
- has once been present to the mind, is quickly forgot, and leaves but a
- small impression behind it. Very refined reflections have little or
- no influence upon us; and yet we do not, and cannot establish it for
- a rule, that they ought not to have any influence; which implies a
- manifest contradiction.
- But what have I here said, that reflections very refined and
- metaphysical have little or no influence upon us? This opinion I can
- scarce forbear retracting, and condemning from my present feeling
- and experience. The intense view of these manifold contradictions and
- imperfections in human reason has so wrought upon me, and heated my
- brain, that I am ready to reject all belief and reasoning, and can look
- upon no opinion even as more probable or likely than another. Where
- am I, or what? From what causes do I derive my existence, and to what
- condition shall I return? Whose favour shall I court, and whose
- anger must I dread? What beings surround me? and on whom have, I any
- influence, or who have any influence on me? I am confounded with all
- these questions, and begin to fancy myself in the most deplorable
- condition imaginable, invironed with the deepest darkness, and utterly
- deprived of the use of every member and faculty.
- Most fortunately it happens, that since reason is incapable of
- dispelling these clouds, nature herself suffices to that purpose,
- and cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium, either by
- relaxing this bent of mind, or by some avocation, and lively impression
- of my senses, which obliterate all these chimeras. I dine, I play a game
- of backgammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends; and when after
- three or four hours' amusement, I would return to these speculations,
- they appear so cold, and strained, and ridiculous, that I cannot find in
- my heart to enter into them any farther.
- Here then I find myself absolutely and necessarily determined to live,
- and talk, and act like other people in the common affairs of life. But
- notwithstanding that my natural propensity, and the course of my animal
- spirits and passions reduce me to this indolent belief in the general
- maxims of the world, I still feel such remains of my former disposition,
- that I am ready to throw all my books and papers into the fire, and
- resolve never more to renounce the pleasures of life for the sake of
- reasoning and philosophy. For those are my sentiments in that splenetic
- humour, which governs me at present. I may, nay I must yield to the
- current of nature, in submitting to my senses and understanding; and in
- this blind submission I shew most perfectly my sceptical disposition and
- principles. But does it follow, that I must strive against the current
- of nature, which leads me to indolence and pleasure; that I must seclude
- myself, in some measure, from the commerce and society of men, which
- is so agreeable; and that I must torture my brains with subtilities and
- sophistries, at the very time that I cannot satisfy myself concerning
- the reasonableness of so painful an application, nor have any tolerable
- prospect of arriving by its means at truth and certainty. Under what
- obligation do I lie of making such an abuse of time? And to what end
- can it serve either for the service of mankind, or for my own private
- interest? No: If I must be a fool, as all those who reason or believe
- any thing certainly are, my follies shall at least be natural and
- agreeable. Where I strive against my inclination, I shall have a good
- reason for my resistance; and will no more be led a wandering into such
- dreary solitudes, and rough passages, as I have hitherto met with.
- These are the sentiments of my spleen and indolence; and indeed I must
- confess, that philosophy has nothing to oppose to them, and expects a
- victory more from the returns of a serious good-humoured disposition,
- than from the force of reason and conviction. In all the incidents of
- life we ought still to preserve our scepticism. If we believe, that fire
- warms, or water refreshes, it is only because it costs us too much pains
- to think otherwise. Nay if we are philosophers, it ought only to be
- upon sceptical principles, and from an inclination, which we feel to the
- employing ourselves after that manner. Where reason is lively, and mixes
- itself with some propensity, it ought to be assented to. Where it does
- not, it never can have any title to operate upon us.
- At the time, therefore, that I am tired with amusement and company,
- and have indulged a reverie in my chamber, or in a solitary walk by a
- river-side, I feel my mind all collected within itself, and am naturally
- inclined to carry my view into all those subjects, about which I have
- met with so many disputes in the course of my reading and conversation.
- I cannot forbear having a curiosity to be acquainted with the principles
- of moral good and evil, the nature and foundation of government, and
- the cause of those several passions and inclinations, which actuate and
- govern me. I am uneasy to think I approve of one object, and disapprove
- of another; call one thing beautiful, and another deformed; decide
- concerning truth and falshood, reason and folly, without knowing upon
- what principles I proceed. I am concerned for the condition of the
- learned world, which lies under such t deplorable ignorance in all these
- particulars. I feel an ambition to arise in me of contributing to the
- instruction of mankind, and of acquiring a name by my inventions
- and discoveries. These sentiments spring up naturally in my present
- disposition; and should I endeavour to banish them, by attaching myself
- to any other business or diversion, I feel I should be a loser in point
- of pleasure; and this is the origin of my philosophy.
- But even suppose this curiosity and ambition should not transport
- me into speculations without the sphere of common life, it would
- necessarily happen, that from my very weakness I must be led into such
- enquiries. It is certain, that superstition is much more bold in its
- systems and hypotheses than philosophy; and while the latter contents
- itself with assigning new causes and principles to the phaenomena, which
- appear in the visible world, the former opens a world of its own, and
- presents us with scenes, and beings, and objects, which are altogether
- new. Since therefore it is almost impossible for the mind of man to
- rest, like those of beasts, in that narrow circle of objects, which
- are the subject of daily conversation and action, we ought only to
- deliberate concerning the choice of our guide, and ought to prefer that
- which is safest and most agreeable. And in this respect I make bold to
- recommend philosophy, and shall not scruple to give it the preference to
- superstition of every kind or denomination. For as superstition arises
- naturally and easily from the popular opinions of mankind, it seizes
- more strongly on the mind, and is often able to disturb us in the
- conduct of our lives and actions. Philosophy on the contrary, if just,
- can present us only with mild and moderate sentiments; and if false and
- extravagant, its opinions are merely the objects of a cold and general
- speculation, and seldom go so far as to interrupt the course of our
- natural propensities. The CYNICS are an extraordinary instance of
- philosophers, who from reasonings purely philosophical ran into as great
- extravagancies of conduct as any Monk or Dervise that ever was in the
- world. Generally speaking, the errors in religion are dangerous; those
- in philosophy only ridiculous.
- I am sensible, that these two cases of the strength and weakness of the
- mind will not comprehend all mankind, and that there are in England, in
- particular, many honest gentlemen, who being always employed in their
- domestic affairs, or amusing themselves in common recreations, have
- carried their thoughts very little beyond those objects, which are every
- day exposed to their senses. And indeed, of such as these I pretend not
- to make philosophers, nor do I expect them either to be associates in
- these researches or auditors of these discoveries. They do well to keep
- themselves in their present situation; and instead of refining them into
- philosophers, I wish we coued communicate to our founders of systems,
- a share of this gross earthy mixture, as an ingredient, which they
- commonly stand much in need of, and which would serve to temper those
- fiery particles, of which they are composed. While a warm imagination
- is allowed to enter into philosophy, and hypotheses embraced merely for
- being specious and agreeable, we can never have any steady principles,
- nor any sentiments, which will suit with common practice and experience.
- But were these hypotheses once removed, we might hope to establish a
- system or set of opinions, which if not true (for that, perhaps, is too
- much to be hoped for) might at least be satisfactory to the human mind,
- and might stand the test of the most critical examination. Nor should we
- despair of attaining this end, because of the many chimerical systems,
- which have successively arisen and decayed away among men, would we
- consider the shortness of that period, wherein these questions have been
- the subjects of enquiry and reasoning. Two thousand years with such long
- interruptions, and under such mighty discouragements are a small space
- of time to give any tolerable perfection to the sciences; and perhaps we
- are still in too early an age of the world to discover any principles,
- which will bear the examination of the latest posterity. For my part,
- my only hope is, that I may contribute a little to the advancement
- of knowledge, by giving in some particulars a different turn to the
- speculations of philosophers, and pointing out to them more distinctly
- those subjects, where alone they can expect assurance and conviction.
- Human Nature is the only science of man; and yet has been hitherto the
- most neglected. It will be sufficient for me, if I can bring it a little
- more into fashion; and the hope of this serves to compose my temper
- from that spleen, and invigorate it from that indolence, which
- sometimes prevail upon me. If the reader finds himself in the same easy
- disposition, let him follow me in my future speculations. If not, let
- him follow his inclination, and wait the returns of application and good
- humour. The conduct of a man, who studies philosophy in this careless
- manner, is more truly sceptical than that of one, who feeling in himself
- an inclination to it, is yet so overwhelmed with doubts and scruples,
- as totally to reject it. A true sceptic will be diffident of his
- philosophical doubts, as well as of his philosophical conviction; and
- will never refuse any innocent satisfaction, which offers itself, upon
- account of either of them.
- Nor is it only proper we should in general indulge our inclination
- in the most elaborate philosophical researches, notwithstanding our
- sceptical principles, but also that we should yield to that propensity,
- which inclines us to be positive and certain in particular points,
- according to the light, in which we survey them in any particular
- instant. It is easier to forbear all examination and enquiry, than
- to check ourselves in so natural a propensity, and guard against that
- assurance, which always arises from an exact and full survey of
- an object. On such an occasion we are apt not only to forget our
- scepticism, but even our modesty too; and make use of such terms as
- these, it is evident, it is certain, it is undeniable; which a due
- deference to the public ought, perhaps, to prevent. I may have fallen
- into this fault after the example of others; but I here enter a caveat
- against any Objections, which may be offered on that head; and declare
- that such expressions were extorted from me by the present view of the
- object, and imply no dogmatical spirit, nor conceited idea of my own
- judgment, which are sentiments that I am sensible can become no body,
- and a sceptic still less than any other.
- BOOK II OF THE PASSIONS
- PART I OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY
- SECT. I DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT
- As all the perceptions of the mind may be divided into impressions and
- ideas, so the impressions admit of another division into original and
- secondary. This division of the impressions is the same with that which
- I formerly made use of [Book I. Part I. Sect. 2.] when I distinguished
- them into impressions of sensation and reflection. Original impressions
- or impressions of sensation are such as without any antecedent
- perception arise in the soul, from the constitution of the body, from
- the animal spirits, or from the application of objects to the external
- organs. Secondary, or reflective impressions are such as proceed from
- some of these original ones, either immediately or by the interposition
- of its idea. Of the first kind are all the impressions of the senses,
- and all bodily pains and pleasures: Of the second are the passions, and
- other emotions resembling them.
- It is certain, that the mind, in its perceptions, must begin somewhere;
- and that since the impressions precede their correspondent ideas, there
- must be some impressions, which without any introduction make their
- appearance in the soul. As these depend upon natural and physical
- causes, the examination of them would lead me too far from my present
- subject, into the sciences of anatomy and natural philosophy. For this
- reason I shall here confine myself to those other impressions, which
- I have called secondary and reflective, as arising either from the
- original impressions, or from their ideas. Bodily pains and pleasures
- are the source of many passions, both when felt and considered by the
- mind; but arise originally in the soul, or in the body, whichever you
- please to call it, without any preceding thought or perception. A fit of
- the gout produces a long train of passions, as grief, hope, fear; but
- is not derived immediately from any affection or idea. The reflective
- impressions may be divided into two kinds, viz. the calm and the
- VIOLENT. Of the first kind is the sense of beauty and deformity in
- action, composition, and external objects. Of the second are the
- passions of love and hatred, grief and joy, pride and humility. This
- division is far from being exact. The raptures of poetry and music
- frequently rise to the greatest height; while those other impressions,
- properly called PASSIONS, may decay into so soft an emotion, as to
- become, in a manner, imperceptible. But as in general the passions are
- more violent than the emotions arising from beauty and deformity,
- these impressions have been commonly distinguished from each other. The
- subject of the human mind being so copious and various, I shall here
- take advantage of this vulgar and spacious division, that I may
- proceed with the greater order; and having said ali I thought necessary
- concerning our ideas, shall now explain those violent emotions or
- passions, their nature, origin, causes, and effects.
- When we take a survey of the passions, there occurs a division of them
- into DIRECT and INDIRECT. By direct passions I understand such as arise
- immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. By indirect such
- as proceed from the same principles, but by the conjunction of other
- qualities. This distinction I cannot at present justify or explain any
- farther. I can only observe in general, that under the indirect passions
- I comprehend pride, humility, ambition, vanity, love, hatred, envy,
- pity, malice, generosity, with their dependants. And under the direct
- passions, desire, aversion, grief, joy, hope, fear, despair and
- security. I shall begin with the former.
- SECT. II OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY, THEIR OBJECTS AND CAUSES
- The passions of PRIDE and HUMILITY being simple and uniform impressions,
- it is impossible we can ever, by a multitude of words, give a just
- definition of them, or indeed of any of the passions. The utmost we
- can pretend to is a description of them, by an enumeration of such
- circumstances, as attend them: But as these words, PRIDE and humility,
- are of general use, and the impressions they represent the most common
- of any, every one, of himself, will be able to form a just idea of them,
- without any danger of mistake. For which reason, not to lose time upon
- preliminaries, I shall immediately enter upon the examination of these
- passions.
- It is evident, that pride and humility, though directly contrary, have
- yet the same OBJECT. This object is self, or that succession of
- related ideas and impressions, of which we have an intimate memory and
- consciousness. Here the view always fixes when we are actuated by either
- of these passions. According as our idea of ourself is more or less
- advantageous, we feel either of those opposite affections, and are
- elated by pride, or dejected with humility. Whatever other objects may
- be comprehended by the mind, they are always considered with a view to
- ourselves; otherwise they would never be able either to excite these
- passions, or produce the smallest encrease or diminution of them. When
- self enters not into the consideration, there is no room either for
- pride or humility.
- But though that connected succession of perceptions, which we call SELF,
- be always the object of these two passions, it is impossible it can
- be their CAUSE, or be sufficient alone to excite them. For as these
- passions are directly contrary, and have the same object in common; were
- their object also their cause; it coued never produce any degree of the
- one passion, but at the same time it must excite an equal degree of
- the other; which opposition and contrariety must destroy both. It is
- impossible a man can at the same time be both proud and humble; and
- where he has different reasons for these passions, as frequently
- happens, the passions either take place alternately; or if they
- encounter, the one annihilates the other, as far as its strength goes,
- and the remainder only of that, which is superior, continues to operate
- upon the mind. But in the present case neither of the passions coued
- ever become superior; because supposing it to be the view only of
- ourself, which excited them, that being perfectly indifferent to either,
- must produce both in the very same proportion; or in other words, can
- produce neither. To excite any passion, and at the same time raise an
- equal share of its antagonist, is immediately to undo what was done, and
- must leave the mind at last perfectly calm and indifferent.
- We must therefore, make a distinction betwixt the cause and the object
- of these passions; betwixt that idea, which excites them, and that to
- which they direct their view, when excited. Pride and humility, being
- once raised, immediately turn our attention to ourself, and regard
- that as their ultimate and final object; but there is something farther
- requisite in order to raise them: Something, which is peculiar to one of
- the passions, and produces not both in the very same degree. The first
- idea, that is presented to the mind, is that of the cause or productive
- principle. This excites the passion, connected with it; and that
- passion, when excited, turns our view to another idea, which is that of
- self. Here then is a passion placed betwixt two ideas, of which the one
- produces it, and the other is produced by it. The first idea, therefore,
- represents the cause, the second the object of the passion.
- To begin with the causes of pride and humility; we may observe, that
- their most obvious and remarkable property is the vast variety of
- subjects, on which they may be placed. Every valuable quality of the
- mind, whether of the imagination, judgment, memory or disposition; wit,
- good-sense, learning, courage, justice, integrity; all these are the
- cause of pride; and their opposites of humility. Nor are these passions
- confined to the mind but extend their view to the body likewise. A man
- may be proud of his beauty, strength, agility, good mein, address
- in dancing, riding, and of his dexterity in any manual business
- or manufacture. But this is not all. The passions looking farther,
- comprehend whatever objects are in the least allyed or related to us.
- Our country, family, children, relations, riches, houses, gardens,
- horses, dogs, cloaths; any of these may become a cause either of pride
- or of humility.
- From the consideration of these causes, it appears necessary we shoud
- make a new distinction in the causes of the passion, betwixt that
- QUALITY, which operates, and the subject, on which it is placed. A man,
- for instance, is vain of a beautiful house, which belongs to him, or
- which he has himself built and contrived. Here the object of the passion
- is himself, and the cause is the beautiful house: Which cause again is
- sub-divided into two parts, viz. the quality, which operates upon the
- passion, and the subject in which the quality inheres. The quality is
- the beauty, and the subject is the house, considered as his property or
- contrivance. Both these parts are essential, nor is the distinction vain
- and chimerical. Beauty, considered merely as such, unless placed upon
- something related to us, never produces any pride or vanity; and the
- strongest relation alone, without beauty, or something else in its
- place, has as little influence on that passion. Since, therefore, these
- two particulars are easily separated and there is a necessity for their
- conjunction, in order to produce the passion, we ought to consider them
- as component parts of the cause; and infix in our minds an exact idea of
- this distinction.
- SECT. III WHENCE THESE OBJECTS AND CAUSES ARE DERIVED
- Being so far advanced as to observe a difference betwixt the object
- of the passions and their cause, and to distinguish in the cause the
- quality, which operates on the passions, from the subject, in which it
- inheres; we now proceed to examine what determines each of them to
- be what it is, and assigns such a particular object, and quality, and
- subject to these affections. By this means we shall fully understand the
- origin of pride and humility.
- It is evident in the first place, that these passions are derermined
- to have self for their object, not only by a natural but also by an
- original property. No one can doubt but this property is natural from
- the constancy and steadiness of its operations. It is always self, which
- is the object of pride and humility; and whenever the passions look
- beyond, it is still with a view to ourselves, nor can any person or
- object otherwise have any influence upon us.
- That this proceeds from an original quality or primary impulse, will
- likewise appear evident, if we consider that it is the distinguishing
- characteristic of these passions Unless nature had given some original
- qualities to the mind, it coued never have any secondary ones; because
- in that case it would have no foundation for action, nor coued ever
- begin to exert itself. Now these qualities, which we must consider as
- original, are such as are most inseparable from the soul, and can be
- resolved into no other: And such is the quality, which determines
- the object of pride and humility. We may, perhaps, make it a greater
- question, whether the causes, that produce the passion, be as natural as
- the object, to which it is directed, and whether all that vast variety
- proceeds from caprice or from the constitution of the mind. This doubt
- we shall soon remove, if we cast our eye upon human nature, and consider
- that in all nations and ages, the same objects still give rise to pride
- and humility; and that upon the view even of a stranger, we can know
- pretty nearly, what will either encrease or diminish his passions of
- this kind. If there be any variation in this particular, it proceeds
- from nothing but a difference in the tempers and complexions of men; and
- is besides very inconsiderable. Can we imagine it possible, that while
- human nature remains the same, men will ever become entirely indifferent
- to their power, riches, beauty or personal merit, and that their pride
- and vanity will not be affected by these advantages?
- But though the causes of pride and humility be plainly natural, we
- shall find upon examination, that they are not original, and that it is
- utterly impossible they should each of them be adapted to these passions
- by a particular provision, and primary constitution of nature, Beside
- their prodigious number, many of them are the effects of art, and arise
- partly from the industry, partly from the caprice, and partly from
- the good fortune of men, Industry produces houses, furniture, cloaths.
- Caprice determines their particular kinds and qualities. And good
- fortune frequently contributes to all this, by discovering the effects
- that result from the different mixtures and combinations of bodies. It
- is absurd, therefore, to imagine, that each of these was foreseen and
- provided for by nature, and that every new production of art, which
- causes pride or humility; instead of adapting itself to the passion by
- partaking of some general quality, that naturally operates on the mind;
- is itself the object of an original principle, which till then lay
- concealed in the soul, and is only by accident at last brought to light.
- Thus the first mechanic, that invented a fine scritoire, produced pride
- in him, who became possest of it, by principles different from those,
- which made him proud of handsome chairs and tables. As this appears
- evidently ridiculous, we must conclude, that each cause of pride and
- humility is not adapted to the passions by a distinct original quality;
- but that there are some one or more circumstances common to all of them,
- on which their efficacy depends.
- Besides, we find in the course of nature, that though the effects be
- many, the principles, from which they arise, are commonly but few and
- simple, and that it is the sign of an unskilful naturalist to have
- recourse to a different quality, in order to explain every different
- operation. How much more must this be true with regard to the human
- mind, which being so confined a subject may justly be thought incapable
- of containing such a monstrous heap of principles, as would be necessary
- to excite the passions of pride and humility, were each distinct cause
- adapted to the passion by a distinct set of principles?
- Here, therefore, moral philosophy is in the same condition as natural,
- with regard to astronomy before the time of COPERNICUS. The antients,
- though sensible of that maxim, THAT NATURE DOES NOTHING IN VAIN,
- contrived such intricate systems of the heavens, as seemed inconsistent
- with true philosophy, and gave place at last to something more simple
- and natural. To invent without scruple a new principle to every
- new phaenomenon, instead of adapting it to the old; to overload our
- hypotheses with a variety of this kind; are certain proofs, that none of
- these principles is the just one, and that we only desire, by a number
- of falsehoods, to cover our ignorance of the truth.
- SECT. IV OF THE RELATIONS OF IMPRESSIONS AND IDEAS
- Thus we have established two truths without any obstacle or difficulty,
- that IT IS FROM NATURAL PRINCIPLES THIS VARIETY OF CAUSES EXCITES PRIDE
- AND HUMILITY, and that IT IS NOT BY A DIFFERENT PRINCIPLE EACH DIFFERENT
- CAUSE IS ADAPTED TO ITS PASSION. We shall now proceed to enquire how
- we may reduce these principles to a lesser number, and find among the
- causes something common, on which their influence depends.
- In order to this we must reflect on certain properties of human nature,
- which though they have a mighty influence on every operation both of
- the understanding and passions, are not commonly much insisted on by
- philosophers. The first of these is the association of ideas, which I
- have so often observed and explained. It is impossible for the mind to
- fix itself steadily upon one idea for any considerable time; nor can
- it by its utmost efforts ever arrive at such a constancy. But however
- changeable our thoughts may be, they are not entirely without rule and
- method in their changes. The rule, by which they proceed, is to pass
- from one object to what is resembling, contiguous to, or produced by it.
- When one idea is present to the imagination, any other, united by these
- relations, naturally follows it, and enters with more facility by means
- of that introduction.
- The second property I shall observe in the human mind is a like
- association of impressions. All resembling impressions are connected
- together, and no sooner one arises than the rest immediately follow.
- Grief and disappointment give rise to anger, anger to envy, envy to
- malice, and malice to grief again, till the whole circle be compleated.
- In like manner our temper, when elevated with joy, naturally throws
- itself into love, generosity, pity, courage, pride, and the other
- resembling affections. It is difficult for the mind, when actuated by
- any passion, to confine itself to that passion alone, without any
- change or variation. Human nature is too inconstant to admit of any such
- regularity. Changeableness is essential to it. And to what can it so
- naturally change as to affections or emotions, which are suitable to the
- temper, and agree with that set of passions, which then prevail? It is
- evident, then, there is an attraction or association among impressions,
- as well as among ideas; though with this remarkable difference, that
- ideas are associated by resemblance, contiguity, and causation; and
- impressions only by resemblance.
- In the THIRD place, it is observable of these two kinds of association,
- that they very much assist and forward each other, and that the
- transition is more easily made where they both concur in the same
- object. Thus a man, who, by any injury from another, is very much
- discomposed and ruffled in his temper, is apt to find a hundred subjects
- of discontent, impatience, fear, and other uneasy passions; especially
- if he can discover these subjects in or near the person, who was
- the cause of his first passion. Those principles, which forward the
- transition of ideas, here concur with those, which operate on the
- passions; and both uniting in one action, bestow on the mind a double
- impulse. The new passion, therefore, must arise with so much greater
- violence, and the transition to it must be rendered so much more easy
- and natural.
- Upon this occasion I may cite the authority of an elegant writer, who
- expresses himself in the following manner.
- "As the fancy delights in every thing that is great, strange, or
- beautiful, and is still more pleased the more it finds of these
- perfections in the same object, so it is capable of receiving a new
- satisfaction by the assistance of another sense. Thus any continued
- sound, as the music of birds, or a fall of waters, awakens every moment
- the mind of the beholder, and makes him more attentive to the several
- beauties of the place, that lie before him. Thus if there arises a
- fragrancy of smells or perfumes, they heighten the pleasure of the
- imagination, and make even the colours and verdure of the landschape
- appear more agreeable; for the ideas of both senses recommend each
- other, and are pleasanter together than when they enter the mind
- separately: As the different colours of a picture, when they are well
- disposed, set off one another, and receive an additional beauty from the
- advantage of the situation." [Addison, SPECTATOR 412, final paragraph.]
- In this phaenomenon we may remark the association both of impressions
- and ideas, as well as the mutual assistance they lend each other.
- SECT. V OF THE INFLUENCE OF THESE RELATIONS ON PRIDE AND HUMILITY
- These principles being established on unquestionable experience, I begin
- to consider how we shall apply them, by revolving over all the causes of
- pride and humility, whether these causes be regarded, as the qualities,
- that operate, or as the subjects, on which the qualities are placed. In
- examining these qualities I immediately find many of them to concur
- in producing the sensation of pain and pleasure, independent of those
- affections, which I here endeavour to explain. Thus the beauty of our
- person, of itself, and by its very appearance, gives pleasure, as well
- as pride; and its deformity, pain as well as humility. A magnificent
- feast delights us, and a sordid one displeases. What I discover to
- be true in some instances, I suppose to be so in all; and take it for
- granted at present, without any farther proof, that every cause of
- pride, by its peculiar qualities, produces a separate pleasure, and of
- humility a separate uneasiness.
- Again, in considering the subjects, to which these qualities adhere, I
- make a new supposition, which also appears probable from many obvious
- instances, viz, that these subjects are either parts of ourselves, or
- something nearly related to us. Thus the good and bad qualities of
- our actions and manners constitute virtue and vice, and determine our
- personal character, than which nothing operates more strongly on these
- passions. In like manner, it is the beauty or deformity of our person,
- houses, equipage, or furniture, by which we are rendered either vain or
- humble. The same qualities, when transfered to subjects, which bear
- us no relation, influence not in the smallest degree either of these
- affections.
- Having thus in a manner supposed two properties of the causes of these
- affections, viz, that the qualities produce a separate pain or pleasure,
- and that the subjects, on which the qualities are placed, are related
- to self; I proceed to examine the passions themselves, in order to find
- something in them, correspondent to the supposed properties of their
- causes. First, I find, that the peculiar object of pride and humility
- is determined by an original and natural instinct, and that it is
- absolutely impossible, from the primary constitution of the mind, that
- these passions should ever look beyond self, or that individual person.
- of whose actions and sentiments each of us is intimately conscious. Here
- at last the view always rests, when we are actuated by either of these
- passions; nor can we, in that situation of mind, ever lose sight of this
- object. For this I pretend not to give any reason; but consider such a
- peculiar direction of the thought as an original quality.
- The SECOND quality, which I discover in these passions, and which I
- likewise consider an an original quality, is their sensations, or the
- peculiar emotions they excite in the soul, and which constitute their
- very being and essence. Thus pride is a pleasant sensation, and humility
- a painful; and upon the removal of the pleasure and pain, there is in
- reality no pride nor humility. Of this our very feeling convinces us;
- and beyond our feeling, it is here in vain to reason or dispute.
- If I compare, therefore, these two established properties of the
- passions, viz, their object, which is self, and their sensation, which
- is either pleasant or painful, to the two supposed properties of the
- causes, viz, their relation to self, and their tendency to produce a
- pain or pleasure, independent of the passion; I immediately find, that
- taking these suppositions to be just, the true system breaks in upon me
- with an irresistible evidence. That cause, which excites the passion, is
- related to the object, which nature has attributed to the passion;
- the sensation, which the cause separately produces, is related to
- the sensation of the passion: From this double relation of ideas and
- impressions, the passion is derived. The one idea is easily converted
- into its correlative; and the one impression into that, which resembles
- and corresponds to it: With how much greater facility must this
- transition be made, where these movements mutually assist each other,
- and the mind receives a double impulse from the relations both of its
- impressions and ideas?
- That we may comprehend this the better, we must suppose, that nature has
- given to the organs of the human mind, a certain disposition fitted to
- produce a peculiar impression or emotion, which we call pride: To this
- emotion she has assigned a certain idea, viz, that of self, which it
- never fails to produce. This contrivance of nature is easily conceived.
- We have many instances of such a situation of affairs. The nerves of the
- nose and palate are so disposed, as in certain circumstances to convey
- such peculiar sensations to the mind: The sensations of lust and hunger
- always produce in us the idea of those peculiar objects, which are
- suitable to each appetite. These two circumstances are united in pride.
- The organs are so disposed as to produce the passion; and the passion,
- after its production, naturally produces a certain idea. All this needs
- no proof. It is evident we never should be possest of that passion, were
- there not a disposition of mind proper for it; and it is as evident,
- that the passion always turns our view to ourselves, and makes us think
- of our own qualities and circumstances.
- This being fully comprehended, it may now be asked, WHETHER NATURE
- PRODUCES THE PASSION IMMEDIATELY, OF HERSELF; OR WHETHER SHE MUST BE
- ASSISTED BY THE CO-OPERATION OF OTHER CAUSES? For it is observable, that
- in this particular her conduct is different in the different passions
- and sensations. The palate must be excited by an external object, in
- order to produce any relish: But hunger arises internally, without the
- concurrence of any external object. But however the case may stand with
- other passions and impressions, it is certain, that pride requires the
- assistance of some foreign object, and that the organs, which produce
- it, exert not themselves like the heart and arteries, by an original
- internal movement. For first, daily experience convinces us, that pride
- requires certain causes to excite it, and languishes when unsupported by
- some excellency in the character, in bodily accomplishments, in cloaths,
- equipage or fortune. SECONDLY, it is evident pride would be perpetual,
- if it arose immediately from nature; since the object is always the
- same, and there is no disposition of body peculiar to pride, as there
- is to thirst and hunger. Thirdly, Humility is in the very same situation
- with pride; and therefore, either must, upon this supposition, be
- perpetual likewise, or must destroy the contrary passion from, the very
- first moment; so that none of them coued ever make its appearance. Upon
- the whole, we may rest satisfyed with the foregoing conclusion, that
- pride must have a cause, as well as an object, and that the one has no
- influence without the other.
- The difficulty, then, is only to discover this cause, and find what
- it is that gives the first motion to pride, and sets those organs in
- action, which are naturally fitted to produce that emotion. Upon
- my consulting experience, in order to resolve this difficulty, I
- immediately find a hundred different causes, that produce pride; and
- upon examining these causes, I suppose, what at first I perceive to be
- probable, that all of them concur in two circumstances; which are, that
- of themselves they produce an impression, allyed to the passion, and
- are placed on a subject, allyed to the object of the passion. When I
- consider after this the nature of relation, and its effects both on the
- passions and ideas, I can no longer doubt, upon these suppositions, that
- it is the very principle, which gives rise to pride, and bestows
- motion on those organs, which being naturally disposed to produce that
- affection, require only a first impulse or beginning to their action.
- Any thing, that gives a pleasant sensation, and is related to self,
- excites the passion of pride, which is also agreeable, and has self for
- its object.
- What I have said of pride is equally true of humility. The sensation of
- humility is uneasy, as that of pride is agreeable; for which reason the
- separate sensation, arising from the causes, must be reversed, while
- the relation to self continues the same. Though pride and humility are
- directly contrary in their effects, and in their sensations, they have
- notwithstanding the same object; so that it is requisite only to change
- the relation of impressions, without making any change upon that
- of ideas. Accordingly we find, that a beautiful house, belonging to
- ourselves, produces pride; and that the same house, still belonging to
- ourselves, produces humility, when by any accident its beauty is
- changed into deformity, and thereby the sensation of pleasure, which
- corresponded to pride, is transformed into pain, which is related to
- humility. The double relation between the ideas and impressions subsists
- in both cases, and produces an easy transition from the one emotion to
- the other.
- In a word, nature has bestowed a kind of attraction on certain
- impressions and ideas, by which one of them, upon its appearance,
- naturally introduces its correlative. If these two attractions or
- associations of impressions and ideas concur on the same object, they
- mutually assist each other, and the transition of the affections and
- of the imagination is made with the greatest ease and facility. When
- an idea produces an impression, related to an impression, which is
- connected with an idea, related to the first idea, these two impressions
- must be in a manner inseparable, nor will the one in any case be
- unattended with the other. It is after this manner, that the particular
- causes of pride and humility are determined. The quality, which operates
- on the passion, produces separately an impression resembling it; the
- subject, to which the quality adheres, is related to self, the object of
- the passion: No wonder the whole cause, consisting of a quality and of a
- subject, does so unavoidably give rise to the pass on.
- To illustrate this hypothesis we may compare it to that, by which I
- have already explained the belief attending the judgments, which we form
- from causation. I have observed, that in all judgments of this kind,
- there is always a present impression and a related idea; and that
- the present impression gives a vivacity to the fancy, and the relation
- conveys this vivacity, by an easy transition, to the related idea.
- Without the present impression, the attention is not fixed, nor the
- spirits excited. Without the relation, this attention rests on its
- first object, and has no farther consequence. There is evidently a great
- analogy betwixt that hypothesis and our present one of an impression
- and idea, that transfuse themselves into another impression and idea by
- means of their double relation: Which analogy must be allowed to be no
- despicable proof of both hypotheses.
- SECT. VI LIMITATIONS OF THIS SYSTEM
- But before we proceed farther in this subject, and examine particularly
- all the causes of pride and humility, it will be proper to make some
- limitations to the general system, THAT ALL AGREEABLE OBJECTS, RELATED
- TO OURSELVES, BY AN ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS AND OF IMPRESSIONS, PRODUCE
- PRIDE, AND DISAGREEABLE ONES, HUMILITY: And these limitations are
- derived from the very nature of the subject.
- I. Suppose an agreeable object to acquire a relation to self, the
- first passion, that appears on this occasion, is joy; and this passion
- discovers itself upon a slighter relation than pride and vain-glory. We
- may feel joy upon being present at a feast, where our senses are regard
- with delicacies of every kind: But it is only the master of the feast,
- who, beside the same joy, has the additional passion of self-applause
- and vanity. It is true, men sometimes boast of a great entertainment,
- at which they have only been present; and by so small a relation convert
- their pleasure into pride: But however, this must in general be owned,
- that joy arises from a more inconsiderable relation than vanity, and
- that many things, which are too foreign to produce pride, are yet able
- to give us a delight and pleasure, The reason of the difference may be
- explained thus. A relation is requisite to joy, in order to approach
- the object to us, and make it give us any satisfaction. But beside this,
- which is common to both passions, it is requisite to pride, in order
- to produce a transition from one passion to another, and convert the
- falsification into vanity. As it has a double task to perform, it must
- be endowed with double force and energy. To which we may add, that where
- agreeable objects bear not a very close relation to ourselves, they
- commonly do to some other person; and this latter relation not only
- excels, but even diminishes, and sometimes destroys the former, as we
- shall see afterwards. [Part II. Sec. 4.]
- Here then is the first limitation, we must make to our general position,
- that every thing related to us, which produces pleasure or pain,
- produces likewise pride or humility. There is not only a relation
- required, but a close one, and a closer than is required to joy.
- II. The second limitation is, that the agreeable or disagreeable object
- be not only closely related, but also peculiar to ourselves, or at least
- common to us with a few persons. It is a quality observable in human
- nature, and which we shall endeavour to explain afterwards, that
- every thing, which is often presented and to which we have been
- long accustomed, loses its value in our eyes, and is in a little
- time despised and neglected. We likewise judge of objects more from
- comparison than from their real and intrinsic merit; and where we cannot
- by some contrast enhance their value, we are apt to overlook even what
- is essentially good in them. These qualities of the mind have an effect
- upon joy as well as pride; and it is remarkable, that goods which are
- common to all mankind, and have become familiar to us by custom, give us
- little satisfaction; though perhaps of a more excellent kind, than those
- on which, for their singularity, we set a much higher value. But though
- this circumstance operates on both these passions, it has a much greater
- influence on vanity. We are rejoiced for many goods, which, on account
- of their frequency, give us no pride. Health, when it returns after a
- long absence, affords us a very sensible satisfaction; but is seldom
- regarded as a subject of vanity, because it is shared with such vast
- numbers.
- The reason, why pride is so much more delicate in this particular than
- joy, I take to be, as follows. In order to excite pride, there are
- always two objects we must contemplate, viz. the cause or that object
- which produces pleasure; and self, which is the real object of the
- passion. But joy has only one object necessary to its production, viz.
- that which gives pleasure; and though it be requisite, that this bear
- some relation to self, yet that is only requisite in order to render it
- agreeable; nor is self, properly speaking, the object of this passion.
- Since, therefore, pride has in a manner two objects, to which it directs
- our view; it follows, that where neither of them have any singularity,
- the passion must be more weakened upon that account, than a passion,
- which has only one object. Upon comparing ourselves with others, as
- we are every moment apt to do, we find we are not in the least
- distinguished; and upon comparing the object we possess, we
- discover still the same unlucky circumstance. By two comparisons so
- disadvantageous the passion must be entirely destroyed.
- III The third limitation is, that the pleasant or painful object be very
- discernible and obvious, and that not only to ourselves, but to others
- also. This circumstance, like the two foregoing, has an effect upon
- joy, as well as pride. We fancy Ourselves more happy, as well as more
- virtuous or beautiful, when we appear so to others; but are still more
- ostentatious of our virtues than of our pleasures. This proceeds from
- causes, which I shall endeavour to explain afterwards.
- IV. The fourth limitation is derived from the inconstancy of the cause
- of these passions, and from the short duration of its connexion with
- ourselves. What is casual and inconstant gives but little joy, and less
- pride. We are not much satisfyed with the thing itself; and are still
- less apt to feel any new degrees of self-satisfaction upon its account.
- We foresee and anticipate its change by the imagination; which makes
- us little satisfyed with the thing: We compare it to ourselves, whose
- existence is more durable; by which means its inconstancy appears still
- greater. It seems ridiculous to infer an excellency in ourselves from an
- object, which is of so much shorter duration, and attends us during so
- small a part of our existence. It will be easy to comprehend the reason,
- why this cause operates not with the same force in joy as in pride;
- since the idea of self is not so essential to the former passion as to
- the latter.
- V. I may add as a fifth limitation, or rather enlargement of this
- system, that general rules have a great influence upon pride and
- humility, as well as on all the other passions. Hence we form a notion
- of different ranks of men, suitable to the power of riches they
- are possest of; and this notion we change not upon account of any
- peculiarities of the health or temper of the persons, which may deprive
- them of all enjoyment in their possessions. This may be accounted for
- from the same principles, that explained the influence of general rules
- on the understanding. Custom readily carries us beyond the just bounds
- in our passions, as well as in our reasonings.
- It may not be amiss to observe on this occasion, that the influence
- of general rules and maxims on the passions very much contributes to
- facilitate the effects of all the principles, which we shall explain
- in the progress of this treatise. For it is evident, that if a
- person full-grown, and of the same nature with ourselves, were on a
- sudden-transported into our world, he would be very much embarrased with
- every object, and would not readily find what degree of love or hatred,
- pride or humility, or any other passion he ought to attribute to it. The
- passions are often varyed by very inconsiderable principles; and these
- do not always play with a perfect regularity, especially on the first
- trial. But as custom and practice have brought to light all these
- principles, and have settled the just value of every thing; this must
- certainly contribute to the easy production of the passions, and guide
- us, by means of general established maxims, in the proportions we
- ought to observe in preferring one object to another. This remark may,
- perhaps, serve to obviate difficulties, that mayarise concerning some
- causes, which I shall hereafter ascribe to particular passions,
- and which may be esteemed too refined to operate so universally and
- certainly, as they are found to do.
- I shall close this subject with a reflection derived from these five
- limitations. This reflection is, that the persons, who are proudest, and
- who in the eye of the world have most reason for their pride, are not
- always the happiest; nor the most humble always the most miserable, as
- may at first sight be imagined from this system. An evil may be real.
- though its cause has no relation to us: It may be real, without being
- peculiar: It may be real, without shewing itself to others: It may be
- real, without being constant: And it may be real, without falling
- under the general rules. Such evils as these will not fail to render
- us miserable, though they have little tendency to diminish pride: And
- perhaps the most real and the most solid evils of life will be found of
- this nature.
- SECT. VII OF VICE AND VIRTUE
- Taking these limitations along with us, let us proceed to examine the
- causes of pride and humility; and see, whether in every case we can
- discover the double relations, by which they operate on the passions.
- If we find that all these causes are related to self, and produce a
- pleasure or uneasiness separate from the passion, there will remain no
- farther scruple with regard to the present system. We shall principally
- endeavour to prove the latter point; the former being in a manner
- self-evident.
- To begin, with vice and virtue; which are the most obvious causes of
- these passions; it would be entirely foreign to my present purpose to
- enter upon the controversy, which of late years has so much excited the
- curiosity of the publick. WHETHER THESE MORAL DISTINCTIONS BE FOUNDED ON
- NATURAL AND ORIGINAL PRINCIPLES, OR ARISE FROM INTEREST AND EDUCATION.
- The examination of this I reserve for the following book; and in the
- mean time I shall endeavour to show, that my system maintains its ground
- upon either of these hypotheses; which will be a strong proof of its
- solidity.
- For granting that morality had no foundation in nature, it must still
- be allowed, that vice and virtue, either from self-interest or the
- prejudices of education, produce in us a real pain and pleasure; and
- this we may observe to be strenuously asserted by the defenders of that
- hypothesis. Every passion, habit, or turn of character (say they)
- which has a tendency to our advantage or prejudice, gives a delight
- or uneasiness; and it is from thence the approbation or disapprobation
- arises. We easily gain from the liberality of others, but are always
- in danger of losing by their avarice: Courage defends us, but cowardice
- lays us open to every attack: Justice is the support of society, but
- injustice, unless checked would quickly prove its ruin: Humility exalts;
- but pride mortifies us. For these reasons the former qualities are
- esteemed virtues, and the latter regarded as vices. Now since it is
- granted there is a delight or uneasiness still attending merit or
- demerit of every kind, this is all that is requisite for my purpose.
- But I go farther, and observe, that this moral hypothesis and my present
- system not only agree together, but also that, allowing the former to be
- just, it is an absolute and invincible proof of the latter. For if
- all morality be founded on the pain or pleasure, which arises from
- the prospect of any loss or advantage, that may result from our own
- characters, or from those of others, all the effects of morality must-be
- derived from the same pain or pleasure, and among the rest, the passions
- of pride and humility. The very essence of virtue, according to this
- hypothesis, is to produce pleasure and that of vice to give pain. The
- virtue and vice must be part of our character in order to excite pride
- or humility. What farther proof can we desire for the double relation of
- impressions and ideas?
- The same unquestionable argument may be derived from the opinion of
- those, who maintain that morality is something real, essential, and
- founded on nature. The most probable hypothesis, which has been advanced
- to explain the distinction betwixt vice and virtue, and the origin of
- moral rights and obligations, is, that from a primary constitution
- of nature certain characters and passions, by the very view and
- contemplation, produce a pain, and others in like manner excite a
- pleasure. The uneasiness and satisfaction are not only inseparable
- from vice and virtue, but constitute their very nature and essence.
- To approve of a character is to feel an original delight upon its
- appearance. To disapprove of it is to be sensible of an uneasiness.
- The pain and pleasure, therefore, being the primary causes of vice and
- virtue, must also be the causes of all their effects, and consequently
- of pride and humility, which are the unavoidable attendants of that
- distinction.
- But supposing this hypothesis of moral philosophy should be allowed to
- be false, it is still evident, that pain and pleasure, if not the causes
- of vice and virtue, are at least inseparable from them. A generous and
- noble character affords a satisfaction even in the survey; and when
- presented to us, though only in a poem or fable, never fails to charm
- and delight us. On the other hand cruelty and treachery displease from
- their very nature; nor is it possible ever to reconcile us to these
- qualities, either in ourselves or others. Thus one hypothesis of
- morality is an undeniable proof of the foregoing system, and the other
- at worst agrees with it. But pride and humility arise not from these
- qualities alone of the mind, which, according to the vulgar systems of
- ethicks, have been comprehended as parts of moral duty, but from
- any other that has a connexion with pleasure and uneasiness. Nothing
- flatters our vanity more than the talent of pleasing by our wit,
- good humour, or any other accomplishment; and nothing gives us a more
- sensible mortification than a disappointment in any attempt of that
- nature. No one has ever been able to tell what wit is, and to-shew why
- such a system of thought must be received under that denomination, and
- such another rejected. It is only by taste we can decide concerning
- it, nor are we possest of any other standard, upon which we can form a
- judgment of this kind. Now what is this taste, from which true and false
- wit in a manner receive their being, and without which no thought can
- have a title to either of these denominations? It is plainly nothing
- but a sensation of pleasure from true wit, and of uneasiness from
- false, without oar being able to tell the reasons of that pleasure
- or uneasiness. The power of bestowing these opposite sensations is.
- therefore, the very essence of true and false wit; and consequently the
- cause of that pride or humility, which arises from them.
- There may, perhaps, be some, who being accustomed to the style of the
- schools and pulpit, and having never considered human nature in any
- other light, than that in which they place it, may here be surprized
- to hear me talk of virtue as exciting pride, which they look upon as a
- vice; and of vice as producing humility, which they have been taught to
- consider as a virtue. But not to dispute about words, I observe, that by
- pride I understand that agreeable impression, which arises in the mind,
- when the view either of our virtue, beauty, riches or power makes us
- satisfyed with ourselves: and that by humility I mean the opposite
- impression. It is evident the former impression is not always vicious,
- nor the latter virtuous. The most rigid morality allows us to receive
- a pleasure from reflecting on a generous action; and it is by none
- esteemed a virtue to feel any fruitless remorses upon the thoughts
- of past villainy and baseness. Let us, therefore, examine these
- impressions, considered in themselves; and enquire into their causes,
- whether placed on the mind or body, without troubling ourselves at
- present with that merit or blame, which may attend them.
- SECT. VIII OF BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY
- Whether we consider the body as a part of ourselves, or assent to those
- philosophers, who regard it as something external, it must still be
- allowed to be near enough connected with us to form one of these double
- relations, which I have asserted to be necessary to the causes of pride
- and humility. Wherever, therefore, we can find the other relation of
- impressions to join to this of ideas, we may expect with assurance
- either of these passions, according as the impression is pleasant
- or uneasy. But beauty of all kinds gives us a peculiar delight and
- satisfaction; as deformity produces pain, upon whatever subject it may
- be placed, and whether surveyed in an animate or inanimate object. If
- the beauty or deformity, therefore, be placed upon our own bodies, this
- pleasure or uneasiness must be converted into pride or humility, as
- having in this case all the circumstances requisite to produce a perfect
- transition of impressions and ideas. These opposite sensations are
- related to the opposite passions. The beauty or deformity is closely
- related to self, the object of both these passions. No wonder, then our
- own beauty becomes an object of pride, and deformity of humility.
- But this effect of personal and bodily qualities is not only a proof of.
- the present system, by shewing that the passions arise not in this case
- without all the circumstances I have required, but may be employed as
- a stronger and more convincing argument. If we consider all the
- hypotheses, which have been formed either by philosophy or common
- reason, to explain the difference betwixt beauty and deformity, we shall
- find that all of them resolve into this, that beauty is such an order
- and construction of parts, as either by the primary constitution of
- our nature, by custom, or by caprice, is fitted to give a pleasure
- and satisfaction to the soul. This is the distinguishing character of
- beauty, and forms all the difference betwixt it and deformity, whose
- natural tendency is to produce uneasiness. Pleasure and pain, therefore,
- are not only necessary attendants of beauty and deformity, but
- constitute their very essence. And indeed, if we consider, that a
- great part of the beauty, which we admire either in animals or in other
- objects, is derived from the idea of convenience and utility, we shall
- make no scruple to assent to this opinion. That shape, which produces
- strength, is beautiful in one animal; and that which is a sign of
- agility in another. The order and convenience of a palace are no less
- essential to its beauty, than its mere figure and appearance. In like
- manner the rules of architecture require, that the top of a pillar
- should be more slender than its base, and that because such a figure
- conveys to us the idea of security, which is pleasant; whereas the
- contrary form gives us the apprehension of danger, which is uneasy. From
- innumerable instances of this kind, as well as from considering that
- beauty like wit, cannot be defined, but is discerned only by a taste
- or sensation, we may conclude, that beauty is nothing but a form, which
- produces pleasure, as deformity is a structure of parts, which conveys
- pain; and since the power of producing pain and pleasure make in this
- manner the essence of beauty and deformity, all the effects of these
- qualities must be derived from the sensation; and among the rest
- pride and humility, which of all their effects are the most common and
- remarkable.
- This argument I esteem just and decisive; but in order to give greater
- authority to the present reasoning, let us suppose it false for a
- moment, and see what will follow. It is certain, then, that if the
- power of producing pleasure and pain forms not the essence of beauty and
- deformity, the sensations are at least inseparable from the qualities,
- and it is even difficult to consider them apart. Now there is nothing
- common to natural and moral beauty, (both of which are the causes of
- pride) but this power of producing pleasure; and as a common effect
- supposes always a common cause, it is plain the pleasure must in both
- cases be the real and influencing cause of the passion. Again; there is
- nothing originally different betwixt the beauty of our bodies and the
- beauty of external and foreign objects, but that the one has a near
- relation to ourselves, which is wanting in the other. This original
- difference, therefore, must be the cause of all their other differences,
- and among the rest, of their different influence upon the passion of
- pride, which is excited by the beauty of our person, but is not affected
- in the lcast by that of foreign and external objects. Placing, then,
- these two conclusions together, we find they compose the preceding
- system betwixt them, viz, that pleasure, as a related or resembling
- impression, when placed on a related object by a natural transition,
- produces pride; and its contrary, humility. This system, then, seems
- already sufficiently confirmed by experience; that we have not yet
- exhausted all our arguments.
- It is not the beauty of the body alone that produces pride, but also
- its strength and force. Strength is a kind of power; and therefore the
- desire to excel in strength is to be considered as an inferior
- species of ambition. For this reason the present phaenomenon will be
- sufficiently accounted for, in explaining that passion.
- Concerning all other bodily accomplishments we may observe in general,
- that whatever in ourselves is either useful, beautiful, or surprising,
- is an object of pride; and it's contrary, of humility. Now it is
- obvious, that every thing useful, beautiful or surprising, agrees in
- producing a separate pleasure and agrees in nothing else. The pleasure,
- therefore, with the relation to self must be the cause of the passion.
- Though it should be questioned, whether beauty be not something real,
- and different from the power of producing pleasure, it can never be
- disputed, that as surprize is nothing but a pleasure arising from
- novelty, it is not, properly speaking, a quality in any object, but
- merely a passion or impression in the soul. It must, therefore, be
- from that impression, that pride by a natural transition arises. And
- it arises so naturally, that there is nothing in us or belonging to
- us, which produces surprize, that does not at the same time excite that
- other passion. Thus we are vain of the surprising adventures we have
- met with, the escapes we have made, and dangers we have been exposed to.
- Hence the origin of vulgar lying; where men without any interest, and
- merely out of vanity, heap up a number of extraordinary events, which
- are either the fictions of their brain, or if true, have at least no
- connexion with themselves. Their fruitful invention supplies them with
- a variety of adventures; and where that talent is wanting, they
- appropriate such as belong to others, in order to satisfy their vanity.
- In this phaenomenon are contained two curious experiments, which if we
- compare them together, according to the known rules, by which we judge
- of cause and effect in anatomy, natural philosophy, and other sciences,
- will be an undeniable argument for that influence of the double
- relations above-mentioned. By one of these experiments we find, that an
- object produces pride merely by the interposition of pleasure; and that
- because the quality, by which it produces pride, is in reality nothing
- but the power of producing pleasure. By the other experiment we find,
- that the pleasure produces the pride by a transition along related
- ideas; because when we cut off that relation the passion is immediately
- destroyed.. A surprising adventure, in which we have been ourselves
- engaged, is related to us, and by that means produces pride: But the
- adventures of others, though they may cause pleasure, yet for want of
- this relation of ideas, never excite that passion. What farther proof
- can be desired for the present system?
- There is only one objection to this system with regard to our body:
- which is, that though nothing be more agreeable than health, and more
- painful than sickness, yet commonly men are neither proud of the one,
- nor mortifyed with the other. This will easily be accounted for, if
- we consider the second and fourth limitations, proposed to our general
- system. It was observed, that no object ever produces pride or humility,
- if it has not something peculiar to ourself; as also, that every
- cause of that passion must be in some measure constant, and hold some
- proportion to the duration of our self, which, is its object. Now as
- health and sickness vary incessantly to all men, and there is none, who
- is solely or certainly fixed in either, these accidental blessings and
- calamities are in a manner separated from us, and are never considered
- as connected with our being and existence. And that this account is just
- appears hence, that wherever a malady of any kind is so rooted in our
- constitution, that we no longer entertain any hopes of recovery, from
- that moment it becomes an object of humility; as is evident in old men,
- whom nothing mortifies more than the consideration of their age and
- infirmities. They endeavour, as long as possible, to conceal their
- blindness and deafness, their rheums and gouts; nor do they ever confess
- them without reluctance and uneasiness. And though young men are not
- ashamed of every head-ach or cold they fall into, yet no topic is so
- proper to mortify human pride, and make us entertain a mean opinion of
- our nature, than this, that we are every moment of our lives subject to
- such infirmities. This sufficiently proves that bodily pain and sickness
- are in themselves proper causes of humility; though the custom of
- estimating every thing by comparison more than by its intrinsic worth
- and value, makes us overlook these calamities, which we find to be
- incident to every one, and causes us to form an idea of our merit and
- character independent of them.
- We are ashamed of such maladies as affect others, and are either
- dangerous or disagreeable to them. Of the epilepsy; because it gives a
- horror to every one present: Of the itch; because it is infectious:
- Of the king's-evil; because it commonly goes to posterity. Men always
- consider the sentiments of others in their judgment of themselves. This
- has evidently appeared in some of the foregoing reasonings; and will
- appear still more evidently, and be more fully explained afterwards.
- SECT. IX OF EXTERNAL ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES
- But though pride and humility have the qualities of our mind and body
- that is self, for their natural and more immediate causes, we find
- by experience, that there are many other objects, which produce these
- affections, and that the primary one is, in some measure, obscured and
- lost by the multiplicity of foreign and extrinsic. We found a vanity
- upon houses, gardens, equipages, as well as upon personal merit and
- accomplishments; and though these external advantages be in themselves
- widely distant from thought or a person, yet they considerably influence
- even a passion, which is directed to that as its ultimate object,
- This, happens when external objects acquire any particular relation to
- ourselves, and are associated or connected with us. A beautiful fish
- in the ocean, an animal in a desart, and indeed any thing that neither
- belongs, nor is related to us, has no manner of influence on our vanity,
- whatever extraordinary qualities it may be endowed with, and whatever
- degree of surprize and admiration it may naturally occasion. It must be
- some way associated with us in order to touch our pride. Its idea must
- hang in a manner, upon that of ourselves and the transition from the one
- to the other must be easy and natural.
- But here it is remarkable, that though the relation of resemblance
- operates upon the mind in the same manner as contiguity and causation,
- in conveying us from one idea to another, yet it is seldom a foundation
- either of pride or of humility. If we resemble a person in any of the
- valuable parts of his character, we must, in some degree, possess the
- quality, in which we resemble him; and this quality we always chuse to
- survey directly in ourselves rather than by reflexion in another person,
- when we would found upon it any degree of vanity. So that though a
- likeness may occasionally produce that passion by suggesting a more
- advantageous idea of ourselves, it is there the view fixes at last, and
- the passion finds its ultimate and final cause.
- There are instances, indeed, wherein men shew a vanity in resembling a
- great man in his countenance, shape, air, or other minute circumstances,
- that contribute not in any degree to his reputation; but it must be
- confessed that this extends not very far, nor is of any considerable
- moment in these affections. For this I assign the following reason. We
- can never have a vanity of resembling in trifles any person, unless
- he be possessed of very shining qualities, which give us a respect and
- veneration for him. These qualities, then, are, properly speaking, the
- causes of our vanity, by means of their relation to ourselves. Now after
- what manner are they related to ourselves? They are parts of the person
- we value, and consequently connected with these trifles; which are
- also supposed to be parts of him. These trifles are connected with the
- resembling qualities in us; and these qualities in us, being parts,
- are connected with the whole; and by that means form a chain of several
- links of the person we resemble. But besides that this multitude of
- relations must weaken the connexion; it is evident the mind, in passing
- from the shining qualities to the trivial ones, must by that contrast
- the better perceive the minuteness of the latter, and be in some measure
- ashamed of the comparison and resemblance.
- The relation, therefore, of contiguity, or that of causation, betwixt
- the cause and object of pride and humility, is alone requisite to
- give rise to these passions; and these relations are nothing else
- but qualities, by which the imagination is conveyed from one idea to
- another. Now let us consider what effect these can possibly have upon
- the mind, and by what means they become so requisite to the production
- of the passions. It is evident, that the association of ideas operates
- in so silent and imperceptible a manner, that we are scarce sensible of
- it, and discover it more by its effects than by any immediate feeling or
- perception. It produces no emotion, and gives rise to no new impression
- of any kind, but only modifies those ideas, of which the mind was
- formerly possessed, and which it coued recal upon occasion. From this
- reasoning, as well as from undoubted experience, we may conclude, that
- an association of ideas, however necessary, is not alone sufficient to
- give rise to any passion.
- It is evident, then, that when the mind feels the passion either of
- pride or humility upon the appearance of related object, there is,
- beside the relation or transition of thought, an emotion or original
- impression produced by some other principle. The question is, whether
- the emotion first produced be the passion itself, or some other
- impression related to it. This question we cannot be long in deciding,
- For besides all the other arguments, with which this subject abounds,
- it must evidently appear, that the relation of ideas, which experience
- shews to be so requisite a circumstance to the production of the
- passion, would be entirely superfluous, were it not to second a relation
- of affections, and facilitate the transition from one impression
- to another. If nature produced immediately the passion of pride or
- humility, it would be compleated in itself, and would require no farther
- addition or encrease from any other affection. But supposing the first
- emotion to be only related to pride or humility, it is easily conceived
- to what purpose the relation of objects may serve, and how the two
- different associations, of impressions and ideas, by uniting their
- forces, may assist each other's operation. This is not only easily
- conceived, but I will venture to affirm it is the only manner, in which
- we can conceive this subject. An easy transition of ideas, which, of
- itself, causes no emotion, can never be necessary, or even useful to
- the passions, but by forwarding the transition betwixt some related
- impressions. Not to mention, that the same object causes a greater
- or smaller degree of pride, not only in proportion to the encrease or
- decrease of its qualities, but also to the distance or nearness of the
- relation; which is a clear argument for the transition of affections
- along the relation of ideas; since every change in the relation produces
- a proportionable change in the passion. Thus one part of the preceding
- system, concerning the relations of ideas is a sufficient proof of
- the other, concerning that of impressions; and is itself so evidently
- founded on experience, that it would be lost time to endeavour farther
- to prove it.
- This will appear still more evidently in particular instances. Men are
- vain of the beauty of their country, of their county, of their parish.
- Here the idea of beauty plainly produces a pleasure. This pleasure
- is related to pride. The object or cause of this pleasure is, by the
- supposition, related to self, or the object of pride. By this double
- relation of impressions and ideas, a transition is made from the one
- impression to the other.
- Men are also vain of the temperature of the climate, in which they were
- born; of the fertility of their native soil; of the goodness of the
- wines, fruits or victuals, produced by it; of the softness or force of
- their language; with other particulars of that kind. These objects have
- plainly a reference to the pleasures of the senses, and are originally
- considered as agreeable to the feeling, taste or hearing. How is it
- possible they coued ever become objects of pride, except by means of
- that transition above-explained?
- There are some, that discover a vanity of an opposite kind, and affect
- to depreciate their own country, in comparison of those, to which
- they have travelled. These persons find, when they are at home, and
- surrounded with their countrymen, that the strong relation betwixt them
- and their own nation is shared with so many, that it is in a manner lost
- to them; whereas their distant relation to a foreign country, which is
- formed by their having seen it and lived in it, is augmented by their
- considering how few there are who have done the same. For this reason
- they always admire the beauty, utility and rarity of what is abroad,
- above what is at home.
- Since we can be vain of a country, climate or any inanimate object,
- which bears a relation to us, it is no wonder we are vain of the
- qualities of those, who are connected with us by blood or friendship.
- Accordingly we find, that the very same qualities, which in ourselves
- produce pride, produce also in a lesser degree the same affection, when
- discovered in persons related to us. The beauty, address, merit, credit
- and honours of their kindred are carefully displayed by the proud, as
- some of their most considerable sources of their vanity.
- As we are proud of riches in ourselves, so to satisfy our vanity we
- desire that every one, who has any connexion with us, should likewise be
- possest of them, and are ashamed of any one, that is mean or poor, among
- our friends and relations. For this reason we remove the poor as far
- from us as possible; and as we cannot prevent poverty in some distant
- collaterals, and our forefathers are taken to be our nearest relations;
- upon this account every one affects to be of a good family, and to be
- descended from a long succession of rich and honourable ancestors.
- I have frequently observed, that those, who boast of the antiquity of
- their families, are glad when they can join this circumstance, that
- their ancestors for many generations have been uninterrupted proprietors
- of the same portion of land, and that their family has never changed its
- possessions, or been transplanted into any other county or province.
- I have also observed, that it is an additional subject of vanity, when
- they can boast, that these possessions have been transmitted through
- a descent composed entirely of males, and that the honour, and fortune
- have never past through any female. Let us endeavour to explain these
- phaenomena by the foregoing system.
- It is evident, that when any one boasts of the antiquity of his family,
- the subjects of his vanity are not merely the extent of time and number
- of ancestors, but also their riches and credit, which are supposed to
- reflect a lustre on himself on account of his relation to them. He first
- considers these objects; is affected by them in an agreeable manner;
- and then returning back to himself, through the relation of parent and
- child, is elevated with the passion of pride, by means of the double
- relation, of impressions and ideas. Since therefore the passion depends
- on these relations, whatever strengthens any of the relations must also
- encrease the passion, and whatever weakens the relations must diminish
- the passion. Now it is certain the identity of the possesion strengthens
- the relation of ideas arising from blood and kindred, and conveys the
- fancy with greater facility from one generation to another, from the
- remote ancestors to their posterity, who are both their heirs and their
- descendants. By this facility the impression is transmitted more entire,
- and excites a greater degree of pride and vanity.
- The case is the same with the transmission of the honours and fortune
- through a succession of males without their passing through any female.
- It is a quality of human nature, which we shall consider [Part II. Sect,
- 2.] afterwards, that the imagination naturally turns to whatever is
- important and considerable; and where two objects are presented to it,
- a small and a great one, usually leaves the former, and dwells entirely
- upon the latter. As in the society of marriage, the male sex has the
- advantage above the female, the husband first engages our attention;
- and whether we consider him directly, or reach him by passing
- through related objects, the thought both rests upon him with greater
- satisfaction, and arrives at him with greater facility than his consort.
- It is easy to see, that this property must strengthen the child's
- relation to the father, and weaken that to the mother. For as all
- relations are nothing hut a propensity to pass from one idea ma another,
- whatever strengthens the propensity strengthens the relation; and as we
- have a stronger propensity to pass from the idea of the children to that
- of the father, than from the same idea to that of the mother, we ought
- to regard the former relation as the closer and more considerable. This
- is the reason why children commonly bear their father's name, and are
- esteemed to be of nobler or baser birth, according to his family. And
- though the mother should be possest of a superior spirit and genius to
- the father, as often happens, the general rule prevails, notwithstanding
- the exceprion, according to the doctrine above-explained. Nay even when
- a superiority of any kind is so great, or when any other reasons have
- such an effect, as to make the children rather represent: the mother's
- family than the father's, the general rule still retains such an
- efficacy that it weakens the relation, and makes a kind of break in the
- line of ancestors. The imagination runs not along them with facility,
- nor is able to transfer the honour and credit of the ancestors to their
- posterity of the same name and family so readily, as when the transition
- is conformable to the general rules, and passes from father to son, or
- from brother to brother.
- SECT. X OF PROPERTY AND RICHES
- But the relation, which is esteemed the closest, and which of all others
- produces most commonly the passion of pride, is that of property. This
- relation it will be impossible for me fully to explain before I come
- to treat of justice and the other moral virtues. It is sufficient to
- observe on this occasion, that property may be defined, such a relation
- betwixt a person and an object as permits him, but forbids any other,
- the free use and possession of it, without violating the laws of justice
- and moral equity. If justice, therefore, be a virtue, which has a
- natural and original influence on the human mind, property may be looked
- upon as a particular species of causation; whether we consider the
- liberty it gives the proprietor to operate as he please upon the object
- or the advantages, which he reaps from it. It is the same case, if
- justice, according to the system of certain philosophers, should be
- esteemed an artificial and not a natural virtue. For then honour, and
- custom, and civil laws supply the place of natural conscience, and
- produce, in some degree, the same effects. This in the mean time is
- certain, that the mention of the property naturally carries our thought
- to the proprietor, and of the proprietor to the property; which being
- a proof of a perfect relation of ideas is all that is requisite to our
- present purpose. A relation of ideas, joined to that of impressions,
- always produces a transition of affections; and therefore, whenever any
- pleasure or pain arises from an object, connected with us by property.
- we may be certain, that either pride or humility must arise from
- this conjunction of relations; if the foregoing system be solid and
- satisfactory. And whether it be so or not, we may soon satisfy ourselves
- by the most cursory view of human life.
- Every thing belonging to a vain man is the best that is any where to be
- found. His houses, equipage, furniture, doaths, horses, hounds, excel
- all others in his conceit; and it is easy to observe, that from the
- least advantage in any of these, he draws a new subject of pride and
- vanity. His wine, if you'll believe him, has a finer flavour than
- any other; his cookery is more exquisite; his table more orderly; his
- servants more expert; the air, in which he lives, more healthful; the
- soil he cultivates more fertile; his fruits ripen earlier and to greater
- perfection: Such a thing is remarkable for its novelty; such another for
- its antiquity: This is the workmanship of a famous artist; that belonged
- once to such a prince or great man: All objects, in a word, that are
- useful, beautiful or surprising, or are related to such, may, by means
- of property, give rise to this passion. These agree in giving pleasure,
- and agree in nothing else. This alone is common to them; and therefore
- must be the quality that produces the passion, which is their common
- effect. As every new instance is a new argument, and as the instances
- are here without number, I may venture to affirm, that scarce any
- system was ever so fully proved by experience, as that which I have here
- advanced.
- If the property of any thing, that gives pleasure either by its
- utility, beauty or novelty, produces also pride by a double relation
- of impressions and ideas; we need not be surprized, that the power of
- acquiring this property, should have the same effect. Now riches are to
- be considered as the power of acquiring the property of what pleases;
- and it is only in this view they have any influence on the passions.
- Paper will, on many occasions, be considered as riches, and that because
- it may convey the power of acquiring money: And money is not riches,
- as it is a metal endowed with certain qualities of solidity, weight
- and fusibility; but only as it has a relation to the pleasures and
- conveniences of life. Taking then this for granted, which is in itself
- so evident, we may draw from it one of the strongest arguments I have
- yet employed to prove the influence of the double relations on pride and
- humility.
- It has been observed in treating of the understanding, that the
- distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt a power and the exercise
- of it, is entirely frivolous, and that neither man nor any other being
- ought ever to be thought possest of any ability, unless it be exerted
- and put in action. But though this be strictly true in a just and
- philosophical way of thinking, it is certain it is not the philosophy
- of our passions; but that many things operate upon them by means of the
- idea and supposition of power, independent of its actual exercise. We
- are pleased when we acquire an ability of procuring pleasure, and are
- displeased when another acquires a power of giving pain. This is evident
- from experience; but in order to give a just explication of the matter,
- and account for this satisfaction and uneasiness, we must weigh the
- following reflections.
- It is evident the error of distinguishing power from its exercise
- proceeds not entirely from the scholastic doctrine of free-will, which,
- indeed, enters very little into common life, and has but small influence
- on our vulgar and popular ways of thinking. According to that doctrine,
- motives deprive us not of free-will, nor take away our power of
- performing or forbearing any action. But according to common notions a
- man has no power, where very considerable motives lie betwixt him and
- the satisfaction of his desires, and determine him to forbear what he
- wishes to perform. I do not think I have fallen into my enemy's power,
- when I see him pass me in the streets with a sword by his side, while
- I am unprovided of any weapon. I know that the fear of the civil
- magistrate is as strong a restraint as any of iron, and that I am in as
- perfect safety as if he were chained or imprisoned. But when a person
- acquires such an authority over me, that not only there is no external
- obstacle to his actions; but also that he may punish or reward me as he
- pleases, without any dread of punishment in his turn, I then attribute a
- full power to him, and consider myself as his subject or vassal.
- Now if we compare these two cases, that of a person, who has very
- strong motives of interest or safety to forbear any action, and that of
- another, who lies under no such obligation, we shall find, according
- to the philosophy explained in the foregoing book, that the only
- known difference betwixt them lies in this, that in the former case we
- conclude from past experience, that the person never will perform that
- action, and in the latter, that he possibly or probably will perform it.
- Nothing is more fluctuating and inconstant on many occasions, than the
- will of man; nor is there any thing but strong motives, which can give
- us an absolute certainty in pronouncing concerning any of his future
- actions. When we see a person free from these motives, we suppose a
- possibility either of his acting or forbearing; and though in general
- we may conclude him to be determined by motives and causes, yet this
- removes not the uncertainty of our judgment concerning these causes, nor
- the influence of that uncertainty on the passions. Since therefore we
- ascribe a power of performing an action to every one, who has no very
- powerful motive to forbear it, and refuse it to such as have; it may
- justly be concluded, that power has always a reference to its exercise,
- either actual or probable, and that we consider a person as endowed with
- any ability when we find from past experience, that it is probable, or
- at least possible he may exert it. And indeed, as our passions always
- regard the real existence of objects, and we always judge of this
- reality from past instances; nothing can be more likely of itself,
- without any farther reasoning, than that power consists in the
- possibility or probability of any action, as discovered by experience
- and the practice of the world.
- Now it is evident, that wherever a person is in such a situadon with
- regard to me, that there is no very powerful motive to deter him from
- injuring me, and consequently it is uncertain whether he will injure me
- or not, I must be uneasy in such a situation, and cannot consider the
- possibility or probability of that injury without a sensible concern.
- The passions are not only affected by such events as are certain and
- infallible, but also in an inferior degree by such as are possible
- and contingent. And though perhaps I never really feel any harm, and
- discover by the event, that, philosophically speaking, the person never
- had any power of harming me; since he did not exert any; this prevents
- not my uneasiness from the preceding uncertainty. The agreeable passions
- may here operate as well as the uneasy, and convey a pleasure when I
- perceive a good to become either possible or probable by the possibility
- or probability of another's bestowing it on me, upon the removal of any
- strong motives, which might formerly have hindered him.
- But we may farther observe, that this satisfaction encreases, when any
- good approaches in such a manner that it it in one's own power to take
- or leave it, and there neither is any physical impediment, nor any
- very strong motive to hinder our enjoyment. As all men desire pleasure,
- nothing can be more probable, than its existence when there is no
- external obstacle to the producing it, and men perceive no danger in
- following their inclinations. In that case their imagination easily
- anticipates the satisfaction, and conveys the same joy, as if they were
- persuaded of its real and actual existence.
- But this accounts not sufficiently for the satisfaction, which attends
- riches. A miser receives delight from his money; that is, from the power
- it affords him of procuring all the pleasures and conveniences of life,
- though he knows he has enjoyed his riches for forty years without ever
- employing them; and consequently cannot conclude by any species of
- reasoning, that the real existence of these pleasures is nearer, than if
- he were entirely deprived of all his possessions. But though he cannot
- form any such conclusion in a way of reasoning concerning she nearer
- approach of the pleasure, it is certain he imagines it to approach
- nearer, whenever all external obstacles are removed, along with the more
- powerful motives of interest and danger, which oppose it. For farther
- satisfaction on this head I must refer to my account of the will, where
- I shall [Part III. Sect. 2.] explain that false sensation of liberty,
- which make, us imagine we can perform any thing, that is not very
- dangerous or destructive. Whenever any other person is under no
- strong obligations of interest to forbear any pleasure, we judge from
- experience, that the pleasure will exist, and that he will probably
- obtain it. But when ourselves are in that situation, we judge from
- an illusion of the fancy, that the pleasure is still closer and more
- immediate. The will seems to move easily every way, and casts a shadow
- or image of itself, even to that side, on which it did not settle. By
- means of this image the enjoyment seems to approach nearer to us, and
- gives us the same lively satisfaction, as if it were perfectly certain
- and unavoidable.
- It will now be easy to draw this whole reasoning to a paint, and to
- prove, that when riches produce any pride or vanity in their possessors,
- as they never fail so do, it is only by means of a double relation of
- impressions and ideas. The very essence of riches consists in the power
- of procuring the pleasures and conveniences of life. The very essence of
- this consists in the probability of its exercise, and in its causing us
- to anticipate, by a true or false reasoning, the real existence of
- the pleasure. This anticipation of pleasure is, in itself, a very
- considerable pleasure; and as its cause is some possession or property,
- which we enjoy, and which is thereby related to us, we here dearly see
- all the parts of the foregoing system most exactly and distinctly drawn
- out before us. For the same reason, that riches cause pleasure and
- pride, and poverty excites uneasiness and humility, power must produce
- the former emotions, and slavery the latter. Power or an authority over
- others makes us capable of satisfying all our desires; as slavery, by
- subjecting us to the will of others, exposes us to a thousand wants, and
- mortifications.
- It is here worth observing, that the vanity of power, or shame of
- slavery, are much augmented by the consideration of the persons,
- over whom we exercise our authority, or who exercise it over us. For
- supposing it possible to frame statues of such an admirable mechanism,
- that they coued move and act in obedience to the will; it is evident
- the possession of them would give pleasure and pride, but not to such a
- degree, as the same authority, when exerted over sensible and rational
- creatures, whose condition, being compared to our own, makes it seem
- more agreeable and honourable. Comparison is in every case a sure method
- of augmenting our esteem of any thing. A rich man feels the felicity of
- his condition better by opposing it to that of a beggar. But there is
- a peculiar advantage in power, by the contrast, which is, in a manner,
- presented to us, betwixt ourselves and the person we command. The
- comparison is obvious and natural: The imagination finds it in the very
- subject: The passage of the thought to its conception is smooth and
- easy. And that this circumstance has a considerable effect in augmenting
- its influence, will appear afterwards in examining the nature of malice
- and envy.
- SECT. XI OF THE LOVE OF FAME
- But beside these original causes of pride and humility, there is a
- secondary one in the opinions of others, which has an equal influence
- on the affections. Our reputation, our character, our name are
- considerations of vast weight and importance; and even the other causes
- of pride; virtue, beauty and riches; have little influence, when not
- seconded by the opinions and sentiments of others. In order to account
- for this phaenomenon it will be necessary to take some compass, and
- first explain the nature of sympathy.
- No quality of human nature is more remarkable, both in itself and in its
- consequences, than that propensity we have to sympathize with others,
- and to receive by communication their inclinations and sentiments,
- however different from, or even contrary to our own. This is not only
- conspicuous in children, who implicitly embrace every opinion proposed
- to them; but also in men of the greatest judgment and understanding,
- who find it very difficult to follow their own reason or inclination,
- in opposition to that of their friends and daily companions. To this
- principle we ought to ascribe the great uniformity we may observe in the
- humours and turn of thinking of those of the same nation; and it is much
- more probable, that this resemblance arises from sympathy, than from
- any influence of the soil and climate, which, though they continue
- invariably the same, are not able to preserve the character of a nation
- the same for a century together. A good-natured man finds himself in an
- instant of the same humour with his company; and even the proudest and
- most surly take a tincture from their countrymen and acquaintance. A
- chearful countenance infuses a sensible complacency and serenity into my
- mind; as an angry or sorrowful one throws a sudden dump upon me. Hatred,
- resentment, esteem, love, courage, mirth and melancholy; all these
- passions I feel more from communication than from my own natural temper
- and disposition. So remarkable a phaenomenon merits our attention, and
- must be traced up to its first principles.
- When any affection is infused by sympathy, it is at first known only
- by its effects, and by those external signs in the countenance and
- conversation, which convey an idea of it. This idea is presently
- converted into an impression, and acquires such a degree of force and
- vivacity, as to become the very passion itself, and produce an equal
- emotion, as any original affection. However instantaneous this change of
- the idea into an impression may be, it proceeds from certain views
- and reflections, which will not escape the strict scrutiny of a.
- philosopher, though they may the person himself, who makes them.
- It is evident, that the idea, or rather impression of ourselves is
- always intimately present with us, and that our consciousness gives us
- so lively a conception of our own person, that it is not possible to
- imagine, that any thing can in this particular go beyond it. Whatever
- object, therefore, is related to ourselves must be conceived with a
- little vivacity of conception, according to the foregoing principles;
- and though this relation should not be so strong as that of causation,
- it must still have a considerable influence. Resemblance and contiguity
- are relations not to be neglected; especially when by an inference
- from cause and effect, and by the observation of external signs, we are
- informed of the real existence of the object, which is resembling or
- contiguous.
- Now it is obvious, that nature has preserved a great resemblance among
- all human creatures, and that we never remark any passion or principle
- in others, of which, in some degree or other, we may not find a parallel
- in ourselves. The case is the same with the fabric of the mind, as with
- that of the body. However the parts may differ in shape or size, their
- structure and composition are in general the same. There is a very
- remarkable resemblance, which preserves itself amidst all their variety;
- and this resemblance must very much contribute to make us enter into
- the sentiments of others; and embrace them with facility and pleasure.
- Accordingly we find, that where, beside the general resemblance of our
- natures, there is any peculiar similarity in our manners, or character,
- or country, or language, it facilitates the sympathy. The stronger the
- relation is betwixt ourselves and any object, the more easily does the
- imagination make the transition, and convey to the related idea the
- vivacity of conception, with which we always form the idea of our own
- person.
- Nor is resemblance the only relation, which has this effect, but
- receives new force from other relations, that may accompany it. The
- sentiments of others have little influence, when far removed from
- us, and require the relation of contiguity, to make them communicate
- themselves entirely. The relations of blood, being a species of
- causation, may sometimes contribute to the same effect; as also
- acquaintance, which operates in the same manner with education and
- custom; as we shall see more fully [Part II. Sect. 4.] afterwards.
- All these relations, when united together, convey the impression
- or consciousness of our own person to the idea of the sentiments or
- passions of others, and makes us conceive them in the strongest and most
- lively manner.
- It has been remarked in the beginning of this treatise, that all ideas
- are borrowed from impressions, and that these two kinds of perceptions
- differ only in the degrees of force and vivacity, with which they
- strike upon the soul. The component part of ideas and impressions are
- precisely alike. The manner and order of their appearance may be the
- same. The different degrees of their force and vivacity are, therefore,
- the only particulars, that distinguish them: And as this difference may
- be removed, in some measure, by a relation betwixt the impressions and
- ideas, it is no wonder an idea of a sentiment or passion, may by this
- means be inlivened as to become the very sentiment or passion. The
- lively idea of any object always approaches is impression; and it
- is certain we may feel sickness and pain from the mere force of
- imagination, and make a malady real by often thinking of it. But this
- is most remarkable in the opinions and affections; and it is there
- principally that a lively idea is converted into an impression. Our
- affections depend more upon ourselves, and the internal operations of
- the mind, than any other impressions; for which reason they arise more
- naturally from the imagination, and from every lively idea we form of
- them. This is the nature and cause of sympathy; and it is after this
- manner we enter so deep into the opinions and affections of others,
- whenever we discover them.
- What is principally remarkable in this whole affair is the strong
- confirmation these phaenomena give to the foregoing system concerning
- the understanding, and consequently to the present one concerning the
- passions; since these are analogous to each other. It is indeed evident,
- that when we sympathize with the passions and sentiments of others,
- these movements appear at first in our mind as mere ideas, and are
- conceived to belong to another person, as we conceive any other matter
- of fact. It is also evident, that the ideas of the affections of others
- are converted into the very impressions they represent, and that the
- passions arise in conformity to the images we form of them. All this is
- an object of the plainest experience, and depends not on any hypothesis
- of philosophy. That science can only be admitted to explain the
- phaenomena; though at the same time it must be confest, they are so
- clear of themselves, that there is but little occasion to employ it. For
- besides the relation of cause and effect, by which we are convinced of
- the reality of the passion, with which we sympathize; besides this, I
- say, we must be assisted by the relations of resemblance and contiguity,
- in order to feel the sympathy in its full perfection. And since these
- relations can entirely convert an idea into an impression, and convey
- the vivacity of the latter into the former, so perfectly as to lose
- nothing of it in the transition, we may easily conceive how the relation
- of cause and effect alone, may serve to strengthen and inliven an
- idea. In sympathy there is an evident conversion of an idea into an
- impression. This conversion arises from the relation of objects to
- ourself. Ourself is always intimately present to us. Let us compare
- all these circumstances, and we shall find, that sympathy is exactly
- correspondent to the operations of our understanding; and even contains
- something more surprizing and extraordinary.
- It is now time to turn our view from the general consideration of
- sympathy, to its influence on pride and humility, when these passions
- arise from praise and blame, from reputation and infamy. We may observe,
- that no person is ever praised by another for any quality, which would
- not, if real, produce, of itself, a pride in the person possest of
- it. The elogiums either turn upon his power, or riches, or family,
- or virtue; all of which are subjects of vanity, that we have already
- explained and accounted for. It is certain, then, that if a person
- considered himself in the same light, in which he appears to his
- admirer, he would first receive a separate pleasure, and afterwards a
- pride or self-satisfaction, according to the hypothesis above explained.
- Now nothing is more natural than for us to embrace the opinions of
- others in this particular; both from sympathy, which renders all their
- sentiments intimately present to us; and from reasoning, which makes us
- regard their judgment, as a kind of argument for what they affirm.
- These two principles of authority and sympathy influence almost all our
- opinions; but must have a peculiar influence, when we judge of our own
- worth and character. Such judgments are always attended with passion
- [Book I, Part III. Sect. 10.]; and nothing tends more to disturb
- our understanding, and precipitate us into any opinions, however
- unreasonable, than their connexion with passion; which diffuses itself
- over the imagination, and gives an additional force to every related
- idea. To which we may add, that being conscious of great partiality in
- our own favour, we are peculiarly pleased with any thing, that confirms
- the good opinion we have of ourselves, and are easily shocked with
- whatever opposes it.
- All this appears very probable in theory; but in order to bestow a
- full certainty on this reasoning, we must examine the phaenonena of the
- passions, and see if they agree with it.
- Among these phaenomena we may esteem it a very favourable one to our
- present purposes that though fame in general be agreeable, yet we
- receive a much greater satisfaction from the approbation of those, whom
- we ourselves esteem and approve of, than of those, whom we hate and
- despise. In like measure we are principally mortifyed with the contempt
- of persons, upon whose judgment we set some value, and are, in a peat
- measure, indifferent about the opinions of the rest of mankind. But
- if the mind received from any original instinct a desire of fame
- and aversion to infamy, fame and infamy would influence us without
- distinction; and every opinion, according as it were favourabk or
- unfavourable, would equally excite that desire or aversion. The judgment
- of a fool is the judgment of another person, as well as that of a wise
- man, and is only inferior in its influence on our own judgment.
- We are not only better pleased with the approbation of a wise man than
- with that of a fool, but receive an additional satisfaction from the
- former, when it is obtained after a long and intimate acquaintance. This
- is accounted for after the same manner.
- The praises of others never give us much pleasure, unless they concur
- with our own opinion, and extol us for those qualities, in which we
- chiefly excel. A mere soldier little values the character of eloquence:
- A gownman of courage: A bishop of humour: Or a merchant of learning.
- Whatever esteem a man may have for any quality, abstractedly considered;
- when he is conscious he is not possest of it; the opinions of the whole
- world will give him little pleasure in that particular, and that because
- they never will be able to draw his own opinion after them.
- Nothing is more usual than for men of good families, but narrow
- circumstances, to leave their friends and country, and rather seek their
- livelihood by mean and mechanical employments among strangers, than
- among those, who are acquainted with their birth and education. We shall
- be unknown, say they, where we go. No body will suspect from what
- family we are sprung. We shall be removed from all our friends and
- acquaintance, and our poverty and meanness will by that means sit more
- easy upon us. In examining these sentiments, I find they afford many
- very convincing arguments for my present purpose.
- First, We may infer from them, that the uneasiness of being contemned
- depends on sympathy, and that sympathy depends on the relation of
- objects to ourselves; since we are most uneasy under the contempt of
- persons, who are both related to us by blood, and contiguous in place.
- Hence we-seek to diminish this sympathy and uneasiness by separating
- these relations, and placing ourselves in a contiguity to strangers, and
- at a distance from relations.
- Secondly, We may conclude, that relations are requisite to sympathy, not
- absolutely considered as relations, but by their influence in converting
- our ideas of the sentiments of others into the very sentiments, by means
- of the association betwixt the idea of their persons, and that of our
- own. For here the relations of kindred and contiguity both subsist; but
- not being united in the same persons, they contribute in a less degree
- to the sympathy.
- Thirdly, This very circumstance of the diminution of sympathy by the
- separation of relations is worthy of our attention. Suppose I am placed
- in a poor condition among strangers, and consequently am but lightly
- treated; I yet find myself easier in that situation, than when I was
- every day exposed to the contempt of my kindred and countrymen. Here
- I feel a double contempt; from my relations, but they are absent; from
- those about me, but they are strangers. This double contempt is likewise
- strengthened by the two relations of kindred and contiguity. But as
- the persons are not the same, who are connected with me by those two
- relations, this difference of ideas separates the impressions arising
- from the contempt, and keeps them from running into each other. The
- contempt of my neighbours has a certain influence; as has also that of
- my kindred: But these influences are distinct, and never unite; as when
- the contempt proceeds from persons who are at once both my neighbours
- and kindred. This phaenomenon is analogous to the system of pride and
- humility above-explained, which may seem so extraordinary to vulgar
- apprehensions.
- Fourthly, A person in these circumstances naturally conceals his birth
- from those among whom he lives, and is very uneasy, if any one suspects
- him to be of a family, much superior to his present fortune and way of
- living. Every thing in this world is judged of by comparison. What is
- an immense fortune for a private gentleman is beggary for a prince. A
- peasant would think himself happy in what cannot afford necessaries for
- a gentleman. When a man has either been acustomed to a more splendid way
- of living, or thinks himself intitled to it by his birth and quality,
- every thing below is disagreeable and even shameful; and it is with she
- greatest industry he conceals his pretensions to a better fortune. Here
- he himself knows his misfortunes; but as those, with whom he lives.
- are ignorant of them, he has the disagreeable reflection and comparison
- suggested only by his own thoughts, and never receives it by a
- sympathy with others; which must contribute very much so his ease and
- satisfaction.
- If there be any objections to this hypothesis, THAT THE PLEASURE, WHICH
- WE RECEIVE FROM PRAISE, ARISES FROM A COMMUNICATION OF SENTIMENTS, we
- shall find, uponexamination, that these objections, when taken in a
- properlight, will serve to confirm it. Popular fame may be agreeable
- even to a man, who despises the vulgar; but it is because their
- multitude gives them additional weight and authority. Plagiaries are
- delighted with praises, which they are conscious they do not deserve;
- but this is a kind of castle-building, where the imagination amuses
- itself with its own fictions, and strives to render them firm and stable
- by a sympathy with the sentiments of others. Proud men are most shocked
- with contempt, should they do not most readily assent to it; but it is
- because of the opposition betwixt the passion, which is natural so them,
- and that received by sympathy. A violent lover in like manner is very
- much disp pleased when you blame and condemn his love; though it is
- evident your opposition can have no influence, but by the hold it
- takes of himself, and by his sympathy with you. If he despises you, or
- perceives you are in jest, whatever you say has no effect upon him.
- SECT. XII OF THE PRIDE AND HUMILITY OF ANIMALS
- Thus in whatever light we consider this subject, we may still observe,
- that die causes of pride and humility correspond exactly to our
- hypothesis, and that nothing can excite either of these passions,
- unless it be both related to ourselves, and produces a pleasure or pain
- independent of the passion. We have not only proved, that a tendency
- to produce pleasure or pain is common to all the causes of pride or
- humility, but also that it is the only thing, which is common; and
- consequently is the quality, by which they operate. We have farther
- proved, that the most considerable causes of these passions are
- really nothing but the power of producing either agreeable or uneasy
- sensations; and therefore that all their effects, and amongst the rest,
- pride and humility, are derived solely from that origin. Such simple
- and natural principles, founded on such solid proofs, cannot fail to be
- received by philosophers, unless opposed by some objections, that have
- escaped me.
- It is usual with anatomists to join their observations and experiments
- on human bodies to those on beasts, and from the agreement of these
- experiments to derive an additional argument for any particular
- hypothesis. It is indeed certain, that where the structure of parts in
- brutes is the same as in men, and the operation of these parts also
- the same, the causes of that operation cannot be different, and that
- whatever we discover to be true of the one species, may be concluded
- without hesitation to be certain of the other. Thus though the mixture
- of humours and the composition of minute parts may justly be presumed
- so be somewhat different in men from what it is in mere animals; and
- therefore any experiment we make upon the one concerning the effects of
- medicines will not always apply to the other; yet as the structure of
- the veins and muscles, the fabric and situation of the heart, of the
- lungs, the stomach, the liver and other parts, are the same or nearly
- the same in all animals, the very same hypothesis, which in one species
- explains muscular motion, the progress of the chyle, the circulation of
- the blood, must be applicable to every one; and according as it
- agrees or disagrees with the experiments we may make in any species of
- creatures, we may draw a proof of its truth or falshood on the whole.
- Let us, therefore, apply this method of enquiry, which is found so just
- and useful in reasonings concerning the body, to our present anatomy of
- the mind, and see what discoveries we can make by it.
- In order to this we must first shew the correspondence of passions in
- men and animals, and afterwards compare the causes, which produce these
- passions.
- It is plain, that almost in every species of creatures, but especially
- of the nobler kind, there are many evident marks of pride and humility.
- The very port and gait of a swan, or turkey, or peacock show the high
- idea he has entertained of himself, and his contempt of all others. This
- is the more remarkable, that in the two last species of animals, the
- pride always attends the beauty, and is discovered in the male only.
- The vanity and emulation of nightingales in singing have been commonly
- remarked; as likewise that of horses in swiftness, of hounds in sagacity
- and smell, of the bull and cock in strength, and of every other animal
- in his particular excellency. Add to this, that every species of
- creatures, which approach so often to man, as to familiarize themselves
- with him, show an evident pride in his approbation, and are pleased with
- his praises and caresses, independent of every other consideration. Nor
- are they the caresses of every one without distinction, which give them
- this vanity, but those principally of the persons they know and love;
- in the same manner as that passion is excited in mankind. All these are
- evident proofs, that pride and humility are not merely human passions,
- but extend themselves over the whole animal creation.
- The CAUSES of these passions are likewise much the same in beasts as
- in us, making a just allowance for our superior knowledge and
- understanding. Thus animals have little or no sense of virtue or vice;
- they quickly lose sight of the relations of blood; and are incapable of
- that of right and property: For which reason the causes of their pride
- and humility must lie solely in the body, and can never be placed either
- in the mind or external objects. But so far as regards the body, the
- same qualities cause pride in the animal as in the human kind; and it is
- on beauty, strength, swiftness or some other useful or agreeable quality
- that this passion is always founded.
- The next question is, whether, since those passions are the same, and
- arise from the same causes through the whole creation, the manner, in
- which the causes operate, be also the same. According to all rules of
- analogy, this is justly to be expected; and if we find upon trial,
- that the explication of these phaenomena, which we make use of in
- one species, will not apply to the rest, we may presume that that
- explication, however specious, is in reality without foundation.
- In order to decide this question, let us consider, that there is
- evidently the same relation of ideas, and derived from the same causes,
- in the minds of animals as in those of men. A dog, that has hid a bone,
- often forgets the place; but when brought to it, his thought passes
- easily to what he formerly concealed, by means of the contiguity, which
- produces a relation among his ideas. In like manner, when he has been
- heartily beat in any place, he will tremble on his approach to it,
- even though he discover no signs of any present danger. The effects
- of resemblance are not so remarkable; but as that relation makes a
- considerable ingredient in causation, of which all animals shew
- so evident a judgment, we may conclude that the three relations of
- resemblance, contiguity and causation operate in the same manner upon
- beasts as upon human creatures.
- There are also instances of the relation of impressions, sufficient
- to convince us, that there is an union of certain affections with each
- other in the inferior species of creatures as well as in the superior,
- and that their minds are frequently conveyed through a series of
- connected emotions. A dog, when elevated with joy, runs naturally into
- love and kindness, whether of his master or of the sex. In like manner,
- when full of pain and sorrow, he becomes quarrelsome and illnatured;
- and that passion; which at first was grief, is by the smallest occasion
- converted into anger.
- Thus all the internal principles, that are necessary in us to produce
- either pride or humility, are commcm to all creaturn; and since the
- causes, which excite these passions, are likewise the same, we may
- justly conclude, that these causes operate after the same manner through
- the whole animal creation. My hypothesis Is so simple, and supposes so
- little reflection and judgment, that it is applicable to every sensible
- creature; which must not only be allowed to be a convincing proof of its
- veracity, but, I am confident, will be found an objection to every other
- system.
- PART II OF LOVE AND HATRED
- SECT. I OF THE OBJECT AND CAUSES OF LOVE AND HATRED
- It is altogether impossible to give any definition of the passions
- of love and hatred; and that because they produce merely a simple
- impression, without any mixture or composition. Twould be as unnecessary
- to attempt any description of them, drawn from their nature, origin,
- causes and objects; and that both because these are the subjects of
- our present enquiry, and because these passions of themselves are
- sufficiently known from our common feeling and experience. This we
- have already observed concerning pride and humility, and here repeat it
- concerning love and hatred; and indeed there is so great a resemblance
- betwixt these two sets of passions, that we shall be obliged to begin
- with a kind of abridgment of our reasonings concerning the former, in
- order to explain the latter.
- As the immediate object of pride and humility is self or that identical
- person, of whose thoughts, actions, and sensations we are intimately
- conscious; so the object of love and hatred is some other person, of
- whose thoughts, actions, and sensations we are not conscious. This is
- sufficiently evident from experience. Our love and hatred are always
- directed to some sensible being external to us; and when we talk
- of self-love, it is not in a proper sense, nor has the sensation it
- produces any thing in common with that tender emotion which is excited
- by a friend or mistress. It is the same case with hatred. We may be
- mortified by our own faults and follies; but never feel any anger or
- hatred except from the injuries of others.
- But though the object of love and hatred be always some other person, it
- is plain that the object is not, properly speaking, the cause of these
- passions, or alone sufficient to excite them. For since love and hatred
- are directly contrary in their sensation, and have the same object in
- common, if that object were also their cause, it would produce these
- opposite passions in an equal degree; and as they must, from the very
- first moment, destroy each other, none of them would ever be able to
- make its appearance. There must, therefore, be some cause different from
- the object.
- If we consider the causes of love and hatred, we shall find they are
- very much diversifyed, and have not many things in common. The virtue,
- knowledge, wit, good sense, good humour of any person, produce love
- and esteem; as the opposite qualities, hatred and contempt. The same
- passions arise from bodily accomplishments, such as beauty, force,
- swiftness, dexterity; and from their contraries; as likewise from the
- external advantages and disadvantages of family, possession, cloaths,
- nation and climate. There is not one of these objects, but what by its
- different qualities may produce love and esteem, or hatred and contempt.
- From the view of these causes we may derive a new distinction betwixt
- the quality that operates, and the subject on which it is placed. A
- prince, that is possessed of a stately palace, commands the esteem
- of the people upon that account; and that first, by the beauty of the
- palace, and secondly, by the relation of property, which connects it
- with him. The removal of either of these destroys the passion; which
- evidently proves that the cause Is a compounded one.
- Twould be tedious to trace the passions of love and hatred, through all
- the observations which we have formed concerning pride and humility,
- and which are equally applicable to both sets of passions. Twill be
- sufficient to remark in general, that the object of love and hatred is
- evidently some thinking person; and that the sensation of the former
- passion is always agreeable, and of the latter uneasy. We may also
- suppose with some shew of probability, THAT THE CAUSE OF BOTH THESE
- PASSIONS IS ALWAYS RELATED TO A THINKING BEING, AND THAT THE CAUSE OF
- THE FORMER PRODUCE A SEPARATE PLEASURE, AND OF THE LATTER A SEPARATE
- UNEASINESS.
- One of these suppositions, viz, that the cause of love and hatred must
- be related to a person or thinking being, in order to produce these
- passions, is not only probable, but too evident to be contested. Virtue
- and vice, when considered in the abstract; beauty and deformity, when
- placed on inanimate objects; poverty and riches when belonging to a
- third person, excite no degree of love or hatred, esteem or contempt
- towards those, who have no relation to them. A person looking out at a
- window, sees me in the street, and beyond me a beautiful palace, with
- which I have no concern: I believe none will pretend, that this person
- will pay me the same respect, as if I were owner of the palace.
- It is not so evident at first sight, that a relation of impressions is
- requisite to these passions, and that because in the transition the one
- impression is so much confounded with the other, that they become in a
- manner undistinguishable. But as in pride and humility, we have easily
- been able to make the separation, and to prove, that every cause of
- these passions, produces a separate pain or pleasure, I might here
- observe the same method with the same success, in examining particularly
- the several causes of love and hatred. But as I hasten a full and
- decisive proof of these systems, I delay this examination for a moment:
- And in the mean time shall endeavour to convert to my present purpose
- all my reaaonings concerning pride and humility, by an argument that
- is founded on unquestionable examination.
- There are few persons, that are satisfyed with their own character, or
- genius, or fortune, who are nor desirous of shewing themselves to the
- world, and of acquiring the love and approbation of mankind. Now it is
- evident, that the very same qualities and circumstances, which are the
- causes of pride or self-esteem, are also the causes of vanity or the
- desire of reputation; and that we always put to view those particulars
- with which in ourselves we are best satisfyed. But if love and esteem
- were not produced by the same qualities as pride, according as these
- qualities are related to ourselves or others, this method of proceeding
- would be very absurd, nor coued men expect a correspondence in
- the sentiments of every other person, with those themselves have
- entertained. It is true, few can form exact systems of the passions, or
- make reflections on their general nature and resemblances. But without
- such a progress in philosophy, we are not subject to many mistakes in
- this particular, but are sufficiently guided by common experience, as
- well as by a kind of presentation; which tells us what will operate on
- others, by what we feel immediately in ourselves. Since then the same
- qualities that produce pride or humility, cause love or hatred; all
- the arguments that have been employed to prove, that the causes of the
- former passions excite a pain or pleasure independent of the passion,
- will be applicable with equal evidence to the causes of the latter.
- SECT. II EXPERIMENTS TO CONFIRM THIS SYSTEM
- Upon duly weighing these arguments, no one will make any scruple to
- assent to that condusion I draw from them, concerning the transition
- along related impressions and ideas, especially as it is a principle,
- in itself, so easy and natural. But that we may place this system beyond
- doubt both with regard to love and hatred, pride and humility, it will
- be proper to make some new experiments upon all these passions, as well
- as to recal a few of these observations, which I have formerly touched
- upon.
- In order to make these experiments, let us suppose I am in company with
- a person, whom I formerly regarded without any sentiments either of
- friendship or enmity. Here I have the natural and ultimate object of all
- these four passions placed before me. Myself am the proper object of
- pride or humility; the other person of love or hatred.
- Regard now with attention the nature of these passions, and their
- situation with respect to each other. It is evident here are four
- affections, placed, as it were, in a square or regular connexion with,
- and distance from each other. The passions of pride and humility, as
- well as those of love and hatred, are connected together by the identity
- of their object, which to the first set of passions is self, to the
- second some other person. These two lines of communication or connexion
- form two opposite sides of the square. Again, pride and love are
- agreeable passions; hatred and humility uneasy. This similitude of
- sensation betwixt pride and love, and that betwixt humility and hatred
- form a new connexion, and may be considered as the other two sides of
- the square. Upon the whole, pride is connected with humility, love
- with hatred, by their objects or ideas: Pride with love, humility with
- hatred, by their sensations or impressions.
- I say then, that nothing can produce any of these passions without
- bearing it a double relation, viz, of ideas to the object of the
- passion, and of sensation to the passion itself. This we must prove by
- our experiments. First Experiment. To proceed with the greater order
- in these experiments, let us first suppose, that being placed in the
- situation above-mentioned, viz, in company with some other person, there
- is an object presented, that has no relation either of impressions
- or ideas to any of these passions. Thus suppose we regard together an
- ordinary stone, or other common object, belonging to neither of us, and
- causing of itself no emotion, or independent pain and pleasure: It is
- evident such an object will produce none of these four passions. Let
- us try it upon each of them successively. Let us apply it to love, to
- hatred, to humility, to pride; none of them ever arises in the smallest
- degree imaginable. Let us change the object, as oft as we please;
- provided still we choose one, that has neither of these two relations.
- Let us repeat the experiment in all the dispositions, of which the mind
- is susceptible. No object, in the vast variety of nature, will, in any
- disposition, produce any passion without these relations.
- Second Experiment. Since an object, that wants both these relations
- can never produce any passion, let us bestow on it only one of these
- relations; and see what will follow. Thus suppose, I regard a stone or
- any common object, that belongs either to me or my companion, and by
- that means acquires a relation of ideas to the object of the passions:
- It is plain, that to consider the matter a priori, no emotion of any
- kind can reasonably be expected. For besides, that a relation of ideas
- operates secretly and calmly on the mind, it bestows an equal impulse
- towards the opposite passions of pride and humility, love and hatred,
- according as the object belongs to ourselves or others; which opposition
- of the passions must destroy both, and leave the mind perfectly free
- from any affection or emotion. This reasoning a priori is confirmed
- by experience. No trivial or vulgar object, that causes not a pain or
- pleasure, independent of the passion, will ever, by its property or
- other relations either to ourselves or others, be able to produce the
- affections of pride or humility, love or hatred.
- Third Experiment. It is evident, therefore, that a relation of ideas is
- not able alone to give rise to these affections. Let us now remove
- this relation, and in its stead place a relation of impressions, by
- presenting an object, which is agreeable or disagreeable, but has
- no relation either to ourself or companion; and let us observe the
- consequences. To consider the matter first a priori, as in the preceding
- experiment; we may conclude, that the object will have a small, but an
- uncertain connexion with these passions. For besides, that this relation
- is not a cold and imperceptible one, it has not the inconvenience of
- the relation of ideas, nor directs us with equal force to two contrary
- passions, which by their opposition destroy each other. But if we
- consider, on the other hand, that this transition from the sensation
- to the affection is not forwarded by any principle, that produces
- a transition of ideas; but, on the contrary, that though the one
- impression be easily transfused into the other, yet the change of
- objects is supposed contrary to all the principles, that cause a
- transition of that kind; we may from thence infer, that nothing will
- ever be a steady or durable cause of any passion, that is connected with
- the passion merely by a relation of impressions. What our reason would
- conclude from analogy, after balancing these arguments, would be, that
- an object, which produces pleasure or uneasiness, but has no manner of
- connexion either with ourselves or others, may give such a turn to the
- disposition, as that may naturally fall into pride or love, humility or
- hatred, and search for other objects, upon which by a double relation,
- it can found these affections; but that an object, which has only one of
- these relations, though the most advantageous one, can never give rise
- to any constant and established passion.
- Most fortunately all this reasoning is found to be exactly conformable
- to experience, and the phaenomena of the passions. Suppose I were
- travelling with a companion through a country, to which we are both
- utter strangers; it is evident, that if the prospects be beautiful,
- the roads agreeable, and the inns commodious, this may put me into good
- humour both with myself and fellow-traveller. But as we suppose, that
- this country has no relation either to myself or friend it can never be
- the immediate cause of pride or love; and therefore if I found not the
- passion on some other object, that bears either of us a closer relation,
- my emotions are rather to be considerd as the overflowings of an elevate
- or humane disposition, than as an established passion. The case is the
- same where the object produces uneasiness.
- Fourth Experiment. Having found, that neither an object without any
- relation of ideas or impressions, nor an object, that has only one
- relation, can ever cause pride or humility, love or hatred; reason alone
- may convince us, without any farther experiment, that whatever has a
- double relation must necessarily excite these passions; since it is
- evident they must have some cause. But to leave as little room for doubt
- as possible, let us renew our experiments, and see whether the event in
- this case answers our expectation. I choose an object, such as virtue,
- that causes a separate satisfaction: On this object I bestow a relation
- to self; and find, that from this disposition of affairs, there
- immediately arises a passion. But what passion? That very one of pride,
- to which this object bears a double relation. Its idea is related
- to that of self, the object of the passion: The sensation it causes
- resembles the sensation of the passion. That I may be sure I am not
- mistaken in this experiment, I remove first one relation; then another;
- and find, that each removal destroys the passion, and leaves the object
- perfectly indifferent. But I am not content with this. I make a still
- farther trial; and instead of removing the relation, I only change
- it for one of a different kind. I suppose the virtue to belong to my
- companion, not to myself; and observe what follows from this alteration.
- I immediately perceive the affections wheel to about, and leaving pride,
- where there is only one relation, viz, of impressions, fall to the side
- of love, where they are attracted by a double relation of impressions
- and ideas. By repeating the same experiment, in changing anew the
- relation of ideas, I bring the affections back to pride; and by a new
- repetition I again place them at love or kindness. Being fully convinced
- of the influence of this relation, I try the effects of the other; and
- by changing virtue for vice, convert the pleasant impression, which
- arises from the former, into the disagreeable one, which proceeds from
- the latter. The effect still answers expectation. Vice, when placed
- on another, excites, by means of its double relations, the passion of
- hatred, instead of love, which for the same reason arises from virtue.
- To continue the experiment, I change anew the relation of ideas, and
- suppose the vice to belong to myself. What follows? What is usual. A
- subsequent change of the passion from hatred to humility. This humility
- I convert into pride by a new change of the impression; and find after
- all that I have compleated the round, and have by these changes brought
- back the passion to that very situation, in which I first found it.
- But to make the matter still more certain, I alter the object; and
- instead of vice and virtue, make the trial upon beauty and deformity,
- riches and poverty, power and servitude. Each of these objects runs
- the circle of the passions in the same manner, by a change of their
- relations: And in whatever order we proceed, whether through pride,
- love, hatred, humility, or through humility, hatred, love, pride, the
- experiment is not in the least diversifyed. Esteem and contempt, indeed,
- arise on some occasions instead of love and hatred; but these are at
- the bottom the same passions, only diversifyed by some causes, which we
- shall explain afterwards.
- Fifth Experiment. To give greater authority to these experiments, let
- us change the situation of affairs as much as possible, and place the
- passions and objects in all the different positions, of which they are
- susceptible. Let us suppose, beside the relations above-mentioned, that
- the person, along with whom I make all these experiments, is closely
- connected with me either by blood or friendship. He is, we shall
- suppose, my son or brother, or is united to me by a long and familiar
- acquaintance. Let us next suppose, that the cause of the passion
- acquires a double relation of impressions and ideas to this person; and
- let us see what the effects are of all these complicated attractions and
- relations.
- Before we consider what they are in fact, let us determine what they
- ought to be, conformable to my hypothesis. It is plain, that, according
- as the impression is either pleasant or uneasy, the passion of love or
- hatred must arise towards the person, who is thus connected to the cause
- of the impression by these double relations, which I have all along
- required. The virtue of a brother must make me love him; as his vice
- or infamy must excite the contrary passion. But to judge only from the
- situation of affairs, I should not expect, that the affections would
- rest there, and never transfuse themselves into any other impression. As
- there is here a person, who by means of a double relation is the object
- of my passion, the very same reasoning leads me to think the passion
- will be carryed farther. The person has a relation of ideas to myself,
- according to the supposition; the passion, of which he is the object, by
- being either agreeable or uneasy, has a relation of impressions to pride
- or humility. It is evident, then, that one of these passions must arise
- from the love or hatred.
- This is the reasoning I form in conformity to my hypothesis; and am
- pleased to find upon trial that every thing answers exactly to my
- expectation. The virtue or vice of a son or brother not only excites
- love or hatred, but by a new transition, from similar causes, gives rise
- to pride or humility. Nothing causes greater vanity than any shining
- quality in our relations; as nothing mortifies us more than their vice
- or infamy. This exact conformity of experience to our reasoning is
- a convincing proof of the solidity of that hypothesis, upon which we
- reason.
- Sixth Experiment. This evidence will be still augmented, if we reverse
- the experiment, and preserving still the same relations, begin only with
- a different passion. Suppose, that instead of the virtue or vice of a
- son or brother, which causes first love or hatred, and afterwards pride
- or humility, we place these good or bad qualities on ourselves,
- without any immediate connexion with the person, who is related to us:
- Experience shews us, that by this change of situation the whole chain is
- broke, and that the mind is not conveyed from one passion to another,
- as in the preceding instance. We never love or hate a son or brother
- for the virtue or vice we discern in ourselves; though it is evident
- the same qualities in him give us a very sensible pride or humility. The
- transition from pride or humility to love or hatred is not so natural
- as from love or hatred to pride or humility. This may at first sight be
- esteemed contrary to my hypothesis; since the relations of impressions
- and ideas are in both cases precisely the same. Pride and humility are
- impressions related to love and hatred. Myself am related to the person.
- It should, therefore, be expected, that like causes must produce like
- effects, and a perfect transition arise from the double relation, as in
- all other cases. This difficulty we may easily solve by the following
- reflections.
- It is evident, that as we are at all times intimately conscious of
- ourselves, our sentiments and passions, their ideas must strike upon us
- with greater vivacity than the ideas of the sentiments and passions of
- any other person. But every thing, that strikes upon us with vivacity,
- and appears in a full and strong light, forces itself, in a manner, into
- our consideration, and becomes present to the mind on the smallest hint
- and most trivial relation. For the same reason, when it is once present,
- it engages the attention, and keeps it from wandering to other
- objects, however strong may be their relation to our first object.
- The imagination passes easily from obscure to lively ideas, but with
- difficulty from lively to obscure. In the one case the relation is aided
- by another principle: In the other case, it is opposed by it.
- Now I have observed, that those two faculties of the mind, the
- imagination and passions, assist each other in their operations when
- their propensities are similar, and when they act upon the same object.
- The mind has always a propensity to pass from a passion to any other
- related to it; and this propensity is forwarded when the object of the
- one passion is related to that of the other. The two impulses concur
- with each other, and render the whole transition more smooth and easy.
- But if it should happen, that while the relation of ideas, strictly
- speaking, continues the same, its influence, in causing a transition
- of the imagination, should no longer take place, it is evident its
- influence on the passions must also cease, as being dependent entirely
- on that transition. This is the reason why pride or humility is not
- transfused into love or hatred with the same ease, that the latter
- passions are changed into the former. If a person be my brother I am
- his likewise: but though the relations be reciprocal they have very
- different effects on the imagination. The passage is smooth and open
- from the consideration of any person related to us to that of ourself,
- of whom we are every moment conscious. But when the affections are once
- directed to ourself, the fancy passes not with the same facility from
- that object to any other person, how closely so ever connected with us.
- This easy or difficult transition of the imagination operates upon the
- passions, and facilitates or retards their transition, which is a clear
- proof, that these two faculties of the passions and imagination are
- connected together, and that the relations of ideas have an influence
- upon the affections. Besides innumerable experiments that prove this,
- we here find, that even when the relation remains; if by any particular
- circumstance its usual effect upon the fancy in producing an association
- or transition of ideas, is prevented; its usual effect upon the
- passions, in conveying us from one to another, is in like manner
- prevented.
- Some may, perhaps, find a contradiction betwixt this phaenomenon
- and that of sympathy, where the mind passes easily from the idea of
- ourselves to that of any other object related to us. But this difficulty
- will vanish, if we consider that in sympathy our own person is not the
- object of any passion, nor is there any thing, that fixes our attention
- on ourselves; as in the present case, where we are supposed to be
- actuated with pride or humility. Ourself, independent of the perception
- of every other object, is in reality nothing: For which reason we must
- turn our view to external objects; and it is natural for us to consider
- with most attention such as lie contiguous to us, or resemble us. But
- when self is the object of a passion, it is not natural to quit the
- consideration of it, till the passion be exhausted: in which case the
- double relations of impressions and ideas can no longer operate.
- Seventh Experiment. To put this whole reasoning to a farther trial, let
- us make a new experiment; and as we have already seen the effects of
- related passions and ideas, let us here suppose an identity of passions
- along with a relation of ideas; and let us consider the effects of this
- new situation. It is evident a transition of the passions from the one
- object to the other is here in all reason to be expected; since the
- relation of ideas is supposed still to continue, and identity of
- impressions must produce a stronger connexion, than the most perfect
- resemblance, that can be imagined. If a double relation, therefore, of
- impressions and ideas is able to produce a transition from one to the
- other, much more an identity of impressions with a relation of ideas.
- Accordingly we find, that when we either love or hate any person,
- the passions seldom continue within their first bounds; but extend
- themselves towards all the contiguous objects, and comprehend the
- friends and relations of him we love or hate. Nothing is more natural
- than to bear a kindness to one brother on account of our friendship for
- another, without any farther examination of his character. A quarrel
- with one person gives us a hatred for the whole family, though entirely
- innocent of that, which displeases us. Instances of this kind are every
- where to be met with.
- There is only one difficulty in this experiment, which it will be
- necessary to account for, before we proceed any farther. It is evident,
- that though all passions pass easily from one object to another related
- to it, yet this transition is made with greater facility, where the more
- considerable object is first presented, and the lesser follows it, than
- where this order is reversed, and the lesser takes the precedence. Thus
- it is more natural for us to love the son upon account of the father,
- than the father upon account of the son; the servant for the master,
- than the master for the servant; the subject for the prince, than the
- prince for the subject. In like manner we more readily contract a hatred
- against a whole family, where our first quarrel is with the head of it,
- than where we are displeased with a son, or servant, or some inferior
- member. In short, our passions, like other objects, descend with greater
- facility than they ascend.
- That we may comprehend, wherein consists the difficulty of explaining
- this phaenomenon, we must consider, that the very same reason, which
- determines the imagination to pass from remote to contiguous objects,
- with more facility than from contiguous to remote, causes it likewise
- to change with more ease, the less for the greater, than the greater for
- the less. Whatever has the greatest influence is most taken notice of;
- and whatever is most taken notice of, presents itself most readily to
- the imagination. We are more apt to over-look in any subject, what is
- trivial, than what appears of considerable moment; but especially if the
- latter takes the precedence, and first engages our attention. Thus if
- any accident makes us consider the Satellites of JUPITER, our fancy is
- naturally determined to form the idea of that planet; but if we first
- reflect on the principal planet, it is more natural for us to overlook
- its attendants. The mention of the provinces of any empire conveys our
- thought to the seat of the empire; but the fancy returns not with the
- same facility to the consideration of the provinces. The idea of the
- servant makes us think of the master; that of the subject carries our
- view to the prince. But the same relation has not an equal influence
- in conveying us back again. And on this is founded that reproach of
- Cornelia to her sons, that they ought to be ashamed she should be more
- known by the title of the daughter of Scipio than by that of the mother
- of the Gracchi. This was, in other words, exhorting them to render
- themselves as illustrious and famous as their grandfather, otherwise the
- imagination of the people, passing from her who was intermediate,
- and placed in an equal relation to both, would always leave them, and
- denominate her by what was more considerable and of greater moment. On
- the same principle is founded that common custom of making wives bear
- the name of their husbands, rather than husbands that of their wives; as
- also the ceremony of giving the precedency to those, whom we honour and
- respect. We might find many other instances to confirm this principle,
- were it not already sufficiently evident.
- Now since the fancy finds the same facility in passing from the lesser
- to the greater, as from remote to contiguous, why does not this easy
- transition of ideas assist the transition of passions in the former
- case, as well as in the latter? The virtues of a friend or brother
- produce first love, and then pride; because in that case the imagination
- passes from remote to contiguous, according to its propensity. Our own
- virtues produce not first pride, and then love to a friend or brother;
- because the passage in that case would be from contiguous to remote,
- contrary to its propensity. But the love or hatred of an inferior causes
- not readily any passion to the superior, though that be the natural
- propensity of the imagination: While the love or hatred of a superior,
- causes a passion to the inferior, contrary to its propensity. In short,
- the same facility of transition operates not in the same manner
- upon superior and inferior as upon contiguous and remote. These two
- phaenomena appear contradictory, and require some attention to be
- reconciled.
- As the transition of ideas is here made contrary to the natural
- propensity of the imagination, that faculty must be overpowered by some
- stronger principle of another kind; and as there is nothing ever present
- to the mind but impressions and ideas, this principle must necessarily
- lie in the impressions. Now it has been observed, that impressions or
- passions are connected only by their resemblance, and that where any two
- passions place the mind in the same or in similar dispositions, it
- very naturally passes from the one to the other: As on the contrary, a
- repugnance in the dispositions produces a difficulty in the transition
- of the passions. But it is observable, that this repugnance may arise
- from a difference of degree as well as of kind; nor do we experience a
- greater difficulty in passing suddenly from a small degree of love to a
- small degree of hatred, than from a small to a great degree of either
- of these affections. A man, when calm or only moderately agitated, is so
- different, in every respect, from himself, when disturbed with a violent
- passion, that no two persons can be more unlike; nor is it easy to
- pass from the one extreme to the other, without a considerable interval
- betwixt them.
- The difficulty is not less, if it be not rather greater, in passing from
- the strong passion to the weak, than in passing from the weak to the
- strong, provided the one passion upon its appearance destroys the other,
- and they do not both of them exist at once. But the case is entirely
- altered, when the passions unite together, and actuate the mind at
- the same time. A weak passion, when added to a strong, makes not so
- considerable a change in the disposition, as a strong when added to a
- weak; for which reason there is a closer connexion betwixt the great
- degree and the small, than betwixt the small degree and the great.
- The degree of any passion depends upon the nature of its object; and an
- affection directed to a person, who is considerable in our eyes, fills
- and possesses the mind much more than one, which has for its object
- a person we esteem of less consequence. Here then the contradiction
- betwixt the propensities of the imagination and passion displays itself.
- When we turn our thought to a great and a small object, the imagination
- finds more facility in passing from the small to the great, than from
- the great to the small; but the affections find a greater difficulty:
- And as the affections are a more powerful principle than the
- imagination, no wonder they prevail over it, and draw the mind to their
- side. In spite of the difficulty of passing from the idea of great to
- that of little, a passion directed to the former, produces always
- a similar passion towards the latter; when the great and little are
- related together. The idea of the servant conveys our thought most
- readily to the master; but the hatred or love of the master produces
- with greater facility anger or good-will to the servant. The strongest
- passion in this case takes the precedence; and the addition of the
- weaker making no considerable change on the disposition, the passage is
- by that means rendered more easy and natural betwixt them.
- As in the foregoing experiment we found, that a relation of ideas,
- which, by any particular circumstance, ceases to produce its usual
- effect of facilitating the transition of ideas, ceases likewise to
- operate on the passions; so in the present experiment we find the same
- property of the impressions. Two different degrees of the same passion
- are surely related together; but if the smaller be first present, it
- has little or no tendency to introduce the greater; and that because the
- addition of the great to the little, produces a more sensible alteration
- on the temper, than the addition of the little to the great. These
- phaenomena, when duly weighed, will be found convincing proofs of this
- hypothesis.
- And these proofs will be confirmed, if we consider the manner in which
- the mind here reconciles the contradiction, I have observed betwixt the
- passions and the imagination. The fancy passes with more facility from
- the less to the greater, than from the greater to the less: But on the
- contrary a violent passion produces more easily a feeble, than that does
- a violent. In this opposition the passion in the end prevails over the
- imagination; but it is commonly by complying with it, and by seeking
- another quality, which may counter-ballance that principle, from whence
- the opposition arises. When we love the father or master of a family,
- we little think of his children or servants. But when these are present
- with us, or when it lies any ways in our power to serve them, the
- nearness and contiguity in this case encreases their magnitude, or at
- least removes that opposition, which the fancy makes to the transition
- of the affections. If the imagination finds a difficulty in passing from
- greater to less, it finds an equal facility in passing from remote to
- contiguous, which brings the matter to an equality, and leaves the way
- open from the one passion to the other.
- Eighth Experiment. I have observed that the transition from love or
- hatred to pride or humility, is more easy than from pride or humility to
- love or hatred; and that the difficulty, which the imagination finds in
- passing from contiguous to remote, is the cause why we scarce have any
- instance of the latter transition of the affections. I must, however,
- make one exception, viz, when the very cause of the pride and humility
- is placed in some other person. For in that case the imagination is
- necessitated to consider the person, nor can it possibly confine its
- view to ourselves. Thus nothing more readily produces kindness and
- affection to any person, than his approbation of our conduct and
- character: As on the other hand, nothing inspires us with a stronger
- hatred, than his blame or contempt. Here it is evident, that the
- original passion is pride or humility, whose object is self; and that
- this passion is transfused into love or hatred, whose object is some
- other person, notwithstanding the rule I have already established, THAT
- THE IMAGINATION PASSES WITH DIFFICULTY FROM CONTIGUOUS TO REMOTE.
- But the transition in this case is not made merely on account of the
- relation betwixt ourselves and the person; but because that very person
- is the real cause of our first passion, and of consequence is intimately
- connected with it. It is his approbation that produces pride; and
- disapprobation, humility. No wonder, then, the imagination returns back
- again attended with the related passions of love and hatred. This is
- not a contradiction, but an exception to the rule; and an exception that
- arises from the same reason with the rule itself.
- Such an exception as this is, therefore, rather a confirmation of
- the rule. And indeed, if we consider all the eight experiments I have
- explained, we shall find that the same principle appears in all of them,
- and that it is by means of a transition arising from a double relation
- of impressions and ideas, pride and humility, love and hatred are
- produced. An object without [First Experiment.] a relation, or [Second
- and Third Experiments] with but one, never produces either of these
- passions; and it is [Fourth Experiment.] found that the passion always
- varies in conformity to the relation. Nay we may observe, that where the
- relation, by any particular circumstance, has not its usual effect
- of producing a transition either of [Sixth Experiment.] ideas or of
- impressions, it ceases to operate upon the passions, and gives rise
- neither to pride nor love, humility nor hatred. This rule we find still
- to hold good [Seventh and Eighth Experiments.] even under the appearance
- of its contrary; and as relation is frequently experienced to have no
- effect; which upon examination is found to proceed from some particular
- circumstance, that prevents the transition; so even in instances, where
- that circumstance, though present, prevents not the transition, it is
- found to arise from some other circumstance, which counter-balances
- it. Thus not only the variations resolve themselves into the general
- principle, but even the variations of these variations.
- SECT. III DIFFICULTIES SOLVED
- After so many and such undeniable proofs drawn from daily experience
- and observation, it may seem superfluous to enter into a particular
- examination of all the causes of love and hatred. I shall, therefore,
- employ the sequel of this part, First, In removing some difficulties,
- concerning particular causes of these passions. Secondly, In examining
- the compound affections, which arise from the mixture of love and hatred
- with other emotions.
- Nothing is more evident, than that any person acquires our kindness, or
- is exposed to our ill-will, in proportion to the pleasure or uneasiness
- we receive from him, and that the passions keep pace exactly with the
- sensations in all their changes and variations. Whoever can find the
- means either by his services, his beauty, or his flattery, to render
- himself useful or agreeable to us, is sure of our affections: As on the
- other hand, whoever harms or displeases us never fails to excite our
- anger or hatred. When our own nation is at war with any other, we detest
- them under the character of cruel, perfidious, unjust and violent: But
- always esteem ourselves and allies equitable, moderate, and merciful. If
- the general of our enemies be successful, it is with difficulty we
- allow him the figure and character of a man. He is a sorcerer: He has a
- communication with daemons; as is reported of OLIVER CROMWELL, and the
- DUKE OF LUXEMBOURG: He is bloody-minded, and takes a pleasure in death
- and destruction. But if the success be on our side, our commander has
- all the opposite good qualities, and is a pattern of virtue, as well as
- of courage and conduct. His treachery we call policy: His cruelty is an
- evil inseparable from war. In short, every one of his faults we either
- endeavour to extenuate, or dignify it with the name of that virtue,
- which approaches it. It is evident the same method of thinking runs
- through common life.
- There are some, who add another condition, and require not only that
- the pain and pleasure arise from the person, but likewise that it arise
- knowingly, and with a particular design and intention. A man, who wounds
- and harms us by accident, becomes not our enemy upon that account, nor
- do we think ourselves bound by any ties of gratitude to one, who does
- us any service after the same manner. By the intention we judge of the
- actions, and according as that is good or bad, they become causes of
- love or hatred.
- But here we must make a distinction. If that quality in another, which
- pleases or displeases, be constant and inherent in his person and
- character, it will cause love or hatred independent of the intention:
- But otherwise a knowledge and design is requisite, in order to give rise
- to these passions. One that is disagreeable by his deformity or folly is
- the object of our aversion, though nothing be more certain, than that he
- has not the least intention of displeasing us by these qualities. But
- if the uneasiness proceed not from a quality, but an action, which
- is produced and annihilated in a moment, it is necessary, in order to
- produce some relation, and connect this action sufficiently with the
- person, that it be derived from a particular fore-thought and design. It
- is not enough, that the action arise from the person, and have him for
- its immediate cause and author. This relation alone is too feeble and
- inconstant to be a foundation for these passions. It reaches not the
- sensible and thinking part, and neither proceeds from any thing durable
- in him, nor leaves any thing behind it; but passes in a moment, and is
- as if it had never been. On the other hand, an intention shews certain
- qualities, which remaining after the action is performed, connect it
- with the person, and facilitate the transition of ideas from one to the
- other. We can never think of him without reflecting on these qualities;
- unless repentance and a change of life have produced an alteration
- in that respect: In which case the passion is likewise altered. This
- therefore is one reason, why an intention is requisite to excite either
- love or hatred.
- But we must farther consider, that an intention, besides its
- strengthening the relation of ideas, is often necessary to produce a
- relation of impressions, and give rise to pleasure and uneasiness. For
- it is observable, that the principal part of an injury is the contempt
- and hatred, which it shews in the person, that injures us; and without
- that, the mere harm gives us a less sensible uneasiness. In like manner,
- a good office is agreeable, chiefly because it flatters our vanity, and
- is a proof of the kindness and esteem of the person, who performs it.
- The removal of the intention, removes the mortification in the one
- case, and vanity in the other, and must of course cause a remarkable
- diminution in the passions of love and hatred.
- I grant, that these effects of the removal of design, in diminishing the
- relations of impressions and ideas, are not entire, nor able to remove
- every degree of these relations. But then I ask, if the removal of
- design be able entirely to remove the passion of love and hatred?
- Experience, I am sure, informs us of the contrary, nor is there any
- thing more certain, than that men often fall into a violent anger for
- injuries, which they themselves must own to be entirely involuntary and
- accidental. This emotion, indeed, cannot be of long continuance; but
- still is sufficient to shew, that there is a natural connexion betwixt
- uneasiness and anger, and that the relation of impressions will operate
- upon a very small relation of ideas. But when the violence of the
- impression is once a little abated, the defect of the relation begins to
- be better felt; and as the character of a person is no wise interested
- in such injuries as are casual and involuntary, it seldom happens that
- on their account, we entertain a lasting enmity.
- To illustrate this doctrine by a parallel instance, we may observe, that
- not only the uneasiness, which proceeds from another by accident, has
- but little force to excite our passion, but also that which arises
- from an acknowledged necessity and duty. One that has a real design of
- harming us, proceeding not from hatred and ill-will, but from justice
- and equity, draws not upon him our anger, if we be in any degree
- reasonable; notwithstanding he is both the cause, and the knowing cause
- of our sufferings. Let us examine a little this phaenomenon.
- It is evident in the first place, that this circumstance is not
- decisive; and though it may be able to diminish the passions, it is
- seldom it can entirely remove them. How few criminals are there, who
- have no ill-will to the person, that accuses them, or to the judge, that
- condemns them, even though they be conscious of their own deserts? In
- like manner our antagonist in a law-suit, and our competitor for
- any office, are commonly regarded as our enemies; though we must
- acknowledge, if we would but reflect a moment, that their motive is
- entirely as justifiable as our own.
- Besides we may consider, that when we receive harm from any person, we
- are apt to imagine him criminal, and it is with extreme difficulty
- we allow of his justice and innocence. This is a clear proof, that,
- independent of the opinion of iniquity, any harm or uneasiness has a
- natural tendency to excite our hatred, and that afterwards we seek for
- reasons upon which we may justify and establish the passion. Here the
- idea of injury produces not the passion, but arises from it.
- Nor is it any wonder that passion should produce the opinion of injury;
- since otherwise it must suffer a considerable diminution, which all the
- passions avoid as much as possible. The removal of injury may remove the
- anger, without proving that the anger arises only from the injury. The
- harm and the justice are two contrary objects, of which the one has a
- tendency to produce hatred, and the other love; and it is according
- to their different degrees, and our particular turn of thinking, that
- either of the objects prevails, and excites its proper passion.
- SECT. IV OF THE LOVE OF RELATIONS
- Having given a reason, why several actions, that cause a real pleasure
- or uneasiness, excite not any degree, or but a small one, of the passion
- of love or hatred towards the actors; it will be necessary to shew,
- wherein consists the pleasure or uneasiness of many objects, which we
- find by experience to produce these passions.
- According to the preceding system there is always required a double
- relation of impressions and ideas betwixt the cause and effect, in order
- to produce either love or hatred. But though this be universally true,
- it is remarkable that the passion of love may be excited by only one
- relation of a different kind, viz, betwixt ourselves and the object; or
- more properly speaking, that this relation is always attended with both
- the others. Whoever is united to us by any connexion is always sure of a
- share of our love, proportioned to the connexion, without enquiring into
- his other qualities. Thus the relation of blood produces the strongest
- tie the mind is capable of in the love of parents to their children, and
- a lesser degree of the same affection, as the relation lessens. Nor
- has consanguinity alone this effect, but any other relation without
- exception. We love our country-men, our neighbours, those of the same
- trade, profession, and even name with ourselves. Every one of these
- relations is esteemed some tie, and gives a title to a share of our
- affection.
- There is another phaenomenon, which is parallel to this, viz, that
- acquaintance, without any kind of relation, gives rise to love and
- kindness. When we have contracted a habitude and intimacy with any
- person; though in frequenting his company we have not been able to
- discover any very valuable quality, of which he is possessed; yet we
- cannot forebear preferring him to strangers, of whose superior merit we
- are fully convinced. These two phaenomena of the effects of relation
- and acquaintance will give mutual light to each other, and may be both
- explained from the same principle.
- Those, who take a pleasure in declaiming against human nature, have
- observed, that man is altogether insufficient to support himself; and
- that when you loosen all the holds, which he has of external objects,
- he immediately drops down into the deepest melancholy and despair.
- From this, say they, proceeds that continual search after amusement
- in gaming, in hunting, in business; by which we endeavour to forget
- ourselves, and excite our spirits from the languid state, into which
- they fall, when not sustained by some brisk and lively emotion. To
- this method of thinking I so far agree, that I own the mind to be
- insufficient, of itself, to its own entertainment, and that it naturally
- seeks after foreign objects, which may produce a lively sensation, and
- agitate the spirits. On the appearance of such an object it awakes, as
- it were, from a dream: The blood flows with a new tide: The heart is
- elevated: And the whole man acquires a vigour, which he cannot command
- in his solitary and calm moments. Hence company is naturally so
- rejoicing, as presenting the liveliest of all objects, viz, a rational
- and thinking Being like ourselves, who communicates to us all the
- actions of his mind; makes us privy to his inmost sentiments and
- affections; and lets us see, in the very instant of their production,
- all the emotions, which are caused by any object. Every lively idea
- is agreeable, but especially that of a passion, because such an idea
- becomes a kind of passion, and gives a more sensible agitation to the
- mind, than any other image or conception.
- This being once admitted, all the rest is easy. For as the company
- of strangers is agreeable to us for a short time, by inlivening our
- thought; so the company of our relations and acquaintance must be
- peculiarly agreeable, because it has this effect in a greater degree,
- and is of more durable influence. Whatever is related to us is conceived
- in a lively manner by the easy transition from ourselves to the related
- object. Custom also, or acquaintance facilitates the entrance, and
- strengthens the conception of any object. The first case is parallel to
- our reasonings from cause and effect; the second to education. And as
- reasoning and education concur only in producing a lively and strong
- idea of any object; so is this the only particular, which is common
- to relation and acquaintance. This must, therefore, be the influencing
- quality, by which they produce all their common effects; and love or
- kindness being one of these effects, it must be from the force and
- liveliness of conception, that the passion is derived. Such a conception
- is peculiarly agreeable, and makes us have an affectionate regard for
- every thing, that produces it, when the proper object of kindness and
- goodwill.
- It is obvious, that people associate together according to their
- particular tempers and dispositions, and that men of gay tempers
- naturally love the gay; as the serious bear an affection to the serious.
- This not only happens, where they remark this resemblance betwixt
- themselves and others, but also by the natural course of the
- disposition, and by a certain sympathy, which always arises betwixt
- similar characters. Where they remark the resemblance, it operates after
- the manner of a relation, by producing a connexion of ideas. Where
- they do not remark it, it operates by some other principle; and if this
- latter principle be similar to the former, it must be received as a
- confirmation of the foregoing reasoning.
- The idea of ourselves is always intimately present to us, and conveys a
- sensible degree of vivacity to the idea of any other object, to which we
- are related. This lively idea changes by degrees into a real impression;
- these two kinds of perception being in a great measure the same, and
- differing only in their degrees of force and vivacity. But this change
- must be produced with the greater ease, that our natural temper gives
- us a propensity to the same impression, which we observe in others,
- and makes it arise upon any slight occasion. In that case resemblance
- converts the idea into an impression, not only by means of the relation,
- and by transfusing the original vivacity into the related idea; but also
- by presenting such materials as take fire from the least spark. And as
- in both cases a love or affection arises from the resemblance, we may
- learn that a sympathy with others is agreeable only by giving an emotion
- to the spirits, since an easy sympathy and correspondent emotions are
- alone common to RELATION, ACQUAINTANCE, and RESEMBLANCE.
- The great propensity men have to pride may be considered as another
- similar phaenomenon. It often happens, that after we have lived a
- considerable time in any city; however at first it might be disagreeable
- to us; yet as we become familiar with the objects, and contact an
- acquaintance, though merely with the streets and buildings, the aversion
- diminishes by degrees, and at last changes into the opposite passion.
- The mind finds a satisfaction and ease in the view of objects, to which
- it is accustomed, and naturally prefers them to others, which, though,
- perhaps, in themselves more valuable, are less known to it. By the same
- quality of the mind we are seduced into a good opinion of ourselves, and
- of all objects, that belong to us. They appear in a stronger light; are
- more agreeable; and consequently fitter subjects of pride and vanity,
- than any other.
- It may not be amiss, in treating of the affection we bear our
- acquaintance and relations, to observe some pretty curious phaenomena,
- which attend it. It is easy to remark in common life, that children
- esteem their relation to their mother to be weakened, in a great
- measure, by her second marriage, and no longer regard her with the same
- eye, as if she had continued in her state of widow-hood. Nor does this
- happen only, when they have felt any inconveniences from her second
- marriage, or when her husband is much her inferior; but even without
- any of these considerations, and merely because she has become part of
- another family. This also takes place with regard to the second marriage
- of a father; but in a much less degree: And it is certain the ties of
- blood are not so much loosened in the latter case as by the marriage of
- a mother. These two phaenomena are remarkable in themselves, but much
- more so when compared.
- In order to produce a perfect relation betwixt two objects, it is
- requisite, not only that the imagination be conveyed from one to the
- other by resemblance, contiguity or causation, but also that it return
- back from the second to the first with the same ease and facility. At
- first sight this may seem a necessary and unavoidable consequence. If
- one object resemble another, the latter object must necessarily resemble
- the former. If one object be the cause of another, the second object is
- effect to its cause. It is the same case with contiguity: And therefore
- the relation being always reciprocal, it may be thought, that the return
- of the imagination from the second to the first must also, in every
- case, be equally natural as its passage from the first to the second.
- But upon farther examination we shall easily discover our mistake.
- For supposing the second object, beside its reciprocal relation to the
- first, to have also a strong relation to a third object; in that case
- the thought, passing from the first object to the second, returns not
- back with the same facility, though the relation continues the same; but
- is readily carryed on to the third object, by means of the new relation,
- which presents itself, and gives a new impulse to the imagination. This
- new relation, therefore, weakens the tie betwixt the first and second
- objects. The fancy is by its very nature wavering and inconstant; and
- considers always two objects as more strongly related together, where it
- finds the passage equally easy both in going and returning, than where
- the transition is easy only in one of these motions. The double motion
- is a kind of a double tie, and binds the objects together in the closest
- and most intimate manner.
- The second marriage of a mother breaks not the relation of child and
- parent; and that relation suffices to convey my imagination from myself
- to her with the greatest ease and facility. But after the imagination is
- arrived at this point of view, it finds its object to be surrounded with
- so many other relations, which challenge its regard, that it knows not
- which to prefer, and is at a loss what new object to pitch upon. The
- ties of interest and duty bind her to another family, and prevent that
- return of the fancy from her to myself, which is necessary to support
- the union. The thought has no longer the vibration, requisite to set it
- perfectly at ease, and indulge its inclination to change. It goes with
- facility, but returns with difficulty; and by that interruption finds
- the relation much weakened from what it would be were the passage open
- and easy on both sides.
- Now to give a reason, why this effect follows not in the same degree
- upon the second marriage of a father: we may reflect on what has been
- proved already, that though the imagination goes easily from the view of
- a lesser object to that of a greater, yet it returns not with the same
- facility from the greater to the less. When my imagination goes from
- myself to my father, it passes not so readily from him to his second
- wife, nor considers him as entering into a different family, but as
- continuing the head of that family, of which I am myself a part. His
- superiority prevents the easy transition of the thought from him to his
- spouse, but keeps the passage still open for a return to myself along
- the same relation of child and parent. He is not sunk in the new
- relation he acquires; so that the double motion or vibration of thought
- is still easy and natural. By this indulgence of the fancy in its
- inconstancy, the tie of child and parent still preserves its full force
- and influence. A mother thinks not her tie to a son weakened, because it
- is shared with her husband: Nor a son his with a parent, because it is
- shared with a brother. The third object is here related to the first, as
- well as to the second; so that the imagination goes and comes along all
- of them with the greatest facility.
- SECT. V OF OUR ESTEEM FOR THE RICH AND POWERFUL
- Nothing has a greater tendency to give us an esteem for any person, than
- his power and riches; or a contempt, than his poverty and meanness:
- And as esteem and contempt are to be considered as species of love and
- hatred, it will be proper in this place to explain these phaenomena.
- Here it happens most fortunately, that the greatest difficulty is not to
- discover a principle capable of producing such an effect, but to choose
- the chief and predominant among several, that present themselves. The
- satisfaction we take in the riches of others, and the esteem we have for
- the possessors may be ascribed to three different causes. FIRST, To the
- objects they possess; such as houses, gardens, equipages; which, being
- agreeable in themselves, necessarily produce a sentiment of pleasure
- in every one; that either considers or surveys them. SECONDLY, To the
- expectation of advantage from the rich and powerful by our sharing
- their possessions. THIRDLY, To sympathy, which makes us partake of the
- satisfaction of every one, that approaches us. All these principles may
- concur in producing the present phaenomenon. The question is, to which
- of them we ought principally to ascribe it.
- It is certain, that the first principle, viz, the reflection on
- agreeable objects, has a greater influence, than what, at first sight,
- we may be apt to imagine. We seldom reflect on what is beautiful or
- ugly, agreeable or disagreeable, without an emotion of pleasure or
- uneasiness; and though these sensations appear not much in our common
- indolent way of thinking, it is easy, either in reading or conversation,
- to discover them. Men of wit always turn the discourse on subjects that
- are entertaining to the imagination; and poets never present any objects
- but such as are of the same nature. Mr Philips has chosen CYDER for the
- subject of an excellent poem. Beer would not have been so proper, as
- being neither so agreeable to the taste nor eye. But he would certainly
- have preferred wine to either of them, coued his native country have
- afforded him so agreeable a liquor. We may learn from thence, that
- every thing, which is agreeable to the senses, is also in some measure
- agreeable to the fancy, and conveys to the thought an image of that
- satisfaction, which it gives by its real application to the bodily
- organs.
- But though these reasons may induce us to comprehend this delicacy of
- the imagination among the causes of the respect, which we pay the
- rich and powerful, there are many other reasons, that may keep us from
- regarding it as the sole or principal. For as the ideas of pleasure
- can have an influence only by means of their vivacity, which makes them
- approach impressions, it is most natural those ideas should have that
- influence, which are favoured by most circumstances, and have a natural
- tendency to become strong and lively; such as our ideas of the passions
- and sensations of any human creature. Every human creature resembles
- ourselves, and by that means has an advantage above any other object, in
- operating on the imagination.
- Besides, if we consider the nature of that faculty, and the great
- influence which all relations have upon it, we shall easily be
- persuaded, that however the ideas of the pleasant wines, music, or
- gardens, which the rich man enjoys, may become lively and agreeable, the
- fancy will not confine itself to them, but will carry its view to the
- related objects; and in particular, to the person, who possesses them.
- And this is the more natural, that the pleasant idea or image produces
- here a passion towards the person, by means of his relation to the
- object; so that it is unavoidable but he must enter into the original
- conception, since he makes the object of the derivative passion: But if
- he enters into the original conception, and is considered as enjoying
- these agreeable objects, it is sympathy, which is properly the cause of
- the affection; and the third principle is more powerful and universal
- than the first.
- Add to this, that riches and power alone, even though unemployed,
- naturally cause esteem and respect: And consequently these passions
- arise not from the idea of any beautiful or agreeable objects. It is
- true; money implies a kind of representation of such objects, by the
- power it affords of obtaining them; and for that reason may still be
- esteemed proper to convey those agreeable images, which may give rise
- to the passion. But as this prospect is very distant, it is more natural
- for us to take a contiguous object, viz, the satisfaction, which this
- power affords the person, who is possest of it. And of this we shall be
- farther satisfyed, if we consider, that riches represent the goods of
- life, only by means of the will; which employs them; and therefore imply
- in their very nature an idea of the person, and cannot be considered
- without a kind of sympathy with his sensations and enjoyments.
- This we may confirm by a reflection, which to some will, perhaps,
- appear too subtile and refined. I have already observed, that power,
- as distinguished from its exercise, has either no meaning at all, or
- is nothing but a possibility or probability of existence; by which any
- object approaches to reality, and has a sensible influence on the mind.
- I have also observed, that this approach, by an illusion of the fancy,
- appears much greater, when we ourselves are possest of the power, than
- when it is enjoyed by another; and that in the former case the objects
- seem to touch upon the very verge of reality, and convey almost an equal
- satisfaction, as if actually in our possession. Now I assert, that where
- we esteem a person upon account of his riches, we must enter into this
- sentiment of the proprietor, and that without such a sympathy the idea
- of the agreeable objects, which they give him the power to produce,
- would have but a feeble influence upon us. An avaritious man is
- respected for his money, though he scarce is possest of a power; that
- is, there scarce is a probability or even possibility of his employing
- it in the acquisition of the pleasures and conveniences of life. To
- himself alone this power seems perfect and entire; and therefore we must
- receive his sentiments by sympathy, before we can have a strong intense
- idea of these enjoyments, or esteem him upon account of them.
- Thus we have found, that the first principle, viz, the agreeable idea of
- those objects, which riches afford the enjoyment of; resolves itself in
- a great measure into the third, and becomes a sympathy with the person
- we esteem or love. Let us now examine the second principle, viz, the
- agreeable expectation of advantage, and see what force we may justly
- attribute to it.
- It is obvious, that though riches and authority undoubtedly give
- their owner a power of doing us service, yet this power is not to be
- considered as on the same footing with that, which they afford him, of
- pleasing himself, and satisfying his own appetites. Self-love approaches
- the power and exercise very near each other in the latter case; but
- in order to produce a similar effect in the former, we must suppose a
- friendship and good-will to be conjoined with the riches. Without that
- circumstance it is difficult to conceive on what we can found our hope
- of advantage from the riches of others, though there is nothing more
- certain, than that we naturally esteem and respect the rich, even before
- we discover in them any such favourable disposition towards us.
- But I carry this farther, and observe, not only that we respect the rich
- and powerful, where they shew no inclination to serve us, but also when
- we lie so much out of the sphere of their activity, that they cannot
- even be supposed to be endowed with that power. Prisoners of war are
- always treated with a respect suitable to their condition; and it is
- certain riches go very far towards fixing the condition of any person.
- If birth and quality enter for a share, this still affords us an
- argument of the same kind. For what is it we call a man of birth,
- but one who is descended from a long succession of rich and powerful
- ancestors, and who acquires our esteem by his relation to persons whom
- we esteem? His ancestors, therefore, though dead, are respected, in some
- measure, on account of their riches, and consequently without any kind
- of expectation.
- But not to go so far as prisoners of war and the dead to find instances
- of this disinterested esteem for riches, let us observe with a
- little attention those phaenomena that occur to us in common life and
- conversation. A man, who is himself of a competent fortune, upon coming
- into a company of strangers, naturally treats them with different
- degrees of respect and deference, as he is informed of their different
- fortunes and conditions; though it is impossible he can ever propose,
- and perhaps would not accept of any advantage from them. A traveller is
- always admitted into company, and meets with civility, in proportion as
- his train and equipage speak him a man of great or moderate fortune. In
- short, the different ranks of men are, in a great measure, regulated
- by riches, and that with regard to superiors as well as inferiors,
- strangers as well as acquaintance.
- There is, indeed, an answer to these arguments, drawn from the influence
- of general rules. It may be pretended, that being accustomed to expect
- succour and protection from the rich and powerful, and to esteem them
- upon that account, we extend the same sentiments to those, who
- resemble them in their fortune, but from whom we can never hope for any
- advantage. The general rule still prevails, and by giving a bent to the
- imagination draws along the passion, in the same manner as if its proper
- object were real and existent.
- But that this principle does not here take place, will easily appear,
- if we consider, that in order to establish a general rule, and extend it
- beyond its proper bounds, there is required a certain uniformity in
- our experience, and a great superiority of those instances, which are
- conformable to the rule, above the contrary. But here the case is quite
- otherwise. Of a hundred men of credit and fortune I meet with, there
- is not, perhaps, one from whom I can expect advantage; so that it is
- impossible any custom can ever prevail in the present case.
- Upon the whole, there remains nothing, which can give us an esteem for
- power and riches, and a contempt for meanness and poverty, except the
- principle of sympathy, by which we enter into the sentiments of the
- rich and poor, and partake of their pleasure and uneasiness. Riches give
- satisfaction to their possessor; and this satisfaction is conveyed to
- the beholder by the imagination, which produces an idea resembling
- the original impression in force and vivacity. This agreeable idea or
- impression is connected with love, which is an agreeable passion. It
- proceeds from a thinking conscious being, which is the very object of
- love. From this relation of impressions, and identity of ideas, the
- passion arises, according to my hypothesis.
- The best method of reconciling us to this opinion is to take a general
- survey of the universe, and observe the force of sympathy through the
- whole animal creation, and the easy communication of sentiments from one
- thinking being to another. In all creatures, that prey not upon others,
- and are not agitated with violent passions, there appears a remarkable
- desire of company, which associates them together, without any
- advantages they can ever propose to reap from their union. This is still
- more conspicuous in man, as being the creature of the universe, who
- has the most ardent desire of society, and is fitted for it by the most
- advantages. We can form no wish, which has not a reference to society.
- A perfect solitude is, perhaps, the greatest punishment we can suffer.
- Every pleasure languishes when enjoyed a-part from company, and every
- pain becomes more cruel and intolerable. Whatever other passions we may
- be actuated by; pride, ambition, avarice, curiosity, revenge or lust;
- the soul or animating principle of them all is sympathy; nor would
- they have any force, were we to abstract entirely from the thoughts and
- sentiments of others. Let all the powers and elements of nature conspire
- to serve and obey one man: Let the sun rise and set at his command: The
- sea and rivers roll as he pleases, and the earth furnish spontaneously
- whatever may be useful or agreeable to him: He will still be miserable,
- till you give him some one person at least, with whom he may share his
- happiness, and whose esteem and friendship he may enjoy.
- This conclusion from a general view of human nature, we may confirm by
- particular instances, wherein the force of sympathy is very remarkable.
- Most kinds of beauty are derived from this origin; and though our first
- object be some senseless inanimate piece of matter, it is seldom we rest
- there, and carry not our view to its influence on sensible and rational
- creatures. A man, who shews us any house or building, takes particular
- care among other things to point out the convenience of the apartments,
- the advantages of their situation, and the little room lost in the
- stairs, antichambers and passages; and indeed it is evident, the chief
- part of the beauty consists in these particulars. The observation of
- convenience gives pleasure, since convenience is a beauty. But after
- what manner does it give pleasure? It is certain our own interest is
- not in the least concerned; and as this is a beauty of interest, not of
- form, so to speak, it must delight us merely by communication, and by
- our sympathizing with the proprietor of the lodging. We enter into his
- interest by the force of imagination, and feel the same satisfaction,
- that the objects naturally occasion in him.
- This observation extends to tables, chairs, scritoires, chimneys,
- coaches, sadles, ploughs, and indeed to every work of art; it being an
- universal rule, that their beauty is chiefly derived from their utility,
- and from their fitness for that purpose, to which they are destined.
- But this is an advantage, that concerns only the owner, nor is there any
- thing but sympathy, which can interest the spectator.
- It is evident, that nothing renders a field more agreeable than its
- fertility, and that scarce any advantages of ornament or situation will
- be able to equal this beauty. It is the same case with particular trees
- and plants, as with the field on which they grow. I know not but a
- plain, overgrown with furze and broom, may be, in itself, as beautiful
- as a hill covered with vines or olive-trees; though it will never appear
- so to one, who is acquainted with the value of each. But this is a
- beauty merely of imagination, and has no foundation in what appears to
- the senses. Fertility and value have a plain reference to use; and
- that to riches, joy, and plenty; in which though we have no hope of
- partaking, yet we enter into them by the vivacity of the fancy, and
- share them, in some measure, with the proprietor.
- There is no rule in painting more reasonable than that of ballancing the
- figures, and placing them with the greatest exactness on their proper
- centers of gravity. A figure, which is not justly ballanced, is
- disagreeable; and that because it conveys the ideas of its fall, of
- harm, and of pain: Which ideas are painful, when by sympathy they
- acquire any degree of force and vivacity.
- Add to this, that the principal part of personal beauty is an air
- of health and vigour, and such a construction of members as promises
- strength and activity. This idea of beauty cannot be accounted for but
- by sympathy.
- In general we may remark, that the minds of men are mirrors to one
- another, not only because they reflect each others emotions, but also
- because those rays of passions, sentiments and opinions may be often
- reverberated, and may decay away by insensible degrees. Thus the
- pleasure, which a rich man receives from his possessions, being thrown
- upon the beholder, causes a pleasure and esteem; which sentiments again,
- being perceived and sympathized with, encrease the pleasure of the
- possessor; and being once more reflected, become a new foundation for
- pleasure and esteem in the beholder. There is certainly an original
- satisfaction in riches derived from that power, which they bestow, of
- enjoying all the pleasures of life; and as this is their very nature and
- essence, it must be the first source of all the passions, which arise
- from them. One of the most considerable of these passions is that of
- love or esteem in others, which therefore proceeds from a sympathy with
- the pleasure of the possessor. But the possessor has also a secondary
- satisfaction in riches arising from the love and esteem he acquires by
- them, and this satisfaction is nothing but a second reflexion of
- that original pleasure, which proceeded from himself. This secondary
- satisfaction or vanity becomes one of the principal recommendations
- of riches, and is the chief reason, why we either desire them for
- ourselves, or esteem them in others. Here then is a third rebound of the
- original pleasure; after which it is difficult to distinguish the images
- and reflexions, by reason of their faintness and confusion.
- SECT. VI OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER
- Ideas may be compared to the extension and solidity of matter, and
- impressions, especially reflective ones, to colours, tastes, smells and
- other sensible qualities. Ideas never admit of a total union, but are
- endowed with a kind of impenetrability, by which they exclude each
- other, and are capable of forming a compound by their conjunction,
- not by their mixture. On the other hand, impressions and passions are
- susceptible of an entire union; and like colours, may be blended so
- perfectly together, that each of them may lose itself, and contribute
- only to vary that uniform impression, which arises from the whole. Some
- of the most curious phaenomena of the human mind are derived from this
- property of the passions.
- In examining those ingredients, which are capable of uniting with love
- and hatred, I begin to be sensible, in some measure, of a misfortune,
- that has attended every system of philosophy, with which the world has
- been yet acquainted. It is commonly found, that in accounting for the
- operations of nature by any particular hypothesis; among a number
- of experiments, that quadrate exactly with the principles we would
- endeavour to establish; there is always some phaenomenon, which is more
- stubborn, and will not so easily bend to our purpose. We need not be
- surprized, that this should happen in natural philosophy. The essence
- and composition of external bodies are so obscure, that we must
- necessarily, in our reasonings, or rather conjectures concerning
- them, involve ourselves in contradictions and absurdities. But as
- the perceptions of the mind are perfectly known, and I have used all
- imaginable caution in forming conclusions concerning them, I have always
- hoped to keep clear of those contradictions, which have attended every
- other system. Accordingly the difficulty, which I have at present in
- my eye, is nowise contrary to my system; but only departs a little from
- that simplicity, which has been hitherto its principal force and beauty.
- The passions of love and hatred are always followed by, or rather
- conjoined with benevolence and anger. It is this conjunction, which
- chiefly distinguishes these affections from pride and humility. For
- pride and humility are pure emotions in the soul, unattended with any
- desire, and not immediately exciting us to action. But love and hatred
- are not compleated within themselves, nor rest in that emotion, which
- they produce, but carry the mind to something farther. Love is always
- followed by a desire of the happiness of the person beloved, and an
- aversion to his misery: As hatred produces a desire of the misery and
- an aversion to the happiness of the person hated. So remarkable a
- difference betwixt these two sets of passions of pride and humility,
- love and hatred, which in so many other particulars correspond to each
- other, merits our attention.
- The conjunction of this desire and aversion with love and hatred may be
- accounted for by two different hypotheses. The first is, that love and
- hatred have not only a cause, which excites them, viz, pleasure and
- pain; and an object, to which they are directed, viz, a person or
- thinking being; but likewise an end, which they endeavour to attain,
- viz, the happiness or misery of the person beloved or hated; all which
- views, mixing together, make only one passion. According to this system,
- love is nothing but the desire of happiness to another person, and
- hatred that of misery. The desire and aversion constitute the very
- nature of love and hatred. They are not only inseparable but the same.
- But this is evidently contrary to experience. For though it is certain
- we never love any person without desiring his happiness, nor hate any
- without wishing his misery, yet these desires arise only upon the ideas
- of the happiness or misery of our friend or enemy being presented by the
- imagination, and are not absolutely essential to love and hatred. They
- are the most obvious and natural sentiments of these affections, but not
- the only ones. The passions may express themselves in a hundred ways,
- and may subsist a considerable time, without our reflecting on the
- happiness or misery of their objects; which clearly proves, that these
- desires are not the same with love and hatred, nor make any essential
- part of them.
- We may, therefore, infer, that benevolence and anger are passions
- different from love and hatred, and only conjoined with them, by the
- original constitution of the mind. As nature has given to the body
- certain appetites and inclinations, which she encreases, diminishes,
- or changes according to the situation of the fluids or solids; she
- has proceeded in the same manner with the mind. According as we are
- possessed with love or hatred, the correspondent desire of the happiness
- or misery of the person, who is the object of these passions, arises
- in the mind, and varies with each variation of these opposite passions.
- This order of things, abstractedly considered, is not necessary. Love
- and hatred might have been unattended with any such desires, or their
- particular connexion might have been entirely reversed. If nature had
- so pleased, love might have had the same effect as hatred, and hatred as
- love. I see no contradiction in supposing a desire of producing misery
- annexed to love, and of happiness to hatred. If the sensation of the
- passion and desire be opposite, nature coued have altered the sensation
- without altering the tendency of the desire, and by that means made them
- compatible with each other.
- SECT. VII OF COMPASSION
- But though the desire of the happiness or misery of others, according to
- the love or hatred we bear them, be an arbitrary and original instinct
- implanted in our nature, we find it may be counterfeited on many
- occasions, and may arise from secondary principles. Pity is a concern
- for, and malice a joy in the misery of others, without any friendship or
- enmity to occasion this concern or joy. We pity even strangers, and
- such as are perfectly indifferent to us: And if our ill-will to another
- proceed from any harm or injury, it is not, properly speaking, malice,
- but revenge. But if we examine these affections of pity and malice we
- shall find them to be secondary ones, arising from original affections,
- which are varied by some particular turn of thought and imagination.
- It will be easy to explain the passion of pity, from the precedent
- reasoning concerning sympathy. We have a lively idea of every thing
- related to us. All human creatures are related to us by resemblance.
- Their persons, therefore, their interests, their passions, their pains
- and pleasures must strike upon us in a lively manner, and produce an
- emotion similar to the original one; since a lively idea is easily
- converted into an impression. If this be true in general, it must be
- more so of affliction and sorrow. These have always a stronger and more
- lasting influence than any pleasure or enjoyment.
- A spectator of a tragedy passes through a long train of grief, terror,
- indignation, and other affections, which the poet represents in the
- persons he introduces. As many tragedies end happily, and no excellent
- one can be composed without some reverses of fortune, the spectator must
- sympathize with all these changes, and receive the fictitious joy as
- well as every other passion. Unless, therefore, it be asserted, that
- every distinct passion is communicated by a distinct original
- quality, and is not derived from the general principle of sympathy
- above-explained, it must be allowed, that all of them arise from
- that principle. To except any one in particular must appear highly
- unreasonable. As they are all first present in the mind of one person,
- and afterwards appear in the mind of another; and as the manner of their
- appearance, first as an idea, then as an impression, is in every case
- the same, the transition must arise from the same principle. I am
- at least sure, that this method of reasoning would be considered as
- certain, either in natural philosophy or common life.
- Add to this, that pity depends, in a great measure, on the contiguity,
- and even sight of the object; which is a proof, that it is derived from
- the imagination. Not to mention that women and children are most subject
- to pity, as being most guided by that faculty. The same infirmity, which
- makes them faint at the sight of a naked sword, though in the hands of
- their best friend, makes them pity extremely those, whom they find in
- any grief or affliction. Those philosophers, who derive this passion
- from I know not what subtile reflections on the instability of fortune,
- and our being liable to the same miseries we behold, will find this
- observation contrary to them among a great many others, which it were
- easy to produce.
- There remains only to take notice of a pretty remarkable phaenomenon
- of this passion; which is, that the communicated passion of sympathy
- sometimes acquires strength from the weakness of its original, and even
- arises by a transition from affections, which have no existence.
- Thus when a person obtains any honourable office, or inherits a great
- fortune, we are always the more rejoiced for his prosperity, the
- less sense he seems to have of it, and the greater equanimity and
- indifference he shews in its enjoyment. In like manner a man, who is
- not dejected by misfortunes, is the more lamented on account of his
- patience; and if that virtue extends so far as utterly to remove all
- sense of uneasiness, it still farther encreases our compassion. When a
- person of merit falls into what is vulgarly esteemed a great misfortune,
- we form a notion of his condition; and carrying our fancy from the cause
- to the usual effect, first conceive a lively idea of his sorrow, and
- then feel an impression of it, entirely over-looking that greatness of
- mind, which elevates him above such emotions, or only considering it so
- far as to encrease our admiration, love and tenderness for him. We find
- from experience, that such a degree of passion is usually connected with
- such a misfortune; and though there be an exception in the present
- case, yet the imagination is affected by the general rule, and makes
- us conceive a lively idea of the passion, or rather feel the passion
- itself, in the same manner, as if the person were really actuated by it.
- From the same principles we blush for the conduct of those, who behave
- themselves foolishly before us; and that though they shew no sense of
- shame, nor seem in the least conscious of their folly. All this proceeds
- from sympathy; but it is of a partial kind, and views its objects only
- on one side, without considering the other, which has a contrary effect,
- and would entirely destroy that emotion, which arises from the first
- appearance.
- We have also instances, wherein an indifference and insensibility under
- misfortune encreases our concern for the misfortunate, even though
- the indifference proceed not from any virtue and magnanimity. It is an
- aggravation of a murder, that it was committed upon persons asleep and
- in perfect security; as historians readily observe of any infant prince,
- who is captive in the hands of his enemies, that he is the more worthy
- of compassion the less sensible he is of his miserable condition. As we
- ourselves are here acquainted with the wretched situation of the person,
- it gives us a lively idea and sensation of sorrow, which is the passion
- that generally attends it; and this idea becomes still more lively,
- and the sensation more violent by a contrast with that security and
- indifference, which we observe in the person himself. A contrast of any
- kind never fails to affect the imagination, especially when presented by
- the subject; and it is on the imagination that pity entirely depends.
- [Footnote 11. To prevent all ambiguity, I must observe,
- that where I oppose the imagination to the memory, I mean in
- general the faculty that presents our fainter ideas. In all
- other places, and particularly when it is opposed to the
- understanding, I understand the same faculty, excluding only
- our demonstrative and probable reasonings.]
- SECT. VIII OF MALICE AND ENVY
- We must now proceed to account for the passion of malice, which imitates
- the effects of hatred, as pity does those of love; and gives us a joy in
- the sufferings and miseries of others, without any offence or injury on
- their part.
- So little are men governed by reason in their sentiments and opinions,
- that they always judge more of objects by comparison than from their
- intrinsic worth and value. When the mind considers, or is accustomed
- to, any degree of perfection, whatever falls short of it, though really
- esteemable, has notwithstanding the same effect upon the passions; as
- what is defective and ill. This is an original quality of the soul, and
- similar to what we have every day experience of in our bodies. Let a man
- heat one hand and cool the other; the same water will, at the same time,
- seem both hot and cold, according to the disposition of the different
- organs. A small degree of any quality, succeeding a greater, produces
- the same sensation, as if less than it really is, and even sometimes as
- the opposite quality. Any gentle pain, that follows a violent one, seems
- as nothing, or rather becomes a pleasure; as on the other hand a violent
- pain, succeeding a gentle one, is doubly grievous and uneasy.
- This no one can doubt of with regard to our passions and sensations. But
- there may arise some difficulty with regard to our ideas and objects.
- When an object augments or diminishes to the eye or imagination from a
- comparison with others, the image and idea of the object are still the
- same, and are equally extended in the retina, and in the brain or organ
- of perception. The eyes refract the rays of light, and the optic nerves
- convey the images to the brain in the very same manner, whether a great
- or small object has preceded; nor does even the imagination alter the
- dimensions of its object on account of a comparison with others. The
- question then is, how from the same impression and the same idea we can
- form such different judgments concerning the same object, and at one
- time admire its bulk, and at another despise its littleness. This
- variation in our judgments must certainly proceed from a variation
- in some perception; but as the variation lies not in the immediate
- impression or idea of the object, it must lie in some other impression,
- that accompanies it.
- In order to explain this matter, I shall just touch upon two principles,
- one of which shall be more fully explained in the progress of this
- treatise; the other has been already accounted for. I believe it may
- safely be established for a general maxim, that no object is presented
- to the senses, nor image formed in the fancy, but what is accompanyed
- with some emotion or movement of spirits proportioned to it; and however
- custom may make us insensible of this sensation and cause us to confound
- it with the object or idea, it will be easy, by careful and exact
- experiments, to separate and distinguish them. For to instance only in
- the cases of extension and number; it is evident, that any very bulky
- object, such as the ocean, an extended plain, a vast chain of mountains,
- a wide forest: or any very numerous collection of objects, such as an
- army, a fleet, a crowd, excite in the mind a sensible emotion; and that
- the admiration, which arises on the appearance of such objects, is one
- of the most lively pleasures, which human nature is capable of enjoying.
- Now as this admiration encreases or diminishes by the encrease or
- diminution of the objects, we may conclude, according to our foregoing
- [Book I. Part III. Sect. 15.] principles, that it is a compound effect,
- proceeding from the conjunction of the several effects, which arise from
- each part of the cause. Every part, then, of extension, and every unite
- of number has a separate emotion attending it; and though that emotion
- be not always agreeable, yet by its conjunction with others, and by its
- agitating the spirits to a just pitch, it contributes to the production
- of admiration, which is always agreeable. If this be allowed with
- respect to extension and number, we can make no difficulty with respect
- to virtue and vice, wit and folly, riches and poverty, happiness and
- misery, and other objects of that kind, which are always attended with
- an evident emotion.
- The second principle I shall take notice of is that of our adherence
- to general rules; which has such a mighty influence on the actions and
- understanding, and is able to impose on the very senses. When an object
- is found by-experience to be always accompanyed with another; whenever
- the first object appears, though changed in very material circumstances;
- we naturally fly to the conception of the second, and form an idea of it
- in as lively and strong a manner, as if we had infered its existence by
- the justest and most authentic conclusion of our understanding. Nothing
- can undeceive us, not even our senses, which, instead of correcting this
- false judgment, are often perverted by it, and seem to authorize its
- errors.
- The conclusion I draw from these two principles, joined to the influence
- of comparison above-mentioned, is very short and decisive. Every object
- is attended with some emotion proportioned to it; a great object with
- a great emotion, a small object with a small emotion. A great object,
- therefore, succeeding a small one makes a great emotion succeed a small
- one. Now a great emotion succeeding a small one becomes still greater,
- and rises beyond its ordinary proportion. But as there is a certain
- degree of an emotion, which commonly attends every magnitude of an
- object; when the emotion encreases, we naturally imagine that the object
- has likewise encreased. The effect conveys our view to its usual cause,
- a certain degree of emotion to a certain magnitude of the object; nor
- do we consider, that comparison may change the emotion without changing
- anything in the object. Those who are acquainted with the metaphysical
- part of optics and know how we transfer the judgments and conclusions
- of the understanding to the senses, will easily conceive this whole
- operation.
- But leaving this new discovery of an impression, that secretly attends
- every idea; we must at least allow of that principle, from whence the
- discovery arose, that objects appear greater or less by a comparison
- with others. We have so many instances of this, that it is impossible
- we can dispute its veracity; and it is from this principle I derive the
- passions of malice and envy.
- It is evident we must receive a greater or less satisfaction or
- uneasiness from reflecting on our own condition and circumstances,
- in proportion as they appear more or less fortunate or unhappy,
- in proportion to the degrees of riches, and power, and merit, and
- reputation, which we think ourselves possest of. Now as we seldom judge
- of objects from their intrinsic value, but form our notions of them
- from a comparison with other objects; it follows, that according as we
- observe a greater or less share of happiness or misery in others,
- we must make an estimate of our own, and feel a consequent pain or
- pleasure. The misery of another gives us a more lively idea of our
- happiness, and his happiness of our misery. The former, therefore,
- produces delight; and the latter uneasiness.
- Here then is a kind of pity reverst, or contrary sensations arising
- in the beholder, from those which are felt by the person, whom he
- considers. In general we may observe, that in all kinds of comparison an
- object makes us always receive from another, to which it is compared,
- a sensation contrary to what arises from itself in its direct and
- immediate survey. A small object makes a great one appear still greater.
- A great object makes a little one appear less. Deformity of itself
- produces uneasiness; but makes us receive new pleasure by its contrast
- with a beautiful object, whose beauty is augmented by it; as on the
- other hand, beauty, which of itself produces pleasure, makes us receive
- a new pain by the contrast with any thing ugly, whose deformity it
- augments. The case, therefore, must be the same with happiness and
- misery. The direct survey of another's pleasure naturally gives us
- plcasure, and therefore produces pain when compared with our own. His
- pain, considered in itself, is painful to us, but augments the idea of
- our own happiness, and gives us pleasure.
- Nor will it appear strange, that we may feel a reverst sensation from
- the happiness and misery of others; since we find the same comparison
- may give us a kind of malice against ourselves, and make us rejoice for
- our pains, and grieve for our pleasures. Thus the prospect of past pain
- is agreeable, when we are satisfyed with our present condition; as on
- the other hand our past pleasures give us uneasiness, when we enjoy
- nothing at present equal to them. The comparison being the same, as when
- we reflect on the sentiments of others, must be attended with the same
- effects.
- Nay a person may extend this malice against himself, even to his present
- fortune, and carry it so far as designedly to seek affliction, and
- encrease his pains and sorrows. This may happen upon two occasions.
- First, Upon the distress and misfortune of a friend, or person dear to
- him. Secondly, Upon the feeling any remorses for a crime, of which he
- has been guilty. It is from the principle of comparison that both these
- irregular appetites for evil arise. A person, who indulges himself
- in any pleasure, while his friend lies under affliction, feels the
- reflected uneasiness from his friend more sensibly by a comparison with
- the original pleasure, which he himself enjoys. This contrast, indeed,
- ought also to inliven the present pleasure. But as grief is here
- supposed to be the predominant passion, every addition falls to that
- side, and is swallowed up in it, without operating in the least upon the
- contrary affection. It is the same case with those penances, which men
- inflict on themselves for their past sins and failings. When a criminal
- reflects on the punishment he deserves, the idea of it is magnifyed by a
- comparison with his present ease and satisfaction; which forces him,
- in a manner, to seek uneasiness, in order to avoid so disagreeable a
- contrast.
- This reasoning will account for the origin of envy as well as of malice.
- The only difference betwixt these passions lies in this, that envy
- is excited by some present enjoyment of another, which by comparison
- diminishes our idea of our own: Whereas malice is the unprovoked desire
- of producing evil to another, in order to reap a pleasure from the
- comparison. The enjoyment, which is the object of envy, is commonly
- superior to our own. A superiority naturally seems to overshade us,
- and presents a disagreeable comparison. But even in the case of an
- inferiority, we still desire a greater distance, in order to augment,
- still more the idea of ourself. When this distance diminishes, the
- comparison is less to our advantage; and consequently gives us less
- pleasure, and is even disagreeable. Hence arises that species of envy,
- which men feel, when they perceive their inferiors approaching or
- overtaking them in the pursuits of glory or happiness. In this envy we
- may see the effects of comparison twice repeated. A man, who compares
- himself to his inferior, receives a pleasure from the comparison: And
- when the inferiority decreases by the elevation of the inferior, what
- should only have been a decrease of pleasure, becomes a real pain, by a
- new comparison with its preceding condition.
- It is worthy of observation concerning that envy, which arises from a
- superiority in others, that it is not the great disproportion betwixt
- ourself and another, which produces it; but on the contrary, our
- proximity. A common soldier bears no such envy to his general as to
- his sergeant or corporal; nor does an eminent writer meet with so great
- jealousy in common hackney scriblers, as in authors, that more
- nearly approach him. It may, indeed, be thought, that the greater
- the disproportion is, the greater must be the uneasiness from the
- comparison. But we may consider on the other hand, that the great
- disproportion cuts off the relation, and either keeps us from comparing
- ourselves with what is remote from us, or diminishes the effects of
- the comparison. Resemblance and proximity always produce a relation of
- ideas; and where you destroy these ties, however other accidents may
- bring two ideas together; as they have no bond or connecting quality
- to join them in the imagination; it is impossible they can remain long
- united, or have any considerable influence on each other.
- I have observed in considering the nature of ambition, that the great
- feel a double pleasure in authority from the comparison of their own
- condition with that of their slaves; and that this comparison has a
- double influence, because it is natural, and presented by the subject.
- When the fancy, in the comparison of objects, passes not easily from the
- one object to the other, the action of the mind is, in a great measure,
- broke, and the fancy, in considering the second object, begins, as it
- were, upon a new footing. The impression, which attends every object,
- seems not greater in that case by succeeding a less of the same kind;
- but these two impressions are distinct, and produce their distinct
- effects, without any communication together. The want of relation in the
- ideas breaks the relation of the impressions, and by such a separation
- prevents their mutual operation and influence.
- To confirm this we may observe, that the proximity in the degree of
- merit is not alone sufficient to give rise to envy, but must be assisted
- by other relations. A poet is not apt to envy a philosopher, or a poet
- of a different kind, of a different nation, or of a different age. All
- these differences prevent or weaken the comparison, and consequently the
- passion.
- This too is the reason, why all objects appear great or little, merely
- by a comparison with those of the same species. A mountain neither
- magnifies nor diminishes a horse in our eyes; but when a Flemish and
- a Welsh horse are seen together, the one appears greater and the other
- less, than when viewed apart.
- From the same principle we may account for that remark of historians,
- that any party in a civil war always choose to call in a foreign enemy
- at any hazard rather than submit to their fellow-citizens. Guicciardin
- applies this remark to the wars in Italy, where the relations betwixt
- the different states are, properly speaking, nothing but of name,
- language, and contiguity. Yet even these relations, when joined with
- superiority, by making the comparison more natural, make it likewise
- more grievous, and cause men to search for some other superiority, which
- may be attended with no relation, and by that means may have a less
- sensible influence on the imagination. The mind quickly perceives its
- several advantages and disadvantages; and finding its situation to be
- most uneasy, where superiority is conjoined with other relations, seeks
- its repose as much as possible, by their separation, and by breaking
- that association of ideas, which renders the comparison so much more
- natural and efficacious. When it cannot break the association, it feels
- a stronger desire to remove the superiority; and this is the reason why
- travellers are commonly so lavish of their praises to the Chinese and
- Persians, at the same time, that they depreciate those neighbouring
- nations, which may stand upon a foot of rivalship with their native
- country.
- These examples from history and common experience are rich and curious;
- but we may find parallel ones in the arts, which are no less remarkable.
- should an author compose a treatise, of which one part was serious and
- profound, another light and humorous, every one would condemn so strange
- a mixture, and would accuse him of the neglect of all rules of art and
- criticism. These rules of art are founded on the qualities of human
- nature; and the quality of human nature, which requires a consistency in
- every performance is that which renders the mind incapable of passing
- in a moment from one passion and disposition to a quite different
- one. Yet this makes us not blame Mr Prior for joining his Alma and his
- Solomon in the same volume; though that admirable poet has succeeded
- perfectly well in the gaiety of the one, as well as in the melancholy
- of the other. Even supposing the reader should peruse these two
- compositions without any interval, he would feel little or no difficulty
- in the change of passions: Why, but because he considers these
- performances as entirely different, and by this break in the ideas,
- breaks the progress of the affections, and hinders the one from
- influencing or contradicting the other?
- An heroic and burlesque design, united in one picture, would be
- monstrous; though we place two pictures of so opposite a character in
- the same chamber, and even close by each other, without any scruple or
- difficulty.
- In a word, no ideas can affect each other, either by comparison, or by
- the passions they separately produce, unless they be united together
- by some relation, which may cause an easy transition of the ideas, and
- consequently of the emotions or impressions, attending the ideas; and
- may preserve the one impression in the passage of the imagination to the
- object of the other. This principle is very remarkable, because it is
- analogous to what we have observed both concerning the understanding and
- the passions. Suppose two objects to be presented to me, which are not
- connected by any kind of relation. Suppose that each of these objects
- separately produces a passion; and that these two passions are in
- themselves contrary: We find from experience, that the want of relation
- in the objects or ideas hinders the natural contrariety of the passions,
- and that the break in the transition of the thought removes the
- affections from each other, and prevents their opposition. It is the
- same case with comparison; and from both these phaenomena we may safely
- conclude, that the relation of ideas must forward the transition of
- impressions; since its absence alone is able to prevent it, and to
- separate what naturally should have operated upon each other. When the
- absence of an object or quality removes any usual or natural effect, we
- may certalnly conclude that its presence contributes to the production
- of the effect.
- SECT. IX OF THE MIXTURE OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER WITH COMPASSION AND MALICE
- Thus we have endeavoured to account for pity and malice. Both these
- affections arise from the imagination, according to the light, in which
- it places its object. When our fancy considers directly the sentiments
- of others, and enters deep into them, it makes us sensible of all the
- passions it surveys, but in a particular manner of grief or sorrow. On
- the contrary, when we compare the sentiments of others to our own, we
- feel a sensation directly opposite to the original one, viz. a joy from
- the grief of others, and a grief from their joy. But these are only the
- first foundations of the affections of pity and malice. Other passions
- are afterwards confounded with them. There is always a mixture of love
- or tenderness with pity, and of hatred or anger with malice. But it must
- be confessed, that this mixture seems at first sight to be contradictory
- to my system. For as pity is an uneasiness, and malice a joy, arising
- from the misery of others, pity should naturally, as in all other cases,
- produce hatred; and malice, love. This contradiction I endeavour to
- reconcile, after the following manner.
- In order to cause a transition of passions, there is required a double
- relation of impressions and ideas, nor is one relation sufficient to
- produce this effect. But that we may understand the full force of this
- double relation, we must consider, that it is not the present sensation
- alone or momentary pain or pleasure, which determines the character of
- any passion, but the whole bent or tendency of it from the beginning to
- the end. One impression may be related to another, not only when
- their sensations are resembling, as we have all along supposed in the
- preceding cases; but also when their impulses or directions are similar
- and correspondent. This cannot take place with regard to pride and
- humility; because these are only pure sensations, without any direction
- or tendency to action. We are, therefore, to look for instances of
- this peculiar relation of impressions only in such affections, as are
- attended with a certain appetite or desire; such as those of love and
- hatred.
- Benevolence or the appetite, which attends love, is a desire of the
- happiness of the person beloved, and an aversion to his misery; as anger
- or the appetite, which attends hatred, is a desire of the misery of the
- person hated, and an aversion to his happiness. A desire, therefore,
- of the happiness of another, and aversion to his misery, are similar to
- benevolence; and a desire of his misery and aversion to his happiness
- are correspondent to anger. Now pity is a desire of happiness to
- another, and aversion to his misery; as malice is the contrary appetite.
- Pity, then, is related to benevolence; and malice to anger: And as
- benevolence has been already found to be connected with love, by a
- natural and original quality, and anger with hatred; it is by this chain
- the passions of pity and malice are connected with love and hatred.
- This hypothesis is founded on sufficient experience. A man, who from any
- motives has entertained a resolution of performing an action, naturally
- runs into every other view or motive, which may fortify that resolution,
- and give it authority and influence on the mind. To confirm us in any
- design, we search for motives drawn from interest, from honour, from
- duty. What wonder, then, that pity and benevolence, malice, and anger,
- being the same desires arising from different principles, should so
- totally mix together as to be undistinguishable? As to the connexion
- betwixt benevolence and love, anger and hatred, being original and
- primary, it admits of no difficulty.
- We may add to this another experiment, viz, that benevolence and anger,
- and consequently love and hatred, arise when our happiness or misery
- have any dependance on the happiness or misery of another person,
- without any farther relation. I doubt not but this experiment will
- appear so singular as to excuse us for stopping a moment to consider it.
- Suppose, that two persons of the same trade should seek employment in a
- town, that is not able to maintain both, it is plain the success of one
- is perfectly incompatible with that of the other, and that whatever is
- for the interest of either is contrary to that of his rival, and so vice
- versa. Suppose again, that two merchants, though living in different
- parts of the world, should enter into co-partnership together, the
- advantage or loss of one becomes immediately the advantage or loss of
- his partner, and the same fortune necessarily attends both. Now it
- is evident, that in the first case, hatred always follows upon the
- contrariety of interests; as in the second, love arises from their
- union. Let us consider to what principle we can ascribe these passions.
- It is plain they arise not from the double relations of impressions and
- ideas, if we regard only the present sensation. For takeing the first
- case of rivalship; though the pleasure and advantage of an antagonist
- necessarily causes my pain and loss, yet to counter-ballance this, his
- pain and loss causes my pleasure and advantage; and supposing him to be
- unsuccessful, I may by this means receive from him a superior degree of
- satisfaction. In the same manner the success of a partner rejoices me,
- but then his misfortunes afflict me in an equal proportion; and it
- is easy to imagine, that the latter sentiment may in many cases
- preponderate. But whether the fortune of a rival or partner be good or
- bad, I always hate the former and love the latter.
- This love of a partner cannot proceed from the relation or connexion
- betwixt us; in the same manner as I love a brother or countryman. A
- rival has almost as close a relation to me as a partner. For as the
- pleasure of the latter causes my pleasure, and his pain my pain; so the
- pleasure of the former causes my pain, and his pain my pleasure. The
- connexion, then, of cause and effect is the same in both cases; and
- if in the one case, the cause and effect have a farther relation of
- resemblance, they have that of contrariety in the other; which, being
- also a species of resemblance, leaves the matter pretty equal.
- The only explication, then, we can give of this phaenomenon is derived
- from that principle of a parallel direction above-mentioned. Our concern
- for our own interest gives us a pleasure in the pleasure, and a pain in
- the pain of a partner, after the same manner as by sympathy we feel a
- sensation correspondent to those, which appear in any person, who is
- present with us. On the other hand, the same concern for our interest
- makes us feel a pain in the pleasure, and a pleasure in the pain of a
- rival; and in short the same contrariety of sentiments as arises from
- comparison and malice. Since, therefore, a parallel direction of the
- affections, proceeding from interest, can give rise to benevolence or
- anger, no wonder the same parallel direction, derived from sympathy and
- from comparison, should have the same effect.
- In general we may observe, that it is impossible to do good to others,
- from whatever motive, without feeling some touches of kindness and
- good-will towards them; as the injuries we do, not only cause hatred in
- the person, who suffers them, but even in ourselves. These phaenomena,
- indeed, may in part be accounted for from other principles.
- But here there occurs a considerable objection, which it will be
- necessary to examine before we proceed any farther. I have endeavoured
- to prove, that power and riches, or poverty and meanness; which give
- rise to love or hatred, without producing any original pleasure or
- uneasiness; operate upon us by means of a secondary sensation derived
- from a sympathy with that pain or satisfaction, which they produce in
- the person, who possesses them. From a sympathy with his pleasure there
- arises love; from that with his uneasiness, hatred. But it is a maxim,
- which I have just now established, and which is absolutely necessary to
- the explication of the phaenomena of pity and malice, that it is not the
- present sensation or momentary pain or pleasure, which determines the
- character of any passion, but the general bent or tendency of it from
- the beginning to the end. For this reason, pity or a sympathy with
- pain produces love, and that because it interests us in the fortunes of
- others, good or bad, and gives us a secondary sensation correspondent
- to the primary; in which it has the same influence with love and
- benevolence. Since then this rule holds good in one case, why does it
- not prevail throughout, and why does sympathy in uneasiness ever produce
- any passion beside good-will and kindness? Is it becoming a philosopher
- to alter his method of reasoning, and run from one principle to its
- contrary, according to the particular phaenomenon, which he would
- explain?
- I have mentioned two different causes, from which a transition of
- passion may arise, viz, a double relation of ideas and impressions, and
- what is similar to it, a conformity in the tendency and direction of any
- two desires, which arise from different principles. Now I assert, that
- when a sympathy with uneasiness is weak, it produces hatred or contempt
- by the former cause; when strong, it produces love or tenderness by the
- latter. This is the solution of the foregoing difficulty, which seems so
- urgent; and this is a principle founded on such evident arguments, that
- we ought to have established it, even though it were not necessary to
- the explication of any phaenomenon.
- It is certain, that sympathy is not always limited to the present
- moment, but that we often feel by communication the pains and pleasures
- of others, which are not in being, and which we only anticipate by the
- force of imagination. For supposing I saw a person perfectly unknown to
- me, who, while asleep in the fields, was in danger of being trod under
- foot by horses, I should immediately run to his assistance; and in this
- I should be actuated by the same principle of sympathy, which makes me
- concerned for the present sorrows of a stranger. The bare mention of
- this is sufficient. Sympathy being nothing but a lively idea converted
- into an impression, it is evident, that, in considering the future
- possible or probable condition of any person, we may enter into it with
- so vivid a conception as to make it our own concern; and by that means
- be sensible of pains and pleasures, which neither belong to ourselves,
- nor at the present instant have any real existence.
- But however we may look forward to the future in sympathizing with any
- person, the extending of our sympathy depends in a great measure upon
- our sense of his present condition. It is a great effort of imagination,
- to form such lively ideas even of the present sentiments of others as
- to feel these very sentiments; but it is impossible we coued extend this
- sympathy to the future, without being aided by some circumstance in
- the present, which strikes upon us in a lively manner. When the present
- misery of another has any strong influence upon me, the vivacity of the
- conception is not confined merely to its immediate object, but diffuses
- its influence over all the related ideas, and gives me a lively notion
- of all the circumstances of that person, whether past, present, or
- future; possible, probable or certain. By means of this lively notion
- I am interested in them; take part with them; and feel a sympathetic
- motion in my breast, conformable to whatever I imagine in his. If I
- diminish the vivacity of the first conception, I diminish that of the
- related ideas; as pipes can convey no more water than what arises at
- the fountain. By this diminution I destroy the future prospect, which is
- necessary to interest me perfectly in the fortune of another. I may
- feel the present impression, but carry my sympathy no farther, and never
- transfuse the force of the first conception into my ideas of the related
- objects. If it be another's misery, which is presented in this feeble
- manner, I receive it by communication, and am affected with all the
- passions related to it: But as I am not so much interested as to
- concern myself in his good fortune, as well as his bad, I never feel the
- extensive sympathy, nor the passions related to it.
- Now in order to know what passions are related to these different kinds
- of sympathy, we must consider, that benevolence is an original pleasure
- arising from the pleasure of the person beloved, and a pain proceeding
- from his pain: From which correspondence of impressions there arises a
- subsequent desire of his pleasure, and aversion to his pain. In order,
- then, to make a passion run parallel with benevolence, it is requisite
- we should feel these double impressions, correspondent to those of the
- person, whom we consider; nor is any one of them alone sufficient for
- that purpose. When we sympathize only with one impression, and that
- a painful one, this sympathy is related to anger and to hatred, upon
- account of the uneasiness it conveys to us. But as the extensive or
- limited sympathy depends upon the force of the first sympathy; it
- follows, that the passion of love or hatred depends upon the same
- principle. A strong impression, when communicated, gives a double
- tendency of the passions; which is related to benevolence and love by a
- similarity of direction; however painful the first impression might have
- been. A weak impression, that is painful, is related to anger and hatred
- by the resemblance of sensations. Benevolence, therefore, arises from a
- great degree of misery, or any degree strongly sympathized with: Hatred
- or contempt from a small degree, or one weakly sympathized with; which
- is the principle I intended to prove and explain.
- Nor have we only our reason to trust to for this principle, but also
- experience. A certain degree of poverty produces contempt; but a degree
- beyond causes compassion and good-will. We may under-value a peasant
- or servant; but when the misery of a beggar appears very great, or
- is painted in very lively colours, we sympathize with him in his
- afflictions; and feel in our heart evident touches of pity and
- benevolence. The same object causes contrary passions according to its
- different degrees. The passions, therefore, must depend upon principles,
- that operate in such certain degrees, according to my hypothesis. The
- encrease of the sympathy has evidently the same effect as the encrease
- of the misery.
- A barren or desolate country always seems ugly and disagreeable, and
- commonly inspires us with contempt for the inhabitants. This deformity,
- however, proceeds in a great measure from a sympathy with the
- inhabitants, as has been already observed; but it is only a weak
- one, and reaches no farther than the immediate sensation, which is
- disagreeable. The view of a city in ashes conveys benevolent sentiments;
- because we there enter so deep into the interests of the miserable
- inhabitants, as to wish for their prosperity, as well as feel their
- adversity.
- But though the force of the impression generally produces pity and
- benevolence, it is certain, that by being carryed too far it ceases
- to have that effect. This, perhaps, may be worth our notice. When the
- uneasiness is either small in itself, or remote from us, it engages not
- the imagination, nor is able to convey an equal concern for the future
- and contingent good, as for the present and real evil Upon its acquiring
- greater force, we become so interested in the concerns of the person, as
- to be sensible both of his good and had fortune; and from that compleat
- sympathy there arises pity and benevolence. But it will easily be
- imagined, that where the present evil strikes with more than ordinary
- force, it may entirely engage our attention, and prevent that double
- sympathy, above-mentioned. Thus we find, that though every one, but
- especially women, are apt to contract a kindness for criminals, who go
- to the scaffold, and readily imagine them to be uncommonly handsome and
- wellshaped; yet one, who is present at the cruel execution of the rack,
- feels no such tender emotions; but is in a manner overcome with horror,
- and has no leisure to temper this uneasy sensation by any opposite
- sympathy.
- But the instance, which makes the most clearly for my hypothesis, is
- that wherein by a change of the objects we separate the double sympathy
- even from a midling degree of the passion; in which case we find, that
- pity, instead of producing love and tenderness as usual, always gives
- rise to the contrary affection. When we observe a person in misfortunes,
- we are affected with pity and love; but the author of that misfortune
- becomes the object of our strongest hatred, and is the more detested in
- proportion to the degree of our compassion. Now for what reason should
- the same passion of pity produce love to the person, who suffers the
- misfortune, and hatred to the person, who causes it; unless it be
- because in the latter case the author bears a relation only to the
- misfortune; whereas in considering the sufferer we carry our view on
- every side, and wish for his prosperity, as well as are sensible of his
- affliction?
- I. shall just observe, before I leave the present subject, that this
- phaenomenon of the double sympathy, and its tendency to cause love, may
- contribute to the production of the kindness, which we naturally bear
- our relations and acquaintance. Custom and relation make us enter deeply
- into the sentiments of others; and whatever fortune we suppose to attend
- them, is rendered present to us by the imagination, and operates as if
- originally our own. We rejoice in their pleasures, and grieve for their
- sorrows, merely from the force of sympathy. Nothing that concerns them
- is indifferent to us; and as this correspondence of sentiments is the
- natural attendant of love, it readily produces that affection.
- SECT. X OF RESPECT AND CONTEMPT
- There now remains only to explain the passion of respect and contempt,
- along with the amorous affection, in order to understand all the
- passions which have any mixture of love or hatred. Let us begin with
- respect and contempt.
- In considering the qualities and circumstances of others, we may either
- regard them as they really are in themselves; or may make a comparison
- betwixt them and our own qualities and circumstances; or may join these
- two methods of consideration. The good qualities of others, from the
- first point of view, produce love; from the second, humility; and from
- the third, respect; which is a mixture of these two passions. Their
- bad qualities, after the same manner, cause either hatred, or pride, or
- contempt, according to the light in which we survey them.
- That there is a mixture of pride in contempt, and of humility
- in respect, is, I think, too evident, from their very feeling or
- appearance, to require any particular proof. That this mixture arises
- from a tacit comparison of the person contemned or respected with
- ourselves is no less evident. The same man may cause either respect,
- love, or contempt by his condition and talents, according as the person,
- who considers him, from his inferior becomes his equal or superior. In
- changing the point of view, though the object may remain the same,
- its proportion to ourselves entirely alters; which is the cause of an
- alteration in the passions. These passions, therefore, arise from our
- observing the proportion; that is, from a comparison.
- I have already observed, that the mind has a much stronger propensity
- to pride than to humility, and have endeavoured, from the principles
- of human nature, to assign a cause for this phaenomenon. Whether my
- reasoning be received or not, the phaenomenon is undisputed, and appears
- in many instances. Among the rest, it is the reason why there is a much
- greater mixture of pride in contempt, than of humility in respect, and
- why we are more elevated with the view of one below us, than mortifyed
- with the presence of one above us. Contempt or scorn has so strong a
- tincture of pride, that there scarce is any other passion discernable:
- Whereas in esteem or respect, love makes a more considerable ingredient
- than humility. The passion of vanity is so prompt, that it rouzes at the
- least call; while humility requires a stronger impulse to make it exert
- itself.
- But here it may reasonably be asked, why this mixture takes place only
- in some cases, and appears not on every occasion. All those objects,
- which cause love, when placed on another person, are the causes of
- pride, when transfered to ourselves; and consequently ought to be causes
- of humility, as well as love, while they belong to others, and are only
- compared to those, which we ourselves possess. In like manner every
- quality, which, by being directly considered, produces hatred, ought
- always to give rise to pride by comparison, and by a mixture of these
- passions of hatred and pride ought to excite contempt or scorn. The
- difficulty then is, why any objects ever cause pure love or hatred, and
- produce not always the mixt passions of respect and contempt.
- I have supposed all along, that the passions of love and pride, and
- those of humility and hatred are similar in their sensations, and that
- the two former are always agreeable, and the two latter painful.
- But though this be universally true, it is observable, that the two
- agreeable, as well as the two painful passions, have some difference,
- and even contrarieties, which distinguish them. Nothing invigorates and
- exalts the mind equally with pride and vanity; though at the same time
- love or tenderness is rather found to weaken and infeeble it. The same
- difference is observable betwixt the uneasy passions. Anger and hatred
- bestow a new force on all our thoughts and actions; while humility and
- shame deject and discourage us. Of these qualities of the passions, it
- will be necessary to form a distinct idea. Let us remember, that pride
- and hatred invigorate the soul; and love and humility infeeble it.
- From this it follows, that though the conformity betwixt love and hatred
- in the agreeableness of their sensation makes them always be excited by
- the same objects, yet this other contrariety is the reason, why they are
- excited in very different degrees. Genius and learning are pleasant
- and magnificent objects, and by both these circumstances are adapted to
- pride and vanity; but have a relation to love by their pleasure only.
- Ignorance and simplicity are disagreeable and mean, which in the same
- manner gives them a double connexion with humility, and a single one
- with hatred. We may, therefore, consider it as certain, that though
- the same object always produces love and pride, humility and hatred,
- according to its different situations, yet it seldom produces either the
- two former or the two latter passions, in the same proportion.
- It is here we must seek for a solution of the difficulty
- above-mentioned, why any object ever excites pure love or hatred, and
- does not always produce respect or contempt, by a mixture of humility
- or pride. No quality in another gives rise to humility by comparison,
- unless it would have produced pride by being placed in ourselves; and
- vice versa no object excites pride by comparison, unless it would have
- produced humility by the direct survey. This is evident, objects always
- produce by comparison a sensation directly contrary to their original
- one. Suppose, therefore, an object to be presented, which is peculiarly
- fitted to produce love, but imperfectly to excite pride; this object,
- belonging to another, gives rise directly to a great degree of love, but
- to a small one of humility by comparison; and consequently that latter
- passion is scarce felt in the compound, nor is able to convert the love
- into respect. This is the case with good nature, good humour, facility,
- generosity, beauty, and many other qualities. These have a peculiar
- aptitude to produce love in others; but not so great a tendency to
- excite pride in ourselves: For which reason the view of them, as
- belonging to another person, produces pure love, with but a small
- mixture of humility and respect. It is easy to extend the same reasoning
- to the opposite passions.
- Before we leave this subject, it may not be amiss to account for a
- pretty curious phaenomenon, viz, why we commonly keep at a distance such
- as we contemn, and allow not our inferiors to approach too near even
- in place and situation. It has already been observed, that almost every
- kind of idea is attended with some emotion, even the ideas of number
- and extension, much more those of such objects as are esteemed of
- consequence in life, and fix our attention. It is not with entire
- indifference we can survey either a rich man or a poor one, but must
- feel some faint touches at least, of respect in the former case, and of
- contempt in the latter. These two passions are contrary to each other;
- but in order to make this contrariety be felt, the objects must be
- someway related; otherwise the affections are totally separate and
- distinct, and never encounter. The relation takes place wherever the
- persons become contiguous; which is a general reason why we are uneasy
- at seeing such disproportioned objects, as a rich man and a poor one, a
- nobleman and a porter, in that situation.
- This uneasiness, which is common to every spectator, must be more
- sensible to the superior; and that because the near approach of the
- inferior is regarded as a piece of ill-breeding, and shews that he is not
- sensible of the disproportion, and is no way affected by it. A sense
- of superiority in another breeds in all men an inclination to keep
- themselves at a distance from him, and determines them to redouble the
- marks of respect and reverence, when they are obliged to approach him;
- and where they do not observe that conduct, it is a proof they are not
- sensible of his superiority. From hence too it proceeds, that any great
- difference in the degrees of any quality is called a distance by a
- common metaphor, which, however trivial it may appear, is founded on
- natural principles of the imagination. A great difference inclines us to
- produce a distance. The ideas of distance and difference are, therefore,
- connected together. Connected ideas are readily taken for each other;
- and this is in general the source of the metaphor, as we shall have
- occasion to observe afterwards.
- SECT. XI OF THE AMOROUS PASSION, OR LOVE BETWIXT THE SEXES
- Of all the compound passions, which proceed from a mixture of love and
- hatred with other affections, no one better deserves our attention, than
- that love, which arises betwixt the sexes, as well on account of its
- force and violence, as those curious principles of philosophy, for
- which it affords us an uncontestable argument. It is plain, that this
- affection, in its most natural state, is derived from the conjunction
- of three different impressions or passions, viz. The pleasing sensation
- arising from beauty; the bodily appetite for generation; and a generous
- kindness or good-will. The origin of kindness from beauty may be
- explained from the foregoing reasoning. The question is how the bodily
- appetite is excited by it.
- The appetite of generation, when confined to a certain degree, is
- evidently of the pleasant kind, and has a strong connexion with, all the
- agreeable emotions. Joy, mirth, vanity, and kindness are all incentives
- to this desire; as well as music, dancing, wine, and good cheer. On the
- other hand, sorrow, melancholy, poverty, humility are destructive of it.
- From this quality it is easily conceived why it should be connected with
- the sense of beauty.
- But there is another principle that contributes to the same effect.
- I have observed that the parallel direction of the desires is a real
- relation, and no less than a resemblance in their sensation, produces
- a connexion among them. That we may fully comprehend the extent of this
- relation, we must consider, that any principal desire may be attended
- with subordinate ones, which are connected with it, and to which if
- other desires are parallel, they are by that means related to the
- principal one. Thus hunger may oft be considered as the primary
- inclination of the soul, and the desire of approaching the meat as the
- secondary one; since it is absolutely necessary to the satisfying that
- appetite. If an object, therefore, by any separate qualities, inclines
- us to approach the meat, it naturally encreases our appetite; as on the
- contrary, whatever inclines us to set our victuals at a distance, is
- contradictory to hunger, and diminishes our inclination to them. Now
- it is plain that beauty has the first effect, and deformity the second:
- Which is the reason why the former gives us a keener appetite for our
- victuals, and the latter is sufficient to disgust us at the most savoury
- dish that cookery has invented. All this is easily applicable to the
- appetite for generation.
- From these two relations, viz, resemblance and a parallel desire,
- there arises such a connexion betwixt the sense of beauty, the bodily
- appetite, and benevolence, that they become in a manner inseparable: And
- we find from experience that it is indifferent which of them advances
- first; since any of them is almost sure to be attended with the related
- affections. One, who is inflamed with lust, feels at least a momentary
- kindness towards the object of it, and at the same time fancies her more
- beautiful than ordinary; as there are many, who begin with kindness and
- esteem for the wit and merit of the person, and advance from that to the
- other passions. But the most common species of love is that which first
- arises from beauty, and afterwards diffuses itself into kindness and
- into the bodily appetite. Kindness or esteem, and the appetite to
- generation, are too remote to unite easily together. The one is,
- perhaps, the most refined passion of the soul; the other the most gross
- and vulgar. The love of beauty is placed in a just medium betwixt them,
- and partakes of both their natures: From whence it proceeds, that it is
- so singularly fitted to produce both.
- This account of love is not peculiar to my system, but is unavoidable
- on any hypothesis. The three affections, which compose this passion,
- are evidently distinct, and has each of them its distinct object. It is
- certain, therefore, that it is only by their relation they produce
- each other. But the relation of passions is not alone sufficient. It is
- likewise necessary, there should be a relation of ideas. The beauty
- of one person never inspires us with love for another. This then is a
- sensible proof of the double relation of impressions and ideas. From one
- instance so evident as this we may form a judgment of the rest.
- This may also serve in another view to illustrate what I have insisted
- on concerning the origin of pride and humility, love and hatred. I have
- observed, that though self be the object of the first set of passions,
- and some other person of the second, yet these objects cannot alone be
- the causes of the passions; as having each of them a relation to two
- contrary affections, which must from the very first moment destroy
- each other. Here then is the situation of the mind, as I have already
- described it. It has certain organs naturally fitted to produce a
- passion; that passion, when produced, naturally turns the view to a
- certain object. But this not being sufficient to produce the passion,
- there is required some other emotion, which by a double relation of
- impressions and ideas may set these principles in action, and bestow on
- them their first impulse. This situation is still more remarkable with
- regard to the appetite of generation. Sex is not only the object, but
- also the cause of the appetite. We not only turn our view to it, when
- actuated by that appetite; but the reflecting on it suffices to excite
- the appetite. But as this cause loses its force by too great frequency,
- it is necessary it should be quickened by some new impulse; and that
- impulse we find to arise from the beauty of the person; that is, from a
- double relation of impressions and ideas. Since this double relation is
- necessary where an affection has both a distinct cause, and object,
- how much more so, where it has only a distinct object, without any
- determinate cause?
- SECT. XII OF THE LOVE AND HATRED OF ANIMALS
- But to pass from the passions of love and hatred, and from their
- mixtures and compositions, as they appear m man, to the same affections,
- as they display themselves in brutes; we may observe, not only that love
- and hatred are common to the whole sensitive creation, but likewise that
- their causes, as above-explained, are of so simple a nature, that they
- may easily be supposed to operate on mere animals. There is no force of
- reflection or penetration required. Every thing is conducted by springs
- and principles, which are not peculiar to man, or any one species of
- animals. The conclusion from this is obvious in favour of the foregoing
- system.
- Love in animals, has not for its only object animals of the same
- species, but extends itself farther, and comprehends almost every
- sensible and thinking being. A dog naturally loves a man above his own
- species, and very commonly meets with a return of affection.
- As animals are but little susceptible either of the pleasures or pains
- of the imagination, they can judge of objects only by the sensible
- good or evil, which they produce, and from that must regulate their
- affections towards them. Accordingly we find, that by benefits or
- injuries we produce their love or hatred; and that by feeding and
- cherishing any animal, we quickly acquire his affections; as by beating
- and abusing him we never fail to draw on us his enmity and ill-will.
- Love in beasts is not caused so much by relation, as in our species;
- and that because their thoughts are not so active as to trace relations,
- except in very obvious instances. Yet it is easy to remark, that on some
- occasions it has a considerable influence upon them. Thus acquaintance,
- which has the same effect as relation, always produces love in animals
- either to men or to each other. For the same reason any likeness among
- them is the source of affection. An ox confined to a park with horses,
- will naturally join their company, if I may so speak, but always leaves
- it to enjoy that of his own species, where he has the choice of both.
- The affection of parents to their young proceeds from a peculiar
- instinct in animals, as well as in our species.
- It is evident, that sympathy, or the communication of passions, takes
- place among animals, no less than among men. Fear, anger, courage, and
- other affections are frequently communicated from one animal to another,
- without their knowledge of that cause, which produced the original
- passion. Grief likewise is received by sympathy; and produces almost all
- the same consequences, and excites the same emotions as in our species.
- The howlings and lamentations of a dog produce a sensible concern in
- his fellows. And it is remarkable, that though almost all animals use in
- play the same member, and nearly the same action as in fighting; a lion,
- a tyger, a cat their paws; an ox his horns; a dog his teeth; a horse
- his heels: Yet they most carefully avoid harming their companion,
- even though they have nothing to fear from his resentment; which is
- an evident proof of the sense brutes have of each other's pain and
- pleasure.
- Every one has observed how much more dogs are animated when they hunt in
- a pack, than when they pursue their game apart; and it is evident this
- can proceed from nothing but from sympathy. It is also well known to
- hunters, that this effect follows in a greater degree, and even in
- too great a degree, where two packs, that are strangers to each other,
- are joined together. We might, perhaps, be at a loss to explain this
- phaenomenon, if we had not experience of a similar in ourselves.
- Envy and malice are passions very remarkable in animals. They are
- perhaps more common than pity; as requiring less effort of thought and
- imagination.
- PART III OF THE WILL AND DIRECT PASSIONS
- SECT. I OF LIBERTY AND NECESSITY
- We come now to explain the direct passions, or the impressions, which
- arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. Of this kind
- are, desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear.
- Of all the immediate effects of pain and pleasure, there is none more
- remarkable than the WILL; and though properly speaking, it be not
- comprehended among the passions, yet as the full understanding of its
- nature and properties, is necessary to the explanation of them, we shall
- here make it the subject of our enquiry. I desire it may be observed,
- that by the will, I mean nothing but the internal impression we feel and
- are conscious of, when we knowingly give rise to any new motion of our
- body, or new perception of our mind. This impression, like the preceding
- ones of pride and humility, love and hatred, it is impossible to define,
- and needless to describe any farther; for which reason we shall cut off
- all those definitions and distinctions, with which philosophers are wont
- to perplex rather than dear up this question; and entering at first
- upon the subject, shall examine that long disputed question concerning
- liberty and necessity; which occurs so naturally in treating of the
- will.
- It is universally acknowledged, that the operations of external bodies
- are necessary, and that in the communication of their motion, in their
- attraction, and mutual cohesion, there are nor the least traces of
- indifference or liberty. Every object is determined by an absolute fate
- toa certain degree and direction of irs motion, and can no more depart
- from that precise line, in which it moves, than it can convert itself
- into an angel, or spirit, or any superior substance. The actions,
- therefore, of matter are to be regarded as instances of necessary
- actions; and whatever is in this respect on the same footing with
- matter, must be acknowledged to be necessary. That we may know whether
- this be the case with the actions of the mind, we shall begin with
- examining matter, and considering on what the idea of a necessity in its
- operations are founded, and why we conclude one body or action to be the
- infallible cause of another.
- It has been observed already, that in no single instance the ultimate
- connexion of any objects is discoverable, either by our senses or
- reason, and that we can never penetrate so far into the essence and
- construction of bodies, as to perceive the principle, on which their
- mutual influence depends. It is their constant union alone, with which
- we are acquainted; and it is from the constant union the necessity
- arises. If objects had nor an uniform and regular conjunction with each
- other, we should never arrive at any idea of cause and effect; and even
- after all, the necessity, which enters into that idea, is nothing but
- a determination of the mind to pass from one object to its usual
- attendant, and infer the existence of one from that of the other. Here
- then are two particulars, which we are to consider as essential to
- necessity, viz, the constant union and the inference of the mind; and
- wherever we discover these we must acknowledge a necessity. As the
- actions of matter have no necessity, but what is derived from these
- circumstances, and it is not by any insight into the essence of bodies
- we discover their connexion, the absence of this insight, while
- the union and inference remain, will never, in any case, remove the
- necessity. It is the observation of the union, which produces the
- inference; for which reason it might be thought sufficient, if we prove
- a constant union in the actions of the mind, in order to establish the
- inference, along with the necessity of these actions. But that I
- may bestow a greater force on my reasoning, I shall examine these
- particulars apart, and shall first prove from experience that
- our actions have a constant union with our motives, tempers, and
- circumstances, before I consider the inferences we draw from it.
- To this end a very slight and general view of the common course of human
- affairs will be sufficient. There is no light, in which we can take
- them, that does nor confirm this principle. Whether we consider mankind
- according to the difference of sexes, ages, governments, conditions,
- or methods of education; the same uniformity and regular operation
- of natural principles are discernible. Uke causes still produce like
- effects; in the same manner as in the mutual action of the elements and
- powers of nature.
- There are different trees, which regularly produce fruit, whose relish
- is different from each other; and this regularity will be admitted as
- an instance of necessity and causes in external bodies. But are the
- products of Guienne and of Champagne more regularly different than the
- sentiments, actions, and passions of the two sexes, of which the one are
- distinguished by their force and maturity, the other by their delicacy
- and softness?
- Are the changes of our body from infancy to old age more regular and
- certain than those of our mind and conduct? And would a man be more
- ridiculous, who would expect that an infant of four years old will raise
- a weight of three hundred pound, than one, who from a person of the
- same age would look for a philosophical reasoning, or a prudent and
- well-concerted action?
- We must certainly allow, that the cohesion of the parts of matter arises
- from natural and necessary principles, whatever difficulty we may find
- in explaining them: And for a reason we must allow, that human society
- is founded on like principles; and our reason in the latter case, is
- better than even that in the former; because we not only observe, that
- men always seek society, but can also explain the principles, on which
- this universal propensity is founded. For is it more certain, that two
- flat pieces of marble will unite together, than that two young savages
- of different sexes will copulate? Do the children arise from this
- copulation more uniformly, than does the parents care for their safety
- and preservation? And after they have arrived at years of discretion
- by the care of their parents, are the inconveniencies attending their
- separation more certain than their foresight of these inconveniencies
- and their care of avoiding them by a close union and confederacy?
- The skin, pores, muscles, and nerves of a day-labourer are different
- from those of a man of quality: So are his sentiments, actions and
- manners. The different stations of life influence the whole fabric,
- external and internal; and different stations arise necessarily, because
- uniformly, from the necessary and uniform principles of human nature.
- Men cannot live without society, and cannot be associated without
- government. Government makes a distinction of property, and establishes
- the different ranks of men. This produces industry, traffic,
- manufactures, law-suits, war, leagues, alliances, voyages, travels,
- cities, fleets, ports, and all those other actions and objects, which
- cause such a diversity, and at the same time maintain such an uniformity
- in human life.
- Should a traveller, returning from a far country, tell us, that he had
- seen a climate in the fiftieth degree of northern latitude, where all
- the fruits ripen and come to perfection in the winter, and decay in the
- summer, after the same manner as in England they are produced and decay
- in the contrary seasons, he would find few so credulous as to believe
- him. I am apt to think a travellar would meet with as little credit, who
- should inform us of people exactly of the same character with those in
- Plato's republic on the one hand, or those in Hobbes's Leviathan on the
- other. There is a general course of nature in human actions, as well as
- in the operations of the sun and the climate. There are also characters
- peculiar to different nations and particular persons, as well as
- common to mankind. The knowledge of these characters is founded on the
- observation of an uniformity in the actions, that flow from them; and
- this uniformity forms the very essence of necessity.
- I can imagine only one way of eluding this argument, which is by denying
- that uniformity of human actions, on which it is founded. As long as
- actions have a constant union and connexion with the situation and
- temper of the agent, however we may in words refuse to acknowledge the
- necessity, we really allow the thing. Now some may, perhaps, find a
- pretext to deny this regular union and connexion. For what is more
- capricious than human actions? What more inconstant than the desires of
- man? And what creature departs more widely, not only from right reason,
- but from his own character and disposition? An hour, a moment is
- sufficient to make him change from one extreme to another, and overturn
- what cost the greatest pain and labour to establish. Necessity is
- regular and certain. Human conduct is irregular and uncertain. The one,
- therefore, proceeds not from the other.
- To this I reply, that in judging of the actions of men we must proceed
- upon the same maxims, as when we reason concerning external objects.
- When any phaenomena are constantly and invariably conjoined together,
- they acquire such a connexion in the imagination, that it passes from
- one to the other, without any doubt or hesitation. But below this there
- are many inferior degrees of evidence and probability, nor does one
- single contrariety of experiment entirely destroy all our reasoning. The
- mind ballances the contrary experiments, and deducting the inferior from
- the superior, proceeds with that degree of assurance or evidence, which
- remains. Even when these contrary experiments are entirely equal, we
- remove not the notion of causes and necessity; but supposing that the
- usual contrariety proceeds from the operation of contrary and concealed
- causes, we conclude, that the chance or indifference lies only in
- our judgment on account of our imperfect knowledge, not in the things
- themselves, which are in every case equally necessary, though to
- appearance not equally constant or certain. No union can be more
- constant and certain, than that of some actions with some motives and
- characters; and if in other cases the union is uncertain, it is no more
- than what happens in the operations of body, nor can we conclude any
- thing from the one irregularity, which will not follow equally from the
- other.
- It is commonly allowed that mad-men have no liberty. But were we to
- judge by their actions, these have less regularity and constancy than
- the actions of wise-men, and consequently are farther removed from
- necessity. Our way of thinking in this particular is, therefore,
- absolutely inconsistent; but is a natural consequence of these confused
- ideas and undefined terms, which we so commonly make use of in our
- reasonings, especially on the present subject.
- We must now shew, that as the union betwixt motives and actions has the
- same constancy, as that in any natural operations, so its influence
- on the understanding is also the same, in determining us to infer the
- existence of one from that of another. If this shall appear, there is no
- known circumstance, that enters into the connexion and production of the
- actions of matter, that is not to be found in all the operations of
- the mind; and consequently we cannot, without a manifest absurdity,
- attribute necessity to the one, and refuse into the other.
- There is no philosopher, whose judgment is so riveted to this
- fantastical system of liberty, as not to acknowledge the force of moral
- evidence, and both in speculation and practice proceed upon it, as upon
- a reasonable foundation. Now moral evidence is nothing but a conclusion
- concerning the actions of men, derived from the consideration of their
- motives, temper and situation. Thus when we see certain characters or
- figures described upon paper, we infer that the person, who produced
- them, would affirm such facts, the death of Caesar, the success of
- Augustus, the cruelty of Nero; and remembering many other concurrent
- testimonies we conclude, that those facts were once really existant, and
- that so many men, without any interest, would never conspire to deceive
- us; especially since they must, in the attempt, expose themselves to the
- derision of all their contemporaries, when these facts were asserted to
- be recent and universally known. The same kind of reasoning runs through
- politics, war, commerce, economy, and indeed mixes itself so entirely
- in human life, that it is impossible to act or subsist a moment without
- having recourse to it. A prince, who imposes a tax upon his subjects,
- expects their compliance. A general, who conducts an army, makes account
- of a certain degree of courage. A merchant looks for fidelity and skill
- in his factor or super-cargo. A man, who gives orders for his dinner,
- doubts not of the obedience of his servants. In short, as nothing
- more nearly interests us than our own actions and those of others, the
- greatest part of our reasonings is employed in judgments concerning
- them. Now I assert, that whoever reasons after this manner, does ipso
- facto believe the actions of the will to arise from necessity, and that
- he knows not what he means, when he denies it.
- All those objects, of which we call the one cause and the other effect,
- considered in themselves, are as distinct and separate from each other,
- as any two things in nature, nor can we ever, by the most accurate
- survey of them, infer the existence of the one from that of the other.
- It is only from experience and the observation of their constant
- union, that we are able to form this inference; and even after all, the
- inference is nothing but the effects of custom on the imagination. We
- must not here be content with saying, that the idea of cause and effect
- arises from objects constantly united; but must affirm, that it is
- the very same with the idea of those objects, and that the necessary
- connexion is not discovered by a conclusion of the understanding, but
- is merely a perception of the mind. Wherever, therefore, we observe the
- same union, and wherever the union operates in the same manner upon the
- belief and opinion, we have the idea of causes and necessity, though
- perhaps we may avoid those expressions. Motion in one body in all past
- instances, that have fallen under our observation, is followed upon
- impulse by motion in another. It is impossible for the mind to penetrate
- farther. From this constant union it forms the idea of cause and
- effect, and by its influence feels the necessity. As there is the same
- constancy, and the same influence in what we call moral evidence, I ask
- no more. What remains can only be a dispute of words.
- And indeed, when we consider how aptly natural and moral evidence cement
- together, and form only one chain of argument betwixt them, we shall
- make no scruple to allow, that they are of the same nature, and
- derived from the same principles. A prisoner, who has neither money nor
- interest, discovers the impossibility of his escape, as well from the
- obstinacy of the goaler, as from the walls and bars with which he is
- surrounded; and in all attempts for his freedom chuses rather to work
- upon the stone and iron of the one, than upon the inflexible nature of
- the other. The same prisoner, when conducted to the scaffold, foresees
- his death as certainly from the constancy and fidelity of his guards
- as from the operation of the ax or wheel. His mind runs along a certain
- train of ideas: The refusal of the soldiers to consent to his escape,
- the action of the executioner; the separation of the head and body;
- bleeding, convulsive motions, and death. Here is a connected chain of
- natural causes and voluntary actions; but the mind feels no difference
- betwixt them in passing from one link to another; nor is less certain of
- the future event than if it were connected with the present impressions
- of the memory and senses by a train of causes cemented together by what
- we are pleased to call a physical necessity. The same experienced union
- has the same effect on the mind, whether the united objects be motives,
- volitions and actions; or figure and motion. We may change the names of
- things; but their nature and their operation on the understanding never
- change.
- I dare be positive no one will ever endeavour to refute these reasonings
- otherwise than by altering my definitions, and assigning a different
- meaning to the terms of cause, and effect, and necessity, and liberty,
- and chance. According to my definitions, necessity makes an essential
- part of causation; and consequently liberty, by removing necessity,
- removes also causes, and is the very same thing with chance. As chance
- is commonly thought to imply a contradiction, and is at least directly
- contrary to experience, there are always the same arguments against
- liberty or free-will. If any one alters the definitions, I cannot
- pretend to argue with him, until I know the meaning he assigns to these
- terms.
- SECT. II THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUed
- I believe we may assign the three following reasons for the prevalance
- of the doctrine of liberty, however absurd it may be in one sense, and
- unintelligible in any other. First, After we have performed any action;
- though we confess we were influenced by particular views and motives; it
- is difficult for us to persuade ourselves we were governed by necessity,
- and that it was utterly impossible for us to have acted otherwise; the
- idea of necessity seeming to imply something of force, and violence,
- and constraint, of which we are not sensible. Few are capable of
- distinguishing betwixt the liberty of spontaniety, as it is called in
- the schools, and the liberty of indifference; betwixt that which is
- opposed to violence, and that which means a negation of necessity and
- causes. The first is even the most common sense of the word; and as it
- is only that species of liberty, which it concerns us to preserve,
- our thoughts have been principally turned towards it, and have almost
- universally confounded it with the other.
- Secondly, There is a false sensation or experience even of the
- liberty of indifference; which is regarded as an argument for its real
- existence. The necessity of any action, whether of matter or of the
- mind, is not properly a quality in the agent, but in any thinking or
- intelligent being, who may consider the action, and consists in the
- determination of his thought to infer its existence from some preceding
- objects: As liberty or chance, on the other hand, is nothing but the
- want of that determination, and a certain looseness, which we feel in
- passing or not passing from the idea of one to that of the other. Now we
- may observe, that though in reflecting on human actions we seldom feel
- such a looseness or indifference, yet it very commonly happens, that in
- performing the actions themselves we are sensible of something like
- it: And as all related or resembling objects are readily taken for each
- other, this has been employed as a demonstrative or even an intuitive
- proof of human liberty. We feel that our actions are subject to our will
- on most occasions, and imagine we feel that the will itself is subject
- to nothing; because when by a denial of it we are provoked to try, we
- feel that it moves easily every way, and produces an image of itself
- even on that side, on which it did not settle. This image or faint
- motion, we persuade ourselves, coued have been compleated into the thing
- itself; because, should that be denyed, we find, upon a second trial,
- that it can. But these efforts are all in vain; and whatever capricious
- and irregular actions we may perform; as the desire of showing our
- liberty is the sole motive of our actions; we can never free ourselves
- from the bonds of necessity. We may imagine we feel a liberty within
- ourselves; but a spectator can commonly infer our actions from our
- motives and character; and even where he cannot, he concludes in
- general, that he might, were he perfectly acquainted with every
- circumstance of our situation and temper, and the most secret springs
- of our complexion and disposition. Now this is the very essence of
- necessity, according to the foregoing doctrine.
- A third reason why the doctrine of liberty has generally been better
- received in the world, than its antagonist, proceeds from religion,
- which has been very unnecessarily interested in this question. There is
- no method of reasoning more common, and yet none more blameable, than in
- philosophical debates to endeavour to refute any hypothesis by a pretext
- of its dangerous consequences to religion and morality. When any opinion
- leads us into absurdities, it is certainly false; but it is not certain
- an opinion is false, because it is of dangerous consequence. Such
- topics, therefore, ought entirely to be foreborn, as serving nothing
- to the discovery of truth, but only to make the person of an antagonist
- odious. This I observe in general, without pretending to draw any
- advantage from it. I submit myself frankly to an examination of this
- kind, and dare venture to affirm, that the doctrine of necessity,
- according to my explication of it, is not only innocent, but even
- advantageous to religion and morality.
- I define necessity two ways, conformable to the two definitions of
- cause, of which it makes an essential part. I place it either in the
- constant union and conjunction of like objects, or in the inference of
- the mind from the one to the other. Now necessity, in both these senses,
- has universally, though tacitely, in the schools, in the pulpit, and in
- common life, been allowed to belong to the will of man, and no one has
- ever pretended to deny, that we can draw inferences concerning human
- actions, and that those inferences are founded on the experienced union
- of like actions with like motives and circumstances. The only particular
- in which any one can differ from me, is either, that perhaps he will
- refuse to call this necessity. But as long as the meaning is understood,
- I hope the word can do no harm. Or that he will maintain there is
- something else in the operations of matter. Now whether it be so or
- not is of no consequence to religion, whatever it may be to natural
- philosophy. I may be mistaken in asserting, that we have no idea of any
- other connexion in the actions of body, and shall be glad to be farther
- instructed on that head: But sure I am, I ascribe nothing to the actions
- of the mind, but what must readily be allowed of. Let no one, therefore,
- put an invidious construction on my words, by saying simply, that
- I assert the necessity of human actions, and place them on the same
- footing with the operations of senseless matter. I do not ascribe to the
- will that unintelligible necessity, which is supposed to lie in matter.
- But I ascribe to matter, that intelligible quality, call it necessity or
- not, which the most rigorous orthodoxy does or must allow to belong to
- the will. I change, therefore, nothing in the received systems, with
- regard to the will, but only with regard to material objects.
- Nay I shall go farther, and assert, that this kind of necessity is so
- essential to religion and morality, that without it there must ensue
- an absolute subversion of both, and that every other supposition is
- entirely destructive to all laws both divine and human. It is indeed
- certain, that as all human laws are founded on rewards and punishments,
- it is supposed as a fundamental principle, that these motives have an
- influence on the mind, and both produce the good and prevent the evil
- actions. We may give to this influence what name we please; but as it
- is usually conjoined with the action, common sense requires it should be
- esteemed a cause, and be booked upon as an instance of that necessity,
- which I would establish.
- This reasoning is equally solid, when applied to divine laws, so far
- as the deity is considered as a legislator, and is supposed to inflict
- punishment and bestow rewards with a design to produce obedience. But I
- also maintain, that even where he acts not in his magisterial capacity,
- but is regarded as the avenger of crimes merely on account of their
- odiousness and deformity, not only it is impossible, without the
- necessary connexion of cause and effect in human actions, that
- punishments coued be inflicted compatible with justice and moral equity;
- but also that it coued ever enter into the thoughts of any reasonable
- being to inflict them. The constant and universal object of hatred or
- anger is a person or creature endowed with thought and consciousness;
- and when any criminal or injurious actions excite that passion, it
- is only by their relation to the person or connexion with him. But
- according to the doctrine of liberty or chance, this connexion is
- reduced to nothing, nor are men more accountable for those actions,
- which are designed and premeditated, than for such as are the most
- casual and accidental. Actions are by their very nature temporary and
- perishing; and where they proceed not from some cause in the characters
- and disposition of the person, who performed them, they infix not
- themselves upon him, and can neither redound to his honour, if good, nor
- infamy, if evil. The action itself may be blameable; it may be contrary
- to all the rules of morality and religion: But the person is not
- responsible for it; and as it proceeded from nothing in him, that is
- durable or constant, and leaves nothing of that nature behind it, it is
- impossible he can, upon its account, become the object of punishment or
- vengeance. According to the hypothesis of liberty, therefore, a man is
- as pure and untainted, after having committed the most horrid crimes, as
- at the first moment of his birth, nor is his character any way concerned
- in his actions; since they are not derived from it, and the wickedness
- of the one can never be used as a proof of the depravity of the other.
- It is only upon the principles of necessity, that a person acquires
- any merit or demerit from his actions, however the common opinion may
- incline to the contrary.
- But so inconsistent are men with themselves, that though they often
- assert, that necessity utterly destroys all merit and demerit either
- towards mankind or superior powers, yet they continue still to
- reason upon these very principles of necessity in all their judgments
- concerning this matter. Men are not blamed for such evil actions as they
- perform ignorantly and casually, whatever may be their consequences.
- Why? but because the causes of these actions are only momentary, and
- terminate in them alone. Men are less blamed for such evil actions, as
- they perform hastily and unpremeditately, than for such as proceed from
- thought and deliberation. For what reason? but because a hasty temper,
- though a constant cause in the mind, operates only by intervals, and
- infects not the whole character. Again, repentance wipes off every
- crime, especially if attended with an evident reformation of life and
- manners. How is this to be accounted for? But by asserting that actions
- render a person criminal, merely as they are proofs of criminal
- passions or principles in the mind; and when by any alteration of these
- principles they cease to be just proofs, they likewise cease to be
- criminal. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance they never
- were just proofs, and consequently never were criminal.
- Here then I turn to my adversary, and desire him to free his own system
- from these odious consequences before he charge them upon others. Or if
- he rather chuses, that this question should be decided by fair arguments
- before philosophers, than by declamations before the people, let him
- return to what I have advanced to prove that liberty and chance
- are synonimous; and concerning the nature of moral evidence and the
- regularity of human actions. Upon a review of these reasonings, I
- cannot doubt of an entire victory; and therefore having proved, that all
- actions of the will have particular causes, I proceed to explain what
- these causes are, and how they operate.
- SECT. III OF THE INFLUENCING MOTIVES OF THE WILL
- Nothing is more usual in philosophy, and even in common life, than to
- talk of the combat of passion and reason, to give the preference to
- reason, and assert that men are only so far virtuous as they conform
- themselves to its dictates. Every rational creature, it is said, is
- obliged to regulate his actions by reason; and if any other motive or
- principle challenge the direction of his conduct, he ought to oppose it,
- till it be entirely subdued, or at least brought to a conformity with
- that superior principle. On this method of thinking the greatest part of
- moral philosophy, antient and modern, seems to be founded; nor is
- there an ampler field, as well for metaphysical arguments, as popular
- declamations, than this supposed pre-eminence of reason above passion.
- The eternity, invariableness, and divine origin of the former have
- been displayed to the best advantage: The blindness, unconstancy, and
- deceitfulness of the latter have been as strongly insisted on. In order
- to shew the fallacy of all this philosophy, I shall endeavour to prove
- first, that reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the
- will; and secondly, that it can never oppose passion in the direction of
- the will.
- The understanding exerts itself after two different ways, as it judges
- from demonstration or probability; as it regards the abstract relations
- of our ideas, or those relations of objects, of which experience only
- gives us information. I believe it scarce will be asserted, that the
- first species of reasoning alone is ever the cause of any action. As its
- proper province is the world of ideas, and as the will always places
- us in that of realities, demonstration and volition seem, upon that
- account, to be totally removed, from each other. Mathematics, indeed,
- are useful in all mechanical operations, and arithmetic in almost every
- art and profession: But it is not of themselves they have any influence:
- Mechanics are the art of regulating the motions of bodies to some
- designed end or purpose; and the reason why we employ arithmetic in
- fixing the proportions of numbers, is only that we may discover the
- proportions of their influence and operation. A merchant is desirous of
- knowing the sum total of his accounts with any person: Why? but that he
- may learn what sum will have the same effects in paying his debt, and
- going to market, as all the particular articles taken together. Abstract
- or demonstrative reasoning, therefore, never influences any of our
- actions, but only as it directs our judgment concerning causes and
- effects; which leads us to the second operation of the understanding.
- It is obvious, that when we have the prospect of pain or pleasure from
- any object, we feel a consequent emotion of aversion or propensity,
- and are carryed to avoid or embrace what will give us this uneasines or
- satisfaction. It is also obvious, that this emotion rests not here, but
- making us cast our view on every side, comprehends whatever objects are
- connected with its original one by the relation of cause and effect.
- Here then reasoning takes place to discover this relation; and according
- as our reasoning varies, our actions receive a subsequent variation. But
- it is evident in this case that the impulse arises not from reason, but
- is only directed by it. It is from the prospect of pain or pleasure that
- the aversion or propensity arises towards any object: And these emotions
- extend themselves to the causes and effects of that object, as they are
- pointed out to us by reason and experience. It can never in the least
- concern us to know, that such objects are causes, and such others
- effects, if both the causes and effects be indifferent to us. Where the
- objects themselves do not affect us, their connexion can never give
- them any influence; and it is plain, that as reason is nothing but the
- discovery of this connexion, it cannot be by its means that the objects
- are able to affect us.
- Since reason alone can never produce any action, or give rise to
- volition, I infer, that the same faculty is as incapable of preventing
- volition, or of disputing the preference with any passion or emotion.
- This consequence is necessary. It is impossible reason coued have the
- latter effect of preventing volition, but by giving an impulse in a
- contrary direction to our passion; and that impulse, had it operated
- alone, would have been able to produce volition. Nothing can oppose
- or retard the impulse of passion, but a contrary impulse; and if this
- contrary impulse ever arises from reason, that latter faculty must have
- an original influence on the will, and must be able to cause, as well as
- hinder any act of volition. But if reason has no original influence,
- it is impossible it can withstand any principle, which has such an
- efficacy, or ever keep the mind in suspence a moment. Thus it appears,
- that the principle, which opposes our passion, cannot be the same
- with reason, and is only called so in an improper sense. We speak not
- strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and
- of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions,
- and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey
- them. As this opinion may appear somewhat extraordinary, it may not be
- improper to confirm it by some other considerations.
- A passion is an original existence, or, if you will, modification of
- existence, and contains not any representative quality, which renders
- it a copy of any other existence or modification. When I am angry, I am
- actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no more a
- reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick, or more
- than five foot high. It is impossible, therefore, that this passion
- can be opposed by, or be contradictory to truth and reason; since this
- contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas, considered as
- copies, with those objects, which they represent.
- What may at first occur on this head, is, that as nothing can be
- contrary to truth or reason, except what has a reference to it, and as
- the judgments of our understanding only have this reference, it must
- follow, that passions can be contrary to reason only so far as they are
- accompanyed with some judgment or opinion. According to this principle,
- which is so obvious and natural, it is only in two senses, that any
- affection can be called unreasonable. First, When a passion, such as
- hope or fear, grief or joy, despair or security, is founded on the
- supposition or the existence of objects, which really do not exist.
- Secondly, When in exerting any passion in action, we chuse means
- insufficient for the designed end, and deceive ourselves in our judgment
- of causes and effects. Where a passion is neither founded on
- false suppositions, nor chuses means insufficient for the end, the
- understanding can neither justify nor condemn it. It is not contrary to
- reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of
- my finger. It is not contrary to reason for me to chuse my total ruin,
- to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian or person wholly unknown
- to me. It is as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own
- acknowledgeed lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent
- affection for the former than the latter. A trivial good may, from
- certain circumstances, produce a desire superior to what arises from
- the greatest and most valuable enjoyment; nor is there any thing more
- extraordinary in this, than in mechanics to see one pound weight raise
- up a hundred by the advantage of its situation. In short, a passion
- must be accompanyed with some false judgment in order to its being
- unreasonable; and even then it is not the passion, properly speaking,
- which is unreasonable, but the judgment.
- The consequences are evident. Since a passion can never, in any sense,
- be called unreasonable, but when founded on a false supposition or when
- it chuses means insufficient for the designed end, it is impossible,
- that reason and passion can ever oppose each other, or dispute for the
- government of the will and actions. The moment we perceive the falshood
- of any supposition, or the insufficiency of any means our passions yield
- to our reason without any opposition. I may desire any fruit as of an
- excellent relish; but whenever you convince me of my mistake, my longing
- ceases. I may will the performance of certain actions as means of
- obtaining any desired good; but as my willing of these actions is only
- secondary, and founded on the supposition, that they are causes of the
- proposed effect; as soon as I discover the falshood of that supposition,
- they must become indifferent to me.
- It is natural for one, that does not examine objects with a strict
- philosophic eye, to imagine, that those actions of the mind are
- entirely the same, which produce not a different sensation, and are not
- immediately distinguishable to the feeling and perception. Reason, for
- instance, exerts itself without producing any sensible emotion; and
- except in the more sublime disquisitions of philosophy, or in the
- frivolous subtilties of the school, scarce ever conveys any pleasure
- or uneasiness. Hence it proceeds, that every action of the mind, which
- operates with the same calmness and tranquillity, is confounded with
- reason by all those, who judge of things from the first view and
- appearance. Now it is certain, there are certain calm desires and
- tendencies, which, though they be real passions, produce little emotion
- in the mind, and are more known by their effects than by the immediate
- feeling or sensation. These desires are of two kinds; either certain
- instincts originally implanted in our natures, such as benevolence and
- resentment, the love of life, and kindness to children; or the general
- appetite to good, and aversion to evil, considered merely as such. When
- any of these passions are calm, and cause no disorder in the soul,
- they are very readily taken for the determinations of reason, and are
- supposed to proceed from the same faculty, with that, which judges of
- truth and falshood. Their nature and principles have been supposed the
- same, because their sensations are not evidently different.
- Beside these calm passions, which often determine the will, there are
- certain violent emotions of the same kind, which have likewise a great
- influence on that faculty. When I receive any injury from another, I
- often feel a violent passion of resentment, which makes me desire his
- evil and punishment, independent of all considerations of pleasure and
- advantage to myself. When I am immediately threatened with any grievous
- ill, my fears, apprehensions, and aversions rise to a great height, and
- produce a sensible emotion.
- The common error of metaphysicians has lain in ascribing the direction
- of the will entirely to one of these principles, and supposing the other
- to have no influence. Men often act knowingly against their interest:
- For which reason the view of the greatest possible good does not always
- influence them. Men often counter-act a violent passion in prosecution
- of their interests and designs: It is not therefore the present
- uneasiness alone, which determines them. In general we may observe, that
- both these principles operate on the will; and where they are contrary,
- that either of them prevails, according to the general character or
- present disposition of the person. What we call strength of mind,
- implies the prevalence of the calm passions above the violent; though
- we may easily observe, there is no man so constantly possessed of this
- virtue, as never on any occasion to yield to the sollicitations of
- passion and desire. From these variations of temper proceeds the great
- difficulty of deciding concerning the actions and resolutions of men,
- where there is any contrariety of motives and passions.
- SECT. IV OF THE CAUSES OF THE VIOLENT PASSIONS
- There is not-in philosophy a subject of more nice speculation than this
- of the different causes and effects of the calm and violent passions.
- It is evident passions influence not the will in proportion to their
- violence, or the disorder they occasion in the temper; but on the
- contrary, that when a passion has once become a settled principle of
- action, and is the predominant inclination of the soul, it commonly
- produces no longer any sensible agitation. As repeated custom and its
- own force have made every thing yield to it, it directs the actions and
- conduct without that opposition and emotion, which so naturally attend
- every momentary gust of passion. We must, therefore, distinguish betwixt
- a calm and a weak passion; betwixt a violent and a strong one. But
- notwithstanding this, it is certain, that when we would govern a man,
- and push him to any action, it will commonly be better policy to work
- upon the violent than the calm passions, and rather take him by his
- inclination, than what is vulgarly called his reason. We ought to place
- the object in such particular situations as are proper to encrease the
- violence of the passion. For we may observe, that all depends upon the
- situation of the object, and that a variation in this particular will be
- able to change the calm and the violent passions into each other. Both
- these kinds of passions pursue good, and avoid evil; and both of them
- are encreased or diminished by the encrease or diminution of the good or
- evil. But herein lies the difference betwixt them: The same good, when
- near, will cause a violent passion, which, when remote, produces only a
- calm one. As this subject belongs very properly to the present question
- concerning the will, we shall here examine it to the bottom, and shall
- consider some of those circumstances and situations of objects, which
- render a passion either calm or violent.
- It is a remarkable property of human nature, that any emotion, which
- attends a passion, is easily converted into it, though in their natures
- they be originally different from, and even contrary to each other.
- It is true; in order to make a perfect union among passions, there is
- always required a double relation of impressions and ideas; nor is one
- relation sufficient for that purpose. But though this be confirmed by
- undoubted experience, we must understand it with its proper limitations,
- and must regard the double relation, as requisite only to make one
- passion produce another. When two passions are already produced by their
- separate causes, and are both present in the mind, they readily mingle
- and unite, though they have but one relation, and sometimes without any.
- The predominant passion swallows up the inferior, and converts it into
- itself. The spirits, when once excited, easily receive a change in their
- direction; and it is natural to imagine this change will come from the
- prevailing affection. The connexion is in many respects closer betwixt
- any two passions, than betwixt any passion and indifference.
- When a person is once heartily in love, the little faults and caprices
- of his mistress, the jealousies and quarrels, to which that commerce is
- so subject; however unpleasant and related to anger and hatred; are yet
- found to give additional force to the prevailing passion. It is a common
- artifice of politicians, when they would affect any person very much by
- a matter of fact, of which they intend to inform him, first to excite
- his curiosity; delay as long as possible the satisfying it; and by that
- means raise his anxiety and impatience to the utmost, before they give
- him a full insight into the business. They know that his curiosity will
- precipitate him into the passion they design to raise, and assist the
- object in its influence on the mind. A soldier advancing to the battle,
- is naturally inspired with courage and confidence, when he thinks on his
- friends and fellow-soldiers; and is struck with fear and terror, when
- he reflects on the enemy. Whatever new emotion, therefore, proceeds
- from the former naturally encreases the courage; as the same emotion,
- proceeding from the latter, augments the fear; by the relation of ideas,
- and the conversion of the inferior emotion into the predominant. Hence
- it is that in martial discipline, the uniformity and lustre of our
- habit, the regularity of our figures and motions, with all the pomp and
- majesty of war, encourage ourselves and allies; while the same objects
- in the enemy strike terror into us, though agreeable and beautiful in
- themselves.
- Since passions, however independent, are naturally transfused into each
- other, if they are both present at the same time; it follows, that when
- good or evil is placed in such a situation, as to cause any particular
- emotion, beside its direct passion of desire or aversion, that latter
- passion must acquire new force and violence.
- This happens, among other cases, whenever any object excites contrary
- passions. For it is observable that an opposition of passions commonly
- causes a new emotion in the spirits, and produces more disorder, than
- the concurrence of any two affections of equal force. This new emotion
- is easily converted into the predominant passion, and encreases its
- violence, beyond the pitch it would have arrived at had it met with
- no opposition. Hence we naturally desire what is forbid, and take a
- pleasure in performing actions, merely because they are unlawful.
- The notion of duty, when opposite to the passions, is seldom able
- to overcome them; and when it fails of that effect, is apt rather to
- encrease them, by producing an opposition in our motives and principles.
- The same effect follows whether the opposition arises from internal
- motives or external obstacles. The passion commonly acquires new force
- and violence in both cases.
- The efforts, which the mind makes to surmount the obstacle, excite the
- spirits and inliven the passion.
- Uncertainty has the same influence as opposition. The agitation of the
- thought; the quick turns it makes from one view to another; the variety
- of passions, which succeed each other, according to the different views;
- All these produce an agitation in the mind, and transfuse themselves
- into the predominant passion.
- There is not in my opinion any other natural cause, why security
- diminishes the passions, than because it removes that uncertainty, which
- encreases them. The mind, when left to itself, immediately languishes;
- and in order to preserve its ardour, must be every moment supported by
- a new flow of passion. For the same reason, despair, though contrary to
- security, has a like influence.
- It is certain nothing more powerfully animates any affection, than to
- conceal some part of its object by throwing it into a kind of shade,
- which at the same time that it chews enough to pre-possess us in favour
- of the object, leaves still some work for the imagination. Besides that
- obscurity is always attended with a kind of uncertainty; the effort,
- which the fancy makes to compleat the idea, rouzes the spirits, and
- gives an additional force to the passion.
- As despair and security, though contrary to each other, produce the
- same effects; so absence is observed to have contrary effects, and in
- different circumstances either encreases or diminishes our affections.
- The Duc de La Rochefoucault has very well observed, that absence
- destroys weak passions, but encreases strong; as the wind extinguishes
- a candle, but blows up a fire. Long absence naturally weakens our idea,
- and diminishes the passion: But where the idea is so strong and lively
- as to support itself, the uneasiness, arising from absence, encreases
- the passion and gives it new force and violence.
- SECT. V OF THE EFFECTS OF CUSTOM
- But nothing has a greater effect both to encrease and diminish our
- passions, to convert pleasure into pain, and pain into pleasure, than
- custom and repetition. Custom has two original effects upon the mind, in
- bestowing a facility in the performance of any action or the conception
- of any object; and afterwards a tendency or inclination towards it;
- and from these we may account for all its other effects, however
- extraordinary.
- When the soul applies itself to the performance of any action, or the
- conception of any object, to which it is not accustomed, there is a
- certain unpliableness in the faculties, and a difficulty of the spirit's
- moving in their new direction. As this difficulty excites the spirits,
- it is the source of wonder, surprize, and of all the emotions, which
- arise from novelty; and is in itself very agreeable, like every thing,
- which inlivens the mind to a moderate degree. But though surprize be
- agreeable in itself, yet as it puts the spirits in agitation, it not
- only augments our agreeable affections, but also our painful, according
- to the foregoing principle, that every emotion, which precedes or
- attends a passion, is easily converted into it. Hence every thing, that
- is new, is most affecting, and gives us either more pleasure or pain,
- than what, strictly speaking, naturally belongs to it. When it often
- returns upon us, the novelty wears off; the passions subside; the
- hurry of the spirits is over; and we survey the objects with greater
- tranquillity.
- By degrees the repetition produces a facility of the human mind, and
- an infallible source of pleasure, where the facility goes not beyond
- a certain degree. And here it is remarkable that the pleasure, which
- arises from a moderate facility, has not the same tendency with that
- which arises from novelty, to augment the painful, as well as the
- agreeable affections. The pleasure of facility does not so much consist
- in any ferment of the spirits, as in their orderly motion; which will
- sometimes be so powerful as even to convert pain into pleasure, and give
- us a relish in time what at first was most harsh and disagreeable.
- But again, as facility converts pain into pleasure, so it often converts
- pleasure into pain, when it is too great, and renders the actions of the
- mind so faint and languid, that they are no longer able to interest and
- support it. And indeed, scarce any other objects become disagreeable
- through custom; but such as are naturally attended with some emotion or
- affection, which is destroyed by the too frequent repetition. One
- can consider the clouds, and heavens, and trees, and stones, however
- frequently repeated, without ever feeling any aversion. But when the
- fair sex, or music, or good cheer, or any thing, that naturally ought
- to be agreeable, becomes indifferent, it easily produces the opposite
- affection.
- But custom not only gives a facility to perform any action, but likewise
- an inclination and tendency towards it, where it is not entirely
- disagreeable, and can never be the object of inclination. And this
- is the reason why custom encreases all active habits, but diminishes
- passive, according to the observation of a late eminent philosopher. The
- facility takes off from the force of the passive habits by rendering
- the motion of the spirits faint and languid. But as in the active, the
- spirits are sufficiently supported of themselves, the tendency of the
- mind gives them new force, and bends them more strongly to the action.
- SECT. VI OF THE INFLUENCE OF THE IMAGINATION ON THE PASSIONS
- It is remarkable, that the imagination and affections have close union
- together, and that nothing, which affects the former, can be entirely
- indifferent to the latter. Wherever our ideas of good or evil acquire a
- new vivacity, the passions become more violent; and keep pace with
- the imagination in all its variations. Whether this proceeds from
- the principle above-mentioned, that any attendant emotion is easily
- converted into the predominant, I shall not determine. It is sufficient
- for my present purpose, that we have many instances to confirm this
- influence of the imagination upon the passions.
- Any pleasure, with which we are acquainted, affects us more than any
- other, which we own to be superior, but of whose nature we are wholly
- ignorant. Of the one we can form a particular and determinate idea:
- The other we conceive under the general notion of pleasure; and it is
- certain, that the more general and universal any of our ideas are, the
- less influence they have upon the imagination. A general idea, though
- it be nothing but a particular one considered in a certain view, is
- commonly more obscure; and that because no particular idea, by which we
- represent a general one, is ever fixed or determinate, but may easily
- be changed for other particular ones, which will serve equally in the
- representation.
- There is a noted passage in the history of Greece, which may serve for
- our present purpose. Themistocles told the Athenians, that he had formed
- a design, which would be highly useful to the public, but which it was
- impossible for him to communicate to them without ruining the execution,
- since its success depended entirely on the secrecy with which it should
- be conducted. The Athenians, instead of granting him full power to
- act as he thought fitting, ordered him to communicate his design to
- Aristides, in whose prudence they had an entire confidence, and
- whose opinion they were resolved blindly to submit to. The design of
- Themistocles was secretly to set fire to the fleet of all the Grecian
- commonwealths, which was assembled in a neighbouring port, and which
- being once destroyed would give the Athenians the empire of the sea
- without any rival Aristides returned to the assembly, and told them,
- that nothing coued be more advantageous than the design of Themistocles
- but at the same time that nothing coued be more unjust: Upon which the
- people unanimously rejected the project.
- A late celebrated historian [Mons. Rollin {Charles Rollin, HISTOIRE
- ANCIENNE.(Paris 1730-38)}.] admires this passage of antient history, as
- one of the most singular that is any where to be met.
- "Here," says he, "they are not philosophers, to whom it is easy in
- their schools to establish the finest maxims and most sublime rules of
- morality, who decide that interest ought never to prevail above justice.
- It is a whole people interested in the proposal which is made to
- them, who consider it as of importance to the public good, and who
- notwithstanding reject it unanimously, and without hesitation, merely
- because it is contrary to justice."
- For my part I see nothing so extraordinary in this proceeding of the
- Athenians. The same reasons, which render it so easy for philosophers to
- establish these sublime maxims, tend, in part, to diminish the merit
- of such a conduct in that people. Philosophers never ballance betwixt
- profit and honesty, because their decisions are general, and neither
- their passions nor imaginations are interested in the objects. And
- though in the present case the advantage was immediate to the Athenians,
- yet as it was known only under the general notion of advantage,
- without being conceived by any particular idea, it must have had a
- less considerable influence on their imaginations, and have been a
- less violent temptation, than if they had been acquainted with all
- its circumstances: Otherwise it is difficult to conceive, that a whole
- people, unjust and violent as men commonly are, should so unanimously
- have adhered to justice, and rejected any considerable advantage.
- Any satisfaction, which we lately enjoyed, and of which the memory is
- fresh and recent, operates on the will with more violence, than another
- of which the traces are decayed, and almost obliterated. From whence
- does this proceed, but that the memory in the first case assists the
- fancy and gives an additional force and vigour to its conceptions?
- The image of the past pleasure being strong and violent, bestows these
- qualities on the idea of the future pleasure, which is connected with it
- by the relation of resemblance.
- A pleasure, which is suitable to the way of life, in which we are
- engaged, excites more our desires and appetites than another, which
- is foreign to it. This phaenomenon may be explained from the same
- principle.
- Nothing is more capable of infusing any passion into the mind, than
- eloquence, by which objects are represented in their strongest and most
- lively colours. We may of ourselves acknowledge, that such an object
- is valuable, and such another odious; but until an orator excites the
- imagination, and gives force to these ideas, they may have but a feeble
- influence either on the will or the affections.
- But eloquence is not always necessary. The bare opinion of another,
- especially when inforced with passion, will cause an idea of good or
- evil to have an influence upon us, which would otherwise have been
- entirely neglected. This proceeds from the principle of sympathy or
- communication; and sympathy, as I have already observed, is nothing
- but the conversion of an idea into an impression by the force of
- imagination.
- It is remarkable, that lively passions commonly attend a lively
- imagination. In this respect, as well as others, the force of the
- passion depends as much on the temper of the person, as the nature or
- situation of the object.
- I have already observed, that belief is nothing but a lively idea
- related to a present impression. This vivacity is a requisite
- circumstance to the exciting all our passions, the calm as well as the
- violent; nor has a mere fiction of the imagination any considerable
- influence upon either of them. It is too weak to take hold of the mind,
- or be attended with emotion.
- SECT. VII OF CONTIGUITY AND DISTANCE IN SPACE AND TIME
- There is an easy reason, why every thing contiguous to us, either in
- space or time, should be conceived with a peculiar force and vivacity,
- and excel every other object, in its influence on the imagination.
- Ourself is intimately present to us, and whatever is related to self
- must partake of that quality. But where an object is so far removed
- as to have lost the advantage of this relation, why, as it is farther
- removed, its idea becomes still fainter and more obscure, would,
- perhaps, require a more particular examination.
- It is obvious, that the imagination can never totally forget the points
- of space and time, in which we are existent; but receives such frequent
- advertisements of them from the passions and senses, that however it
- may turn its attention to foreign and remote objects, it is necessitated
- every moment to reflect on the present. IOt is also remarkable, that in
- the conception of those objects, which we regard as real and existent,
- we take them in their proper order and situation, and never leap from
- one object to another, which is distant from it, without running over,
- at least in a cursory manner, all those objects, which are interposed
- betwixt them. When we reflect, therefore, on any object distant from
- ourselves, we are obliged not only to reach it at first by passing
- through all the intermediate space betwixt ourselves and the object, but
- also to renew our progress every moment; being every moment recalled to
- the consideration of ourselves and our present situation. It is easily
- conceived, that this interruption must weaken the idea by breaking the
- action of the mind, and hindering the conception from being so intense
- and continued, as when we reflect on a nearer object. The fewer steps
- we make to arrive at the object, and the smoother the road is, this
- diminution of vivacity is less sensibly felt, but still may be observed
- more or less in proportion to the degrees of distance and difficulty.
- Here then we are to consider two kinds of objects, the contiguous and
- remote; of which the former, by means of their relation to ourselves,
- approach an impression in force and vivacity; the latter by reason of
- the interruption in our manner of conceiving them, appear in a weaker
- and more imperfect light. This is their effect on the imagination. If
- my reasoning be just, they must have a proportionable effect on the will
- and passions. Contiguous objects must have an influence much superior to
- the distant and remote. Accordingly we find in common life, that men are
- principally concerned about those objects, which are not much removed
- either in space or time, enjoying the present, and leaving what is afar
- off to the care of chance and fortune. Talk to a man of his condition
- thirty years hence, and he will not regard you. Speak of what is to
- happen tomorrow, and he will lend you attention. The breaking of a
- mirror gives us more concern when at home, than the burning of a house,
- when abroad, and some hundred leagues distant.
- But farther; though distance both in space and time has a considerable
- effect on the imagination, and by that means on the will and passions,
- yet the consequence of a removal in space are much inferior to those of
- a removal in time. Twenty years are certainly but a small distance
- of time in comparison of what history and even the memory of some may
- inform them of, and yet I doubt if a thousand leagues, or even the
- greatest distance of place this globe can admit of, will so remarkably
- weaken our ideas, and diminish our passions. A West-Indian merchant will
- tell you, that he is not without concern about what passes in Jamaica;
- though few extend their views so far into futurity, as to dread very
- remote accidents.
- The cause of this phaenomenon must evidently lie in the different
- properties of space and time. Without having recourse to metaphysics,
- any one may easily observe, that space or extension consists of a number
- of co-existent parts disposed in a certain order, and capable of being
- at once present to the sight or feeling. On the contrary, time or
- succession, though it consists likewise of parts, never presents to us
- more than one at once; nor is it possible for any two of them ever to
- be co-existent. These qualities of the objects have a suitable effect on
- the imagination. The parts of extension being susceptible of an union to
- the senses, acquire an union in the fancy; and as the appearance of
- one part excludes not another, the transition or passage of the thought
- through the contiguous parts is by that means rendered more smooth and
- easy. On the other hand, the incompatibility of the parts of time in
- their real existence separates them in the imagination, and makes it
- more difficult for that faculty to trace any long succession or series
- of events. Every part must appear single and alone, nor can regularly
- have entrance into the fancy without banishing what is supposed to have
- been immediately precedent. By this means any distance in time causes a
- greater interruption in the thought than an equal distance in space, and
- consequently weakens more considerably the idea, and consequently the
- passions; which depend in a great measure, on the imagination, according
- to my system.
- There is another phaenomenon of a like nature with the foregoing, viz,
- the superior effects of the same distance in futurity above that in the
- past. This difference with respect to the will is easily accounted for.
- As none of our actions can alter the past, it is not strange it should
- never determine the will. But with respect to the passions the question
- is yet entire, and well worth the examining.
- Besides the propensity to a gradual progression through the points of
- space and time, we have another peculiarity in our method of thinking,
- which concurs in producing this phaenomenon. We always follow the
- succession of time in placing our ideas, and from the consideration of
- any object pass more easily to that, which follows immediately after
- it, than to that which went before it. We may learn this, among other
- instances, from the order, which is always observed in historical
- narrations. Nothing but an absolute necessity can oblige an historian to
- break the order of time, and in his narration give the precedence to an
- event, which was in reality posterior to another.
- This will easily be applied to the question in hand, if we reflect on
- what I have before observed, that the present situation of the person is
- always that of the imagination, and that it is from thence we proceed
- to the conception of any distant object. When the object is past, the
- progression of the thought in passing to it from the present is contrary
- to nature, as proceeding from one point of time to that which is
- preceding, and from that to another preceding, in opposition to the
- natural course of the succession. On the other hand, when we turn our
- thought to a future object, our fancy flows along the stream of time,
- and arrives at the object by an order, which seems most natural, passing
- always from one point of time to that which is immediately posterior to
- it. This easy progression of ideas favours the imagination, and makes
- it conceive its object in a stronger and fuller light, than when we
- are continually opposed in our passage, and are obliged to overcome the
- difficulties arising from the natural propensity of the fancy. A small
- degree of distance in the past has, therefore, a greater effect, in
- interupting and weakening the conception, than a much greater in
- the future. From this effect of it on the imagination is derived its
- influence on the will and passions.
- There is another cause, which both contributes to the same effect, and
- proceeds from the same quality of the fancy, by which we are determined
- to trace the succession of time by a similar succession of ideas. When
- from the present instant we consider two points of time equally distant
- in the future and in the past, it is evident, that, abstractedly
- considered, their relation to the present is almost equal. For as the
- future will sometime be present, so the past was once present. If we
- coued, therefore, remove this quality of the imagination, an equal
- distance in the past and in the future, would have a similar influence.
- Nor is this only true, when the fancy remains fixed, and from the
- present instant surveys the future and the past; but also when it
- changes its situation, and places us in different periods of time. For
- as on the one hand, in supposing ourselves existent in a point of time
- interposed betwixt the present instant and the future object, we find
- the future object approach to us, and the past retire, and become more
- distant: so on the other hand, in supposing ourselves existent in a
- point of time interposed betwixt the present and the past, the past
- approaches to us, and the future becomes more distant. But from the
- property of the fancy above-mentioned we rather chuse to fix our thought
- on the point of time interposed betwixt the present and the future, than
- on that betwixt the present and the past. We advance, rather than retard
- our existence; and following what seems the natural succession of time,
- proceed from past to present, and from present to future. By which means
- we conceive the future as flowing every moment nearer us, and the
- past as retiring. An equal distance, therefore, in the past and in the
- future, has not the same effect on the imagination; and that because we
- consider the one as continually encreasing, and the other as continually
- diminishing. The fancy anticipates the course of things, and surveys the
- object in that condition, to which it tends, as well as in that, which
- is regarded as the present.
- SECT. VIII THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUed
- Thus we have accounted for three phaenomena, which seem pretty
- remarkable. Why distance weakens the conception and passion: Why
- distance in time has a greater effect than that in space: And why
- distance in past time has still a greater effect than that in future. We
- must now consider three phaenomena, which seem to be, in a manner, the
- reverse of these: Why a very great distance encreases our esteem and
- admiration for an object; Why such a distance in time encreases it
- more than that in space: And a distance in past time more than that in
- future. The curiousness of the subject will, I hope, excuse my dwelling
- on it for some time.
- To begin with the first phaenomenon, why a great distance encreases our
- esteem and admiration for an object; it is evident that the mere view
- and contemplation of any greatness, whether successive or extended,
- enlarges the soul, and give it a sensible delight and pleasure. A wide
- plain, the ocean, eternity, a succession of several ages; all these are
- entertaining objects, and excel every thing, however beautiful, which
- accompanies not its beauty with a suitable greatness. Now when any very
- distant object is presented to the imagination, we naturally reflect on
- the interposed distance, and by that means, conceiving something great
- and magnificent, receive the usual satisfaction. But as the fancy passes
- easily from one idea to another related to it, and transports to the
- second all the passions excited by the first, the admiration, which is
- directed to the distance, naturally diffuses itself over the distant
- object. Accordingly we find, that it is not necessary the object should
- be actually distant from us, in order to cause our admiration; but that
- it is sufficient, if, by the natural association of ideas, it conveys
- our view to any considerable distance. A great traveller, though in
- the same chamber, will pass for a very extraordinary person; as a Greek
- medal, even in our cabinet, is always esteemed a valuable curiosity.
- Here the object, by a natural transition, conveys our views to the
- distance; and the admiration, which arises from that distance, by
- another natural transition, returns back to the object.
- But though every great distance produces an admiration for the distant
- object, a distance in time has a more considerable effect than that in
- space. Antient busts and inscriptions are more valued than Japan tables:
- And not to mention the Greeks and Romans, it is certain we regard with
- more veneration the old Chaldeans and Egyptians, than the modern Chinese
- and Persians, and bestow more fruitless pains to dear up the history and
- chronology of the former, than it would cost us to make a voyage, and
- be certainly informed of the character, learning and government of the
- latter. I shall be obliged to make a digression in order to explain this
- phaenomenon.
- It is a quality very observable in human nature, that any opposition,
- which does not entirely discourage and intimidate us, has rather a
- contrary effect, and inspires us with a more than ordinary grandeur
- and magnanimity. In collecting our force to overcome the opposition, we
- invigorate the soul, and give it an elevation with which otherwise it
- would never have been acquainted. Compliance, by rendering our strength
- useless, makes us insensible of it: but opposition awakens and employs
- it.
- This is also true in the universe. Opposition not only enlarges the
- soul; but the soul, when full of courage and magnanimity, in a manner
- seeks opposition.
- SPUMANTEMQUE DARI PECORA INTER INERTIA VOTIS OPTAT APRUM, AUT FULVUM
- DESCENDERE MONTE LEONEM.
- [And, among the tamer beasts, [he] longs to be granted, in answer to his
- prayers, a slavering boar, or to have a tawny lion come down from the
- mountain.]
- Whatever supports and fills the passions is agreeable to us; as on the
- contrary, what weakens and infeebles them is uneasy. As opposition
- has the first effect, and facility the second, no wonder the mind, in
- certain dispositions, desires the former, and is averse to the latter.
- These principles have an effect on the imagination as well as on the
- passions. To be convinced of this we need only consider the influence
- of heights and depths on that faculty. Any great elevation of place
- communicates a kind of pride or sublimity of imagination, and gives
- a fancyed superiority over those that lie below; and, vice versa, a
- sublime and strong imagination conveys the idea of ascent and elevation.
- Hence it proceeds, that we associate, in a manner, the idea of whatever
- is good with that of height, and evil with lowness. Heaven is supposed
- to be above, and hell below. A noble genius is called an elevate and
- sublime one. ATQUE UDAM SPERNIT HUMUM FUGIENTE PENNA. [Spurns the dank
- soil in winged flight.] On the contrary, a vulgar and trivial conception
- is stiled indifferently low or mean. Prosperity is denominated ascent,
- and adversity descent. Kings and princes are supposed to be placed at
- the top of human affairs; as peasants and day-labourers are said to be
- in the lowest stations. These methods of thinking, and of expressing
- ourselves, are not of so little consequence as they may appear at first
- sight.
- It is evident to common sense, as well as philosophy, that there is no
- natural nor essential difference betwixt high and low, and that this
- distinction arises only from the gravitation of matter, which produces a
- motion from the one to the other. The very same direction, which in
- this part of the globe is called ascent, is denominated descent in our
- antipodes; which can proceed from nothing but the contrary tendency
- of bodies. Now it is certain, that the tendency of bodies, continually
- operating upon our senses, must produce, from custom, a like tendency in
- the fancy, and that when we consider any object situated in an ascent,
- the idea of its weight gives us a propensity to transport it from the
- place, in which it is situated, to the place immediately below it, and
- so on, until we come to the ground, which equally stops the body and
- our imagination. For a like reason we feel a difficulty in mounting, and
- pass not without a kind of reluctance from the inferior to that which is
- situated above it; as if our ideas acquired a kind of gravity from their
- objects. As a proof of this, do we not find, that the facility, which
- is so much studyed in music and poetry, is called the fail or cadency of
- the harmony or period; the idea of facility communicating to us that of
- descent, in the same manner as descent produces a facility?
- Since the imagination, therefore, in running from low to high, finds an
- opposition in its internal qualities and principles, and since the soul,
- when elevated with joy and courage, in a manner seeks opposition, and
- throws itself with alacrity into any scene of thought or action, where
- its courage meets with matter to nourish and employ it; it follows, that
- everything, which invigorates and inlivens the soul, whether by touching
- the passions or imagination naturally conveys to the fancy this
- inclination for ascent, and determines it to run against the natural
- stream of its thoughts and conceptions. This aspiring progress of
- the imagination suits the present disposition of the mind; and the
- difficulty, instead of extinguishing its vigour and alacrity, has the
- contrary affect, of sustaining and encreasing it. Virtue, genius, power,
- and riches are for this reason associated with height and sublimity; as
- poverty, slavery, and folly are conjoined with descent and lowness. Were
- the case the same with us as Milton represents it to be with the angels,
- to whom descent is adverse, and who cannot sink without labour and
- compulsion, this order of things would be entirely inverted; as appears
- hence, that the very nature of ascent and descent is derived from the
- difficulty and propensity, and consequently every one of their effects
- proceeds from that origin.
- All this is easily applied to the present question, why a considerable
- distance in time produces a greater veneration for the distant objects
- than a like removal in space. The imagination moves with more difficulty
- in passing from one portion of time to another, than in a transition
- through the parts of space; and that because space or extension appears
- united to our senses, while time or succession is always broken and
- divided. This difficulty, when joined with a small distance, interrupts
- and weakens the fancy: But has a contrary effect in a great removal. The
- mind, elevated by the vastness of its object, is still farther elevated
- by the difficulty of the conception; and being obliged every moment to
- renew its efforts in the transition from one part of time to another,
- feels a more vigorous and sublime disposition, than in a transition
- through the parts of space, where the ideas flow along with easiness and
- facility. In this disposition, the imagination, passing, as is usual,
- from the consideration of the distance to the view of the distant
- objects, gives us a proportionable veneration for it; and this is the
- reason why all the relicts of antiquity are so precious in our eyes, and
- appear more valuable than what is brought even from the remotest parts
- of the world.
- The third phaenomenon I have remarked will be a full confirmation of
- this. It is not every removal in time, which has the effect of producing
- veneration and esteem. We are not apt to imagine our posterity
- will excel us, or equal our ancestors. This phaenomenon is the more
- remarkable, because any distance in futurity weakens not our ideas so
- much as an equal removal in the past. Though a removal in the past, when
- very great, encreases our passions beyond a like removal in the future,
- yet a small removal has a greater influence in diminishing them.
- In our common way of thinking we are placed in a kind of middle station
- betwixt the past and future; and as our imagination finds a kind of
- difficulty in running along the former, and a facility in following the
- course of the latter, the difficulty conveys the notion of ascent, and
- the facility of the contrary. Hence we imagine our ancestors to be, in
- a manner, mounted above us, and our posterity to lie below us. Our fancy
- arrives not at the one without effort, but easily reaches the other:
- Which effort weakens the conception, where the distance is small; but
- enlarges and elevates the imagination, when attended with a suitable
- object. As on the other hand, the facility assists the fancy in a
- small removal, but takes off from its force when it contemplates any
- considerable distance.
- It may not be improper, before we leave this subject of the will, to
- resume, in a few words, all that has been said concerning it, in order
- to set the whole more distinctly before the eyes of the reader. What
- we commonly understand by passion is a violent and sensible emotion of
- mind, when any good or evil is presented, or any object, which, by the
- original formation of our faculties, is fitted to excite an appetite.
- By reason we mean affections of the very same kind with the former; but
- such as operate more calmly, and cause no disorder in the temper: Which
- tranquillity leads us into a mistake concerning them, and causes us to
- regard them as conclusions only of our intellectual faculties. Both
- the causes and effects of these violent and calm passions are pretty
- variable, and depend, in a great measure, on the peculiar temper
- and disposition of every individual. Generally speaking, the violent
- passions have a more powerful influence on the will; though it is often
- found, that the calm ones, when corroborated by reflection, and
- seconded by resolution, are able to controul them in their most furious
- movements. What makes this whole affair more uncertain, is, that a calm
- passion may easily be changed into a violent one, either by a change of
- temper, or of the circumstances and situation of the object, as by the
- borrowing of force from any attendant passion, by custom, or by exciting
- the imagination. Upon the whole, this struggle of passion and of reason,
- as it is called, diversifies human life, and makes men so different
- not only from each other, but also from themselves in different times.
- Philosophy can only account for a few of the greater and more sensible
- events of this war; but must leave all the smaller and more delicate
- revolutions, as dependent on principles too fine and minute for her
- comprehension.
- SECT. IX OF THE DIRECT PASSIONS
- It is easy to observe, that the passions, both direct and indirect, are
- founded on pain and pleasure, and that in order to produce an affection
- of any kind, it is only requisite to present some good or evil. Upon the
- removal of pain and pleasure there immediately follows a removal of love
- and hatred, pride and humility, desire and aversion, and of most of our
- reflective or secondary impressions.
- The impressions, which arise from good and evil most naturally, and with
- the least preparation are the direct passions of desire and aversion,
- grief and joy, hope and fear, along with volition. The mind by an
- original instinct tends to unite itself with the good, and to avoid the
- evil, though they be conceived merely in idea, and be considered as to
- exist in any future period of time.
- But supposing that there is an immediate impression of pain or pleasure,
- and that arising from an object related to ourselves or others, this
- does not prevent the propensity or aversion, with the consequent
- emotions, but by concurring with certain dormant principles of the human
- mind, excites the new impressions of pride or humility, love or hatred.
- That propensity, which unites us to the object, or separates us from
- it, still continues to operate, but in conjunction with the indirect
- passions, which arise from a double relation of impressions and ideas.
- These indirect passions, being always agreeable or uneasy, give in their
- turn additional force to the direct passions, and encrease our desire
- and aversion to the object. Thus a suit of fine cloaths produces
- pleasure from their beauty; and this pleasure produces the direct
- passions, or the impressions of volition and desire. Again, when these
- cloaths are considered as belonging to ourself, the double relation
- conveys to us the sentiment of pride, which is an indirect passion; and
- the pleasure, which attends that passion, returns back to the direct
- affections, and gives new force to our desire or volition, joy or hope.
- When good is certain or probable, it produces joy. When evil is in the
- same situation there arises GRIEF or SORROW.
- When either good or evil is uncertain, it gives rise to FEAR or HOPE,
- according to the degrees of uncertainty on the one side or the other.
- DESIRE arises from good considered simply, and AVERSION is derived from
- evil. The WILL exerts itself, when either the good or the absence of the
- evil may be attained by any action of the mind or body.
- Beside good and evil, or in other words, pain and pleasure, the direct
- passions frequently arise from a natural impulse or instinct, which is
- perfectly unaccountable. Of this kind is the desire of punishment to our
- enemies, and of happiness to our friends; hunger, lust, and a few other
- bodily appetites. These passions, properly speaking, produce good and
- evil, and proceed not from them, like the other affections.
- None of the direct affections seem to merit our particular attention,
- except hope and fear, which we shall here endeavour to account for.
- It is evident that the very same event, which by its certainty would
- produce grief or joy, gives always rise to fear or hope, when only
- probable and uncertain. In order, therefore, to understand the reason
- why this circumstance makes such a considerable difference, we must
- reflect on what I have already advanced in the preceding book concerning
- the nature of probability.
- Probability arises from an opposition of contrary chances or causes, by
- which the mind is not allowed to fix on either side, but is incessantly
- tost from one to another, and at one moment is determined to consider
- an object as existent, and at another moment as the contrary. The
- imagination or understanding, call it which you please, fluctuates
- betwixt the opposite views; and though perhaps it may be oftener turned
- to the one side than the other, it is impossible for it, by reason of
- the opposition of causes or chances, to rest on either. The pro and con
- of the question alternately prevail; and the mind, surveying the object
- in its opposite principles, finds such a contrariety as utterly destroys
- all certainty and established opinion.
- Suppose, then, that the object, concerning whose reality we are
- doubtful, is an object either of desire or aversion, it is evident,
- that, according as the mind turns itself either to the one side or the
- other, it must feel a momentary impression of joy or sorrow. An object,
- whose existence we desire, gives satisfaction, when we reflect on those
- causes, which produce it; and for the same reason excites grief
- or uneasiness from the opposite consideration: So that as the
- understanding, in all probable questions, is divided betwixt the
- contrary points of view, the affections must in the same manner be
- divided betwixt opposite emotions.
- Now if we consider the human mind, we shall find, that with regard to
- the passions, it is not the nature of a wind-instrument of music, which
- in running over all the notes immediately loses the sound after the
- breath ceases; but rather resembles a string-instrument, where after
- each stroke the vibrations still retain some sound, which gradually and
- insensibly decays. The imagination is extreme quick and agile; but the
- passions are slow and restive: For which reason, when any object is
- presented, that affords a variety of views to the one, and emotions to
- the other; though the fancy may change its views with great celerity;
- each stroke will not produce a clear and distinct note of passion,
- but the one passion will always be mixt and confounded with the other.
- According as the probability inclines to good or evil, the passion of
- joy or sorrow predominates in the composition: Because the nature of
- probability is to cast a superior number of views or chances on one
- side; or, which is the same thing, a superior number of returns of
- one passion; or since the dispersed passions are collected into one, a
- superior degree of that passion. That is, in other words, the grief and
- joy being intermingled with each other, by means of the contrary views
- of the imagination, produce by their union the passions of hope and
- fear.
- Upon this head there may be started a very curious question concerning
- that contrariety of passions, which is our present subject. It is
- observable, that where the objects of contrary passions are presented
- at once, beside the encrease of the predominant passion (which has
- been already explained, and commonly arises at their first shock
- or rencounter) it sometimes happens, that both the passions exist
- successively, and by short intervals; sometimes, that they destroy each
- other, and neither of them takes place; and sometimes that both of them
- remain united in the mind. It may, therefore, be asked, by what theory
- we can explain these variations, and to what general principle we can
- reduce them.
- When the contrary passions arise from objects entirely different, they
- take place alternately, the want of relation in the ideas separating the
- impressions from each other, and preventing their opposition. Thus when
- a man is afflicted for the loss of a law-suit, and joyful for the birth
- of a son, the mind running from the agreeable to the calamitous object,
- with whatever celerity it may perform this motion, can scarcely temper
- the one affection with the other, and remain betwixt them in a state of
- indifference.
- It more easily attains that calm situation, when the same event is of a
- mixt nature, and contains something adverse and something prosperous
- in its different circumstances. For in that case, both the passions,
- mingling with each other by means of the relation, become mutually
- destructive, and leave the mind in perfect tranquility.
- But suppose, in the third place, that the object is not a compound of
- good or evil, but is considered as probable or improbable in any degree;
- in that case I assert, that the contrary passions will both of them be
- present at once in the soul, and instead of destroying and tempering
- each other, will subsist together, and produce a third impression
- or affection by their union. Contrary passions are not capable of
- destroying each other, except when their contrary movements exactly
- rencounter, and are opposite in their direction, as well as in the
- sensation they produce. This exact rencounter depends upon the relations
- of those ideas, from which they are derived, and is more or less
- perfect, according to the degrees of the relation. In the case of
- probability the contrary chances are so far related, that they determine
- concerning the existence or non-existence of the same object. But this
- relation is far from being perfect; since some of the chances lie on
- the side of existence, and others on that of non-existence; which are
- objects altogether incompatible. It is impossible by one steady view to
- survey the opposite chances, and the events dependent on them; but it is
- necessary, that the imagination should run alternately from the one to
- the other. Each view of the imagination produces its peculiar passion,
- which decays away by degrees, and is followed by a sensible vibration
- after the stroke. The incompatibility of the views keeps the passions
- from shocking in a direct line, if that expression may be allowed; and
- yet their relation is sufficient to mingle their fainter emotions. It is
- after this manner that hope and fear arise from the different mixture of
- these opposite passions of grief and joy, and from their imperfect union
- and conjunction.
- Upon the whole, contrary passions succeed each other alternately, when
- they arise from different objects: They mutually destroy each other,
- when they proceed from different parts of the same: And they subsist
- both of them and mingle together, when they are derived from the
- contrary and incompatible chances or possibilities, on which any one
- object depends. The influence of the relations of ideas is plainly seen
- in this whole affair. If the objects of the contrary passions be totally
- different, the passions are like two opposite liquors in different
- bottles, which have no influence on each other. If the objects be
- intimately connected, the passions are like an alcali and an acid,
- which, being mingled, destroy each other. If the relation be more
- imperfect, and consists in the contradictory views of the same object,
- the passions are like oil and vinegar, which, however mingled, never
- perfectly unite and incorporate.
- As the hypothesis concerning hope and fear carries its own evidence
- along with it, we shall be the more concise in our proofs. A few strong
- arguments are better than many weak ones.
- The passions of fear and hope may arise when the chances are equal on
- both sides, and no superiority can be discovered in the one above the
- other. Nay, in this situation the passions are rather the strongest, as
- the mind has then the least foundation to rest upon, and is tossed with
- the greatest uncertainty. Throw in a superior degree of probability to
- the side of grief, you immediately see that passion diffuse itself over
- the composition, and tincture it into fear. Encrease the probability,
- and by that means the grief, the fear prevails still more and more, till
- at last it runs insensibly, as the joy continually diminishes, into pure
- grief. After you have brought it to this situation, diminish the
- grief, after the same manner that you encreased it; by diminishing the
- probability on that side, and you'll see the passion clear every moment,
- until it changes insensibly into hope; which again runs, after the same
- manner, by slow degrees, into joy, as you encrease that part of the
- composition by the encrease of the probability. Are not these as plain
- proofs, that the passions of fear and hope are mixtures of grief and
- joy, as in optics it is a proof, that a coloured ray of the sun passing
- through a prism, is a composition of two others, when, as you diminish
- or encrease the quantity of either, you find it prevail proportionably
- more or less in the composition? I am sure neither natural nor moral
- philosophy admits of stronger proofs.
- Probability is of two kinds, either when the object is really in itself
- uncertain, and to be determined by chance; or when, though the object
- be already certain, yet it is uncertain to our judgment, which finds
- a number of proofs on each side of the question. Both these kinds of
- probabilities cause fear and hope; which can only proceed from that
- property, in which they agree, viz, the uncertainty and fluctuation they
- bestow on the imagination by that contrariety of views, which is common
- to both.
- It is a probable good or evil, that commonly produces hope or fear;
- because probability, being a wavering and unconstant method of surveying
- an object, causes naturally a like mixture and uncertainty of passion.
- But we may observe, that wherever from other causes this mixture can be
- produced, the passions of fear and hope will arise, even though there
- be no probability; which must be allowed to be a convincing proof of the
- present hypothesis. We find that an evil, barely conceived as possible,
- does sometimes produce fear; especially if the evil be very great. A man
- cannot think of excessive pains and tortures without trembling, if he be
- in the least danger of suffering them. The smallness of the probability
- is compensated by the greatness of the evil; and the sensation is
- equally lively, as if the evil were more probable. One view or glimpse
- of the former, has the same effect as several of the latter.
- But they are not only possible evils, that cause fear, but even
- some allowed to be impossible; as when we tremble on the brink of a
- precipice, though we know ourselves to be in perfect security, and have
- it in our choice whether we wili advance a step farther. This
- proceeds from the immediate presence of the evil, which influences the
- imagination in the same manner as the certainty of it would do; but
- being encountered by the reflection on our security, is immediately
- retracted, and causes the same kind of passion, as when from a
- contrariety of chances contrary passions are produced.
- Evils, that are certain, have sometimes the same effect in producing
- fear, as the possible or impossible. Thus a man in a strong prison
- well-guarded, without the least means of escape, trembles at the thought
- of the rack, to which he is sentenced. This happens only when the
- certain evil is terrible and confounding; in which case the mind
- continually rejects it with horror, while it continually presses in
- upon the thought. The evil is there flxed and established, but the mind
- cannot endure to fix upon it; from which fluctuation and uncertainty
- there arises a passion of much the same appearance with fear.
- But it is not only where good or evil is uncertain, as to its existence,
- but also as to its kind, that fear or hope arises. Let one be told by
- a person, whose veracity he cannot doubt of, that one of his sons is
- suddenly killed, it is evident the passion this event would occasion,
- would not settle into pure grief, till he got certain information, which
- of his sons he had lost. Here there is an evil certain, but the kind of
- it uncertain. Consequently the fear we feel on this occasion is without
- the least mixture of joy, and arises merely from the fluctuation of the
- fancy betwixt its objects. And though each side of the question produces
- here the same passion, yet that passion cannot settle, but receives
- from the imagination a tremulous and unsteady motion, resembling in its
- cause, as well as in its sensation, the mixture and contention of grief
- and joy.
- From these principles we may account for a phaenomenon in the passions,
- which at first sight seems very extraordinary, viz, that surprize is apt
- to change into fear, and every thing that is unexpected affrights
- us. The most obvious conclusion from this is, that human nature is in
- general pusillanimous; since upon the sudden appearance of any object.
- we immediately conclude it to be an evil, and without waiting till we
- can examine its nature, whether it be good or bad, are at first affected
- with fear. This I say is the most obvious conclusion; but upon farther
- examination we shall find that the phaenomenon is otherwise to be
- accounted for. The suddenness and strangeness of an appearance naturally
- excite a commotion in the mind, like every thing for which we are not
- prepared, and to which we are not accustomed. This commotion, again,
- naturally produces a curiosity or inquisitiveness, which being very
- violent, from the strong and sudden impulse of the object, becomes
- uneasy, and resembles in its fluctuation and uncertainty, the sensation
- of fear or the mixed passions of grief and joy. This image of
- fear naturally converts into the thing itself, and gives us a real
- apprehension of evil, as the mind always forms its judgments more from
- its present disposition than from the nature of its objects.
- Thus all kinds of uncertainty have a strong connexion with fear, even
- though they do not cause any opposition of passions by the opposite
- views and considerations they present to us. A person, who has left his
- friend in any malady, will feel more anxiety upon his account, than if
- he were present, though perhaps he is not only incapable of giving him
- assistance, but likewise of judging of the event of his sickness. In
- this case, though the principal object of the passion, viz, the life or
- death of his friend, be to him equally uncertain when present as when
- absent; yet there are a thousand little circumstances of his friend's
- situation and condition, the knowledge of which fixes the idea, and
- prevents that fluctuation and uncertainty so near allyed to fear.
- Uncertainty is, indeed, in one respect as near allyed to hope as to
- fear, since it makes an essential part in the composition of the former
- passion; but the reason, why it inclines not to that side, is, that
- uncertainty alone is uneasy, and has a reladon of impressions to the
- uneasy passions.
- It is thus our uncertainty concerning any minute circumstance relating
- to a person encreases our apprehensions of his death or misfortune.
- Horace has remarked this phaenomenon.
- UT ASSIDENS IMPLUMI BUS PULLUS AVIS SERPENTIUM ALLAPSUS TIRNET, MAGIS
- RELICTIS; NON, UT ADSIT, AUXILI LATURA PLUS PRESENTIBUS.
- [As a bird, watching over her fledgelings, is more afraid of their being
- attacked by snakes if she were to leave them even though, were she to
- stay, she would not be any more capable of helping them, when they were
- with her.]
- But this principle of the connexion of fear with uncertainty I carry
- farther, and observe that any doubt produces that passion, even though
- it presents nothing to us on any side but what is good and desireable. A
- virgin, on her bridalnight goes to bed full of fears and apprehensions,
- though she expects nothing but pleasure of the highest kind, and what
- she has long wished for. The newness and greatness of the event, the
- confusion of wishes and joys so embarrass the mind, that it knows not
- on what passion to fix itself; from whence arises a fluttering or
- unsettledness of the spirits which being, in some degree, uneasy, very
- naturally degenerates into fear.
- Thus we still find, that whatever causes any fluctuation or mixture of
- passions, with any degree of uneasiness, always produces fear, or at
- least a passion so like it, that they are scarcely to be distinguished.
- I have here confined myself to the examination of hope and fear in
- their most simple and natural situation, without considering all the
- variations they may receive from the mixture of different views and
- reflections. Terror, consternation, astonishment, anxiety, and other
- passions of that kind, are nothing but different species and degrees of
- fear. It is easy to imagine how a different situation of the object, or
- a different turn of thought, may change even the sensation of a passion;
- and this may in general account for all the particular sub-divisions of
- the other affections, as well as of fear. Love may shew itself in the
- shape of tenderness, friendship, intimacy, esteem, good-will, and in
- many other appearances; which at the bottom are the same affections; and
- arise from the same causes, though with a small variation, which it is
- not necessary to give any particular account of. It is for this reason I
- have all along confined myself to the principal passion.
- The same care of avoiding prolixity is the reason why I wave the
- examination of the will and direct passions, as they appear in animals;
- since nothing is more evident, than that they are of the same nature,
- and excited by the same causes as in human creatures. I leave this to
- the reader's own observation; desiring him at the same time to consider
- the additional force this bestows on the present system.
- SECT. X OF CURIOSITY, OR THE LOVE OF TRUTH
- But methinks we have been not a little inattentive to run over so many
- different parts of the human mind, and examine so many passions, without
- taking once into the consideration that love of truth, which was the
- first source of all our enquiries. Twill therefore be proper, before
- we leave this subject, to bestow a few reflections on that passion, and
- shew its origin in human nature. It is an affection of so peculiar a
- kind, that it would have been impossible to have treated of it under any
- of those heads, which we have examined, without danger of obscurity and
- confusion.
- Truth is of two kinds, consisting either in the discovery of the
- proportions of ideas, considered as such, or in the conformity of our
- ideas of objects to their real existence. It is certain, that the former
- species of truth, is not desired merely as truth, and that it is not the
- justness of our conclusions, which alone gives the pleasure. For these
- conclusions are equally just, when we discover the equality of two
- bodies by a pair of compasses, as when we learn it by a mathematical
- demonstration; and though in the one case the proofs be demonstrative,
- and in the other only sensible, yet generally speaking, the mind
- acquiesces with equal assurance in the one as in the other. And in an
- arithmetical operation, where both the truth and the assurance are
- of the same nature, as in the most profound algebraical problem, the
- pleasure is very inconsiderable, if rather it does not degenerate
- into pain: Which is an evident proof, that the satisfaction, which we
- sometimes receive from the discovery of truth, proceeds not from it,
- merely as such, but only as endowed with certain qualities.
- The first and most considerable circumstance requisite to render
- truth agreeable, is the genius and capacity, which is employed in its
- invention and discovery. What is easy and obvious is never valued; and
- even what is in itself difficult, if we come to the knowledge of it
- without difficulty, and without any stretch of thought or judgment,
- is but little regarded. We love to trace the demonstrations of
- mathematicians; but should receive small entertainment from a person,
- who should barely inform us of the proportions of lines and angles,
- though we reposed the utmost confidence both in his judgment and
- veracity. In this case it is sufficient to have ears to learn the truth.
- We never are obliged to fix our attention or exert our genius; which of
- all other exercises of the mind is the most pleasant and agreeable.
- But though the exercise of genius be the principal source of that
- satisfaction we receive from the sciences, yet I doubt, if it be alone
- sufficient to give us any considerable enjoyment. The truth we discover
- must also be of some importance. It is easy to multiply algebraical
- problems to infinity, nor is there any end in the discovery of the
- proportions of conic sections; though few mathematicians take any
- pleasure in these researches, but turn their thoughts to what is more
- useful and important. Now the question is, after what manner this
- utility and importance operate upon us? The difficulty on this head
- arises from hence, that many philosophers have consumed their time, have
- destroyed their health, and neglected their fortune, in the search of
- such truths, as they esteemed important and useful to the world, though
- it appeared from their whole conduct and behaviour, that they were not
- endowed with any share of public spirit, nor had any concern for the
- interests of mankind. Were they convinced, that their discoveries
- were of no consequence, they would entirely lose all relish for their
- studies, and that though the consequences be entirely indifferent to
- them; which seems to be a contradiction.
- To remove this contradiction, we must consider, that there are certain
- desires and inclinations, which go no farther than the imagination,
- and are rather the faint shadows and images of passions, than any
- real affections. Thus, suppose a man, who takes a survey of the
- fortifications of any city; considers their strength and advantages,
- natural or acquired; observes the disposition and contrivance of the
- bastions, ramparts, mines, and other military works; it is plain, that
- in proportion as all these are fitted to attain their ends he will
- receive a suitable pleasure and satisfaction. This pleasure, as it
- arises from the utility, not the form of the objects, can be no other
- than a sympathy with the inhabitants, for whose security all this art is
- employed; though it is possible, that this person, as a stranger or an
- enemy, may in his heart have no kindness for them, or may even entertain
- a hatred against them.
- It may indeed be objected, that such a remote sympathy is a very slight
- foundation for a passion, and that so much industry and application,
- as we frequently observe in philosophers, can never be derived from so
- inconsiderable an original. But here I return to what I have already
- remarked, that the pleasure of study conflicts chiefly in the action
- of the mind, and the exercise of the genius and understanding in the
- discovery or comprehension of any truth. If the importance of the truth
- be requisite to compleat the pleasure, it is not on account of any
- considerable addition, which of itself it brings to our enjoyment, but
- only because it is, in some measure, requisite to fix our attention.
- When we are careless and inattentive, the same action of the
- understanding has no effect upon us, nor is able to convey any of that
- satisfaction, which arises from it, when we are in another disposition.
- But beside the action of the mind, which is the principal foundation
- of the pleasure, there is likewise required a degree of success in the
- attainment of the end, or the discovery of that truth we examine. Upon
- this head I shall make a general remark, which may be useful on many
- occasions, viz, that where the mind pursues any end with passion; though
- that passion be not derived originally from the end, but merely from
- the action and pursuit; yet by the natural course of the affections,
- we acquire a concern for the end itself, and are uneasy under any
- disappointment we meet with in the pursuit of it. This proceeds from the
- relation and parallel direction of the passions above-mentioned.
- To illustrate all this by a similar instance, I shall observe, that
- there cannot be two passions more nearly resembling each other, than
- those of hunting and philosophy, whatever disproportion may at first
- sight appear betwixt them. It is evident, that the pleasure of hunting
- conflicts in the action of the mind and body; the motion, the attention,
- the difficulty, and the uncertainty. It is evident likewise, that these
- actions must be attended with an idea of utility, in order to their
- having any effect upon us. A man of the greatest fortune, and the
- farthest removed from avarice, though he takes a pleasure in hunting
- after patridges and pheasants, feels no satisfaction in shooting crows
- and magpies; and that because he considers the first as fit for the
- table, and the other as entirely useless. Here it is certain, that the
- utility or importance of itself causes no real passion, but is
- only requisite to support the imagination; and the same person, who
- over-looks a ten times greater profit in any other subject, is pleased
- to bring home half a dozen woodcocks or plovers, after having employed
- several hours in hunting after them. To make the parallel betwixt
- hunting and philosophy more compleat, we may observe, that though in
- both cases the end of our action may in itself be despised, yet in the
- heat of the action we acquire such an attention to this end, that we are
- very uneasy under any disappointments, and are sorry when we either miss
- our game, or fall into any error in our reasoning.
- If we want another parallel to these affections, we may consider the
- passion of gaming, which affords a pleasure from the same principles
- as hunting and philosophy. It has been remarked, that the pleasure of
- gaming arises not from interest alone; since many leave a sure gain for
- this entertainment: Neither is it derived from the game alone; since
- the same persons have no satisfaction, when they play for nothing: But
- proceeds from both these causes united, though separately they have
- no effect. It is here, as in certain chymical preparations, where the
- mixture of two clear and transparent liquids produces a third, which is
- opaque and coloured..
- The interest, which we have in any game, engages our attention, without
- which we can have no enjoyment, either in that or in any other action.
- Our attention being once engaged, the difficulty, variety, and sudden
- reverses of fortune, still farther interest us; and it is from that
- concern our satisfaction arises. Human life is so tiresome a scene, and
- men generally are of such indolent dispositions, that whatever amuses
- them, though by a passion mixt with pain, does in the main give them a
- sensible pleasure. And this pleasure is here encreased by the nature of
- the objects, which being sensible, and of a narrow compass, are entered
- into with facility, and are agreeable to the imagination.
- The same theory, that accounts for the love of truth in mathematics and
- algebra may be extended to morals, politics, natural philosophy, and
- other studies, where we consider not the other abstract relations of
- ideas, but their real connexions and existence. But beside the love of
- knowledge, which displays itself in the sciences, there is a certain
- curiosity implanted in human nature, which is a passion derived from
- a quite different principle. Some people have an insatiable desire of
- knowing the actions and circumstances of their neighbours, though their
- interest be no way concerned in them, and they must entirely depend on
- others for their information; in which case there is no room for study
- or application. Let us search for the reason of this phaenomenon.
- It has been proved at large, that the influence of belief is at once to
- inliven and infix any idea in the imagination, and prevent all kind
- of hesitation and uncertainty about it. Both these circumstances are
- advantageous. By the vivacity of the idea we interest the fancy, and
- produce, though in a lesser degree, the same pleasure, which arises from
- a moderate passion. As the vivacity of the idea gives pleasure, so its
- certainty prevents uneasiness, by fixing one particular idea in the
- mind, and keeping it from wavering in the choice of its objects. It is a
- quality of human nature, which is conspicuous on many occasions, and is
- common both to the mind and body, that too sudden and violent a change
- is unpleasant to us, and that however any objects may in themselves be
- indifferent, yet their alteration gives uneasiness. As it is the nature
- of doubt to cause a variation in the thought, and transport us suddenly
- from one idea to another, it must of consequence be the occasion of
- pain. This pain chiefly takes place, where interest, relation, or the
- greatness and novelty of any event interests us in it. It is not every
- matter of fact, of which we have a curiosity to be informed; neither are
- they such only as we have an interest to know. It is sufficient if the
- idea strikes on us with such force, and concerns us so nearly, as to
- give us an uneasiness in its instability and inconstancy. A stranger,
- when he arrives first at any town, may be entirely indifferent about
- knowing the history and adventures of the inhabitants; but as he becomes
- farther acquainted with them, and has lived any considerable time among
- them, he acquires the same curiosity as the natives. When we are reading
- the history of a nation, we may have an ardent desire of clearing up
- any doubt or difficulty, that occurs in it; but become careless in such
- researches, when the ideas of these events are, in a great measure,
- obliterated.
- BOOK III OF MORALS
- PART I OF VIRTUE AND VICE IN GENERAL
- SECT. I MORAL DISTINCTIONS NOT DERIVed FROM REASON
- There is an inconvenience which attends all abstruse reasoning that
- it may silence, without convincing an antagonist, and requires the
- same intense study to make us sensible of its force, that was at first
- requisite for its invention. When we leave our closet, and engage in
- the common affairs of life, its conclusions seem to vanish, like the
- phantoms of the night on the appearance of the morning; and it is
- difficult for us to retain even that conviction, which we had attained
- with difficulty. This is still more conspicuous in a long chain of
- reasoning, where we must preserve to the end the evidence of the first
- propositions, and where we often lose sight of all the most received
- maxims, either of philosophy or common life. I am not, however, without
- hopes, that the present system of philosophy will acquire new force as
- it advances; and that our reasonings concerning morals will corroborate
- whatever has been said concerning the UNDERSTANDING and the PASSIONS.
- Morality is a subject that interests us above all others: We fancy the
- peace of society to be at stake in every decision concerning it; and
- it is evident, that this concern must make our speculations appear
- more real and solid, than where the subject is, in a great measure,
- indifferent to us. What affects us, we conclude can never be a chimera;
- and as our passion is engaged on the one side or the other, we naturally
- think that the question lies within human comprehension; which, in other
- cases of this nature, we are apt to entertain some doubt of. Without
- this advantage I never should have ventured upon a third volume of such
- abstruse philosophy, in an age, wherein the greatest part of men seem
- agreed to convert reading into an amusement, and to reject every thing
- that requires any considerable degree of attention to be comprehended.
- It has been observed, that nothing is ever present to the mind but
- its perceptions; and that all the actions of seeing, hearing, judging,
- loving, hating, and thinking, fall under this denomination. The mind can
- never exert itself in any action, which we may not comprehend under the
- term of perception; and consequently that term is no less applicable to
- those judgments, by which we distinguish moral good and evil, than
- to every other operation of the mind. To approve of one character, to
- condemn another, are only so many different perceptions.
- Now as perceptions resolve themselves into two kinds, viz. impressions
- and ideas, this distinction gives rise to a question, with which we
- shall open up our present enquiry concerning morals. WHETHER IT IS
- BY MEANS OF OUR IDEAS OR IMPRESSIONS WE DISTINGUISH BETWIXT VICE AND
- VIRTUE, AND PRONOUNCE AN ACTION BLAMEABLE OR PRAISEWORTHY? This will
- immediately cut off all loose discourses and declamations, and reduce us
- to something precise and exact on the present subject.
- Those who affirm that virtue is nothing but a conformity to reason; that
- there are eternal fitnesses and unfitnesses of things, which are the
- same to every rational being that considers them; that the immutable
- measures of right and wrong impose an obligation, not only on human
- creatures, but also on the Deity himself: All these systems concur in
- the opinion, that morality, like truth, is discerned merely by ideas,
- and by their juxta-position and comparison. In order, therefore, to
- judge of these systems, we need only consider, whether it be possible,
- from reason alone, to distinguish betwixt moral good and evil, or
- whether there must concur some other principles to enable us to make
- that distinction.
- If morality had naturally no influence on human passions and actions,
- it were in vain to take such pains to inculcate it; and nothing would be
- more fruitless than that multitude of rules and precepts, with which all
- moralists abound. Philosophy is commonly divided into speculative and
- practical; and as morality is always comprehended under the latter
- division, it is supposed to influence our passions and actions, and to
- go beyond the calm and indolent judgments of the understanding. And this
- is confirmed by common experience, which informs us, that men are often
- governed by their duties, and are detered from some actions by the
- opinion of injustice, and impelled to others by that of obligation.
- Since morals, therefore, have an influence on the actions and
- affections, it follows, that they cannot be derived from reason; and
- that because reason alone, as we have already proved, can never have any
- such influence. Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions.
- Reason of itself is utterly impotent in this particular. The rules of
- morality therefore, are not conclusions of our reason.
- No one, I believe, will deny the justness of this inference; nor is
- there any other means of evading it, than by denying that principle,
- on which it is founded. As long as it is allowed, that reason has no
- influence on our passions and action, it is in vain to pretend,
- that morality is discovered only by a deduction of reason. An active
- principle can never be founded on an inactive; and if reason be inactive
- in itself, it must remain so in all its shapes and appearances, whether
- it exerts itself in natural or moral subjects, whether it considers the
- powers of external bodies, or the actions of rational beings.
- It would be tedious to repeat all the arguments, by which I have proved
- [Book II. Part III. Sect 3.], that reason is perfectly inert, and can
- never either prevent or produce any action or affection, it will be easy
- to recollect what has been said upon that subject. I shall only recall
- on this occasion one of these arguments, which I shall endeavour
- to render still more conclusive, and more applicable to the present
- subject.
- Reason is the discovery of truth or falshood. Truth or falshood consists
- in an agreement or disagreement either to the real relations of ideas,
- or to real existence and matter of fact. Whatever, therefore, is not
- susceptible of this agreement or disagreement, is incapable of being
- true or false, and can never be an object of our reason. Now it is
- evident our passions, volitions, and actions, are not susceptible of
- any such agreement or disagreement; being original facts and realities,
- compleat in themselves, and implying no reference to other passions,
- volitions, and actions. It is impossible, therefore, they can be
- pronounced either true or false, and be either contrary or conformable
- to reason.
- This argument is of double advantage to our present purpose. For
- it proves DIRECTLY, that actions do not derive their merit from a
- conformity to reason, nor their blame from a contrariety to it; and it
- proves the same truth more INDIRECTLY, by shewing us, that as reason
- can never immediately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or
- approving of it, it cannot be the source of moral good and evil, which
- are found to have that influence. Actions may be laudable or blameable;
- but they cannot be reasonable: Laudable or blameable, therefore, are
- not the same with reasonable or unreasonable. The merit and demerit
- of actions frequently contradict, and sometimes controul our natural
- propensities. But reason has no such influence. Moral distinctions,
- therefore, are not the offspring of reason. Reason is wholly inactive,
- and can never be the source of so active a principle as conscience, or a
- sense of morals.
- But perhaps it may be said, that though no will or action can
- be immediately contradictory to reason, yet we may find such a
- contradiction in some of the attendants of the action, that is, in its
- causes or effects. The action may cause a judgment, or may be obliquely
- caused by one, when the judgment concurs with a passion; and by an
- abusive way of speaking, which philosophy will scarce allow of, the same
- contrariety may, upon that account, be ascribed to the action. How
- far this truth or faishood may be the source of morals, it will now be
- proper to consider.
- It has been observed, that reason, in a strict and philosophical sense,
- can have influence on our conduct only after two ways: Either when it
- excites a passion by informing us of the existence of something which is
- a proper object of it; or when it discovers the connexion of causes and
- effects, so as to afford us means of exerting any passion. These are the
- only kinds of judgment, which can accompany our actions, or can be
- said to produce them in any manner; and it must be allowed, that these
- judgments may often be false and erroneous. A person may be affected
- with passion, by supposing a pain or pleasure to lie in an object, which
- has no tendency to produce either of these sensations, or which produces
- the contrary to what is imagined. A person may also take false measures
- for the attaining his end, and may retard, by his foolish conduct,
- instead of forwarding the execution of any project. These false
- judgments may be thought to affect the passions and actions, which are
- connected with them, and may be said to render them unreasonable, in
- a figurative and improper way of speaking. But though this be
- acknowledged, it is easy to observe, that these errors are so far
- from being the source of all immorality, that they are commonly
- very innocent, and draw no manner of guilt upon the person who is so
- unfortunate as to fail into them. They extend not beyond a mistake of
- fact, which moralists have not generally supposed criminal, as being
- perfectly involuntary. I am more to be lamented than blamed, if I am
- mistaken with regard to the influence of objects in producing pain or
- pleasure, or if I know not the proper means of satisfying my desires.
- No one can ever regard such errors as a defect in my moral character.
- A fruit, for instance, that is really disagreeable, appears to me at a
- distance, and through mistake I fancy it to be pleasant and delicious.
- Here is one error. I choose certain means of reaching this fruit, which
- are not proper for my end. Here is a second error; nor is there any
- third one, which can ever possibly enter into our reasonings concerning
- actions. I ask, therefore, if a man, in this situation, and guilty of
- these two errors, is to be regarded as vicious and criminal, however
- unavoidable they might have been? Or if it be possible to imagine, that
- such errors are the sources of all immorality?
- And here it may be proper to observe, that if moral distinctions be
- derived from the truth or falshood of those judgments, they must take
- place wherever we form the judgments; nor will there be any difference,
- whether the question be concerning an apple or a kingdom, or whether the
- error be avoidable or unavoidable. For as the very essence of morality
- is supposed to consist in an agreement or disagreement to reason, the
- other circumstances are entirely arbitrary, and can never either bestow
- on any action the character of virtuous or vicious, or deprive it
- of that character. To which we may add, that this agreement or
- disagreement, not admitting of degrees, all virtues and vices would of
- course be equal.
- Should it be pretended, that though a mistake of fact be not criminal,
- yet a mistake of right often is; and that this may be the source of
- immorality: I would answer, that it is impossible such a mistake can
- ever be the original source of immorality, since it supposes a real
- right and wrong; that is, a real distinction in morals, independent of
- these judgments. A mistake, therefore, of right may become a species
- of immorality; but it is only a secondary one, and is founded on some
- other, antecedent to it.
- As to those judgments which are the effects of our actions, and which,
- when false, give occasion to pronounce the actions contrary to truth
- and reason; we may observe, that our actions never cause any judgment,
- either true or false, in ourselves, and that it is only on others
- they have such an influence. It is certain, that an action, on many
- occasions, may give rise to false conclusions in others; and that a
- person, who through a window sees any lewd behaviour of mine with my
- neighbour's wife, may be so simple as to imagine she is certainly my
- own. In this respect my action resembles somewhat a lye or falshood;
- only with this difference, which is material, that I perform not the
- action with any intention of giving rise to a false judgment in another,
- but merely to satisfy my lust and passion. It causes, however, a mistake
- and false judgment by accident; and the falshood of its effects may be
- ascribed, by some odd figurative way of speaking, to the action itself.
- But still I can see no pretext of reason for asserting, that the
- tendency to cause such an error is the first spring or original source
- of all immorality.
- [Footnote 12. One might think it were entirely superfluous
- to prove this, if a late author [William Wollaston, THE
- RELIGION OF NATURE DELINEATED (London 1722)], who has had
- the good fortune to obtain some reputation, had not
- seriously affirmed, that such a falshood is the foundation
- of all guilt and moral deformity. That we may discover the
- fallacy of his hypothesis, we need only consider, that a
- false conclusion is drawn from an action, only by means of
- an obscurity of natural principles, which makes a cause be
- secretly interrupted In its operation, by contrary causes,
- and renders the connexion betwixt two objects uncertain and
- variable. Now, as a like uncertainty and variety of causes
- take place, even in natural objects, and produce a like
- error in our judgment, if that tendency to produce error
- were the very essence of vice and immorality, it should
- follow, that even inanimate objects might be vicious and
- immoral.
- One might think It were entirely superfluous to prove this,
- if a late author [William Wollaston, THE RELIGION OF NATURE
- DELINEATED (London 1722)], who has had the good fortune to
- obtain some reputation, had not seriously affirmed, that
- such a falshood is the foundation of all guilt and moral
- deformity. That we may discover the fallacy of his
- hypothesis, we need only consider, that a false conclusion
- is drawn from an action, only by means of an obscurity of
- natural principles, which makes a cause be secretly
- interrupted In its operation, by contrary causes, and
- renders the connexion betwixt two objects uncertain and
- variable. Now, as a like uncertainty and variety of causes
- take place, even in natural objects, and produce a like
- error in our judgment, if that tendency to produce error
- were the very essence of vice and immorality, it should
- follow, that even inanimate objects might be vicious and
- immoral.
- It is in vain to urge, that inanimate objects act without
- liberty and choice. For as liberty and choice are not
- necessary to make an action produce in us an erroneous
- conclusion, they can be, in no respect, essential to
- morality; and I do not readily perceive, upon this system,
- how they can ever come to be regarded by it. If the tendency
- to cause error be the origin of immorality, that tendency
- and immorality would in every case be inseparable.
- Add to this, that if I had used the precaution of shutting
- the windows, while I indulged myself in those liberties with
- my neighbour's wife, I should have been guilty of no
- immorality; and that because my action, being perfectly
- concealed, would have had no tendency to produce any false
- conclusion.
- For the same reason, a thief, who steals In by a ladder at a
- window, and takes all imaginable care to cause no
- disturbance, is in no respect criminal. For either he will
- not be perceived, or if he be, it is impossible he can
- produce any error, nor will any one, from these
- circumstances, take him to be other than what he really is.
- It is well known, that those who are squint-sighted, do very
- readily cause mistakes in others, and that we Imagine they
- salute or are talking to one person, while they address
- themselves to anther. Are they therefore, upon that account,
- immoral?
- Besides, we may easily observe, that in all those arguments
- there is an evident reasoning in a circle. A person who
- takes possession of another's goods, and uses them as his
- own, in a manner declares them to be his own; and this
- falshood is the source of the immorality of injustice. But
- is property, or right, or obligation, intelligible, without
- an antecedent morality?
- A man that is ungrateful to his benefactor, in a manner
- affirms, that he never received any favours from him. But in
- what manner? Is it because it is his duty to be grateful?
- But this supposes, that there is some antecedent rule of
- duty and morals. Is it because human nature is generally
- grateful, and makes us conclude, that a man who does any
- harm never received any favour from the person he harmed?
- But human nature is not so generally grateful, as to justify
- such a conclusion. Or if it were, is an exception to a
- general rule in every case criminal, for no other reason
- than because it is an exception?
- But what may suffice entirely to destroy this whimsical
- system is, that it leaves us under the same difficulty to
- give a reason why truth is virtuous and falshood vicious, as
- to account for the merit or turpitude of any other action. I
- shall allow, if you please, that all immorality is derived
- from this supposed falshood in action, provided you can give
- me any plausible reason, why such a falshood is immoral. If
- you consider rightly of the matter, you will find yourself
- in the same difficulty as at the beginning.
- This last argument is very conclusive; because, if there be
- not an evident merit or turpitude annexed to this species of
- truth or falahood, It can never have any influence upon our
- actions. For, who ever thought of forbearing any action,
- because others might possibly draw false conclusions from
- it? Or, who ever performed any, that he might give rise to
- true conclusions?]
- Thus upon the whole, it is impossible, that the distinction betwixt
- moral good and evil, can be made to reason; since that distinction
- has an influence upon our actions, of which reason alone is incapable.
- Reason and judgment may, indeed, be the mediate cause of an action, by
- prompting, or by directing a passion: But it is not pretended, that a
- judgment of this kind, either in its truth or falshood, is attended
- with virtue or vice. And as to the judgments, which are caused by our
- judgments, they can still less bestow those moral qualities on the
- actions, which are their causes.
- But to be more particular, and to shew, that those eternal immutable
- fitnesses and unfitnesses of things cannot be defended by sound
- philosophy, we may weigh the following considerations.
- If the thought and understanding were alone capable of fixing the
- boundaries of right and wrong, the character of virtuous and vicious
- either must lie in some relations of objects, or must be a matter of
- fact, which is discovered by our reasoning. This consequence is evident.
- As the operations of human understanding divide themselves into two
- kinds, the comparing of ideas, and the inferring of matter of fact; were
- virtue discovered by the understanding; it must be an object of one of
- these operations, nor is there any third operation of the understanding.
- which can discover it. There has been an opinion very industriously
- propagated by certain philosophers, that morality is susceptible of
- demonstration; and though no one has ever been able to advance a single
- step in those demonstrations; yet it is taken for granted, that this
- science may be brought to an equal certainty with geometry or algebra.
- Upon this supposition vice and virtue must consist in some relations;
- since it is allowed on all hands, that no matter of fact is capable
- of being demonstrated. Let us, therefore, begin with examining this
- hypothesis, and endeavour, if possible, to fix those moral qualities,
- which have been so long the objects of our fruitless researches. Point
- out distinctly the relations, which constitute morality or obligation,
- that we may know wherein they consist, and after what manner we must
- judge of them.
- If you assert, that vice and virtue consist in relations susceptible
- of certainty and demonstration, you must confine yourself to those four
- relations, which alone admit of that degree of evidence; and in that
- case you run into absurdities, from which you will never be able to
- extricate yourself. For as you make the very essence of morality to lie
- in the relations, and as there is no one of these relations but what is
- applicable, not only to an irrational, but also to an inanimate object;
- it follows, that even such objects must be susceptible of merit or
- demerit. RESEMBLANCE, CONTRARIETY, DEGREES IN QUALITY, and PROPORTIONS
- IN QUANTITY AND NUMBER; all these relations belong as properly
- to matter, as to our actions, passions, and volitions. It is
- unquestionable, therefore, that morality lies not in any of these
- relations, nor the sense of it in their discovery.
- [Footnote 13. As a proof, how confused our way of thinking
- on this subject commonly is, we may observe, that those who
- assert, that morality is demonstrable, do not say, that
- morality lies in the relations, and that the relations are
- distinguishable by reason. They only say, that reason can
- discover such an action, In such relations, to be virtuous,
- and such another vicious. It seems they thought it
- sufficient, if they could bring the word, Relation, into the
- proposition, without troubling themselves whether it was to
- the purpose or not. But here, I think, is plain argument.
- Demonstrative reason discovers only relations. But that
- reason, according to this hypothesis, discovers also vice
- and virtue. These moral qualities, therefore, must be
- relations. When we blame any action, in any situation, the
- whole complicated object, of action and situation, must form
- certain relations, wherein the essence of vice consists.
- This hypothesis is not otherwise intelligible. For what does
- reason discover, when it pronounces any action vicious? Does
- it discover a relation or a matter of fact? These questions
- are decisive, and must not be eluded.]
- Should it be asserted, that the sense of morality consists in
- the discovery of some relation, distinct from these, and that our
- enumeration was not compleat, when we comprehended all demonstrable
- relations under four general heads: To this I know not what to reply,
- till some one be so good as to point out to me this new relation. It is
- impossible to refute a system, which has never yet been explained. In
- such a manner of fighting in the dark, a man loses his blows in the air,
- and often places them where the enemy is not present.
- I must, therefore, on this occasion, rest contented with requiring the
- two following conditions of any one that would undertake to clear up
- this system. First, As moral good and evil belong only to the actions
- of the mind, and are derived from our situation with regard to external
- objects, the relations, from which these moral distinctions arise, must
- lie only betwixt internal actions, and external objects, and must not be
- applicable either to internal actions, compared among themselves, or to
- external objects, when placed in opposition to other external objects.
- For as morality is supposed to attend certain relations, if these
- relations coued belong to internal actions considered singly, it would
- follow, that we might be guilty of crimes in ourselves, and independent
- of our situation, with respect to the universe: And in like manner, if
- these moral relations coued be applied to external objects, it would
- follow, that even inanimate beings would be susceptible of moral beauty
- and deformity. Now it seems difficult to imagine, that any relation can
- be discovered betwixt our passions, volitions and actions, compared
- to external objects, which relation might not belong either to these
- passions and volitions, or to these external objects, compared among
- themselves. But it will be still more difficult to fulfil the second
- condition, requisite to justify this system. According to the principles
- of those who maintain an abstract rational difference betwixt moral good
- and evil, and a natural fitness and unfitness of things, it is not only
- supposed, that these relations, being eternal and immutable, are the
- same, when considered by every rational creature, but their effects are
- also supposed to be necessarily the same; and it is concluded they have
- no less, or rather a greater, influence in directing the will of the
- deity, than in governing the rational and virtuous of our own species.
- These two particulars are evidently distinct. It is one thing to know
- virtue, and another to conform the will to it. In order, therefore, to
- prove, that the measures of right and wrong are eternal laws, obligatory
- on every rational mind, it is not sufficient to shew the relations upon
- which they are founded: We must also point out the connexion betwixt
- the relation and the will; and must prove that this connexion is so
- necessary, that in every well-disposed mind, it must take place and have
- its influence; though the difference betwixt these minds be in other
- respects immense and infinite. Now besides what I have already proved,
- that even in human nature no relation can ever alone produce any
- action: besides this, I say, it has been shewn, in treating of the
- understanding, that there is no connexion of cause and effect, such
- as this is supposed to be, which is discoverable otherwise than by
- experience, and of which we can pretend to have any security by the
- simple consideration of the objects. All beings in the universe,
- considered in themselves, appear entirely loose and independent of each
- other. It is only by experience we learn their influence and connexion;
- and this influence we ought never to extend beyond experience.
- Thus it will be impossible to fulfil the first condition required to the
- system of eternal measures of right and wrong; because it is impossible
- to shew those relations, upon which such a distinction may be founded:
- And it is as impossible to fulfil the second condition; because we
- cannot prove A PRIORI, that these relations, if they really existed and
- were perceived, would be universally forcible and obligatory.
- But to make these general reflections more dear and convincing, we may
- illustrate them by some particular instances, wherein this character of
- moral good or evil is the most universally acknowledged. Of all crimes
- that human creatures are capable of committing, the most horrid and
- unnatural is ingratitude, especially when it is committed against
- parents, and appears in the more flagrant instances of wounds and death.
- This is acknowledged by all mankind, philosophers as well as the people;
- the question only arises among philosophers, whether the guilt or moral
- deformity of this action be discovered by demonstrative reasoning, or
- be felt by an internal sense, and by means of some sentiment, which the
- reflecting on such an action naturally occasions. This question will
- soon be decided against the former opinion, if we can shew the same
- relations in other objects, without the notion of any guilt or iniquity
- attending them. Reason or science is nothing but the comparing of ideas,
- and the discovery of their relations; and if the same relations have
- different characters, it must evidently follow, that those characters
- are not discovered merely by reason. To put the affair, therefore, to
- this trial, let us chuse any inanimate object, such as an oak or elm;
- and let us suppose, that by the dropping of its seed, it produces a
- sapling below it, which springing up by degrees, at last overtops and
- destroys the parent tree: I ask, if in this instance there be wanting
- any relation, which is discoverable in parricide or ingratitude? Is
- not the one tree the cause of the other's existence; and the latter the
- cause of the destruction of the former, in the same manner as when a
- child murders his parent? It is not sufficient to reply, that a choice
- or will is wanting. For in the case of parricide, a will does not give
- rise to any DIFFERENT relations, but is only the cause from which the
- action is derived; and consequently produces the same relations, that in
- the oak or elm arise from some other principles. It is a will or choice,
- that determines a man to kill his parent; and they are the laws of
- matter and motion, that determine a sapling to destroy the oak, from
- which it sprung. Here then the same relations have different causes; but
- still the relations are the same: And as their discovery is not in both
- cases attended with a notion of immorality, it follows, that that notion
- does not arise from such a discovery.
- But to chuse an instance, still more resembling; I would fain ask any
- one, why incest in the human species is criminal, and why the very same
- action, and the same relations in animals have not the smallest moral
- turpitude and deformity? If it be answered, that this action is innocent
- in animals, because they have not reason sufficient to discover its
- turpitude; but that man, being endowed with that faculty which ought to
- restrain him to his duty, the same action instantly becomes criminal to
- him; should this be said, I would reply, that this is evidently
- arguing in a circle. For before reason can perceive this turpitude, the
- turpitude must exist; and consequently is independent of the decisions
- of our reason, and is their object more properly than their effect.
- According to this system, then, every animal, that has sense, and
- appetite, and will; that is, every animal must be susceptible of all the
- same virtues and vices, for which we ascribe praise and blame to human
- creatures. All the difference is, that our superior reason may serve to
- discover the vice or virtue, and by that means may augment the blame
- or praise: But still this discovery supposes a separate being in these
- moral distinctions, and a being, which depends only on the will and
- appetite, and which, both in thought and reality, may be distinguished
- from the reason. Animals are susceptible of the same relations, with
- respect to each other, as the human species, and therefore would also be
- susceptible of the same morality, if the essence of morality consisted
- in these relations. Their want of a sufficient degree of reason may
- hinder them from perceiving the duties and obligations of morality,
- but can never hinder these duties from existing; since they must
- antecedently exist, in order to their being perceived. Reason must find
- them, and can never produce them. This argument deserves to be weighed,
- as being, in my opinion, entirely decisive.
- Nor does this reasoning only prove, that morality consists not in any
- relations, that are the objects of science; but if examined, will prove
- with equal certainty, that it consists not in any matter of fact, which
- can be discovered by the understanding. This is the second part of our
- argument; and if it can be made evident, we may conclude, that morality
- is not an object of reason. But can there be any difficulty in proving,
- that vice and virtue are not matters of fact, whose existence we can
- infer by reason? Take any action allowed to be vicious: Wilful murder,
- for instance. Examine it in all lights, and see if you can find that
- matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In which-ever
- way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives, volitions
- and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice
- entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. You never can
- find it, till you turn your reflection into your own breast, and find a
- sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action.
- Here is a matter of fact; but it is the object of feeling, not of
- reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So that when you
- pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing,
- but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or
- sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. Vice and virtue,
- therefore, may be compared to sounds, colours, heat and cold, which,
- according to modern philosophy, are not qualities in objects, but
- perceptions in the mind: And this discovery in morals, like that other
- in physics, is to be regarded as a considerable advancement of the
- speculative sciences; though, like that too, it has little or no
- influence on practice. Nothing can be more real, or concern us more,
- than our own sentiments of pleasure and uneasiness; and if these be
- favourable to virtue, and unfavourable to vice, no more can be requisite
- to the regulation of our conduct and behaviour.
- I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may,
- perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality,
- which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that the author
- proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes
- the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs;
- when of a sudden I am surprized to find, that instead of the usual
- copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition
- that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is
- imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this
- ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, it is
- necessary that it should be observed and explained; and at the same time
- that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable,
- how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely
- different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution,
- I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that
- this small attention would subvert all the vulgar systems of morality,
- and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded
- merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by reason.
- SECT. II MORAL DISTINCTIONS DERIVed FROM A MORAL SENSE
- Thus the course of the argument leads us to conclude, that since vice
- and virtue are not discoverable merely by reason, or the comparison
- of ideas, it must be by means of some impression or sentiment they
- occasion, that we are able to mark the difference betwixt them. Our
- decisions concerning moral rectitude and depravity are evidently
- perceptions; and as all perceptions are either impressions or ideas, the
- exclusion of the one is a convincing argument for the other. Morality,
- therefore, is more properly felt than judged of; though this feeling or
- sentiment is commonly so soft and gentle, that we are apt to confound
- it with an idea, according to our common custom of taking all things for
- the same, which have any near resemblance to each other.
- The next question is, Of what nature are these impressions, and after
- what manner do they operate upon us? Here we cannot remain long in
- suspense, but must pronounce the impression arising from virtue, to
- be agreeable, and that proceding from vice to be uneasy. Every moments
- experience must convince us of this. There is no spectacle so fair and
- beautiful as a noble and generous action; nor any which gives us more
- abhorrence than one that is cruel and treacherous. No enjoyment equals
- the satisfaction we receive from the company of those we love and
- esteem; as the greatest of all punishments is to be obliged to pass our
- lives with those we hate or contemn. A very play or romance may afford
- us instances of this pleasure, which virtue conveys to us; and pain,
- which arises from vice.
- Now since the distinguishing impressions, by which moral good or evil is
- known, are nothing but particular pains or pleasures; it follows,
- that in all enquiries concerning these moral distinctions, it will be
- sufficient to shew the principles, which make us feel a satisfaction or
- uneasiness from the survey of any character, in order to satisfy us
- why the character is laudable or blameable. An action, or sentiment,
- or character is virtuous or vicious; why? because its view causes
- a pleasure or uneasiness of a particular kind. In giving a reason,
- therefore, for the pleasure or uneasiness, we sufficiently explain the
- vice or virtue. To have the sense of virtue, is nothing but to feel a
- satisfaction of a particular kind from the contemplation of a character.
- The very feeling constitutes our praise or admiration. We go no farther;
- nor do we enquire into the cause of the satisfaction. We do not infer
- a character to be virtuous, because it pleases: But in feeling that it
- pleases after such a particular manner, we in effect feel that it is
- virtuous. The case is the same as in our judgments concerning all kinds
- of beauty, and tastes, and sensations. Our approbation is implyed in the
- immediate pleasure they convey to us.
- I have objected to the system, which establishes eternal rational
- measures of right and wrong, that it is impossible to shew, in the
- actions of reasonable creatures, any relations, which are not found
- in external objects; and therefore, if morality always attended these
- relations, it were possible for inanimate matter to become virtuous or
- vicious. Now it may, in like manner, be objected to the present system,
- that if virtue and vice be determined by pleasure and pain, these
- qualities must, in every case, arise from the sensations; and
- consequently any object, whether animate or inanimate, rational or
- irrational, might become morally good or evil, provided it can excite
- a satisfaction or uneasiness. But though this objection seems to be the
- very same, it has by no means the same force, in the one case as in
- the other. For, first, tis evident, that under the term pleasure, we
- comprehend sensations, which are very different from each other, and
- which have only such a distant resemblance, as is requisite to make them
- be expressed by the same abstract term. A good composition of music and
- a bottle of good wine equally produce pleasure; and what is more, their
- goodness is determined merely by the pleasure. But shall we say upon
- that account, that the wine is harmonious, or the music of a good
- flavour? In like manner an inanimate object, and the character or
- sentiments of any person may, both of them, give satisfaction; but as
- the satisfaction is different, this keeps our sentiments concerning them
- from being confounded, and makes us ascribe virtue to the one, and not
- to the other. Nor is every sentiment of pleasure or pain, which arises
- from characters and actions, of that peculiar kind, which makes us
- praise or condemn. The good qualities of an enemy are hurtful to us; but
- may still command our esteem and respect. It is only when a character
- is considered in general, without reference to our particular interest,
- that it causes such a feeling or sentiment, as denominates it morally
- good or evil. It is true, those sentiments, from interest and morals,
- are apt to be confounded, and naturally run into one another. It seldom
- happens, that we do not think an enemy vicious, and can distinguish
- betwixt his opposition to our interest and real villainy or baseness.
- But this hinders not, but that the sentiments are, in themselves,
- distinct; and a man of temper and judgment may preserve himself from
- these illusions. In like manner, though it is certain a musical voice is
- nothing but one that naturally gives a particular kind of pleasure; yet
- it is difficult for a man to be sensible, that the voice of an enemy is
- agreeable, or to allow it to be musical. But a person of a fine ear, who
- has the command of himself, can separate these feelings, and give praise
- to what deserves it.
- SECONDLY, We may call to remembrance the preceding system of the
- passions, in order to remark a still more considerable difference
- among our pains and pleasures. Pride and humility, love and hatred are
- excited, when there is any thing presented to us, that both bears a
- relation to the object of the passion, and produces a separate sensation
- related to the sensation of the passion. Now virtue and vice are
- attended with these circumstances. They must necessarily be placed
- either in ourselves or others, and excite either pleasure or uneasiness;
- and therefore must give rise to one of these four passions; which
- clearly distinguishes them from the pleasure and pain arising from
- inanimate objects, that often bear no relation to us: And this is,
- perhaps, the most considerable effect that virtue and vice have upon the
- human mind.
- It may now be asked in general, concerning this pain or pleasure, that
- distinguishes moral good and evil, FROM WHAT PRINCIPLES IS IT DERIVED,
- AND WHENCE DOES IT ARISE IN THE HUMAN MIND? To this I reply, first,
- that it is absurd to imagine, that in every particular instance, these
- sentiments are produced by an original quality and primary constitution.
- For as the number of our duties is, in a manner, infinite, it is
- impossible that our original instincts should extend to each of them,
- and from our very first infancy impress on the human mind all that
- multitude of precepts, which are contained in the compleatest system
- of ethics. Such a method of proceeding is not conformable to the usual
- maxims, by which nature is conducted, where a few principles produce all
- that variety we observe in the universe, and every thing is carryed on
- in the easiest and most simple manner. It is necessary, therefore, to
- abridge these primary impulses, and find some more general principles,
- upon which all our notions of morals are founded.
- But in the second place, should it be asked, Whether we ought to search
- for these principles in nature, or whether we must look for them in some
- other origin? I would reply, that our answer to this question depends
- upon the definition of the word, Nature, than which there is none more
- ambiguous and equivocal. If nature be opposed to miracles, not only the
- distinction betwixt vice and virtue is natural, but also every event,
- which has ever happened in the world, EXCEPTING THOSE MIRACLES, ON WHICH
- OUR RELIGION IS FOUNDED. In saying, then, that the sentiments of vice
- and virtue are natural in this sense, we make no very extraordinary
- discovery.
- But nature may also be opposed to rare and unusual; and in this sense
- of the word, which is the common one, there may often arise disputes
- concerning what is natural or unnatural; and one may in general affirm,
- that we are not possessed of any very precise standard, by which these
- disputes can be decided. Frequent and rare depend upon the number of
- examples we have observed; and as this number may gradually encrease
- or diminish, it will be impossible to fix any exact boundaries betwixt
- them. We may only affirm on this head, that if ever there was any thing,
- which coued be called natural in this sense, the sentiments of morality
- certainly may; since there never was any nation of the world, nor any
- single person in any nation, who was utterly deprived of them, and
- who never, in any instance, shewed the least approbation or dislike of
- manners. These sentiments are so rooted in our constitution and temper,
- that without entirely confounding the human mind by disease or madness,
- it is impossible to extirpate and destroy them.
- But nature may also be opposed to artifice, as well as to what is rare
- and unusual; and in this sense it may be disputed, whether the notions
- of virtue be natural or not. We readily forget, that the designs,
- and projects, and views of men are principles as necessary in their
- operation as heat and cold, moist and dry: But taking them to be free
- and entirely our own, it is usual for us to set them in opposition
- to the other principles of nature should it, therefore, be demanded,
- whether the sense of virtue be natural or artificial, I am of opinion,
- that it is impossible for me at present to give any precise answer to
- this question. Perhaps it will appear afterwards, that our sense of some
- virtues is artificial, and that of others natural. The discussion of
- this question will be more proper, when we enter upon an exact detail of
- each particular vice and virtue.
- [Footnote 14. In the following discourse natural is also
- opposed sometimes to civil, sometimes to moral. The
- opposition will always discover the sense, in which it is
- taken.]
- Mean while it may not be amiss to observe from these definitions of
- natural and unnatural, that nothing can be more unphilosophical than
- those systems, which assert, that virtue is the same with what is
- natural, and vice with what is unnatural. For in the first sense of the
- word, Nature, as opposed to miracles, both vice and virtue are equally
- natural; and in the second sense, as opposed to what is unusual, perhaps
- virtue will be found to be the most unnatural. At least it must be
- owned, that heroic virtue, being as unusual, is as little natural as the
- most brutal barbarity. As to the third sense of the word, it is certain,
- that both vice and virtue are equally artificial, and out of nature. For
- however it may be disputed, whether the notion of a merit or demerit
- in certain actions be natural or artificial, it is evident, that the
- actions themselves are artificial, and are performed with a certain
- design and intention; otherwise they coued never be ranked under any of
- these denominations. It is impossible, therefore, that the character
- of natural and unnatural can ever, in any sense, mark the boundaries of
- vice and virtue.
- Thus we are still brought back to our first position, that virtue is
- distinguished by the pleasure, and vice by the pain, that any action,
- sentiment or character gives us by the mere view and contemplation.
- This decision is very commodious; because it reduces us to this simple
- question, Why any action or sentiment upon the general view or survey,
- gives a certain satisfaction or uneasiness, in order to shew the
- origin of its moral rectitude or depravity, without looking for any
- incomprehensible relations and qualities, which never did exist
- in nature, nor even in our imagination, by any clear and distinct
- conception. I flatter myself I have executed a great part of my present
- design by a state of the question, which appears to me so free from
- ambiguity and obscurity.
- PART II OF JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE
- SECT. I JUSTICE, WHETHER A NATURAL OR ARTIFICIAL VIRTUE?
- I have already hinted, that our sense of every kind of virtue is not
- natural; but that there are some virtues, that produce pleasure and
- approbation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from
- the circumstances and necessity of mankind. Of this kind I assert
- justice to be; and shall endeavour to defend this opinion by a short,
- and, I hope, convincing argument, before I examine the nature of the
- artifice, from which the sense of that virtue is derived.
- It is evident, that when we praise any actions, we regard only the
- motives that produced them, and consider the actions as signs or
- indications of certain principles in the mind and temper. The external
- performance has no merit. We must look within to find the moral quality.
- This we cannot do directly; and therefore fix our attention on actions,
- as on external signs. But these actions are still considered as signs;
- and the ultimate object of our praise and approbation is the motive,
- that produced them.
- After the same manner, when we require any action, or blame a person for
- not performing it, we always suppose, that one in that situation should
- be influenced by the proper motive of that action, and we esteem it
- vicious in him to be regardless of it. If we find, upon enquiry, that
- the virtuous motive was still powerful over his breast, though checked
- in its operation by some circumstances unknown to us, we retract our
- blame, and have the same esteem for him, as if he had actually performed
- the action, which we require of him.
- It appears, therefore, that all virtuous actions derive their merit
- only from virtuous motives, and are considered merely as signs of those
- motives. From this principle I conclude, that the first virtuous motive,
- which bestows a merit on any action, can never be a regard to the virtue
- of that action, but must be some other natural motive or principle. To
- suppose, that the mere regard to the virtue of the action may be the
- first motive, which produced the action, and rendered it virtuous, is to
- reason in a circle. Before we can have such a regard, the action must
- be really virtuous; and this virtue must be derived from some virtuous
- motive: And consequently the virtuous motive must be different from the
- regard to the virtue of the action. A virtuous motive is requisite to
- render an action virtuous. An action must be virtuous, before we can
- have a regard to its virtue. Some virtuous motive, therefore, must be
- antecedent to that regard.
- Nor is this merely a metaphysical subtilty; but enters into all our
- reasonings in common life, though perhaps we may not be able to place it
- in such distinct philosophical terms. We blame a father for neglecting
- his child. Why? because it shews a want of natural affection, which is
- the duty of every parent. Were not natural affection a duty, the care of
- children coued not be a duty; and it were impossible we coued have the
- duty in our eye in the attention we give to our offspring. In this case,
- therefore, all men suppose a motive to the action distinct from a sense
- of duty.
- Here is a man, that does many benevolent actions; relieves the
- distressed, comforts the afflicted, and extends his bounty even to the
- greatest strangers. No character can be more amiable and virtuous. We
- regard these actions as proofs of the greatest humanity. This humanity
- bestows a merit on the actions. A regard to this merit is, therefore,
- a secondary consideration, and derived from the antecedent principle of
- humanity, which is meritorious and laudable.
- In short, it may be established as an undoubted maxim, THAT NO ACTION
- CAN BE VIRTUOUS, OR MORALLY GOOD, UNLESS THERE BE IN HUMAN NATURE SOME
- MOTIVE TO PRODUCE IT, DISTINCT FROM THE SENSE OF ITS MORALITY.
- But may not the sense of morality or duty produce an action, without any
- other motive? I answer, It may: But this is no objection to the present
- doctrine. When any virtuous motive or principle is common in human
- nature, a person, who feels his heart devoid of that motive, may hate
- himself upon that account, and may perform the action without the
- motive, from a certain sense of duty, in order to acquire by practice,
- that virtuous principle, or at least, to disguise to himself, as much
- as possible, his want of it. A man that really feels no gratitude in his
- temper, is still pleased to perform grateful actions, and thinks he has,
- by that means, fulfilled his duty. Actions are at first only considered
- as signs of motives: But it is usual, in this case, as in all others, to
- fix our attention on the signs, and neglect, in some measure, the thing
- signifyed. But though, on some occasions, a person may perform an action
- merely out of regard to its moral obligation, yet still this supposes
- in human nature some distinct principles, which are capable of producing
- the action, and whose moral beauty renders the action meritorious.
- Now to apply all this to the present case; I suppose a person to have
- lent me a sum of money, on condition that it be restored in a few days;
- and also suppose, that after the expiration of the term agreed on, he
- demands the sum: I ask, What reason or motive have I to restore the
- money? It will, perhaps, be said, that my regard to justice, and
- abhorrence of villainy and knavery, are sufficient reasons for me, if
- I have the least grain of honesty, or sense of duty and obligation. And
- this answer, no doubt, is just and satisfactory to man in his civilized
- state, and when trained up according to a certain discipline and
- education. But in his rude and more natural condition, if you are
- pleased to call such a condition natural, this answer would be rejected
- as perfectly unintelligible and sophistical. For one in that situation
- would immediately ask you, WHEREIN CONSISTS THIS HONESTY AND JUSTICE,
- WHICH YOU FIND IN RESTORING A LOAN, AND ABSTAINING FROM THE PROPERTY
- OF OTHERS? It does not surely lie in the external action. It must,
- therefore be placed in the motive, from which the external action is
- derived. This motive can never be a regard to the honesty of the action.
- For it is a plain fallacy to say, that a virtuous motive is requisite
- to render an action honest, and at the same time that a regard to the
- honesty is the motive of the action. We can never have a regard to the
- virtue of an action, unless the action be antecedently virtuous. No
- action can be virtuous, but so far as it proceeds from a virtuous
- motive. A virtuous motive, therefore, must precede the regard to the
- virtue, and it is impossible, that the virtuous motive and the regard to
- the virtue can be the same.
- It is requisite, then, to find some motive to acts of justice and
- honesty, distinct from our regard to the honesty; and in this lies the
- great difficulty. For should we say, that a concern for our private
- interest or reputation is the legitimate motive to all honest actions;
- it would follow, that wherever that concern ceases, honesty can no
- longer have place. But it is certain, that self-love, when it acts at
- its liberty, instead of engaging us to honest actions, is the source
- of all injustice and violence; nor can a man ever correct those vices,
- without correcting and restraining the natural movements of that
- appetite.
- But should it be affirmed, that the reason or motive of such actions is
- the regard to publick interest, to which nothing is more contrary than
- examples of injustice and dishonesty; should this be said, I would
- propose the three following considerations, as worthy of our attention.
- First, public interest is not naturally attached to the observation of
- the rules of justice; but is only connected with it, after an artificial
- convention for the establishment of these rules, as shall be shewn more
- at large hereafter. Secondly, if we suppose, that the loan was secret,
- and that it is necessary for the interest of the person, that the money
- be restored in the same manner (as when the lender would conceal his
- riches) in that case the example ceases, and the public is no longer
- interested in the actions of the borrower; though I suppose there is no
- moralist, who will affirm, that the duty and obligation ceases. Thirdly,
- experience sufficiently proves, that men, in the ordinary conduct
- of life, look not so far as the public interest, when they pay their
- creditors, perform their promises, and abstain from theft, and robbery,
- and injustice of every kind. That is a motive too remote and too sublime
- to affect the generality of mankind, and operate with any force in
- actions so contrary to private interest as are frequently those of
- justice and common honesty.
- In general, it may be affirmed, that there is no such passion in human
- minds, as the love of mankind, merely as such, independent of personal
- qualities, of services, or of relation to ourseit It is true, there is
- no human, and indeed no sensible, creature, whose happiness or misery
- does not, in some measure, affect us when brought near to us, and
- represented in lively colours: But this proceeds merely from sympathy,
- and is no proof of such an universal affection to mankind, since this
- concern extends itself beyond our own species. An affection betwixt the
- sexes is a passion evidently implanted in human nature; and this passion
- not only appears in its peculiar symptoms, but also in inflaming every
- other principle of affection, and raising a stronger love from beauty,
- wit, kindness, than what would otherwise flow from them. Were there an
- universal love among all human creatures, it would appear after the same
- manner. Any degree of a good quality would cause a stronger affection
- than the same degree of a bad quality would cause hatred; contrary to
- what we find by experience. Men's tempers are different, and some have a
- propensity to the tender, and others to the rougher, affections: But
- in the main, we may affirm, that man in general, or human nature, is
- nothing but the object both of love and hatred, and requires some other
- cause, which by a double relation of impressions and ideas, may excite
- these passions. In vain would we endeavour to elude this hypothesis.
- There are no phaenomena that point out any such kind affection to
- men, independent of their merit, and every other circumstance. We
- love company in general; but it is as we love any other amusement. An
- Englishman in Italy is a friend: A Euro paean in China; and perhaps a
- man would be beloved as such, were we to meet him in the moon. But
- this proceeds only from the relation to ourselves; which in these cases
- gathers force by being confined to a few persons.
- If public benevolence, therefore, or a regard to the interests of
- mankind, cannot be the original motive to justice, much less can private
- benevolence, or a regard to the interests of the party concerned, be
- this motive. For what if he be my enemy, and has given me just cause to
- hate him? What if he be a vicious man, and deserves the hatred of all
- mankind? What if he be a miser, and can make no use of what I would
- deprive him of? What if he be a profligate debauchee, and would rather
- receive harm than benefit from large possessions? What if I be in
- necessity, and have urgent motives to acquire something to my family?
- In all these cases, the original motive to justice would fail; and
- consequently the justice itself, and along with it all property, tight,
- and obligation.
- A rich man lies under a moral obligation to communicate to those in
- necessity a share of his superfluities. Were private benevolence the
- original motive to justice, a man would not be obliged to leave others
- in the possession of more than he is obliged to give them. At least
- the difference would be very inconsiderable. Men generally fix their
- affections more on what they are possessed of, than on what they never
- enjoyed: For this reason, it would be greater cruelty to dispossess a
- man of any thing, than not to give it him. But who will assert, that
- this is the only foundation of justice?
- Besides, we must consider, that the chief reason, why men attach
- themselves so much to their possessions is, that they consider them
- as their property, and as secured to them inviolably by the laws of
- society. But this is a secondary consideration, and dependent on the
- preceding notions of justice and property.
- A man's property is supposed to be fenced against every mortal, in every
- possible case. But private benevolence is, and ought to be, weaker in
- some persons, than in others: And in many, or indeed in most persons,
- must absolutely fail. Private benevolence, therefore, is not the
- original motive of justice.
- From all this it follows, that we have no real or universal motive for
- observing the laws of equity, but the very equity and merit of that
- observance; and as no action can be equitable or meritorious, where
- it cannot arise from some separate motive, there is here an evident
- sophistry and reasoning in a circle. Unless, therefore, we will allow,
- that nature has established a sophistry, and rendered it necessary and
- unavoidable, we must allow, that the sense of justice and injustice is
- not derived from nature, but arises artificially, though necessarily
- from education, and human conventions.
- I shall add, as a corollary to this reasoning, that since no action can
- be laudable or blameable, without some motives or impelling passions,
- distinct from the sense of morals, these distinct passions must have a
- great influence on that sense. It is according to their general force
- in human nature, that we blame or praise. In judging of the beauty of
- animal bodies, we always carry in our eye the oeconomy of a certain
- species; and where the limbs and features observe that proportion, which
- is common to the species, we pronounce them handsome and beautiful.
- In like manner we always consider the natural and usual force of the
- passions, when we determine concerning vice and virtue; and if the
- passions depart very much from the common measures on either side, they
- are always disapproved as vicious. A man naturally loves his children
- better than his nephews, his nephews better than his cousins, his
- cousins better than strangers, where every thing else is equal. Hence
- arise our common measures of duty, in preferring the one to the other.
- Our sense of duty always follows the common and natural course of our
- passions.
- To avoid giving offence, I must here observe, that when I deny justice
- to be a natural virtue, I make use of the word, natural, only as opposed
- to artificial. In another sense of the word; as no principle of the
- human mind is more natural than a sense of virtue; so no virtue is more
- natural than justice. Mankind is an inventive species; and where an
- invention is obvious and absolutely necessary, it may as properly be
- said to be natural as any thing that proceeds immediately from original
- principles, without the intervention of thought or reflection. Though
- the rules of justice be artificial, they are not arbitrary. Nor is
- the expression improper to call them Laws of Nature; if by natural we
- understand what is common to any species, or even if we confine it to
- mean what is inseparable from the species.
- SECT. II OF THE ORIGIN OF JUSTICE AND PROPERTY
- We now proceed to examine two questions, viz, CONCERNING THE MANNER, IN
- WHICH THE RULES OF JUSTICE ARE ESTABLISHed BY THE ARTIFICE OF MEN;
- and CONCERNING THE REASONS, WHICH DETERMINE US TO ATTRIBUTE TO THE
- OBSERVANCE OR NEGLECT OF THESE RULES A MORAL BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY. These
- questions will appear afterwards to be distinct. We shall begin with the
- former.
- Of all the animals, with which this globe is peopled, there is none
- towards whom nature seems, at first sight, to have exercised more
- cruelty than towards man, in the numberless wants and necessities, with
- which she has loaded him, and in the slender means, which she affords
- to the relieving these necessities. In other creatures these two
- particulars generally compensate each other. If we consider the lion as
- a voracious and carnivorous animal, we shall easily discover him to be
- very necessitous; but if we turn our eye to his make and temper, his
- agility, his courage, his arms, and his force, we shall find, that his
- advantages hold proportion with his wants. The sheep and ox are deprived
- of all these advantages; but their appetites are moderate, and their
- food is of easy purchase. In man alone, this unnatural conjunction of
- infirmity, and of necessity, may be observed in its greatest perfection.
- Not only the food, which is required for his sustenance, flies his
- search and approach, or at least requires his labour to be produced, but
- he must be possessed of cloaths and lodging, to defend him against the
- injuries of the weather; though to consider him only in himself, he
- is provided neither with arms, nor force, nor other natural abilities,
- which are in any degree answerable to so many necessities.
- It is by society alone he is able to supply his defects, and raise
- himself up to an equality with his fellow-creatures, and even acquire a
- superiority above them. By society all his infirmities are compensated;
- and though in that situation his wants multiply every moment upon him,
- yet his abilities are still more augmented, and leave him in every
- respect more satisfied and happy, than it is possible for him, in his
- savage and solitary condition, ever to become. When every individual
- person labours a-part, and only for himself, his force is too small to
- execute any considerable work; his labour being employed in supplying
- all his different necessities, he never attains a perfection in any
- particular art; and as his force and success are not at all times equal,
- the least failure in either of these particulars must be attended with
- inevitable ruin and misery. Society provides a remedy for these three
- inconveniences. By the conjunction of forces, our power is augmented:
- By the partition of employments, our ability encreases: And by mutual
- succour we are less exposed to fortune and accidents. It is by
- this additional force, ability, and security, that society becomes
- advantageous.
- But in order to form society, it is requisite not only that it be
- advantageous, but also that men be sensible of these advantages; and
- it is impossible, in their wild uncultivated state, that by study and
- reflection alone, they should ever be able to attain this knowledge.
- Most fortunately, therefore, there is conjoined to those necessities,
- whose remedies are remote and obscure, another necessity, which having a
- present and more obvious remedy, may justly be regarded as the first
- and original principle of human society. This necessity is no other than
- that natural appetite betwixt the sexes, which unites them together, and
- preserves their union, till a new tye takes place in their concern for
- their common offspring. This new concern becomes also a principle of
- union betwixt the parents and offspring, and forms a more numerous
- society; where the parents govern by the advantage of their superior
- strength and wisdom, and at the same time are restrained in the exercise
- of their authority by that natural affection, which they bear their
- children. In a little time, custom and habit operating on the tender
- minds of the children, makes them sensible of the advantages, which they
- may reap from society, as well as fashions them by degrees for it, by
- rubbing off those rough corners and untoward affections, which prevent
- their coalition.
- For it must be confest, that however the circumstances of human nature
- may render an union necessary, and however those passions of lust and
- natural affection may seem to render it unavoidable; yet there are other
- particulars in our natural temper, and in our outward circumstances,
- which are very incommodious, and are even contrary to the requisite
- conjunction. Among the former, we may justly esteem our selfishness to
- be the most considerable. I am sensible, that generally speaking, the
- representations of this quality have been carried much too far; and that
- the descriptions, which certain philosophers delight so much to form
- of mankind in this particular, are as wide of nature as any accounts
- of monsters, which we meet with in fables and romances. So far from
- thinking, that men have no affection for any thing beyond themselves,
- I am of opinion, that though it be rare to meet with one, who loves any
- single person better than himself; yet it is as rare to meet with one,
- in whom all the kind affections, taken together, do not overbalance all
- the selfish. Consult common experience: Do you not see, that though
- the whole expence of the family be generally under the direction of the
- master of it, yet there are few that do not bestow the largest part of
- their fortunes on the pleasures of their wives, and the education of
- their children, reserving the smallest portion for their own proper use
- and entertainment. This is what we may observe concerning such as have
- those endearing ties; and may presume, that the case would be the same
- with others, were they placed in a like situation.
- But though this generosity must be acknowledged to the honour of human
- nature, we may at the same time remark, that so noble an affection,
- instead of fitting men for large societies, is almost as contrary
- to them, as the most narrow selfishness. For while each person loves
- himself better than any other single person, and in his love to others
- bears the greatest affection to his relations and acquaintance, this
- must necessarily produce an oppositon of passions, and a consequent
- opposition of actions; which cannot but be dangerous to the
- new-established union.
- It is however worth while to remark, that this contrariety of passions
- would be attended with but small danger, did it not concur with
- a peculiarity in our outward circumstances, which affords it an
- opportunity of exerting itself. There are different species of goods,
- which we are possessed of; the internal satisfaction of our minds, the
- external advantages of our body, and the enjoyment of such possessions
- as we have acquired by our industry and good fortune. We are perfectly
- secure in the enjoyment of the first. The second may be ravished from
- us, but can be of no advantage to him who deprives us of them. The last
- only are both exposed to the violence of others, and may be transferred
- without suffering any loss or alteration; while at the same time, there
- is not a sufficient quantity of them to supply every one's desires and
- necessities. As the improvement, therefore, of these goods is the chief
- advantage of society, so the instability of their possession, along with
- their scarcity, is the chief impediment.
- In vain should we expect to find, in uncultivated nature, a remedy to
- this inconvenience; or hope for any inartificial principle of the
- human mind, which might controul those partial affections, and make us
- overcome the temptations arising from our circumstances. The idea of
- justice can never serve to this purpose, or be taken for a natural
- principle, capable of inspiring men with an equitable conduct towards
- each other. That virtue, as it is now understood, would never have
- been dreamed of among rude and savage men. For the notion of injury or
- injustice implies an immorality or vice committed against some
- other person: And as every immorality is derived from some defect or
- unsoundness of the passions, and as this defect must be judged of, in a
- great measure, from the ordinary course of nature in the constitution
- of the mind; it will be easy to know, whether we be guilty of any
- immorality, with regard to others, by considering the natural, and usual
- force of those several affections, which are directed towards them.
- Now it appears, that in the original frame of our mind, our strongest
- attention is confined to ourselves; our next is extended to our
- relations and acquaintance; and it is only the weakest which reaches to
- strangers and indifferent persons. This partiality, then, and unequal
- affection, must not only have an influence on our behaviour and conduct
- in society, but even on our ideas of vice and virtue; so as to make
- us regard any remarkable transgression of such a degree of partiality,
- either by too great an enlargement, or contraction of the affections,
- as vicious and immoral. This we may observe in our common judgments
- concerning actions, where we blame a person, who either centers all
- his affections in his family, or is so regardless of them, as, in any
- opposition of interest, to give the preference to a stranger, or
- mere chance acquaintance. From all which it follows, that our natural
- uncultivated ideas of morality, instead of providing a remedy for the
- partiality of our affections, do rather conform themselves to that
- partiality, and give it an additional force and influence.
- The remedy, then, is not derived from nature, but from artifice; or
- more e properly speaking, nature provides a remedy in the judgment and
- understanding, for what is irregular and incommodious in the affections.
- For when men, from their early education in society, have become
- sensible of the infinite advantages that result from it, and have
- besides acquired a new affection to company and conversation; and when
- they have observed, that the principal disturbance in society arises
- from those goods, which we call external, and from their looseness and
- easy transition from one person to another; they must seek for a remedy
- by putting these goods, as far as possible, on the same footing with
- the fixed and constant advantages of the mind and body. This can be
- done after no other manner, than by a convention entered into by all the
- members of the society to bestow stability on the possession of those
- external goods, and leave every one in the peaceable enjoyment of what
- he may acquire by his fortune and industry. By this means, every one
- knows what he may safely possess; and the passions ale restrained
- in their partial and contradictory motions. Nor is such a restraint
- contrary to these passions; for if so, it coued never be entered into,
- nor maintained; but it is only contrary to their heedless and impetuous
- movement. Instead of departing from our own interest, or from that of
- our nearest friends, by abstaining from the possessions of others, we
- cannot better consult both these interests, than by such a convention;
- because it is by that means we maintain society, which is so necessary
- to their well-being and subsistence, as well as to our own.
- This convention is not of the nature of a promise: For even promises
- themselves, as we shall see afterwards, arise from human conventions. It
- is only a general sense of common interest; which sense all the members
- of the society express to one another, and which induces them to
- regulate their conduct by certain rules. I observe, that it will be for
- my interest to leave another in the possession of his goods, provided he
- will act in the same manner with regard to me. He is sensible of a like
- interest in the regulation of his conduct. When this common sense of
- interest is mutually expressed, and is known to both, it produces a
- suitable resolution and behaviour. And this may properly enough
- be called a convention or agreement betwixt us, though without the
- interposition of a promise; since the actions of each of us have a
- reference to those of the other, and are performed upon the supposition,
- that something is to be performed on the other part. Two men, who pull
- the oars of a boat, do it by an agreement or convention, though they
- have never given promises to each other. Nor is the rule concerning the
- stability of possession the less derived from human conventions, that it
- arises gradually, and acquires force by a slow progression, and by our
- repeated experience of the inconveniences of transgressing it. On the
- contrary, this experience assures us still more, that the sense of
- interest has become common to all our fellows, and gives us a confidence
- of the future regularity of their conduct: And it is only on the
- expectation of this, that our moderation and abstinence are founded.
- In like manner are languages gradually established by human conventions
- without any promise. In like manner do gold and silver become the common
- measures of exchange, and are esteemed sufficient payment for what is of
- a hundred times their value.
- After this convention, concerning abstinence from the possessions of
- others, is entered into, and every one has acquired a stability in his
- possessions, there immediately arise the ideas of justice and injustice;
- as also those of property, right, and obligation. The latter are
- altogether unintelligible without first understanding the former.
- Our property is nothing but those goods, whose constant possession is
- established by the laws of society; that is, by the laws of justice.
- Those, therefore, who make use of the words property, or right, or
- obligation, before they have explained the origin of justice, or
- even make use of them in that explication, are guilty of a very gross
- fallacy, and can never reason upon any solid foundation. A man's
- property is some object related to him. This relation is not natural,
- but moral, and founded on justice. It is very preposterous, therefore,
- to imagine, that we can have any idea of property, without fully
- comprehending the nature of justice, and shewing its origin in the
- artifice and contrivance of man. The origin of justice explains that of
- property. The same artifice gives rise to both. As our first and most
- natural sentiment of morals is founded on the nature of our passions,
- and gives the preference to ourselves and friends, above strangers; it
- is impossible there can be naturally any such thing as a fixed right
- or property, while the opposite passions of men impel them in contrary
- directions, and are not restrained by any convention or agreement.
- No one can doubt, that the convention for the distinction of property,
- and for the stability of possession, is of all circumstances the most
- necessary to the establishment of human society, and that after the
- agreement for the fixing and observing of this rule, there remains
- little or nothing to be done towards settling a perfect harmony and
- concord. All the other passions, besides this of interest, are either
- easily restrained, or are not of such pernicious consequence, when
- indulged. Vanity is rather to be esteemed a social passion, and a bond
- of union among men. Pity and love are to be considered in the same
- light. And as to envy and revenge, though pernicious, they operate
- only by intervals, and are directed against particular persons, whom we
- consider as our superiors or enemies. This avidity alone, of acquiring
- goods and possessions for ourselves and our nearest friends, is
- insatiable, perpetual, universal, and directly destructive of society.
- There scarce is any one, who is not actuated by it; and there is no one,
- who has not reason to fear from it, when it acts without any restraint,
- and gives way to its first and most natural movements. So that upon
- the whole, we are to esteem the difficulties in the establishment of
- society, to be greater or less, according to those we encounter in
- regulating and restraining this passion.
- It is certain, that no affection of the human mind has both a
- sufficient force, and a proper direction to counterbalance the love of
- gain, and render men fit members of society, by making them abstain from
- the possessions of others. Benevolence to strangers is too weak for this
- purpose; and as to the other passions, they rather inflame this avidity,
- when we observe, that the larger our possessions are, the more ability
- we have of gratifying all our appetites. There is no passion, therefore,
- capable of controlling the interested affection, but the very affection
- itself, by an alteration of its direction. Now this alteration must
- necessarily take place upon the least reflection; since it is evident,
- that the passion is much better satisfyed by its restraint, than by its
- liberty, and that in preserving society, we make much greater advances
- in the acquiring possessions, than in the solitary and forlorn
- condition, which must follow upon violence and an universal licence.
- The question, therefore, concerning the wickedness or goodness of human
- nature, enters not in the least into that other question concerning
- the origin of society; nor is there any thing to be considered but
- the degrees of men's sagacity or folly. For whether the passion of
- self-interest be esteemed vicious or virtuous, it is all a case; since
- itself alone restrains it: So that if it be virtuous, men become social
- by their virtue; if vicious, their vice has the same effect.
- Now as it is by establishing the rule for the stability of possession,
- that this passion restrains itself; if that rule be very abstruse,
- and of difficult invention; society must be esteemed, in a manner,
- accidental, and the effect of many ages. But if it be found, that
- nothing can be more simple and obvious than that rule; that every
- parent, in order to preserve peace among his children, must establish
- it; and that these first rudiments of justice must every day be
- improved, as the society enlarges: If all this appear evident, as it
- certainly must, we may conclude, that it is utterly impossible for men
- to remain any considerable time in that savage condition, which precedes
- society; but that his very first state and situation may justly be
- esteemed social. This, however, hinders not, but that philosophers may,
- if they please, extend their reasoning to the supposed state of nature;
- provided they allow it to be a mere philosophical fiction, which never
- had, and never coued have any reality. Human nature being composed
- of two principal parts, which are requisite in all its actions, the
- affections and understanding; it is certain, that the blind motions of
- the former, without the direction of the latter, incapacitate men for
- society: And it may be allowed us to consider separately the effects,
- that result from the separate operations of these two component parts of
- the mind. The same liberty may be permitted to moral, which is allowed
- to natural philosophers; and it is very usual with the latter to
- consider any motion as compounded and consisting of two parts separate
- from each other, though at the same time they acknowledge it to be in
- itself uncompounded and inseparable.
- This state of nature, therefore, is to be regarded as a mere fiction,
- not unlike that of the golden age, which poets have invented; only with
- this difference, that the former is described as full of war, violence
- and injustice; whereas the latter is pointed out to us, as the most
- charming and most peaceable condition, that can possibly be imagined.
- The seasons, in that first age of nature, were so temperate, if we
- may believe the poets, that there was no necessity for men to provide
- themselves with cloaths and houses as a security against the violence
- of heat and cold. The rivers flowed with wine and milk: The oaks yielded
- honey; and nature spontaneously produced her greatest delicacies.
- Nor were these the chief advantages of that happy age. The storms and
- tempests were not alone removed from nature; but those more furious
- tempests were unknown to human breasts, which now cause such uproar, and
- engender such confusion. Avarice, ambition, cruelty, selfishness, were
- never heard of: Cordial affection, compassion, sympathy, were the
- only movements, with which the human mind was yet acquainted. Even
- the distinction of mine and thine was banished from that happy race
- of mortals, and carryed with them the very notions of property and
- obligation, justice and injustice.
- This, no doubt, is to be regarded as an idle fiction; but yet deserves
- our attention, because nothing can more evidently shew the origin of
- those virtues, which are the subjects of our present enquiry. I have
- already observed, that justice takes its rise from human conventions;
- and that these are intended as a remedy to some inconveniences, which
- proceed from the concurrence of certain qualities of the human mind
- with the situation of external objects. The qualities of the mind
- are selfishness and limited generosity: And the situation of external
- objects is their easy change, joined to their scarcity in comparison
- of the wants and desires of men. But however philosophers may have
- been bewildered in those speculations, poets have been guided more
- infallibly, by a certain taste or common instinct, which in most kinds
- of reasoning goes farther than any of that art and philosophy, with
- which we have been yet acquainted. They easily perceived, if every man
- had a tender regard for another, or if nature supplied abundantly all
- our wants and desires, that the jealousy of interest, which justice
- supposes, could no longer have place; nor would there be any occasion
- for those distinctions and limits of property and possession, which at
- present are in use among mankind. Encrease to a sufficient degree the
- benevolence of men, or the bounty of nature, and you render justice
- useless, by supplying its place with much nobler virtues, and more
- valuable blessings. The selfishness of men is animated by the few
- possessions we have, in proportion to our wants; and it is to restrain
- this selfishness, that men have been obliged to separate themselves from
- the community, and to distinguish betwixt their own goods and those of
- others.
- Nor need we have recourse to the fictions of poets to learn this; but
- beside the reason of the thing, may discover the same truth by common
- experience and observation. It is easy to remark, that a cordial
- affection renders all things common among friends; and that married
- people in particular mutually lose their property, and are unacquainted
- with the mine and thine, which are so necessary, and yet cause such
- disturbance in human society. The same effect arises from any alteration
- in the circumstances of mankind; as when there is such a plenty of any
- thing as satisfies all the desires of men: In which case the distinction
- of property is entirely lost, and every thing remains in common. This
- we may observe with regard to air and water, though the most valuable of
- all external objects; and may easily conclude, that if men were supplied
- with every thing in the same abundance, or if every one had the same
- affection and tender regard for every one as for himself; justice and
- injustice would be equally unknown among mankind.
- Here then is a proposition, which, I think, may be regarded as certain,
- that it is only from the selfishness and confined generosity of men,
- along with the scanty provision nature has made for his wants, that
- justice derives its origin. If we look backward we shall find, that this
- proposition bestows an additional force on some of those observations,
- which we have already made on this subject.
- First, we may conclude from it, that a regard to public interest, or a
- strong extensive benevolence, is not our first and original motive for
- the observation of the rules of justice; since it is allowed, that if
- men were endowed with such a benevolence, these rules would never have
- been dreamt of.
- Secondly, we may conclude from the same principle, that the sense
- of justice is not founded on reason, or on the discovery of certain
- connexions and relations of ideas, which are eternal, immutable, and
- universally obligatory. For since it is confest, that such an alteration
- as that above-mentioned, in the temper and circumstances of mankind,
- would entirely alter our duties and obligations, it is necessary upon
- the common system, that the sense of virtue is derived from reason, to
- shew the change which this must produce in the relations and ideas. But
- it is evident, that the only cause, why the extensive generosity of man,
- and the perfect abundance of every thing, would destroy the very idea of
- justice, is because they render it useless; and that, on the other hand,
- his confined benevolence, and his necessitous condition, give rise to
- that virtue, only by making it requisite to the publick interest, and to
- that of every individual. Twas therefore a concern for our own, and
- the publick interest, which made us establish the laws of justice; and
- nothing can be more certain, than that it is not any relation of ideas,
- which gives us this concern, but our impressions and sentiments, without
- which every thing in nature is perfectly indifferent to us, and can
- never in the least affect us. The sense of justice, therefore, is not
- founded on our ideas, but on our impressions.
- Thirdly, we may farther confirm the foregoing proposition, THAT THOSE
- IMPRESSIONS, WHICH GIVE RISE TO THIS SENSE OF JUSTICE, ARE NOT NATURAL
- TO THE MIND OF MAN, BUT ARISE FROM ARTIFICE AND HUMAN CONVENTIONS. For
- since any considerable alteration of temper and circumstances destroys
- equally justice and injustice; and since such an alteration has an
- effect only by changing our own and the publick interest; it follows,
- that the first establishment of the rules of justice depends on these
- different interests. But if men pursued the publick interest naturally,
- and with a hearty affection, they would never have dreamed of
- restraining each other by these rules; and if they pursued their own
- interest, without any precaution, they would run head-long into every
- kind of injustice and violence. These rules, therefore, are artificial,
- and seek their end in an oblique and indirect manner; nor is the
- interest, which gives rise to them, of a kind that coued be pursued by
- the natural and inartificial passions of men.
- To make this more evident, consider, that though the rules of justice
- are established merely by interest, their connexion with interest is
- somewhat singular, and is different from what may be observed on other
- occasions. A single act of justice is frequently contrary to public
- interest; and were it to stand alone, without being followed by other
- acts, may, in itself, be very prejudicial to society. When a man of
- merit, of a beneficent disposition, restores a great fortune to a miser,
- or a seditious bigot, he has acted justly and laudably, but the public
- is a real sufferer. Nor is every single act of justice, considered
- apart, more conducive to private interest, than to public; and it is
- easily conceived how a man may impoverish himself by a signal instance
- of integrity, and have reason to wish, that with regard to that single
- act, the laws of justice were for a moment suspended in the universe.
- But however single acts of justice may be contrary, either to public or
- private interest, it is certain, that the whole plan or scheme is
- highly conducive, or indeed absolutely requisite, both to the support
- of society, and the well-being of every individual. It is impossible
- to separate the good from the ill. Property must be stable, and must be
- fixed by general rules. Though in one instance the public be a sufferer,
- this momentary ill is amply compensated by the steady prosecution of the
- rule, and by the peace and order, which it establishes in society. And
- even every individual person must find himself a gainer, on ballancing
- the account; since, without justice society must immediately dissolve,
- and every one must fall into that savage and solitary condition, which
- is infinitely worse than the worst situation that can possibly be
- supposed in society. When therefore men have had experience enough
- to observe, that whatever may be the consequence of any single act of
- justice, performed by a single person, yet the whole system of actions,
- concurred in by the whole society, is infinitely advantageous to the
- whole, and to every part; it is not long before justice and property
- take place. Every member of society is sen sible of this interest: Every
- one expresses this sense to his fellows, along with the resolution he
- has taken of squaring his actions by it, on condition that others will
- do the same. No more is requisite to induce any one of them to perform
- an act of justice, who has the first opportunity. This becomes an
- example to others. And thus justice establishes itself by a kind of
- convention or agreement; that is, by a sense of interest, supposed to
- be common to all, and where every single act is performed in expectation
- that others are to perform the like. Without such a convention, no one
- would ever have dreamed, that there was such a virtue as justice, or
- have been induced to conform his actions to it. Taking any single act,
- my justice may be pernicious in every respect; and it is only upon
- the supposition that others are to imitate my example, that I can be
- induced to embrace that virtue; since nothing but this combination can
- render justice advantageous, or afford me any motives to conform my self
- to its rules.
- We come now to the second question we proposed, viz. Why we annex the
- idea of virtue to justice, and of vice to injustice. This question
- will not detain us long after the principles, which we have already
- established, All we can say of it at present will be dispatched in a few
- words: And for farther satisfaction, the reader must wait till we come
- to the third part of this book. The natural obligation to justice, viz,
- interest, has been fully explained; but as to the moral obligation, or
- the sentiment of right and wrong, it will first be requisite to examine
- the natural virtues, before we can give a full and satisfactory account
- of it. After men have found by experience, that their selfishness and
- confined generosity, acting at their liberty, totally incapacitate
- them for society; and at the same time have observed, that society is
- necessary to the satisfaction of those very passions, they are naturally
- induced to lay themselves under the restraint of such rules, as may
- render their commerce more safe and commodious. To the imposition then,
- and observance of these rules, both in general, and in every particular
- instance, they are at first induced only by a regard to interest; and
- this motive, on the first formation of society, is sufficiently strong
- and forcible. But when society has become numerous, and has encreased to
- a tribe or nation, this interest is more remote; nor do men so readily
- perceive, that disorder and confusion follow upon every breach of these
- rules, as in a more narrow and contracted society. But though in our own
- actions we may frequently lose sight of that interest, which we have in
- maintaining order, and may follow a lesser and more present interest,
- we never fail to observe the prejudice we receive, either mediately or
- immediately, from the injustice of others; as not being in that case
- either blinded by passion, or byassed by any contrary temptation.
- Nay when the injustice is so distant from us, as no way to affect our
- interest, it still displeases us; because we consider it as prejudicial
- to human society, and pernicious to every one that approaches the person
- guilty of it. We partake of their uneasiness by sympathy; and as every
- thing, which gives uneasiness in human actions, upon the general survey,
- is called Vice, and whatever produces satisfaction, in the same manner,
- is denominated Virtue; this is the reason why the sense of moral good
- and evil follows upon justice and injustice. And though this sense,
- in the present case, be derived only from contemplating the actions
- of others, yet we fail not to extend it even to our own actions. The
- general rule reaches beyond those instances, from which it arose; while
- at the same time we naturally sympathize with others in the sentiments
- they entertain of us. Thus self-interest is the original motive to the
- establishment of justice: but a sympathy with public interest is the
- source of the moral approbation, which attends that virtue.
- Though this progress of the sentiments be natural, and even necessary,
- it is certain, that it is here forwarded by the artifice of politicians,
- who, in order to govern men more easily, and preserve peace in human
- society, have endeavoured to produce an esteem for justice, and an
- abhorrence of injustice. This, no doubt, must have its effect; but
- nothing can be more evident, than that the matter has been carryed too
- far by certain writers on morals, who seem to have employed their
- utmost efforts to extirpate all sense of virtue from among mankind.
- Any artifice of politicians may assist nature in the producing of those
- sentiments, which she suggests to us, and may even on some occasions,
- produce alone an approbation or esteem for any particular action; but
- it is impossible it should be the sole cause of the distinction we
- make betwixt vice and virtue. For if nature did not aid us in this
- particular, it would be in vain for politicians to talk of honourable or
- dishonourable, praiseworthy or blameable. These words would be perfectly
- unintelligible, and would no more have any idea annexed to them, than
- if they were of a tongue perfectly unknown to us. The utmost politicians
- can perform, is, to extend the natural sentiments beyond their original
- bounds; but still nature must furnish the materials, and give us some
- notion of moral distinctions.
- As publick praise and blame encrease our esteem for justice; so private
- education and instruction contribute to the same effect. For as parents
- easily observe, that a man is the more useful, both to himself and
- others, the greater degree of probity and honour he is endowed with;
- and that those principles have greater force, when custom and education
- assist interest and reflection: For these reasons they are induced to
- inculcate on their children, from their earliest infancy, the principles
- of probity, and teach them to regard the observance of those rules,
- by which society is maintained, as worthy and honourable, and their
- violation as base and infamous. By this means the sentiments of honour
- may take root in their tender minds, and acquire such firmness and
- solidity, that they may fall little short of those principles, which are
- the most essential to our natures, and the most deeply radicated in our
- internal constitution.
- What farther contributes to encrease their solidity, is the interest
- of our reputation, after the opinion, that a merit or demerit attends
- justice or injustice, is once firmly established among mankind. There is
- nothing, which touches us more nearly than our reputation, and nothing
- on which our reputation more depends than our conduct, with relation to
- the property of others. For this reason, every one, who has any regard
- to his character, or who intends to live on good terms with mankind,
- must fix an inviolable law to himself, never, by any temptation, to be
- induced to violate those principles, which are essential to a man of
- probity and honour.
- I shall make only one observation before I leave this subject, viz, that
- though I assert, that in the state of nature, or that imaginary state,
- which preceded society, there be neither justice nor injustice, yet
- I assert not, that it was allowable, in such a state, to violate the
- property of others. I only maintain, that there was no such thing
- as property; and consequently coued be no such thing as justice or
- injustice. I shall have occasion to make a similar reflection with
- regard to promises, when I come to treat of them; and I hope this
- reflection, when duly weighed, will suffice to remove all odium from the
- foregoing opinions, with regard to justice and injustice.
- SECT. III OF THE RULES WHICH DETERMINE PROPERTY
- Though the establishment of the rule, concerning the stability of
- possession, be not only useful, but even absolutely necessary to human
- society, it can never serve to any purpose, while it remains in such
- general terms. Some method must be shewn, by which we may distinguish
- what particular goods are to be assigned to each particular person,
- while the rest of mankind are excluded from their possession and
- enjoyment. Our next business, then, must be to discover the reasons
- which modify this general rule, and fit it to the common use and
- practice of the world.
- It is obvious, that those reasons are not derived from any utility or
- advantage, which either the particular person or the public may reap
- from his enjoyment of any particular goods, beyond what would result
- from the possession of them by any other person. Twere better, no doubt,
- that every one were possessed of what is most suitable to him, and
- proper for his use: But besides, that this relation of fitness may be
- common to several at once, it is liable to so many controversies, and
- men are so partial and passionate in judging of these controversies,
- that such a loose and uncertain rule would be absolutely incompatible
- with the peace of human society. The convention concerning the stability
- of possession is entered into, in order to cut off all occasions of
- discord and contention; and this end would never be attained, were
- we allowed to apply this rule differently in every particular case,
- according to every particular utility, which might be discovered in such
- an application. Justice, in her decisions, never regards the fitness or
- unfitness of objects to particular persons, but conducts herself by more
- extensive views. Whether a man be generous, or a miser, he is equally
- well received by her, and obtains with the same facility a decision in
- his favours, even for what is entirely useless to him.
- It follows therefore, that the general rule, that possession must be
- stable, is not applied by particular judgments, but by other general
- rules, which must extend to the whole society, and be inflexible
- either by spite or favour. To illustrate this, I propose the following
- instance. I first consider men in their savage and solitary condition;
- and suppose, that being sensible of the misery of that state, and
- foreseeing the advantages that would result from society, they seek each
- other's company, and make an offer of mutual protection and assistance.
- I also suppose, that they are endowed with such sagacity as immediately
- to perceive, that the chief impediment to this project of society and
- partnership lies in the avidity and selfishness of their natural temper;
- to remedy which, they enter into a convention for the stability of
- possession, and for mutual restraint and forbearance. I am sensible,
- that this method of proceeding is not altogether natural; but besides
- that I here only suppose those reflections to be formed at once, which
- in fact arise insensibly and by degrees; besides this, I say, it is very
- possible, that several persons, being by different accidents separated
- from the societies, to which they formerly belonged, may be obliged to
- form a new society among themselves; in which case they are entirely in
- the situation above-mentioned.
- It is evident, then, that their first difficulty, in this situation,
- after the general convention for the establishment of society, and for
- the constancy of possession, is, how to separate their possessions,
- and assign to each his particular portion, which he must for the future
- inalterably enjoy. This difficulty will not detain them long; but it
- must immediately occur to them, as the most natural expedient, that
- every one continue to enjoy what he is at present master of, and
- that property or constant possession be conjoined to the immediate
- possession. Such is the effect of custom, that it not only reconciles
- us to any thing we have long enjoyed, but even gives us an affection for
- it, and makes us prefer it to other objects, which may be more valuable,
- but are less known to us. What has long lain under our eye, and has
- often been employed to our advantage, that we are always the most
- unwilling to part with; but can easily live without possessions,
- which we never have enjoyed, and are not accustomed to. It is evident,
- therefore, that men would easily acquiesce in this expedient, that every
- one continue to enjoy what he is at present possessed of; and this is
- the reason, why they would so naturally agree in preferring it.
- [Footnote 15. No questions in philosophy are more
- difficult, than when a number of causes present themselves
- for the same phaenomenon, to determine which is the
- principal and predominant. There seldom is any very precise
- argument to fix our choice, and men must be contented to be
- guided by a kind of taste or fancy, arising from analogy,
- and a comparison of familiar instances. Thus, in the present
- case, there are, no doubt, motives of public interest for
- most of the rules, which determine property; but still I
- suspect, that these rules are principally fixed by the
- imagination, or the more frivolous properties of our thought
- and conception. I shall continue to explain these causes,
- leaving it to the reader's choice, whether he will prefer
- those derived from publick utility, or those derived from
- the imagination. We shall begin with the right of the
- present possessor.
- It is a quality, which I have already observed in human
- nature, that when two objects appear in a close relation to
- each other, the mind is apt to ascribe to them any
- additional relation, in order to compleat the union; and
- this inclination is so strong, as often to make us run into
- errors (such as that of the conjunction of thought and
- matter) if we find that they can serve to that purpose. Many
- of our impressions are incapable of place or local position;
- and yet those very impressions we suppose to have a local
- conjunction with the impressions of sight and touch, merely
- because they are conjoined by causation, and are already
- united in the imagination. Since, therefore, we can feign a
- new relation, and even an absurd one, in order to compleat
- any union, it will easily be imagined, that if there be any
- relations, which depend on the mind, it will readily conjoin
- them to any preceding relation, and unite, by a new bond,
- such objects as have already an union in the fancy. Thus for
- instance, we never fail, in our arrangement of bodies, to
- place those which are resembling in contiguity to each
- other, or at least in correspondent points of view; because
- we feel a satisfaction in joining the relation of contiguity
- to that of resemblance, or the resemblance of situation to
- that of qualities. And this is easily accounted for from the
- known properties of human nature. When the mind is
- determined to join certain objects, but undetermined in its
- choice of the particular objects, It naturally turns its eye
- to such as are related together. They are already united in
- the mind: They present themselves at the same time to the
- conception; and instead of requiring any new reason for
- their conjunction, it would require a very powerful reason
- to make us over-look this natural affinity. This we shall
- have occasion to explain more fully afterwards, when we come
- to treat of beauty. In the mean time, we may content
- ourselves with observing, that the same love of order and
- uniformity, which arranges the books in a library, and the
- chairs in a parlour, contribute to the formation of society,
- and to the well-being of mankind, by modifying the general
- rule concerning the stability of possession. And as property
- forms a relation betwixt a person and an object, it is
- natural to found it on some preceding relation; and as
- property Is nothing but a constant possession, secured by
- the laws of society, it is natural to add it to the present
- possession, which is a relation that resembles it. For this
- also has its influence. If it be natural to conjoin all
- sorts of relations, it is more so, to conjoin such relations
- as are resembling, and are related together.]
- But we may observe, that though the rule of the assignment of property
- to the present possessor be natural, and by that means useful, yet its
- utility extends not beyond the first formation of society; nor would any
- thing be more pernicious, than the constant observance of it; by which
- restitution would be excluded, and every injustice would be authorized
- and rewarded. We must, therefore, seek for some other circumstance, that
- may give rise to property after society is once established; and of
- this kind, I find four most considerable, viz. Occupation, Prescription,
- Accession, and Succession. We shall briefly examine each of these,
- beginning with Occupation.
- The possession of all external goods is changeable and uncertain; which
- is one of the most considerable impediments to the establishment of
- society, and is the reason why, by universal agreement, express or
- tacite, men restrain themselves by what we now call the rules of justice
- and equity. The misery of the condition, which precedes this restraint,
- is the cause why we submit to that remedy as quickly as possible; and
- this affords us an easy reason, why we annex the idea of property to the
- first possession, or to occupation. Men are unwilling to leave property
- in suspense, even for the shortest time, or open the least door to
- violence and disorder. To which we may add, that the first possession
- always engages the attention most; and did we neglect it, there would be
- no colour of reason for assigning property to any succeeding possession.
- [Footnote 16. Some philosophers account for the right of
- occupation, by saying, that every one has a property in his
- own labour; and when he joins that labour to any thing, it
- gives him the property of the whole: But, 1. There are
- several kinds of occupation, where we cannot be said to join
- our labour to the object we acquire: As when we possess a
- meadow by grazing our cattle upon it. 2. This accounts for
- the matter by means of accession; which is taking a needless
- circuit. 3. We cannot be said to join our labour to any
- thing but in a figurative sense. Properly speaking, we only
- make an alteration on it by our labour. This forms a
- relation betwixt us and the object; and thence arises the
- property, according to the preceding principles.]
- There remains nothing, but to determine exactly, what is meant by
- possession; and this is not so easy as may at first sight be imagined.
- We are said to be in possession of any thing, not only when we
- immediately touch it, but also when we are so situated with respect
- to it, as to have it in our power to use it; and may move, alter,
- or destroy it, according to our present pleasure or advantage. This
- relation, then, is a species of cause and effect; and as property is
- nothing but a stable possession, derived from the rules of justice, or
- the conventions of men, it is to be considered as the same species of
- relation. But here we may observe, that as the power of using any object
- becomes more or less certain, according as the interruptions we may meet
- with are more or less probable; and as this probability may increase
- by insensible degrees; it is in many cases impossible to determine when
- possession begins or ends; nor is there any certain standard, by which
- we can decide such controversies. A wild boar, that falls into our
- snares, is deemed to be in our possession, if it be impossible for him
- to escape. But what do we mean by impossible? How do we separate this
- impossibility from an improbability? And how distinguish that exactly
- from a probability? Mark the precise limits of the one and the other,
- and shew the standard, by which we may decide all disputes that may
- arise, and, as we find by experience, frequently do arise upon this
- subject.
- [Footnote 17. If we seek a solution of these difficulties in
- reason and public interest, we never shall find
- satisfaction; and If we look for it in the imagination, it
- is evident, that the qualities, which operate upon that
- faculty, run so insensibly and gradually into each other,
- that it is impossible to give them any precise bounds or
- termination. The difficulties on this head must encrease,
- when we consider, that our judgment alters very sensibly,
- according to the subject, and that the same power and
- proximity will be deemed possession in one case, which is
- not esteemed such in another. A person, who has hunted a
- hare to the last degree of weariness, would look upon it as
- an injustice for another to rush in before him, and seize
- his prey. But the same person advancing to pluck an apple,
- that hangs within his reach, has no reason to complain, if
- another, more alert, passes him, and takes possession. What
- is the reason of this difference, but that immobility, not
- being natural to the hare, but the effect of industry, forms
- in that case a strong relation with the hunter, which is
- wanting in the other?
- Here then it appears, that a certain and infallible power of
- enjoyment, without touch or some other sensible relation,
- often produces not property: And I farther observe, that a
- sensible relation, without any present power, is sometimes
- sufficient to give a title to any object. The sight of a
- thing is seldom a considerable relation, and is only
- regarded as such, when the object is hidden, or very
- obscure; in which case we find, that the view alone conveys
- a property; according to that maxim, THAT EVEN A WHOLE
- CONTINENT BELONGS TO THE NATION, WHICH FIRST DISCOVERED IT.
- It is however remarkable that both in the case of discovery
- and that of possession, the first discoverer and possessor
- must join to the relation an intention of rendering himself
- proprietor, otherwise the relation will not have Its effect;
- and that because the connexion in our fancy betwixt the
- property and the relation is not so great, but that it
- requires to be helped by such an intention.
- From all these circumstances, it is easy to see how
- perplexed many questions may become concerning the
- acquisition of property by occupation; and the least effort
- of thought may present us with instances, which are not
- susceptible of any reasonable decision. If we prefer
- examples, which are real, to such as are feigned, we may
- consider the following one, which is to be met with In
- almost every writer, that has treated of the laws of nature.
- Two Grecian colonies, leaving their native country, in
- search of new feats, were informed that a city near them was
- deserted by its inhabitants. To know the truth of this
- report, they dispatched at once two messengers, one from
- each colony; who finding on their approach, that their
- information was true, begun a race together with an
- intention to take possession of the city, each of them for
- his countrymen. One of these messengers, finding that he was
- not an equal match for the other, launched his spear at the
- gates of the city, and was so fortunate as to fix it there
- before the arrival of his companion. This produced a dispute
- betwixt the two colonies, which of them was the proprietor
- of the empty city and this dispute still subsists among
- philosophers. For my part I find the dispute impossible to
- be decided, and that because the whole question hangs upon
- the fancy, which in this case is not possessed of any
- precise or determinate standard, upon which it can give
- sentence. To make this evident, let us consider, that if
- these two persons had been simply members of the colonies,
- and not messengers or deputies, their actions would not have
- been of any consequence; since in that case their relation
- to the colonies would have been but feeble and imperfect.
- Add to this, that nothing determined them to run to the
- gates rather than the walls, or any other part of the city,
- but that the gates, being the most obvious and remarkable
- part, satisfy the fancy best in taking them for the whole;
- as we find by the poets, who frequently draw their images
- and metaphors from them. Besides we may consider, that the
- touch or contact of the one messenger is not properly
- possession, no more than the piercing the gates with a
- spear; but only forms a relation; and there is a relation,
- in the other case, equally obvious, tho' not, perhaps, of
- equal force. Which of these relations, then, conveys a right
- and property, or whether any of them be sufficient for that
- effect, I leave to the decision of such as are wiser than
- myself.]
- But such disputes may not only arise concerning the real existence of
- property and possession, but also concerning their extent; and these
- disputes are often susceptible of no decision, or can be decided by no
- other faculty than the imagination. A person who lands on the shore of
- a small island, that is desart and uncultivated, is deemed its possessor
- from the very first moment, and acquires the property of the whole;
- because the object is there bounded and circumscribed in the fancy, and
- at the same time is proportioned to the new possessor. The same person
- landing on a desart island, as large as Great Britain, extends his
- property no farther than his immediate possession; though a numerous
- colony are esteemed the proprietors of the whole from the instant of
- their debarkment.
- But it often happens, that the title of first possession becomes obscure
- through time; and that it is impossible to determine many controversies,
- which may arise concerning it. In that case long possession or
- prescription naturally takes place, and gives a person a sufficient
- property in any thing he enjoys. The nature of human society admits not
- of any great accuracy; nor can we always remount to the first origin of
- things, in order to determine their present condition. Any considerable
- space of time sets objects at such a distance, that they seem, in a
- manner, to lose their reality, and have as little influence on the mind,
- as if they never had been in being. A man's title, that is clear and
- certain at present, will seem obscure and doubtful fifty years hence,
- even though the facts, on which it is founded, should be proved with
- the greatest evidence and certainty. The same facts have not the same
- influence after so long an interval of time. And this may be received as
- a convincing argument for our preceding doctrine with regard to property
- and justice. Possession during a long tract of time conveys a title to
- any object. But as it is certain, that, however every thing be produced
- in time, there is nothing real that is produced by time; it follows,
- that property being produced by time, is not any thing real in the
- objects, but is the off-spring of the sentiments, on which alone time is
- found to have any influence.
- [Footnote 18. Present possession is plainly a relation
- betwixt a person and an object; but is not sufficient to
- counter-ballance the relation of first possession, unless
- the former be long and uninterrupted: In which case the
- relation is encreased on the side of the present possession,
- by the extent of time, and dlminished on that of first
- possession, by the distance, This change in the relation
- produces a consequent change in the property.]
- We acquire the property of objects by accession, when they
- are connected in an intimate manner with objects that are
- already our property, and at the same time are inferior to
- them. Thus the fruits of our garden, the offspring of our
- cattle, and the work of our slaves, are all of them esteemed
- our property, even before possession. Where objects are
- connected together in the imagination, they are apt to be
- put on the same footing, and are commonly supposed to be
- endowed with the same qualities. We readily pass from one to
- the other, and make no difference in our judgments
- concerning them; especially if the latter be inferior to the
- former.
- [Footnote 19. This source of property can never be
- explained but from the imaginations; and one may affirm,
- that the causes are here unmixed. We shall proceed to
- explain them more particularly, and illustrate them by
- examples from common life and experience.
- It has been observed above, that the mind has a natural
- propensity to join relations, especially resembling ones,
- and finds a hind of fitness and uniformity in such an union.
- From this propensity are derived these laws of nature, that
- upon the first formation of society, property always follows
- the present possession; and afterwards, that it arises from
- first or from long possession. Now we may easily observe,
- that relation is not confined merely to one degree; but that
- from an object, that is related to us, we acquire a relation
- to every other object, which is related to it, and so on,
- till the thought loses the chain by too long a progress,
- However the relation may weaken by each remove, it is not
- immediately destroyed; but frequently connects two objects
- by means of an intermediate one, which is related to both.
- And this principle is of such force as to give rise to the
- right of accession, and causes us to acquire the property
- not only of such objects as we are immediately possessed of;
- but also of such as are closely connected with them.
- Suppose a German, a Frenchman, and a Spaniard to come into a
- room, where there are placed upon the table three bottles of
- wine, Rhenish, Burgundy and Port; and suppose they shoued
- fall a quarrelling about the division of them; a person, who
- was chosen for umpire would naturally, to shew his
- impartiality, give every one the product of his own country:
- And this from a principle, which, in some measure, is the
- source of those laws of nature, that ascribe property to
- occupation, prescription and accession.
- In all these Cases, and particularly that of accession,
- there is first a natural union betwixt the Idea of the
- person and that of the object, and afterwards a new and
- moral union produced by that right or property, which we
- ascribe to the person. But here there occurs a difficulty,
- which merits our attention, and may afford us an opportunity
- of putting to tryal that singular method of reasoning, which
- has been employed on the present subject. I have already
- observed that the imagination passes with greater facility
- from little to great, than from great to littie, and that
- the transition of ideas is always easier and smoother in the
- former case than in the latter. Now as the right of
- accession arises from the easy transition of ideas, by which
- related objects are connected together, it shoued naturally
- be imagined, that the right of accession must encrease in
- strength, in proportion as the transition of ideas is
- performed with greater facility. It may, therefore, be
- thought, that when we have acquired the property of any
- small object, we shall readily consider any great object
- related to it as an accession, and as belonging to the
- proprietor of the small one; since the transition is in that
- case very easy from the small object to the great one, and
- shoued connect them together in the closest manner. But In
- fact the case is always found to be otherwise, The empire of
- Great Britain seems to draw along with it the dominion of
- the Orkneys, the Hebrides, the isle of Man, and the Isle of
- Wight; but the authority over those lesser islands does not
- naturally imply any title to Great Britain. In short, a
- small object naturally follows a great one as its accession;
- but a great one Is never supposed to belong to the
- proprietor of a small one related to it, merely on account
- of that property and relation. Yet in this latter case the
- transition of ideas is smoother from the proprietor to the
- small object, which is his property, and from the small
- object to the great one, than in the former case from the
- proprietor to the great object, and from the great one to
- the small. It may therefore be thought, that these
- phaenomena are objections to the foregoing hypothesis, THAT
- THE ASCRIBING OF PROPERTY TO ACCESSION IS NOTHING BUT AN
- AFFECT OF THE RELATIONS OF IDEAS, AND OF THE SMOOTH
- TRANSITION OF THE IMAGINATION.
- It will be easy to solve this objection, if we consider the
- agility and unsteadiness of the imagination, with the
- different views, in which it is continually placing its
- objects. When we attribute to a person a property in two
- objects, we do not always pass from the person to one
- object, and from that to the other related to it. The
- objects being here to be considered as the property of the
- person, we are apt to join them together, and place them in
- the same light. Suppose, therefore, a great and a small
- object to be related together; if a person be strongly
- related to the great object, he will likewise be strongly
- related to both the objects, considered together, because he
- Is related to the most considerable part. On the contrary,
- if he be only related to the small object, he will not be
- strongly related to both, considered together, since his
- relation lies only with the most trivial part, which is not
- apt to strike us in any great degree, when we consider the
- whole. And this Is the reason, why small objects become
- accessions to great ones, and not great to small.
- It is the general opinion of philosophers and civilians,
- that the sea is incapable of becoming the property of any
- nation; and that because it is impossible to take possession
- of it, or form any such distinct relation with it, as may be
- the foundation of property. Where this reason ceases,
- property immediately takes place. Thus the most strenuous
- advocates for the liberty of the seas universally allow,
- that friths and hays naturally belong as an accession to the
- proprietors of the surrounding continent. These have
- properly no more bond or union with the land, than the
- pacific ocean would have; but having an union in the fancy,
- and being at the same time inferior, they are of course
- regarded as an accession.
- The property of rivers, by the laws of most nations, and by
- the natural turn of our thought, Is attributed to the
- proprietors of their banks, excepting such vast rivers as
- the Rhine or the Danube, which seem too large to the
- imagination to follow as an accession the property of the
- neighbouring fields. Yet even these rivers are considered as
- the property of that nation, thro' whose dominions they run;
- the idea of a nation being of a suitable bulk to correspond
- with them, and bear them such a relation in the fancy.
- The accessions, which are made to lands bordering upon
- rivers, follow the land, say the civilians, provided it be
- made by what they call alluvion, that is, Insensibly and
- Imperceptibly; which are circumstances that mightily assist
- the imagination in the conjunction. Where there Is any
- considerable portion torn at once from one bank, and joined
- to another, it becomes not his property, whose land it falls
- on, till it unite with the land, and till the trees or
- plants have spread their roots into both. Before that, the
- imagination does not sufficiently join them.
- There are other cases, which somewhat resemble this of
- accession, but which, at the bottom, are considerably
- different, and merit our attention. Of this kind Is the
- conjunction of the properties of different persons, after
- such a manner as not to admit of separation. The question
- is, to whom the united mass must belong.
- Where this conjunction is of such a nature as to admit of
- division, but not of separation, the decision is natural and
- easy. The whole mass must be supposed to be common betwixt
- the proprietors of the several parts, and afterwards must be
- divided according to the proportions of these parts. But
- here I cannot forbear taking notice of a remarkable subtilty
- of the Roman law, in distinguishing betwixt confusion and
- commixtion. Confusion is an union of two bodies, such as
- different liquors, where the parts become entirely
- undistinguishable. Commixtion is the blending of two bodies,
- such as two bushels of corn, where the parts remain separate
- in an obvious and visible manner. As in the latter case the
- imagination discovers not so entire an union as in the
- former, but is able to trace and preserve a distinct idea of
- the property of each; this is the reason, why the civil law,
- tho' it established an entire community in the case of
- confusion, and after that a proportional division, yet in
- the case of commixtion, supposes each of the proprietors to
- maintain a distinct right; however necessity may at last
- force them to submit to the same division.
- QUOD SI FRUMENTUM TITII FRUMENTO TUO MISTUM FUERIT: SIQUIDEM
- EX VOLUNTATE VESTRA, COMMUNE EST: QUIA SINGULA CORPORA, ID
- EST, SINGULA GRANA, QUAE CUJUSQUE PRO PRIA FUERUNT, EX
- CONSENSU VESTRO COMMUNICATA SUNT. QUOD SI CASU ID MISTUM
- FUERIT, VEL TITIUS ID MISCUERIT SINE TUA VOLUNT ATE, NON
- VIDETUR ID COMMUNE ESSE; QUIA SINGULA CORPORA IN SUA
- SUBSTANTIA DURANT. SED NEC MAGIS ISTIS CASIBUS COMMUNE SIT
- FRUMENTUM QUAM GREX INTELLIGITUR ESSE CORN MUNIS, SI PECORA
- TITII TUIS PECORIBUS MISTA FUERINT. SED SI AB ALTERUTRO
- VESTRUM TOTUM ID FRUMENTUM RETINEATUR, IN REM QUIDEM ACTIO
- PRO MODO FRUMENTI CUJUSQUE CORN PETIT. ARBITRIO AUTEM
- JUDICIS, UT IPSE AESTIMET QUALE CUJUSQUE FRUMENTUM FUERIT.
- Inst. Lib. IL Tit. i. Sect 28.
- (In the case that your grain was mixed with that of Titius,
- if it was done voluntarily on the part of both of you, it is
- common property, inasmuch as the individual items, i.e., the
- single grains, which were the peculiar property of either of
- you, were combined with your joint consent. If, however, the
- mixture was accidental, or if Titius mixed it without your
- consent, it does not appear that it is common property,
- Inasmuch as the several components retain their original
- identity. Rather, in circumstances of this sort the grain
- does not become common property, any more than a herd of
- cattle is regarded as common property, If Titius beasts
- should have become mixed up with yours.
- However, if all of the aforesaid corn is kept by either of
- you, this gives rise to a suit to determine the ownership of
- property, in respect of the amount of corn belonging to
- each. It is in the discretion of the judge to determine
- which is the corn belonging to either party.]
- Where the properties of two persons are united after such a
- manner as neither to admit of division nor separation, as
- when one builds a house on another's ground, in that case,
- the whole must belong to one of the proprietors: And here I
- assert, that it naturally is conceived to belong to the
- proprietor of the most considerable part. For however the
- compound object may have a relation to two different
- persons, and carry our view at once to both of them, yet as
- the most considerable part principally engages our
- attention, and by the strict union draws the inferior along
- it; for this reason, the whole bears a relation to the
- proprietor of that part, and is regarded as his property.
- The only difficulty is, what we shall be pleased to call the
- most considerable part, and most attractive to the
- imagination.
- This quality depends on several different circumstances,
- which have little connexion with each other. One part of a
- compound object may become more considerable than another,
- either because it is more constant and durable; because it
- is of greater value; because it is more obvious and
- remarkable; because it is of greater extent; or because its
- existence is more separate and independent. It will be easy
- to conceive, that, as these circumstances may be conjoined
- and opposed in all the different ways, and according to all
- the different degrees, which can be imagined, there will
- result many cases, where the reasons on both sides are so
- equally balanced, that it is impossible for us to give any
- satisfactory decision. Here then is the proper business of
- municipal laws, to fix what the principles of human nature
- have left undetermined.
- The superficies yields to the soil, says the civil law: The
- writing to the paper: The canvas to the picture. These
- decisions do not well agree together, and are a proof of the
- contrariety of those principles, from which they are
- derived.
- But of all the questions of this kind the most curious is
- that, which for so many ages divided the disciples of
- Proculus and Sabinus. Suppose a person shoued make a cup
- from the metal of another, or a ship from his wood, and
- suppose the proprietor of the metal or wood shoued demand
- his goods, the question is, whether he acquires a title to
- the cup or ship. Sabinus maintained the affirmative, and
- asserted that the substance or matter is the foundation of
- all the qualities; that it is incorruptible and immortal,
- and therefore superior to the form, which is casual and
- dependent. On the other hand, Proculus observed, that the
- form is the most obvious and remarkable part, and that from
- it bodies are denominated of this or that particular
- species. To which he might have added, that the matter or
- substance is in most bodies so fluctuating and uncertain,
- that it is utterly impossible to trace it in all its
- changes. For my part, I know not from what principles such a
- controversy can be certainly determined. I shall therefore
- content my self with observing, that the decision of
- Trebonian seems to me pretty ingenious; that the cup belongs
- to the proprietor of the metal, because it can be brought
- back to its first form: But that the ship belongs to the
- author of its form for a contrary reason. But however
- ingenious this reason may seem, it plainly depends upon the
- fancy, which by the possibility of such a reduction, finds a
- closer connexion and relation betwixt a cup and the
- proprietor of its metal, than betwixt a ship and the
- proprietor of its wood, where the substance is more fixed
- and unalterable.]
- The right of succession is a very natural one, from the presumed
- consent of the parent or near relation, and from the general interest
- of mankind, which requires, that men's possessions should pass to those,
- who are dearest to them, in order to render them more industrious and
- frugal. Perhaps these causes are seconded by the influence of relation,
- or the association of ideas, by which we are naturally directed to
- consider the son after the parent's decease, and ascribe to him a title
- to his father's possessions. Those goods must become the property of
- some body: But of whom is the question. Here it is evident the persons
- children naturally present themselves to the mind; and being already.
- connected to those possessions by means of their deceased parent, we are
- apt to connect them still farther by the relation of property. Of this
- there are many parallel instances.
- [Footnote 20 In examining the different titles to authority
- in government, we shall meet with many reasons to convince
- us, that the right of succession depends, in a great measure
- on the imagination. Mean while I shall rest contented with
- observing one example, which belongs to the present subject.
- Suppose that a person die without children, and that a
- dispute arises among his relations concerning his
- inheritance; it is evident, that if his riches be deriv'd
- partly from his father, partly from his mother, the most
- natural way of determining such a dispute, is, to divide his
- possessions, and assign each part to the family, from whence
- it is deriv'd. Now as the person is suppos'd to have been
- once the full and entire proprietor of those goods; I ask,
- what is it makes us find a certain equity and natural reason
- in this partition, except it be the imagination? His
- affection to these families does not depend upon his
- possessions; for which reason his consent can never be
- presum'd precisely for such a partition. And as to the
- public interest, it seems not to be in the least concern'd
- on the one side or the other.]
- SECT. IV OF THE TRANSFERENCE OF PROPERTY BY CONSENT
- However useful, or even necessary, the stability of possession may be to
- human society, it is attended with very considerable inconveniences.
- The relation of fitness or suitableness ought never to enter into
- consideration, in distributing the properties of mankind; but we must
- govern ourselves by rules, which are more general in their application,
- and more free from doubt and uncertainty. Of this kind is present
- possession upon the first establishment of society; and afterwards
- occupation, prescription, accession, and succession. As these depend
- very much on chance, they must frequently prove contradictory both to
- men's wants and desires; and persons and possessions must often be very
- ill adjusted. This is a grand inconvenience, which calls for a remedy.
- To apply one directly, and allow every man to seize by violence what he
- judges to be fit for him, would destroy society; and therefore the
- rules of justice seek some medium betwixt a rigid stability, and this
- changeable and uncertain adjustment. But there is no medium better than
- that obvious one, that possession and property should always be stable,
- except when the proprietor consents to bestow them on some other
- person. This rule can have no ill consequence, in occasioning wars and
- dissentions; since the proprietor's consent, who alone is concerned, is
- taken along in the alienation: And it may serve to many good purposes
- in adjusting property to persons. Different parts of the earth produce
- different commodities; and not only so, but different men both are
- by nature fitted for different employments, and attain to greater
- perfection in any one, when they confine themselves to it alone. All
- this requires a mutual exchange and commerce; for which reason the
- translation of property by consent is founded on a law of nature, as
- well as its stability without such a consent.
- So far is determined by a plain utility and interest. But perhaps it is
- from more trivial reasons, that delivery, or a sensible transference of
- the object is commonly required by civil laws, and also by the laws of
- nature, according to most authors, as a requisite circumstance in the
- translation of property. The property of an object, when taken for
- something real, without any reference to morality, or the sentiments of
- the mind, is a quality perfectly insensible, and even inconceivable; nor
- can we form any distinct notion, either of its stability or translation.
- This imperfection of our ideas is less sensibly felt with regard to its
- stability, as it engages less our attention, and is easily past over by
- the mind, without any scrupulous examination. But as the translation
- of property from one person to another is a more remarkable event, the
- defect of our ideas becomes more sensible on that occasion, and obliges
- us to turn ourselves on every side in search of some remedy. Now as
- nothing more enlivens any idea than a present impression, and a relation
- betwixt that impression and the idea; it is natural for us to seek
- some false light from this quarter. In order to aid the imagination in
- conceiving the transference of property, we take the sensible object,
- and actually transfer its possession to the person, on whom we would
- bestow the property. The supposed resemblance of the actions, and the
- presence of this sensible delivery, deceive the mind, and make it fancy,
- that it conceives the mysterious transition of the property. And that
- this explication of the matter is just, appears hence, that men have
- invented a symbolical delivery, to satisfy the fancy, where the real one
- is impracticable. Thus the giving the keys of a granary is understood
- to be the delivery of the corn contained in it: The giving of stone
- and earth represents the delivery of a mannor. This is a kind of
- superstitious practice in civil laws, and in the laws of nature,
- resembling the Roman catholic superstitions in religion. As the Roman
- catholics represent the inconceivable mysteries of the Christian
- religion, and render them more present to the mind, by a taper, or
- habit, or grimace, which is supposed to resemble them; so lawyers and
- moralists have run into like inventions for the same reason, and
- have endeavoured by those means to satisfy themselves concerning the
- transference of property by consent.
- SECT. V OF THE OBLIGATION OF PROMISES
- That the rule of morality, which enjoins the performance of promises, is
- not natural, will sufficiently appear from these two propositions,
- which I proceed to prove, viz, that a promise would not be intelligible,
- before human conventions had established it; and that even if it were
- intelligible, it would not be attended with any moral obligation.
- I say, first, that a promise is not intelligible naturally, nor
- antecedent to human conventions; and that a man, unacquainted with
- society, could never enter into any engagements with another, even
- though they could perceive each other's thoughts by intuition. If
- promises be natural and intelligible, there must be some act of the mind
- attending these words, I promise; and on this act of the mind must the
- obligation depend. Let us, therefore, run over all the faculties of the
- soul, and see which of them is exerted in our promises.
- The act of the mind, exprest by a promise, is not a resolution to
- perform any thing: For that alone never imposes any obligation. Nor is
- it a desire of such a performance: For we may bind ourselves without
- such a desire, or even with an aversion, declared and avowed. Neither
- is it the willing of that action, which we promise to perform: For a
- promise always regards some future time, and the will has an influence
- only on present actions. It follows, therefore, that since the act of
- the mind, which enters into a promise, and produces its obligation, is
- neither the resolving, desiring, nor willing any particular performance,
- it must necessarily be the willing of that obligation, which arises
- from the promise. Nor is this only a conclusion of philosophy; but is
- entirely conformable to our common ways of thinking and of expressing
- ourselves, when we say that we are bound by our own consent, and that
- the obligation arises from our mere will and pleasure. The only question
- then is, whether there be not a manifest absurdity in supposing this
- act of the mind, and such an absurdity as no man coued fall into,
- whose ideas are not confounded with prejudice and the fallacious use of
- language.
- All morality depends upon our sentiments; and when any action, or
- quality of the mind, pleases us after a certain manner, we say it is
- virtuous; and when the neglect, or nonperformance of it, displeases us
- after a like manner, we say that we lie under an obligation to perform
- it. A change of the obligation supposes a change of the sentiment; and
- a creation of a new obligation supposes some new sentiment to arise. But
- it is certain we can naturally no more change our own sentiments, than
- the motions of the heavens; nor by a single act of our will, that is,
- by a promise, render any action agreeable or disagreeable, moral
- or immoral; which, without that act, would have produced contrary
- impressions, or have been endowed with different qualities. It would
- be absurd, therefore, to will any new obligation, that is, any new
- sentiment of pain or pleasure; nor is it possible, that men coued
- naturally fall into so gross an absurdity. A promise, therefore, is
- naturally something altogether unintelligible, nor is there any act of
- the mind belonging to it.
- [Footnote 21 Were morality discoverable by reason, and not
- by sentiment, it would be still more evident, that promises
- cou'd make no alteration upon it. Morality is suppos'd to
- consist in relation. Every new imposition of morality,
- therefore, must arise from some new relation of objects; and
- consequently the will coud not produce immediately any
- change in morals, but cou'd have that effect only by
- producing a change upon the objects. But as the moral
- obligation of a promise is the pure effect of the will,
- without the least change in any part of the universe; it
- follows, that promises have no natural obligation.
- Shou'd it be said, that this act of the will being in effect
- a new object, produces new relations and new duties; I wou'd
- answer, that this is a pure sophism, which may be detected
- by a very moderate share of accuracy and exactness. To will
- a new obligation, is to will a new relation of objects; and
- therefore, if this new relation of objects were form'd by
- the volition itself, we should in effect will the volition;
- which is plainly absurd and impossible. The will has here no
- object to which it cou'd tend; but must return upon itself
- in infinitum. The new obligation depends upon new relations.
- The new relations depend upon a new volition. The new
- volition has for object a new obligation, and consequently
- new relations, and consequently a new volition; which
- volition again has in view a new obligation, relation and
- volition, without any termination. It is impossible,
- therefore, we cou'd ever will a new obligation; and
- consequently it is impossible the will cou'd ever accompany
- a promise, or produce a new obligation of morality.]
- But, secondly, if there was any act of the mind belonging to it, it
- could not naturally produce any obligation. This appears evidently
- from the foregoing reasoning. A promise creates a new obligation. A new
- obligation supposes new sentiments to arise. The will never creates new
- sentiments. There could not naturally, therefore, arise any obligation
- from a promise, even supposing the mind could fall into the absurdity of
- willing that obligation.
- The same truth may be proved still more evidently by that reasoning,
- which proved justice in general to be an artificial virtue. No action
- can be required of us as our duty, unless there be implanted in human
- nature some actuating passion or motive, capable of producing the
- action. This motive cannot be the sense of duty. A sense of duty
- supposes an antecedent obligation: And where an action is not required
- by any natural passion, it cannot be required by any natural obligation;
- since it may be omitted without proving any defect or imperfection
- in the mind and temper, and consequently without any vice. Now it is
- evident we have no motive leading us to the performance of promises,
- distinct from a sense of duty. If we thought, that promises had no moral
- obligation, we never should feel any inclination to observe them. This
- is not the case with the natural virtues. Though there was no obligation
- to relieve the miserable, our humanity would lead us to it; and when we
- omit that duty, the immorality of the omission arises from its being a
- proof, that we want the natural sentiments of humanity. A father knows
- it to be his duty to take care of his children: But he has also a
- natural inclination to it. And if no human creature had that indination,
- no one coued lie under any such obligation. But as there is naturally
- no inclination to observe promises, distinct from a sense of their
- obligation; it follows, that fidelity is no natural virtue, and that
- promises have no force, antecedent to human conventions.
- If any one dissent from this, he must give a regular proof of these two
- propositions, viz. THAT THERE IS A PECULIAR ACT OF THE MIND, ANNEXT TO
- PROMISES; AND THAT CONSEQUENT TO THIS ACT OF THE MIND, THERE ARISES AN
- INCLINATION TO PERFORM, DISTINCT FROM A SENSE OF DUTY. I presume, that
- it is impossible to prove either of these two points; and therefore I
- venture to conclude that promises are human inventions, founded on the
- necessities and interests of society.
- In order to discover these necessities and interests, we must consider
- the same qualities of human nature, which we have already found to give
- rise to the preceding laws of society. Men being naturally selfish, or
- endowed only with a confined generosity, they are not easily induced to
- perform any action for the interest of strangers, except with a view to
- some reciprocal advantage, which they had no hope of obtaining but by
- such a performance. Now as it frequently happens, that these mutual
- performances cannot be finished at the same instant, it is necessary,
- that one party be contented to remain in uncertainty, and depend
- upon the gratitude of the other for a return of kindness. But so much
- corruption is there among men, that, generally speaking, this becomes
- but a slender security; and as the benefactor is here supposed to bestow
- his favours with a view to self-interest, this both takes off from the
- obligation, and sets an example to selfishness, which is the true mother
- of ingratitude. Were we, therefore, to follow the natural course of our
- passions and inclinations, we should perform but few actions for the
- advantage of others, from distinterested views; because we are naturally
- very limited in our kindness and affection: And we should perform as few
- of that kind, out of a regard to interest; because we cannot depend upon
- their gratitude. Here then is the mutual commerce of good offices in a
- manner lost among mankind, and every one reduced to his own skill and
- industry for his well-being and subsistence. The invention of the law of
- nature, concerning the stability of possession, has already rendered
- men tolerable to each other; that of the transference of property and
- possession by consent has begun to render them mutually advantageous:
- But still these laws of nature, however strictly observed, are not
- sufficient to render them so serviceable to each other, as by nature
- they are fitted to become. Though possession be stable, men may often
- reap but small advantage from it, while they are possessed of a greater
- quantity of any species of goods than they have occasion for, and at the
- same time suffer by the want of others. The transference of property,
- which is the proper remedy for this inconvenience, cannot remedy it
- entirely; because it can only take place with regard to such objects as
- are present and individual, but not to such as are absent or general.
- One cannot transfer the property of a particular house, twenty leagues
- distant; because the consent cannot be attended with delivery, which is
- a requisite circumstance. Neither can one transfer the property of ten
- bushels of corn, or five hogsheads of wine, by the mere expression
- and consent; because these are only general terms, and have no direct
- relation to any particular heap of corn, or barrels of wine. Besides,
- the commerce of mankind is not confined to the barter of commodities,
- but may extend to services and actions, which we may exchange to our
- mutual interest and advantage. Your corn is ripe to-day; mine will be
- so tomorrow. It is profitable for us both, that I should labour with
- you to-day, and that you should aid me to-morrow. I have no kindness for
- you, and know you have as little for me. I will not, therefore, take
- any pains upon your account; and should I labour with you upon my own
- account, in expectation of a return, I know I should be disappointed,
- and that I should in vain depend upon your gratitude. Here then I
- leave you to labour alone: You treat me in the same manner. The seasons
- change; and both of us lose our harvests for want of mutual confidence
- and security.
- All this is the effect of the natural and inherent principles and
- passions of human nature; and as these passions and principles are
- inalterable, it may be thought, that our conduct, which depends on them,
- must be so too, and that it would be in vain, either for moralists or
- politicians, to tamper with us, or attempt to change the usual course of
- our actions, with a view to public interest. And indeed, did the success
- of their designs depend upon their success in correcting the selfishness
- and ingratitude of men, they would never make any progress, unless aided
- by omnipotence, which is alone able to new-mould the human mind, and
- change its character in such fundamental articles. All they can pretend
- to, is, to give a new direction to those natural passions, and teach us
- that we can better satisfy our appetites in an oblique and artificial
- manner, than by their headlong and impetuous motion. Hence I learn to do
- a service to another, without bearing him any real kindness; because I
- forsee, that he will return my service, in expectation of another of
- the same kind, and in order to maintain the same correspondence of good
- offices with me or with others. And accordingly, after I have served
- him, and he is in possession of the advantage arising from my action,
- he is induced to perform his part, as foreseeing the consequences of his
- refusal.
- But though this self-interested commerce of man begins to take place,
- and to predominate in society, it does not entirely abolish the more
- generous and noble intercourse of friendship and good offices. I may
- still do services to such persons as I love, and am more particularly
- acquainted with, without any prospect of advantage; and they may make me
- a return in the same manner, without any view but that of recompensing
- my past services. In order, therefore, to distinguish those two
- different sorts of commerce, the interested and the disinterested, there
- is a certain form of words invented for the former, by which we
- bind ourselves to the performance of any action. This form of words
- constitutes what we call a promise, which is the sanction of the
- interested commerce of mankind. When a man says he promises any thing,
- he in effect expresses a resolution of performing it; and along with
- that, by making use of this form of words, subjects himself to the
- penalty of never being trusted again in case of failure. A resolution is
- the natural act of the mind, which promises express: But were there
- no more than a resolution in the case, promises would only declare our
- former motives, and would not create any new motive or obligation. They
- are the conventions of men, which create a new motive, when experience
- has taught us, that human affairs would be conducted much more for
- mutual advantage, were there certain symbols or signs instituted,
- by which we might give each, other security of our conduct in any
- particular incident, After these signs are instituted, whoever uses them
- is immediately bound by his interest to execute his engagements, and
- must never expect to be trusted any more, if he refuse to perform what
- he promised.
- Nor is that knowledge, which is requisite to make mankind sensible
- of this interest in the institution and observance of promises, to be
- esteemed superior to the capacity of human nature, however savage and
- uncultivated. There needs but a very little practice of the world, to
- make us perceive all these consequences and advantages. The shortest
- experience of society discovers them to every mortal; and when each
- individual perceives the same sense of interest in all his fellows, he
- immediately performs his part of any contract, as being assured, that
- they will not be wanting in theirs. All of them, by concert, enter into
- a scheme of actions, calculated for common benefit, and agree to be true
- to their word; nor is there any thing requisite to form this concert or
- convention, but that every one have a sense of interest in the faithful
- fulfilling of engagements, and express that sense to other members of
- the society. This immediately causes that interest to operate upon them;
- and interest is the first obligation to the performance of promises.
- Afterwards a sentiment of morals concurs with interest, and becomes
- a new obligation upon mankind. This sentiment of morality, in the
- performance of promises, arises from the same principles as that in the
- abstinence from the property of others. Public interest, education, and
- the artifices of politicians, have the same effect in both cases. The
- difficulties, that occur to us, in supposing a moral obligation
- to attend promises, we either surmount or elude. For instance; the
- expression of a resolution is not commonly supposed to be obligatory;
- and we cannot readily conceive how the making use of a certain form of
- words should be able to cause any material difference. Here, therefore,
- we feign a new act of the mind, which we call the willing an obligation;
- and on this we suppose the morality to depend. But we have proved
- already, that there is no such act of the mind, and consequently that
- promises impose no natural obligation.
- To confirm this, we may subjoin some other reflections concerning
- that will, which is supposed to enter into a promise, and to cause its
- obligation. It is evident, that the will alone is never supposed to
- cause the obligation, but must be expressed by words or signs, in order
- to impose a tye upon any man. The expression being once brought in as
- subservient to the will, soon becomes the principal part of the promise;
- nor will a man be less bound by his word, though he secretly give a
- different direction to his intention, and with-hold himself both from
- a resolution, and from willing an obligation. But though the expression
- makes on most occasions the whole of the promise, yet it does not always
- so; and one, who should make use of any expression, of which he knows
- not the meaning, and which he uses without any intention of binding
- himself, would not certainly be bound by it. Nay, though he knows its
- meaning, yet if he uses it in jest only, and with such signs as shew
- evidently he has no serious intention of binding himself, he would not
- lie under any obligation of performance; but it is necessary, that the
- words be a perfect expression of the will, without any contrary signs.
- Nay, even this we must not carry so far as to imagine, that one, whom,
- by our quickness of understanding, we conjecture, from certain signs,
- to have an intention of deceiving us, is not bound by his expression or
- verbal promise, if we accept of it; but must limit this conclusion
- to those cases, where the signs are of a different kind from those
- of deceit. All these contradictions are easily accounted for, if the
- obligation of promises be merely a human invention for the convenience
- of society; but will never be explained, if it be something real and
- natural, arising from any action of the mind or body.
- I shall farther observe, that since every new promise imposes a new
- obligation of morality on the person who promises, and since this new
- obligation arises from his will; it is one of the most mysterious and
- incomprehensible operations that can possibly be imagined, and may even
- be compared to TRANSUBSTANTIATION, or HOLY ORDERS [I mean so far, as
- holy orders are suppos'd to produce the indelible character. In other
- respects they are only a legal qualification.], where a certain form of
- words, along with a certain intention, changes entirely the nature of an
- external object, and even of a human nature. But though these mysteries
- be so far alike, it is very remarkable, that they differ widely in other
- particulars, and that this difference may be regarded as a strong proof
- of the difference of their origins. As the obligation of promises is
- an invention for the interest of society, it is warped into as many
- different forms as that interest requires, and even runs into direct
- contradictions, rather than lose sight of its object. But as those other
- monstrous doctines are mere priestly inventions, and have no public
- interest in view, they are less disturbed in their progress by new
- obstacles; and it must be owned, that, after the first absurdity, they
- follow more directly the current of reason and good sense. Theologians
- clearly perceived, that the external form of words, being mere sound,
- require an intention to make them have any efficacy; and that this
- intention being once considered as a requisite circumstance, its absence
- must equally prevent the effect, whether avowed or concealed, whether
- sincere or deceitful. Accordingly they have commonly determined, that
- the intention of the priest makes the sacrament, and that when he
- secretly withdraws his intention, he is highly criminal in himself; but
- still destroys the baptism, or communion, or holy orders. The terrible
- consequences of this doctrine were not able to hinder its taking place;
- as the inconvenience of a similar doctrine, with regard to promises,
- have prevented that doctrine from establishing itself. Men are always
- more concerned about the present life than the future; and are apt to
- think the smallest evil, which regards the former, more important than
- the greatest, which regards the latter.
- We may draw the same conclusion, concerning the origin of promises, from
- the force, which is supposed to invalidate all contracts, and to free us
- from their obligation. Such a principle is a proof, that promises have
- no natural obligation, and are mere artificial contrivances for the
- convenience and advantage of society. If we consider aright of the
- matter, force is not essentially different from any other motive of hope
- or fear, which may induce us to engage our word, and lay ourselves under
- any obligation. A man, dangerously wounded, who promises a competent
- sum to a surgeon to cure him, would certainly be bound to performance;
- though the case be not so much different from that of one, who promises
- a sum to a robber, as to produce so great a difference in our sentiments
- of morality, if these sentiments were not built entirely on public
- interest and convenience.
- SECT. VI SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE
- We have now run over the three fundamental laws of nature, that of the
- stability of possession, of its transference by consent, and of the
- performance of promises. It is on the strict t observance of those three
- laws, that the peace and security of human society entirely depend; nor
- is there any possibility of establishing a good correspondence among
- men, where these are neglected. Society is absolutely necessary for the
- well-being of men; and these are as necessary to the support of society.
- Whatever restraint they may impose on the passions of men, they are the
- real offspring of those passions, and are only a more artful and more
- refined way of satisfying them. Nothing is more vigilant and inventive
- than our passions; and nothing is more obvious, than the convention
- for the observance of these rules. Nature has, therefore, trusted this
- affair entirely to the conduct of men, and has not placed in the mind
- any peculiar original principles, to determine us to a set of actions,
- into which the other principles of our frame and constitution were
- sufficient to lead us. And to convince us the more fully of this truth,
- we may here stop a moment, and from a review of the preceding reasonings
- may draw some new arguments, to prove that those laws, however
- necessary, are entirely artificial, and of human invention; and
- consequently that justice is an artificial, and not a natural virtue.
- (1) The first argument I shall make use of is derived from the vulgar
- definition of justice. Justice is commonly defined to be a constant and
- perpetual will of giving every one his due. In this definition it is
- supposed, that there are such things as right and property, independent
- of justice, and antecedent to it; and that they would have subsisted,
- though men had never dreamt of practising such a virtue. I have already
- observed, in a cursory manner, the fallacy of this opinion, and shall
- here continue to open up a little more distinctly my sentiments on that
- subject.
- I shall begin with observing, that this quality, which we shall call
- property, is like many of the imaginary qualities of the peripatetic
- philosophy, and vanishes upon a more accurate inspection into the
- subject, when considered a-part from our moral sentiments. It is evident
- property does not consist in any of the sensible qualities of the
- object. For these may continue invariably the same, while the property
- changes. Property, therefore, must consist in some relation of the
- object. But it is not in its relation with regard to other external
- and inanimate objects. For these may also continue invariably the same,
- while the property changes. This quality, therefore, consists in the
- relations of objects to intelligent and rational beings. But it is
- not the external and corporeal relation, which forms the essence of
- property. For that relation may be the same betwixt inanimate objects,
- or with regard to brute creatures; though in those cases it forms no
- property. It is, therefore, in some internal relation, that the property
- consists; that is, in some influence, which the external relations of
- the object have on the mind and actions. Thus the external relation,
- which we call occupation or first possession, is not of itself imagined
- to be the property of the object, but only to cause its property. Now it
- is evident, this external relation causes nothing in external objects,
- and has only an influence on the mind, by giving us a sense of duty in
- abstaining from that object, and in restoring it to the first possessor.
- These actions are properly what we call justice; and consequently it is
- on that virtue that the nature of property depends, and not the virtue
- on the property.
- If any one, therefore, would assert, that justice is a natural virtue,
- and injustice a natural vice, he must assert, that abstracting from the
- nations of property, and right and obligation, a certain conduct
- and train of actions, in certain external relations of objects, has
- naturally a moral beauty or deformity, and causes an original pleasure
- or uneasiness. Thus the restoring a man's goods to him is considered as
- virtuous, not because nature has annexed a certain sentiment of pleasure
- to such a conduct, with regard to the property of others, but because
- she has annexed that sentiment to such a conduct, with regard to those
- external objects, of which others have had the first or long possession,
- or which they have received by the consent of those, who have had first
- or long possession. If nature has given us no such sentiment, there is
- not, naturally, nor antecedent to human conventions, any such thing as
- property. Now, though it seems sufficiently evident, in this dry and
- accurate consideration of the present subject, that nature has annexed
- no pleasure or sentiment of approbation to such a conduct; yet that I
- may leave as little room for doubt as possible, I shall subjoin a few
- more arguments to confirm my opinion.
- First, If nature had given us a pleasure of this kind, it would have
- been as evident and discernible as on every other occasion; nor should
- we have found any difficulty to perceive, that the consideration of such
- actions, in such a situation, gives a certain pleasure and sentiment of
- approbation. We should not have been obliged to have recourse to notions
- of property in the definition of justice, and at the same time make use
- of the notions of justice in the definition of property. This deceitful
- method of reasoning is a plain proof, that there are contained in the
- subject some obscurities and difficulties, which we are not able to
- surmount, and which we desire to evade by this artifice.
- Secondly, Those rules, by which properties, rights, and obligations
- are determined, have in them no marks of a natural origin but many of
- artifice and contrivance. They are too numerous to have proceeded from
- nature: They are changeable by human laws: And have all of them a direct
- and evident tendency to public good, and the support, of civil society.
- This last circumstance is remarkable upon two accounts. First, because,
- though the cause of the establishment of these laws had been a regard
- for the public good, as much as the public good is their natural
- tendency, they would still have been artificial, as being purposely
- contrived and directed to a certain end. Secondly, because, if men had
- been endowed with such a strong regard for public good, they would never
- have restrained themselves by these rules; so that the laws of justice
- arise from natural principles in a manner still more oblique and
- artificial. It is self-love which is their real origin; and as the
- self-love of one person is naturally contrary to that of another, these
- several interested passions are obliged to adjust themselves after such
- a manner as to concur in some system of conduct and behaviour. This
- system, therefore, comprehending the interest of each individual, is of
- course advantageous to the public; though it be not intended for that
- purpose by die inventors.
- (2) In the second place we may observe, that all kinds of vice and
- virtue run insensibly into each other, and may approach by such
- imperceptible degrees as will make it very difficult, if not absolutely
- impossible, to determine when the one ends, and the other begins; and
- from this observation we may derive a new argument for the foregoing
- principle. For whatever may be the case, with regard to all kinds
- of vice and virtue, it is certain, that rights, and obligations, and
- property, admit of no such insensible gradation, but that a man either
- has a full and perfect property, or none at all; and is either entirely
- obliged to perform any action, or lies under no manner of obligation.
- However civil laws may talk of a perfect dominion, and of an imperfect,
- it is easy to observe, that this arises from a fiction, which has no
- foundation in reason, and can never enter into our notions of natural
- justice and equity. A man that hires a horse, though but for a day, has
- as full a right to make use of it for that time, as he whom we call its
- proprietor has to make use of it any other day; and it was evident, that
- however the use may be bounded in time or degree, the right itself is
- not susceptible of any such gradation, but is absolute and entire, so
- far as it extends. Accordingly we may observe, that this right both
- arises and perishes in an instant; and that a man entirely acquires the
- property of any object by occupation, or the consent of the proprietor;
- and loses it by his own consent; without any of that insensible
- gradation, which is remarkable in other qualities and relations, Since,
- therefore, this is die case with regard to property, and rights, and
- obligations, I ask, how it stands with regard to justice and
- injustice? After whatever manner you answer this question, you run into
- inextricable difficulties. If you reply, that justice and injustice
- admit of degree, and run insensibly into each other, you expressly
- contradict the foregoing position, that obligation and property are not
- susceptible of such a gradation. These depend entirely upon justice and
- injustice, and follow them in all their variations. Where the justice is
- entire, the property is also entire: Where the justice is imperfect, the
- property must also be imperfect And vice versa, if the property admit of
- no such variations, they must also be incompatible with justice. If you
- assent, therefore, to this last proposition, and assert, that justice
- and injustice are not susceptible of degrees, you in effect assert,
- that they are not naturally either vicious or virtuous; since vice
- and virtue, moral good and evil, and indeed all natural qualities,
- run insensibly into each other, and are, on many occasions,
- undistinguishable.
- And here it may be worth while to observe, that though abstract
- reasoning, and the general maxims of philosophy and law establish this
- position, that property, and right, and obligation admit not of
- degrees, yet in our common and negligent way of thinking, we find great
- difficulty to entertain that opinion, and do even secretly embrace the
- contrary principle. An object must either be in the possession of
- one person or another. An action must either be performed or not The
- necessity there is of choosing one side in these dilemmas, and the
- impossibility there often is of finding any just medium, oblige us,
- when we reflect on the matter, to acknowledge, that all property and
- obligations are entire. But on the other hand, when we consider the
- origin of property and obligation, and find that they depend on public
- utility, and sometimes on the propensities of the imagination, which are
- seldom entire on any side; we are naturally inclined to imagine, that
- these moral relations admit of an insensible gradation. Hence it is,
- that in references, where the consent of the parties leave the referees
- entire masters of the subject, they commonly discover so much equity and
- justice on both sides, as induces them to strike a medium, and divide
- the difference betwixt the parties. Civil judges, who have not this
- liberty, but are obliged to give a decisive sentence on some one side,
- are often at a loss how to determine, and are necessitated to proceed
- on the most frivolous reasons in the world. Half rights and obligations,
- which seem so natural in common life, are perfect absurdities in their
- tribunal; for which reason they are often obliged to take half arguments
- for whole ones, in order to terminate the affair one way or other.
- (3) The third argument of this kind I shall make use of may be explained
- thus. If we consider the ordinary course of human actions, we shall
- find, that the mind restrains not itself by any general and universal
- rules; but acts on most occasions as it is determined by its present
- motives and inclination. As each action is a particular individual
- event, it must proceed from particular principles, and from our
- immediate situation within ourselves, and with respect to the rest of
- the universe. If on some occasions we extend our motives beyond those
- very circumstances, which gave rise to them, and form something like
- general rules for our conduct, it is easy to observe, that these rules
- are not perfectly inflexible, but allow of many exceptions. Since,
- therefore, this is the ordinary course of human actions, we may
- conclude, that the laws of justice, being universal and perfectly
- inflexible, can never be derived from nature, nor be the immediate
- offspring of any natural motive or inclination. No action can be either
- morally good or evil, unless there be some natural passion or motive
- to impel us to it, or deter us from it; and it is evident, that die
- morality must be susceptible of all the same variations, which are
- natural to the passion. Here are two persons, who dispute for an estate;
- of whom one is rich, a fool, and a batchelor; the other poor, a man of
- sense, and has a numerous family: The first is my enemy; the second
- my friend. Whether I be actuated in this affair by a view to public or
- private interest, by friendship or enmity, I must be induced to do my
- utmost to procure the estate to the latter. Nor would any consideration
- of the right and property of the persons be able to restrain me, were I
- actuated only by natural motives, without any combination or convention
- with others. For as all property depends on morality; and as all
- morality depends on the ordinary course of our passions and actions; and
- as these again are only directed by particular motives; it is evident,
- such a partial conduct must be suitable to the strictest morality, and
- coued never be a violation of property. Were men, therefore, to take
- the liberty of acting with regard to the laws of society, as they do in
- every other affair, they would conduct themselves, on most occasions, by
- particular judgments, and would take into consideration the characters
- and circumstances of the persons, as well as the general nature of the
- question. But it is easy to observe, that this would produce an infinite
- confusion in human society, and that the avidity and partiality of men
- would quickly bring disorder into the world, if not restrained by some
- general and inflexible principles. Twas, therefore, with a view to this
- inconvenience, that men have established those principles, and have
- agreed to restrain themselves by general rules, which are unchangeable
- by spite and favour, and by particular views of private or public
- interest. These rules, then, are artificially invented for a certain
- purpose, and are contrary to the common principles of human nature,
- which accommodate themselves to circumstances, and have no stated
- invariable method of operation.
- Nor do I perceive how I can easily be mistaken in this matter. I see
- evidently, that when any man imposes on himself general inflexible
- rules in his conduct with others, he considers certain objects as
- their property, which he supposes to be sacred and inviolable. But
- no proposition can be more evident, than that property is perfectly
- unintelligible without first supposing justice and injustice; and that
- these virtues and vices are as unintelligible, unless we have motives,
- independent of the morality, to impel us to just actions, and deter us
- from unjust ones. Let those motives, therefore, be what they will, they
- must accommodate themselves to circumstances, and must admit of all the
- variations, which human affairs, in their incessant revolutions, are
- susceptible of. They are consequently a very improper foundation for
- such rigid inflexible rules as the laws of nature; and it is evident
- these laws can only be derived from human conventions, when men have
- perceived the disorders that result from following their natural and
- variable principles.
- Upon the whole, then, we are to consider this distinction betwixt
- justice and injustice, as having two different foundations, viz, that
- of interest, when men observe, that it is impossible to live in society
- without restraining themselves by certain rules; and that of morality,
- when this interest is once observed and men receive a pleasure from the
- view of such actions as tend to the peace of society, and an uneasiness
- from such as are contrary to it. It is the voluntary convention
- and artifice of men, which makes the first interest take place;
- and therefore those laws of justice are so far to be considered as
- artifrial. After that interest is once established and acknowledged, the
- sense of morality in the observance of these rules follows naturally,
- and of itself; though it is certain, that it is also augmented by a
- new artifice, and that the public instructions of politicians, and the
- private education of parents, contribute to the giving us a sense of
- honour and duty in the strict regulation of our actions with regard to
- the properties of others.
- SECT. VII OF THE ORIGIN OF GOVERNMENT
- Nothing is more certain, than that men are, in a great measure, governed
- by interest, and that even when they extend their concern beyond
- themselves, it is not to any great distance; nor is it usual for
- them, in common life, to look farther than their nearest friends and
- acquaintance. It is no less certain, that it is impossible for men to
- consult, their interest in so effectual a manner, as by an universal and
- inflexible observance of the rules of justice, by which alone they can
- preserve society, and keep themselves from falling into that wretched
- and savage condition, which is commonly represented as the state of
- nature. And as this interest, which all men have in the upholding of
- society, and the observation of the rules of justice, is great, so is
- it palpable and evident, even to the most rude and uncultivated of human
- race; and it is almost impossible for any one, who has had experience of
- society, to be mistaken in this particular. Since, therefore, men are
- so sincerely attached to their interest, and their interest is so much
- concerned in the observance of justice, and this interest is so certain
- and avowed; it may be asked, how any disorder can ever arise in
- society, and what principle there is in human nature so powerful as to
- overcome so strong a passion, or so violent as to obscure so clear a
- knowledge?
- It has been observed, in treating of the passions, that men are mightily
- governed by the imagination, and proportion their affections more to
- the light, under which any object appears to them, than to its real and
- intrinsic value. What strikes upon them with a strong and lively idea
- commonly prevails above what lies in a more obscure light; and it
- must be a great superiority of value, that is able to compensate this
- advantage. Now as every thing, that is contiguous to us, either in space
- or time, strikes upon us with such an idea, it has a proportional effect
- on the will and passions, and commonly operates with more force than any
- object, that lies in a more distant and obscure light. Though we may be
- fully convinced, that the latter object excels the former, we are
- not able to regulate our actions by this judgment; but yield to the
- sollicitations of our passions, which always plead in favour of whatever
- is near and contiguous.
- This is the reason why men so often act in contradiction to their known
- interest; and in particular why they prefer any trivial advantage,
- that is present, to the maintenance of order in society, which so much
- depends on the observance of justice. The consequences of every breach
- of equity seem to lie very remote, and are not able to counter-ballance
- any immediate advantage, that may be reaped from it. They are, however,
- never the less real for being remote; and as all men are, in some
- degree, subject to the same weakness, it necessarily happens, that
- the violations of equity must become very frequent in society, and
- the commerce of men, by that means, be rendered very dangerous and
- uncertain. You have the same propension, that I have, in favour of
- what is contiguous above what is remote. You are, therefore, naturally
- carried to commit acts of injustice as well as me. Your example both
- pushes me forward in this way by imitation, and also affords me a new
- reason for any breach of equity, by shewing me, that I should be the
- cully of my integrity, if I alone should impose on myself a severe
- restraint amidst the licentiousness of others.
- This quality, therefore, of human nature, not only is very dangerous
- to society, but also seems, on a cursory view, to be incapable of any
- remedy. The remedy can only come from the consent of men; and if men be
- incapable of themselves to prefer remote to contiguous, they will never
- consent to any thing, which would oblige them to such a choice, and
- contradict, in so sensible a manner, their natural principles and
- propensities. Whoever chuses the means, chuses also the end; and if it
- be impossible for us to prefer what is remote, it is equally impossible
- for us to submit to any necessity, which would oblige us to such a
- method of acting.
- But here it is observable, that this infirmity of human nature becomes
- a remedy to itself, and that we provide against our negligence about
- remote objects, merely because we are naturally inclined to that
- negligence. When we consider any objects at a distance, all their minute
- distinctions vanish, and we always give the preference to whatever is in
- itself preferable, without considering its situation and circumstances.
- This gives rise to what in an improper sense we call reason, which is
- a principle, that is often contradictory to those propensities that
- display themselves upon the approach of the object. In reflecting on any
- action, which I am to perform a twelve-month hence, I always resolve to
- prefer the greater good, whether at that time it will be more contiguous
- or remote; nor does any difference in that particular make a difference
- in my present intentions and resolutions. My distance from the final
- determination makes all those minute differences vanish, nor am I
- affected by any thing, but the general and more discernible qualities of
- good and evil. But on my nearer approach, those circumstances, which
- I at first over-looked, begin to appear, and have an influence on my
- conduct and affections. A new inclination to the present good springs
- up, and makes it difficult for me to adhere inflexibly to my first
- purpose and resolution. This natural infirmity I may very much regret,
- and I may endeavour, by all possible means, to free my self from it. I
- may have recourse to study and reflection within myself; to the advice
- of friends; to frequent meditation, and repeated resolution: And having
- experienced how ineffectual all these are, I may embrace with pleasure
- any other expedient, by which I may impose a restraint upon myself, and
- guard against this weakness.
- The only difficulty, therefore, is to find out this expedient, by which
- men cure their natural weakness, and lay themselves under the necessity
- of observing the laws of justice and equity, notwithstanding their
- violent propension to prefer contiguous to remote. It is evident such a
- remedy can never be effectual without correcting this propensity; and as
- it is impossible to change or correct any thing material in our nature,
- the utmost we can do is to change our circumstances and situation, and
- render the observance of the laws of justice our nearest interest,
- and their violation our most remote. But this being impracticable with
- respect to all mankind, it can only take place with respect to a few,
- whom we thus immediately interest in the execution of justice. There are
- the persons, whom we call civil magistrates, kings and their ministers,
- our governors and rulers, who being indifferent persons to the greatest
- part of the state, have no interest, or but a remote one, in any act of
- injustice; and being satisfied with their present condition, and with
- their part in society, have an immediate interest in every execution of
- justice, which is so necessary to the upholding of society. Here then is
- the origin of civil government and society. Men are not able radically
- to cure, either in themselves or others, that narrowness of soul, which
- makes them prefer the present to the remote. They cannot change their
- natures. All they can do is to change their situation, and render the
- observance of justice the immediate interest of some particular persons,
- and its violation their more remote. These persons, then, are not
- only induced to observe those rules in their own conduct, but also
- to constrain others to a like regularity, and inforce the dictates of
- equity through the whole society. And if it be necessary, they may also
- interest others more immediately in the execution of justice, and
- create a number of officers, civil and military, to assist them in their
- government.
- But this execution of justice, though the principal, is not the only
- advantage of government. As violent passion hinder men from seeing
- distinctly the interest they have in an equitable behaviour towards
- others; so it hinders them from seeing that equity itself, and gives
- them a remarkable partiality in their own favours. This inconvenience is
- corrected in the same manner as that above-mentioned. The same persons,
- who execute the laws of justice, will also decide all controversies
- concerning them; and being indifferent to the greatest part of the
- society, will decide them more equitably than every one would in his own
- case.
- By means of these two advantages, in the execution and decision of
- justice, men acquire a security against each others weakness and
- passion, as well as against their own, and under the shelter of their
- governors, begin to taste at ease the sweets of society and mutual
- assistance. But government extends farther its beneficial influence; and
- not contented to protect men in those conventions they make for their
- mutual interest, it often obliges them to make such conventions, and
- forces them to seek their own advantage, by a concurrence in some common
- end or purpose. There is no quality in human nature, which causes more
- fatal errors in our conduct, than that which leads us to prefer whatever
- is present to the distant and remote, and makes us desire objects more
- according to their situation than their intrinsic value. Two neighbours
- may agree to drain a meadow, which they possess in common; because it is
- easy for them to know each others mind; and each must perceive, that the
- immediate consequence of his failing in his part, is, the abandoning the
- whole project. But it is very difficult, and indeed impossible, that a
- thousand persons should agree in any such action; it being difficult for
- them to concert so complicated a design, and still more difficult for
- them to execute it; while each seeks a pretext to free himself of the
- trouble and expence, and would lay the whole burden on others. Political
- society easily remedies both these inconveniences. Magistrates find an
- immediate interest in the interest of any considerable part of their
- subjects. They need consult no body but themselves to form any scheme
- for the promoting of that interest. And as the failure of any one piece
- in the execution is connected, though not immediately, with the failure
- of the whole, they prevent that failure, because they find no interest
- in it, either immediate or remote. Thus bridges are built; harbours
- opened; ramparts raised; canals formed; fleets equiped; and armies
- disciplined every where, by the care of government, which, though
- composed of men subject to all human infirmities, becomes, by one of the
- finest and most subtle inventions imaginable, a composition, which is,
- in some measure, exempted from all these infirmities.
- SECT. VIII OF THE SOURCE OF ALLEGIANCE
- Though government be an invention very advantageous, and even in some
- circumstances absolutely necessary to mankind; it is not necessary in
- all circumstances, nor is it impossible for men to preserve society
- for some time, without having recourse to such an invention. Men, it is
- true, are always much inclined to prefer present interest to distant
- and remote; nor is it easy for them to resist the temptation of any
- advantage, that they may immediately enjoy, in apprehension of an evil
- that lies at a distance from them: But still this weakness is less
- conspicuous where the possessions, and the pleasures of life are few,
- and of little value, as they always are in the infancy of society. An
- Indian is but little tempted to dispossess another of his hut, or to
- steal his bow, as being already provided of the same advantages; and as
- to any superior fortune, which may attend one above another in hunting
- and fishing, it is only casual and temporary, and will have but small
- tendency to disturb society. And so far am I from thinking with
- some philosophers, that men are utterly incapable of society without
- government, that I assert the first rudiments of government to arise
- from quarrels, not among men of the same society, but among those of
- different societies. A less degree of riches will suffice to this latter
- effect, than is requisite for the former. Men fear nothing from public
- war and violence but the resistance they meet with, which, because
- they share it in common, seems less terrible; and because it comes from
- strangers, seems less pernicious in its consequences, than when they are
- exposed singly against one whose commerce is advantageous to them, and
- without whose society it is impossible they can subsist. Now foreign war
- to a society without government necessarily produces civil war. Throw
- any considerable goods among men, they instantly fall a quarrelling,
- while each strives to get possession of what pleases him, without regard
- to the consequences. In a foreign war the most considerable of all
- goods, life and limbs, are at stake; and as every one shuns dangerous
- ports, seizes the best arms, seeks excuse for the slightest wounds, the
- laws, which may be well enough observed while men were calm, can now no
- longer take place, when they are in such commotion.
- This we find verified in the American tribes, where men live in concord
- and amity among themselves without any established government and never
- pay submission to any of their fellows, except in time of war, when
- their captain enjoys a shadow of authority, which he loses after
- their return from the field, and the establishment of peace with the
- neighbouring tribes. This authority, however, instructs them in the
- advantages of government, and teaches them to have recourse to it,
- when either by the pillage of war, by commerce, or by any fortuitous
- inventions, their riches and possessions have become so considerable as
- to make them forget, on every emergence, the interest they have in the
- preservation of peace and justice. Hence we may give a plausible reason,
- among others, why all governments are at first monarchical, without any
- mixture and variety; and why republics arise only from the abuses of
- monarchy and despotic power. Camps are the true mothers of cities; and
- as war cannot be administered, by reason of the suddenness of every
- exigency, without some authority in a single person, the same kind of
- authority naturally takes place in that civil government, which succeeds
- the military. And this reason I take to be more natural, than the common
- one derived from patriarchal government, or the authority of a father,
- which is said first to take place in one family, and to accustom the
- members of it to the government of a single person. The state of society
- without government is one of the most natural states of men, and must
- submit with the conjunction of many families, and long after the first
- generation. Nothing but an encrease of riches and possessions coued
- oblige men to quit it; and so barbarous and uninstructed are all
- societies on their first formation, that many years must elapse before
- these can encrease to such a degree, as to disturb men in the enjoyment
- of peace and concord. But though it be possible for men to maintain a
- small uncultivated society without government, it is impossible
- they should maintain a society of any kind without justice, and the
- observance of those three fundamental laws concerning the stability of
- possession, its translation by consent, and the performance of promises.
- These are, therefore, antecedent to government, and are supposed to
- impose an obligation before the duty of allegiance to civil magistrates
- has once been thought of. Nay, I shall go farther, and assert, that
- government, upon its first establishment, would naturally be supposed.
- to derive its obligation from those laws of nature, and, in particular,
- from that concerning the performance of promises. When men have once
- perceived the necessity of government to maintain peace, and
- execute justice, they would naturally assemble together, would chuse
- magistrates, determine power, and promise them obedience. As a promise
- is supposed to be a bond or security already in use, and attended with
- a moral obligation, it is to be considered as the original sanction of
- government, and as the source of the first obligation to obedience. This
- reasoning appears so natural, that it has become the foundation of our
- fashionable system of politics, and is in a manner the creed of a party
- amongst us, who pride themselves, with reason, on the soundness of their
- philosophy, and their liberty of thought. All men, say they, are born
- free and equal: Government and superiority can only be established by
- consent: The consent of men, in establishing government, imposes on them
- a new obligation, unknown to the laws of nature. Men, therefore, are
- bound to obey their magistrates, only because they promise it; and if
- they had not given their word, either expressly or tacitly, to preserve
- allegiance, it would never have become a part of their moral duty. This
- conclusion, however, when carried so far as to comprehend government in
- all its ages and situations, is entirely erroneous; and I maintain, that
- though the duty of allegiance be at first grafted on the obligation
- of promises, and be for some time supported by that obligation, yet
- it quickly takes root of itself, and has an original obligation and
- authority, independent of all contracts. This is a principle of moment,
- which we must examine with care and attention, before we proceed any
- farther.
- It is reasonable for those philosophers, who assert justice to be a
- natural virtue, and antecedent to human conventions, to resolve all
- civil allegiance into the obligation of a promise, and assert that it is
- our own consent alone, which binds us to any submission to magistracy.
- For as all government is plainly an invention of men, and the origin of
- most governments is known in history, it is necessary to mount higher,
- in order to find the source of our political duties, if we would assert
- them to have any natural obligation of morality. These philosophers,
- therefore, quickly observe, that society is as antient as the human
- species, and those three fundamental laws of nature as antient as
- society: So that taking advantage of the antiquity, and obscure origin
- of these laws, they first deny them to be artificial and voluntary
- inventions of men, and then seek to ingraft on them those other duties,
- which are more plainly artificial. But being once undeceived in this
- particular, and having found that natural, as well as civil justice,
- derives its origin from human conventions, we shall quickly perceive,
- how fruitless it is to resolve the one into the other, and seek, in
- the laws of nature, a stronger foundation for our political duties than
- interest, and human conventions; while these laws themselves are built
- on the very same foundation. On which ever side we turn this subject,
- we shall find, that these two kinds of duty are exactly on the same
- footing, and have the same source both of their first invention and
- moral obligation. They are contrived to remedy like inconveniences, and
- acquire their moral sanction in the same manner, from their remedying
- those inconveniences. These are two points, which we shall endeavour to
- prove as distinctly as possible.
- We have already shewn, that men invented the three fundamental laws
- of nature, when they observed the necessity of society to their
- mutual subsistance, and found, that it was impossible to maintain
- any correspondence together, without some restraint on their natural
- appetites. The same self-love, therefore, which renders men so
- incommodious to each other, taking a new and more convenient direction,
- produces the rules of justice, and is the first motive of their
- observance. But when men have observed, that though the rules of justice
- be sufficient to maintain any society, yet it is impossible for them,
- of themselves, to observe those rules, in large and polished societies;
- they establish government, as a new invention to attain their ends, and
- preserve the old, or procure new advantages, by a more strict execution
- of justice. So far, therefore, our civil duties are connected with
- our natural, that the former are invented chiefly for the sake of the
- latter; and that the principal object of government is to constrain men
- to observe the laws of nature. In this respect, however, that law of
- nature, concerning the performance of promises, is only comprized along
- with the rest; and its exact observance is to be considered as an effect
- of the institution of government, and not the obedience to government as
- an effect of the obligation of a promise. Though the object of our civil
- duties be the enforcing of our natural, yet the first [First in
- time, not in dignity or force.] motive of the invention, as well as
- performance of both, is nothing but self-interest: and since there is
- a separate interest in the obedience to government, from that in the
- performance of promises, we must also allow of a separate obligation. To
- obey the civil magistrate is requisite to preserve order and concord
- in society. To perform promises is requisite to beget mutual trust
- and confidence in the common offices of life. The ends, as well as the
- means, are perfectly distinct; nor is the one subordinate to the other.
- To make this more evident, let us consider, that men will often bind
- themselves by promises to the performance of what it would have been
- their interest to perform, independent of these promises; as when they
- would give others a fuller security, by super-adding a new obligation
- of interest to that which they formerly lay under. The interest in
- the performance of promises, besides its moral obligation, is general,
- avowed, and of the last consequence in life. Other interests may be
- more particular and doubtful; and we are apt to entertain a greater
- suspicion, that men may indulge their humour, or passion, in acting
- contrary to them. Here, therefore, promises come naturally in play, and
- are often required for fuller satisfaction and security. But supposing
- those other interests to be as general and avowed as the interest in the
- performance of a promise, they will be regarded as on the same footing,
- and men will begin to repose the same confidence in them. Now this is
- exactly the case with regard to our civil duties, or obedience to the
- magistrate; without which no government coued subsist, nor any peace
- or order be maintained in large societies, where there are so many
- possessions on the one hand, and so many wants, real or imaginary, on
- the other. Our civil duties, therefore, must soon detach themselves from
- our promises, and acquire a separate force and influence. The interest
- in both is of the very same kind: It is general, avowed, and prevails in
- all times and places. There is, then, no pretext of reason for founding
- the one upon the other; while each of them has a foundation peculiar
- to itself. We might as well resolve the obligation to abstain from the
- possessions of others, into the obligation of a promise, as that of
- allegiance. The interests are not more distinct in the one case than the
- other. A regard to property is not more necessary to natural society,
- than obedience is to civil society or government; nor is the former
- society more necessary to the being of mankind, than the latter to their
- well-being and happiness. In short, if the performance of promises be
- advantageous, so is obedience to government: If the former interest be
- general, so is the latter: If the one interest be obvious and avowed, so
- is the other. And as these two rules are founded on like obligations of
- interest, each of them must have a peculiar authority, independent of
- the other.
- But it is not only the natural obligations of interest, which are
- distinct in promises and allegiance; but also the moral obligations of
- honour and conscience: Nor does the merit or demerit of the one depend
- in the least upon that of the other. And indeed, if we consider the
- close connexion there is betwixt the natural and moral obligations, we
- shall find this conclusion to be entirely unavoidable. Our interest
- is always engaged on the side of obedience to magistracy; and there is
- nothing but a great present advantage, that can lead us to rebellion, by
- making us over-look the remote interest, which we have in the preserving
- of peace and order in society. But though a present interest may thus
- blind us with regard to our own actions, it takes not place with regard
- to those of others; nor hinders them from appearing in their true
- colours, as highly prejudicial to public interest, and to our own in
- particular. This naturally gives us an uneasiness, in considering such
- seditious and disloyal actions, and makes us attach to them the idea of
- vice and moral deformity. It is the same principle, which causes us to
- disapprove of all kinds of private injustice, and in particular of the
- breach of promises. We blame all treachery and breach of faith; because
- we consider, that the freedom and extent of human commerce depend
- entirely on a fidelity with regard to promises. We blame all disloyalty
- to magistrates; because we perceive, that the execution of justice,
- in the stability of possession, its translation by consent, and
- the performance of promises, is impossible, without submission to
- government. As there are here two interests entirely distinct from each
- other, they must give rise to two moral obligations, equally separate
- and independent. Though there was no such thing as a promise in the
- world, government would still be necessary in all large and civilized
- societies; and if promises had only their own proper obligation, without
- the separate sanction of government, they would have but little efficacy
- in such societies. This separates the boundaries of our public and
- private duties, and shews that the latter are more dependant on the
- former, than the former on the latter. Education, and the artifice of
- politicians, concur to bestow a farther morality on loyalty, and to
- brand all rebellion with a greater degree of guilt and infamy. Nor is
- it a wonder, that politicians should be very industrious in inculcating
- such notions, where their interest is so particularly concerned.
- Lest those arguments should not appear entirely conclusive (as I think
- they are) I shall have recourse to authority, and shall prove, from
- the universal consent of mankind, that the obligation of submission to
- government is not derived from any promise of the subjects. Nor need
- any one wonder, that though I have all along endeavoured to establish my
- system on pure reason, and have scarce ever cited the judgment even
- of philosophers or historians on any article, I should now appeal
- to popular authority, and oppose the sentiments of the rabble to any
- philosophical reasoning. For it must be observed, that the opinions of
- men, in this case, carry with them a peculiar authority, and are, in
- a great measure, infallible. The distinction of moral good and evil
- is founded on the pleasure or pain, which results from the view of any
- sentiment, or character; and as that pleasure or pain cannot be unknown
- to the person who feels it, it follows [Footnote 22], that there is just
- so much vice or virtue in any character, as every one places in it, and
- that it is impossible in this particular we can ever be mistaken. And
- though our judgments concerning the origin of any vice or virtue, be not
- so certain as those concerning their degrees; yet, since the question in
- this case regards not any philosophical origin of an obligation, but a
- plain matter of fact, it is not easily conceived how we can fall into
- an error. A man, who acknowledges himself to be bound to another, for a
- certain sum, must certainly know whether it be by his own bond, or that
- of his father; whether it be of his mere good-will, or for money lent
- him; and under what conditions, and for what purposes he has bound
- himself. In like manner, it being certain, that there is a moral
- obligation to submit to government, because every one thinks so; it must
- be as certain, that this obligation arises not from a promise; since no
- one, whose judgment has not been led astray by too strict adherence to
- a system of philosophy, has ever yet dreamt of ascribing it to that
- origin. Neither magistrates nor subjects have formed this idea of our
- civil duties.
- [Footnote 22 This proposition must hold strictly true, with
- regard to every quality, that is determin'd merely by
- sentiment. In what sense we can talk either of a right or a
- wrong taste in morals, eloquence, or beauty, shall be
- considerd afterwards. In the mean time, it may be observ'd,
- that there is such an uniformity in the GENERAL sentiments
- of mankind, as to render such questions of but small
- importance.]
- We find, that magistrates are so far from deriving their authority, and
- the obligation to obedience in their subjects, from the foundation of
- a promise or original contract, that they conceal, as far as possible,
- from their people, especially from the vulgar, that they have their
- origin from thence. Were this the sanction of government, our rulers
- would never receive it tacitly, which is the utmost that can be
- pretended; since what is given tacitly and insensibly can never have
- such influence on mankind, as what is performed expressly and openly.
- A tacit promise is, where the will is signified by other more diffuse
- signs than those of speech; but a will there must certainly be in the
- case, and that can never escape the person's notice, who exerted it,
- however silent or tacit. But were you to ask the far greatest part of
- the nation, whether they had ever consented to the authority of their
- rulers, or promised to obey them, they would be inclined to think very
- strangely of you; and would certainly reply, that the affair depended
- not on their consent, but that they were born to such an obedience. In
- consequence of this opinion, we frequently see them imagine such persons
- to be their natural rulers, as are at that time deprived of all power
- and authority, and whom no man, however foolish, would voluntarily
- chuse; and this merely because they are in that line, which ruled
- before, and in that degree of it, which used to succeed; though perhaps
- in so distant a period, that scarce any man alive coued ever have given
- any promise of obedience. Has a government, then, no authority over such
- as these, because they never consented to it, and would esteem the very
- attempt of such a free choice a piece of arrogance and impiety? We
- find by experience, that it punishes them very freely for what it
- calls treason and rebellion, which, it seems, according to this system,
- reduces itself to common injustice. If you say, that by dwelling in its
- dominions, they in effect consented to the established government; I
- answer, that this can only be, where they think the affair depends on
- their choice, which few or none, beside those philosophers, have ever
- yet imagined. It never was pleaded as an excuse for a rebel, that the
- first act he perform d, after he came to years of discretion, was to
- levy war against the sovereign of the state; and that while he was a
- child he coued not bind himself by his own consent, and having become
- a man, showed plainly, by the first act he performed, that he had no
- design to impose on himself any obligation to obedience. We find, on
- the contrary, that civil laws punish this crime at the same age as any
- other, which is criminal, of itself, without our consent; that is, when
- the person is come to the full use of reason: Whereas to this crime
- they ought in justice to allow some intermediate time, in which a tacit
- consent at least might be supposed. To which we may add, that a man
- living under an absolute government, would owe it no allegiance; since,
- by its very nature, it depends not on consent. But as that is as
- natural and common a government as any, it must certainly occasion some
- obligation; and it is plain from experience, that men, who are subjected
- to it, do always think so. This is a clear proof, that we do not
- commonly esteem our allegiance to be derived from our consent or
- promise; and a farther proof is, that when our promise is upon any
- account expressly engaged, we always distinguish exactly betwixt the two
- obligations, and believe the one to add more force to the other, than in
- a repetition of the same promise. Where no promise is given, a man
- looks not on his faith as broken in private matters, upon account of
- rebellion; but keeps those two duties of honour and allegiance perfectly
- distinct and separate. As the uniting of them was thought by these
- philosophers a very subtile invention, this is a convincing proof, that
- it is not a true one; since no man can either give a promise, or be
- restrained by its sanction and obligation unknown to himself.
- SECT. IX OF THE MEASURES OF ALLEGIANCE
- Those political writers, who have had recourse to a promise, or original
- contract, as the source of our allegiance to government, intended to
- establish a principle, which is perfectly just and reasonable; though
- the reasoning, upon which they endeavoured to establish it, was
- fallacious and sophistical. They would prove, that our submission to
- government admits of exceptions, and that an egregious tyranny in the
- rulers is sufficient to free the subjects from all ties of allegiance.
- Since men enter into society, say they, and submit themselves to
- government, by their free and voluntary consent, they must have in view
- certain advantages, which they propose to reap from it, and for which
- they are contented to resign their native liberty. There is, therefore,
- something mutual engaged on the part of the magistrate, viz, protection
- and security; and it is only by the hopes he affords of these
- advantages, that he can ever persuade men to submit to him. But
- when instead of protection and security, they meet with tyranny and
- oppression, they are freeed from their promises, (as happens in all
- conditional contracts) and return to that state of liberty, which
- preceded the institution of government. Men would never be so foolish as
- to enter into such engagements as should turn entirely to the advantage
- of others, without any view of bettering their own condition. Whoever
- proposes to draw any profit from our submission, must engage himself,
- either expressly or tacitly, to make us reap some advantage from his
- authority; nor ought he to expect, that without the performance of his
- part we will ever continue in obedience.
- I repeat it: This conclusion is just, though the principles be
- erroneous; and I flatter myself, that I can establish the same
- conclusion on more reasonable principles. I shall not take such a
- compass, in establishing our political duties, as to assert, that men
- perceive the advantages of government; that they institute government
- with a view to those advantages; that this institution requires a
- promise of obedience; which imposes a moral obligation to a certain
- degree, but being conditional, ceases to be binding, whenever the other
- contracting party performs not his part of the engagement. I perceive,
- that a promise itself arises entirely from human conventions, and is
- invented with a view to a certain interest. I seek, therefore, some such
- interest more immediately connected with government, and which may be
- at once the original motive to its institution, and the source of our
- obedience to it. This interest I find to consist in the security and
- protection, which we enjoy in political society, and which we can never
- attain, when perfectly free and independent. As interest, therefore, is
- the immediate sanction of government, the one can have no longer being
- than the other; and whenever the civil magistrate carries his oppression
- so far as to render his authority perfectly intolerable, we are no
- longer bound to submit to it. The cause ceases; the effect must cease
- also.
- So far the conclusion is immediate and direct, concerning the natural
- obligation which we have to allegiance. As to the moral obligation, we
- may observe, that the maxim would here be false, that when the cause
- ceases, the effect must cease also. For there is a principle of human
- nature, which we have frequently taken notice of, that men are mightily
- addicted to general rules, and that we often carry our maxims beyond
- those reasons, which first induced us to establish them. Where cases
- are similar in many circumstances, we are apt to put them on the same
- footing, without considering, that they differ in the most material
- circumstances, and that the resemblance is more apparent than real. It
- may, therefore, be thought, that in the case of allegiance our moral
- obligation of duty will not cease, even though the natural obligation of
- interest, which is its cause, has ceased; and that men may be bound by
- conscience to submit to a tyrannical government against their own and
- the public interest. And indeed, to the force of this argument I so far
- submit, as to acknowledge, that general rules commonly extend beyond
- the principles, on which they are founded; and that we seldom make any
- exception to them, unless that exception have the qualities of a general
- rule, and be founded on very numerous and common instances. Now this I
- assert to be entirely the present case. When men submit to the authority
- of others, it is to procure themselves some security against the
- wickedness and injustice of men, who are perpetually carried, by their
- unruly passions, and by their present and immediate interest, to the
- violation of all the laws of society. But as this imperfection is
- inherent in human nature, we know that it must attend men in all their
- states and conditions; and that these, whom we chuse for rulers, do not
- immediately become of a superior nature to the rest of mankind, upon
- account of their superior power and authority. What we expect from them
- depends not on a change of their nature but of their situation, when
- they acquire a more immediate interest in the preservation of order and
- the execution of justice. But besides that this interest is only more
- immediate in the execution of justice among their subjects; besides
- this, I say, we may often expect, from the irregularity of human nature,
- that they will neglect even this immediate interest, and be transported
- by their passions into all the excesses of cruelty and ambition.. Our
- general knowledge of human nature, our observation of the past history
- of mankind, our experience of present times; all these causes must
- induce us to open the door to exceptions, and must make us conclude,
- that we may resist the more violent effects of supreme power, without
- any crime or injustice.
- Accordingly we may observe, that this is both the general practice and
- principle of mankind, and that no nation, that coued find any remedy,
- ever yet suffered the cruel ravages of a tyrant, or were blamed for
- their resistance. Those who took up arms against Dionysius or Nero, or
- Philip the second, have the favour of every reader in the perusal of
- their history: and nothing but the most violent perversion of common
- sense can ever lead us to condemn them. It is certain, therefore, that
- in all our notions of morals we never entertain such an absurdity as
- that of passive obedience, but make allowances for resistance in the
- more flagrant instances of tyranny and oppression. The general opinion
- of mankind has some authority in all cases; but in this of morals it
- is perfectly infallible. Nor is it less infallible, because men cannot
- distinctly explain the principles, on which it is founded. Few persons
- can carry on this train of reasoning:
- Government is a mere human invention for the interest of society. Where
- the tyranny of the governor removes this interest, it also removes the
- natural obligation to obedience. The moral obligation is founded on the
- natural, and therefore must cease where that ceases; especially where
- the subject is such as makes us foresee very many occasions wherein the
- natural obligation may cease, and causes us to form a kind of general
- rule for the regulation of our conduct in such occurrences.
- But though this train of reasoning be too subtile for the vulgar, it is
- certain, that all men have an implicit notion of it, and are sensible,
- that they owe obedience to government merely on account of the public
- interest; and at the same time, that human nature is so subject to
- frailties and passions, as may easily pervert this institution, and
- change their governors into tyrants and public enemies. If the sense of
- common interest were not our original motive to obedience, I would fain
- ask, what other principle is there in human nature capable of subduing
- the natural ambition of men, and forcing them to such a submission?
- Imitation and custom are not sufficient. For the question still recurs,
- what motive first produces those instances of submission, which we
- imitate, and that train of actions, which produces the custom? There
- evidently is no other principle than public interest; and if interest
- first produces obedience to government, the obligation to obedience
- must cease, whenever the interest ceases, in any great degree, and in a
- considerable number of instances.
- SECT. X OF THE OBJECTS OF ALLEGIANCE
- But though, on some occasions, it may be justifiable, both in sound
- politics and morality, to resist supreme power, it is certain, that in
- the ordinary course of human affairs nothing can be more pernicious
- and criminal; and that besides the convulsions, which always attend
- revolutions, such a practice tends directly to the subversion of all
- government, and the causing an universal anarchy and confusion among
- mankind. As numerous and civilized societies cannot subsist without
- government, so government is entirely useless without an exact
- obedience. We ought always to weigh the advantages, which we reap from
- authority, against the disadvantages; and by this means we shall become
- more scrupulous of putting in practice the doctrine of resistance. The
- common rule requires submission; and it is only in cases of grievous
- tyranny and oppression, that the exception can take place.
- Since then such a blind submission is commonly due to magistracy, the
- next question is, to whom it is due, and whom we are to regard as our
- lawful magistrates? In order to answer this question, let us recollect
- what we have already established concerning the origin of government and
- political society. When men have once experienced the impossibility
- of preserving any steady order in society, while every one is his own
- master, and violates or observes the laws of society, according to his
- present interest or pleasure, they naturally run into the invention of
- government, and put it out of their own power, as far as possible, to
- transgress the laws of society. Government, therefore, arises from the
- same voluntary conversation of men; and it is evident, that the same
- convention, which establishes government, will also determine the
- persons who are to govern, and will remove all doubt and ambiguity in
- this particular. And the voluntary consent of men must here have the
- greater efficacy, that the authority of the magistrate does at first
- stand upon the foundation of a promise of the subjects, by which they
- bind themselves to obedience; as in every other contract or engagement.
- The same promise, then, which binds them to obedience, ties them down to
- a particular person, and makes him the object of their allegiance.
- But when government has been established on this footing for some
- considerable time, and the separate interest, which we have in
- submission, has produced a separate sentiment of morality, the case
- is entirely altered, and a promise is no longer able to determine the
- particular magistrate since it is no longer considered as the foundation
- of government. We naturally suppose ourselves born to submission; and
- imagine, that such particular persons have a right to command, as we on
- our part are bound to obey. These notions of right and obligation are
- derived from nothing but the advantage we reap from government, which
- gives us a repugnance to practise resistance ourselves, and makes us
- displeased with any instance of it in others. But here it is remarkable,
- that in this new state of affairs, the original sanction of government,
- which is interest, is not admitted to determine the persons, whom we are
- to obey, as the original sanction did at first, when affairs were on
- the footing of a promise. A promise fixes and determines the persons,
- without any uncertainty: But it is evident, that if men were to regulate
- their conduct in this particular, by the view of a peculiar interest,
- either public or private, they would involve themselves in endless
- confusion, and would render all government, in a great measure,
- ineffectual. The private interest of every one is different; and though
- the public interest in itself be always one and the same, yet it becomes
- the source of as great dissentions, by reason of the different opinions
- of particular persons concerning it. The same interest, therefore,
- which causes us to submit to magistracy, makes us renounce itself in
- the choice of our magistrates, and binds us down to a certain form of
- government, and to particular persons, without allowing us to aspire to
- the utmost perfection in either. The case is here the same as in that
- law of nature concerning the stability of possession. It is highly
- advantageous, and even absolutely necessary to society, that possession
- should be stable; and this leads us to the establishment of such a rule:
- But we find, that were we to follow the same advantage, in assigning
- particular possessions to particular persons, we should disappoint
- our end, and perpetuate the confusion, which that rule is intended to
- prevent. We must, therefore, proceed by general rules, and regulate
- ourselves by general interests, in modifying the law of nature
- concerning the stability of possession. Nor need we fear, that our
- attachment to this law will diminish upon account of the seeming
- frivolousness of those interests, by which it is determined. The impulse
- of the mind is derived from a very strong interest; and those other more
- minute interests serve only to direct the motion, without adding
- any thing to it, or diminishing from it. It is the same case with
- government. Nothing is more advantageous to society than such an
- invention; and this interest is sufficient to make us embrace it with
- ardour and alacrity; though we are obliged afterwards to regulate and
- direct our devotion to government by several considerations, which are
- not of the same importance, and to chuse our magistrates without having
- in view any particular advantage from the choice.
- The first of those principles I shall take notice of, as a foundation of
- the right of magistracy, is that which gives authority to all the most
- established governments of the world without exception: I mean, long
- possession in any one form of government, or succession of princes. It
- is certain, that if we remount to the first origin of every nation,
- we shall find, that there scarce is any race of kings, or form of a
- commonwealth, that is not primarily founded on usurpation and rebellion,
- and whose title is not at first worse than doubtful and uncertain. Time
- alone gives solidity to their right; and operating gradually on the
- minds of men, reconciles them to any authority, and makes it seem just
- and reasonable. Nothing causes any sentiment to have a greater influence
- upon us than custom, or turns our imagination more strongly to any
- object. When we have been long accustomed to obey any set of men,
- that general instinct or tendency, which we have to suppose a moral
- obligation attending loyalty, takes easily this direction, and chuses
- that set of men for its objects. It is interest which gives the general
- instinct; but it is custom which gives the particular direction.
- And here it is observable, that the same length of time has a different
- influence on our sentiments of morality, according to its different
- influence on the mind. We naturally judge of every thing by comparison;
- and since in considering the fate of kingdoms and republics, we embrace
- a long extent of time, a small duration has not in this case a like
- influence on our sentiments, as when we consider any other object. One
- thinks he acquires a right to a horse, or a suit of cloaths, in a very
- short time; but a century is scarce sufficient to establish any
- new government, or remove all scruples in the minds of the subjects
- concerning it. Add to this, that a shorter period of time will suffice
- to give a prince a title to any additional power he may usurp, than will
- serve to fix his right, where the whole is an usurpation. The kings of
- France have not been possessed of absolute power for above two reigns;
- and yet nothing will appear more extravagant to Frenchmen than to
- talk of their liberties. If we consider what has been said concerning
- accession, we shall easily account for this phaenomenon.
- When there is no form of government established by long possession,
- the present possession is sufficient to supply its place, and may
- be regarded as the second source of all public authority. Right
- to authority is nothing but the constant possession of authority,
- maintained by the laws of society and the interests of mankind; and
- nothing can be more natural than to join this constant possession to the
- present one, according to the principles above-mentioned. If the same
- principles did not take place with regard to the property of private
- persons, it was because these principles were counter-ballanced by
- very strong considerations of interest; when we observed, that all
- restitution would by that means be prevented, and every violence be
- authorized and protected. And though the same motives may seem to
- have force, with regard to public authority, yet they are opposed by a
- contrary interest; which consists in the preservation of peace, and the
- avoiding of all changes, which, however they may be easily produced in
- private affairs, are unavoidably attended with bloodshed and confusion,
- where the public is interested.
- Any one, who finding the impossibility of accounting for the right of
- the present possessor, by any received system of ethics, should resolve
- to deny absolutely that right, and assert, that it is not authorized
- by morality, would be justly thought to maintain a very extravagant
- paradox, and to shock the common sense and judgment of mankind. No maxim
- is more conformable, both to prudence and morals, than to submit quietly
- to the government, which we find established in the country where we
- happen to live, without enquiring too curiously into its origin and
- first establishment. Few governments will bear being examined so
- rigorously. How many kingdoms are there at present in the world, and
- how many more do we find in history, whose governors have no better
- foundation for their authority than that of present possession? To
- confine ourselves to the Roman and Grecian empire; is it not evident,
- that the long succession of emperors, from the dissolution of the Roman
- liberty, to the final extinction of that empire by the Turks, coued not
- so much as pretend to any other title to the empire? The election of the
- senate was a mere form, which always followed the choice of the legions;
- and these were almost always divided in the different provinces, and
- nothing but the sword was able to terminate the difference. It was by
- the sword, therefore, that every emperor acquired, as well as defended
- his right; and we must either say, that all the known world, for so
- many ages, had no government, and owed no allegiance to any one, or
- must allow, that the right of the stronger, in public affairs, is to be
- received as legitimate, and authorized by morality, when not opposed by
- any other title.
- The right of conquest may be considered as a third source of the
- title of sovereigns. This right resembles very much that of present
- possession; but has rather a superior force, being seconded by the
- notions of glory and honour, which we ascribe to conquerors, instead
- of the sentiments of hatred and detestation, which attend usurpers. Men
- naturally favour those they love; and therefore are more apt to ascribe
- a right to successful violence, betwixt one sovereign and another, than
- to the successful rebellion of a subject against his sovereign.
- [Footnote 23 It is not here asserted, that present
- possession or conquest are sufficient to give a title
- against long possession and positive laws but only that they
- have some force, and will be able to call the ballance where
- the titles are otherwise equal, and will even be sufficient
- sometimes to sanctify the weaker title. What degree of force
- they have is difficult to determine. I believe all moderate
- men will allow, that they have great force in all disputes
- concerning the rights of princes.]
- When neither long possession, nor present possession, nor conquest take
- place, as when the first sovereign, who founded any monarchy, dies; in
- that case, the right of succession naturally prevails in their stead,
- and men are commonly induced to place the son of their late monarch
- on the throne, and suppose him to inherit his father's authority. The
- presumed consent of the father, the imitation of the succession to
- private families, the interest, which the state has in chusing the
- person, who is most powerful, and has the most numerous followers; all
- these reasons lead men to prefer the son of their late monarch to any
- other person.
- [Footnote 24 To prevent mistakes I must observe, that this
- case of succession is not the same with that of hereditary
- monarchies, where custom has fix'd the right of succession.
- These depend upon the principle of long possession above
- explain'd.]
- These reasons have some weight; but I am persuaded, that to one, who
- considers impartially of the matter, it will appear, that there concur
- some principles of the imagination, along with those views of interest.
- The royal authority seems to be connected with the young prince even in
- his father's life-time, by the natural transition of the thought; and
- still more after his death: So that nothing is more natural than to
- compleat this union by a new relation, and by putting him actually in
- possession of what seems so naturally to belong to him.
- To confirm this we may weigh the following phaenomena, which are pretty
- curious in their kind. In elective monarchies the right of succession
- has no place by the laws and settled custom; and yet its influence is
- so natural, that it is impossible entirely to exclude it from the
- imagination, and render the subjects indifferent to the son of their
- deceased monarch. Hence in some governments of this kind, the choice
- commonly falls on one or other of the royal family; and in some
- governments they are all excluded. Those contrary phaenomena proceed
- from the same principle. Where the royal family is excluded, it is
- from a refinement in politics, which makes people sensible of their
- propensity to chuse a sovereign in that family, and gives them a
- jealousy of their liberty, lest their new monarch, aided by this
- propensity, should establish his family, and destroy the freedom of
- elections for the future.
- The history of Artaxerxes, and the younger Cyrus, may furnish us with
- some reflections to the same purpose. Cyrus pretended a right to the
- throne above his elder brother, because he was born after his father's
- accession. I do not pretend, that this reason was valid. I would only
- infer from it, that he would never have made use of such a pretext, were
- it not for the qualities of the imagination above-mentioned, by which
- we are naturally inclined to unite by a new relation whatever objects we
- find already united. Artaxerxes had an advantage above his brother, as
- being the eldest son, and the first in succession: But Cyrus was more
- closely related to the royal authority, as being begot after his father
- was invested with it.
- Should it here be pretended, that the view of convenience may be
- the source of all the right of succession, and that men gladly take
- advantage of any rule, by which they can fix the successor of their late
- sovereign, and prevent that anarchy and confusion, which attends all
- new elections? To this I would answer, that I readily allow, that this
- motive may contribute something to the effect; but at the same time I
- assert, that without another principle, it is impossible such a
- motive should take place. The interest of a nation requires, that the
- succession to the crown should be fixed one way or other; but it is
- the same thing to its interest in what way it be fixed: So that if the
- relation of blood had not an effect independent of public interest, it
- would never have been regarded, without a positive law; and it would
- have been impossible, that so many positive laws of different nations
- coued ever have concured precisely in the same views and intentions.
- This leads us to consider the fifth source of authority, viz. positive
- laws; when the legislature establishes a certain form of government and
- succession of princes. At first sight it may be thought, that this must
- resolve into some of the preceding titles of authority. The legislative
- power, whence the positive law is derived, must either be established
- by original contract, long possession, present possession, conquest, or
- succession; and consequently the positive law must derive its force
- from some of those principles. But here it is remarkable, that though
- a positive law can only derive its force from these principles, yet it
- acquires not all the force of the principle from whence it is derived,
- but loses considerably in the transition; as it is natural to imagine.
- For instance; a government is established for many centuries on
- a certain system of laws, forms, and methods of succession. The
- legislative power, established by this long succession, changes all on a
- sudden the whole system of government, and introduces a new constitution
- in its stead. I believe few of the subjects will think themselves bound
- to comply with this alteration, unless it have an evident tendency to
- the public good: But men think themselves still at liberty to return to
- the antient government. Hence the notion of fundamental laws; which are
- supposed to be inalterable by the will of the sovereign: And of this
- nature the Salic law is understood to be in France. How far these
- fundamental laws extend is not determined in any government; nor is it
- possible it ever should. There is such an indefensible gradation from
- the most material laws to the most trivial, and from the most antient
- laws to the most modem, that it will be impossible to set bounds to
- the legislative power, and determine how far it may innovate in the
- principles of government. That is the work more of imagination and
- passion than of reason.
- Whoever considers the history of the several nations of the world; their
- revolutions, conquests, increase, and diminution; the manner in which
- their particular governments are established, and the successive right
- transmitted from one person to another, will soon learn to treat very
- lightly all disputes concerning the rights of princes, and will be
- convinced, that a strict adherence to any general rules, and the rigid
- loyalty to particular persons and families, on which some people set so
- high a value, are virtues that hold less of reason, than of bigotry
- and superstition. In this particular, the study of history confirms the
- reasonings of true philosophy; which, shewing us the original qualities
- of human nature, teaches us to regard the controversies in politics as
- incapable of any decision in most cases, and as entirely subordinate
- to the interests of peace and liberty. Where the public good does not
- evidently demand a change; it is certain, that the concurrence of all
- those titles, original contract, long possession, present possession,
- succession, and positive laws, forms the strongest title to sovereignty,
- and is justly regarded as sacred and inviolable. But when these titles
- are mingled and opposed in different degrees, they often occasion
- perplexity; and are less capable of solution from the arguments of
- lawyers and philosophers, than from the swords of the soldiery. Who
- shall tell me, for instance, whether Germanicus, or Drufus, ought to
- have succeeded Tiberius, had he died while they were both alive, without
- naming any of them for his successor? Ought the right of adoption to be
- received as equivalent to that of blood in a nation, where it had the
- same effect in private families, and had already, in two instances,
- taken place in the public? Ought Germanicus to be esteemed the eldest
- son, because he was born before Drufus; or the younger, because he was
- adopted after the birth of his brother? Ought the right of the elder to
- be regarded in a nation, where the eldest brother had no advantage in
- the succession to private families? Ought the Roman empire at that time
- to be esteemed hereditary, because of two examples; or ought it, even
- so early, to be regarded as belonging to the stronger, or the present
- possessor, as being founded on so recent an usurpation? Upon whatever
- principles we may pretend to answer these and such like questions, I
- am afraid we shall never be able to satisfy an impartial enquirer, who
- adopts no party in political controversies, and will be satisfied with
- nothing but sound reason and philosophy.
- But here an English reader will be apt to enquire concerning that famous
- revolution, which has had such a happy influence on our constitution,
- and has been attended with such mighty consequences. We have already
- remarked, that in the case of enormous tyranny and oppression, it is
- lawful to take arms even against supreme power; and that as government
- is a mere human invention for mutual advantage and security, it no
- longer imposes any obligation, either natural or moral, when once it
- ceases to have that tendency. But though this general principle
- be authorized by common sense, and the practice of all ages, it is
- certainly impossible for the laws, or even for philosophy, to establish
- any particular rules, by which we may know when resistance is lawful;
- and decide all controversies, which may arise on that subject. This may
- not only happen with regard to supreme power; but it is possible, even
- in some constitutions, where the legislative authority is not lodged in
- one person, that there may be a magistrate so eminent and powerful, as
- to oblige the laws to keep silence in this particular. Nor would this
- silence be an effect only of their respect, but also of their prudence;
- since it is certain, that in the vast variety of circumstances,
- which occur in all governments, an exercise of power, in so great
- a magistrate, may at one time be beneficial to the public, which at
- another time would be pernicious and tyrannical. But notwithstanding
- this silence of the laws in limited monarchies, it is certain, that the
- people still retain the right of resistance; since it is impossible,
- even in the most despotic governments, to deprive them of it. The same
- necessity of self-preservation, and the same motive of public good,
- give them the same liberty in the one case as in the other. And we may
- farther observe, that in such mixed governments, the cases, wherein
- resistance is lawful, must occur much oftener, and greater indulgence
- be given to the subjects to defend themselves by force of arms, than in
- arbitrary governments. Not only where the chief magistrate enters into
- measures, in themselves, extremely pernicious to the public, but even
- when he would encroach on the other parts of the constitution, and
- extend his power beyond the legal bounds, it is allowable to resist and
- dethrone him; though such resistance and violence may, in the general
- tenor of the laws, be deemed unlawful and rebellious. For besides that
- nothing is more essential to public interest, than the preservation of
- public liberty; it is evident, that if such a mixed government be once
- supposed to be established, every part or member of the constitution
- must have a right of self-defence, and of maintaining its antient bounds
- against the enaoachment of every other authority. As matter would have
- been created in vain, were it deprived of a power of resistance, without
- which no part of it coued preserve a distinct existence, and the whole
- might be crowded up into a single point: So it is a gross absurdity to
- suppose, in any government, a right without a remedy, or allow, that the
- supreme power is shared with the people, without allowing, that it is
- lawful for them to defend their share against every invader. Those,
- therefore, who would seem to respect our free government, and yet deny
- the right of resistance, have renounced all pretensions to common sense,
- and do not merit a serious answer.
- It does not belong to my present purpose to shew, that these general
- principles are applicable to the late revolution; and that all the
- rights and privileges, which ought to be sacred to a free nation, were
- at that time threatened with the utmost danger. I am better pleased to
- leave this controverted subject, if it really admits of controversy;
- and to indulge myself in some philosophical reflections, which naturally
- arise from that important event.
- First, We may observe, that should the lords and commons in our
- constitution, without any reason from public interest, either depose the
- king in being, or after his death exclude the prince, who, by laws and
- settled custom, ought to succeed, no one would esteem their proceedings
- legal, or think themselves bound to comply with them. But should the
- king, by his unjust practices, or his attempts for a tyrannical and
- despotic power, justly forfeit his legal, it then not only becomes
- morally lawful and suitable to the nature of political society to
- dethrone him; but what is more, we are apt likewise to think, that the
- remaining members of the constitution acquire a right of excluding his
- next heir, and of chusing whom they please for his successor. This is
- founded on a very singular quality of our thought and imagination. When
- a king forfeits his authority, his heir ought naturally to remain in the
- same situation, as if the king were removed by death; unless by mixing
- himself in the tyranny, he forfeit it for himself. But though this
- may seem reasonable, we easily comply with the contrary opinion. The
- deposition of a king, in such a government as ours, is certainly an act
- beyond all common authority, and an illegal assuming a power for public
- good, which, in the ordinary course of government, can belong to no
- member of the constitution. When the public good is so great and so
- evident as to justify the action, the commendable use of this licence
- causes us naturally to attribute to the parliament a right of using
- farther licences; and the antient bounds of the laws being once
- transgressed with approbation, we are not apt to be so strict in
- confining ourselves precisely within their limits. The mind naturally
- runs on with any train of action, which it has begun; nor do we commonly
- make any scruple concerning our duty, after the first action of any
- kind, which we perform. Thus at the revolution, no one who thought the
- deposition of the father justifiable, esteemed themselves to be confined
- to his infant son; though had that unhappy monarch died innocent at that
- time, and had his son, by any accident, been conveyed beyond seas, there
- is no doubt but a regency would have been appointed till he should
- come to age, and coued be restored to his dominions. As the slightest
- properties of the imagination have an effect on the judgments of the
- people, it shews the wisdom of the laws and of the parliament to take
- advantage of such properties, and to chuse the magistrates either in
- or out of a line, according as the vulgar will most naturally attribute
- authority and right to them.
- Secondly, Though the accession of the Prince of Orange to the throne
- might at first give occasion to many disputes, and his title be
- contested, it ought not now to appear doubtful, but must have acquired
- a sufficient authority from those three princes, who have succeeded him
- upon the same title. Nothing is more usual, though nothing may, at first
- sight, appear more unreasonable, than this way of thinking. Princes
- often seem to acquire a right from their successors, as well as from
- their ancestors; and a king, who during his life-time might justly be
- deemed an usurper, will be regarded by posterity as a lawful prince,
- because he has had the good fortune to settle his family on the throne,
- and entirely change the antient form of government. Julius Caesar is
- regarded as the first Roman emperor; while Sylla and Marius, whose
- titles were really the same as his, are treated as tyrants and usurpers.
- Time and custom give authority to all forms of government, and all
- successions of princes; and that power, which at first was founded only
- on injustice and violence, becomes in time legal and obligatory.
- Nor does the mind rest there; but returning back upon its footsteps,
- transfers to their predecessors and ancestors that right, which it
- naturally ascribes to the posterity, as being related together, and
- united in the imagination. The present king of France makes Hugh Capet
- a more lawful prince than Cromwell; as the established liberty of the
- Dutch is no inconsiderable apology for their obstinate resistance to
- Philip the second.
- SECT. XI OF THE LAWS OF NATIONS
- When civil government has been established over the greatest part of
- mankind, and different societies have been formed contiguous to each
- other, there arises a new set of duties among the neighbouring states,
- suitable to the nature of that commerce, which they carry on with each
- other. Political writers tell us, that in every kind of intercourse,
- a body politic is to be considered as one person; and indeed this
- assertion is so far just, that different nations, as well as private
- persons, require mutual assistance; at the same time that their
- selfishness and ambition are perpetual sources of war and discord. But
- though nations in this particular resemble individuals, yet as they are
- very different in other respects, no wonder they regulate themselves by
- different maxims, and give rise to a new set of rules, which we call the
- laws of nations. Under this head we may comprize the sacredness of the
- persons of ambassadors, the declaration of war, the abstaining from
- poisoned arms, with other duties of that kind, which are evidently
- calculated for the commerce, that is peculiar to different societies.
- But though these rules be super-added to the laws of nature, the former
- do not entirely abolish the latter; and one may safely affirm, that the
- three fundamental rules of justice, the stability of possession, its
- transference by consent, and the performance of promises, are duties
- of princes, as well as of subjects. The same interest produces the same
- effect in both cases. Where possession has no stability, there must be
- perpetual war. Where property is not transferred by consent, there can
- be no commerce. Where promises are not observed, there can be no leagues
- nor alliances. The advantages, therefore, of peace, commerce, and
- mutual succour, make us extend to different kingdoms the same notions of
- justice, which take place among individuals.
- There is a maxim very current in the world, which few politicians are
- willing to avow, but which has been authorized by the practice of all
- ages, that there is a system of morals cakulated for princes, much more
- free than that which ought to govern private parsons. It is evident
- this is not to be understood of the lesser extent of public duties and
- obligations; nor will any one be so extravagant as to assert, that
- the most solemn treaties ought to have no force among princes. For as
- princes do actually form treaties among themselves, they must propose
- some advantage from the execution of them; and the prospect of such
- advantage for the future must engage them to perform their part, and
- must establish that law of nature. The meaning, therefore, of this
- political maxim is, that though the morality of princes has the same
- extent, yet it has not the same force as that of private persons, and
- may lawfully be trangressed from a more trivial motive. However shocking
- such a proposition may appear to certain philosophers, it will be easy
- to defend it upon those principles, by which we have accounted for the
- origin of justice and equity.
- When men have found by experience, that it is impossible to subsist
- without society, and that it is impossible to maintain society, while
- they give free course to their appetites; so urgent an interest quickly
- restrains their actions, and imposes an obligation to observe those
- rules, which we call the laws of justice. This obligation of interest
- rests nor here; but by the necessary course of the passions and
- sentiments, gives rise to the moral obligation of duty; while we approve
- of such actions as tend to the peace of society, and disapprove of such
- as tend to its disturbance. The same natural obligation of interest
- takes place among independent kingdoms, and gives rise to the same
- morality; so that no one of ever so corrupt morals will approve of a
- prince, who voluntarily, and of his own accord, breaks his word,
- or violates any treaty. But here we may observe, that though the
- intercourse of different states be advantageous, and even sometimes
- necessary, yet it is nor so necessary nor advantageous as that among
- individuals, without which it is utterly impossible for human nature
- ever to subsist. Since, therefore, the natural obligation to justice,
- among different states, is not so strong as among individuals, the moral
- obligation, which arises from it, must partake of its weakness; and we
- must necessarily give a greater indulgence to a prince or minister, who
- deceives another; than to a private gentleman, who breaks his word of
- honour.
- Should it be asked, what proportion these two species of morality bear
- to each other? I would answer, that this is a question, to which we can
- never give any precise answer; nor is it possible to reduce to numbers
- the proportion, which we ought to fix betwixt them. One may safely
- affirm, that this proportion finds itself, without any art or study
- of men; as we may observe on many other occasions. The practice of the
- world goes farther in teaching us the degrees of our duty, than the most
- subtile philosophy, which was ever yet invented. And this may serve as a
- convincing proof, that all men have an implicit notion of the foundation
- of those moral rules concerning natural and civil justice, and are
- sensible, that they arise merely from human conventions, and from the
- interest, which we have in the preservation of peace and order.
- For otherwise the diminution of the interest would never produce
- a relaxation of the morality, and reconcile us more easily to any
- transgression of justice among princes and republics, than in the
- private commerce of one subject with another.
- SECT. XII OF CHASTITY AND MODESTY
- If any difficulty attend this system concerning the laws of nature and
- nations, it will be with regard to the universal approbation or blame,
- which follows their observance or transgression, and which some may not
- think sufficiently explained from the general interests of society.
- To remove, as far as possible, all scruples of this kind, I shall here
- consider another set of duties, viz, the modesty and chastity which
- belong to the fair sex: And I doubt not but these virtues will be
- found to be still more conspicuous instances of the operation of those
- principles, which I have insisted on.
- There are some philosophers, who attack the female virtues with great
- vehemence, and fancy they have gone very far in detecting popular
- errors, when they can show, that there is no foundation in nature for
- all that exterior modesty, which we require in the expressions, and
- dress, and behaviour of the fair sex. I believe I may spare myself the
- trouble of insisting on so obvious a subject, and may proceed, without
- farther preparation, to examine after what manner such notions arise
- from education, from the voluntary conventions of men, and from the
- interest of society.
- Whoever considers the length and feebleness of human infancy, with the
- concern which both sexes naturally have for their offspring, will
- easily perceive, that there must be an union of male and female for
- the education of the young, and that this union must be of considerable
- duration. But in order to induce the men to impose on themselves this
- restraint, and undergo chearfully all the fatigues and expences, to
- which it subjects them, they must believe, that the children are their
- own, and that their natural instinct is not directed to a wrong object,
- when they give a loose to love and tenderness. Now if we examine the
- structure of the human body, we shall find, that this security is very
- difficult to be attained on our part; and that since, in the copulation
- of the sexes, the principle of generation goes from the man to the
- woman, an error may easily take place on the side of the former, though
- it be utterly impossible with regard to the latter. From this trivial
- and anatomical observation is derived that vast difference betwixt the
- education and duties of the two sexes.
- Were a philosopher to examine the matter a priori, he would reason after
- the following manner. Men are induced to labour for the maintenance
- and education of their children, by the persuasion that they are really
- their own; and therefore it is reasonable, and even necessary, to give
- them some security in this particular. This security cannot consist
- entirely in the imposing of severe punishments on any transgressions
- of conjugal fidelity on the part of the wife; since these public
- punishments cannot be inflicted without legal proof, which it is
- difficult to meet with in this subject. What restraint, therefore, shall
- we impose on women, in order to counter-balance so strong a temptation
- as they have to infidelity? There seems to be no restraint possible, but
- in the punishment of bad fame or reputation; a punishment, which has a
- mighty influence on the human mind, and at the same time is inflicted by
- the world upon surmizes, and conjectures, and proofs, that would never
- be received in any court of judicature. In order, therefore, to impose
- a due restraint on the female sex, we must attach a peculiar degree of
- shame to their infidelity, above what arises merely from its injustice,
- and must bestow proportionable praises on their chastity.
- But though this be a very strong motive to fidelity, our philosopher
- would quickly discover, that it would not alone be sufficient to that
- purpose. All human creatures, especially of the female sex, are apt
- to over-look remote motives in favour of any present temptation:
- The temptation is here the strongest imaginable: Its approaches are
- insensible and seducing: And a woman easily finds, or flatters herself
- she shall find, certain means of securing her reputation, and preventing
- all the pernicious consequences of her pleasures. It is necessary,
- therefore, that, beside the infamy attending such licences, there should
- be some preceding backwardness or dread, which may prevent their first
- approaches, and may give the female sex a repugnance to all expressions,
- and postures, and liberties, that have an immediate relation to that
- enjoyment.
- Such would be the reasonings of our speculative philosopher: But I am
- persuaded, that if he had not a perfect knowledge of human nature, he
- would be apt to regard them as mere chimerical speculations, and would
- consider the infamy attending infidelity, and backwardness to all its
- approaches, as principles that were rather to be wished than hoped for
- in the world. For what means, would he say, of persuading mankind, that
- the transgressions of conjugal duty are more infamous than any other
- kind of injustice, when it is evident they are more excusable, upon
- account of the greatness of the temptation? And what possibility of
- giving a backwardness to the approaches of a pleasure, to which nature
- has inspired so strong a propensity; and a propensity that it is
- absolutely necessary in the end to comply with, for the support of the
- species?
- But speculative reasonings, which cost so much pains to philosophers,
- are often formed by the world naturally, and without reflection: As
- difficulties, which seem unsurmountable in theory, are easily got over
- in practice. Those, who have an interest in the fidelity of women,
- naturally disapprove of their infidelity, and all the approaches to
- it. Those, who have no interest, are carried along with the stream.
- Education takes possession of the ductile minds of the fair sex in their
- infancy. And when a general rule of this kind is once established, men
- are apt to extend it beyond those principles, from which it first arose.
- Thus batchelors, however debauched, cannot chuse but be shocked with any
- instance of lewdness or impudence in women. And though all these maxims
- have a plain reference to generation, yet women past child-bearing have
- no more privilege in this respect, than those who are in the flower of
- their youth and beauty. Men have undoubtedly an implicit notion, that
- all those ideas of modesty and decency have a regard to generation;
- since they impose not the same laws, with the same force, on the male
- sex, where that reason takes nor place. The exception is there obvious
- and extensive, and founded on a remarkable difference, which produces
- a clear separation and disjunction of ideas. But as the case is not the
- same with regard to the different ages of women, for this reason, though
- men know, that these notions are founded on the public interest, yet
- the general rule carries us beyond the original principle, and makes us
- extend the notions of modesty over the whole sex, from their earliest
- infancy to their extremest old-age and infirmity.
- Courage, which is the point of honour among men, derives its merit, in
- a great measure, from artifice, as well as the chastity of women; though
- it has also some foundation in nature, as we shall see afterwards.
- As to the obligations which the male sex lie under, with regard to
- chastity, we may observe, that according to the general notions of the
- world, they bear nearly the same proportion to the obligations of women,
- as the obligations of the law of nations do to those of the law of
- nature. It is contrary to the interest of civil society, that men
- should have an entire liberty of indulging their appetites in venereal
- enjoyment: But as this interest is weaker than in the case of the female
- sex, the moral obligation, arising from it, must be proportionably
- weaker. And to prove this we need only appeal to the practice and
- sentiments of all nations and ages.
- PART III OF THE OTHER VIRTUES AND VICES
- SECT. I OF THE ORIGIN OF THE NATURAL VIRTUES AND VICES
- We come now to the examination of such virtues and vices as are entirely
- natural, and have no dependance on the artifice and contrivance of men.
- The examination of these will conclude this system of morals.
- The chief spring or actuating principle of the human mind is pleasure or
- pain; and when these sensations are removed, both from our thought and
- feeling, we are, in a great measure, incapable of passion or action, of
- desire or volition. The most immediate effects of pleasure and pain are
- the propense and averse motions of the mind; which are diversified
- into volition, into desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear,
- according as the pleasure or pain changes its situation, and becomes
- probable or improbable, certain or uncertain, or is considered as out of
- our power for the present moment. But when along with this, the objects,
- that cause pleasure or pain, acquire a relation to ourselves or others;
- they still continue to excite desire and aversion, grief and joy: But
- cause, at the same time, the indirect passions of pride or humility,
- love or hatred, which in this case have a double relation of impressions
- and ideas to the pain or pleasure.
- We have already observed, that moral distinctions depend entirely on
- certain peculiar sentiments of pain and pleasure, and that whatever
- mental quality in ourselves or others gives us a satisfaction, by the
- survey or reflection, is of course virtuous; as every thing of this
- nature, that gives uneasiness, is vicious. Now since every quality in
- ourselves or others, which gives pleasure, always causes pride or love;
- as every one, that produces uneasiness, excites humility or hatred: It
- follows, that these two particulars are to be considered as equivalent,
- with regard to our mental qualities, virtue and the power of producing
- love or pride, vice and the power of producing humility or hatred. In
- every case, therefore, we must judge of the one by the other; and may
- pronounce any quality of the mind virtuous, which causes love or pride;
- and any one vicious, which causes hatred or humility.
- If any action be either virtuous or vicious, it is only as a sign of
- some quality or character. It must depend upon durable principles of the
- mind, which extend over the whole conduct, and enter into the personal
- character. Actions themselves, not proceeding from any constant
- principle, have no influence on love or hatred, pride or humility; and
- consequently are never considered in morality.
- This reflection is self-evident, and deserves to be attended to, as
- being of the utmost importance in the present subject. We are never to
- consider any single action in our enquiries concerning the origin
- of morals; but only the quality or character from which the action
- proceeded. These alone are durable enough to affect our sentiments
- concerning the person. Actions are, indeed, better indications of a
- character than words, or even wishes and sentiments; but it is only so
- far as they are such indications, that they are attended with love or
- hatred, praise or blame.
- To discover the true origin of morals, and of that love or hatred, which
- arises from mental qualities, we must take the matter pretty deep, and
- compare some principles, which have been already examined and explained.
- We may begin with considering a-new the nature and force of sympathy.
- The minds of all men are similar in their feelings and operations; nor
- can any one be actuated by any affection, of which all others are not,
- in some degree, susceptible. As in strings equally wound up, the motion
- of one communicates itself to the rest; so all the affections readily
- pass from one person to another, and beget correspondent movements in
- every human creature. When I see the effects of passion in the voice and
- gesture of any person, my mind immediately passes from these effects
- to their causes, and forms such a lively idea of the passion, as is
- presently converted into the passion itself. In like manner, when I
- perceive the causes of any emotion, my mind is conveyed to the effects,
- and is actuated with a like emotion. Were I present at any of the more
- terrible operations of surgery, it is certain, that even before it
- begun, the preparation of the instruments, the laying of the bandages
- in order, the heating of the irons, with all the signs of anxiety and
- concern in the patient and assistants, would have a great effect upon my
- mind, and excite the strongest sentiments of pity and terror. No
- passion of another discovers itself immediately to the mind. We are only
- sensible of its causes or effects. From these we infer the passion: And
- consequently these give rise to our sympathy.
- Our sense of beauty depends very much on this principle; and where any
- object has atendency to produce pleasure in its possessor, it is always
- regarded as beautiful; as every object, that has a tendency to produce
- pain, is disagreeable and deformed. Thus the conveniency of a house, the
- fertility of a field, the strength of a horse, the capacity, security,
- and swift-sailing of a vessel, form the principal beauty of these
- several objects. Here the object, which is denominated beautiful,
- pleases only by its tendency to produce a certain effect. That effect
- is the pleasure or advantage of some other person. Now the pleasure of
- a stranger, for whom we have no friendship, pleases us only by sympathy.
- To this principle, therefore, is owing the beauty, which we find in
- every thing that is useful. How considerable a part this is of beauty
- can easily appear upon reflection. Wherever an object has a tendency
- to produce pleasure in the possessor, or in other words, is the proper
- cause of pleasure, it is sure to please the spectator, by a delicate
- sympathy with the possessor. Most of the works of art are esteemed
- beautiful, in proportion to their fitness for the use of man, and even
- many of the productions of nature derive their beauty from that source.
- Handsome and beautiful, on most occasions, is nor an absolute but a
- relative quality, and pleases us by nothing but its tendency to produce
- an end that is agreeable.
- [Footnote 25 Decentior equus cujus astricta sunt ilia; sed
- idem velocior. Pulcher aspectu sit athieta, cujus lacertos
- exercitatio expressit; idem certamini paratior. Nunquam vero
- species ab utilitate dividitur. Sed hoc quidem discernere,
- modici judicii est. Quinct. lib. 8. (A horse with narrow
- flanks looks more comely; It also moves faster. An athlete
- whose muscles have been developed by training presents a
- handsome appearance; he is also better prepared for the
- contest. Attractive appearance is invariably associated with
- efficient functioning. Yet it takes no outstanding powers of
- judgement to wake this distinction.)]
- The same principle produces, in many instances, our sentiments of
- morals, as well as those of beauty. No virtue is more esteemed than
- justice, and no vice more detested than injustice; nor are there any
- qualities, which go farther to the fixing the character, either as
- amiable or odious. Now justice is a moral virtue, merely because it has
- that tendency to the good of mankind; and, indeed, is nothing but
- an artificial invention to that purpose. The same may be said of
- allegiance, of the laws of nations, of modesty, and of good-manners. All
- these are mere human contrivances for the interest of society. And since
- there is a very strong sentiment of morals, which in all nations, and
- all ages, has attended them, we must allow, that the reflecting on the
- tendency of characters and mental qualities, is sufficient to give us
- the sentiments of approbation and blame. Now as the means to an end
- can only be agreeable, where the end is agreeable; and as the good
- of society, where our own interest is not concerned, or that of our
- friends, pleases only by sympathy: It follows, that sympathy is the
- source of the esteem, which we pay to all the artificial virtues.
- Thus it appears, that sympathy is a very powerful principle in human
- nature, that it has a great influence on our taste of beauty, and that
- it produces our sentiment of morals in all the artificial virtues. From
- thence we may presume, that it also gives rise to many of the other
- virtues; and that qualities acquire our approbation, because of
- their tendency to the good of mankind. This presumption must become a
- certainty, when we find that most of those qualities, which we naturally
- approve of, have actually that tendency, and render a man a proper
- member of society: While the qualities, which we naturally disapprove
- of, have a contrary tendency, and render any intercourse with the person
- dangerous or disagreeable. For having found, that such tendencies have
- force enough to produce the strongest sentiment of morals, we can never
- reasonably, in these cases, look for any other cause of approbation
- or blame; it being an inviolable maxim in philosophy, that where any
- particular cause is sufficient for an effect, we ought to rest satisfied
- with it, and ought not to multiply causes without necessity. We have
- happily attained experiments in the artificial virtues, where the
- tendency of qualities to the good of society, is the sole cause of
- our approbation, without any suspicion of the concurrence of another
- principle. From thence we learn the force of that principle. And where
- that principle may take place, and the quality approved of is really
- beneficial to society, a true philosopher will never require any other
- principle to account for the strongest approbation and esteem.
- That many of the natural virtues have this tendency to the good
- of society, no one can doubt of. Meekness, beneficence, charity,
- generosity, clemency, moderation, equity bear the greatest figure among
- the moral qualities, and are commonly denominated the social virtues, to
- mark their tendency to the good of society. This goes so far, that some
- philosophers have represented all moral distinctions as the effect of
- artifice and education, when skilful politicians endeavoured to restrain
- the turbulent passions of men, and make them operate to the public
- good, by the notions of honour and shame. This system, however, is nor
- consistent with experience. For, first, there are other virtues and
- vices beside those which have this tendency to the public advantage
- and loss. Secondly, had not men a natural sentiment of approbation and
- blame, it coued never be excited by politicians; nor would the
- words laudable and praise-worthy, blameable and odious be any more
- intelligible, than if they were a language perfectly known to us, as we
- have already observed. But though this system be erroneous, it may teach
- us, that moral distinctions arise, in a great measure, from the tendency
- of qualities and characters to the interests of society, and that it is
- our concern for that interest, which makes us approve or disapprove
- of them. Now we have no such extensive concern for society but from
- sympathy; and consequently it is that principle, which takes us so far
- out of ourselves, as to give us the same pleasure or uneasiness in the
- characters of others, as if they had a tendency to our own advantage or
- loss.
- The only difference betwixt the natural virtues and justice lies in
- this, that the good, which results from the former, arises from every
- single act, and is the object of some natural passion: Whereas a single
- act of justice, considered in itself, may often be contrary to the
- public good; and it is only the concurrence of mankind, in a general
- scheme or system of action, which is advantageous. When I relieve
- persons in distress, my natural humanity is my motive; and so far as
- my succour extends, so far have I promoted the happiness of my
- fellow-creatures. But if we examine all the questions, that come before
- any tribunal of justice, we shall find, that, considering each case
- apart, it would as often be an instance of humanity to decide contrary
- to the laws of justice as conformable them. Judges take from a poor
- man to give to a rich; they bestow on the dissolute the labour of the
- industrious; and put into the hands of the vicious the means of harming
- both themselves and others. The whole scheme, however, of law and
- justice is advantageous to the society; and it was with a view to this
- advantage, that men, by their voluntary conventions, established it.
- After it is once established by these conventions, it is naturally
- attended with a strong sentiment of morals; which can proceed from
- nothing but our sympathy with the interests of society. We need no other
- explication of that esteem, which attends such of the natural virtues,
- as have a tendency to the public good. I must farther add, that there
- are several circumstances, which render this hypothesis much more
- probable with regard to the natural than the artificial virtues. It is
- certain that the imagination is more affected by what is particular,
- than by what is general; and that the sentiments are always moved
- with difficulty, where their objects are, in any degree, loose and
- undetermined: Now every particular act of justice is not beneficial to
- society, but the whole scheme or system: And it may not, perhaps, be any
- individual person for whom we are concerned, who receives benefit from
- justice, but the whole society alike. On the contrary, every particular
- act of generosity, or relief of the industrious and indigent, is
- beneficial; and is beneficial to a particular person, who is not
- undeserving of it. It is more natural, therefore, to think, that the
- tendencies of the latter virtue will affect our sentiments, and command
- our approbation, than those of the former; and therefore, since we find,
- that the approbation of the former arises from their tendencies, we may
- ascribe, with better reason, the same cause to the approbation of the
- latter. In any number of similar effects, if a cause can be discovered
- for one, we ought to extend that cause to all the other effects, which
- can be accounted for by it: But much more, if these other effects be
- attended with peculiar circumstances, which facilitate the operation of
- that cause.
- Before I proceed farther, I must observe two remarkable circumstances in
- this affair, which may seem objections to the present system. The first
- may be thus explained. When any quality, or character, has a tendency to
- the good of mankind, we are pleased with it, and approve of it; because
- it presents the lively idea of pleasure; which idea affects us by
- sympathy, and is itself a kind of pleasure. But as this sympathy is very
- variable, it may be thought that our sentiments of morals must admit of
- all the same variations. We sympathize more with persons contiguous to
- us, than with persons remote from us: With our acquaintance, than
- with strangers: With our countrymen, than with foreigners. But
- notwithstanding this variation of our sympathy, we give the same
- approbation to the same moral qualities in China as in England. They
- appear equally virtuous, and recommend themselves equally to the esteem
- of a judicious spectator. The sympathy varies without a variation in our
- esteem. Our esteem, therefore, proceeds not from sympathy.
- To this I answer: The approbation of moral qualities most certainly
- is not derived from reason, or any comparison of ideas; but proceeds
- entirely from a moral taste, and from certain sentiments of pleasure
- or disgust, which arise upon the contemplation and view of particular
- qualities or characters. Now it is evident, that those sentiments,
- whence-ever they are derived, must vary according to the distance or
- contiguity of the objects; nor can I feel the same lively pleasure from
- the virtues of a person, who lived in Greece two thousand years ago,
- that I feel from the virtues of a familiar friend and acquaintance. Yet
- I do not say, that I esteem the one more than the other: And therefore,
- if the variation of the sentiment, without a variation of the esteem,
- be an objection, it must have equal force against every other system, as
- against that of sympathy. But to consider the matter a-right, it has no
- force at all; and it is the easiest matter in the world to account
- for it. Our situation, with regard both to persons and things, is in
- continual fluctuation; and a man, that lies at a distance from us,
- may, in a little time, become a familiar acquaintance. Besides, every
- particular man has a peculiar position with regard to others; and it is
- impossible we coued ever converse together on any reasonable terms, were
- each of us to consider characters and persons, only as they appear
- from his peculiar point of view. In order, therefore, to prevent those
- continual contradictions, and arrive at a more stable judgment of
- things, we fix on some steady and general points of view; and always,
- in our thoughts, place ourselves in them, whatever may be our present
- situation. In like manner, external beauty is determined merely by
- pleasure; and it is evident, a beautiful countenance cannot give so
- much pleasure, when seen at the distance of twenty paces, as when it
- is brought nearer us. We say not, however, that it appears to us less
- beautiful: Because we know what effect it will have in such a position,
- and by that reflection we correct its momentary appearance.
- In general, all sentiments of blame or praise are variable, according
- to our situation of nearness or remoteness, with regard to the person
- blamed or praised, and according to the present disposition of our mind.
- But these variations we regard not in our general decision, but still
- apply the terms expressive of our liking or dislike, in the same manner,
- as if we remained in one point of view. Experience soon teaches us this
- method of correcting our sentiments, or at least, of correcting our
- language, where the sentiments are more stubborn and inalterable. Our
- servant, if diligent and faithful, may excite stronger sentiments of
- love and kindness than Marcus Brutus, as represented in history; but we
- say not upon that account, that the former character is more laudable
- than the latter. We know, that were we to approach equally near to that
- renowned patriot, he would command a much higher degree of affection and
- admiration. Such corrections are common with regard to all the senses;
- and indeed it were impossible we could ever make use of language,
- or communicate our sentiments to one another, did we not correct the
- momentary appearances of things, and overlook our present situation.
- It is therefore from the influence of characters and qualities, upon
- those who have an intercourse with any person, that we blame or praise
- him. We consider not whether the persons, affected by the qualities,
- be our acquaintance or strangers, countrymen or foreigners. Nay, we
- over-look our own interest in those general judgments; and blame not a
- man for opposing us in any of our pretensions, when his own interest
- is particularly concerned. We make allowance for a certain degree of
- selfishness in men; because we know it to be inseparable from human
- nature, and inherent in our frame and constitution. By this reflection
- we correct those sentiments of blame, which so naturally arise upon any
- opposition.
- But however the general principle of our blame or praise may be
- corrected by those other principles, it is certain, they are not
- altogether efficacious, nor do our passions often correspond entirely
- to the present theory. It is seldom men heartily love what lies at
- a distance from them, and what no way redounds to their particular
- benefit; as it is no less rare to meet with persons, who can pardon
- another any opposition he makes to their interest, however justifiable
- that opposition may be by the general rules of morality. Here we are
- contented with saying, that reason requires such an Impartial conduct,
- but that it is seldom we can bring ourselves to it, and that our
- passions do not readily follow the determination of our judgment. This
- language will be easily understood, if we consider what we formerly said
- concerning that reason, which is able to oppose our passion; and which
- we have found to be nothing but a general calm determination of the
- passions, founded on some distant view or reflection. When we form our
- judgments of persons, merely from the tendency of their characters
- to our own benefit, or to that of our friends, we find so many
- contradictions to our sentiments in society and conversation, and such
- an uncertainty from the incessant changes of our situation, that we
- seek some other standard of merit and demerit, which may not admit of so
- great variation. Being thus loosened from our first station, we cannot
- afterwards fix ourselves so commodiously by any means as by a sympathy
- with those, who have any commerce with the person we consider. This is
- far from being as lively as when our own interest is concerned, or that
- of our particular friends; nor has it such an influence on our love
- and hatred: But being equally conformable to our calm and general
- principles, it is said to have an equal authority over our reason, and
- to command our judgment and opinion. We blame equally a bad action,
- which we read of in history, with one performed in our neighbourhood the
- other day: The meaning of which is, that we know from reflection, that
- the former action would excite as strong sentiments of disapprobation as
- the latter, were it placed in the same position.
- I now proceed to the second remarkable circumstance, which I proposed to
- take notice of. Where a person is possessed of a character, that in its
- natural tendency is beneficial to society, we esteem him virtuous, and
- are delighted with the view of his character, even though particular
- accidents prevent its operation, and incapacitate him from being
- serviceable to his friends and country. Virtue in rags is still virtue;
- and the love, which it procures, attends a man into a dungeon or desart,
- where the virtue can no longer be exerted in action, and is lost to all
- the world. Now this may be esteemed an objection to the present system.
- Sympathy interests us in the good of mankind; and if sympathy were the
- source of our esteem for virtue, that sentiment of approbation coued
- only take place, where the virtue actually attained its end, and
- was beneficial to mankind. Where it fails of its end, it is only an
- imperfect means; and therefore can never acquire any merit from that
- end. The goodness of an end can bestow a merit on such means alone as
- are compleat, and actually produce the end.
- To this we may reply, that where any object, in all its parts, is fitted
- to attain any agreeable end, it naturally gives us pleasure, and is
- esteemed beautiful, even though some external circumstances be wanting
- to render it altogether effectual. It is sufficient if every thing be
- compleat in the object itself. A house, that is contrived with great
- judgment for all the commodities of life, pleases us upon that account;
- though perhaps we are sensible, that noone will ever dwell in it. A
- fertile soil, and a happy climate, delight us by a reflection on the
- happiness which they would afford the inhabitants, though at present the
- country be desart and uninhabited. A man, whose limbs and shape promise
- strength and activity, is esteemed handsome, though condemned to
- perpetual imprisonment. The imagination has a set of passions belonging
- to it, upon which our sentiments of beauty much depend. These passions
- are moved by degrees of liveliness and strength, which are inferior to
- belief, and independent of the real existence of their objects. Where a
- character is, in every respect, fitted to be beneficial to society,
- the imagination passes easily from the cause to the effect, without
- considering that there are some circumstances wanting to render the
- cause a complete one. General rules create a species of probability,
- which sometimes influences the judgment, and always the imagination.
- It is true, when the cause is compleat, and a good disposition is
- attended with good fortune, which renders it really beneficial to
- society, it gives a stronger pleasure to the spectator, and is attended
- with a more lively sympathy. We are more affected by it; and yet we do
- not say that it is more virtuous, or that we esteem it more. We know,
- that an alteration of fortune may render the benevolent disposition
- entirely impotent; and therefore we separate, as much as possible, the
- fortune from the disposition. The case is the same, as when we correct
- the different sentiments of virtue, which proceed from its different
- distances from ourselves. The passions do not always follow our
- corrections; but these corrections serve sufficiently to regulate our
- abstract notions, and are alone regarded, when we pronounce in general
- concerning the degrees of vice and virtue.
- It is observed by critics, that all words or sentences, which are
- difficult to the pronunciation, are disagreeable to the ear. There is no
- difference, whether a man hear them pronounced, or read them silently
- to himself. When I run over a book with my eye, I Imagine I hear it all;
- and also, by the force of imagination, enter into the uneasiness, which
- the delivery of it would give the speaker. The uneasiness is not real;
- but as such a composition of words has a natural tendency to produce
- it, this is sufficient to affect the mind with a painful sentiment, and
- render the discourse harsh and disagreeable. It is a similar case, where
- any real quality is, by accidental circumstances, rendered impotent, and
- is deprived of its natural influence on society.
- Upon these principles we may easily remove any contradiction, which may
- appear to be betwixt the extensive sympathy, on which our sentiments
- of virtue depend, and that limited generosity which I have frequently
- observed to be natural to men, and which justice and property suppose,
- according to the precedent reasoning. My sympathy with another may
- give me the sentiment of pain and disapprobation, when any object is
- presented, that has a tendency to give him uneasiness; though I may not
- be willing to sacrifice any thing of my own interest, or cross any of
- my passions, for his satisfaction. A house may displease me by being
- ill-contrived for the convenience of the owner; and yet I may refuse to
- give a shilling towards the rebuilding of it. Sentiments must touch
- the heart, to make them controul our passions: But they need not
- extend beyond the imagination, to make them influence our taste. When
- a building seems clumsy and tottering to the eye, it is ugly and
- disagreeable; though we be fully assured of the solidity of the
- workmanship. It is a kind of fear, which causes this sentiment of
- disapprobation; but the passion is not the same with that which we feel,
- when obliged to stand under a wall, that we really think tottering and
- insecure. The seeming tendencies of objects affect the mind: And the
- emotions they excite are of a like species with those, which proceed
- from the real consequences of objects, but their feeling is different.
- Nay, these emotions are so different in their feeling, that they
- may often be contrary, without destroying each other; as when the
- fortifications of a city belonging to an enemy are esteemed beautiful
- upon account of their strength, though we coued wish that they were
- entirely destroyed. The imagination adheres to the general views of
- things, and distinguishes the feelings they produce, from those which
- arise from our particular and momentary situation.
- If we examine the panegyrics that are commonly made of great men, we
- shall find, that most of the qualities, which are attributed to them,
- may be divided into two kinds, viz. such as make them perform their
- part in society; and such as render them serviceable to themselves, and
- enable them to promote their own interest. Their prudence, temperance,
- frugality, industry, assiduity, enterprize, dexterity, are celebrated,
- as well as their generosity and humanity. If we ever give an indulgence
- to any quality, that disables a man from making a figure in life, it is
- to that of indolence, which is not supposed to deprive one of his parts
- and capacity, but only suspends their exercise; and that without any
- inconvenience to the person himself, since it is, in some measure, from
- his own choice. Yet indolence is always allowed to be a fault, and a
- very great one, if extreme: Nor do a man's friends ever acknowledge him
- to be subject to it, but in order to save his character in more material
- articles. He coued make a figure, say they, if he pleased to give
- application: His understanding is sound, his conception quick, and his
- memory tenacious; but he hates business, and is indifferent about his
- fortune. And this a man sometimes may make even a subject of vanity;
- though with the air of confessing a fault: Because he may think, that
- his incapacity for business implies much more noble qualities; such as
- a philosophical spirit, a fine taste, a delicate wit, or a relish for
- pleasure and society. But take any other case: Suppose a quality, that
- without being an indication of any other good qualities, incapacitates
- a man always for business, and is destructive to his interest; such as
- a blundering understanding, and a wrong judgment of every thing in life;
- inconstancy and irresolution; or a want of address in the management
- of men and business: These are all allowed to be imperfections in a
- character; and many men would rather acknowledge the greatest crimes,
- than have it suspected, that they are, in any degree, subject to them.
- It is very happy, in our philosophical researches, when we find the
- same phaenomenon diversified by a variety of circumstances; and by
- discovering what is common among them, can the better assure ourselves
- of the truth of any hypothesis we may make use of to explain it. Were
- nothing esteemed virtue but what were beneficial to society, I am
- persuaded, that the foregoing explication of the moral sense ought still
- to be received, and that upon sufficient evidence: But this evidence
- must grow upon us, when we find other kinds of virtue, which will not
- admit of any explication except from that hypothesis. Here is a man,
- who is not remarkably defective in his social qualities; but what
- principally recommends him is his dexterity in business, by which he
- has extricated himself from the greatest difficulties, and conducted the
- most delicate affairs with a singular address and prudence. I find an
- esteem for him immediately to arise in me: His company is a satisfaction
- to me; and before I have any farther acquaintance with him, I would
- rather do him a service than another, whose character is in every other
- respect equal, but is deficient in that particular. In this case, the
- qualities that please me are all considered as useful to the person, and
- as having a tendency to promote his interest and satisfaction. They are
- only regarded as means to an end, and please me in proportion to their
- fitness for that end. The end, therefore, must be agreeable to me. But
- what makes the end agreeable? The person is a stranger: I am no way
- interested in him, nor lie under any obligation to him: His happiness
- concerns not me, farther than the happiness of every human, and indeed
- of every sensible creature: That is, it affects me only by sympathy.
- From that principle, whenever I discover his happiness and good, whether
- in its causes or effects, I enter so deeply into it, that it gives me a
- sensible emotion. The appearance of qualities, that have a tendency to
- promote it, have an agreeable effect upon my imagination, and command my
- love and esteem.
- This theory may serve to explain, why the same qualities, in all cases,
- produce both pride and love, humility and hatred; and the same man is
- always virtuous or vicious, accomplished or despicable to others, who is
- so to himself. A person, in whom we discover any passion or habit, which
- originally is only incommodious to himself, becomes always disagreeable
- to us, merely on its account; as on the other hand, one whose character
- is only dangerous and disagreeable to others, can never be satisfied
- with himself, as long as he is sensible of that disadvantage. Nor is
- this observable only with regard to characters and manners, but may
- be remarked even in the most minute circumstances. A violent cough in
- another gives us uneasiness; though in itself it does not in the least
- affect us. A man will be mortified, if you tell him he has a stinking
- breath; though it is evidently no annoyance to himself. Our fancy easily
- changes its situation; and either surveying ourselves as we appear to
- others, or considering others as they feel themselves, we enter, by that
- means, into sentiments, which no way belong to us, and in which nothing
- but sympathy is able to interest us. And this sympathy we sometimes
- carry so far, as even to be displeased with a quality commodious to us,
- merely because it displeases others, and makes us disagreeable in
- their eyes; though perhaps we never can have any interest in rendering
- ourselves agreeable to them.
- There have been many systems of morality advanced by philosophers in
- all ages; but if they are strictly examined, they may be reduced to
- two, which alone merit our attention. Moral good and evil are certainly
- distinguished by our sentiments, not by reason: But these sentiments
- may arise either from the mere species or appearance of characters and
- passions, or from reflections on their tendency to the happiness of
- mankind, and of particular persons. My opinion is, that both these
- causes are intermixed in our judgments of morals; after the same manner
- as they are in our decisions concerning most kinds of external beauty:
- Though I am also of opinion, that reflections on the tendencies of
- actions have by far the greatest influence, and determine all the great
- lines of our duty. There are, however, instances, in cases of less
- moment, wherein this immediate taste or sentiment produces our
- approbation. Wit, and a certain easy and disengaged behaviour, are
- qualities immediately agreeable to others, and command their love
- and esteem. Some of these qualities produce satisfaction in others
- by particular original principles of human nature, which cannot be
- accounted for: Others may be resolved into principles, which are more
- general. This will best appear upon a particular enquiry.
- As some qualities acquire their merit from their being immediately
- agreeable to others, without any tendency to public interest; so some
- are denominated virtuous from their being immediately agreeable to the
- person himself, who possesses them. Each of the passions and operations
- of the mind has a particular feeling, which must be either agreeable or
- disagreeable. The first is virtuous, the second vicious. This particular
- feeling constitutes the very nature of the passion; and therefore needs
- not be accounted for.
- But however directly the distinction of vice and virtue may seem to flow
- from the immediate pleasure or uneasiness, which particular qualities
- cause to ourselves or others; it is easy to observe, that it has also a
- considerable dependence on the principle of sympathy so often insisted
- on. We approve of a person, who is possessed of qualities immediately
- agreeable to those, with whom he has any commerce; though perhaps we
- ourselves never reaped any pleasure from them. We also approve of
- one, who is possessed of qualities, that are immediately agreeable to
- himself; though they be of no service to any mortal. To account for this
- we must have recourse to the foregoing principles.
- Thus, to take a general review of the present hypothesis: Every quality
- of the mind is denominated virtuous, which gives pleasure by the mere
- survey; as every quality, which produces pain, is called vicious. This
- pleasure and this pain may arise from four different sources. For we
- reap a pleasure from the view of a character, which is naturally fitted
- to be useful to others, or to the person himself, or which is agreeable
- to others, or to the person himself. One may, perhaps, be surprized.
- that amidst all these interests and pleasures, we should forget our own,
- which touch us so nearly on every other occasion. But we shall easily
- satisfy ourselves on this head, when we consider, that every particular
- person s pleasure and interest being different, it is impossible men
- coued ever agree in their sentiments and judgments, unless they chose
- some common point of view, from which they might survey their object,
- and which might cause it to appear the same to all of them. Now in
- judging of characters, the only interest or pleasure, which appears the
- same to every spectator, is that of the person himself, whose character
- is examined; or that of persons, who have a connexion with him. And
- though such interests and pleasures touch us more faintly than our own,
- yet being more constant and universal, they counter-ballance the latter
- even in practice, and are alone admitted in speculation as the standard
- of virtue and morality. They alone produce that particular feeling or
- sentiment, on which moral distinctions depend.
- As to the good or ill desert of virtue or vice, it is an evident
- consequence of the sentiments of pleasure or uneasiness. These
- sentiments produce love or hatred; and love or hatred, by the original
- constitution of human passion, is attended with benevolence or anger;
- that is, with a desire of making happy the person we love, and miserable
- the person we hate. We have treated of this more fully on another
- occasion.
- SECT. II OF GREATNESS OF MIND
- It may now be proper to illustrate this general system of morals, by
- applying it to particular instances of virtue and vice, and shewing how
- their merit or demerit arises from the four sources here explained. We
- shall begin with examining the passions of pride and humility, and
- shall consider the vice or virtue that lies in their excesses or just
- proportion. An excessive pride or overweaning conceit of ourselves is
- always esteemed vicious, and is universally hated; as modesty, or a just
- sense of our weakness, is esteemed virtuous, and procures the good-will
- of every-one. Of the four sources of moral distinctions, this is to
- be ascribed to the third; viz, the immediate agreeableness and
- disagreeableness of a quality to others, without any reflections on the
- tendency of that quality.
- In order to prove this, we must have recourse to two principles,
- which are very conspicuous in human nature. The first of these is the
- sympathy, and communication of sentiments and passions above-mentioned.
- So close and intimate is the correspondence of human souls, that
- no sooner any person approaches me, than he diffuses on me all his
- opinions, and draws along my judgment in a greater or lesser degree.
- And though, on many occasions, my sympathy with him goes not so far as
- entirely to change my sentiments, and way of thinking; yet it seldom
- is so weak as not to disturb the easy course of my thought, and give an
- authority to that opinion, which is recommended to me by his assent
- and approbation. Nor is it any way material upon what subject he and I
- employ our thoughts. Whether we judge of an indifferent person, or of my
- own character, my sympathy gives equal force to his decision: And even
- his sentiments of his own merit make me consider him in the same light,
- in which he regards himself.
- This principle of sympathy is of so powerful and insinuating a nature,
- that it enters into most of our sentiments and passions, and often takes
- place under the appearance of its contrary. For it is remarkable, that
- when a person opposes me in any thing, which I am strongly bent upon,
- and rouzes up my passion by contradiction, I have always a degree of
- sympathy with him, nor does my commotion proceed from any other origin.
- We may here observe an evident conflict or rencounter of opposite
- principles and passions. On the one side there is that passion or
- sentiment, which is natural to me; and it is observable, that the
- stronger this passion is, the greater is the commotion. There must also
- be some passion or sentiment on the other side; and this passion can
- proceed from nothing but sympathy. The sentiments of others can never
- affect us, but by becoming, in some measure, our own; in which case they
- operate upon us, by opposing and encreasing our passions, in the very
- same manner, as if they had been originally derived from our own temper
- and disposition. While they remain concealed in the minds of others,
- they can never have an influence upon us: And even when they are known,
- if they went no farther than the imagination, or conception; that
- faculty is so accustomed to objects of every different kind, that a mere
- idea, though contrary to our sentiments and inclinations, would never
- alone be able to affect us.
- The second principle I shall take notice of is that of comparison, or
- the variation of our judgments concerning ob jects, according to the
- proportion they bear to those with which we compare them. We judge more,
- of objects by comparison, than by their intrinsic worth and value; and
- regard every thing as mean, when set in opposition to what is superior
- of the same kind. But no comparison is more obvious than that with
- ourselves; and hence it is that on all occasions it takes place, and
- mixes with most of our passions. This kind of comparison is directly
- contrary to sympathy in its operation, as we have observed in treating
- of com passion and malice. [Book II. Part II. Sect. VIII.] IN ALL KINDS
- OF COMPARISON AN OBJECT MAKES US ALWAYS RECEIVE FROM ANOTHER, TO WHICH
- IT IS COMPARED, A SENSATION CONTRARY TO WHAT ARISES FROM ITSELF IN ITS
- DIRECT AND IMMEDIATE SURVEY. THE DIRECT SURVEY OF ANOTHER'S PLEASURE
- NATURALLY GIVES US PLEASURE; AND THEREFORE PRODUCES PAIN, WHEN COMPARed
- WITH OUR OWN. HIS PAIN, CONSIDERED IN ITSELF, IS PAIN FUL; BUT AUGMENTS
- THE IDEA OF OUR OWN HAPPINESS, AND GIVES US PLEASURE.
- Since then those principles of sympathy, and a comparison with
- ourselves, are directly contrary, it may be worth while to consider,
- what general rules can be formed, beside the particular temper of the
- person, for the prevalence of the one or the other. Suppose I am now
- in safety at land, and would willingly reap some pleasure from this
- consideration: I must think on the miserable condition of those who are
- at sea in a storm, and must endeavour to render this idea as strong
- and lively as possible, in order to make me more sensible of my own
- happiness. But whatever pains I may take, the comparison will never have
- an equal efficacy, as if I were really on the shore [Footnote 26], and
- saw a ship at a distance tossed by a tempest, and in danger every moment
- of perishing on a rock or sand-bank. But suppose this idea to become
- still more lively. Suppose the ship to be driven so near me, that I can
- perceive distinctly the horror, painted on the countenance of the seamen
- and passengers, hear their lamentable cries, see the dearest friends
- give their last adieu, or embrace with a resolution to perish in each
- others arms: No man has so savage a heart as to reap any pleasure from
- such a spectacle, or withstand the motions of the tenderest compassion
- and sympathy. It is evident, therefore, there is a medium in this case;
- and that if the idea be too feint, it has no influence by comparison;
- and on the other hand, if it be too strong, it operates on us entirely
- by sympathy, which is the contrary to comparison. Sympathy being the
- conversion of an idea into an impression, demands a greater force and
- vivacity in the idea than is requisite to comparison.
- [Footnote 26. Suave mari magno turbantibus aequora ventis E
- terra magnum alterius spectare laborem; Non quia vexari
- quenquam eat jucunda voluptas, Sed quibus ipse malls caress
- qula cernere sauv' est. LUCRET.
- (There is something pleasant in watching, from dry land, the
- great difficulties another man is undergoing out on the high
- sea, with the winds lashing the waters. This is not because
- one derives delight from any man's distress, but because it
- is pleasurable to perceive from what troubles one is oneself
- free.)]
- All this is easily applied to the present subject. We sink very much in
- our own eyes, when in the presence of a great man, or one of a superior
- genius; and this humility makes a considerable ingredient in that
- respect, which we pay our superiors, according to our foregoing
- reasonings on that passion [Book II. Part II. Sect. X.]. Sometimes even
- envy and hatred arise from the comparison; but in the greatest part of
- men, it rests at respect and esteem. As sympathy has such a powerful
- influence on the human mind, it causes pride to have, in some measure,
- the same effect as merit; and by making us enter into those elevated
- sentiments, which the proud man entertains of himself, presents that
- comparison, which is so mortifying and disagreeable. Our judgment
- does not entirely accompany him in the flattering conceit, in which
- he pleases himself; but still is so shaken as to receive the idea it
- presents, and to give it an influence above the loose conceptions of
- the imagination. A man, who, in an idle humour, would form a notion of a
- person of a merit very much superior to his own, would not be mortified
- by that fiction: But when a man, whom we are really persuaded to be
- of inferior merit, is presented to us; if we observe in him any
- extraordinary degree of pride and self-conceit; the firm persuasion he
- has of his own merit, takes hold of the imagination, and diminishes us
- in our own eyes, in the same manner, as if he were really possessed of
- all the good qualities which he so liberally attributes to himself. Our
- idea is here precisely in that medium, which is requisite to make it
- operate on us by comparison. Were it accompanied with belief, and did
- the person appear to have the same merit, which he assumes to himself,
- it would have a contrary effect, and would operate on us by sympathy.
- The influence of that principle would then be superior to that of
- comparison, contrary to what happens where the person's merit seems
- below his pretensions.
- The necessary consequence of these principles is, that pride, or an
- over-weaning conceit of ourselves, must be vicious; since it
- causes uneasiness in all men, and presents them every moment with a
- disagreeable comparison. It is a trite observation in philosophy, and
- even in common life and conversation, that it is our own pride, which
- makes us so much displeased with the pride of other people; and that
- vanity becomes insupportable to us merely because we are vain. The gay
- naturally associate themselves with the gay, and the amorous with the
- amorous: But the proud never can endure the proud, and rather seek the
- company of those who are of an opposite disposition. As we are, all of
- us, proud in some degree, pride is universally blamed and condemned by
- all mankind; as having a natural tendency to cause uneasiness in others
- by means of comparison. And this effect must follow the more naturally,
- that those, who have an ill-grounded conceit of themselves, are for ever
- making those comparisons, nor have they any other method of supporting
- their vanity. A man of sense and merit is pleased with himself,
- independent of all foreign considerations: But a fool must always find
- some person, that is more foolish, in order to keep himself in good
- humour with his own parts and understanding.
- But though an over-weaning conceit of our own merit be vicious and
- disagreeable, nothing can be more laudable, than to have a value for
- ourselves, where we really have qualities that are valuable. The utility
- and advantage of any quality to ourselves is a source of virtue, as well
- as its agreeableness to others; and it is certain, that nothing is more
- useful to us in the conduct of life, than a due degree of pride, which
- makes us sensible of our own merit, and gives us a confidence and
- assurance in all our projects and enterprizes. Whatever capacity any
- one may be endowed with, it is entirely useless to him, if he be not
- acquainted with it, and form not designs suitable to it. It is requisite
- on all occasions to know our own force; and were it allowable to err on
- either side, it would be more advantageous to over-rate our merit, than
- to form ideas of it, below its just standard. Fortune commonly favours
- the bold and enterprizing; and nothing inspires us with more boldness
- than a good opinion of ourselves.
- Add to this, that though pride, or self-applause, be sometimes
- disagreeable to others, it is always agreeable to ourselves; as on the
- other hand, modesty, though it gives pleasure to every one, who observes
- it, produces often uneasiness in the person endowed with it. Now it has
- been observed, that our own sensations determine the vice and virtue of
- any quality, as well as those sensations, which it may excite in others.
- Thus self-satisfaction and vanity may not only be allowable, but
- requisite in a character. It is, however, certain, that good-breeding
- and decency require that we should avoid all signs and expressions,
- which tend directly to show that passion. We have, all of us, a
- wonderful partiality for ourselves, and were we always to give vent to
- our sentiments in this particular, we should mutually cause the greatest
- indignation in each other, not only by the immediate presence of so
- disagreeable a subject of comparison, but also by the contrariety of
- our judgments. In like manner, therefore, as we establish the laws
- of nature, in order to secure property in society, and prevent the
- opposition of self-interest; we establish the rules of good-breeding, in
- order to prevent the opposition of men's pride, and render conversation
- agreeable and inoffensive. Nothing is more disagreeable than a
- man's over-weaning conceit of himself: Every one almost has a strong
- propensity to this vice: No one can well distinguish in himself betwixt
- the vice and virtue, or be certain, that his esteem of his own merit is
- well-founded: For these reasons, all direct expressions of this passion
- are condemned; nor do we make any exception to this rule in favour of
- men of sense and merit. They are not allowed to do themselves justice
- openly, in words, no more than other people; and even if they show
- a reserve and secret doubt in doing themselves justice in their own
- thoughts, they will be more applauded. That impertinent, and almost
- universal propensity of men, to over-value themselves, has given us such
- a prejudice against self-applause, that we are apt to condemn it, by a
- general rule, wherever we meet with it; and it is with some difficulty
- we give a privilege to men of sense, even in their most secret thoughts.
- At least, it must be owned, that some disguise in this particular is
- absolutely requisite; and that if we harbour pride in our breasts, we
- must carry a fair outside, and have the appearance of modesty and mutual
- deference in all our conduct and behaviour. We must, on every occasion,
- be ready to prefer others to ourselves; to treat them with a kind of
- deference, even though they be our equals; to seem always the lowest
- and least in the company, where we are not very much distinguished above
- them: And if we observe these rules in our conduct, men will have
- more indulgence for our secret sentiments, when we discover them in an
- oblique manner.
- I believe no one, who has any practice of the world, and can penetrate
- into the inward sentiments of men, will assert, that the humility, which
- good-breeding and decency require of us, goes beyond the outside, or
- that a thorough sincerity in this particular is esteemed a real part
- of our duty. On the contrary, we may observe, that a genuine and hearty
- pride, or self-esteem, if well concealed and well founded, is essential
- to the character of a man of honour, and that there is no quality of the
- mind, which is more indispensibly requisite to procure the esteem
- and approbation of mankind. There are certain deferences and mutual
- submissions, which custom requires of the different ranks of men towards
- each other; and whoever exceeds in this particular, if through interest,
- is accused of meanness; if through ignorance, of simplicity. It is
- necessary, therefore, to know our rank and station in the world, whether
- it be fixed by our birth, fortune, employments, talents or reputation.
- It is necessary to feel the sentiment and passion of pride in conformity
- to it, and to regulate our actions accordingly. And should it be said,
- that prudence may suffice to regulate our actions in this particular,
- without any real pride, I would observe, that here the object of
- prudence is to conform our actions to the general usage and custom; and,
- that it is impossible those tacit airs of superiority should ever have
- been established and authorized by custom, unless men were generally
- proud, and unless that passion were generally approved, when
- well-grounded.
- If we pass from common life and conversation to history, this reasoning
- acquires new force, when we observe, that all those great actions and
- sentiments, which have become the admiration of mankind, are founded on
- nothing but pride and self-esteem. Go, says Alexander the Great to his
- soldiers, when they refused to follow him to the Indies, go tell your
- countrymen, that you left Alexander corn pleating the conquest of the
- world. This passage was always particularly admired by the prince of
- Conde, as we learn from St Evremond.
- "ALEXANDER," said that prince, "abandoned by his soldiers, among
- barbarians, not yet fully subdued, felt in himself such a dignity of
- right and of empire, that he coued not believe it possible any one
- coued refuse to obey him. Whether in Europe or in Asia, among Greeks or
- Persians, all was indifferent to him: Wherever he found men, he fancied
- he found subjects."
- In general we may observe, that whatever we call heroic virtue, and
- admire under the character of greatness and elevation of mind, is either
- nothing but a steady and wellestablished pride and self-esteem, or
- partakes largely of that passion. Courage, intrepidity, ambition, love
- of glory, magnanimity, and all the other shining virtues of that kind,
- have plainly a strong mixture of self-esteem in them, and derive a great
- part of their merit from that origin. Accordingly we find, that many
- religious declaimers decry those virtues as purely pagan and natural,
- and represent to us the excellency of the Christian religion, which
- places humility in the rank of virtues, and corrects the judgment of the
- world, and even of philosophers, who so generally admire all the efforts
- of pride and ambition. Whether this virtue of humility has been rightly
- understood, I shall not pretend to determine. I am content with the
- concession, that the world naturally esteems a well-regulated pride,
- which secretly animates our conduct, without breaking out into such
- indecent expressions of vanity, as many offend the vanity of others.
- The merit of pride or self-esteem is derived from two circumstances,
- viz, its utility and its agreeableness to ourselves; by which it
- capacitates us for business, and, at the same time, gives us an
- immediate satisfaction. When it goes beyond its just bounds, it loses
- the first advantage, and even becomes prejudicial; which is the reason
- why we condemn an extravagant pride and ambition, however regulated by
- the decorums of good-breeding and politeness. But as such a passion is
- still agreeable, and conveys an elevated and sublime sensation to the
- person, who is actuated by it, the sympathy with that satisfaction
- diminishes considerably the blame, which naturally attends its dangerous
- influence on his conduct and behaviour. Accordingly we may observe, that
- an excessive courage and magnanimity, especially when it displays itself
- under the frowns of fortune, contributes in a great measure, to
- the character of a hero, and will render a person the admiration of
- posterity; at the same time, that it ruins his affairs, and leads him
- into dangers and difficulties, with which otherwise he would never have
- been acquainted.
- Heroism, or military glory, is much admired by the generality of
- mankind. They consider it as the most sublime kind of merit. Men of
- cool reflection are not so sanguine in their praises of it. The infinite
- confusions and disorder, which it has caused in the world, diminish much
- of its merit in their eyes. When they would oppose the popular notions
- on this head, they always paint out the evils, which this supposed
- virtue has produced in human society; the subversion of empires, the
- devastation of provinces, the sack of cities. As long as these are
- present to us, we are more inclined to hate than admire the ambition
- of heroes. But when we fix our view on the person himself, who is the
- author of all this mischief, there is something so dazzling in his
- character, the mere contemplation of it so elevates the mind, that we
- cannot refuse it our admiration. The pain, which we receive from its
- tendency to the prejudice of society, is over-powered by a stronger and
- more immediate sympathy.
- Thus our explication of the merit or demerit, which attends the
- degrees of pride or self-esteem, may serve as a strong argument for the
- preceding hypothesis, by shewing the effects of those principles
- above explained in all the variations of our judgments concerning that
- passion. Nor will this reasoning be advantageous to us only by shewing,
- that the distinction of vice and virtue arises from the four principles
- of the advantage and of the pleasure of the person himself, and of
- others: But may also afford us a strong proof of some under-parts of
- that hypothesis.
- No one, who duly considers of this matter, will make any scruple of
- allowing, that any piece of in-breeding, or any expression of pride
- and haughtiness, is displeasing to us, merely because it shocks our
- own pride, and leads us by sympathy into a comparison, which causes the
- disagreeable passion of humility. Now as an insolence of this kind
- is blamed even in a person who has always been civil to ourselves in
- particular; nay, in one, whose name is only known to us in history; it
- follows, that our disapprobation proceeds from a sympathy with others,
- and from the reflection, that such a character is highly displeasing
- and odious to every one, who converses or has any intercourse with
- the person possest of it. We sympathize with those people in their
- uneasiness; and as their uneasiness proceeds in part from a sympathy
- with the person who insults them, we may here observe a double rebound
- of the sympathy; which is a principle very similar to what we have
- observed. [Book II. Part II. Sect. V.]
- SECT. III OF GOODNESS AND BENEVOLENCE
- Having thus explained the origin of that praise and approbation, which
- attends every thing we call great in human affections; we now proceed to
- give an account of their goodness, and shew whence its merit is derived.
- When experience has once given us a competent knowledge of human
- affairs, and has taught us the proportion they bear to human passion, we
- perceive, that the generosity of men is very limited, and that it seldom
- extends beyond their friends and family, or, at most, beyond their
- native country. Being thus acquainted with the nature of man, we expect
- not any impossibilities from him; but confine our view to that narrow
- circle, in which any person moves, in order to form a judgment of his
- moral character. When the natural tendency of his passions leads him
- to be serviceable and useful within his sphere, we approve of his
- character, and love his person, by a sympathy with the sentiments of
- those, who have a more particular connexion with him. We are quickly
- obliged to forget our own interest in our judgments of this kind, by
- reason of the perpetual contradictions, we meet with in society and
- conversation, from persons that are not placed in the same situation,
- and have not the same interest with ourselves. The only point of
- view, in which our sentiments concur with those of others, is, when we
- consider the tendency of any passion to the advantage or harm of
- those, who have any immediate connexion or intercourse with the person
- possessed of it. And though this advantage or harm be often very remote
- from ourselves, yet sometimes it is very near us, and interests us
- strongly by sympathy. This concern we readily extend to other cases,
- that are resembling; and when these are very remote, our sympathy
- is proportionably weaker, and our praise or blame fainter and more
- doubtful. The case is here the same as in our judgments concerning
- external bodies. All objects seem to diminish by their distance: But
- though the appearance of objects to our senses be the original standard,
- by which we judge of them, yet we do not say, that they actually
- diminish by the distance; but correcting the appearance by reflection,
- arrive at a more constant and established judgment concerning them.
- In like manner, though sympathy be much fainter than our concern for
- ourselves, and a sympathy with persons remote from us much fainter
- than that with persons near and contiguous; yet we neglect all these
- differences in our calm judgments concerning the characters of
- men. Besides, that we ourselves often change our situation in this
- particular, we every day meet with persons, who are in a different
- situation from ourselves, and who coued never converse with us on any
- reasonable terms, were we to remain constantly in that situation and
- point of view, which is peculiar to us. The intercourse of sentiments,
- therefore, in society and conversation, makes us form some general
- inalterable standard, by which we may approve or disapprove of
- characters and manners. And though the heart does not always take part
- with those general notions, or regulate its love and hatred by them, yet
- are they sufficient for discourse, and serve all our purposes m company,
- in the pulpit, on the theatre, and in the schools.
- From these principles we may easily account for that merit, which
- is commonly ascribed to generosity, humanity, compassion, gratitude,
- friendship, fidelity, zeal, disinterestedness, liberality, and all those
- other qualities, which form the character of good and benevolent. A
- propensity to the tender passions makes a man agreeable and useful
- in all the parts of life; and gives a just direction to all his other
- quailties, which otherwise may become prejudicial to society. Courage
- and ambition, when not regulated by benevolence, are fit only to make
- a tyrant and public robber. It is the same case with judgment and
- capacity, and all the qualities of that kind. They are indifferent in
- themselves to the interests of society, and have a tendency to the
- good or ill of mankind, according as they are directed by these other
- passions.
- As Love is immediately agreeable to the person, who is actuated by it,
- and hatred immediately disagreeable; this may also be a considerable
- reason, why we praise all the passions that partake of the former, and
- blame all those that have any considerable share of the latter. It is
- certain we are infinitely touched with a tender sentiment, as well
- as with a great one. The tears naturally start in our eyes at the
- conception of it; nor can we forbear giving a loose to the same
- tenderness towards the person who exerts it. All this seems to me a
- proof, that our approbation has, in those cases, an origin different
- from the prospect of utility and advantage, either to ourselves or
- others. To which we may add, that men naturally, without reflection,
- approve of that character, which is most like their own. The man of a
- mild disposition and tender affections, in forming a notion of the most
- perfect virtue, mixes in it more of benevolence and humanity, than
- the man of courage and enterprize, who naturally looks upon a certain
- elevation of mind as the most accomplished character. This must
- evidently proceed from an immediate sympathy, which men have with
- characters similar to their own. They enter with more warmth into such
- sentiments, and feel more sensibly the pleasure, which arises from them.
- It is remarkable, that nothing touches a man of humanity more than any
- instance of extraordinary delicacy in love or friendship, where a person
- is attentive to the smallest concerns of his friend, and is willing
- to sacrifice to them the most considerable interest of his own. Such
- delicacies have little influence on society; because they make us regard
- the greatest trifles: But they are the more engaging, the more minute
- the concern is, and are a proof of the highest merit in any one, who is
- capable of them. The passions are so contagious, that they pass with the
- greatest facility from one person to another, and produce correspondent
- movements in all human breasts. Where friendship appears in very signal
- instances, my heart catches the same passion, and is warmed by those
- warm sentiments, that display themselves before me. Such agreeable
- movements must give me an affection to every one that excites them.
- This is the case with every thing that is agreeable in any person. The
- transition from pleasure to love is easy: But the transition must here
- be still more easy; since the agreeable sentiment, which is excited by
- sympathy, is love itself; and there is nothing required but to change
- the object.
- Hence the peculiar merit of benevolence in all its shapes and
- appearances. Hence even its weaknesses are virtuous and amiable; and a
- person, whose grief upon the loss of a friend were excessive, would be
- esteemed upon that account. His tenderness bestows a merit, as it does a
- pleasure, on his melancholy.
- We are not, however, to imagine, that all the angry passions are
- vicious, though they are disagreeable. There is a certain indulgence due
- to human nature in this respect. Anger and hatred are passions
- inherent in Our very frame and constitutions. The want of them, on some
- occasions, may even be a proof of weakness and imbecillity. And where
- they appear only in a low degree, we not only excuse them because they
- are natural; but even bestow our applauses on them, because they are
- inferior to what appears in the greatest part of mankind.
- Where these angry passions rise up to cruelty, they form the most
- detested of all vices. All the pity and concern which we have for the
- miserable sufferers by this vice, turns against the person guilty of
- it, and produces a stronger hatred than we are sensible of on any other
- occasion. Even when the vice of inhumanity rises not to this extreme
- degree, our sentiments concerning it are very much influenced by
- reflections on the harm that results from it. And we may observe in
- general, that if we can find any quality in a person, which renders him
- incommodious to those, who live and converse with him, we always allow
- it to be a fault or blemish, without any farther examination. On the
- other hand, when we enumerate the good qualities of any person, we
- always mention those parts of his character, which render him a safe
- companion, an easy friend, a gentle master, an agreeable husband, or an
- indulgent father. We consider him with all his relations in society; and
- love or hate him, according as he affects those, who have any immediate
- intercourse with him. And it is a most certain rule, that if there be
- no relation of life, in which I coued not wish to stand to a particular
- person, his character must so far be allowed to be perfect. If he be
- as little wanting to himself as to others, his character is entirely
- perfect. This is the ultimate test of merit and virtue.
- SECT. IV OF NATURAL ABILITIES
- No distinction is more usual in all systems of ethics, than that betwixt
- natural abilities and moral virtues; where the former are placed on the
- same footing with bodily endowments, and are supposed to have no merit
- or moral worth annexed to them. Whoever considers the matter accurately,
- will find, that a dispute upon this head would be merely a dispute of
- words, and that though these qualities are not altogether of the same
- kind, yet they agree in the most material circumstances. They are both
- of them equally mental qualities: And both of them equally produce
- pleasure; and have of course an equal tendency to procure the love
- and esteem of mankind. There are few, who are not as jealous of their
- character, with regard to sense and knowledge, as to honour and courage;
- and much more than with regard to temperance and sobriety. Men are even
- afraid of passing for goodnatured; lest that should be taken for want
- of understanding: And often boast of more debauches than they have been
- really engaged in, to give themselves airs of fire and spirit. In short,
- the figure a man makes in the world, the reception he meets with in
- company, the esteem paid him by his acquaintance; all these advantages
- depend almost as much upon his good sense and judgment, as upon any
- other part of his character. Let a man have the best intentions in the
- world, and be the farthest from all injustice and violence, he will
- never be able to make himself be much regarded without a moderate
- share, at least, of parts and understanding. Since then natural
- abilities, though, perhaps, inferior, yet are on the same footing, both
- as to their causes and effects, with those qualities which we call moral
- virtues, why should we make any distinction betwixt them?
- Though we refuse to natural abilities the title of virtues, we must
- allow, that they procure the love and esteem of mankind; that they give
- a new lustre to the other virtues; and that a man possessed of them is
- much more intitled to our good-will and services, than one entirely
- void of them. It may, indeed, be pretended that the sentiment of
- approbation, which those qualities produce, besides its being inferior,
- is also somewhat different from that, which attends the other virtues.
- But this, in my opinion, is not a sufficient reason for excluding them
- from the catalogue of virtues. Each of the virtues, even benevolence,
- justice, gratitude, integrity, excites a different sentiment or feeling
- in the spectator. The characters of Caesar and Cato, as drawn by
- Sallust, are both of them virtuous, in the strictest sense of the word;
- but in a different way: Nor are the sentiments entirely the same, which
- arise from them. The one produces love; the other esteem: The one is
- amiable; the other awful: We could wish to meet with the one character
- in a friend; the other character we would be ambitious of in ourselves.
- In like manner, the approbation which attends natural abilities, may be
- somewhat different to the feeling from that, which arises from the other
- virtues, without making them entirely of a different species. And indeed
- we may observe, that the natural abilities, no more than the other
- virtues, produce not, all of them, the same kind of approbation. Good
- sense and genius beget esteem: Wit and humour excite love.
- [Footnote 27 Love and esteem are at the bottom the same
- passions, and arise from like causes. The qualities, that
- produce both, are agreeable, and give pleasure. But where
- this pleasure is severe and serious; or where its object is
- great, and makes a strong impression; or where it produces
- any degree of humility and awe: In all these cases, the
- passion, which arises from the pleasure, is more properly
- denominated esteem than love. Benevolence attends both: But
- is connected with love in a more eminent degree.]
- Those, who represent the distinction betwixt natural abilities and
- moral virtues as very material, may say, that the former are entirely
- involuntary, and have therefore no merit attending them, as having no
- dependance on liberty and free-will. But to this I answer, first, that
- many of those qualities, which all moralists, especially the antients,
- comprehend under the title of moral virtues, are equally involuntary and
- necessary, with the qualities of the judgment and imagination. Of this
- nature are constancy, fortitude, magnanimity; and, in short, all the
- qualities which form the great man. I might say the same, in some
- degree, of the others; it being almost impossible for the mind to
- change its character in any considerable article, or cure itself of a
- passionate or splenetic temper, when they are natural to it. The greater
- degree there is of these blameable qualities, the more vicious they
- become, and yet they are the less voluntary. Secondly, I would have
- anyone give me a reason, why virtue and vice may not be involuntary, as
- well as beauty and deformity. These moral distinctions arise from the
- natural distinctions of pain and pleasure; and when we receive those
- feelings from the general consideration of any quality or character,
- we denominate it vicious or virtuous. Now I believe no one will assert,
- that a quality can never produce pleasure or pain to the person who
- considers it, unless it be perfectly voluntary in the person who
- possesses it. Thirdly, As to free-will, we have shewn that it has no
- place with regard to the actions, no more than the qualities of men. It
- is not a just consequence, that what is voluntary is free. Our actions
- are more voluntary than our judgments; but we have not more liberty in
- the one than in the other.
- But though this distinction betwixt voluntary and involuntary be not
- sufficient to justify the distinction betwixt natural abilities and
- moral virtues, yet the former distinction will afford us a plausible
- reason, why moralists have invented the latter. Men have observed, that
- though natural abilities and moral qualities be in the main on the
- same footing, there is, however, this difference betwixt them, that the
- former are almost invariable by any art or industry; while the latter,
- or at least, the actions, that proceed from them, may be changed by the
- motives of rewards and punishments, praise and blame. Hence legislators,
- and divines, and moralists, have principally applied themselves to the
- regulating these voluntary actions, and have endeavoured to produce
- additional motives, for being virtuous in that particular. They
- knew, that to punish a man for folly, or exhort him to be prudent and
- sagacious, would have but little effect; though the same punishments
- and exhortations, with regard to justice and injustice, might have a
- considerable influence. But as men, in common life and conversation,
- do not carry those ends in view, but naturally praise or blame whatever
- pleases or displeases them, they do not seem much to regard this
- distinction, but consider prudence under the character of virtue as well
- as benevolence, and penetration as well as justice. Nay, we find, that
- all moralists, whose judgment is not perverted by a strict adherence
- to a system, enter into the same way of thinking; and that the antient
- moralists in particular made no scruple of placing prudence at the head
- of the cardinal virtues. There is a sentiment of esteem and approbation,
- which may be excited, in some degree, by any faculty of the mind, in its
- perfect state and condition; and to account for this sentiment is the
- business of Philosophers. It belongs to Grammarians to examine what
- qualities are entitled to the denomination of virtue; nor will they
- find, upon trial, that this is so easy a task, as at first sight they
- may be apt to imagine.
- The principal reason why natural abilities are esteemed, is because of
- their tendency to be useful to the person, who is possessed of them.
- It is impossible to execute any design with success, where it is not
- conducted with prudence and discretion; nor will the goodness of our
- intentions alone suffice to procure us a happy issue to our enterprizes.
- Men are superior to beasts principally by the superiority of their
- reason; and they are the degrees of the same faculty, which set such an
- infinite difference betwixt one man and another. All the advantages of
- art are owing to human reason; and where fortune is not very capricious,
- the most considerable part of these advantages must fall to the share of
- the prudent and sagacious.
- When it is asked, whether a quick or a slow apprehension be most
- valuable? whether one, that at first view penetrates into a subject, but
- can perform nothing upon study; or a contrary character, which must
- work out every thing by dint of application? whether a clear head, or
- a copious invention? whether a profound genius, or a sure judgment? in
- short, what character, or peculiar understanding, is more excellent than
- another? It is evident we can answer none of these questions, without
- considering which of those qualities capacitates a man best for the
- world, and carries him farthest in any of his undertakings.
- There are many other qualities of the mind, whose merit is derived from
- the same origin, industry, perseverance, patience, activity, vigilance,
- application, constancy, with other virtues of that kind, which it will
- be easy to recollect, are esteemed valuable upon no other account,
- than their advantage in the conduct of life. It is the same case with
- temperance, frugality, economy, resolution: As on the other hand,
- prodigality, luxury, irresolution, uncertainty, are vicious, merely
- because they draw ruin upon us, and incapacitate us for business and
- action.
- As wisdom and good-sense are valued, because they are useful to the
- person possessed of them; so wit and eloquence are valued, because they
- are immediately agreeable to others. On the other hand, good humour is
- loved and esteemed, because it is immediately agreeable to the person
- himself. It is evident, that the conversation of a man of wit is very
- satisfactory; as a chearful good-humoured companion diffuses a joy over
- the whole company, from a sympathy with his gaiety. These qualities,
- therefore, being agreeable, they naturally beget love and esteem, and
- answer to all the characters of virtue.
- It is difficult to tell, on many occasions, what it is that renders
- one man's conversation so agreeable and entertaining, and another's so
- insipid and distasteful. As conversation is a transcript of the mind as
- well as books, the same qualities, which render the one valuable, must
- give us an esteem for the other. This we shall consider afterwards. In
- the mean time it may be affirmed in general, that all the merit a
- man may derive from his conversation (which, no doubt, may be very
- considerable) arises from nothing but the pleasure it conveys to those
- who are present.
- In this view, cleanliness is also to be regarded as a virtue; since it
- naturally renders us agreeable to others, and is a very considerable
- source of love and affection. No one will deny, that a negligence in
- this particular is a fault; and as faults are nothing but smaller vices,
- and this fault can have no other origin than the uneasy sensation, which
- it excites in others, we may in this instance, seemingly so trivial,
- dearly discover the origin of the moral distinction of vice and virtue
- in other instances.
- Besides all those qualities, which render a person lovely or valuable,
- there is also a certain JE-NE-SCAI-QUOI of agreeable and handsome, that
- concurs to the same effect. In this case, as well as in that of wit and
- eloquence, we must have recourse to a certain sense, which acts without
- reflection, and regards not the tendencies of qualities and characters.
- Some moralists account for all the sentiments of virtue by this sense.
- Their hypothesis is very plausible. Nothing but a particular enquiry can
- give the preference to any other hypothesis. When we find, that almost
- all the virtues have such particular tendencies; and also find, that
- these tendencies are sufficient alone to give a strong sentiment of
- approbation: We cannot doubt, after this, that qualities are approved
- of, in proportion to the advantage, which results from them.
- The decorum or indecorum of a quality, with regard to the age, or
- character, or station, contributes also to its praise or blame. This
- decorum depends, in a great measure, upon experience. It is usual to
- see men lose their levity, as they advance in years. Such a degree
- of gravity, therefore, and such years, are connected together in our
- thoughts. When we observe them separated in any person's character, this
- imposes a kind of violence on our imagination, and is disagreeable.
- That faculty of the soul, which, of all others, is of the least
- consequence to the character, and has the least virtue or vice in its
- several degrees, at the same time, that it admits of a great variety of
- degrees, is the memory. Unless it rise up to that stupendous height
- as to surprize us, or sink so low as, in some measure, to affect the
- judgment, we commonly take no notice of its variations, nor ever mention
- them to the praise or dispraise of any person. It is so far from being a
- virtue to have a good memory, that men generally affect to complain of
- a bad one; and endeavouring to persuade the world, that what they say
- is entirely of their own invention, sacrifice it to the praise of genius
- and judgment. Yet to consider the matter abstractedly, it would be
- difficult to give a reason, why the faculty of recalling past ideas with
- truth and clearness, should not have as much merit in it, as the
- faculty of placing our present ideas, in such an order, as to form true
- propositions and opinions. The reason of the difference certainly must
- be, that the memory is exerted without any sensation of pleasure or
- pain; and in all its middling degrees serves almost equally well in
- business and affairs. But the least variations in the judgment are
- sensibly felt in their consequences; while at the same time that faculty
- is never exerted in any eminent degree, without an extraordinary delight
- and satisfaction. The sympathy with this utility and pleasure bestows a
- merit on the understanding; and the absence of it makes us consider the
- memory as a faculty very indifferent to blame or praise.
- Before I leave this subject of natural abilities, I must observe, that,
- perhaps, one source of the esteem and affection, which attends them, is
- derived from the importance and weight, which they bestow on the person
- possessed of them. He becomes of greater consequence in life. His
- resolutions and actions affect a greater number of his fellow-creatures.
- Both his friendship and enmity are of moment. And it is easy to observe,
- that whoever is elevated, after this manner, above the rest of mankind,
- must excite in us the sentiments of esteem and approbation. Whatever is
- important engages our attention, fixes our thought, and is contemplated
- with satisfaction. The histories of kingdoms are more interesting than
- domestic stories: The histories of great empires more than those
- of small cities and principalities: And the histories of wars and
- revolutions more than those of peace and order. We sympathize with the
- persons that suffer, in all the various sentiments which belong to their
- fortunes. The mind is occupied by the multitude of the objects, and by
- the strong passions, that display themselves. And this occupation or
- agitation of the mind is commonly agreeable and amusing. The same theory
- accounts for the esteem and regard we pay to men of extraordinary parts
- and abilities. The good and ill of multitudes are connected with their
- actions. Whatever they undertake is important, and challenges our
- attention. Nothing is to be over-looked and despised, that regards them.
- And where any person can excite these sentiments, he soon acquires our
- esteem; unless other circumstances of his character render him odious
- and disagreeable.
- SECT. V SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING THE NATURAL VIRTUES
- It has been observed, in treating of the passions, that pride
- and humility, love and hatred, are excited by any advantages or
- disadvantages of the mind, body, or fortune; and that these advantages
- or disadvantages have that effect by producing a separate impression of
- pain or pleasure. The pain or pleasure, which arises from the general
- survey or view of any action or quality of the mind, constitutes its
- vice or virtue, and gives rise to our approbation or blame, which is
- nothing but a fainter and more imperceptible love or hatred. We have
- assigned four different sources of this pain and pleasure; and in order
- to justify more fully that hypothesis, it may here be proper to observe,
- that the advantages or disadvantages of the body and of fortune, produce
- a pain or pleasure from the very same principles. The tendency of any
- object to be useful to the person possess d of it, or to others; to
- convey pleasure to him or to others; all these circumstances convey an
- immediate pleasure to the person, who considers the object, and command
- his love and approbation.
- To begin with the advantages of the body; we may observe a phaenomenon,
- which might appear somewhat trivial and ludicrous, if any thing coued be
- trivial, which fortified a conclusion of such importance, or ludicrous,
- which was employed in a philosophical reasoning. It is a general
- remark, that those we call good women's men, who have either signalized
- themselves by their amorous exploits, or whose make of body promises any
- extraordinary vigour of that kind, are well received by the fair sex,
- and naturally engage the affections even of those, whose virtue prevents
- any design of ever giving employment to those talents. Here it is
- evident, that the ability of such a person to give enjoyment, is the
- real source of that love and esteem he meets with among the females; at
- the same time that the women, who love and esteem him, have no prospect
- of receiving that enjoyment themselves, and can only be affected by
- means of their sympathy with one, that has a commerce of love with him.
- This instance is singular, and merits our attention.
- Another source of the pleasure we receive from considering bodily
- advantages, is their utility to the person himself, who is possessed of
- them. It is certain, that a considerable part of the beauty of men, as
- well as of other animals, consists in such a conformation of members, as
- we find by experience to be attended with strength and agility, and to
- capacitate the creature for any action or exercise. Broad shoulders,
- a lank belly, firm joints, taper legs; all these are beautiful in
- our species because they are signs of force and vigour, which being
- advantages we naturally sympathize with, they convey to the beholder a
- share of that satisfaction they produce in the possessor.
- So far as to the utility, which may attend any quality of the body. As
- to the immediate pleasure, it is certain, that an air of health, as well
- as of strength and agility, makes a considerable part of beauty; and
- that a sickly air in another is always disagreeable, upon account of
- that idea of pain and uneasiness, which it conveys to us. On the other
- hand, we are pleased with the regularity of our own features, though
- it be neither useful to ourselves nor others; and it is necessary at a
- distance, to make it convey to us any satisfaction. We commonly consider
- ourselves as we appear in the eyes of others, and sympathize with the
- advantageous sentiments they entertain with regard to us.
- How far the advantages of fortune produce esteem and approbation from
- the same principles, we may satisfy ourselves by reflecting on our
- precedent reasoning on that subject. We have observed, that our
- approbation of those, who are possess d of the advantages of fortune,
- may be ascribed to three different causes. First, To that immediate
- pleasure, which a rich man gives us, by the view of the beautiful
- cloaths, equipage, gardens, or houses, which he possesses. Secondly,
- To the advantage, which we hope to reap from him by his generosity and
- liberality. Thirdly, To the pleasure and advantage, which he himself
- reaps from his possessions, and which produce an agreeable sympathy in
- us. Whether we ascribe our esteem of the rich and great to one or all of
- these causes, we may clearly see the traces of those principles, which
- give rise to the sense of vice and virtue. I believe most people, at
- first sight, will be inclined to ascribe our esteem of the rich to
- self-interest, and the prospect of advantage. But as it is certain,
- that our esteem or deference extends beyond any prospect of advantage
- to ourselves, it is evident, that that sentiment must proceed from
- a sympathy with those, who are dependent on the person we esteem and
- respect, and who have an immediate connexion with him. We consider him
- as a person capable of contributing to the happiness or enjoyment of
- his fellow-creatures, whose sentiments, with regard to him, we naturally
- embrace. And this consideration will serve to justify my hypothesis
- in preferring the third principle to the other two, and ascribing our
- esteem of the rich to a sympathy with the pleasure and advantage, which
- they themselves receive from their possessions. For as even the other
- two principles cannot operate to a due extent, or account for all the
- phaenomena, without having recourse to a sympathy of one kind or other;
- it is much more natural to chuse that sympathy, which is immediate and
- direct, than that which is remote and indirect. To which we may add,
- that where the riches or power are very great, and render the person
- considerable and important in the world, the esteem attending them, may,
- in part, be ascribed to another source, distinct from these three,
- viz. their interesting the mind by a prospect of the multitude, and
- importance of their consequences: Though, in order to account for the
- operation of this principle, we must also have recourse to sympathy; as
- we have observed in the preceding section.
- It may not be amiss, on this occasion, to remark the flexibility of our
- sentiments, and the several changes they so readily receive from
- the objects, with which they are conjoined. All the sentiments of
- approbation, which attend any particular species of objects, have a
- great resemblance to each other, though derived from different sources;
- and, on the other hand, those sentiments, when directed to different
- objects, are different to the feeling, though derived from the same
- source. Thus the beauty of all visible objects causes a pleasure pretty
- much the same, though it be sometimes derived from the mere species and
- appearance of the objects; sometimes from sympathy, and an idea of their
- utility. In like manner, whenever we survey the actions and characters
- of men, without any particular interest in them, the pleasure, or pain,
- which arises from the survey (with some minute differences) is, in the
- main, of the same kind, though perhaps there be a great diversity in the
- causes, from which it is derived. On the other hand, a convenient house,
- and a virtuous character, cause not the same feeling of approbation;
- even though the source of our approbation be the same, and flow
- from sympathy and an idea of their utility. There is something very
- inexplicable in this variation of our feelings; but it is what we have
- experience of with regard to all our passions and sentiments.
- SECT. VI CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK
- Thus upon the whole I am hopeful, that nothing is wanting to an accurate
- proof of this system of ethics. We are certain, that sympathy is a very
- powerful principle in human nature. We are also certain, that it has a
- great influence on our sense of beauty, when we regard external
- objects, as well as when we judge of morals. We find, that it has force
- sufficient to give us the strongest sentiments of approbation, when it
- operates alone, without the concurrence of any other principle; as in
- the cases of justice, allegiance, chastity, and good-manners. We may
- observe, that all the circumstances requisite for its operation are
- found in most of the virtues; which have, for the most part, a tendency
- to the good of society, or to that of the person possessed of them. If
- we compare all these circumstances, we shall not doubt, that sympathy is
- the chief source of moral distinctions; especially when we reflect, that
- no objection can be raised against this hypothesis in one case, which
- will not extend to all cases. Justice is certainly approved of for no
- other reason, than because it has a tendency to the public good: And the
- public good is indifferent to us, except so far as sympathy interests
- us in it. We may presume the like with regard to all the other virtues,
- which have a like tendency to the public good. They must derive all
- their merit from our sympathy with those, who reap any advantage from
- them: As the virtues, which have a tendency to the good of the person
- possessed of them, derive their merit from our sympathy with him.
- Most people will readily allow, that the useful qualities of the mind
- are virtuous, because of their utility. This way of thinking is so
- natural, and occurs on so many occasions, that few will make any scruple
- of admitting it. Now this being once admitted, the force of sympathy
- must necessarily be acknowledged. Virtue is considered as means to an
- end. Means to an end are only valued so far as the end is valued.
- But the happiness of strangers affects us by sympathy alone. To that
- principle, therefore, we are to ascribe the sentiment of approbation,
- which arises from the survey of all those virtues, that are useful
- to society, or to the person possessed of them. These form the most
- considerable part of morality.
- Were it proper in such a subject to bribe the reader's assent, or employ
- any thing but solid argument, we are here abundantly supplied with
- topics to engage the affections. All lovers of virtue (and such we
- all are in speculation, however we may degenerate in practice) must
- certainly be pleased to see moral distinctions derived from so noble a
- source, which gives us a just notion both of the generosity and capacity
- of human nature. It requires but very little knowledge of human affairs
- to perceive, that a sense of morals is a principle inherent in the soul,
- and one of the most powerful that enters into the composition. But this
- sense must certainly acquire new force, when reflecting on itself,
- it approves of those principles, from whence it is derived, and finds
- nothing but what is great and good in its rise and origin. Those who
- resolve the sense of morals into original instincts of the human mind,
- may defend the cause of virtue with sufficient authority; but want
- the advantage, which those possess, who account for that sense by an
- extensive sympathy with mankind. According to their system, not only
- virtue must be approved of, but also the sense of virtue: And not only
- that sense, but also the principles, from whence it is derived. So that
- nothing is presented on any side, but what is laudable and good.
- This observation may be extended to justice, and the other virtues of
- that kind. Though justice be artificial, the sense of its morality is
- natural. It is the combination of men, in a system of conduct, which
- renders any act of justice beneficial to society. But when once it has
- that tendency, we naturally approve of it; and if we did not so, it
- is impossible any combination or convention coued ever produce that
- sentiment.
- Most of the inventions of men are subject to change. They depend upon
- humour and caprice. They have a vogue for a time, and then sink into
- oblivion. It may, perhaps, be apprehended, that if justice were allowed
- to be a human invention, it must be placed on the same footing. But the
- cases are widely different. The interest, on which justice is founded,
- is the greatest imaginable, and extends to all times and places. It
- cannot possibly be served by any other invention. It is obvious, and
- discovers itself on the very first formation of society. All these
- causes render the rules of justice stedfast and immutable; at least,
- as immutable as human nature. And if they were founded on original
- instincts, coued they have any greater stability?
- The same system may help us to form a just notion of the happiness, as
- well as of the dignity of virtue, and may interest every principle
- of our nature in the embracing and cherishing that noble quality.
- Who indeed does not feel an accession of alacrity in his pursuits of
- knowledge and ability of every kind, when he considers, that besides the
- advantage, which immediately result from these acquisitions, they
- also give him a new lustre in the eyes of mankind, and are universally
- attended with esteem and approbation? And who can think any advantages
- of fortune a sufficient compensation for the least breach of the social
- virtues, when he considers, that not only his character with regard to
- others, but also his peace and inward satisfaction entirely depend upon
- his strict observance of them; and that a mind will never be able to
- bear its own survey, that has been wanting in its part to mankind and
- society? But I forbear insisting on this subject. Such reflections
- require a work a-part, very different from the genius of the present.
- The anatomist ought never to emulate the painter; nor in his accurate
- dissections and portraitures of the smaller parts of the human body,
- pretend to give his figures any graceful and engaging attitude or
- expression. There is even something hideous, or at least minute in the
- views of things, which he presents; and it is necessary the objects
- should be set more at a distance, and be more covered up from sight, to
- make them engaging to the eye and imagination. An anatomist, however,
- is admirably fitted to give advice to a painter; and it is even
- impracticable to excel in the latter art, without the assistance of the
- former. We must have an exact knowledge of the parts, their situation
- and connexion, before we can design with any elegance or correctness.
- And thus the most abstract speculations concerning human nature, however
- cold and unentertaining, become subservient to practical morality; and
- may render this latter science more correct in its precepts, and more
- persuasive in its exhortations.
- APPENDIX
- There is nothing I would more willingly lay hold of, than an opportunity
- of confessing my errors; and should esteem such a return to truth and
- reason to be more honourable than the most unerring judgment. A man,
- who is free from mistakes, can pretend to no praises, except from the
- justness of his understanding: But a man, who corrects his mistakes,
- shews at once the justness of his understanding, and the candour and
- ingenuity of his temper. I have not yet been so fortunate as to discover
- any very considerable mistakes in the reasonings delivered in
- the preceding volumes, except on one article: But I have found by
- experience, that some of my expressions have not been so well chosen,
- as to guard against all mistakes in the readers; and it is chiefly to
- remedy this defect, I have subjoined the following appendix.
- We can never be induced to believe any matter of fact, except where its
- cause, or its effect, is present to us; but what the nature is of that
- belief, which arises from the relation of cause and effect, few have
- had the curiosity to ask themselves. In my opinion, this dilemma is
- inevitable. Either the belief is some new idea, such as that of reality
- or existence, which we join to the simple conception of an object, or
- it is merely a peculiar feeling or sentiment. That it is not a new
- idea, annexed to the simple conception, may be evinced from these two
- arguments. First, We have no abstract idea of existence, distinguishable
- and separable from the idea of particular objects. It is impossible,
- therefore, that this idea of existence can be annexed to the idea of any
- object, or form the difference betwixt a simple conception and belief.
- Secondly, The mind has the command over all its ideas, and can separate,
- unite, mix, and vary them, as it pleases; so that if belief consisted
- merely in a new idea, annexed to the conception, it would be in a man's
- power to believe what he pleased. We may, therefore, conclude, that
- belief consists merely in a certain feeling or sentiment; in something,
- that depends not on the will, but must arise from certain determinate
- causes and principles, of which we are not masters. When we are
- convinced of any matter of fact, we do nothing but conceive it, along
- with a certain feeling, different from what attends the mere reveries
- of the imagination. And when we express our incredulity concerning any
- fact, we mean, that the arguments for the fact produce not that feeling.
- Did not the belief consist in a sentiment different from our mere
- conception, whatever objects were presented by the wildest imagination,
- would be on an equal footing with the most established truths founded on
- history and experience. There is nothing but the feeling, or sentiment,
- to distinguish the one from the other.
- This, therefore, being regarded as an undoubted truth, that belief is
- nothing but a peculiar feeling, different from the simple conception,
- the next question, that naturally occurs, is, what is the nature of
- this feeling, or sentiment, and whether it be analogous to any other
- sentiment of the human mind? This question is important. For if it be
- not analogous to any other sentiment, we must despair of explaining its
- causes, and must consider it as an original principle of the human mind.
- If it be analogous, we may hope to explain its causes from analogy,
- and trace it up to more general principles. Now that there is a greater
- firmness and solidity in the conceptions, which are the objects of
- conviction and assurance, than in the loose and indolent reveries of
- a castle-builder, every one will readily own. They strike upon us with
- more force; they are more present to us; the mind has a firmer hold of
- them, and is more actuated and moved by them. It acquiesces in them;
- and, in a manner, fixes and reposes itself on them. In short, they
- approach nearer to the impressions, which are immediately present to us;
- and are therefore analogous to many other operations of the mind.
- There is not, in my opinion, any possibility of evading this conclusion,
- but by asserting, that belief, beside the simple conception, consists in
- some impression or feeling, distinguishable from the conception. It does
- not modify the conception, and render it more present and intense: It
- is only annexed to it, after the same manner that will and desire
- are annexed to particular conceptions of good and pleasure. But the
- following considerations will, I hope, be sufficient to remove this
- hypothesis. First, It is directly contrary to experience, and our
- immediate consciousness. All men have ever allowed reasoning to be
- merely an operation of our thoughts or ideas; and however those ideas
- may be varied to the feeling, there is nothing ever enters into our
- conclusions but ideas, or our fainter conceptions. For instance; I hear
- at present a person's voice, whom I am acquainted with; and this sound
- comes from the next room. This impression of my senses immediately
- conveys my thoughts to the person, along with all the surrounding
- objects. I paint them out to myself as existent at present, with the
- same qualities and relations, that I formerly knew them possessed of.
- These ideas take faster hold of my mind, than the ideas of an inchanted
- castle. They are different to the feeling; but there is no distinct or
- separate impression attending them. It is the same case when I recollect
- the several incidents of a journey, or the events of any history. Every
- particular fact is there the object of belief. Its idea is modified
- differently from the loose reveries of a castle-builder: But no distinct
- impression attends every distinct idea, or conception of matter of fact.
- This is the subject of plain experience. If ever this experience can
- be disputed on any occasion, it is when the mind has been agitated with
- doubts and difficulties; and afterwards, upon taking the object in a new
- point of view, or being presented with a new argument, fixes and reposes
- itself in one settled conclusion and belief. In this case there is a
- feeling distinct and separate from the conception. The passage from
- doubt and agitation to tranquility and repose, conveys a satisfaction
- and pleasure to the mind. But take any other case. Suppose I see the
- legs and thighs of a person in motion, while some interposed object
- conceals the rest of his body. Here it is certain, the imagination
- spreads out the whole figure. I give him a head and shoulders, and
- breast and neck. These members I conceive and believe him to be
- possessed of. Nothing can be more evident, than that this whole
- operation is performed by the thought or imagination alone. The
- transition is immediate. The ideas presently strike us. Their customary
- connexion with the present impression, varies them and modifies them in
- a certain manner, but produces no act of the mind, distinct from this
- peculiarity of conception. Let any one examine his own mind, and he will
- evidently find this to be the truth.
- Secondly, Whatever may be the case, with regard to this distinct
- impression, it must be allowed, that the mind has a firmer hold, or
- more steady conception of what it takes to be matter of fact, than of
- fictions. Why then look any farther, or multiply suppositions without
- necessity?
- Thirdly, We can explain the causes of the firm conception, but not those
- of any separate impression. And not only so, but the causes of the firm
- conception exhaust the whole subject, and nothing is left to produce any
- other effect. An inference concerning a matter of fact is nothing but
- the idea of an object, that is frequently conjoined, or is associated
- with a present impression. This is the whole of it. Every part is
- requisite to explain, from analogy, the more steady conception; and
- nothing remains capable of producing any distinct impression.
- Fourthly, The effects of belief, in influencing the passions and
- imagination, can all be explained from the firm conception; and there
- is no occasion to have recourse to any other principle. These arguments,
- with many others, enumerated in the foregoing volumes, sufficiently
- prove, that belief only modifies the idea or conception; and renders
- it different to the feeling, without producing any distinct impression.
- Thus upon a general view of the subject, there appear to be two
- questions of importance, which we may venture to recommend to the
- consideration of philosophers, Whether there be any thing to distinguish
- belief from the simple conception beside the feeling of sentiment? And,
- Whether this feeling be any thing but a firmer conception, or a faster
- hold, that we take of the object?
- If, upon impartial enquiry, the same conclusion, that I have formed,
- be assented to by philosophers, the next business is to examine the
- analogy, which there is betwixt belief, and other acts of the mind, and
- find the cause of the firmness and strength of conception: And this I do
- not esteem a difficult task. The transition from a present impression,
- always enlivens and strengthens any idea. When any object is presented,
- the idea of its usual attendant immediately strikes us, as something
- real and solid. It is felt, rather than conceived, and approaches the
- impression, from which it is derived, in its force and influence. This I
- have proved at large. I cannot add any new arguments.
- I had entertained some hopes, that however deficient our theory of the
- intellectual world might be, it would be free from those contradictions,
- and absurdities, which seem to attend every explication, that human
- reason can give of the material world. But upon a more strict review of
- the section concerning personal identity, I find myself involved in
- such a labyrinth, that, I must confess, I neither know how to correct
- my former opinions, nor how to render them consistent. If this be not a
- good general reason for scepticism, it is at least a sufficient one (if
- I were not already abundantly supplied) for me to entertain a diffidence
- and modesty in all my decisions. I shall propose the arguments on both
- sides, beginning with those that induced me to deny the strict and
- proper identity and simplicity of a self or thinking being.
- When we talk of self or substance, we must have an idea annexed to
- these terms, otherwise they are altogether unintelligible. Every idea is
- derived from preceding impressions; and we have no impression of self
- or substance, as something simple and individual. We have, therefore, no
- idea of them in that sense.
- Whatever is distinct, is distinguishable; and whatever is
- distinguishable, is separable by the thought or imagination. All
- perceptions are distinct. They are, therefore, distinguishable, and
- separable, and may be conceived as separately existent, and may exist
- separately, without any contradiction or absurdity.
- When I view this table and that chimney, nothing is present to me but
- particular perceptions, which are of a like nature with all the other
- perceptions. This is the doctrine of philosophers. But this table, which
- is present to me, and the chimney, may and do exist separately. This is
- the doctrine of the vulgar, and implies no contradiction. There is no
- contradiction, therefore, in extending the same doctrine to all the
- perceptions.
- In general, the following reasoning seems satisfactory. All ideas are
- borrowed from preceding perceptions. Our ideas of objects, therefore,
- are derived from that source. Consequently no proposition can be
- intelligible or consistent with regard to objects, which is not so with
- regard to perceptions. But it is intelligible and consistent to say,
- that objects exist distinct and independent, without any common simple
- substance or subject of inhesion. This proposition, therefore, can never
- be absurd with regard to perceptions.
- When I turn my reflection on myself, I never can perceive this self
- without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing
- but the perceptions. It is the composition of these, therefore, which
- forms the self. We can conceive a thinking being to have either many or
- few perceptions. Suppose the mind to be reduced even below the life
- of an oyster. Suppose it to have only one perception, as of thirst or
- hunger. Consider it in that situation. Do you conceive any thing but
- merely that perception? Have you any notion of self or substance? If
- not, the addition of other perceptions can never give you that notion.
- The annihilation, which some people suppose to follow upon death, and
- which entirely destroys this self, is nothing but an extinction of all
- particular perceptions; love and hatred, pain and pleasure, thought and
- sensation. These therefore must be the same with self; since the one
- cannot survive the other.
- Is self the same with substance? If it be, how can that question have
- place, concerning the subsistence of self, under a change of substance?
- If they be distinct, what is the difference betwixt them? For my part,
- I have a notion of neither, when conceived distinct from particular
- perceptions.
- Philosophers begin to be reconciled to the principle, that we have
- no idea of external substance, distinct from the ideas of particular
- qualities. This must pave the way for a like principle with regard to
- the mind, that we have no notion of it, distinct from the particular
- perceptions.
- So far I seem to be attended with sufficient evidence. But having thus
- loosened all our particular perceptions, when I proceed to explain
- the principle of connexion, which binds them together, and makes us
- attribute to them a real simplicity and identity; I am sensible, that my
- account is very defective, and that nothing but the seeming evidence
- of the precedent reasonings coued have induced me to receive it. If
- perceptions are distinct existences, they form a whole only by being
- connected together. But no connexions among distinct existences are
- ever discoverable by human understanding. We only feel a connexion or
- determination of the thought, to pass from one object to another. It
- follows, therefore, that the thought alone finds personal identity, when
- reflecting on the train of past perceptions, that compose a mind, the
- ideas of them are felt to be connected together, and naturally introduce
- each other. However extraordinary this conclusion may seem, it need not
- surprize us. Most philosophers seem inclined to think, that personal
- identity arises from consciousness; and consciousness is nothing but a
- reflected thought or perception. The present philosophy, therefore,
- has so far a promising aspect. But all my hopes vanish, when I come to
- explain the principles, that unite our successive perceptions in our
- thought or consciousness. I cannot discover any theory, which gives me
- satisfaction on this head.
- In short there are two principles, which I cannot render consistent; nor
- is it in my power to renounce either of them, viz, that all our distinct
- perceptions are distinct existences, and that the mind never perceives
- any real connexion among distinct existences. Did our perceptions either
- inhere in something simple and individual, or did the mind perceive some
- real connexion among them, there would be no difficulty in the case. For
- my part, I must plead the privilege of a sceptic, and confess, that this
- difficulty is too hard for my understanding. I pretend not, however, to
- pronounce it absolutely insuperable. Others, perhaps, or myself,
- upon more mature reflections, may discover some hypothesis, that will
- reconcile those contradictions.
- I shall also take this opportunity of confessing two other errors of
- less importance, which more mature reflection has discovered to me in my
- reasoning. The first may be found in Vol. I. page 106. where I say, that
- the distance betwixt two bodies is known, among other things, by the
- angles, which the rays of light flowing from the bodies make with each
- other. It is certain, that these angles are not known to the mind, and
- consequently can never discover the distance. The second error may be
- found in Vol. I. page 144 where I say, that two ideas of the same object
- can only be different by their different degrees of force and vivacity.
- I believe there are other differences among ideas, which cannot properly
- be comprehended under these terms. Had I said, that two ideas of the
- same object can only be different by their different feeling, I should
- have been nearer the truth.
- End of Project Gutenberg's A Treatise of Human Nature, by David Hume
- *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE ***
- ***** This file should be named 4705.txt or 4705.zip *****
- This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
- http://www.gutenberg.org/4/7/0/4705/
- Produced by Col Choat
- Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
- will be renamed.
- Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
- one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
- (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
- permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
- set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
- copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
- protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
- Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
- charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
- do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
- rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
- such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
- research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
- practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
- subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
- redistribution.
- *** START: FULL LICENSE ***
- THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
- PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
- To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
- distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
- (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
- Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
- http://gutenberg.org/license).
- Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic works
- 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
- and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
- (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
- the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
- all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
- If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
- terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
- entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
- 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
- used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
- agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
- things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
- even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
- paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
- and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works. See paragraph 1.E below.
- 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
- or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
- collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
- individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
- located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
- copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
- works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
- are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
- Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
- freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
- this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
- the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
- keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
- Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
- 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
- what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
- a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
- the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
- before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
- creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
- Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
- the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
- States.
- 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
- 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
- access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
- whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
- phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
- Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
- copied or distributed:
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
- almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
- re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
- with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
- 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
- from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
- posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
- and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
- or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
- with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
- work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
- through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
- Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
- 1.E.9.
- 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
- with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
- must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
- terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
- to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
- permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
- 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
- work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
- 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
- electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
- prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
- active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm License.
- 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
- compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
- word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
- distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
- "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
- posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
- you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
- copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
- request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
- form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
- 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
- performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
- unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
- access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
- that
- - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
- the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
- you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
- owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
- has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
- Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
- must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
- prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
- returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
- sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
- address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
- the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
- - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
- you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
- does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
- License. You must require such a user to return or
- destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
- and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
- Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
- money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
- electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
- of receipt of the work.
- - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
- distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
- electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
- forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
- both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
- Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
- Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
- 1.F.
- 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
- effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
- public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
- collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
- "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
- corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
- property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
- computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
- your equipment.
- 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
- of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
- Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
- Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
- liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
- fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
- LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
- PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
- TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
- LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
- INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
- DAMAGE.
- 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
- defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
- receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
- written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
- received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
- your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
- the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
- refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
- providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
- receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
- is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
- opportunities to fix the problem.
- 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
- in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
- WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
- WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
- 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
- warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
- If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
- law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
- interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
- the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
- provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
- 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
- trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
- providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
- with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
- promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
- harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
- that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
- or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
- work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
- Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
- Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
- Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
- electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
- including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
- because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
- people in all walks of life.
- Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
- assistance they need, are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
- goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
- remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
- and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
- To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
- and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
- and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.
- Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
- Foundation
- The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
- 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
- state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
- Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
- number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
- http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
- permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
- The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
- Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
- throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
- 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
- business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact
- information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
- page at http://pglaf.org
- For additional contact information:
- Dr. Gregory B. Newby
- Chief Executive and Director
- gbnewby@pglaf.org
- Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation
- Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
- spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
- increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
- freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
- array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
- ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
- status with the IRS.
- The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
- charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
- States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
- considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
- with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
- where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
- SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
- particular state visit http://pglaf.org
- While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
- have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
- against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
- approach us with offers to donate.
- International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
- any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
- outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
- Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
- methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
- ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
- To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate
- Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
- works.
- Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
- concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
- with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
- Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
- Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
- editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
- unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
- keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
- Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
- http://www.gutenberg.org
- This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
- including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
- subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.