- The Project Gutenberg EBook of Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind by Georg Wilhelm
- Friedrich Hegel
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no
- restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under
- the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or
- online at http://www.gutenberg.org/license
- Title: Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind
- Author: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
- Release Date: March 5, 2012 [Ebook #39064]
- Language: English
- Character set encoding: UTF‐8
- ***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HEGEL’S PHILOSOPHY OF MIND***
- Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind
- By
- Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
- Translated From
- The Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences
- With
- Five Introductory Essays
- By
- William Wallace, M.A., LL.D.
- Fellow of Merton College, and Whyte’s Professor of Moral Philosophy in the
- University of Oxford
- Oxford
- Clarendon Press
- 1894
- CONTENTS
- Preface.
- Five Introductory Essays In Psychology And Ethics.
- Essay I. On The Scope Of A Philosophy Of Mind.
- Essay II. Aims And Methods Of Psychology.
- Essay III. On Some Psychological Aspects Of Ethics.
- Essay IV. Psycho-Genesis.
- Essay V. Ethics And Politics.
- Introduction.
- Section I. Mind Subjective.
- Sub-Section A. Anthropology. The Soul.
- Sub-Section B. Phenomenology Of Mind. Consciousness.
- Sub-Section C. Psychology. Mind.
- Section II. Mind Objective.
- Distribution.
- Sub-Section A. Law.
- Sub-Section B. The Morality Of Conscience.
- Sub-Section C. The Moral Life, Or Social Ethics.
- Section III. Absolute Mind.
- Sub-Section A. Art.
- Sub-Section B. Revealed Religion.
- Sub-Section C. Philosophy.
- Index.
- Footnotes
- PREFACE.
- I here offer a translation of the third or last part of Hegel’s
- encyclopaedic sketch of philosophy,—the _Philosophy of Mind_. The volume,
- like its subject, stands complete in itself. But it may also be regarded
- as a supplement or continuation of the work begun in my version of his
- _Logic_. I have not ventured upon the _Philosophy of Nature_ which lies
- between these two. That is a province, to penetrate into which would
- require an equipment of learning I make no claim to,—a province, also, of
- which the present-day interest would be largely historical, or at least
- bound up with historical circumstances.
- The translation is made from the German text given in the Second Part of
- the Seventh Volume of Hegel’s Collected Works, occasionally corrected by
- comparison with that found in the second and third editions (of 1827 and
- 1830) published by the author. I have reproduced only Hegel’s own
- paragraphs, and entirely omitted the _Zusätze_ of the editors. These
- addenda—which are in origin lecture-notes—to the paragraphs are, in the
- text of the Collected Works, given for the first section only. The
- psychological part which they accompany has been barely treated elsewhere
- by Hegel: but a good popular exposition of it will be found in Erdmann’s
- _Psychologische Briefe_. The second section was dealt with at greater
- length by Hegel himself in his _Philosophy of Law_ (1820). The topics of
- the third section are largely covered by his lectures on Art, Religion,
- and History of Philosophy.
- I do not conceal from myself that the text offers a hard nut to crack. Yet
- here and there, even through the medium of the translation, I think some
- light cannot fail to come to an earnest student. Occasionally, too, as,
- for instance, in §§ 406, 459, 549, and still more in §§ 552, 573, at the
- close of which might stand the words _Liberavi animam meam_, the writer
- really “lets himself go,” and gives his mind freely on questions where
- speculation comes closely in touch with life.
- In the _Five Introductory Essays_ I have tried sometimes to put together,
- and sometimes to provide with collateral elucidation, some points in the
- Mental Philosophy. I shall not attempt to justify the selection of
- subjects for special treatment further than to hope that they form a more
- or less connected group, and to refer for a study of some general
- questions of system and method to my _Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel’s
- Philosophy_ which appear almost simultaneously with this volume.
- OXFORD,
- _December, 1893_.
- FIVE INTRODUCTORY ESSAYS IN PSYCHOLOGY AND ETHICS.
- Essay I. On The Scope Of A Philosophy Of Mind.
- The art of finding titles, and of striking out headings which catch the
- eye or ear, and lead the mind by easy paths of association to the subject
- under exposition, was not one of Hegel’s gifts. A stirring phrase, a vivid
- or picturesque turn of words, he often has. But his lists of contents,
- when they cease to be commonplace, are apt to run into the bizarre and the
- grotesque. Generally, indeed, his rubrics are the old and (as we may be
- tempted to call them) insignificant terms of the text-books. But, in
- Hegel’s use of them, these conventional designations are charged with a
- highly individualised meaning. They may mean more—they may mean less—than
- they habitually pass for: but they unquestionably specify their meaning
- with a unique and almost personal flavour. And this can hardly fail to
- create and to disappoint undue expectations.
- (i.) Philosophy and its Parts.
- Even the main divisions of his system show this conservatism in
- terminology. The names of the three parts of the Encyclopaedia are, we may
- say, non-significant of their peculiar contents. And that for a good
- reason. What Hegel proposes to give is no novel or special doctrine, but
- the universal philosophy which has passed on from age to age, here
- narrowed and there widened, but still essentially the same. It is
- conscious of its continuity and proud of its identity with the teachings
- of Plato and Aristotle.
- The earliest attempts of the Greek philosophers to present philosophy in a
- complete and articulated order—attempts generally attributed to the
- Stoics, the schoolmen of antiquity—made it a tripartite whole. These three
- parts were Logic, Physics, and Ethics. In their entirety they were meant
- to form a cycle of unified knowledge, satisfying the needs of theory as
- well as practice. As time went on, however, the situation changed: and if
- the old names remained, their scope and value suffered many changes. New
- interests and curiosities, due to altered circumstances, brought other
- departments of reality under the focus of investigation besides those
- which had been primarily discussed under the old names. Inquiries became
- more specialised, and each tended to segregate itself from the rest as an
- independent field of science. The result was that in modern times the
- territory still marked by the ancient titles had shrunk to a mere phantom
- of its former bulk. Almost indeed things had come to such a pass that the
- time-honoured figures had sunk into the misery of _rois fainéants_; while
- the real business of knowledge was discharged by the younger and less
- conventional lines of research which the needs and fashions of the time
- had called up. Thus Logic, in the narrow formal sense, was turned into an
- “art” of argumentation and a system of technical rules for the analysis
- and synthesis of academical discussion. Physics or Natural Philosophy
- restricted itself to the elaboration of some metaphysical postulates or
- hypotheses regarding the general modes of physical operation. And Ethics
- came to be a very unpractical discussion of subtleties regarding moral
- faculty and moral standard. Meanwhile a theory of scientific method and of
- the laws governing the growth of intelligence and formation of ideas grew
- up, and left the older logic to perish of formality and inanition. The
- successive departments of physical science, each in turn asserting its
- independence, finally left Natural Philosophy no alternative between
- clinging to its outworn hypotheses and abstract generalities, or
- identifying itself (as Newton in his great book put it) with the
- _Principia Mathematica_ of the physical sciences. Ethics, in its turn, saw
- itself, on one hand, replaced by psychological inquiries into the
- relations between the feelings and the will and the intelligence; while,
- on the other hand, a host of social, historical, economical, and other
- researches cut it off from the real facts of human life, and left it no
- more than the endless debates on the logical and metaphysical issues
- involved in free-will and conscience, duty and merit.
- It has sometimes been said that Kant settled this controversy between the
- old departments of philosophy and the new branches of science. And the
- settlement, it is implied, consisted in assigning to the philosopher a
- sort of police and patrol duty in the commonwealth of science. He was to
- see that boundaries were duly respected, and that each science kept
- strictly to its own business. For this purpose each branch of philosophy
- was bound to convert itself into a department of criticism—an examination
- of first principles in the several provinces of reality or experience—with
- a view to get a distinct conception of what they were, and thus define
- exactly the lines on which the structures of more detailed science could
- be put up solidly and safely. This plan offered tempting lines to
- research, and sounded well. But on further reflection there emerge one or
- two difficulties, hard to get over. Paradoxical though it may seem, one
- cannot rightly estimate the capacity and range of foundations, before one
- has had some familiarity with the buildings erected upon them. Thus you
- are involved in a circle: a circle which is probably inevitable, but which
- for that reason it is well to recognise at once. Then—what is only another
- way of saying the same thing—it is impossible to draw an inflexible line
- between premises of principle and conclusions of detail. There is no spot
- at which criticism can stop, and, having done its business well, hand on
- the remaining task to dogmatic system. It was an instinctive feeling of
- this implication of system in what professed only to be criticism which
- led the aged Kant to ignore his own previous professions that he offered
- as yet no system, and when Fichte maintained himself to be erecting the
- fabric for which Kant had prepared the ground, to reply by the
- counter-declaration that the criticism was the system—that “the curtain
- was the picture.”
- The Hegelian philosophy is an attempt to combine criticism with system,
- and thus realise what Kant had at least foretold. It is a system which is
- self-critical, and systematic only through the absoluteness of its
- criticism. In Hegel’s own phrase, it is an immanent and an incessant
- dialectic, which from first to last allows finality to no dogmatic rest,
- but carries out Kant’s description of an Age of Criticism, in which
- nothing, however majestic and sacred its authority, can plead for
- exception from the all-testing _Elenchus_. Then, on the other hand, Hegel
- refuses to restrict philosophy and its branches to anything short of the
- totality. He takes in its full sense that often-used phrase—the Unity of
- Knowledge. Logic becomes the all-embracing research of “first
- principles,”—the principles which regulate physics and ethics. The old
- divisions between logic and metaphysic, between induction and deduction,
- between theory of reasoning and theory of knowledge,—divisions which those
- who most employed them were never able to show the reason and purpose
- of—because indeed they had grown up at various times and by “natural
- selection” through a vast mass of incidents: these are superseded and
- merged in one continuous theory of real knowledge considered under its
- abstract or formal aspect,—of organised and known reality in its
- underlying thought-system. But these first principles were only an
- abstraction from complete reality—the reality which nature has when
- unified by mind—and they presuppose the total from which they are derived.
- The realm of pure thought is only the ghost of the Idea—of the unity and
- reality of knowledge, and it must be reindued with its flesh and blood.
- The logical world is (in Kantian phrase) only the _possibility_ of Nature
- and Mind. It comes first—because it is a system of First Principles: but
- these first principles could only be elicited by a philosophy which has
- realised the meaning of a mental experience, gathered by interpreting the
- facts of Nature.
- Natural Philosophy is no longer—according to Hegel’s view of it—merely a
- scheme of mathematical ground-work. That may be its first step. But its
- scope is a complete unity (which is not a mere aggregate) of the branches
- of natural knowledge, exploring both the inorganic and the organic world.
- In dealing with this endless problem, philosophy seems to be baulked by an
- impregnable obstacle to its progress. Every day the advance of
- specialisation renders any comprehensive or synoptic view of the totality
- of science more and more impossible. No doubt we talk readily enough of
- Science. But here, if anywhere, we may say there is no Science, but only
- sciences. The generality of science is a proud fiction or a gorgeous
- dream, variously told and interpreted according to the varying interest
- and proclivity of the scientist. The sciences, or those who specially
- expound them, know of no unity, no philosophy of science. They are content
- to remark that in these days the thing is impossible, and to pick out the
- faults in any attempts in that direction that are made outside their pale.
- Unfortunately for this contention, the thing is done by us all, and,
- indeed, has to be done. If not as men of science, yet as men—as human
- beings—we have to put together things and form some total estimate of the
- drift of development, of the unity of nature. To get a notion, not merely
- of the general methods and principles of the sciences, but of their
- results and teachings, and to get this not as a mere lot of fragments, but
- with a systematic unity, is indispensable in some degree for all rational
- life. The life not founded on science is not the life of man. But he will
- not find what he wants in the text-books of the specialist, who is obliged
- to treat his subject, as Plato says, “under the pressure of necessity,”
- and who dare not look on it in its quality “to draw the soul towards
- truth, and to form the philosophic intellect so as to uplift what we now
- unduly keep down(1).” If the philosopher in this province does his work
- but badly, he may plead the novelty of the task to which he comes as a
- pioneer or even an architect. He finds little that he can directly
- utilise. The materials have been gathered and prepared for very special
- aims; and the great aim of science—that human life may be made a higher,
- an ampler, and happier thing,—has hardly been kept in view at all, except
- in its more materialistic aspects. To the philosopher the supreme interest
- of the physical sciences is that man also belongs to the physical
- universe, or that Mind and Matter as we know them are (in Mr. Spencer’s
- language) “at once antithetical and inseparable.” He wants to find the
- place of Man,—but of Man as Mind—in Nature.
- If the scope of Natural Philosophy be thus expanded to make it the unity
- and more than the synthetic aggregate of the several physical sciences—to
- make it the whole which surpasses the addition of all their fragments, the
- purpose of Ethics has not less to be deepened and widened. Ethics, under
- that title, Hegel knows not. And for those who cannot recognise anything
- unless it be clearly labelled, it comes natural to record their censure of
- Hegelianism for ignoring or disparaging ethical studies. But if we take
- the word in that wide sense which common usage rather justifies than
- adopts, we may say that the whole philosophy of Mind is a moral
- philosophy. Its subject is the moral as opposed to the physical aspect of
- reality: the inner and ideal life as opposed to the merely external and
- real materials of it: the world of intelligence and of humanity. It
- displays Man in the several stages of that process by which he expresses
- the full meaning of nature, or discharges the burden of that task which is
- implicit in him from the first. It traces the steps of that growth by
- which what was no better than a fragment of nature—an intelligence located
- (as it seemed) in one piece of matter—comes to realise the truth of it and
- of himself. That truth is his ideal and his obligation: but it is
- also—such is the mystery of his birthright—his idea and possession.
- He—like the natural universe—is (as the _Logic_ has shown) a principle of
- unification, organisation, idealisation: and his history (in its ideal
- completeness) is the history of the process by which he, the typical man,
- works the fragments of reality (and such mere reality must be always a
- collection of fragments) into the perfect unity of a many-sided character.
- Thus the philosophy of mind, beginning with man as a sentient organism,
- the focus in which the universe gets its first dim confused expression
- through mere feeling, shows how he “erects himself above himself” and
- realises what ancient thinkers called his kindred with the divine.
- In that total process of the mind’s liberation and self-realisation the
- portion specially called Morals is but one, though a necessary, stage.
- There are, said Porphyry and the later Platonists, four degrees in the
- path of perfection and self-accomplishment. And first, there is the career
- of honesty and worldly prudence, which makes the duty of the citizen.
- Secondly, there is the progress in purity which casts earthly things
- behind, and reaches the angelic height of passionless serenity. And the
- third step is the divine life which by intellectual energy is turned to
- behold the truth of things. Lastly, in the fourth grade, the mind, free
- and sublime in self-sustaining wisdom, makes itself an “exemplar” of
- virtue, and is even a “father of Gods.” Even so, it may be said, the human
- mind is the subject of a complicated Teleology,—the field ruled by a
- multifarious Ought, psychological, aesthetical, social and religious. To
- adjust their several claims cannot be the object of any science, if
- adjustment means to supply a guide in practice. But it is the purpose of
- such a teleology to show that social requirements and moral duty as
- ordinarily conceived do not exhaust the range of obligation,—of the
- supreme ethical Ought. How that can best be done is however a question of
- some difficulty. For the ends under examination do not fall completely
- into a serial order, nor does one involve others in such a way as to
- destroy their independence. You cannot absolve psychology as if it stood
- independent of ethics or religion, nor can aesthetic considerations merely
- supervene on moral. Still, it may be said, the order followed by Hegel
- seems on the whole liable to fewer objections than others.
- Mr. Herbert Spencer, the only English philosopher who has even attempted a
- _System_ of Philosophy, may in this point be compared with Hegel. He also
- begins with a _First Principles_,—a work which, like Hegel’s _Logic_,
- starts by presenting Philosophy as the supreme arbiter between the
- subordinate principles of Religion and Science, which are in it “necessary
- correlatives.” The positive task of philosophy is (with some inconsistency
- or vagueness) presented, in the next place, as a “unification of
- knowledge.” Such a unification has to make explicit the implicit unity of
- known reality: because “every thought involves a whole system of
- thoughts.” And such a programme might again suggest the Logic. But
- unfortunately Mr. Spencer does not (and he has Francis Bacon to justify
- him here) think it worth his while to toil up the weary, but necessary,
- mount of Purgatory which is known to us as Logic. With a naïve realism, he
- builds on Cause and Power, and above all on Force, that “Ultimate of
- Ultimates,” which seems to be, however marvellously, a denizen both of the
- Known and the Unknowable world. In the known world this Ultimate appears
- under two forms, matter and motion, and the problem of science and
- philosophy is to lay down in detail and in general the law of their
- continuous redistribution, of the segregation of motion from matter, and
- the inclusion of motion into matter.
- Of this process, which has no beginning and no end,—the rhythm of
- generation and corruption, attraction and repulsion, it may be said that
- it is properly not a first principle of all knowledge, but the general or
- fundamental portion of Natural Philosophy to which Mr. Spencer next
- proceeds. Such a philosophy, however, he gives only in part: viz. as a
- Biology, dealing with organic (and at a further stage and under other
- names, with supra-organic) life. And that the Philosophy of Nature should
- take this form, and carry both the First Principles and the later portions
- of the system with it, as parts of a philosophy of evolution, is what we
- should have expected from the contemporaneous interests of science(2).
- Even a one-sided attempt to give speculative unity to those researches,
- which get—for reasons the scientific specialist seldom asks—the title of
- biological, is however worth noting as a recognition of the necessity of a
- _Natur-philosophie_,—a speculative science of Nature.
- The third part of the Hegelian System corresponds to what in the
- _Synthetic Philosophy_ is known as Psychology, Ethics, and Sociology. And
- here Mr. Spencer recognises that something new has turned up. Psychology
- is “unique” as a science: it is a “double science,” and as a whole quite
- _sui generis_. Whether perhaps all these epithets would not, _mutatis
- mutandis_, have to be applied also to Ethics and Sociology, if these are
- to do their full work, he does not say. In what this doubleness consists
- he even finds it somewhat difficult to show. For, as his fundamental
- philosophy does not on this point go beyond noting some pairs of verbal
- antitheses, and has no sense of unity except in the imperfect shape of a
- “relation(3)” between two things which are “antithetical and inseparable,”
- he is perplexed by phrases such as “in” and “out of” consciousness, and
- stumbles over the equivocal use of “inner” to denote both mental (or
- non-spatial) in general, and locally sub-cuticular in special. Still, he
- gets so far as to see that the law of consciousness is that in it neither
- feelings nor relations have independent subsistence, and that the unit of
- mind does not begin till what he calls two feelings are made one. The
- phraseology may be faulty, but it shows an inkling of the _a priori_.
- Unfortunately it is apparently forgotten; and the language too often
- reverts into the habit of what he calls the “objective,” i.e. purely
- physical, sciences.
- Mr. Spencer’s conception of Psychology restricts it to the more general
- physics of the mind. For its more concrete life he refers us to Sociology.
- But his Sociology is yet unfinished: and from the plan of its inception,
- and the imperfect conception of the ends and means of its investigation,
- hardly admits of completion in any systematic sense. To that incipiency is
- no doubt due its excess in historical or anecdotal detail—detail, however,
- too much segregated from its social context, and in general its tendency
- to neglect normal and central theory for incidental and peripheral facts.
- Here, too, there is a weakness in First Principles and a love of
- catchwords, which goes along with the fallacy that illustration is proof.
- Above all, it is evident that the great fact of religion overhangs Mr.
- Spencer with the attraction of an unsolved and unacceptable problem. He
- cannot get the religious ideas of men into co-ordination with their
- scientific, aesthetic, and moral doctrines; and only betrays his sense of
- the high importance of the former by placing them in the forefront of
- inquiry, as due to the inexperience and limitations of the so-called
- primitive man. That is hardly adequate recognition of the religious
- principle: and the defect will make itself seriously felt, should he ever
- come to carry out the further stage of his prospectus dealing with “the
- growth and correlation of language, knowledge, morals, and aesthetics.”
- (ii.) Mind and Morals.
- A Mental Philosophy—if we so put what might also be rendered a Spiritual
- Philosophy, or Philosophy of Spirit—may to an English reader suggest
- something much narrower than it actually contains. A Philosophy of the
- Human Mind—if we consult English specimens—would not imply much more than
- a psychology, and probably what is called an inductive psychology. But as
- Hegel understands it, it covers an unexpectedly wide range of topics, the
- whole range from Nature to Spirit. Besides Subjective Mind, which would
- seem on first thoughts to exhaust the topics of psychology, it goes on to
- Mind as Objective, and finally to Absolute mind. And such combinations of
- words may sound either self-contradictory or meaningless.
- The first Section deals with the range of what is usually termed
- Psychology. That term indeed is employed by Hegel, in a restricted sense,
- to denote the last of the three sub-sections in the discussion of
- Subjective Mind. The Mind, which is the topic of psychology proper, cannot
- be assumed as a ready-made object, or datum. A Self, a self-consciousness,
- an intelligent and volitional agent, if it be the birthright of man, is a
- birthright which he has to realise for himself, to earn and to make his
- own. To trace the steps by which mind in its stricter acceptation, as will
- and intelligence, emerges from the general animal sensibility which is the
- crowning phase of organic life, and the final problem of biology, is the
- work of two preliminary sub-sections—the first entitled _Anthropology_,
- the second the _Phenomenology of Mind_.
- The subject of Anthropology, as Hegel understands it, is the Soul—the raw
- material of consciousness, the basis of all higher mental life. This is a
- borderland, where the ground is still debateable between Nature and Mind:
- it is the region of feeling, where the sensibility has not yet been
- differentiated to intelligence. Soul and body are here, as the phrase
- goes, in communion: the inward life is still imperfectly disengaged from
- its natural co-physical setting. Still one with nature, it submits to
- natural influences and natural vicissitudes: is not as yet master of
- itself, but the half-passive receptacle of a foreign life, of a general
- vitality, of a common soul not yet fully differentiated into
- individuality. But it is awaking to self-activity: it is emerging to
- Consciousness,—to distinguish itself, as aware and conscious, from the
- facts of life and sentiency of which it is aware.
- From this region of psychical physiology or physiological psychology,
- Hegel in the second sub-section of his first part takes us to the
- “Phenomenology of Mind,”—to Consciousness. The sentient soul is also
- conscious—but in a looser sense of that word(4): it has feelings, but can
- scarcely be said _itself_ to know that it has them. As consciousness, the
- Soul has come to separate what it is from what it feels. The distinction
- emerges of a subject which is conscious, and an object _of_ which it is
- conscious. And the main thing is obviously the relationship between the
- two, or the Consciousness itself, as tending to distinguish itself alike
- from its subject and its object. Hence, perhaps, may be gathered why it is
- called Phenomenology of Mind. Mind as yet is not yet more than emergent or
- apparent: nor yet self-possessed and self-certified. No longer, however,
- one with the circumambient nature which it feels, it sees itself set
- against it, but only as a passive recipient of it, a _tabula rasa_ on
- which external nature is reflected, or to which phenomena are presented.
- No longer, on the other hand, a mere passive instrument of suggestion from
- without, its instinct of life, its _nisus_ of self-assertion is developed,
- through antagonism to a like _nisus_, into the consciousness of self-hood,
- of a Me and Mine as set against a Thee and Thine. But just in proportion
- as it is so developed in opposition to and recognition of other equally
- self-centred selves, it has passed beyond the narrower characteristic of
- Consciousness proper. It is no longer mere intelligent perception or
- reproduction of a world, but it is life, with perception (or apperception)
- of that life. It has returned in a way to its original unity with nature,
- but it is now the sense of its self-hood—the consciousness of itself as
- the focus in which subjective and objective are at one. Or, to put it in
- the language of the great champion of Realism(5), the standpoint of Reason
- or full-grown Mind is this: “The world which appears to us is our percept,
- therefore in us. The real world, out of which we explain the phenomenon,
- is our thought: therefore in us.”
- The third sub-section of the theory of Subjective Mind—the Psychology
- proper—deals with Mind. This is the real, independent Psyché—hence the
- special appropriation of the term Psychology. “The Soul,” says Herbart,
- “no doubt dwells in a body: there are, moreover, corresponding states of
- the one and the other: but nothing corporeal occurs in the Soul, nothing
- purely mental, which we could reckon to our Ego, occurs in the body: the
- affections of the body are no representations of the Ego, and our pleasant
- and unpleasant feelings do not immediately lie in the organic life they
- favour or hinder.” Such a Soul, so conceived, is an intelligent and
- volitional self, a being of intellectual and “active” powers or phenomena:
- it is a Mind. And “Mind,” adds Hegel(6), “is just this elevation above
- Nature and physical modes and above the complication with an external
- object.” Nothing is _external_ to it: it is rather the internalising of
- all externality. In this psychology proper, we are out of any immediate
- connexion with physiology. “Psychology as such,” remarks Herbart, “has its
- questions common to it with Idealism”—with the doctrine that all reality
- is mental reality. It traces, in Hegel’s exposition of it, the steps of
- the way by which mind realises that independence which is its
- characteristic stand-point. On the intellectual side that independence is
- assured in language,—the system of signs by which the intelligence stamps
- external objects as its own, made part of its inner world. A science, some
- one has said, is after all only _une langue bien faite_. So, reversing the
- saying, we may note that a language is an inwardised and mind-appropriated
- world. On the active side, the independence of mind is seen in
- self-enjoyment, in happiness, or self-content, where impulse and volition
- have attained satisfaction in equilibrium, and the soul possesses itself
- in fullness. Such a mind(7), which has made the world its certified
- possession in language, and which enjoys itself in self-possession of
- soul, called happiness, is a free Mind. And that is the highest which
- Subjective Mind can reach.
- At this point, perhaps, having rounded off by a liberal sweep the scope of
- psychology, the ordinary mental philosophy would stop. Hegel, instead of
- finishing, now goes on to the field of what he calls Objective Mind. For
- as yet it has been only the story of a preparation, an inward adorning and
- equipment, and we have yet to see what is to come of it in actuality. Or
- rather, we have yet to consider the social forms on which this preparation
- rests. The mind, self-possessed and sure of itself or free, is so only
- through the objective shape which its main development runs parallel with.
- An intelligent Will, or a practical reason, was the last word of the
- psychological development. But a reason which is practical, or a volition
- which is intelligent, is realised by action which takes regular shapes,
- and by practice which transforms the world. The theory of Objective Mind
- delineates the new form which nature assumes under the sway of
- intelligence and will. That intellectual world realises itself by
- transforming the physical into a social and political world, the given
- natural conditions of existence into a freely-instituted system of life,
- the primitive struggle of kinds for subsistence into the ordinances of the
- social state. Given man as a being possessed of will and intelligence,
- this inward faculty, whatever be its degree, will try to impress itself on
- nature and to reproduce itself in a legal, a moral, and social world. The
- kingdom of deed replaces, or rises on the foundation of, the kingdom of
- word: and instead of the equilibrium of a well-adjusted soul comes the
- harmonious life of a social organism. We are, in short, in the sphere of
- Ethics and Politics, of Jurisprudence and Morals, of Law and Conscience.
- Here,—as always in Hegel’s system—there is a triad of steps. First the
- province of Law or Right. But if we call it Law, we must keep out of sight
- the idea of a special law-giver, of a conscious imposition of laws, above
- all by a political superior. And if we call it Right, we must remember
- that it is neutral, inhuman, abstract right: the right whose principle is
- impartial and impassive uniformity, equality, order;—not moral right, or
- the equity which takes cognisance of circumstances, of personal claims,
- and provides against its own hardness. The intelligent will of Man,
- throwing itself upon the mere gifts of nature as their appointed master,
- creates the world of Property—of things instrumental, and regarded as
- adjectival, to the human personality. But the autonomy of Reason (which is
- latent in the will) carries with it certain consequences. As it acts, it
- also, by its inherent quality of uniformity or universality, enacts for
- itself a law and laws, and creates the realm of formal equality or
- order-giving law. But this is a _mere_ equality: which is not inconsistent
- with what in other respects may be excess of inequality. What one does, if
- it is really to be treated as done, others may or even must do: each act
- creates an expectation of continuance and uniformity of behaviour. The
- doer is bound by it, and others are entitled to do the like. The material
- which the person appropriates creates a system of obligation. Thus is
- constituted—in the natural give and take of rational Wills—in the
- inevitable course of human action and reaction,—a system of rights and
- duties. This law of equality—the basis of justice, and the seed of
- benevolence—is the scaffolding or perhaps rather the rudimentary framework
- of society and moral life. Or it is the bare skeleton which is to be
- clothed upon by the softer and fuller outlines of the social tissues and
- the ethical organs.
- And thus the first range of Objective Mind postulates the second, which
- Hegel calls “Morality.” The word is to be taken in its strict sense as a
- protest against the quasi-physical order of law. It is the morality of
- conscience and of the good will, of the inner rectitude of soul and
- purpose, as all-sufficient and supreme. Here is brought out the
- complementary factor in social life: the element of liberty, spontaneity,
- self-consciousness. The motto of mere inward morality (as opposed to the
- spirit of legality) is (in Kant’s words): “There is nothing without
- qualification good, in heaven or earth, but only a good will.” The
- essential condition of goodness is that the action be done with purpose
- and intelligence, and in full persuasion of its goodness by the conscience
- of the agent. The characteristic of Morality thus described is its
- essential inwardness, and the sovereignty of the conscience over all
- heteronomy. Its justification is that it protests against the authority of
- a mere external or objective order, subsisting and ruling in separation
- from the subjectivity. Its defect is the turn it gives to this assertion
- of the rights of subjective conscience: briefly in the circumstance that
- it tends to set up a mere individualism against a mere universalism,
- instead of realising the unity and essential interdependence of the two.
- The third sub-section of the theory of Objective Mind describes a state of
- affairs in which this antithesis is explicitly overcome. This is the moral
- life in a social community. Here law and usage prevail and provide the
- fixed permanent scheme of life: but the law and the usage are, in their
- true or ideal conception, only the unforced expression of the mind and
- will of those who live under them. And, on the other hand, the mind and
- will of the individual members of such a community are pervaded and
- animated by its universal spirit. In such a community, and so constituting
- it, the individual is at once free and equal, and that because of the
- spirit of fraternity, which forms its spiritual link. In the world
- supposed to be governed by mere legality the idea of right is exclusively
- prominent; and when that is the case, it may often happen that _summum jus
- summa injuria_. In mere morality, the stress falls exclusively on the idea
- of inward freedom, or the necessity of the harmony of the judgment and the
- will, or the dependence of conduct upon conscience. In the union of the
- two, in the moral community as normally constituted, the mere idea of
- right is replaced, or controlled and modified, by the idea of equity—a
- balance as it were between the two preceding, inasmuch as motive and
- purpose are employed to modify and interpret strict right. But this
- effect—this harmonisation—is brought about by the predominance of a new
- idea—the principle of benevolence,—a principle however which is itself
- modified by the fundamental idea of right or law(8) into a wise or
- regulated kindliness.
- But what Hegel chiefly deals with under this head is the interdependence
- of form and content, of social order and personal progress. In the picture
- of an ethical organisation or harmoniously-alive moral community he shows
- us partly the underlying idea which gave room for the antithesis between
- law and conscience, and partly the outlines of the ideal in which that
- conflict becomes only the instrument of progress. This organisation has
- three grades or three typical aspects. These are the Family, Civil
- Society, and the State. The first of these, the Family, must be taken to
- include those primary unities of human life where the natural affinity of
- sex and the natural ties of parentage are the preponderant influence in
- forming and maintaining the social group. This, as it were, is the
- soul-nucleus of social organisation: where the principle of unity is an
- instinct, a feeling, an absorbing solidarity. Next comes what Hegel has
- called Civil Society,—meaning however by civil the antithesis to
- political, the society of those who may be styled _bourgeois_, not
- _citoyens_:—and meaning by society the antithesis to community. There are
- other natural influences binding men together besides those which form the
- close unities of the family, gens, tribe, or clan. Economical needs
- associate human beings within a much larger radius—in ways capable of
- almost indefinite expansion—but also in a way much less intense and deep.
- Civil Society is the more or less loosely organised aggregate of such
- associations, which, if, on one hand, they keep human life from stagnating
- in the mere family, on another, accentuate more sharply the tendency to
- competition and the struggle for life. Lastly, in the Political State
- comes the synthesis of family and society. Of the family; in so far as the
- State tends to develope itself on the nature-given unit of the Nation (an
- extended family, supplementing as need arises real descent by fictitious
- incorporations), and has apparently never permanently maintained itself
- except on the basis of a predominant common nationality. Of society; in so
- far as the extension and dispersion of family ties have left free room for
- the differentiation of many other sides of human interest and action, and
- given ground for the full development of individuality. In consequence of
- this, the State (and such a state as Hegel describes is essentially the
- idea or ideal of the modern State)(9) has a certain artificial air about
- it. It can only be maintained by the free action of intelligence: it must
- make its laws public: it must bring to consciousness the principles of its
- constitution, and create agencies for keeping up unity of organisation
- through the several separate provinces or contending social interests,
- each of which is inclined to insist on the right of home mis-rule.
- The State—which in its actuality must always be a quasi-national state—is
- thus the supreme unity of Nature and Mind. Its natural basis in land,
- language, blood, and the many ties which spring therefrom, has to be
- constantly raised into an intelligent unity through universal interests.
- But the elements of race and of culture have no essential connexion, and
- they perpetually incline to wrench themselves asunder. Blood and judgment
- are for ever at war in the state as in the individual(10): the
- cosmopolitan interest, to which the maxim is _Ubi bene, ibi patria_,
- resists the national, which adopts the patriotic watchword of Hector(11).
- The State however has another source of danger in the very principle that
- gave it birth. It arose through antagonism: it was baptised on the
- battlefield, and it only lives as it is able to assert itself against a
- foreign foe. And this circumstance tends to intensify and even pervert its
- natural basis of nationality:—tends to give the very conception of the
- political a negative and superficial look. But, notwithstanding all these
- drawbacks, the State in its Idea is entitled to the name Hobbes gave
- it,—the Mortal God. Here in a way culminates the obviously objective,—we
- may almost say, visible and tangible—development of Man and Mind. Here it
- attains a certain completeness—a union of reality and of ideality: a
- quasi-immortality, a quasi-universality. What the individual person could
- not do unaided, he can do in the strength of his commonwealth. Much that
- in the solitary was but implicit or potential, is in the State actualised.
- But the God of the State is a mortal God. It is but a national and a
- limited mind. To be actual, one must at least begin by restricting
- oneself. Or, rather actuality is rational, but always with a conditioned
- and a relative rationality(12): it is in the realm of action and
- re-action,—in the realm of change and nature. It has warring forces
- outside it,—warring forces inside it. Its unity is never perfect: because
- it never produces a true identity of interests within, or maintains an
- absolute independence without. Thus the true and real State—the State in
- its Idea—the realisation of concrete humanity,—of Mind as the fullness and
- unity of nature—is not reached in any single or historical State: but
- floats away, when we try to seize it, into the endless progress of
- history. Always indeed the State, the historical and objective, points
- beyond itself. It does so first in the succession of times. _Die
- Weltgeschichte ist das Weltgericht._(13) And in that doom of the world the
- eternal blast sweeps along the successive generations of the temporal, one
- expelling another from the stage of time—each because it is inadequate to
- the Idea which it tried to express, and has succumbed to an enemy from
- without because it was not a real and true unity within.
- But if temporal flees away before another temporal, it abides in so far as
- it has, however inadequately, given expression and visible reality—as it
- points inward and upward—to the eternal. The earthly state is also the
- city of God; and if the republic of Plato seems to find scant admission
- into the reality of flesh and blood, it stands eternal as a witness in the
- heaven of idea. Behind the fleeting succession of consulates and
- dictatures, of aristocracy and empire, feuds of plebeian with patrician,
- in that apparent anarchy of powers which the so-called Roman constitution
- is to the superficial observer, there is the eternal Rome, one, strong,
- victorious, _semper eadem_: the Rome of Virgil and Justinian, the ghost
- whereof still haunts with memories the seven-hilled city, but which with
- full spiritual presence lives in the law, the literature, the manners of
- the modern world. To find fitter expression for this Absolute Mind than it
- has in the Ethical community—to reach that reality of which the moral
- world is but one-sidedly representative—is the work of Art, Religion, and
- Philosophy. And to deal with these efforts to find the truth and the unity
- of Mind and Nature is the subject of Hegel’s third Section.
- (iii.) Religion and Philosophy.
- It may be well at this point to guard against a misconception of this
- serial order of exposition(14). As stage is seen to follow stage, the
- historical imagination, which governs our ordinary current of ideas, turns
- the logical dependence into a time-sequence. But it is of course not meant
- that the later stage follows the earlier in history. The later is the more
- real, and therefore the more fundamental. But we can only understand by
- abstracting and then transcending our abstractions, or rather by showing
- how the abstraction implies relations which force us to go further and
- beyond our arbitrary arrest. Each stage therefore either stands to that
- preceding it as an antithesis, which inevitably dogs its steps as an
- accusing spirit, or it is the conjunction of the original thesis with the
- antithesis, in a union which should not be called synthesis because it is
- a closer fusion and true marriage of minds. A truth and reality, though
- fundamental, is only appreciated at its true value and seen in all its
- force where it appears as the reconciliation and reunion of partial and
- opposing points of view. Thus, e.g., the full significance of the State
- does not emerge so long as we view it in isolation as a supposed single
- state, but only as it is seen in the conflict of history, in its actual
- “energy” as a world-power among powers, always pointing beyond itself to a
- something universal which it fain would be, and yet cannot be. Or, again,
- there never was a civil or economic society which existed save under the
- wing of a state, or in one-sided assumption of state powers to itself: and
- a family is no isolated and independent unit belonging to a supposed
- patriarchal age, but was always mixed up with, and in manifold dependence
- upon, political and civil combinations. The true family, indeed, far from
- preceding the state in time, presupposes the political power to give it
- its precise sphere and its social stability: as is well illustrated by
- that typical form of it presented in the Roman state.
- So, again, religion does not supervene upon an already existing political
- and moral system and invest it with an additional sanction. The true order
- would be better described as the reverse. The real basis of social life,
- and even of intelligence, is religion. As some thinkers quaintly put it,
- the known rests and lives on the bosom of the Unknowable. But when we say
- that, we must at once guard against a misconception. There are religions
- of all sorts; and some of them which are most heard of in the modern world
- only exist or survive in the shape of a traditional name and venerated
- creed which has lost its power. Nor is a religion necessarily committed to
- a definite conception of a supernatural—of a personal power outside the
- order of Nature. But in all cases, religion is a faith and a theory which
- gives unity to the facts of life, and gives it, not because the unity is
- in detail proved or detected, but because life and experience in their
- deepest reality inexorably demand and evince such a unity to the heart.
- The religion of a time is not its nominal creed, but its dominant
- conviction of the meaning of reality, the principle which animates all its
- being and all its striving, the faith it has in the laws of nature and the
- purpose of life. Dimly or clearly felt and perceived, religion has for its
- principle (one cannot well say, its object) not the unknowable, but the
- inner unity of life and knowledge, of act and consciousness, a unity which
- is certified in its every knowledge, but is never fully demonstrable by
- the summation of all its ascertained items. As such a felt and believed
- synthesis of the world and life, religion is the unity which gives
- stability and harmony to the social sphere; just as morality in its turn
- gives a partial and practical realisation to the ideal of religion. But
- religion does not merely establish and sanction morality; it also frees it
- from a certain narrowness it always has, as of the earth. Or, otherwise
- put, morality has to the keener inspection something in it which is more
- than the mere moral injunction at first indicates. Beyond the moral, in
- its stricter sense, as the obligatory duty and the obedience to law, rises
- and expands the beautiful and the good: a beautiful which is
- disinterestedly loved, and a goodness which has thrown off all utilitarian
- relativity, and become a free self-enhancing joy. The true spirit of
- religion sees in the divine judgment not a mere final sanction to human
- morality which has failed of its earthly close, not the re-adjustment of
- social and political judgments in accordance with our more conscientious
- inner standards, but a certain, though, for our part-by-part vision,
- incalculable proportion between what is done and suffered. And in this
- liberation of the moral from its restrictions, Art renders no slight aid.
- Thus in different ways, religion presupposes morality to fill up its
- vacant form, and morality presupposes religion to give its laws an
- ultimate sanction, which at the same time points beyond their limitations.
- But art, religion, and philosophy still rest on the national culture and
- on the individual mind. However much they rise in the heights of the ideal
- world, they never leave the reality of life and circumstance behind, and
- float in the free empyrean. Yet there are degrees of universality, degrees
- in which they reach what they promised. As the various psychical _nuclei_
- of an individual consciousness tend through the course of experience to
- gather round a central idea and by fusion and assimilation form a complete
- mental organisation; so, through the march of history, there grows up a
- complication and a fusion of national ideas and aspirations, which, though
- still retaining the individuality and restriction of a concrete national
- life, ultimately present an organisation social, aesthetic, and religious
- which is a type of humanity in its universality and completeness. Always
- moving in the measure and on the lines of the real development of its
- social organisation, the art and religion of a nation tend to give
- expression to what social and political actuality at its best but
- imperfectly sets in existence. They come more and more to be, not mere
- competing fragments as set side by side with those of others, but
- comparatively equal and complete representations of the many-sided and
- many-voiced reality of man and the world. Yet always they live and
- flourish in reciprocity with the fullness of practical institutions and
- individual character. An abstractly universal art and religion is a
- delusion—until all diversities of geography and climate, of language and
- temperament, have been made to disappear. If these energies are in power
- and reality and not merely in name, they cannot be applied like a panacea
- or put on like a suit of ready-made clothes. If alive, they grow with
- individualised type out of the social situation: and they can only attain
- a vulgar and visible universality, so far as they attach themselves to
- some simple and uniform aspects,—a part tolerably identical everywhere—in
- human nature in all times and races.
- Art, according to Hegel’s account, is the first of the three expressions
- of Absolute Mind. But the key-note to the whole is to be found in
- Religion(15): or Religion is the generic description of that phase of mind
- which has found rest in the fullness of attainment and is no longer a
- struggle and a warfare, but a fruition. “It is the conviction of all
- nations,” he says(16), “that in the religious consciousness they hold
- their truth; and they have always regarded religion as their dignity and
- as the Sunday of their life. Whatever excites our doubts and alarms, all
- grief and all anxiety, all that the petty fields of finitude can offer to
- attract us, we leave behind on the shoals of time: and as the traveller on
- the highest peak of a mountain range, removed from every distinct view of
- the earth’s surface, quietly lets his vision neglect all the restrictions
- of the landscape and the world; so in this pure region of faith man,
- lifted above the hard and inflexible reality, sees it with his mind’s eye
- reflected in the rays of the mental sun to an image where its discords,
- its lights and shades, are softened to eternal calm. In this region of
- mind flow the waters of forgetfulness, from which Psyche drinks, and in
- which she drowns all her pain: and the darknesses of this life are here
- softened to a dream-image, and transfigured into a mere setting for the
- splendours of the Eternal.’”
- If we take Religion, in this extended sense, we find it is the sense, the
- vision, the faith, the certainty of the eternal in the changeable, of the
- infinite in the finite, of the reality in appearance, of the truth in
- error. It is freedom from the distractions and pre-occupations of the
- particular details of life; it is the sense of permanence, repose,
- certainty, rounding off, toning down and absorbing the vicissitude, the
- restlessness, the doubts of actual life. Such a victory over palpable
- reality has no doubt its origin—its embryology—in phases of mind which
- have been already discussed in the first section. Religion will vary
- enormously according to the grade of national mood of mind and social
- development in which it emerges. But whatever be the peculiarities of its
- original swaddling-clothes, its cardinal note will be a sense of
- dependence on, and independence in, something more permanent, more august,
- more of a surety and stay than visible and variable nature and
- man,—something also which whether God or devil, or both in one, holds the
- keys of life and death, of weal and woe, and holds them from some safe
- vantage-ground above the lower realms of change. By this central being the
- outward and the inward, past and present and to come, are made one. And as
- already indicated, Religion, emerging, as it does, from social man, from
- mind ethical, will retain traces of the two _foci_ in society: the
- individual subjectivity and the objective community. Retain them however
- only as traces, which still show in the actually envisaged reconciliation.
- For that is what religion does to morality. It carries a step higher the
- unity or rather combination gained in the State: it is the fuller harmony
- of the individual and the collectivity. The moral conscience rests in
- certainty and fixity on the religious.
- But Religion (thus widely understood as the faith in sempiternal and
- all-explaining reality) at first appears under a guise of Art. The poem
- and the pyramid, the temple-image and the painting, the drama and the
- fairy legend, these are religion: but they are, perhaps, religion as Art.
- And that means that they present the eternal under sensible
- representations, the work of an artist, and in a perishable material of
- limited range. Yet even the carvers of a long-past day whose works have
- been disinterred from the plateaux of Auvergne knew that they gave to the
- perishable life around them a quasi-immortality: and the myth-teller of a
- savage tribe elevated the incident of a season into a perennial power of
- love and fear. The cynic may remind us that from the finest picture of the
- artist, readily
- “We turn
- To yonder girl that fords the burn.”
- And yet it may be said in reply to the cynic that, had it not been for the
- deep-imprinted lesson of the artist, it would have been but a brutal
- instinct that would have drawn our eyes. The artist, the poet, the
- musician, reveal the meaning, the truth, the reality of the world: they
- teach us, they help us, backward younger brothers, to see, to hear, to
- feel what our rude senses had failed to detect. They enact the miracle of
- the loaves and fishes, again and again: out of the common limited things
- of every day they produce a bread of life in which the generations
- continue to find nourishment.
- But if Art embodies for us the unseen and the eternal, it embodies it in
- the stone, the colour, the tone, and the word: and these are by themselves
- only dead matter. To the untutored eye and taste the finest
- picture-gallery is only a weariness: when the national life has drifted
- away, the sacred book and the image are but idols and enigmas. “The
- statues are now corpses from which the vivifying soul has fled, and the
- hymns are words whence faith has departed: the tables of the Gods are
- without spiritual meat and drink, and games and feasts no longer afford
- the mind its joyful union with the being of being. The works of the Muse
- lack that intellectual force which knew itself strong and real by crushing
- gods and men in its winepress. They are now (in this iron age) what they
- are for us,—fair fruits broken from the tree, and handed to us by a kindly
- destiny. But the gift is like the fruits which the girl in the picture
- presents: she does not give the real life of their existence, not the tree
- which bore them, not the earth and the elements which entered into their
- substance, nor the climate which formed their quality, nor the change of
- seasons which governed the process of their growth. Like her, Destiny in
- giving us the works of ancient art does not give us their world, not the
- spring and summer of the ethical life in which they blossomed and ripened,
- but solely a memory and a suggestion of this actuality. Our act in
- enjoying them, therefore, is not a Divine service: were it so, our mind
- would achieve its perfect and satisfying truth. All that we do is a mere
- externalism, which from these fruits wipes off some rain-drop, some speck
- of dust, and which, in place of the inward elements of moral actuality
- that created and inspired them, tries from the dead elements of their
- external reality, such as language and historical allusion, to set up a
- tedious mass of scaffolding, not in order to live ourselves into them, but
- only to form a picture of them in our minds. But as the girl who proffers
- the plucked fruits is more and nobler than the natural element with all
- its details of tree, air, light, &c. which first yielded them, because she
- gathers all this together, in a nobler way, into the glance of the
- conscious eye and the gesture which proffers them; so the spirit of
- destiny which offers us those works of art is more than the ethical life
- and actuality of the ancient people: for it is the inwardising of that
- mind which in them was still self-estranged and self-dispossessed:—it is
- the spirit of tragic destiny, the destiny which collects all those
- individualised gods and attributes of substance into the one Pantheon. And
- that temple of all the gods is Mind conscious of itself as mind(17).”
- Religion enters into its more adequate form when it ceases to appear in
- the guise of Art and realises that the kingdom of God is within, that the
- truth must be _felt_, the eternal _inwardly_ revealed, the holy one
- apprehended by _faith_(18), not by outward vision. Eye hath not seen, nor
- ear heard, the things of God. They cannot be presented, or delineated:
- they come only in the witness of the spirit. The human soul itself is the
- only worthy temple of the Most High, whom heaven, and the heaven of
- heavens, cannot contain. Here in truth God has come down to dwell with
- men; and the Son of Man, caught up in the effusion of the Spirit, can in
- all assurance and all humility claim that he is divinified. Here
- apparently Absolute Mind is reached: the soul knows no limitation, no
- struggle: in time it is already eternal. Yet, there is, according to
- Hegel, a flaw,—not in the essence and the matter, but in the manner and
- mode in which the ordinary religious consciousness represents to itself,
- or pictures that unification which it feels and experiences.
- “In religion then this unification of ultimate Being with the Self is
- implicitly reached. But the religious consciousness, if it has this
- symbolic idea of its reconciliation, still has it as a mere symbol or
- representation. It attains the satisfaction by tacking on to its pure
- negativity, and that externally, the positive signification of its unity
- with the ultimate Being: its satisfaction remains therefore tainted by the
- antithesis of another world. Its own reconciliation, therefore, is
- presented to its consciousness as something far away, something far away
- in the future: just as the reconciliation which the other Self
- accomplished appears as a far-away thing in the past. The one Divine Man
- had but an implicit father and only an actual mother; conversely the
- universal divine man, the community, has its own deed and knowledge for
- its father, but for its mother only the eternal Love, which it only
- _feels_, but does not _behold_ in its consciousness as an actual immediate
- object. Its reconciliation therefore is in its heart, but still at
- variance with its consciousness, and its actuality still has a flaw. In
- its field of consciousness the place of implicit reality or side of pure
- mediation is taken by the reconciliation that lies far away behind: the
- place of the actually present, or the side of immediacy and existence, is
- filled by the world which has still to wait for its transfiguration to
- glory. Implicitly no doubt the world is reconciled with the eternal Being;
- and that Being, it is well known, no longer looks upon the object as alien
- to it, but in its love sees it as like itself. But for self-consciousness
- this immediate presence is not yet set in the full light of mind. In its
- immediate consciousness accordingly the spirit of the community is parted
- from its religious: for while the religious consciousness declares that
- they are implicitly not parted, this implicitness is not raised to reality
- and not yet grown to absolute self-certainty(19).”
- Religion therefore, which as it first appeared in art-worship had yet to
- realise its essential inwardness or spirituality, so has now to overcome
- the antithesis in which its (the religious) consciousness stands to the
- secular. For the peculiarly religious type of mind is distinguished by an
- indifference and even hostility, more or less veiled, to art, to morality
- and the civil state, to science and to nature. Strong in the certainty of
- faith, or of its implicit rest in God, it resents too curious inquiry into
- the central mystery of its union, and in its distincter consciousness sets
- the foundation of faith on the evidence of a fact, which, however, it in
- the same breath declares to be unique and miraculous, the central event of
- the ages, pointing back in its reference to the first days of humanity,
- and forward in the future to the winding-up of the business of terrestrial
- life. Philosophy, according to Hegel’s conception of it, does but draw the
- conclusion supplied by the premisses of religion: it supplements and
- rounds off into coherence the religious implications. The unique events in
- Judea nearly nineteen centuries ago are for it also the first step in a
- new revelation of man’s relationship to God: but while it acknowledges the
- transcendent interest of that age, it lays main stress on the permanent
- truth then revealed, and it insists on the duty of carrying out the
- principle there awakened to all the depth and breadth of its explication.
- Its task—its supreme task—is to _explicate religion_. But to do so is to
- show that religion is no exotic, and no _mere_ revelation from an external
- source. It is to show that religion is the truth, the complete reality, of
- the mind that lived in Art, that founded the state and sought to be
- dutiful and upright: the truth, the crowning fruit of all scientific
- knowledge, of all human affections, of all secular consciousness. Its
- lesson ultimately is that there is nothing essentially common or unclean:
- that the holy is not parted off from the true and the good and the
- beautiful.
- Religion thus expanded descends from its abstract or “intelligible” world,
- to which it had retired from art and science, and the affairs of ordinary
- life. Its God—as a true God—is not of the dead alone, but also of the
- living: not a far-off supreme and ultimate Being, but also a man among
- men. Philosophy thus has to break down the middle partition-wall of life,
- the fence between secular and sacred. It is but religion come to its
- maturity, made at home in the world, and no longer a stranger and a
- wonder. Religion has pronounced in its inmost heart and faith of faith,
- that the earth is the Lord’s, and that day unto day shows forth the divine
- handiwork. But the heart of unbelief, of little faith, has hardly uttered
- the word, than it forgets its assurance and leans to the conviction that
- the prince of this world is the Spirit of Evil. The mood of Théodicée is
- also—but with a difference—the mood of philosophy. It asserts the ways of
- Providence: but its providence is not the God of the Moralist, or the
- ideal of the Artist, or rather is not these only, but also the Law of
- Nature, and more than that. Its aim is the Unity of History. The words
- have sometimes been lightly used to mean that events run on in one
- continuous flow, and that there are no abrupt, no ultimate beginnings,
- parting age from age. But the Unity of History in its full sense is beyond
- history: it is history “reduced” from the expanses of time to the eternal
- present: its thousand years made one day,—made even the glance of a
- moment. The theme of the Unity of History—in the full depth of unity and
- the full expanse of history—is the theme of Hegelian philosophy. It traces
- the process in which Mind has to be all-inclusive, self-upholding, one
- with the Eternal reality.
- “That process of the mind’s self-realisation” says Hegel in the close of
- his _Phenomenology_, “exhibits a lingering movement and succession of
- minds, a gallery of images, each of which, equipped with the complete
- wealth of mind, only seems to linger because the Self has to penetrate and
- to digest this wealth of its Substance. As its perfection consists in
- coming completely to _know_ what it _is_ (its substance), this knowledge
- is its self-involution in which it deserts its outward existence and
- surrenders its shape to recollection. Thus self-involved, it is sunk in
- the night of its self-consciousness: but in that night its vanished being
- is preserved, and that being, thus in idea preserved,—old, but now
- new-born of the spirit,—is the new sphere of being, a new world, a new
- phase of mind. In this new phase it has again to begin afresh and from the
- beginning, and again nurture itself to maturity from its own resources, as
- if for it all that preceded were lost, and it had learned nothing from the
- experience of the earlier minds. Yet is that recollection a preservation
- of experience: it is the quintessence, and in fact a higher form, of the
- substance. If therefore this new mind appears only to count on its own
- resources, and to start quite fresh and blank, it is at the same time on a
- higher grade that it starts. The intellectual and spiritual realm, which
- is thus constructed in actuality, forms a succession in time, where one
- mind relieved another of its watch, and each took over the kingdom of the
- world from the preceding. The purpose of that succession is to reveal the
- depth, and that depth is the absolute comprehension of mind: this
- revelation is therefore to uplift its depth, to spread it out in breadth,
- so negativing this self-involved Ego, wherein it is self-dispossessed or
- reduced to substance. But it is also its time: the course of time shows
- this dispossession itself dispossessed, and thus in its extension it is no
- less in its depth, the self. The way to that goal,—absolute
- self-certainty—or the mind knowing itself as mind—is the inwardising of
- the minds, as they severally are in themselves, and as they accomplish the
- organisation of their realm. Their conservation,—regarded on the side of
- its free and apparently contingent succession of fact—is history: on the
- side of their comprehended organisation, again, it is the science of
- mental phenomenology: the two together, comprehended history, form at once
- the recollection and the grave-yard of the absolute Mind, the actuality,
- truth, and certitude of his throne, apart from which he were lifeless and
- alone.”
- Such in brief outline—lingering most on the points where Hegel has here
- been briefest—is the range of the Philosophy of Mind. Its aim is to
- comprehend, not to explain: to put together in intelligent unity, not to
- analyse into a series of elements. For it psychology is not an analysis or
- description of mental phenomena, of laws of association, of the growth of
- certain powers and ideas, but a “comprehended history” of the formation of
- subjective mind, of the intelligent, feeling, willing self or ego. For it
- Ethics is part and only part of the great scheme or system of
- self-development; but continuing into greater concreteness the normal
- endowment of the individual mind, and but preparing the ground on which
- religion may be most effectively cultivated. And finally Religion itself,
- released from its isolation and other-world sacrosanctity, is shown to be
- only the crown of life, the ripest growth of actuality, and shown to be so
- by philosophy, whilst it is made clear that religion is the basis of
- philosophy, or that a philosophy can only go as far as the religious
- stand-point allows. The hierarchy, if so it be called, of the spiritual
- forces is one where none can stand alone, or claim an abstract and
- independent supremacy. The truth of egoism is the truth of altruism: the
- truly moral is the truly religious: and each is not what it professes to
- be unless it anticipate the later, or include the earlier.
- (iv.) Mind or Spirit.
- It may be said, however, that for such a range of subjects the term Mind
- is wretchedly inadequate and common-place, and that the better rendering
- of the title would be Philosophy of Spirit. It may be admitted that Mind
- is not all that could be wished. But neither is Spirit blameless. And, it
- may be added, Hegel’s own term _Geist_ has to be unduly strained to cover
- so wide a region. It serves—and was no doubt meant to serve—as a sign of
- the conformity of his system with the religion which sees in God no
- other-world being, but our very self and mind, and which worships him in
- spirit and in truth. And if the use of a word like this could allay the
- “ancient variance” between the religious and the philosophic mood, it
- would be but churlish perhaps to refuse the sign of compliance and
- compromise. But whatever may be the case in German,—and even there the new
- wine was dangerous to the old wine-skin—it is certain that to average
- English ears the word Spiritual would carry us over the medium line into
- the proper land of religiosity. And to do that, as we have seen, is to sin
- against the central idea: the idea that religion is of one blood with the
- whole mental family, though the most graciously complete of all the
- sisters. Yet, however the word may be chosen, the philosophy of Hegel,
- like the august lady who appeared in vision to the emprisoned Boëthius,
- has on her garment a sign which “signifies the life which is on earth,” as
- also a sign which signifies the “right law of heaven”; if her right-hand
- holds the “book of the justice of the King omnipotent,” the sceptre in her
- left is “corporal judgment against sin(20).”
- There is indeed no sufficient reason for contemning the term Mind. If
- Inductive Philosophy of the Human Mind has—perhaps to a dainty taste—made
- the word unsavoury, that is no reason for refusing to give it all the
- wealth of soul and heart, of intellect and will. The _mens aeterna_ which,
- if we hear Tacitus, expressed the Hebrew conception of the spirituality of
- God, and the Νοῦς which Aristotelianism set supreme in the Soul, are not
- the mere or abstract intelligence, which late-acquired habits of
- abstraction have made out of them. If the reader will adopt the term (in
- want of a better) in its widest scope, we may shelter ourselves under the
- example of Wordsworth. His theme is—as he describes it in the
- _Recluse_—“the Mind and Man”: his
- “voice proclaims
- How exquisitely the individual Mind
- (And the progressive powers perhaps no less
- Of the whole species) to the external World
- Is fitted;—and how exquisitely too
- The external World is fitted to the Mind;
- And the creation (by no lower name
- Can it be called) which they with blended might
- Accomplish.”
- The verse which expounds that “high argument” speaks
- “Of Truth, of Grandeur, Beauty, Love and Hope
- And melancholy Fear subdued by Faith.”
- And the poet adds:
- “As we look
- Into our Minds, into the Mind of Man—
- My haunt, and the main region of my song;
- Beauty—a living Presence of the earth
- Surpassing the most fair ideal forms
- ... waits upon my steps.”
- The reality duly seen in the spiritual vision
- “That inspires
- The human Soul of universal earth
- Dreaming of things to come”
- will be a greater glory than the ideals of imaginative fiction ever
- fancied:
- “For the discerning intellect of Man,
- When wedded to this goodly universe
- In love and holy passion, shall find these
- A simple produce of the common day.”
- If Wordsworth, thus, as it were, echoing the great conception of Francis
- Bacon,
- “Would chant, in lonely peace, the spousal verse
- Of this great consummation,”
- perhaps the poet and the essayist may help us with Hegel to rate the
- Mind—the Mind of Man—at its highest value.
- Essay II. Aims And Methods Of Psychology.
- It is not going too far to say that in common estimation psychology has as
- yet hardly reached what Kant has called the steady walk of science—_der
- sichere Gang der Wissenschaft_. To assert this is not, of course, to throw
- any doubts on the importance of the problems, or on the intrinsic value of
- the results, in the studies which have been prosecuted under that name. It
- is only to note the obvious fact that a number of inquiries of somewhat
- discrepant tone, method, and tendency have all at different times covered
- themselves under the common title of psychological, and that the work of
- orientation is as yet incomplete. Such a destiny seems inevitable, when a
- name is coined rather as the title of an unexplored territory, than fixed
- on to describe an accomplished fact.
- (i.) Psychology as a Science and as a Part of Philosophy.
- The _De Anima_ of Aristotle, gathering up into one the work of Plato and
- his predecessors, may be said to lay the foundation of psychology. But
- even in it, we can already see that there are two elements or aspects
- struggling for mastery: two elements not unrelated or independent, but
- hard to keep fairly and fully in unity. On one hand there is the
- conception of Soul as a part of Nature, as a grade of existence in the
- physical or natural universe,—in the universe of things which suffer
- growth and change, which are never entirely “without matter,” and are
- always attached to or present in body. From this point of view Aristotle
- urged that a sound and realistic psychology must, e.g. in its definition
- of a passion, give the prominent place to its physical (or material)
- expression, and not to its mental form or significance. It must remember,
- he said, that the phenomena or “accidents” are what really throw light on
- the nature or the “substance” of the Soul. On the other hand, there are
- two points to be considered. There is, first of all, the counterpoising
- remark that the conception of Soul as such, as a unity and common
- characteristic, will be determinative of the phenomena or
- “accidents,”—will settle, as it were, what we are to observe and look for,
- and how we are to describe our observations. And by the _conception_ of
- Soul, is meant not _a_ soul, as a thing or agent (subject) which has
- properties attaching to it; but soul, as the generic feature, the
- universal, which is set as a stamp on everything that claims to be
- psychical. In other words, Soul is one, not as a single thing contrasted
- with its attributes, activities, or exercises of force (such single thing
- will be shown by logic to be a metaphysical fiction); but as the unity of
- form and character, the comprehensive and identical feature, which is
- present in all its manifestations and exercises. But there is a second
- consideration. The question is asked by Aristotle whether it is completely
- and strictly accurate to put Soul under the category of natural objects.
- There is in it, or of it, perhaps, something, and something essential to
- it, which belongs to the order of the eternal and self-active: something
- which is “form” and “energy” quite unaffected by and separate from
- “matter.” How this is related to the realm of the perishable and
- changeable is a problem on which Aristotle has been often (and with some
- reason) believed to be obscure, if not even inconsistent(21).
- In these divergent elements which come to the fore in Aristotle’s
- treatment we have the appearance of a radical difference of conception and
- purpose as to psychology. He himself does a good deal to keep them both in
- view. But it is evident that here already we have the contrast between a
- purely physical or (in the narrower sense) “scientific” psychology,
- empirical and realistic in treatment, and a more philosophical—what in
- certain quarters would be called a speculative or metaphysical—conception
- of the problem. There is also in Aristotle the antithesis of a popular or
- superficial, and an accurate or analytic, psychology. The former is of a
- certain use in dealing, say, with questions of practical ethics and
- education: the latter is of more strictly scientific interest. Both of
- these distinctions—that between a speculative and an empirical, and that
- between a scientific and a popular treatment—affect the subsequent history
- of the study. Psychology is sometimes understood to mean the results of
- casual observation of our own minds by what is termed introspection, and
- by the interpretation of what we may observe in others. Such observations
- are in the first place carried on under the guidance of distinctions or
- points of view supplied by the names in common use. We interrogate our own
- consciousness as to what facts or relations of facts correspond to the
- terms of our national language. Or we attempt—what is really an
- inexhaustible quest—to get definite divisions between them, and clear-cut
- definitions. Inquiries like these which start from popular distinctions
- fall a long way short of science: and the inquirer will find that
- accidental and essential properties are given in the same handful of
- conclusions. Yet there is always much value in these attempts to get our
- minds cleared: and it is indispensable for all inquiries that all alleged
- or reported facts of mind should be realised and reproduced in our own
- mental experience. And this is especially the case in psychology, just
- because here we cannot get the object outside us, we cannot get or make a
- diagram, and unless we give it reality by re-constructing it,—by
- re-interrogating our own experience, our knowledge of it will be but
- wooden and mechanical. And the term introspection need not be too
- seriously taken: it means much more than watching passively an internal
- drama; and is quite as well describable as mental projection, setting out
- what was within, and so as it were hidden and involved, before ourselves
- in the field of mental vision. Here, as always, the essential point is to
- get ourselves well out of the way of the object observed, and to stand,
- figuratively speaking, quite on one side.
- But even at the best, such a popular or empirical psychology has no
- special claim to be ranked as science. It may no doubt be said that at
- least it collects, describes, or notes down facts. But even this is not so
- certain as it seems. Its so-called facts are very largely fictions, or so
- largely interpolated with error, that they cannot be safely used for
- construction. If psychology is to accomplish anything valuable, it must go
- more radically to work. It must—at least in a measure—discard from its
- preliminary view the data of common and current distinctions, and try to
- get at something more primary or ultimate as its starting-point. And this
- it may do in two ways. It may, in the one case, follow the example of the
- physical sciences. In these it is the universal practice to assume that
- the explanation of complex and concrete facts is to be attained by (_a_)
- postulating certain simple elements (which we may call atoms, molecules,
- and perhaps units or monads), which are supposed to be clearly conceivable
- and to justify themselves by intrinsic intelligibility, and by (_b_)
- assuming that these elements are compounded and combined according to laws
- which again are in the last resort self-evident, or such that they seem to
- have an obvious and palpable lucidity. Further, such laws being always
- axioms or plain postulates of mechanics (for these alone possess this
- feature of self-evident intelligibility), they are subject to and invite
- all the aids and refinements of the higher mathematical calculus. What the
- primary and self-explicative bits of psychical reality may be, is a
- further question on which there may be some dispute. They may be, so to
- say, taken in a more physical or in a more metaphysical way: i.e. more as
- units of nerve-function or more as elements of ideative-function. And
- there may be differences as to how far and in what provinces the
- mathematical calculus may be applicable. But, in any case, there will be a
- strong tendency in psychology, worked on this plan, to follow, _mutatis
- mutandis_, and at some distance perhaps, the analogy of material physics.
- In both the justification of the postulated units and laws will be their
- ability to describe and systematise the observed phenomena in a uniform
- and consistent way.
- The other way in which psychology gets a foundation and ulterior certainty
- is different, and goes deeper. After all, the “scientific” method is only
- a way in which the facts of a given sphere are presented in thoroughgoing
- interconnexion, each reduced to an exact multiple or fraction of some
- other, by an inimitably continued subtraction and addition of an assumed
- homogeneous element, found or assumed to be perfectly imaginable
- (conceivable). But we may also consider the province in relation to the
- whole sphere of reality, may ask what is its place and meaning in the
- whole, what reality is in the end driving at or coming to be, and how far
- this special province contributes to that end. If we do this, we attach
- psychology to philosophy, or, if we prefer so to call it, to metaphysics,
- as in the former way we established it on the principles generally
- received as governing the method of the physical sciences.
- This—the relation of psychology to fundamental philosophy—is a question
- which also turns up in dealing with Ethics. There is on the part of those
- engaged in either of these inquiries a certain impatience against the
- intermeddling (which is held to be only muddling) of metaphysics with
- them. It is clear that in a very decided way both psychology and ethics
- can, up to some extent at least, be treated as what is called empirical
- (or, to use the more English phrase, inductive) sciences. On many hands
- they are actually so treated: and not without result. Considering the
- tendency of metaphysical inquiries, it may be urged that it is well to
- avoid preliminary criticism of the current conceptions and beliefs about
- reality which these sciences imply. Yet such beliefs are undoubtedly
- present and effective. Schopenhauer has popularised the principle that the
- pure empiricist is a fiction, that man is a radically metaphysical animal,
- and that he inevitably turns what he receives into a part of a dogmatic
- creed—a conviction how things ought to be. Almost without effort there
- grows up in him, or flows in upon him, a belief and a system of beliefs as
- to the order and values of things. Every judgment, even in logic, rests on
- such an order of truth. He need not be able to formulate his creed: it
- will influence him none the less: nay, his faith will probably seem more a
- part of the solid earth and common reality, the less it has been reduced
- to a determinate creed or to a code of principles. For such formulation
- presupposes doubt and scepticism, which it beats back by mere assertion.
- Each human being has such a background of convictions which govern his
- actions and conceptions, and of which it so startles him to suggest the
- possibility of a doubt, that he turns away in dogmatic horror. Such ruling
- ideas vary, from man to man, and from man to woman—if we consider them in
- all their minuteness. But above all they constitute themselves in a
- differently organised system or aggregate according to the social and
- educational stratum to which an individual belongs. Each group, engaged in
- a common task, it may be in the study of a part of nature, is ideally
- bound and obliged by a common language, and special standards of truth and
- reality for its own. Such a group of ideas is what Bacon would have called
- a scientific fetich or _idolum theatri_. A scientific _idolum_ is a
- traditional belief or dogma as to principles, values, and methods, which
- has so thoroughly pervaded the minds of those engaged in a branch of
- inquiry, that they no longer recognise its hypothetical character,—its
- relation of means to the main end of their function.
- Such a collected and united theory of reality (it is what Hegel has
- designated the Idea) is what is understood by a natural metaphysic. It has
- nothing necessarily to do with a supersensible or a supernatural, if these
- words mean a ghostly, materialised, but super-finely-materialised nature,
- above and beyond the present. But that there is a persistent tendency to
- conceive the unity and coherence, the theoretic idea of reality, in this
- pseudo-sensuous (i.e. super-sensuous) form, is of course a well-known
- fact. For the present, however, this aberration—this idol of the tribe—may
- be left out of sight. By a metaphysic or fundamental philosophy, is, in
- the present instance, meant a system of first principles—a secular and
- cosmic creed: a belief in ends and values, a belief in truth—again
- premising that the system in question is, for most, a rudely organised and
- almost inarticulate mass of belief and hope, conviction and impression. It
- is, in short, a _natural_ metaphysic: a metaphysic, that is, which has but
- an imperfect coherence, which imperfectly realises both its nature and its
- limits.
- In certain parts, however, it is more and better than this crude
- background of belief. Each science—or at least every group of sciences—has
- a more definite system or aggregate of first principles, axioms, and
- conceptions belonging to it. It has, that is,—and here in a much
- distincter way—its special standard of reality, its peculiar forms of
- conceiving things, its distinctions between the actual and the apparent,
- &c. Here again it will probably be found that the scientific specialist is
- hardly conscious that these are principles and concepts: on the contrary,
- they will be supposed self-evident and ultimate facts, foundations of
- being. Instead of being treated as modes of conception, more or less
- justified by their use and their results, these categories will be
- regarded as fundamental facts, essential conditions of all reality. Like
- popular thought in its ingrained categories, the specialist cannot
- understand the possibility of any limitation to his radical ideas of
- reality. To him they are not hypotheses, but principles. The scientific
- specialist may be as convinced of the universal application of his
- peculiar categories, as the Chinese or the Eskimo that his standards are
- natural and final.
- Under such metaphysical or extra-empirical presuppositions all
- investigation, whether it be crudely empirical or (in the physical sense)
- scientific, is carried on. And when so carried on, it is said to be
- prosecuted apart from any interference from metaphysic. Such a naïve or
- natural metaphysic, not raised to explicit consciousness, not followed as
- an imposed rule, but governing with the strength of an immanent faith,
- does not count for those who live under it as a metaphysic at all. M.
- Jourdain was amazed suddenly to learn he had been speaking prose for forty
- years without knowing it. But in the present case there is something worse
- than amazement sure to be excited by the news. For the critic who thus
- reveals the secrets of the scientist’s heart is pretty sure to go on to
- say that a good deal of this naïve unconscious metaphysic is incoherent,
- contradictory, even bad: that it requires correction, revision, and
- readjustment, and has by criticism to be made one and harmonious. That
- readjustment or criticism which shall eliminate contradiction and produce
- unity, is the aim of the _science_ of metaphysic—the science of the
- meta-physical element in physical knowledge: what Hegel has chosen to call
- the Science of Logic (in the wide sense of the term). This higher Logic,
- this _science_ of metaphysic, is the process to revise and harmonise in
- systematic completeness the imperfect or misleading and partial estimates
- of reality which are to be found in popular and scientific thought.
- In the case of the run of physical sciences this revision is less
- necessary; and for no very recondite reason. Every science by its very
- nature deals with a special, a limited topic. It is confined to a part or
- aspect of reality. Its propositions are not complete truths; they apply to
- an artificial world, to a part expressly cut off from the concrete
- reality. Its principles are generally cut according to their
- cloth,—according to the range in which they apply. The only danger that
- can well arise is if these categories are transplanted without due
- reservations, and made of universal application, i.e. if the scientist
- elects on his speciality to pronounce _de omnibus rebus_. But in the case
- of psychology and ethics the harmlessness of natural metaphysics will be
- less certain. Here a general human or universal interest is almost an
- inevitable coefficient: especially if they really rise to the full sweep
- of the subject. For as such they both seem to deal not with a part of
- reality, but with the very centre and purpose of all reality. In them we
- are not dealing with topics of secondary interest, but with the very heart
- of the human problem. Here the questions of reality and ideals, of unity
- and diversity, and of the evaluation of existence, come distinctly to the
- fore. If psychology is to answer the question, What am I? and ethics the
- question, What ought I to do? they can hardly work without some formulated
- creed of metaphysical character, without some preliminary criticisms of
- current first principles.
- (ii.) Herbart.
- The German thinker, who has given perhaps the most fruitful stimulus to
- the scientific study of psychology in modern times—Johann Friedrich
- Herbart—is after all essentially a philosopher, and not a mere scientist,
- even in his psychology. His psychological inquiry, that is, stands in
- intimate connexion with the last questions of all intelligence, with
- metaphysics and ethics. The business of philosophy, says Herbart, is to
- touch up and finish off conceptions (_Bearbeitung der Begriffe_)(22). It
- finds, as it supervenes upon the unphilosophical world, that mere and pure
- facts (if there ever are or were such purisms) have been enveloped in a
- cloud of theory, have been construed into some form of unity, but have
- been imperfectly, inadequately construed: and that the existing concepts
- in current use need to be corrected, supplemented and readjusted. It has,
- accordingly, for its work to “reconcile experience with itself(23),” and
- to elicit “the hidden pre-suppositions without which the fact of
- experience is unthinkable.” Psychology, then, as a branch of this
- philosophic enterprise, has to readjust the facts discovered in inner
- experience. For mere uncritical experience or merely empirical knowledge
- only offers _problems_; it suggests gaps, which indeed further reflection
- serves at first only to deepen into contradictions. Such a psychology is
- “speculative”: i.e. it is not content to accept the mere given, but goes
- forward and backward to find something that will make the fact
- intelligible. It employs totally different methods from the
- “classification, induction, analogy” familiar to the logic of the
- empirical sciences. Its “principles,” therefore, are not given facts: but
- facts which have been manipulated and adjusted so as to lose their
- self-contradictory quality: they are facts “reduced,” by introducing the
- omitted relationships which they postulate if they are to be true and
- self-consistent(24). While it is far from rejecting or ignoring
- experience, therefore, psychology cannot strictly be said to build upon it
- alone. It uses experimental fact as an unfinished datum,—or it sees in
- experience a torso which betrays its imperfection, and suggests
- completing.
- The starting-point, it may be said, of Herbart’s psychology is a question
- which to the ordinary psychologist (and to the so-called scientific
- psychologist) has a secondary, if it have any interest. It was, he says,
- the problem of Personality, the problem of the Self or Ego, which first
- led to his characteristic conception of psychological method. “My first
- discovery,” he tells us(25), “was that the Self was neither primitive nor
- independent, but must be the most dependent and most conditioned thing one
- can imagine. The second was that the elementary ideas of an intelligent
- being, if they were ever to reach the pitch of self-consciousness, must be
- either all, or at least in part, opposed to each other, and that they must
- check or block one another in consequence of this opposition. Though held
- in check, however, these ideas were not to be supposed lost: they subsist
- as endeavours or tendencies to return into the position of actual idea, as
- soon as the check became, for any reason, either in whole or in part
- inoperative. This check could and must be calculated, and thus it was
- clear that psychology required a mathematical as well as a metaphysical
- foundation.”
- The place of the conception of the Ego in Kant’s and Fichte’s theory of
- knowledge is well known. Equally well known is Kant’s treatment of the
- soul-reality or soul-substance in his examination of Rational Psychology.
- Whereas the (logical) unity of consciousness, or “synthetic unity of
- apperception,” is assumed as a fundamental starting-point in explanation
- of our objective judgments, or of our knowledge of objective existence,
- its real (as opposed to its formal) foundation in a “substantial” soul is
- set aside as an illegitimate interpretation of, or inference from, the
- facts of inner experience. The belief in the separate unity and
- persistence of the soul, said Kant, is not a scientifically-warranted
- conclusion. Its true place is as an ineffaceable postulate of the faith
- which inspires human life and action. Herbart did not rest content with
- either of these—as he believed—dogmatic assumptions of his master. He did
- not fall in cheerfully with the idealism which seemed ready to dispense
- with a soul, or which justified its acceptance of empirical reality by
- referring to the fundamental unity of the function of judgment. With a
- strong bent towards fully-differentiated and individualised experience
- Herbart conjoined a conviction of the need of logical analysis to prevent
- us being carried away by the first-come and inadequate generalities. The
- Ego which, in its extremest abstraction, he found defined as the unity of
- subject and object, did not seem to him to offer the proper guarantees of
- reality: it was itself a problem, full of contradictions, waiting for
- solution. On the other hand, the real Ego, or self of concrete experience,
- is very much more than this logical abstract, and differs widely from
- individual to individual, and apparently from time to time even in the
- same individual. Our self, of which we talk so fluently, as one and the
- self-same—how far does it really possess the continuity and identity with
- which we credit it? Does it not rather seem to be an ideal which we
- gradually form and set before ourselves as the standard for measuring our
- attainments of the moment,—the perfect fulfilment of that oneness of being
- and purpose and knowledge which we never reach? Sometimes even it seems no
- better than a name which we move along the varying phenomena of our inner
- life, at one time identifying it with the power which has gained the
- victory in a moral struggle, at another with that which has been
- defeated(26), according as the attitude of the moment makes us throw now
- one, now another, aspect of mental activity in the foreground.
- The other—or logical Ego—the mere identity of subject and object,—when
- taken in its utter abstractness and simplicity, shrivels up to something
- very small indeed—to a something which is little better than nothing. The
- mere _I_ which is not contra-distinguished by a _Thou_ and a _He_—which is
- without all definiteness of predication (the I=I of Fichte and
- Schelling)—is only as it were a point of being cut off from all its
- connexions in reality, and treated as if it were or could be entirely
- independent. It is an identity in which subject and object have not yet
- appeared: it is not a real I, though we may still retain the name. It
- is—as Hegel’s _Logic_ will tell us—exactly definable as Being, which is as
- yet Nothing: the impossible edge of abstraction on which we try—and in
- vain—to steady ourselves at the initial point of thought. And to reach or
- stand at that intangible, ungraspable point, which slips away as we
- approach, and transmutes itself as we hold it, is not the natural
- beginning, but the result of introspection and reflection on the concrete
- self. But with this aspect of the question we are not now concerned.
- That the unity of the Self as an intelligent and moral being, that the Ego
- of self-consciousness was an ideal and a product of development, was what
- Herbart soon became convinced of. The unity of Self is even as given in
- mature experience an imperfect fact. It is a fact, that is, which does not
- come up to what it promised, and which requires to be supplemented, or
- philosophically justified. Here and everywhere the custom of life carries
- us over gaps which yawn deep to the eye of philosophic reflection: even
- though accident and illness force them not unfrequently even upon the
- blindest. To trace the process of unification towards this unity—to trace,
- if you like, even the formation of the concept of such unity, as a
- governing and guiding principle in life and conduct, comes to be the
- problem of the psychologist, in the largest sense of that problem. From
- Soul (_Seele_) to Mind or Spirit (_Geist_) is for Herbart, as for Hegel,
- the course of psychology(27). The growth and development of mind, the
- formation of a self, the realisation of a personality, is for both the
- theme which psychology has to expound. And Herbart, not less than Hegel,
- had to bear the censure that such a conception of mental reality as a
- growth would destroy personality(28).
- But with so much common in the general plan, the two thinkers differ
- profoundly in their special mode of carrying out the task. Or, rather,
- they turn their strength on different departments of the whole. Herbart’s
- great practical interest had been the theory of education: “paedagogic” is
- the subject of his first important writings. The inner history of
- ideas—the processes which are based on the interaction of elements in the
- individual soul—are what he specially traces. Hegel’s interests, on the
- contrary, are more towards the greater process, the unities of historical
- life, and the correlations of the powers of art, religion, and philosophy
- that work therein. He turns to the macrocosm, almost as naturally as
- Herbart does to the microcosm. Thus, even in Ethics, while Herbart gives a
- delicate analysis of the distinct aspects or elements in the Ethical
- idea,—the diverse headings under which the disinterested spectator within
- the breast measures with purely aesthetic eye his approach to unity and
- strength of purpose, Hegel seems to hurry away from the field of moral
- sense or conscience to throw himself on the social and political
- organisation of the moral life. The General Paedagogic of Herbart has its
- pendant in Hegel’s Philosophy of Law and of History.
- At an early period Herbart had become impressed with the necessity of
- applying mathematics to psychology(29). To the usual objection, that
- psychical facts do not admit of measurement, he had a ready reply. We can
- calculate even on hypothetical assumptions: indeed, could we measure, we
- should scarcely take the trouble to calculate(30). To calculate (i.e. to
- deduce mathematically) is to perform a general experiment, and to perform
- it in the medium where there is least likelihood of error or disturbance.
- There may be anomalies enough apparent in the mental life: there may be
- the great anomalies of Genius and of Freedom of Will; but the Newton and
- the Kepler of psychology will show by calculation on assumed conditions of
- psychic nature that these aberrations can be explained by mechanical laws.
- “The human Soul is no puppet-theatre: our wishes and resolutions are no
- marionettes: no juggler stands behind; but our true and proper life lies
- in our volition, and this life has its rule not outside, but in itself: it
- has its own purely mental rule, by no means borrowed from the material
- world. But this rule is in it sure and fixed; and on account of this its
- fixed quality it has more similarity to (what is otherwise heterogeneous)
- the laws of impact and pressure than to the marvels of an alleged
- inexplicable freedom(31).”
- Psychology then deals with a real, which exhibits phenomena analogous in
- several respects to those discussed by statics and mechanics. Its
- foundation is a statics and mechanics of the Soul,—as this real is called.
- We begin by presupposing as the ultimate reality, underlying the
- factitious and generally imperfect unity of self-consciousness and mind,
- an essential and primary unity—the unity of an absolutely simple or
- individual point of being—a real point which amongst other points asserts
- itself, maintains itself. It has a character of its own, but that
- character it only shows in and through a development conditioned by
- external influences. The specific nature of the soul-reality is to be
- representative, to produce, or manifest itself in, ideas
- (_Vorstellungen_). But the character only emerges into actuality in the
- conflict of the soul-atom with other ultimate realities in the
- congregation of things. A soul _per se_ or isolated is not possessed of
- ideas. It is merely blank, undeveloped, formal unity, of which nothing can
- be said. But like other realities it defines and characterises itself by
- antithesis, by resistance: it shows what it is by its behaviour in the
- struggle for existence. It acts in self-defence: and its peculiar style or
- weapon of self-defence is an idea or representation. The way the Soul
- maintains itself is by turning the assailant into an idea(32): and each
- idea is therefore a _Selbsterhaltung_ of the Soul. The Soul is thus
- enriched—to appearance or incidentally: and the assailant is annexed. In
- this way the one Soul may develop or evolve or express an innumerable
- variety of ideas: for in response to whatever it meets, the living and
- active Soul ideates, or gives rise to a representation. Thus, while the
- soul is one, its ideas or representations are many. Taken separately, they
- each express the psychic self-conservation. But brought in relation with
- each other, as so many acts or self-affirmations of the one soul, they
- behave as forces, and tend to thwart or check each other. It is as forces,
- as reciprocally arresting or fostering each other, that ideas are objects
- of science. When a representation is thus held in check, it is reduced to
- a mere endeavour or active tendency to represent. Thus there arises a
- distinction between representations proper, and those imperfect states or
- acts which are partly or wholly held in abeyance. But the latent phase of
- an idea is as essential to a thorough understanding of it as what appears.
- It is the great blunder of empirical psychology to ignore what is sunk
- below the surface of consciousness. And to Herbart consciousness is not
- the condition but rather the product of ideas, which are primarily forces.
- But representations are not merely in opposition,—impinging and resisting.
- The same reason which makes them resist, viz. that they are or would fain
- be acts of the one soul, but are more or less incompatible, leads them in
- other circumstances to form combinations with each other. These
- combinations are of two sorts. They are, first, complications, or
- “complexions”: a number of ideas combine by quasi-addition and
- juxtaposition to form a total. Second, there is fusion: ideas presenting
- certain degrees of contrast enter into a union where the parts are no
- longer separately perceptible. It is easy to see how the problems of
- psychology now assume the form of a statics and mechanics of the mind.
- Quantitative data are to be sought in the strength of each separate single
- idea, and the degree in which two or more ideas block each other: in the
- degree of combination between ideas, and the number of ideas in a
- combination: and in the terms of relation between the members of a series
- of ideas. A statical theory has to show the conditions required for what
- we may call the ideal state of equilibrium of the “idea-forces”: to
- determine, that is, the ultimate degree of obscuration suffered by any two
- ideas of different strength, and the conditions of their permanent
- combination or fusion. A mechanics of the mind will, on the contrary, deal
- with the rate at which these processes are brought about, the velocity
- with which in the movement of mind ideas are obscured or reawakened, &c.
- It is fortunately unnecessary, here, to go further into details. What
- Herbart proposes is not a method for the mathematical measurement of
- psychic facts: it is a theory of mechanics and statics specially adapted
- to the peculiarities of psychical phenomena, where the forces are given
- with no sine or cosine, where instead of gravitation we have the constant
- effort (as it were elasticity) of each idea to revert to its unchecked
- state. He claims—in short—practically to be a Kepler and Newton of the
- mind, and in so doing to justify the vague professions of more than one
- writer on mind—above all, perhaps of David Hume, who goes beyond mere
- professions—to make mental science follow the example of physics. And a
- main argument in favour of his enterprise is the declaration of Kant that
- no body of knowledge can claim to be a science except in such proportion
- as it is mathematical. And the peculiarity of this enterprise is that
- self-consciousness, the Ego, is not allowed to interfere with the free
- play of psychic forces. The Ego is—psychologically—the result, the
- product, and the varying product of that play. The play of forces is no
- doubt a unity: but its unity lies not in the synthesis of consciousness,
- but in the essential unity of Soul. And Soul is in its essence neither
- consciousness, nor self-consciousness, nor mind: but something on the
- basis of whose unity these are built up and developed(33). The mere
- “representation” does not include the further supervenience of
- consciousness: it represents, but it is not as yet necessary that we
- should also be conscious that there is representation. It is, in the
- phrase of Leibniz, perception: but not apperception. It is mere
- straight-out, not as yet reflected, representation. Gradually there
- emerges through the operation of mechanical psychics a nucleus, a floating
- unity, a fixed or definite central aggregate.
- The suggestion of mathematical method has been taken up by subsequent
- inquirers (as it was pursued even before Herbart’s time), but not in the
- sense he meant. Experimentation has now taken a prominent place in
- psychology. But in proportion as it has done so, psychology has lost its
- native character, and thrown itself into the arms of physiology. What
- Herbart calculated were actions and reactions of idea-forces: what the
- modern experimental school proposes to measure are to a large extent the
- velocities of certain physiological processes, the numerical specification
- of certain facts. Such ascertainments are unquestionably useful; as
- numerical precision is in other departments. But, taken in themselves,
- they do not carry us one bit further on the way to science. As
- experiments, further,—to note a point discussed elsewhere(34)—their value
- depends on the point of view, on the theory which has led to them, on the
- value of the general scheme for which they are intended to provide a
- special new determination. In many cases they serve to give a vivid
- reality to what was veiled under a general phrase. The truth looks so much
- more real when it is put in figures: as the size of a huge tree when set
- against a rock; or as when Milton bodies out his fallen angel by setting
- forth the ratio between his spear and the tallest Norway pine. But until
- the general relationship between soul and body is more clearly formulated,
- such statistics will have but a value of curiosity.
- (iii.) The Faculty-Psychology and its Critics.
- What Herbart (as well as Hegel) finds perpetual ground for objecting to is
- the talk about mental faculties. This objection is part of a general
- characteristic of all the higher philosophy; and the recurrence of it
- gives an illustration of how hard it is for any class of men to see
- themselves as others see them. If there be anything the vulgar believe to
- be true of philosophy, it is that it deals in distant and abstruse
- generalities, that it neglects the shades of individuality and reality,
- and launches out into unsubstantial general ideas. But it would be easy to
- gather from the great thinkers an anthology of passages in which they hold
- it forth as the great work of philosophy to rescue our conceptions from
- the indefiniteness and generality of popular conception, and to give them
- real, as opposed to a merely nominal, individuality.
- The Wolffian school, which Herbart (not less than Kant) found in
- possession of the field, and which in Germany may be taken to represent
- only a slight variant of the half-and-half attitude of vulgar thought, was
- entrenched in the psychology of faculties. Empirical psychology, said
- Wolff(35), tells the number and character of the soul’s faculties:
- rational psychology will tell what they “properly” are, and how they
- subsist in soul. It is assumed that there are general receptacles or
- tendencies of mental operation which in course of time get filled or
- qualified in a certain way: and that when this question is disposed of, it
- still remains to fix on the metaphysical bases of these facts.
- That a doctrine of faculties should fix itself in psychology is not so
- wonderful. In the non-psychical world objects are easily discriminated in
- space, and the individual thing lasts through a time. But a phase of mind
- is as such fleeting and indeterminate: its individual features which come
- from its “object” tend soon to vanish in memory: all freshness of definite
- characters wears off, and there is left behind only a vague “recept” of
- the one and same in many, a sort of hypostatised representative, faint but
- persistent, of what in experience was an ever-varying succession. We
- generalise here as elsewhere: but elsewhere the many singulars remain to
- confront us more effectually. But in Mind the immense variety of real
- imagination, memory, judgment is forgotten, and the name in each case
- reduced to a meagre abstract. Thus the identity in character and
- operation, having been cut off from the changing elements in its real
- action, is transmuted into a substantial somewhat, a subsistent faculty.
- The relationship of one to another of the powers thus by abstraction and
- fancy created becomes a problem of considerable moment, their causal
- relations in particular: till in the end they stand outside and
- independent of each other, engaged, as Herbart says, in a veritable
- _bellum omnium contra omnes_.
- But this hypostatising of faculties becomes a source of still further
- difficulties when it is taken in connexion with the hypostasis of the Soul
- or Self or Ego. To Aristotle the Soul in its general aspect is Energy or
- Essence; and its individual phases are energies. But in the hands of the
- untrained these conceptions came to be considerably displaced. Essence or
- Substance came to be understood (as may be seen in Locke, and still more
- in loose talk) as a something,—a substratum,—or peculiar nature—(of which
- _in itself_ nothing further could be said(36) but which notwithstanding
- was permanent and perhaps imperishable): this something subsistent
- exhibited certain properties or activities. There thus arose, on one hand,
- the Soul-thing,—a substance misunderstood and sensualised with a
- supernatural sensuousness,—a denizen of the transcendental or even of the
- transcendent world: and, on the other hand, stood the actual
- manifestations, the several exhibitions of this force, the assignable and
- describable psychic facts. We are accordingly brought before the problem
- of how this one substance or essence stands to the several entities or
- hypostases known as faculties. And we still have in the rear the further
- problem of how these abstract entities stand to the real and concrete
- single acts and states of soul and mind.
- This hypostatising of faculties, and this distinction of the “Substantial”
- soul from its “accidentia” or phenomena, had grown—through the
- materialistic proclivities of popular conception—from the indications
- found in Aristotle. It attained its climax, perhaps in the Wolffian school
- in Germany, but it has been the resort of superficial psychology in all
- ages. For while it, on one hand, seemed to save the substantial Soul on
- whose incorruptibility great issues were believed to hinge, it held out,
- on the other, an open hand to the experimental inquirer, whom it bade
- freely to search amongst the phenomena. But if it was the refuge of
- pusillanimity, it was also the perpetual object of censure from all the
- greater and bolder spirits. Thus, the psychology of Hobbes may be hasty
- and crude, but it is at least animated by a belief that the mental life is
- continuous, and not cut off by abrupt divisions severing the mental
- faculties. The “image” (according to his materialistically coloured
- psychology) which, when it is a strong motion, is called sense, passes, as
- it becomes weaker or decays, into imagination, and gives rise, by its
- various complications and associations with others, to reminiscence,
- experience, expectation. Similarly, the voluntary motion which is an
- effect or a phase of imagination, beginning at first in small
- motions—called by themselves “endeavours,” and in relation to their cause
- “appetites” or “desires(37)”—leads on cumulatively to Will, which is the
- “last appetite in deliberating.” Spinoza, his contemporary, speaks in the
- same strain(38). “Faculties of intellect, desire, love, &c., are either
- utterly fictitious, or nothing but metaphysical entities, or universals
- which we are in the habit of forming from particulars. Will and intellect
- are thus supposed to stand to this or that idea, this or that volition, in
- the same way as stoniness to this or that stone, or as man to Peter or
- Paul.” They are supposed to be a general something which gets defined and
- detached. But, in the mind, or in the cogitant soul, there are no such
- things. There are only ideas: and by an “idea” we are to understand not an
- image on the retina or in the brain, not a “dumb something, like a
- painting on a panel(39),” but a mode of thinking, or even the act of
- intellection itself. The ideas _are_ the mind: mind does not _have_ ideas.
- Further, every “idea,” as such, “involves affirmation or negation,”—is not
- an image, but an act of judgment—contains, as we should say, an implicit
- reference to actuality,—a reference which in volition is made explicit.
- Thus (concludes the corollary of Eth. ii. 49) “Will and Intellect are one
- and the same.” But in any case the “faculties” as such are no better than
- _entia rationis_ (i.e. auxiliary modes of representing facts).
- Leibniz speaks no less distinctly and sanely in this direction. “True
- powers are never mere possibilities: they are always tendency and action.”
- The “Monad”—that is the quasi-intelligent unit of existence,—is
- essentially activity, and its actions are perceptions and appetitions,
- i.e. tendencies to pass from one perceptive state or act to another. It is
- out of the variety, the complication, and relations of these miniature or
- little perceptions and appetitions, that the conspicuous phenomena of
- consciousness are to be explained, and not by supposing them due to one or
- other faculty. The soul is a unity, a self-developing unity, a unity which
- at each stage of its existence shows itself in a perception or idea,—each
- such perception however being, to repeat the oft quoted phrase, _plein de
- l’avenir et chargé du passé_:—each, in other words, is not stationary, but
- active and urgent, a progressive force, as well as a representative
- element. Above all, Leibniz has the view that the soul gives rise to all
- its ideas from itself: that its life is its own production, not a mere
- inheritance of ideas which it has from birth and nature, nor a mere
- importation into an empty room from without, but a necessary result of its
- own constitution acting in necessary (predetermined) reciprocity and
- harmony with the rest of the universe.
- But Hobbes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, were most attentively heard in the
- passages where they favoured or combatted the dominant social and
- theological prepossessions. Their glimpses of truer insight and even their
- palpable contributions in the line of a true psychology were ignored or
- forgotten. More attention, perhaps, was attracted by an attempt of a very
- different style. This was the system of Condillac, who, as Hegel says (p.
- 61), made an unmistakable attempt to show the necessary interconnexion of
- the several modes of mental activity. In his _Traité des Sensations_
- (1754), following on his _Essai sur l’origine des connaissances humaines_
- (1746), he tried to carry out systematically the deduction or derivation
- of all our ideas from sense, or to trace the filiation of all our
- faculties from sensation. Given a mind with no other power than
- sensibility, the problem is to show how it acquires all its other
- faculties. Let us then suppose a sentient animal to which is offered a
- single sensation, or one sensation standing out above the others. In such
- circumstances the sensation “becomes” (_devient_) attention: or a
- sensation “is” (_est_) attention, either because it is alone, or because
- it is more lively than all the rest. Again: before such a being, let us
- set two sensations: to perceive or feel (_apercevoir ou sentir_) the two
- sensations is the same thing (_c’est la même chose_). If one of the
- sensations is not present, but a sensation made already, then to perceive
- it is memory. Memory, then, is only “transformed sensation” (_sensation
- transformée_). Further, suppose we attend to both ideas, this is “the same
- thing” as to compare them. And to compare them we must see difference or
- resemblance. This is judgment. “Thus sensation becomes successively
- attention, comparison, judgment.” And—by further steps of the equating
- process—it appears that sensation again “becomes” an act of reflection.
- And the same may be said of imagination and reasoning: all are transformed
- sensations.
- If this is so with the intelligence, it is equally the case with the Will.
- To feel and not feel well or ill is impossible. Coupling then this feeling
- of pleasure or pain with the sensation and its transformations, we get the
- series of phases ranging from desire, to passion, hope, will. “Desire is
- only the action of the same faculties as are attributed to the
- understanding.” A lively desire is a passion: a desire, accompanied with a
- belief that nothing stands in its way, is a volition. But combine these
- affective with the intellectual processes already noticed, and you have
- thinking (_penser_)(40). Thus thought in its entirety is, only and always,
- transformed sensation.
- Something not unlike this, though scarcely so simply and directly
- doctrinaire, is familiar to us in some English psychology, notably James
- Mill’s(41). Taken in their literal baldness, these identifications may
- sound strained,—or trifling. But if we look beyond the words, we can
- detect a genuine instinct for maintaining and displaying the unity and
- continuity of mental life through all its modifications,—coupled
- unfortunately with a bias sometimes in favour of reducing higher or more
- complex states of mind to a mere prolongation of lower and beggarly
- rudiments. But otherwise such analyses are useful as aids against the
- tendency of inert thought to take every name in this department as a
- distinguishable reality: the tendency to part will from thought—ideas from
- emotion—and even imagination from reason, as if either could be what it
- professed without the other.
- (iv.) Methods and Problems of Psychology.
- The difficulties of modern psychology perhaps lie in other directions, but
- they are not less worth guarding against. They proceed mainly from failure
- or inability to grasp the central problem of psychology, and a disposition
- to let the pen (if it be a book on the subject) wander freely through the
- almost illimitable range of instance, illustration, and application.
- Though it is true that the proper study of mankind is man, it is hardly
- possible to say what might not be brought under this head. _Homo sum,
- nihil a me alienum puto_, it might be urged. Placed in a sort of middle
- ground between physiology (summing up all the results of physical science)
- and general history (including the contributions of all the branches of
- sociology), the psychologist need not want for material. He can wander
- into ethics, aesthetic, and logic, into epistemology and metaphysics. And
- it cannot be said with any conviction that he is actually trespassing, so
- long as the ground remains so ill-fenced and vaguely enclosed. A desultory
- collection of observations on traits of character, anecdotes of mental
- events, mixed up with hypothetical descriptions of how a normal human
- being may be supposed to develop his so-called faculties, and including
- some dictionary-like verbal distinctions, may make a not uninteresting and
- possibly bulky work entitled Psychology.
- It is partly a desire of keeping up to date which is responsible for the
- copious extracts or abstracts from treatises on the anatomy and functions
- of the nerve-system, which, accompanied perhaps by a diagram of the brain,
- often form the opening chapter of a work on psychology. Even if these
- researches had achieved a larger number of authenticated results than they
- as yet have, they would only form an appendix and an illustration to the
- proper subject(42). As they stand, and so long as they remain largely
- hypothetical, the use of them in psychology only fosters the common
- delusion that, when we can picture out in material outlines a theory
- otherwise unsupported, it has gained some further witness in its favour.
- It is quite arguable indeed that it may be useful to cut out a section
- from general human biology which should include the parts of it that were
- specially interesting in connexion with the expression or generation of
- thought, emotion, and desire. But in that case, there is a blunder in
- singling out the brain alone, and especially the organs of sense and
- voluntary motion,—except for the reason that this province of
- psycho-physics alone has been fairly mapped out. The preponderant half of
- the soul’s life is linked to other parts of the physical system. Emotion
- and volition, and the general tone of the train of ideas, if they are to
- be connected with their expression and physical accompaniment (or aspect),
- would require a sketch of the heart and lungs, as well as the digestive
- system in general. Nor these alone. Nerve analysis (especially confined to
- the larger system), though most modern, is not alone important, as Plato
- and Aristotle well saw. So that if biology is to be adapted for
- psychological use (and if psychology deals with more than cognitive
- processes), a liberal amount of physiological information seems required.
- Experimental psychology is a term used with a considerable laxity of
- content; and so too is that of physiological psychology, or
- psycho-physics. And the laxity mainly arises because there is an
- uncertainty as to what is principal and what secondary in the inquiry.
- Experiment is obviously a help to observation: and so far as the latter is
- practicable, the former would seem to have a chance of introduction. But
- in any case, experiment is only a means to an end and only practicable
- under the guidance of hypothesis and theory. Its main value would be in
- case the sphere of psychology were completely paralleled with one province
- of physiology. It was long ago maintained by Spinoza and (in a way by)
- Leibniz, that there is no mental phenomenon without its bodily equivalent,
- pendant, or correspondent. The _ordo rerum_ (the molecular system of
- movements) is, he held, the same as the order of ideas. But it is only at
- intervals, under special conditions, or when they reach a certain
- magnitude, that ideas emerge into full consciousness. As consciousness
- presents them, they are often discontinuous, and abrupt: and they do not
- always carry with them their own explanation. Hence if we are confined to
- the larger phenomena of consciousness alone, our science is imperfect:
- many things seem anomalous; above all, perhaps, will, attention, and the
- like. We have seen how Herbart (partly following the hints of Leibniz),
- attempted to get over this difficulty by the hypothesis of idea-forces
- which generate the forms and matter of consciousness by their mutual
- impact and resistance. Physiological psychology substitutes for Herbart’s
- reals and his idea-forces a more materialistic sort of reality; perhaps
- functions of nerve-cells, or other analogous entities. There, it hopes one
- day to discover the underlying continuity of event which in the upper
- range of consciousness is often obscured, and then the process would be,
- as the phrase goes, explained: we should be able to picture it out without
- a gap.
- These large hopes may have a certain fulfilment. They may lead to the
- withdrawal of some of the fictitious mental processes which are still
- described in works of psychology. But on the whole they can only have a
- negative and auxiliary value. The value, that is, of helping to confute
- feigned connexions and to suggest truer. They will be valid against the
- mode of thought which, when Psyché fails us for an explanation, turns to
- body, and interpolates soul between the states of body: the mode which, in
- an older phraseology, jumps from final causes to physical, and from
- physical (or efficient) to final. Here, as elsewhere, the physical has its
- place: and here, more than in many places, the physical has been unfairly
- treated. But the whole subject requires a discussion of the so-called
- “relations” of soul and body: a subject on which popular conceptions and
- so-called science are radically obscure.
- “But the danger which threatens experimental psychology,” says
- Münsterberg, “is that, in investigating details, the connexion with
- questions of principle may be so lost sight of that the investigation
- finally lands at objects scientifically quite worthless(43). Psychology
- forgets only too easily that all those numerical statistics which
- experiment allows us to form are only means for psychological analysis and
- interpretation, not ends in themselves. It piles up numbers and numbers,
- and fails to ask whether the results so formed have any theoretical value
- whatever: it seeks answers before a question has been clearly and
- distinctly framed; whereas the value of experimental answers always
- depends on the exactitude with which the question is put. Let me remind
- the reader, how one inquirer after another made many thousand experiments
- on the estimation of small intervals of time, without a single one of them
- raising the question what the precise point was which these experiments
- sought to measure, what was the psychological occurrence in the case, or
- what psychological phenomena were employed as the standard of
- time-intervals. And so each had his own arbitrary standard of measurement,
- each of them piled up mountains of numbers, each demonstrated that his
- predecessor was wrong; but neither Estel nor Mehner have carried the
- problem of the time-sense a single step further.
- “This must be all changed, if we are not to drift into the barrenest
- scholastic.... Everywhere out of the correct perception that problems of
- principle demand the investigation of detailed phenomena, and that the
- latter investigation must proceed in comparative independence of the
- question of principles, there has grown the false belief that the
- description of detail phenomena is the ultimate aim of science. And so,
- side by side with details which are of importance to principles, we have
- others, utterly indifferent and theoretically worthless, treated with the
- same zeal. To the solution of their barren problems the old Schoolmen
- applied a certain acuteness; but in order to turn out masses of numbers
- from barren experiments, all that is needed is a certain insensibility to
- fits of ennui. Let numbers be less collected for their own sake: and
- instead, let the problems be so brought to a point that the answers may
- possess the character of principles. Let each experiment be founded on far
- more theoretical considerations, then the number of the experiments may be
- largely diminished(44).”
- What is thus said of a special group of inquiries by one of the foremost
- of the younger psychologists, is not without its bearings on all the
- departments in which psychology can learn. For physiological, or what is
- technically called psychological, experiment, is co-ordinate with many
- other sources of information. Much, for instance, is to be learnt by a
- careful study of language by those who combine sound linguistic knowledge
- with psychological training. It is in language, spoken and written, that
- we find at once the great instrument and the great document of the
- distinctively human progress from a mere _Psyche_ to a mature _Nous_, from
- Soul to Mind. Whether we look at the varieties of its structure under
- different ethnological influences, or at the stages of its growth in a
- nation and an individual, we get light from language on the
- differentiation and consolidation of ideas. But here again it is easy to
- lose oneself in the world of etymology, or to be carried away into the
- enticing questions of real and ideal philology.
- “The human being of the psychologist,” says Herbart(45), “is the social
- and civilised human being who stands on the apex of the whole history
- through which his race has passed. In him is found visibly together all
- the multiplicity of elements, which, under the name of mental faculties,
- are regarded as a universal inheritance of humanity. Whether they are
- originally in conjunction, whether they are originally a multiplicity, is
- a point on which the facts are silent. The savage and the new-born child
- give us far less occasion to admire the range of their mind than do the
- nobler animals. But the psychologists get out of this difficulty by the
- unwarranted assumption that all the higher mental activities exist
- potentially in children and savages—though not in the animals—as a
- rudimentary predisposition or psychical endowment. Of such a nascent
- intellect, a nascent reason, and nascent moral sense, they find
- recognisable traces in the scanty similarities which the behaviour of
- child or savage offers to those of civilised man. We cannot fail to note
- that in their descriptions they have before them a special state of man,
- and one which, far from accurately defined, merely follows the general
- impression made upon us by those beings we name civilised. An extremely
- fluctuating character inevitably marks this total impression. For there
- are no general facts:—the genuine psychological documents lie in the
- momentary states of individuals: and there is an immeasurably long way
- from these to the height of the universal concept of man in general.”
- And yet Man in general,—Man as man and therefore as mind—the concept of
- Man—normal and ideal man—the complete and adequate Idea of man—is the true
- terminus of the psychological process; and whatever be the difficulties in
- the way, it is the only proper goal of the science. Only it has to be
- built up, constructed, evolved, developed,—and not assumed as a datum of
- popular imagination. We want a concept, concrete and real, of Man and of
- Mind, which shall give its proper place to each of the elements that, in
- the several examples open to detailed observation, are presented with
- unfair or exaggerated prominence. The savage and the child are not to be
- left out as free from contributing to form the ideal: virtues here are not
- more important than vices, and are certainly not likely to be so
- informing: even the insane and the idiot show us what human intelligence
- is and requires: and the animals are also within the sweep of psychology.
- Man is not its theatre to the exclusion of woman; if it records the
- results of introspection of the Me, it will find vast and copious quarries
- in the various modes in which an individual identifies himself with others
- as We. And even the social and civilised man gets his designation, as
- usual, _a potiori_. He is more civilised and social than others: perhaps
- rather more civilised than not. But always, in some measure, he is at the
- same time unsocial or anti-social, and uncivilised. Each unit in the
- society of civilisation has to the outside observer—and sometimes even to
- his own self-detached and impartial survey—a certain oddity or fixity, a
- gleam of irrationality, which shows him to fall short of complete sanity
- or limpid and mobile intelligence. He has not wholly put off the
- savage,—least of all, says the cynic, in his relations with the other sex.
- He carries with him even to the grave some grains of the recklessness and
- petulance of childhood. And rarely, if ever, can it be said of him that he
- has completely let the ape and tiger die.
- But that is only one way of looking at the matter—and one which, perhaps,
- is more becoming to the pathologist and the cynic, than to the
- psychologist. Each of these stages of psychical development, even if that
- development be obviously describable as degeneration, has something which,
- duly adjusted, has its place and function in the theory of the
- normally-complete human mind. The animal, the savage, and the child,—each
- has its part there. It is a mutilated, one-sided and superficial advance
- in socialisation which cuts off the civilised creature from the natural
- stem of his ancestry, from the large freedom, the immense _insouciance_,
- the childlikeness of his first estate. There is something, again, wanting
- in the man who utterly lacks the individualising realism and tenderness of
- the woman, as in the woman who can show no comprehension of view or
- bravery of enterprise. Even pathological states of mind are not mere
- anomalies and mere degenerations. Nature perhaps knows no proper
- degenerations, but only by-ways and intricacies in the course of
- development. Still less is the vast enormity or irregularity of genius to
- be ignored. It is all—to the philosophic mind—a question of degree and
- proportion,—though often the proportion seems to exceed the scale of our
- customary denominators. If an element is latent or quiescent (in arrest),
- that is no index to its absolute amount: “we know not what’s resisted.”
- Let us by all means keep proudly to our happy mediocrity of faculty, and
- step clear of insanity or idiotcy on one hand, and from genius or heroism
- on the other. But the careful observer will notwithstanding note how
- delicately graded and how intricately combined are the steps which connect
- extremes so terribly disparate. It is only vulgar ignorance which turns
- away in hostility or contempt from the imbecile and the deranged, and only
- a worse than vulgar sciolism which sees in genius and the hero nothing but
- an aberration from its much-prized average. Criminalistic anthropology, or
- the psychology of the criminal, may have indulged in much frantic
- exaggeration as to the doom which nature and heredity have pronounced over
- the fruit of the womb even before it entered the shores of light: yet they
- have at least served to discredit the free and easy assumption of the
- abstract averagist, and shown how little the penalties of an unbending law
- meet the requirements of social well-being.
- Yet, if psychology be willing to learn in all these and other provinces of
- the estate of man, it must remember that, once it goes beyond the narrow
- range in which the interpretations of symbol and expression have become
- familiar, it is constantly liable to blunder in the inevitable effort to
- translate observation into theory. The happy mean between making too much
- of palpable differences and hurrying on to a similar rendering of similar
- signs is the rarest of gifts. Or, perhaps, it were truer to say it is the
- latest and most hardly won of acquirements. To learn to observe—observe
- with mind—is not a small thing. There are rules for it—both rules of
- general scope and, above all, rules in each special department. But like
- all “major premisses” in practice, everything depends on the power of
- judgment, the tact, the skill, the “gift” of applying them. They work not
- as mere rules to be conned by rote, but as principles assimilated into
- constituents of the mental life-blood: rules which serve only as condensed
- reminders and hints of habits of thought and methods of research which
- have grown up in action and reflection. To observe we must comprehend: yet
- we can only comprehend by observing. We all know how unintelligible—save
- for epochs of ampler reciprocity, and it may be even of acquired unity of
- interest—the two sexes are for each other. Parents can remember how
- mysteriously minded they found their own elders; and in most cases they
- have to experience the depth of the gulf which in certain directions parts
- them from their children’s hearts. Even in civilised Europe, the ordinary
- member of each nation has an underlying conviction (which at moments of
- passion or surprise will rise and find harsh utterance) that the foreigner
- is queer, irrational, and absurd. If the foreigner, further, be so far
- removed as a Chinaman (or an Australian “black”), there is hardly anything
- too vile, meaningless, or inhuman which the European will not readily
- believe in the case of one who, it may be, in turn describes him as a
- “foreign devil.” It can only be in a fit of noble chivalry that the
- British rank and file can so far temporise with its insular prejudice as
- to admit of “Fuzzy-wuzzy” that
- “He’s a poor benighted ’eathen—but a first-class fightin’ man.”
- Not every one is an observer who chooses to dub himself so, nor is it in a
- short lapse of time and with condescension for foreign habits, that any
- observer whatever can become a trustworthy reporter of the ideas some
- barbarian tribe holds concerning the things of earth and air, and the
- hidden things of spirits and gods. The “interviewer” no doubt is a useful
- being when it is necessary to find “copy,” or when sharp-drawn characters
- and picturesque incidents are needed to stimulate an inert public, ever
- open to be interested in some new thing. But he is a poor contributor to
- the stored materials of science.
- It is of other stuff that true science is made. And if even years of
- nominal intercourse and spatial juxtaposition sometimes leave human
- beings, as regards their inner selves, in the position of strangers still,
- what shall be said of the attempt to discern the psychic life of animals?
- Will the touch of curiosity which prompts us to watch the proceedings of
- the strange creatures,—will a course of experimentation on their behaviour
- under artificial conditions,—justify us in drawing liberal conclusions as
- to why they so behaved, and what they thought and felt about it? It is
- necessary in the first place to know what to observe, and how, and above
- all what for. But that presumed, we must further live with the animals not
- only as their masters and their examiners, but as their friends and
- fellow-creatures; we must be able—and so lightly that no effort is
- discernable—to lay aside the burden and garb of civilisation; we must
- possess that stamp of sympathy and similarity which invites confidence,
- and breaks down the reserve which our poor relations, whether human or
- others, offer to the first approaches of a strange superior. It is
- probable that in that case we should have less occasion to wonder at their
- oddities or to admire their sagacity. But a higher and more philosophical
- wonder might, as in other cases when we get inside the heart of our
- subject, take the place of the cheap and childish love of marvels, or of
- the vulgar straining after comic traits.
- Of all this mass of materials the psychologist proper can directly make
- only a sparing use. Even as illustrations, his data must not be presented
- too often in all their crude and undigested individuality, or he runs the
- risk of leaving one-sided impressions. Every single instance,
- individualised and historical,—unless it be exhibited by that true art of
- genius which we cannot expect in the average psychologist—narrows, even
- though it be but slightly, the complete and all-sided truth. Anecdotes are
- good, and to the wise they convey a world of meaning, but to lesser minds
- they sometimes suggest anything but the points they should accentuate.
- Without the detail of individual realistic study there is no psychology
- worth the name. History, story, we must have: but at the same time, with
- the philosopher, we must say, I don’t give much weight to stories. And
- this is what will always—except in rare instances where something like
- genius is conjoined with it—make esoteric science hard and unpopular. It
- dare not—if it is true to its idea—rest on any amount of mere instances,
- as isolated, unreduced facts. Yet it can only have real power so far as it
- concentrates into itself the life-blood of many instances, and indeed
- extracts the pith and unity of all instances.
- Nor, on the other hand, can it turn itself too directly and intently
- towards practical applications. All this theory of mental progress from
- the animate soul to the fullness of religion and science deals solely with
- the universal process of education: “the education of humanity” we may
- call it: the way in which mind is made true and real(46). It is therefore
- a question of intricacy and of time how to carry over this general theory
- into the arena of education as artificially directed and planned. To try
- to do so at a single step would be to repeat the mistake of Plato, if
- Plato may be taken to suppose (which seems incredible) that a theoretical
- study of the dialectics of truth and goodness would enable his rulers,
- without the training of special experience, to undertake the supreme tasks
- of legislation or administration. All politics, like all education, rests
- on these principles of the means and conditions of mental growth: but the
- schooling of concrete life, though it may not develop the faculty of
- formulating general laws, will often train better for the management of
- the relative than a mere logical Scholastic in first or absolute
- principles.
- In conclusion, there are one or two points which seem of cardinal
- importance for the progress of psychology. (1) Its difference from the
- physical sciences has to be set out: in other words, the peculiarity of
- psychical fact. It will not do merely to say that experience marks out
- these boundaries with sufficient clearness. On the contrary, the terms
- consciousness, feeling, mind, &c., are evidently to many psychologists
- mere names. In particular, the habits of physical research when introduced
- into mental study lead to a good deal of what can only be called
- mythology. (2) There should be a clearer recognition of the problem of the
- relations of mental unity to mental elements. But to get that, a more
- thorough logical and metaphysical preparation is needed than is usually
- supposed necessary. The doctrine of identity and necessity, of universal
- and individual, has to be faced, however tedious. (3) The distinction
- between first-grade and second-grade elements and factors in the mental
- life has to be realised. The mere idea as presentative or immediate has to
- be kept clear of the more logico-reflective, or normative ideas, which
- belong to judgment and reasoning. And the number of these grades in mental
- development seems endless. (4) But, also, a separation is required—were it
- but temporary—between what may be called principles, and what is detail.
- At present, in psychology, “principles” is a word almost without meaning.
- A complete all-explaining system is of course impossible at present and
- may always be so. Yet if an effort of thought could be concentrated on
- cardinal issues, and less padding of conventional and traditional detail
- were foisted in, much might thereby be done to make detailed research
- fruitful. (5) And finally, perhaps, if psychology be a philosophical
- study, some hint as to its purpose and problem would be desirable. If it
- is only an abstract branch of science, of course, no such hint is in
- place.
- Essay III. On Some Psychological Aspects Of Ethics.
- Allusion has already been made to the question of the boundaries between
- logic and psychology, between logic and ethics, ethics and psychology, and
- psychology and epistemology. Each of these occasionally comes to cover
- ground that seems more appropriate to the others. Logic is sometimes
- restricted to denote the study of the conditions of derivative knowledge,
- of the canons of inference and the modes of proof. If taken more widely as
- the science of thought-form, it is supposed to imply a world of fixed or
- stereotyped relations between ideas, a system of stable thoughts governed
- by inflexible laws in an absolute order of immemorial or eternal truth. As
- against such fixity, psychology is supposed to deal with these same ideas
- as products—as growing out of a living process of thought—having a history
- behind them and perhaps a prospect of further change. The genesis so given
- may be either a mere chronicle-history, or it may be a philosophical
- development. In the former case, it would note the occasions of incident
- and circumstance, the reactions of mind and environment, under which the
- ideas were formed. Such a psychological genesis of several ideas is found
- in the Second Book of Locke’s Essay. In the latter case, the account would
- be more concerned with the inner movement, the action and reaction in
- ideas themselves, considered not as due to casual occurrences, but as
- self-developing by an organic growth. But in either case, ideas would be
- shown not to be ready-made and independently existing kinds in a world of
- idea-things, and not to form an unchanging diagram or framework, but to be
- a growth, to have a history, and a development. Psychology in this sense
- would be a dynamical, as opposed to the supposed statical, treatment of
- ideas and concepts in logic. But it may be doubted how far it is well to
- call this psychology: unless psychology deals with the contents of the
- mental life, in their meaning and purpose, instead of, as seems proper,
- merely in their character of psychic events. Such psychology is rather an
- evolutionist logic,—a dialectic process more than an analytic of a datum.
- In the same way, ethics may be brought into one kind of contact with
- psychology. Ethics, like logic, may be supposed to presuppose and to deal
- with a certain inflexible scheme of requirements, a world of moral order
- governed by invariable or universal law; an eternal kingdom of right,
- existing independently of human wills, but to be learned and followed out
- in uncompromising obedience. As against this supposed absolute order,
- psychology may be said to show the genesis of the idea of obligation and
- duty, the growth of the authority of conscience, the formation of ideals,
- the relativity of moral ideas. Here also it may reach this conclusion, by
- a more external or a more internal mode of argument. It may try to show,
- in other words, that circumstances give rise to these forms of estimating
- conduct, or it may argue that they are a necessary development in the
- human being, constituted as he is. It may again be doubted whether this is
- properly called psychology. Yet its purport seems ultimately to be that
- the objective order is misconceived when it is regarded as an external or
- quasi-physical order: as a law written up and sanctioned with an external
- authority—as, in Kant’s words, a heteronomy. If that order is objective,
- it is so because it is also in a sense subjective: if it is above the mere
- individuality of the individual, it is still in a way identical with his
- true or universal self-hood. Thus “psychological” here means the
- recognition that the logical and the moral law is an autonomy: that it is
- not given, but though necessary, necessary by the inward movement of the
- mind. The metaphor of law is, in brief, misleading. For, according to a
- common, though probably an erroneous, analysis of that term, the essence
- of a law in the political sphere is to be a species of command. And that
- is rather a one-sidedly practical or aesthetic way of looking at it. The
- essence of law in general, and the precondition of every law in special,
- is rather uniformity and universality, self-consistency and absence of
- contradiction: or, in other words, rationality. Its essential opposite—or
- its contradiction in essence—is a privilege, an attempt at isolating a
- case from others. It need not indeed always require bare
- uniformity—require i.e. the same act to be done by different people: but
- it must always require that every thing within its operation shall be
- treated on principles of utter and thorough harmony and consistency. It
- requires each thing to be treated on public principles and with publicity:
- nothing apart and mere singular, as a mere incident or as a world by
- itself. Differently it may be treated, but always on grounds of common
- well-being, as part of an embracing system.
- There is probably another sense, however, in which psychology comes into
- close relation with ethics. If we look on man as a microcosm, his inner
- system will more or less reproduce the system of the larger world. The
- older psychology used to distinguish an upper or superior order of
- faculties from a lower or inferior. Thus in the intellectual sphere, the
- intellect, judgment, and reason were set above the senses, imagination,
- and memory. Among the active powers, reasonable will, practical reason and
- conscience were ranked as paramount over the appetites and desires and
- emotions. And this use of the word “faculty” is as old as Plato, who
- regards science as a superior faculty to opinion or imagination. But this
- application—which seems a perfectly legitimate one—does not, in the first
- instance, belong to psychology at all. No doubt it is psychically
- presented: but it has an other source. It springs from an appreciation, a
- judgment of the comparative truth or reality of what the so-called
- psychical act means or expresses. Such faculties are powers in a hierarchy
- of means and ends and presuppose a normative or critical function which
- has classified reality. Psychically, the elements which enter into
- knowledge are not other than those which belong to opinion: but they are
- nearer an adequate rendering of reality, they are truer, or nearer the
- Idea. And in the main we may say, that is truer or more real which
- succeeds in more completely organising and unifying elements—which rises
- more and more above the selfish or isolated part into the thorough unity
- of all parts.
- The superior faculty is therefore the more thorough organisation of that
- which is elsewhere less harmoniously systematised. Opinion is fragmentary
- and partial: it begins abruptly and casually from the unknown, and runs
- off no less abruptly into the unknown. Knowledge, on the contrary, is
- unified: and its unity gives it its strength and superiority. The powers
- which thus exist are the subjective counterparts of objectively valuable
- products. Thus, reason is the subjective counterpart of a world in which
- all the constituents are harmonised and fall into due relationship. It is
- a product or result, which is not psychologically, but logically or
- morally important. It is a faculty, because it means that actually its
- possessor has ordered and systematised his life or his ideas of things.
- Psychologically, it, like unreason, is a compound of elements: but in the
- case of reason the composition is unendingly and infinitely consistent; it
- is knowledge completely unified. The distinction then is not in the
- strictest sense psychological: for it has an aesthetic or normative
- character; it is logical or ethical: it denotes that the idea or the act
- is an approach to truth or goodness. And so, when Butler or Plato
- distinguishes reason or reflection from appetites and affections, and even
- from self-love or from the heart which loves and hates, this is not
- exactly a psychological division in the narrower sense. That is to say:
- these are, in Plato’s words, not merely “parts,” but quite as much “kinds”
- and “forms” of soul. They denote degrees in that harmonisation of mind and
- soul which reproduces the permanent and complete truth of things. For
- example, self-love, as Butler describes it, has but a partial and narrowed
- view of the worth of acts: it is engrossing and self-involved: it cannot
- take in the full dependence of the narrower interest on the larger and
- eternal self. So, in Plato, the man of heart is but a nature which by fits
- and starts, or with steady but limited vision, realises the larger life.
- These parts or kinds are not separate and co-existent faculties: but
- grades in the co-ordination and unification of the same one human nature.
- (i.) Psychology and Epistemology.
- Psychology however in the strict sense is extremely difficult to define.
- Those who describe it as the “science of mind,” the “phenomenology of
- consciousness,” seem to give it a wider scope than they really mean. The
- psychologist of the straiter sect tends, on the other hand, to carry us
- beyond mind and consciousness altogether. His, it has been said, is a
- psychology without a Psyché. For him Mind, Soul, and Consciousness are
- only current and convenient names to designate the field, the ground on
- which the phenomena he observes are supposed to transact themselves. But
- they must not on any account interfere with the operations; any more than
- Nature in general may interfere with strictly physical inquiries, or Life
- and vital force with the theories of biology. The so-called Mind is only
- to be regarded as a stage on which certain events represent themselves. In
- this field, or on this stage, there are certain relatively ultimate
- elements, variously called ideas, presentations, feelings, or states of
- consciousness. But these elements, though called ideas, must not be
- supposed more than mechanical or dynamical elements; consciousness is
- rather their product, a product which presupposes certain operations and
- relations between them. If we are to be strictly scientific, we must, it
- is urged, treat the factors of consciousness as not themselves conscious:
- we must regard them as quasi-objective, or in abstraction from the
- consciousness which surveys them. The Ego must sink into a mere receptacle
- or arena of psychic event; its independent meaning or purport is to be
- ignored, as beside the question.
- When this line is once fixed upon, it seems inevitable to go farther.
- Comte was inclined to treat psychology as falling between two stools: it
- must, he thought, draw all its content either from physiology on the one
- hand, or from social factors on the other. The dominant or experimental
- psychology of the present day seems inclined, without however formulating
- any very definite statement, to pronounce for the former alternative. It
- does not indeed adopt the materialistic view that mind is only a function
- of matter. Its standpoint rather is that the psychical presents itself
- even to unskilled observation as dependent on (i.e. not independent of) or
- as concomitant with certain physical or corporeal facts. It adds that the
- more accurately trained the observer becomes, the more he comes to
- discover a corporeal aspect even where originally he had not surmised its
- existence, and to conclude that the two cycles of psychical and physical
- event never interfere with each other: that soul does not intervene in
- bodily process, nor body take up and carry on psychical. If it is said
- that the will moves the limbs, he replies that the will which moves is
- really certain formerly unnoticed movements of nerve and muscle which are
- felt or interpreted as a discharge of power. If the ocular impression is
- said to cause an impression on the mind, he replies that any fact hidden
- under that phrase refers to a change in the molecules of the brain. He
- will therefore conclude that for the study of psychical phenomena the
- physical basis, as it may be called, is all important. Only so can
- observation really deal with fact capable of description and measurement.
- Thus psychology, it may be said, tends to become a department of
- physiology. From another standpoint, biology may be said to receive its
- completion in psychology. How much either phrase means, however, will
- depend on the estimate we form of biology. If biology is only the study of
- mechanical and chemical phenomena on the peculiar field known as an
- organism, and if that organism is only treated as an environment which may
- be ignored, then psychology, put on the same level, is not the full
- science of mind, any more than the other is the full study of life. They
- both have narrowed their subject to suit the abstract scheme of the
- laboratory, where the victim of experiment is either altered by mutilation
- and artificial restrictions, or is dead. If, on the contrary, biology has
- a substantial unity of its own to which mechanical and chemical
- considerations are subordinate and instrumental, psychology may even take
- part with physiology without losing its essential rank. But in that case,
- we must, as Spinoza said(47), think less mechanically of the animal frame,
- and recognise (after the example of Schelling) something truly inward
- (i.e. not merely locally inside the skin) as the supreme phase or
- characteristic of life. We must, in short, recognise sensibility as the
- culmination of the physiological and the beginning of the psychological.
- To the strictly scientific psychologist, as has been noted—or to the
- psychology which imitates optical and electrical science—ideas are only
- psychical events: they are not ideas _of_ anything, relative, i.e. to
- something else; they have no meaning, and no reference to a reality beyond
- themselves. They are presentations;—not representations of something
- outside consciousness. They are appearances: but not appearances of
- something: they do not reveal anything beyond themselves. They are, we may
- almost say, a unique kind of physical phenomena. If we say they are
- presentations of something, we only mean that in the presented something,
- in the felt something, the wished something, we separate the quality or
- form or aspect of presentativeness, of feltness, of wishedness, and
- consider this aspect by itself. There are grades, relations,
- complications, of such presentations or in such presentedness: and with
- the description and explanation of these, psychology is concerned. They
- are fainter or stronger, more or less correlated and antithetical.
- Presentation (or ideation), in short, is the name of a train of event,
- which has its peculiarities, its laws, its systems, its history.
- All reality, it may be said, subsists in such presentation; it is for a
- consciousness, or in a consciousness. All _esse_, in its widest sense, is
- _percipi_. And yet, it seems but the commonest of experiences to say that
- all that is presented is not reality. It _is_, it has a sort of being,—is
- somehow presumed to exist: but it is not reality. And this reference and
- antithesis to _what_ is presented is implied in all such terms as “ideas,”
- “feelings,” “states of consciousness”: they are distinguished from and
- related to objects of sense or external facts, to something, as it is
- called, outside consciousness. Thoughts and ideas are set against things
- and realities. In their primitive stage both the child and the savage seem
- to recognise no such difference. What they imagine is, as we might say, on
- the same plane with what they touch and feel. They do not, as we
- reproachfully remark, recognise the difference between fact and fiction.
- All of us indeed are liable to lapses into the same condition. A strong
- passion, a keen hope or fear, as we say, invests its objects with reality:
- even a sanguine moment presents as fact what calmer reflection disallows
- as fancy. With natural and sane intelligences, however, the recrudescence
- of barbarous imagination is soon dispelled, and the difference between
- hallucinations and realities is established. With the utterly wrecked in
- mind, the reality of hallucinations becomes a permanent or habitual state.
- With the child and the untrained it is a recurrent and a disturbing
- influence: and it need hardly be added that the circle of these _decepti
- deceptores_—people with the “lie in the Soul”—is a large one. There thus
- emerges a distinction of vast importance, that of truth and falsehood, of
- reality and unreality, or between representation and reality. There arise
- two worlds, the world of ideas, and the world of reality which it is
- supposed to represent, and, in many cases, to represent badly.
- With this distinction we are brought across the problem sometimes called
- Epistemological. Strictly speaking, it is really part of a larger problem:
- the problem of what—if Greek compounds must be used—may be styled
- Aletheiology—the theory of truth and reality: what Hegel called Logic, and
- what many others have called Metaphysics. As it is ordinarily taken up,
- “ideas” are believed to be something _in us_ which is representative or
- symbolical of something truly real _outside us_. This inward something is
- said to be the first and immediate object of knowledge(48), and gives
- us—in a mysterious way we need not here discuss—the mediate knowledge of
- the reality, which is sometimes said to cause it. Ideas in the Mind, or in
- the Subject, or in us, bear witness to something outside the
- mind,—trans-subjective—beyond us. The Mind, Subject, or Ego, in this
- parallelism is evidently in some way identified with our corporeal
- organism: perhaps even located, and provided with a “seat,” in some
- defined space of that organism. It is, however, the starting-point of the
- whole distinction that ideas _do not_, no less than they do, conform or
- correspond to this supra-conscious or extra-conscious world of real
- things. Truth or falsehood arises, according to these assumptions,
- according as psychical image or idea corresponds or not to physical fact.
- But how, unless by some miraculous second-sight, where the supreme
- consciousness, directly contemplating by intuition the true and
- independent reality, turns to compare with this immediate vision the
- results of the mediate processes conducted along the organs of sense,—how
- this agreement or disagreement of copy and original, of idea and reality,
- can be detected, it is impossible to say.
- As has been already noted, the mischief lies in the hypostatisation of
- ideas as something existing in abstraction from things—and, of things, in
- abstraction from ideas. They are two abstractions, the first by the
- realist, the second by the idealist called subjective and psychological.
- To the realist, things exist by themselves, and they manage to produce a
- copy of themselves (more or less exact, or symbolical) in _our_ mind, i.e.
- in a materialistically-spiritual or a spiritualistically-material locus
- which holds “images” and ideas. To the psychological idealist, ideas have
- a substantive and primary right to existence, them alone do we really
- know, and from them we more or less legitimately are said (but probably no
- one takes this seriously) to infer or postulate a world of permanent
- things. Now ideas have no substantive existence as a sort of things, or
- even images of things anywhere. All this is pure mythology. It is said by
- comparative mythologists that in some cases the epithet or quality of some
- deity has been substantialised (hypostatised) into a separate god, who,
- however (so still to keep up the unity), is regarded as a relative, a son,
- or daughter, of the original. So the phrase “ideas of things” has been
- taken literally as if it was double. But to have an idea of a thing merely
- means that we know it, or think it. An idea is not given: it is a thing
- which is given in the idea. An idea is not an additional and intervening
- object of our knowledge or supposed knowledge. That a thing is our object
- of thought is another word for its being our idea, and that means we know
- it.
- The distinction between truth and falsehood, between reality and
- appearance, is not arrived at by comparing what we have before us in our
- mind with some inaccessible reality beyond. It is a distinction that grows
- up with the growth and organisation of our presentations—with their
- gradual systematisation and unification in one consciousness. But this
- consciousness which thinks, i.e. judges and reasons, is something superior
- to the contrast of physical and psychical: superior, i.e. in so far as it
- includes and surveys the antithesis, without superseding it. It is the
- “transcendental unity of consciousness” of Kant—his synthetic unity of
- apperception. It means that all ideas ultimately derive their reality from
- their coherence with each other in an all-embracing or infinite idea. Real
- in a sense ideas always are, but with an imperfect reality. Thus the
- education to truth is not—such a thing would be meaningless—ended by a
- rough and ready recommendation to compare our ideas with facts: it must
- teach the art which discovers facts. And the teaching may have to go
- through many grades or provinces: in each of which it is possible to
- acquire a certain virtuosoship without being necessarily an adept in
- another. It is through what is called the development of intellect,
- judgment, and reasoning that the faculty of truth-detecting or
- truth-selecting comes. And the common feature of all of these is, so to
- say, their superiority to the psychological mechanism, not in the sense of
- working without it and directly, but of being the organising unity or
- unifier and controller and judge of that mechanism. The certainty and
- necessity of truth and knowledge do not come from a constraint from the
- external thing which forces the inner idea into submission; they come from
- the inner necessity of conformity and coherence in the organism of
- experience. We in fact had better speak of ideas as experience—as felt
- reality: a reality however which has its degrees and perhaps even its
- provinces. All truth comes with the reasoned judgment, i.e. the
- syllogism—i.e. with the institution or discovery of relations of fact or
- element to fact or element, immediate or derivative, partial and less
- partial, up to its ideal coherence in one Idea. It is because this
- coherence is so imperfectly established in many human beings that their
- knowledge is so indistinguishable from opinion, and that they separate so
- loosely truth from error. They have not worked their way into a definitely
- articulated system, where there are no gaps, no abrupt transitions: their
- mental order is so loosely put together that divergences and
- contradictions which vex another drop off ineffectual from them.
- (ii.) Kant, Fichte, and Hegel.
- This was the idealism which Kant taught and Fichte promoted. Of the other
- idealism there are no doubt abundant traces in the language of Kant: and
- they were greedily fastened on by Schopenhauer. To him the doctrine, that
- the world is my idea, is adequately represented when it is translated into
- the phrase that the world is a phantasmagoria of my brain; and escape from
- the subjective idealism thus initiated is found by him only through a
- supposed revelation of immediate being communicated in the experience of
- will. But according to the more consistently interpreted Kant, the problem
- of philosophy consists in laying bare the supreme law or conditions of
- consciousness on which depend the validity of our knowledge, our estimates
- of conduct, and our aesthetic standards. And these roots of reality are
- for Kant in the mind—or, should we rather say—in mind—in “Consciousness in
- General.” In the _Criticism of Pure Reason_ the general drift of his
- examination is to show that the great things or final realities which are
- popularly supposed to stand in self-subsistent being, as ultimate and
- all-comprehensive objects set up for knowledge, are not “things” as
- popularly supposed, but imperative and inevitable ideas. They are not
- objects to be known—(these are always finite): but rather the unification,
- the basis, or condition, and the completion of all knowledge. To know
- them—in the ordinary petty sense of knowledge—is as absurd and impossible
- as it would be, in the Platonic scheme of reality, to know the idea of
- good which is “on the further side of knowledge and being.” God and the
- Soul—and the same would be true of the World (though modern speculators
- sometimes talk as if they had it at least within their grasp)—are not mere
- _objects_ of knowledge. It would be truer to say they are that by which we
- know, and they are what in us knows: they make knowledge possible, and
- actual. Kant has sometimes spoken of them as the objects of a faith of
- reason. What he means is that reason only issues in knowledge because of
- and through this inevitable law of reason bidding us go on for ever in our
- search, because there can be nothing isolated and nowhere any _ne plus
- ultra_ in science, which is infinite and yet only justified as it
- postulates or commands unity.
- Kant’s central idea is that truth, beauty, goodness, are not dependent on
- some qualities of the object, but on the universal nature or law of
- consciousness. Beauty is not an attribute of things in their abstractness:
- but of things as ideas of a subject, and depends on the proportion and
- symmetry in the play of human faculty. Goodness is not conformity to an
- outward law, but is obligatory on us through that higher nature which is
- our truer being. Truth is not conformity of ideas with supposed
- trans-subjective things, but coherence and stability in the system of
- ideas. The really infinite world is not out there, but in here—in
- consciousness in general, which is the denial of all limitation, of all
- finality, of all isolation. God is the essential and inherent unity and
- unifier of spirit and nature—the surety that the world in all its
- differentiations is one. The Soul is not an essential entity, but the
- infinite fruitfulness and freshness of mental life, which forbids us
- stopping at anything short of complete continuity and unity. The Kingdom
- of God—the Soul—the moral law—is within us: within us, as supreme,
- supra-personal and infinite intelligences, even amid all our littleness
- and finitude. Even happiness which we stretch our arms after is not really
- beyond us, but is the essential self which indeed we can only reach in
- detail. It is so both in knowledge and in action. Each knowledge and
- enjoyment in reality is limited and partial, but it is made stable, and it
- gets a touch of infinitude, by the larger idea which it helps to realise.
- Only indeed in that antithesis between the finite and the infinite does
- the real live. Every piece of knowledge is real, only because it assumes
- _pro tempore_ certain premisses which are given: every actual beauty is
- set in some defect of aesthetic completeness: every actually good deed has
- to get its foil in surrounding badness. The real is always partial and
- incomplete. But it has the basis or condition of its reality in an idea—in
- a transcendental unity of consciousness, which is so to say a law, or a
- system and an order, which imposes upon it the condition of conformity and
- coherence; but a conformity which is essential and implicit in it.
- Fichte has called his system a _Wissenschaftslehre_—a theory of knowledge.
- Modern German used the word _Wissenschaft_, as modern English uses the
- word Science, to denote the certified knowledge of piecemeal fact, the
- partial unification of elements still kept asunder. But by _Wissen_, as
- opposed to _Erkennen_, is meant the I know, am aware and sure, am in
- contact with reality, as opposed to the derivative and conditional
- reference of something to something else which explains it. The former is
- a wider term: it denotes all consciousness of objective truth, the
- certainty which claims to be necessary and universal, which pledges its
- whole self for its assertion. Fichte thus unifies and accentuates the
- common element in the Kantian criticisms. In the first of these Kant had
- begun by explaining the nature and limitation of empirical science. It was
- essentially conditioned by the given sensation—dependent i.e. on an
- unexplained and preliminary element. This is what makes it science in the
- strict or narrow sense of the term: its being set, as it were, in the
- unknown, the felt, the sense-datum. The side of reality is thus the side
- of limitation and of presupposition. But what makes it truth and knowledge
- in general, on the other hand,—as distinct from _a_ truth (i.e. partial
- truth) and a knowledge,—is the ideal element—the mathematical, the
- logical, the rational law,—or in one word, the universal and formal
- character. So too every real action is on one hand the product of an
- impulse, a dark, merely given, immediate tendency to be, and without that
- would be nothing: but on the other hand it is only an intelligent and
- moral action in so far as it has its constitution from an intelligence, a
- formal system, which determine its place and function.
- It is on the latter or ideal element that Kant makes the emphasis
- increasingly turn. Not truths, duties, beauties, but truth, duty, beauty,
- form his theme. The formal element—the logical or epistemological
- condition of knowledge and morality and of beauty—is what he (and still
- more Fichte) considers the prime question of fundamental philosophy. His
- philosophy is an attempt to get at the organism of our fundamental
- belief—the construction, from the very base, of our conception of reality,
- of our primary certainty. In technical language, he describes our
- essential nature as a Subject-object. It is the unity of an I am which is
- also I know that I am: an I will which is also I am conscious of my
- will(49). Here there is a radical disunion and a supersession of that
- disunion. Action and contemplation are continually outrunning each other.
- The I will rests upon one I know, and works up to another: the I know
- reflects upon an I will, and includes it as an element in its idea.
- Kant had brought into use the term Deduction, and Fichte follows him. The
- term leads to some confusion: for in English, by its modern antithesis to
- induction, it suggests _a priori_ methods in all their iniquity. It means
- a kind of jugglery which brings an endless series out of one small term.
- Kant has explained that he uses it in the lawyer’s sense in which a claim
- is justified by being traced step by step back to some acknowledged and
- accepted right(50). It is a regressive method which shows us that if the
- original datum is to be accepted it carries along with it the legitimation
- of the consequence. This method Fichte applies to psychology. Begin, he
- says like Condillac, with the barest nucleus of soul-life; the mere
- sentiency, or feeling: the contact, as it were, with being, at a single
- point. But such a mere point is unthinkable. You find, as Mr. Spencer
- says, that “Thought” (or Consciousness) “cannot be framed out of one term
- only.” “Every sensation to be known as one must be perceived.” Such is the
- nature of the Ego—a subject which insists on each part being qualified by
- the whole and so transformed. As Mr. Spencer, again, puts it, the mind not
- merely tends to revive, to associate, to assimilate, to represent its own
- presentations, but it carries on this process infinitely and in ever
- higher multiples. Ideas as it were are growing in complexity by
- re-presenting: i.e. by embracing and enveloping elements which cannot be
- found existing in separation. In the mind there is no mere presentation,
- no bare sensation. Such a unit is a fiction or hypothesis we employ, like
- the atom, for purposes of explanation. The pure sensation therefore—which
- you admit because you must have something to begin with, not a mere
- nothing, but something so simple that it seems to stand out clear and
- indisputable—this pure sensation, when you think of it, forces you to go a
- good deal further. Even to be itself, it must be more than itself. It is
- like the pure or mere being of the logicians. Admit the simple
- sensation—and you have admitted everything which is required to make
- sensation a possible reality. But you do not—in the sense of vulgar
- logic—deduce what follows out of the beginning. From that, taken by
- itself, you will get only itself: mere being will give you only nothing,
- to the end of the chapter. But, as the phrase is, sensation is an element
- in a consciousness: it is, when you think of it, always more than you
- called it: there is a curious “continuity” about the phenomena, which
- makes real isolation impossible.
- Of course this “deduction” is not history: it is logic. It says, if you
- posit sensation, then in doing so, you posit a good deal more. You have
- imagination, reason, and many more, all involved in your original
- assumption. And there is a further point to be noted. You cannot really
- stop even at reason, at intelligence and will, if you take these in the
- full sense. You must realise that these only exist as part and parcel of a
- reasonable world. An individual intelligence presupposes a society of
- intelligences. The successive steps in this argument are presented by
- Fichte in the chief works of his earlier period (1794-98). The works of
- that period form a kind of trilogy of philosophy, by which the faint
- outlines of the absolute selfhood is shown acquiring definite consistency
- in the moral organisation of society. First comes the “Foundation for the
- collective philosophy.” It shows how our conception of reality and our
- psychical organisation are inevitably presupposed in the barest function
- of intelligence, in the abstractest forms of logical law. Begin where you
- like, with the most abstract and formal point of consciousness, you are
- forced, as you dwell upon it (you identifying yourself with the thought
- you realise), to go step by step on till you accept as a self-consistent
- and self-explanatory unity all that your cognitive and volitional nature
- claims to own as its birthright. Only in such an intelligent will is
- perception and sensation possible. Next came the “Foundation of Natural
- Law, on the principles of the general theory.” Here the process of
- deduction is carried a step further. If man is to realise himself as an
- intelligence with an inherent bent to action, then he must be conceived as
- a person among persons, as possessed of rights, as incapable of acting
- without at the same moment claiming for his acts recognition, generality,
- and logical consecution. The reference, which in the conception of a
- practical intelligence was implicit,—the reference to fellow-agents, to a
- world in which law rules—is thus, by the explicit recognition of these
- references, made a fact patent and positive—_gesetzt_,—expressly
- instituted in the way that the nature and condition of things postulates.
- But this is not all: we step from the formal and absolute into the
- material and relative. If man is to be a real intelligence, he must be an
- intelligence served by organs. “The rational being cannot realise its
- efficient individuality, unless it ascribes to itself a material body”: a
- body, moreover, in which Fichte believes he can show that the details of
- structure and organs are equally with the general corporeity predetermined
- by reason(51). In the same way it is shown that the social and political
- organisation is required for the realisation—the making positive and yet
- coherent—of the rights of all individuals. You deduce society by showing
- it is required to make a genuine individual man. Thirdly came the “System
- of Ethics.” Here it is further argued that, at least in a certain
- respect(52), in spite of my absolute reason and my absolute freedom, I can
- only be fully real as a part of Nature: that my reason is realised in a
- creature of appetite and impulse. From first to last this deduction is one
- process which may be said to have for its object to determine “the
- conditions of self-hood or egoity.” It is the deduction of the concrete
- and empirical moral agent—the actual ego of actual life—from the abstract,
- unconditioned ego, which in order to be actual must condescend to be at
- once determining and determined.
- In all of this Fichte makes—especially formally—a decided advance upon
- Kant. In Ethics Kant in particular, (—especially for readers who never got
- beyond the beginning of his moral treatise and were overpowered by the
- categorical imperative of duty) had found the moral initiative or dynamic
- apparently in the other world. The voice of duty seemed to speak from a
- region outside and beyond the individual conscience. In a sense it must do
- so: but it comes from a consciousness which is, and yet is more than, the
- individual. It is indeed true that appearances here are deceptive: and
- that the idea of autonomy, the self-legislation of reason, is trying to
- become the central conception of Kant’s Ethics. Still it is Fichte’s merit
- to have seen this clearly, to have held it in view unfalteringly, and to
- have carried it out in undeviating system or deduction. Man, intelligent,
- social, ethical, is a being all of one piece and to be explained entirely
- immanently, or from himself. Law and ethics are no accident either to
- sense or to intelligence—nothing imposed by mere external or supernal
- authority(53). Society is not a brand-new order of things supervening upon
- and superseding a state of nature, where the individual was entirely
- self-supporting. Morals, law, society, are all necessary steps (necessary
- i.e. in logic, and hence in the long run also inevitable in course of
- time) to complete the full evolution or realisation of a human being. The
- same conditions as make man intelligent make him social and moral. He does
- not proceed so far as to become intelligent and practical, under terms of
- natural and logical development, then to fall into the hands of a foreign
- influence, an accident _ab extra_, which causes him to become social and
- moral. Rather he is intelligent, because he is a social agent.
- Hence, in Fichte, the absence of the ascetic element so often stamping its
- character on ethics, and representing the moral life as the enemy of the
- natural, or as mainly a struggle to subdue the sensibility and the flesh.
- With Kant,—as becomes his position of mere inquirer—the sensibility has
- the place of a predominant and permanent foreground. Reason, to his way of
- talking, is always something of an intruder, a stranger from a far-off
- world, to be feared even when obeyed: sublime, rather than beautiful. From
- the land of sense which we habitually occupy, the land of reason is a
- country we can only behold from afar: or if we can be said to have a
- standpoint in it, that is only a figurative way of saying that though it
- is really over the border, we can act—it would sometimes seem by a sort of
- make-believe—as if we were already there. But these moments of high
- enthusiasm are rare; and Kant commends sobriety and warns against
- high-minded _Schwärmerei_, or over-strained Mysticism. For us it is
- reserved to struggle with a recalcitrant selfhood, a grovelling
- sensibility: it were only fantastic extravagance, fit for “fair souls” who
- unfortunately often lapse into “fair sinners,” should we fancy ourselves
- already anchored in the haven of untempted rest and peace.
- When we come to Fichte, we find another spirit breathing. We have passed
- from the age of Frederick the Great to the age of the French Revolution;
- and the breeze that burst in the War of Liberation is already beginning to
- freshen the air. Boldly he pronounces the primacy of that faith of reason
- whereby not merely the just but all shall live. Your will shall show you
- what you really are. You are essentially a rational will, or a
- will-reason. Your sensuous nature, of impulse and appetite, far from being
- the given and found obstacle to the realisation of reason,—which Kant
- strictly interpreted might sometimes seem to imply—(and in this point
- Schopenhauer carries out the implications of Kant)—is really the condition
- or mode of being which reason assumes, or rises up to, in order to be a
- practical or moral being. Far from the body and the sensible needs being a
- stumbling-block to hamper the free fullness of rationality and morality,
- the truth rather is that it is only by body and sense, by flesh and blood,
- that the full moral and rational life can be realised(54). Or, to put it
- otherwise, if human reason (intelligence and will) is to be more than a
- mere and empty inner possibility, if man is to be a real and concrete
- cognitive and volitional being, he must be a member of an ethical and
- actual society, which lives by bread, and which marries and has children.
- (iii.) Psychology in Ethics.
- In this way, for Fichte, and through Fichte still more decidedly for
- Hegel, both psychology and ethics breathe an opener and ampler air than
- they often enjoy. Psychology ceases to be a mere description of psychic
- events, and becomes the history of the self-organising process of human
- reason. Ethics loses its cloistered, negative, unnatural aspect, and
- becomes a name for some further conditions of the same development,
- essentially postulated to complete or supplement its shortcomings.
- Psychology—taken in this high philosophical acceptation—thus leads on to
- Ethics; and Ethics is parted by no impassable line from Psychology. That,
- at least, is what must happen if they are still to retain a place in
- philosophy: for, as Kant says(55), “under the government of reason our
- cognitions cannot form a rhapsody, but must constitute a system, in which
- alone can they support and further its essential aims.” As parts of such a
- system, they carry out their special work in subordination to, and in the
- realisation of, a single Idea—and therefore in essential interconnexion.
- From that interconnecting band we may however in detail-enquiry dispense
- ourselves; and then we have the empirical or inductive sciences of
- psychology and ethics. But even with these, the necessity of the situation
- is such that it is only a question of degree how far we lose sight of the
- philosophical horizon, and entrench ourselves in special enquiry.
- Something of the philosophic largeness must always guide us; even when, to
- further the interests of the whole, it is necessary for the special
- enquirer to bury himself entirely in his part. So long as each part is
- sincerely and thoroughly pursued, and no part is neglected, there is an
- indwelling reason in the parts which will in the long run tend to
- constitute the total.
- A philosophical psychology will show us how the sane intelligence and the
- rational will are, at least approximately, built up out of elements, and
- through stages and processes, which modify and complement, as they may
- also arrest and perplex, each other. The unity, coherence, and
- completeness of the intelligent self is not, as vulgar irreflectiveness
- supposes and somewhat angrily maintains, a full-grown thing or agent, of
- whose actions and modes of behaviour the psychologist has to narrate the
- history,—a history which is too apt to degenerate into the anecdotal and
- the merely interesting. This unity of self has to be “deduced,” as Fichte
- would say: it has to be shown as the necessary result which certain
- elements in a certain order will lead to(56). A normal mind,
- self-possessed, developed and articulated, yet thoroughly one, a real
- microcosm, or true and full monad, which under the mode of its
- individuality still represents the universe: that is, what psychology has
- to show as the product of factors and processes. And it is clearly
- something great and good, something valuable, and already possessing, by
- implication we may say, an ethical character.
- In philosophy, at least, it is difficult, or rather impossible to draw a
- hard and fast line which shall demarcate ethical from non-ethical
- characters,—to separate them from other intellectual and reasonable
- motives. Kant, as we know, attempted to do so: but with the result that he
- was forced to add a doubt whether a purely moral act could ever be said to
- exist(57); or rather to express the certainty that if it did it was for
- ever inaccessible to observation. All such designations of the several
- “factors” or “moments” in reality, as has been hinted, are only _a
- potiori_. But they are misused when it is supposed that they connote
- abrupt and total discontinuity. And Kant, after all, only repeated in his
- own terminology an old and inveterate habit of thought:—the habit which in
- Stoicism seemed to see sage and foolish utterly separated, and which in
- the straiter sects of Christendom fenced off saint absolutely from sinner.
- It is a habit to which Hegel, and even his immediate predecessors, are
- radically opposed. With Herder, he might say, “Ethics is only a higher
- physics of the mind(58).” This—the truth in Spinozism—no doubt demands
- some emphasis on the word “higher”: and it requires us to read ethics (or
- something like it) into physics; but it is a step on the right road,—the
- step which Utilitarianism and Evolutionism had (however awkwardly) got
- their foot upon, and which “transcendent” ethics seems unduly afraid of
- committing itself to. Let us say, if we like, that the mind is more than
- mere nature, and that it is no proper object of a merely natural science.
- But let us remember that a merely natural science is only a fragment of
- science: let us add that the _merely_ natural is an abstraction which in
- part denaturalises and mutilates the larger nature—a nature which includes
- the natural mind, and cannot altogether exclude the ethical.
- What have been called “formal duties(59)” seem to fall under this
- range—the province of a philosophical psychology which unveils the
- conditions of personality. Under that heading may be put self-control,
- consistency, resolution, energy, forethought, prudence, and the like. The
- due proportion of faculty, the correspondence of head and heart, the
- vivacity and quickness of sympathy, the ease and simplicity of mental
- tone, the due vigour of memory and the grace of imagination, sweetness of
- temper, and the like, are parts of the same group(60). They are lovely,
- and of good report: they are praise and virtue. If it be urged that they
- are only natural gifts and graces, that objection cuts two ways. The
- objector may of course be reminded that religion tones down the
- self-complacency of morality. Yet, first, even apart from that, it may be
- said that of virtues, which stand independent of natural conditions—of
- external supply of means (as Aristotle would say)—nothing can be known and
- nothing need be said. And secondly, none of these qualities are mere
- gifts;—all require exercise, habituation, energising, to get and keep
- them. How much and how little in each case is nature’s and how much ours
- is a problem which has some personal interest—due perhaps to a rather
- selfish and envious curiosity. But on the broad field of experience and
- history we may perhaps accept the—apparently one-sided—proverb that “Each
- man is the architect of his own fortune.” Be this as it may, it will not
- do to deny the ethical character of these “formal duties” on the ground
- e.g. that self-control, prudence, and even sweetness of temper may be used
- for evil ends,—that one may smile and smile, and yet be a villain.
- That—let us reply,—on one hand, is a fault (if fault it be) incidental to
- all virtues in detail (for every single quality has its defect): nay it
- may be a limitation attaching to the whole ethical sphere: and, secondly,
- its inevitable limitation does not render the virtue in any case one whit
- less genuine so far as it goes. And yet of such virtues it may be said, as
- Hume(61) would say (who calls them “natural,” as opposed to the more
- artificial merits of justice and its kin), that they please in themselves,
- or in the mere contemplation, and without any regard to their social
- effects. But they please as entering into our idea of complete human
- nature, of mind and spirit as will and intellect.
- The moralists of last century sometimes divided the field of ethics by
- assigning to man three grades or kinds of duty: duties to himself, duties
- to society, and duties to God. For the distinction there is a good deal to
- be said: there are also faults to be found with it. It may be said,
- amongst other things, that to speak of duties to self is a metaphorical
- way of talking, and that God lies out of the range of human duty
- altogether, except in so far as religious service forms a part of social
- obligation. It may be urged that man is essentially a social being, and
- that it is only in his relations to other such beings that his morality
- can find a sphere. The sphere of morality, according to Dr. Bain, embraces
- whatever “society has seen fit to enforce with all the rigour of positive
- inflictions. Positive good deeds and self-sacrifice ... transcend the
- region of morality proper and occupy a sphere of their own(62).” And there
- is little doubt that this restriction is in accordance with a main current
- of usage. It may even be said that there are tendencies towards a narrower
- usage still, which would restrict the term to questions affecting the
- relations of the sexes. But, without going so far, we may accept the
- standpoint which finds in the phrase “popular or social” sanction, as
- equivalent to the moral sanction, a description of the average level of
- common opinion on the topic. The morality of an age or country thus
- denotes, first, the average requirement in act and behaviour imposed by
- general consent on the members of a community, and secondly, the average
- performance of the members in response to these requirements. Generally
- speaking the two will be pretty much the same. If the society is in a
- state of equilibrium, there will be a palpable agreement between what all
- severally expect and what all severally perform. On the other hand, as no
- society is ever in complete equilibrium, this harmony will never be
- perfect and may often be widely departed from. In what is called a single
- community, if it reach a considerable bulk, there are (in other words)
- often a number of minor societies, more or less thwarting and modifying
- each other; and different observers, who belong in the main to one or
- other of these subordinate groups, may elicit from the facts before them a
- somewhat different social code, and a different grade of social
- observance. Still, with whatever diversity of detail, the important
- feature of such social ethics is that the stress is laid on the
- performance of certain acts, in accordance with the organisation of
- society. So long as the required compliance is given, public opinion is
- satisfied, and morality has got its due.
- But in two directions this conception of morality needs to be
- supplementing. There is, on one hand, what is called duty to God. The
- phrase is not altogether appropriate: for it follows too closely the
- analogy of social requirement, and treats Deity as an additional and
- social authority,—a lord paramount over merely human sovereigns. But
- though there may be some use in the analogy, to press the conception is
- seriously to narrow the divine character and the scope of religion. As in
- similar cases, we cannot change one term without altering its correlative.
- And therefore to describe our relation to God under the name of duty is to
- narrow and falsify that relation. The word is no longer applicable in this
- connexion without a strain, and where it exists it indicates the survival
- of a conception of theocracy: of God regarded as a glorification of the
- magistrate, as king of kings and lord of lords. It is the social world—and
- indeed we may say the outside of the social world—that is the sphere of
- duties. Duty is still with these reductions a great august name: but in
- literal strictness it only rules over the medial sphere of life, the
- sphere which lies between the individual as such and his universal
- humanity(63). Beyond duty, lies the sphere of conscience and of religion.
- And that is not the mere insistence by the individual to have a voice and
- a vote in determining the social order. It is the sense that the social
- order, however omnipotent it may seem, is limited and finite, and that man
- has in him a kindred with the Eternal.
- It is not very satisfactory, either, as Aristotle and others have pointed
- out, to speak of man’s duties to himself. The phrase is analogical, like
- the other. But it has the merit, like that of duty to God, of reminding us
- that the ordinary latitude occupied by morality is not all that comes
- under the larger scope of ethics. The “ethics of individual life” is a
- subject which Mr. Spencer has touched upon: and by this title, he means
- that, besides his general relationship to others, a human being has to
- mind his own health, food, and amusement, and has duties as husband and
- parent. But, after all, these are not matters of peculiarly individual
- interest. They rather refer to points which society at certain epochs
- leaves to the common sense of the agent,—apparently on an assumption that
- he is the person chiefly interested. And these points—as the Greeks taught
- long ago—are of fundamental importance: they are the very bases of life.
- Yet the comparative neglect in which so-called civilised societies(64)
- hold the precepts of wisdom in relation to bodily health and vigour, in
- regard to marriage and progeny, serve to illustrate the doctrine of the
- ancient Stoics that πάντα ὑπόληψις, or the modern idealist utterance that
- the World is my idea. More and more as civilisation succeeds in its
- disruption of man from nature, it shows him governed not by bare facts and
- isolated experiences, but by the systematic idea under which all things
- are subsumed. He loses the naïveté of the natural man, which takes each
- fact as it came, all alike good: he becomes sentimental, and artificial,
- sees things under a conventional point of view, and would rather die than
- not be in the fashion. And this tendency is apparently irresistible. Yet
- the mistake lies in the one-sidedness of sentiment and convention. Not the
- domination of the idea is evil; but the domination of a partial and
- fragmentary idea: and this is what constitutes the evil of artificiality.
- And the correction must lie not in a return to nature, but in the
- reconstruction of a wider and more comprehensive idea: an idea which shall
- be the unity and system of all nature; not a fantastic idealism, but an
- attempt to do justice to the more realist as well as the idealist sides of
- life.
- There is however another side of individualist ethics which needs even
- more especial enforcement. It is the formation of
- “The reason firm, the temperate will,
- Endurance, foresight, strength and skill:”
- the healthy mind in a healthy body. Ethics is only too apt to suppose that
- will and intelligence are assumptions which need no special justification.
- But the truth is that they vary from individual to individual in degree
- and structure. It is the business of ethical psychology to give to these
- vague attributions the definiteness of a normal standard: to show what
- proportions are required to justify the proper title of reason and will—to
- show what reason and will really are if they do what they are encouraged
- or expected to do. It talks of the diseases of will and personality: it
- must also set forth their educational ideal. The first problem of Ethics,
- it may be said, is the question of the will and its freedom. But to say
- this is of course not to say that, unless freedom of will be understood in
- some special sense, ethics becomes impossible. If the moral law is the
- _ratio cognoscendi_ of freedom, then must our conception of morality and
- of freedom hang together. And it will clearly be indispensable to begin by
- some attempt to discover in what sense man may be in the most general way
- described as a moral agent—as an intelligent will, or (more briefly, yet
- synonymously) as a will. “The soil of law and morality,” says Hegel(65),
- “is the intelligent life: and its more precise place and starting-point
- the will, which is free, in the sense that freedom is its substance and
- characteristic, and the system of law the realm of freedom realised, the
- world of intelligence produced out of itself as a second nature.” Such a
- freedom is a freedom made and acquired, the work of the mind’s
- self-realisation, not to be taken as a given fact of consciousness which
- must be believed(66). To have a will—in other words, to have freedom, is
- the consummation—and let us add, only the formal or ideal consummation—of
- a process by which man raises himself out of his absorption in sensation
- and impulse, establishes within himself a mental realm, an organism of
- ideas, a self-consciousness, and a self.
- The vulgar apprehension of these things seems to assume that we have by
- nature, or are born with, a general faculty or set of general faculties,
- which we subsequently fill up and embody by the aid of experience. We
- possess—they seem to imply—so many “forms” and “categories” latent in our
- minds ready to hold and contain the raw materials supplied from without.
- According to this view we have all a will and an intelligence: the
- difference only is that some put more into them, and some put less. But
- such a separation of the general form from its contents is a piece of pure
- mythology. It is perhaps true and safe to say that the human being is of
- such a character that will and intelligence are in the ordinary course
- inevitably produced. But the forms which grow up are the more and more
- definite and systematic organisation of a graded experience, of series of
- ideas, working themselves up again and again in representative and
- re-representative degree, till they constitute a mental or inner world of
- their own. The will is thus the title appropriate to the final stage of a
- process, by which sensation and impulse have polished and perfected
- themselves by union and opposition, by differentiation and accompanying
- redintegration, till they assume characters quite unsurmised in their
- earliest aspects, and yet only the consolidation or self-realisation of
- implications. Thus the mental faculties are essentially acquired
- powers,—acquired not from without, but by action which generates the
- faculties it seems to imply. The process of mind is a process which
- creates individual centres, raises them to completer independence;—which
- produces an inner life more and more self-centered and also more and more
- equal to the universe which it has embodied. And will and intelligence are
- an important stage in that process.
- Herbart (as was briefly hinted at in the first essay) has analysed ethical
- appreciation (which may or may not be accompanied by approbation) into
- five distinct standard ideas. These are the ideas of inward liberty, of
- perfection, of right, benevolence, and equity. Like Hume, he regards the
- moral judgment as in its purity a kind of aesthetic pronouncement on the
- agreement or proportion of certain activities in relations to each other.
- Two of these standard ideas,—that of inward liberty and of perfection—seem
- to belong to the sphere at present under review. They emerge as conditions
- determining the normal development of human nature to an intelligent and
- matured personality. By inward freedom Herbart means the harmony between
- the will and the intellect: what Aristotle has named “practical truth or
- reality,” and what he describes in his conception of wisdom or moral
- intelligence,—the power of discerning the right path and of pursuing it
- with will and temper: the unity, clear but indissoluble, of will and
- discernment. By the idea of perfection Herbart means the sense of
- proportion and of propriety which is awakened by comparing a progress in
- development or an increase in strength with its earlier stages of promise
- and imperfection. The pleasure such perception affords works in two ways:
- it is a satisfaction in achievement past, and a stimulus to achievement
- yet to come.
- Such ideas of inward liberty and of growth in ability or in performance
- govern (at least in part) our judgment of the individual, and have an
- ethical significance. Indeed, if the cardinal feature of the ethical
- sentiment be the inwardness and independence of its approbation and
- obligation, these ideas lie at the root of all true morality. Inward
- harmony and inward progress, lucidity of conscience and the resolution
- which knows no finality of effort, are the very essence of moral life.
- Yet, if ethics is to include in the first instance social relationships
- and external utilities and sanctions, these conditions of true life must
- rather be described as pre-ethical. The truth seems to be that here we get
- to a range of ethics which is far wider than what is ordinarily called
- practice and conduct. At this stage logic, aesthetic, and ethic, are yet
- one: the true, the good, and the beautiful are still held in their
- fundamental unity. An ethics of wide principle precedes its narrower
- social application; and whereas in ordinary usage the social provinciality
- is allowed to prevail, here the higher ethics emerge clear and imperial
- above the limitations of local and temporal duty.
- And though it is easy to step into exaggeration, it is still well to
- emphasise this larger conception of ethics. The moral principle of the
- “maximising of life,” as it has been called(67), may be open to
- misconception (—so, unfortunately are all moral principles when stated in
- the effrontery of isolation): but it has its truth in the conviction that
- all moral evil is marked by a tendency to lower or lessen the total
- vitality. So too Friedrich Nietzsche’s maxim, _Sei vornehm_(68), ensue
- distinction, and above all things be not common or vulgar (_gemein_), will
- easily lend itself to distortion. But it is good advice for all that, even
- though it may be difficult to define in a general formula wherein
- distinction consists, to mark the boundary between self-respect and vanity
- or obstinacy, or to say wherein lies the beauty and dignity of human
- nature. Kant has laid it down as the principle of duty to ask ourselves if
- in our act we are prepared to universalise the maxim implied by our
- conduct. And that this—which essentially bids us look at an act in the
- whole of its relations and context—is a safeguard against some forms of
- moral evil, is certain. But there is an opposite—or rather an apparently
- opposite—principle which bids us be individual, be true to our own selves,
- and never allow ourselves to be dismayed from our own unique
- responsibility. Perhaps the two principles are not so far apart as they
- seem. In any case true individuality is the last word and the first word
- in ethics; though, it may be added, there is a good deal to be said
- between the two termini.
- (iv.) An Excursus on Greek Ethics.
- It is in these regions that Greek ethics loves to linger; on the duty of
- the individual to himself, to be perfectly lucid and true, and to rise to
- ever higher heights of achievement. _Ceteris paribus_, there is felt to be
- something meritorious in superiority, something good:—even were it that
- you are master, and another is slave. Thus naïvely speaks Aristotle(69).
- To a modern, set amid so many conflicting ideals, perhaps, the immense
- possibilities of yet further growth might suggest themselves with
- overpowering force. To him the idea of perfection takes the form of an
- idea of perfectibility: and sometimes it smites down his conceit in what
- he has actually done, and impresses a sense of humility in comparison with
- what yet remains unaccomplished. An ancient Greek apparently was little
- haunted by these vistas of possibilities of progress through worlds beyond
- worlds. A comparatively simple environment, a fixed and definite mental
- horizon, had its plain and definite standards, or at least seemed to have
- such. There were fewer cases of the man, unattached or faintly attached to
- any definite profession—moving about in worlds half realised—who has grown
- so common in a more developed civilisation. The ideals of the Greek were
- clearly descried: each man had his definite function or work to perform:
- and to do it better than the average, or than he himself habitually had
- done, that was perfection, excellence, virtue. For virtue to the Greek is
- essentially ability and respectability: promise of excellent performance:
- capacity to do better than others. Virtue is praiseworthy or meritorious
- character and quality: it is achievement at a higher rate, as set against
- one’s past and against others’ average.
- The Greek moralists sometimes distinguish and sometimes combine moral
- virtue and wisdom, ἀρετή and φρόνησις: capacity to perform, and wisdom to
- guide that capacity. To the ordinary Greek perhaps the emphasis fell on
- the former, on the attainment of all recognised good quality which became
- a man, all that was beautiful and honourable, all that was appropriate,
- glorious, and fame-giving; and that not for any special reference to its
- utilitarian qualities. Useful, of course, such qualities were: but that
- was not in question at the time. In the more liberal commonwealths of
- ancient Greece there was little or no anxious care to control the
- education of its citizens, so as to get direct service, overt contribution
- to the public good. A suspicious Spartan legislation might claim to do
- that. But in the free air of Athens all that was required was loyalty,
- good-will—εὔνοια—to the common weal; it might be even a sentiment of human
- kindliness, of fraternity of spirit and purpose. Everything beyond and
- upon that basis was left to free development. Let each carry out to the
- full the development of his powers in the line which national estimation
- points out. He is—nature and history alike emphasise that fact beyond the
- reach of doubt, for all except the outlaw and the casual stranger—a member
- of a community, and as such has a governing instinct and ideal which
- animates him. But he is also a self-centered individual, with special
- endowments of nature, in his own person and in the material objects which
- are his. A purely individualist or selfish use of them is not—to the
- normal Greek—even dreamed of. He is too deeply rooted in the substance of
- his community for that: or it is on the ground and in the atmosphere of an
- assured community that his individuality is to be made to flourish. Nature
- has secured that his individuality shall rest securely in the
- presupposition of his citizenship. It seems, therefore, as if he were left
- free and independent in his personal search for perfection, for
- distinction. His place is fixed for him: _Spartam nactus es; hanc orna_:
- his duty is his virtue. That duty, as Plato expresses it, is to do his own
- deeds—and not meddle with others. Nature and history have arranged that
- others, in other posts, shall do theirs: that all severally shall energise
- their function. The very word “duty” seems out of place; if, at least,
- duty suggests external obligation, an order imposed and a debt to be
- discharged. If there be a task-master and a creditor, it is the inflexible
- order of nature and history:—or, to be more accurate, of nature, the
- indwelling and permanent reality of things. But the obligation to follow
- nature is scarcely felt as a yoke of constraint. A man’s virtue is to
- perform his work and to perform it well: to do what he is specially
- capable of doing, and therefore specially charged to do.
- Nowhere has this character of Greek ethics received more classical
- expression than in the Republic of Plato. In the prelude to his
- subject—which is the nature of Right and Morality—Plato has touched
- briefly on certain popular and inadequate views. There is the view that
- Right has its province in performance of certain single and external
- acts—in business honesty and commercial straightforwardness. There is the
- view that it is rendering to each what is due to him; that it consists in
- the proper reciprocity of services, in the balance of social give and
- take. There is the critical or hyper-critical view which, from seeing so
- much that is called justice to be in harmony with the interest of the
- predominant social order, bluntly identifies mere force or strength as the
- ground of right. And there are views which regard it as due to social
- conventions and artifices, to the influence of education, to political
- arrangements and the operation of irrational prejudices. To all these
- views Plato objects: not because they are false—for they are all in part,
- often in large part, true—but because they are inadequate and do not go to
- the root of the matter. The foundations of right lie, he says, not in
- external act, but in the inner man: not in convention, but in nature: not
- in relation to others, but in the constitution of the soul itself. That
- ethical idea—the idea of right—which seems most obviously to have its
- centre outside the individual, to live and grow only in the relations
- between individuals, Plato selects in order to show the independent
- royalty of the single human soul. The world, as Hume afterwards, called
- justice artificial: Plato will prove it natural. In a way he joins company
- with those who bid us drive out the spectre of duty, of obligation coming
- upon the soul from social authority, from traditional idea, from religious
- sanctions. He preaches—or he is about to preach—the autonomy of the will.
- The four cardinal virtues of Plato’s list are the qualities which go to
- make a healthy, normal, natural human soul, fit for all activity, equipped
- with all arms for the battle of life. They tell us what such a soul is,
- not what it does. They are the qualities which unless a soul has, and has
- them each perfect, yet all co-operant, its mere outward and single acts
- have no virtue or merit, but are only lucky accidents at the best. On the
- other hand, if a man has these constitutive qualities, he will act in the
- social world, and act well. Plato has said scornful things of mere outward
- and verbal truthfulness, and has set at the very lowest pitch of
- degradation the “lie in the soul.” His “temperance” or “self-restraint,”
- if it be far from breathing any suggestion of self-suppression or
- self-assertion, is still farther from any suspicion of asceticism, or war
- against the flesh. It is the noble harmony of the ruling and the ruled,
- which makes the latter a partner of the sovereign, and takes from the
- dictates of the ruler any touch of coercion. It is literally sanity of
- soul, integrity and purity of spirit; it is what has been sometimes called
- the beautiful soul—the indiscerptible unity of reason and impulse. Plato’s
- bravery, again, is fortitude and consistency of soul, the full-blooded
- heart which is fixed in reason, the zeal which is according to knowledge,
- unflinching loyalty to the idea, the spirit which burns in the martyrs to
- truth and humanity: yet withal with gentleness and courtesy and noble
- urbanity in its immediate train. And his truthfulness is that inner
- lucidity which cannot be self-deceived, the spirit which is a safeguard
- against fanaticism and hypocrisy, the sunlike warmth of intelligence
- without which the heart is a darkness full of unclean things.
- The full development and crowning grace of such a manly nature Aristotle
- has tried to present in the character of the Great-souled man—him whom
- Plato has called the true king by divine right, or the autocrat by the
- patent of nature. Like all such attempts to delineate a type in the terms
- necessarily single and successive of abstract analysis, it tends
- occasionally to run into caricature, and to give partial aspects an absurd
- prominency. Only the greatest of artists could cope with such a task,
- though that artist may be found perhaps classed among the historians. Yet
- it is possible to form some conception of the ideal which Aristotle would
- set before us. The Great-souled man _is_ great, and he dare not deny the
- witness of his spirit. He is one who does not quail before the anger and
- seek the applause of popular opinion: he holds his head as his own, and as
- high as his undimmed self-consciousness shows it is worth. There has been
- said to him by the reason within him the word that Virgil erewhile
- addressed to Dante:
- “Libero, dritto, e sano è il tuo arbitrio
- E fallo fora non fare a suo cenno;
- Per ch’ io te sopra te corono e mitrio.”
- He is his own Emperor and his own Pope. He is the perfected man, in whom
- is no darkness, whose soul is utter clearness, and complete harmony. Calm
- in self-possessed majesty, he stands, if need be, _contra mundum_: but
- rather, with the world beneath his feet. The chatter of personality has no
- interest for him. Bent upon the best, lesser competitions for distinction
- have no attraction for him. To the vulgar he will seem cold,
- self-confined: in his apartness and distinction they will see the signs of
- a “prig.” His look will be that of one who pities men—rather than loves
- them: and should he speak ill of a foe, it is rather out of pride of heart
- and unbroken spirit than because these things touch him. Such an one, in
- many ways, was the Florentine poet himself.
- If the Greek world in general thus conceived ἀρετή as the full bloom of
- manly excellence (we all know how slightly—witness the remarks in the
- Periclean oration—Greeks, in their public and official utterances, rated
- womanliness), the philosophers had a further point to emphasise. That was
- what they variously called knowledge, prudence, reason, insight,
- intelligence, wisdom, truth. From Socrates to Aristotle, from Aristotle to
- the Stoics and Epicureans, and from the Stoics to the Neo-Platonists, this
- is the common theme: the supremacy of knowledge, its central and essential
- relation to virtue. They may differ—perhaps not so widely as current
- prejudice would suppose—as to how this knowledge is to be defined, what
- kind of knowledge it is, how acquired and maintained, and so on. But in
- essentials they are at one. None of them, of course, mean that in order to
- right conduct nothing more is needed than to learn and remember what is
- right, the precepts and commandments of ordinary morality. Memory is not
- knowledge, especially when it is out of mind. Even an ancient philosopher
- was not wholly devoid of common sense. They held—what they supposed was a
- fact of observation and reflection—that all action was prompted by
- feelings of the values of things, by a desire of something good or
- pleasing to self, and aimed at self-satisfaction and self-realisation, but
- that there was great mistake in what thus afforded satisfaction. People
- chose to act wrongly or erroneously, because they were, first, mistaken
- about themselves and what they wanted, and, secondly, mistaken in the
- means which would give them satisfaction. But this second point was
- secondary. The main thing was to know yourself, what you really were; in
- Plato’s words, to “see the soul as it is, and know whether it have one
- form only or many, or what its nature is; to look upon it with the eye of
- reason in its original purity.” Self-deception, confusion, that worst
- ignorance which is unaware of itself, false estimation—these are the
- radical evils of the natural man. To these critics the testimony of
- consciousness was worthless, unless corroborated. To cure this mental
- confusion, this blindness of will and judgment, is the task set for
- philosophy: to give inward light, to teach true self-measurement. In one
- passage, much misunderstood, Plato has called this philosophic art the due
- measurement of pleasures and pains. It should scarcely have been possible
- to mistake the meaning. But, with the catchwords of Utilitarianism ringing
- in their ears, the commentators ran straight contrary to the true teaching
- of the _Protagoras_, consentient as it is with that of the _Phaedo_ and
- the _Philebus_. To measure, one must have a standard: and if Plato has one
- lesson always for us, it is that a sure standard the multitude have not,
- but only confusion. The so-called pleasures and pains of the world’s
- experiences are so entitled for different reasons, for contrary aims, and
- with no unity or harmony of judgment. They are—not a fact to be accepted,
- but—a problem for investigation: their reality is in question, their
- genuineness, solidity and purity: and till you have settled that, you
- cannot measure, for you may be measuring vacuity under the idea that there
- is substance. You have still to get at the unit—i.e. the reality of
- pleasure. It was not Plato’s view that pleasure was a separate and
- independent entity: that it was exactly as it was felt. Each pleasure is
- dependent for its pleasurable quality on the consciousness it belongs to,
- and has only a relative truth and reality. Bentham has written about
- computing the value of a “lot” of pleasures and pains. But Plato had his
- mind on an earlier and more fundamental problem, what is the truth and
- reality of pleasure; and his fullest but not his only essay towards
- determining the value or estimating the meaning of pleasure in the scale
- of being is that given in the _Philebus_.
- This then is the knowledge which Greek philosophy meant: not mere
- intellect—though, of course, there is always a danger of theoretical
- inquiry degenerating into abstract and formal dogma. But of the meaning
- there can be no serious doubt. It is a knowledge, says Plato, to which the
- method of mathematical science—the most perfect he can find
- acknowledged—is only an _ouverture_, or perhaps, only the preliminary
- tuning of the strings. It is a knowledge not eternally hypothetical—a
- system of sequences which have no sure foundation. It is a knowledge which
- rests upon the conviction and belief of the “idea of good”: a kind of
- knowledge which does not come by direct teaching, which is not mere
- theory, but implies a lively conviction, a personal apprehension, a crisis
- which is a kind of “conversion,” or “inspiration.” It is as it were the
- prize of a great contest, in which the sword that conquers is the sword of
- dialectic: a sword whereof the property is, like that of Ithuriel’s spear,
- to lay bare all deceptions and illusions of life. Or, to vary the
- metaphor: the son of man is like the prince in the fairy tale who goes
- forth to win the true queen; but there are many false pretenders decked
- out to deceive his unwary eyes and foolish heart. Yet in himself there is
- a power of discernment: there is something kindred with the truth:—the
- witness of the Spirit—and all that education and discipline can do is to
- remove obstacles, especially the obstacles within the self which perturb
- the sight and mislead the judgment. Were not the soul originally possessed
- of and dominated by the idea of good, it could never discern it elsewhere.
- On this original kindred depends all the process of education; the
- influence of which therefore is primarily negative or auxiliary. Thus the
- process of history and experience,—which the work of education only
- reproduces in an accelerated _tempo_—serves but to bring out the implicit
- reason within into explicit conformity with the rationality of the world.
- Knowledge, then, in this ethical sphere means the harmony of will,
- emotion, intellect: it means the clear light which has no illusions and no
- deceptions. And to those who feel that much of their life and of the
- common life is founded on prejudice and illusion, such white light will
- occasionally seem hard and steely. At its approach they fear the loss of
- the charm of that twilight hour ere the day has yet begun, or before the
- darkness has fully settled down. Thus the heart and feelings look upon the
- intellect as an enemy of sentiment. And Plato himself is not without
- anticipations of such an issue. Yet perhaps we may add that the danger is
- in part an imaginary one, and only arises because intelligence takes its
- task too lightly, and encroaches beyond its proper ground. Philosophy, in
- other words, mistakes its place when it sets itself up as a dogmatic
- system of life. Its function is to comprehend, and from comprehension to
- criticise, and through criticising to unify. It has no positive and
- additional teaching of its own: no addition to the burden of life and
- experience. And experience it must respect. Its work is to maintain the
- organic or super-organic interconnexion between all the spheres of life
- and all the forms of reality. It has to prevent stagnation and absorption
- of departments—to keep each in its proper place, but not more than its
- place, and yet to show how each is not independent of the others. And this
- is what the philosopher or ancient sage would be. If he is passionless, it
- is not that he has no passions, but that they no longer perturb and
- mislead. If his controlling spirit be reason, it is not the reason of the
- so-called “rationalist,” but the reason which seeks in patience to
- comprehend, and to be at home in, a world it at first finds strange. And
- if he is critical of others, he is still more critical of himself:
- critical however not for criticism’s sake (which is but a poor thing), but
- because through criticism the faith of reason may be more fully justified.
- To the last, if he is true to his mission and faithful to his loyalty to
- reality, he will have the simplicity of the child.
- Whether therefore we agree or not with Plato’s reduction of Right and Duty
- to self-actualisation, we may at least admit that in the idea of
- perfection or excellence, combined with the idea of knowledge or inward
- lucidity, he has got the fundamental ideas on which further ethical
- development must build. Self-control, self-knowledge, internal harmony,
- are good: and so are the development of our several faculties and of the
- totality of them to the fullest pitch of excellence. But their value does
- not lie entirely in themselves, or rather there is implicit in them a
- reference to something beyond themselves. They take for granted something
- which, because it is so taken, may also be ignored and neglected, just
- because it seems so obvious. And that implication is the social humanity
- in which they are the spirits of light and leading.
- To lay the stress on ἀρετή or excellence tends to leave out of sight the
- force of duty; and to emphasise knowledge is allowed to disparage the
- heart and feelings. The mind—even of a philosopher—finds a difficulty in
- holding very different points of view in one, and where it is forced from
- one to another, tends to forget the earlier altogether. Thus when the
- ethical philosopher, presupposing as an absolute or unquestionable fact
- that man the individual was rooted in the community, proceeded to discuss
- the problem of the best and completest individual estate, he was easily
- led to lose sight of the fundamental and governing condition altogether.
- From the moment that Aristotle lays down the thesis that man is naturally
- social, to the moment when he asks how the bare ideal of excellence in
- character and life can become an actuality, the community in which man
- lives has retired out of sight away into the background. And it only comes
- in, as it first appears, as the paedagogue to bring us to morality. And
- Plato, though professedly he is speaking of the community, and is well
- aware that the individual can only be saved by the salvation of the
- community, is constantly falling back into another problem—the development
- of an individual soul. He feels the strength of the egoistic effort after
- perfection, and his essay in the end tends to lose sight altogether of its
- second theme. Instead of a man he gives us a mere philosopher, a man, that
- is, not living with his country’s life, instinct with the heart and
- feeling of humanity, inspired by art and religion, but a being set apart
- and exalted above his fellows,—charged no doubt in theory with the duty of
- saving them, of acting vicariously as the mediator between them and the
- absolute truth—but really tending more and more to seclude himself on the
- _edita templa_ of the world, on the high-towers of speculation.
- And what Plato and Aristotle did, so to speak, against their express
- purpose and effort, yet did, because the force of contemporary tendency
- was irresistible—that the Stoa and Epicurus did more openly and
- professedly. With a difference in theory, it is true, owing to the
- difference in the surroundings. Virtue in the older day of the free and
- glorious commonwealth had meant physical and intellectual achievement,
- acts done in the public eye, and of course for the public good—a good with
- which the agent was identified at least in heart and soul, if not in his
- explicit consciousness. In later and worse days, when the political world,
- with the world divine, had withdrawn from actual identity with the central
- heart of the individual, and stood over-against him as a strange power and
- little better than a nuisance, virtue came to be counted as endurance,
- indifference, negative independence against a cold and a perplexing world.
- But even still, virtue is excellence: it is to rise above the ignoble
- level: to assert self-liberty against accident and circumstance—to attain
- self-controlled, self-satisfying independence—and to become God-like in
- its seclusion. Yet in two directions even it had to acknowledge something
- beyond the individual. The Epicurean—following out a suggestion of
- Aristotle—recognised the help which the free society of friends gave to
- the full development of the single seeker after a self-satisfying and
- complete life. The Stoic, not altogether refusing such help, tended rather
- to rest his single self on a fellowship of ideal sort, on the great city
- of gods and men, the _civitas Dei_. Thus, in separate halves, the two
- schools, into which Greek ethics was divided, gave expression to the sense
- that a new and higher community was needed—to the sense that the visible
- actual community no longer realised its latent idea. The Stoic emphasised
- the all-embracing necessity, the absolute comprehensiveness of the moral
- kingdom. The Epicurean saw more clearly that, if the everlasting city came
- from heaven, it could only visibly arise by initiation upon the earth.
- Christianity—in its best work—was a conjunction of the liberty with the
- necessity, of the human with the divine.
- More interesting, perhaps, it is to note the misconception of reason and
- knowledge which grew up. Knowledge came more and more to be identified
- with the reflective and critical consciousness, which is outside reality
- and life, and judges it from a standpoint of its own. It came to be
- esteemed only in its formal and abstract shape, and at the expense of the
- heart and feelings. The antithesis of philosophy (or knowledge strictly so
- called) according to Plato was mere opinion, accidental and imperfect
- knowledge. The knowledge which is truly valuable is a knowledge which
- presupposes the full reality of life, and is the more and more completely
- articulated theory of it as a whole. It is—abstractly taken—a mere form of
- unity which has no value except in uniting: it is—taken concretely—the
- matter, we may say, in complete unity. It is ideal and perfect harmony of
- thought, appetite, and emotion: or putting it otherwise, the philosopher
- is one who is not merely a creature of appetite and production, not merely
- a creature of feeling and practical energy, but a creature, who to both of
- these superadds an intelligence which sets eyes in the blind forehead of
- these other powers, and thus, far from superseding them altogether, only
- raises them into completeness, and realises all that is worthy in their
- implicit natures. Always these two impulsive tendencies of our nature are
- guided by some sort of ideas and intelligence, by beliefs and opinions.
- But they, like their guides, are sporadically emergent, unconnected, and
- therefore apt to be contradictory. It is to such erratic and occasional
- ideas, half-truths and deceptions, that philosophy is opposed.
- Unfortunately for all parties, the antithesis is carried farther.
- Philosophy and the philosopher are further set in opposition to the faith
- of the heart, the intimacy and intensity of feeling, the depth of love and
- trust, which in practice often go along with imperfect ideas. The
- philosopher is made one who has emancipated himself from the heart and
- feelings,—a pure intelligence, who is set above all creeds, contemplating
- all, and holding none. Consistency and clearness become his idol, to be
- worshipped at any cost, save one sacrifice: and that one sacrifice is the
- sacrifice of his own self-conceit. For consistency generally means that
- all is made to harmonise with one assumed standpoint, and that whatever
- presents discrepancies with this alleged standard is ruthlessly thrown
- away. Such a philosophy mistakes its function, which is not, as Heine
- scoffs, to make an intelligible system by rejecting the discordant
- fragments of life, but to follow reverently, if slowly, in the wake of
- experience. Such a “perfect sage,” with his parade of reasonableness, may
- often assume the post of a dictator.
- And, above all, intelligence is only half itself when it is not also will.
- And both are more than mere consciousness. Plato—whom we refer to, because
- he is the coryphaeus of all the diverse host of Greek philosophy—seems to
- overestimate or rather to misconceive the place of knowledge. That it is
- the supreme and crowning grace of the soul, he sees. But he tends to
- identify it with the supreme or higher soul:—as Aristotle did after him,
- to be followed by the Stoics and Neo-Platonists. For them the supreme, or
- almost supreme reality is the intelligence or reason: the soul is only on
- a second grade of reality, on the borders of the natural or physical
- world. When Plato takes that line, he turns towards the path of
- asceticism, and treats the philosophic life as a preparation for that
- truer life when intelligence shall be all in all, for that better land
- where “divine dialogues” shall form the staple and substance of spiritual
- existence. Aristotle,—who less often treads these solitudes,—still extols
- the theoretic life, when the body and its needs trouble no more, when the
- activity of reason—the theory of theory—is attained at least as entirely
- as mortal conditions allow man to be deified. Of the “apathy” and the
- reasonable conformity of the Stoics, or of the purely negative character
- of Epicurean happiness (the excision of all that pained) we need not here
- speak. And in Plotinus and Proclus the deification of mere reason is at
- any rate the dominant note; whatever protests the larger Greek nature in
- the former may from time to time offer. The truth which philosophy should
- have taught was that Mind or intelligence was the element where the inner
- life culminated and expanded and flourished: the error which it often
- tended to spread was that intelligence was the higher life of which all
- other was a degenerate shortcoming, and something valuable on its own
- account.
- It may be that thus to interpret Plato is to do him an injustice. It has
- been sometimes said that his division of parts or kinds of soul—or his
- distinction between its fighting horses—tends to destroy the unity of
- mental life. But perhaps this was exactly what he wanted to convey. There
- are—we may paraphrase his meaning—three kinds of human being, three types
- of human life. There is the man or the life of appetite and the flesh:
- there is the man of noble emotion and energetic depth of soul: there is
- the life of reasonable pursuits and organised principle. Or, we may take
- his meaning to be that there are three elements or provinces of mental
- life, which in all except a few are but imperfectly coherent and do not
- reach a true or complete unity. Some unity there always is: but in the
- life of mere appetite and impulse, even when these impulses are our nobler
- sentiments of love and hatred, the unity falls very far short. Or, as he
- puts the theme elsewhere, the soul has a passion for self-completion, a
- love of beauty, which in most is but a misleading lust. It is the business
- of the philosophic life to re-create or to foster this unity: or
- philosophy is the persistent search of the soul for its lost unity, the
- search to see that unity which is always its animating principle, its
- inner faith. When the soul has reached this ideal—if it can be supposed to
- attain it (and of this the strong-souled ancient philosophers feel no
- doubt),—then a change must take place. The love of beauty is not
- suppressed; it is only made self-assured and its object freed from all
- imperfection. It is not that passion has ceased; but its nature is so
- transfigured, that it seems worthy of a nobler name, which yet we cannot
- give. To such a life, where battle and conflict are as such unknown, we
- cannot longer give the title of life: and we say that philosophy is in
- life a rehearsal of death(70). And yet if there be no battle, there is not
- for that reason mere inaction. Hence, as the Republic concludes, the true
- philosopher is the complete man. He is the truth and reality which the
- appetitive and emotional man were seeking after and failed to realise. It
- is true they at first will not see this. But the whole long process of
- philosophy is the means to induce this conviction. And for Plato it
- remains clear that through experience, through wisdom, and through
- abstract deduction, the philosopher will justify his claim to him who hath
- ears to hear and heart to understand. If that be so, the asceticism of
- Plato is not a mere war upon flesh and sense as such, but upon flesh and
- sense as imperfect truth, fragmentary reality, which suppose themselves
- complete, though they are again and again confuted by experience, by
- wisdom, and by mere calculation,—a war against their blindness and
- shortsightedness.
- Essay IV. Psycho-Genesis.
- “The key,” says Carus, “for the ascertainment of the nature of the
- conscious psychical life lies in the region of the unconscious(71).” The
- view which these words take is at least as old as the days of Leibniz. It
- means that the mental world does not abruptly emerge a full-grown
- intelligence, but has a genesis, and follows a law of development: that
- its life may be described as the differentiation (with integration) of a
- simple or indifferentiated mass. The terms conscious and unconscious,
- indeed, with their lax popular uses, leave the door wide open for
- misconception. But they may serve to mark that the mind is to be
- understood only in a certain relation (partly of antithesis) to nature,
- and the soul only in reference to the body. The so-called “superior
- faculties”—specially characteristic of humanity—are founded upon, and do
- not abruptly supersede, the lower powers which are supposed to be
- specially obvious in the animals(72). The individual and specific
- phenomena of consciousness, which the psychologist is generally supposed
- to study, rest upon a deeper, less explicated, more indefinite, life of
- sensibility, which in its turn fades away by immeasurable gradations into
- something irresponsive to the ordinary tests for sensation and life.
- And yet the moment we attempt to leave the daylight of consciousness for
- the darker sides of sub-conscious life, the risks of misinterpretation
- multiply. The problem is to some extent the same as confronts the student
- of the ideas and principles of primitive races. There, the temptation of
- seeing things through the “spectacles of civilisation” is almost
- irresistible. So in psychology we are apt to import into the life of
- sensation and feeling the distinctions and relations of subsequent
- intellection. Nor is the difficulty lessened by Hegel’s method which deals
- with soul, sentiency, and consciousness as grades or general
- characteristics in a developmental advance. He borrows his illustrations
- from many quarters, from morbid and anomalous states of
- consciousness,—less from the cases of savages, children and animals. These
- illustrations may be called a loose induction. But it requires a much more
- powerful instrument than mere induction to build up a scientific system; a
- framework of general principle or theory is the only basis on which to
- build theory by the allegation of facts, however numerous. Yet in
- philosophic science, which is systematised knowledge, all facts strictly
- so described will find their place and be estimated at their proper value.
- (i.) Primitive Sensibility.
- Psychology (with Hegel) takes up the work of science from biology. The
- mind comes before it as the supreme product of the natural world, the
- finest flower of organic life, the “truth” of the physical process. As
- such it is called by the time-honoured name of Soul. If we further go on
- to say that the soul is the principle of life, we must not understand this
- vital principle to be something over and above the life of which it is the
- principle. Such a locally-separable principle is an addition which is due
- to the analogy of mechanical movement, where a detached agent sets in
- motion and directs the machinery. But in the organism the principle is not
- thus detachable as a thing or agent. By calling Soul the principle of life
- we rather mean that in the vital organism, so far as it _lives_, all the
- real variety, separation, and discontinuity of parts must be reduced to
- unity and identity, or as Hegel would say, to _ideality_. To live is thus
- to keep all differences fluid and permeable in the fire of the
- life-process. Or to use a familiar term of logic, the Soul is the concept
- or intelligible unity of the organic body. But to call it a concept might
- suggest that it is only the conception through which _we_ represent to
- ourselves the variety in unity of the organism. The soul, however, is more
- than a mere concept: and life is more than a mere mode of description for
- a group of movements forming an objective unity. It is a unity, subjective
- and objective. The organism is one life, controlling difference: and it is
- also one by our effort to comprehend it. The Soul therefore is in Hegelian
- language described as the Idea rather than the concept of the organic
- body. Life is the generic title for this subject-object: but the life may
- be merely physical, or it may be intellectual and practical, or it may be
- absolute, i.e. will and know all that it is, and be all that it knows and
- wills.
- Up to this point the world is what is called an external, which is here
- taken to mean (not a world external to the individual, but) a
- self-externalised world. That is to say, it is the observer who has
- hitherto by his interpretation of his perceptions supplied the “Spirit in
- Nature.” In itself the external world has no inside, no centre: it is we
- who read into it the conception of a life-history. We are led to believe
- that a principle of unity is always at work throughout the physical
- world—even in the mathematical laws of natural operation. It is only
- intelligible and credible to us as a system, a continuous and regular
- development. But that system is only a hypothetical idea, though it is
- held to be a conclusion to which all the evidence seems unequivocally to
- point. And, even in organic life, the unity, though more perfect and
- palpable than in the mechanical and inorganic world, is only a perception,
- a vision,—a necessary mode of realising the unity of the facts. The
- phenomenon of life reveals as in a picture and an ocular demonstration the
- conformity of inward and outward, the identity of whole and parts, of
- power and utterance. But it is still outside the observer. In the function
- of sensibility and sentiency, however, we stand as it were on the
- border-line between biology and psychology. At one step we have been
- brought within the harmony, and are no longer mere observers and
- reflecters. The sentient not merely is, but is aware that it is. Hitherto
- as life, it only is the unity in diversity, and diversity in unity, for
- the outsider, i.e. only implicitly: now it is so for itself, or
- consciously. And in the first stage it does not know, but feels or is
- sentient. Here, for the first time, is created the distinction of inward
- and outward. Loosely indeed we may, like Mr. Spencer, speak of outward and
- inward in physiology: but strictly speaking, what Goethe says is true,
- _Natur hat weder Kern noch Schaale_(73). Nature in the narrower sense
- knows no distinction of the inward and outward in its phenomena: it is a
- purely superficial order and succession of appearance and event. The Idea
- which has been visible to an intelligent percipient in the types and laws
- of the natural world, now _is_, actually is—is in and for itself—but at
- first in a minimum of content, a mere point of light, or rather the dawn
- which has yet to expand into the full day.
- Spinoza has asserted that “all individual bodies are animate, though in
- different degrees(74).” Now it is to a great extent this diversity of
- degree on which the main interest turns. Yet it is well to remember that
- the abrupt and trenchant separations which popular practice loves are
- overridden to a deeper view by an essential unity of idea, reducing them
- to indifference. If, that is, we take seriously the Spinozist unity of
- Substance, and the continual correlation (to call it no more) of extension
- and consciousness therein, we cannot avoid the conclusion which even Bacon
- would admit of something describable as attraction and perception,
- something subduing diversity to unity. But whether it be well to name this
- soul or life is a different matter. It may indeed only be taken to mean
- that all true being must be looked on as a real unity and individuality,
- must, that is, be conceived as manifesting itself in organisation, must be
- referred to a self-centred and self-developing activity. But this—which is
- the fundamental thesis of idealism—is hardly all that is meant. Rather
- Spinoza would imply that all things which form a real unity must have
- life—must have inner principle and unifying reality: and what he teaches
- is closely akin to the Leibnitian doctrine that every substantial
- existence reposes upon a monad, a unity which is at once both a force and
- a cognition, a “representation” and an appetite or _nisus_ to act. When
- Fechner in a series of works(75) expounds and defends the hypothesis that
- plants and planets are not destitute of soul, any more than man and
- animals, he only gives a more pronounced expression to this idealisation
- or spiritualisation of the natural world. But for the moment the point to
- be noted is that all of this idealistic doctrine is an inference, or a
- development which finds its _point d’appui_ in the fact of sensation. And
- the problem of the Philosophy of Mind is just to trace the process whereby
- a mere shock of sensation has grown into a conception and a faith in the
- goodness, beauty and intelligence of the world.
- Schopenhauer has put the point with his usual picturesqueness. Outward
- nature presents nothing but a play of forces. At first, however, this
- force shows merely the mechanical phenomena of pressure and impact, and
- its theory is sufficiently described by mathematical physics. But in the
- process of nature force assumes higher types, types where it loses a
- certain amount of its externality(76), till in the organic world it
- acquires a peculiar phase which Schopenhauer calls _Will_, meaning by
- that, however, an organising and controlling power, a tendency or _nisus_
- to be and live, which is persistent and potent, but without consciousness.
- This blind force, which however has a certain coherence and purposiveness,
- is in the animal organism endowed with a new character, in consequence of
- the emergence of a new organ. This organ, the brain and nervous system,
- causes the evolution into clear day of an element which has been growing
- more and more urgent. The gathering tendency of force to return into
- itself is now complete: the cycle of operation is formed: and the junction
- of the two currents issues in the spark of sensation. The blind force now
- becomes seeing.
- But at first—and this is the point we have to emphasise—its powers of
- vision are limited. Sensibility is either a local and restricted
- phenomenon: or, in so far as it is not local, it is vague and indefinite,
- and hardly entitled to the name of sensibility. Either it is a dim, but
- far-reaching, sympathy with environing existence, and in that case only
- so-called blind will or feeling: or if it is clear, is locally confined,
- and at first within very narrow limits. Neither of these points must be
- lost sight of. On the one hand feeling has to be regarded as the dull and
- confused stirring of an almost infinite sympathy with the world—a pulse
- which has come from the far-distant movements of the universe, and bears
- with it, if but as a possibility, the wealth of an infinite message. On
- the other hand, feeling at first only becomes real, in this boundless
- ideality to which its possibilities extend, by restricting itself to one
- little point and from several points organising itself to a unity of
- bodily feeling, till it can go on from thence to embrace the universe in
- distinct and articulate comprehension.
- Soul, says Hegel, is not a separate and additional something over and
- above the rest of nature: it is rather nature’s “’universal immaterialism,
- and simple ideal life(77).” There were ancient philosophers who spoke of
- the soul as a self-adjusting number,—as a harmony, or equilibrium(78)—and
- the moderns have added considerably to the list of these analogical
- definitions. As definitions they obviously fall short. Yet these things
- give, as it were, by anticipation, an image of soul, as the “ideality,”
- which reduces the manifold to unity. The adhesions and cohesions of
- matter, its gravitating attractions, its chemical affinities and
- electrical polarities, the intricate out-and-in of organic structure, are
- all preludes to the true incorporating unity which is the ever-immanent
- supersession of the endless self-externalism and successionalism of
- physical reality. But in sentiency, feeling, or sensibility, the unity
- which all of these imply without reaching, is explicitly present. It is
- implicitly an all-embracing unity: an infinite,—which has no doors and no
- windows, for the good reason that it needs none, because it has nothing
- outside it, because it “expresses” and “envelopes” (however confusedly at
- first) the whole universe. Thus, even if, with localising phraseology, we
- may describe mind, where it _appears_ emerging in the natural world, as a
- mere feeble and incidental outburst,—a rebellion breaking out as in some
- petty province or isolated region against the great law of the physical
- realm—we are in so speaking taking only an external standpoint. But with
- the rise of mind in nature the bond of externalism is implicitly overcome.
- To it, and where it really is, there is nothing outside, nothing
- transcendent. Everything which is said to be outside mind is only outside
- a localised and limited mind—outside a mind which is imperfectly and
- abstractly realised—not outside mind absolutely. Mind is the absolute
- negation of externality: not a mere relative negative, as the organism may
- be biologically described as inner in respect of the environment. To
- accomplish this negation in actuality, to bring the multiplicity and
- externality of things into the unity and identity of one Idea, is the
- process of development of mind from animal sensibility to philosophic
- knowledge, from appetite to art,—the process of culture through the social
- state under the influence of religion.
- Sentiency or psychic matter (mind-stuff), to begin with, is in some
- respects like the _tabula rasa_ of the empiricists. It is the
- possibility—but the real possibility—of intelligence rather than
- intelligence itself. It is the monotonous undifferentiated inwardness—a
- faint self-awareness and self-realisation of the material world, but at
- first a mere vague _psychical protoplasm_ and without defined nucleus,
- without perceptible organisation or separation of structures. If there is
- self-awareness, it is not yet discriminated into a distinct and unified
- self, not yet differentiated and integrated,—soul in the condition of a
- mere “Is,” which, however, is nothing determinate. It is very much in the
- situation of Condillac’s statue-man—_une statue organisée intérieurement
- comme nous, et animée d’un esprit privé de toute espèce d’idées_: alike at
- least so far that the rigid uniformity of the latter’s envelope prevents
- all articulated organisation of its faculties. The foundation under all
- the diversity and individuality in the concrete intelligent and volitional
- life is a common feeling,—a _sensus communis_—a general and indeterminate
- susceptibility to influence, a sympathy responsive, but responsive vaguely
- and equivocally, to all the stimuli of the physical environment. There was
- once a time, according to primitive legend, when man understood the
- language of beast and bird, and even surprised the secret converse of
- trees and flowers. Such fancies are but the exaggeration of a solidarity
- of conscious life which seems to spread far in the sub-conscious realm,
- and to narrow the individual’s soul into limited channels as it rises into
- clear self-perception,
- “As thro’ the frame that binds him in
- His isolation grows defined.”
- It may be a mere dream that, as Goethe feigns of Makaria in his
- romance(79), there are men and women in sympathy with the vicissitudes of
- the starry regions: and hypotheses of lunar influence, or dogmas of
- astrological destiny, may count to the present guardians of the sciences
- as visionary superstitions. Yet science in these regions has no reason to
- be dogmatic; her function hitherto can only be critical; and even for
- that, her data are scanty and her principles extremely general. The
- influences on the mental mood and faculty, produced by climate and
- seasons, by local environment and national type, by individual
- peculiarities, by the differences of age and sex, and by the alternation
- of night and day, of sleep and waking, are less questionable. It is easy
- no doubt to ignore or forget them: easy to remark how indefinable and
- incalculable they are. But that does not lessen their radical and
- inevitable impress in the determination of the whole character. “The sum
- of our existence, divided by reason, never comes out exact, but always
- leaves a marvellous remainder(80).” Irrational this residue is, in the
- sense that it is inexplicable, and incommensurable with the well-known
- quantities of conscious and voluntarily organised life. But a scientific
- psychology, which is adequate to the real and concrete mind, should never
- lose sight of the fact that every one of its propositions in regard to the
- more advanced phases of intellectual development is thoroughly and in
- indefinable ways modified by these preconditions. When that is remembered,
- it will be obvious how complicated is the problem of adapting psychology
- for the application to education, and how dependent the solution of that
- problem is upon an experiential familiarity with the data of individual
- and national temperament and character.
- The first stage in mental development is the establishment of regular and
- uniform relations between soul and body: it is the differentiation of
- organs and the integration of function: the balance between sensation and
- movement, between the afferent and efferent processes of sensitivity.
- Given a potential soul, the problem is to make it actual in an individual
- body. It is the business of a physical psychology to describe in detail
- the steps by which the body we are attached to is made inward as our idea
- through the several organs and their nervous appurtenances: whereas a
- psychical physiology would conversely explain the corresponding processes
- for the expression of the emotions and for the objectification of the
- volitions. Thus soul inwardises (_erinnert_) or envelops body: which body
- “expresses” or develops soul. The actual soul is the unity of both, is the
- percipient individual. The solidarity or “communion” of body and soul is
- here the dominant fact: the soul sentient of changes in its peripheral
- organs, and transmitting emotion and volition into physical effect. It is
- on this psychical unity,—the unity which is the soul of the diversity of
- body—that all the subsequent developments of mind rest. Sensation is thus
- the _prius_—or basis—of all mental life: the organisation of soul in body
- and of body in soul. It is the process which historically has been
- prepared in the evolution of animal life from those undifferentiated forms
- where specialised organs are yet unknown, and which each individual has
- further to realise and complete for himself, by learning to see and hear,
- and use his limbs. At first, moreover, it begins from many separate
- centres and only through much collision and mutual compliance arrives at
- comparative uniformity and centralisation. The common basis of united
- sensibility supplied by the one organism has to be made real and
- effective, and it is so at first by sporadic and comparatively independent
- developments. If self-hood means reference to self of what is prima facie
- not self, and projection of self therein, there is in primitive
- sensibility only the germ or possibility of self-hood. In the early phases
- of psychic development the centre is fluctuating and ill-defined, and it
- takes time and trouble to co-ordinate or unify the various starting-points
- of sensibility(81).
- This consolidation of inward life may be looked at either formally or
- concretely. Under the first head, it means the growth of a central unity
- of apperception. In the second case, it means a peculiar aggregate of
- ideas and sentiments. There is growing up within him what we may call the
- individuality of the individual,—an irrational, i.e. not consciously
- intelligent, nether-self or inner soul, a firm aggregation of hopes and
- wishes, of views and feelings, or rather of tendencies and temperament, of
- character hereditary and acquired. It is the law of the natural will or
- character which from an inaccessible background dominates our
- action,—which, because it is not realised and formulated in consciousness,
- behaves like a guardian spirit, or genius, or destiny within us. This
- genius is the sub-conscious unity of the sensitive life—the manner of man
- which unknown to ourselves we are,—and which influences us against our
- nominal or formal purposes. So far as this predominates, our ends, rough
- hew them how we will, are given by a force which is not really, i.e. with
- full consciousness, ours: by a mass of ingrained prejudice and unreasoned
- sympathies, of instincts and passions, of fancies and feelings, which have
- condensed and organised themselves into a natural power. As the child in
- the mother’s womb is responsive to her psychic influences, so the
- development of a man’s psychic life is guided by feelings centred in
- objects and agents external to him, who form the genius presiding over his
- development. His soul, to that extent, is really in another: he himself is
- selfless, and when his stay is removed the principle of his life is
- gone(82). He is but a bundle of impressions, held together by influences
- and ties which in years before consciousness proper began made him what he
- is. Such is the involuntary adaptation to example and environment, which
- establishes in the depths below personality a self which becomes hereafter
- the determinant of action. Early years, in which the human being is
- naturally susceptible, build up by imitation, by pliant obedience, an
- image, a system, reproducing the immediate surroundings. The soul, as yet
- selfless, and ready to accept any imprint, readily moulds itself into the
- likeness of an authoritative influence.
- The step by which the universality or unity of the self is realised in the
- variety of its sensation is Habit. Habit gives us a definite
- standing-ground in the flux of single impressions: it is the
- identification of ourselves with what is most customary and familiar: an
- identification which takes place by practice and repetition. If it
- circumscribes us to one little province of being, it on the other frees us
- from the vague indeterminateness where we are at the mercy of every
- passing mood. It makes thus much of our potential selves our very own, our
- acquisition and permanent possession. It, above all, makes us free and at
- one with our bodily part, so that henceforth we start as a subjective unit
- of body and soul. We have now as the result of the anthropological process
- a self or ego, an individual consciousness able to reflect and compare,
- setting itself on one side (a soul in bodily organisation), and on the
- other setting an object of consciousness, or external world, a world of
- other things. All this presupposes that the soul has actualised itself by
- appropriating and acquiring as its expression and organ the physical
- sensibility which is its body. By restricting and establishing itself, it
- has gained a fixed standpoint. No doubt it has localised and confined
- itself, but it is no longer at the disposal of externals and accident: it
- has laid the foundation for higher developments.
- (ii.) Anomalies of Psychical Life.
- Psychology, as we have seen, goes for information regarding the earlier
- stages of mental growth to the child and the animal,—perhaps also to the
- savage. So too sociology founds certain conclusions upon the observations
- of savage customs and institutions, or on the earlier records of the race.
- In both cases with a limitation caused by the externality and
- fragmentariness of the facts and the need of interpreting them through our
- own conscious experiences. There is however another direction in which
- corresponding inquiries may be pursued; and where the danger of the
- conclusions arrived at, though not perhaps less real, is certainly of a
- different kind. In sociology we can observe—and almost experiment upon—the
- phenomena of the lapsed, degenerate and criminal classes. The advantage of
- such observation is that the object of study can be made to throw greater
- light on his own inner states. He is a little of the child and a little of
- the savage, but these aspects co-exist with other features which put him
- more on a level with the intelligent observer. Similar pathological
- regions are open to us in the case of psychology. There the anomalous and
- morbid conditions of mind co-exist with a certain amount of mature
- consciousness. So presented, they are thrown out into relief. They form
- the negative instances which serve to corroborate our positive inductions.
- The regularly concatenated and solid structure of normal mind is under
- abnormal and deranged conditions thrown into disorder, and its
- constituents are presented in their several isolation. Such phenomena are
- relapses into more rudimentary grades: but with the difference that they
- are set in the midst of a more advanced phase of intellectual life.
- Even amongst candid and honest-minded students of psychology there is a
- certain reluctance to dabble in researches into the night-side of the
- mental range. Herbart is an instance of this shrinking. The region of the
- Unconscious seemed—and to many still seems—a region in which the charlatan
- and the dupe can and must play into each other’s hands. Once in the whirl
- of spiritualist and crypto-psychical inquiry you could not tell how far
- you might be carried. The facts moreover were of a peculiar type.
- Dependent as they seemed to be on the frame of mind of observers and
- observed, they defied the ordinary criteria of detached and abstract
- observation. You can only observe them, it is urged, when you believe;
- scepticism destroys them. Now there is a widespread natural impatience
- against what Bacon has called “monodical” phenomena, phenomena i.e. which
- claim to come under a special law of their own, or to have a private and
- privileged sphere. And this impatience cuts the Gordian knot by a
- determination to treat all instances which oppose its hitherto ascertained
- laws as due to deception and fraud, or, at the best, to incompetent
- observation, confusions of memory, and superstitions of ignorance. Above
- all, great interests of religion and personality seemed to connect
- themselves with these revelations—interests, at any rate, to which our
- common humanity thrills; it seemed as if, in this region beyond the
- customary range of the conscious and the seen, one might learn something
- of the deeper realities which lie in the unseen. But to feel that so much
- was at stake was naturally unfavourable to purely dispassionate
- observation.
- The philosophers were found—as might have been expected—amongst those most
- strongly attracted by these problems. Even Kant had been fascinated by the
- spiritualism of Swedenborg, though he finally turned away sceptical. At
- least as early as 1806 Schelling had been interested by Ritter’s
- researches into the question of telepathy, or the power of the human will
- to produce without mechanical means of conveyance an effect at a distance.
- He was looking forward to the rise of a _Physica coelestis_, or New
- Celestial Physics, which should justify the old magic. About the same date
- his brother Karl published an essay on Animal Magnetism. The novel
- phenomena of galvanism and its congeners suggested vast possibilities in
- the range of the physical powers, especially of the physical powers of the
- human psyche as a natural agent. The divining-rod was revived.
- Clairvoyance and somnambulism were carefully studied, and the curative
- powers of animal magnetism found many advocates(83).
- Interest in these questions went naturally with the new conception of the
- place of Man in Nature, and of Nature as the matrix of mind(84). But it
- had been acutely stimulated by the performances and professions of Mesmer
- at Vienna and Paris in the last quarter of the eighteenth century.
- These—though by no means really novel—had forced the artificial world of
- science and fashion to discuss the claim advanced for a new force which,
- amongst other things, could cure ailments that baffled the ordinary
- practitioner. This new force—mainly because of the recent interest in the
- remarkable advances of magnetic and electrical research—was conceived as a
- fluid, and called Animal Magnetism. At one time indeed Mesmer actually
- employed a magnet in the manipulation by which he induced the peculiar
- condition in his patients. The accompaniments of his procedure were in
- many respects those of the quack-doctor; and with the quack indeed he was
- often classed. A French commission of inquiry appointed to examine into
- his performances reported in 1784 that, while there was no doubt as to the
- reality of many of the phenomena, and even of the cures, there was no
- evidence for the alleged new physical force, and declared the effects to
- be mainly attributable to the influence of imagination. And with the
- mention of this familiar phrase, further explanation was supposed to be
- rendered superfluous.
- In France political excitement allowed the mesmeric theory and practice to
- drop out of notice till the fall of the first Empire. But in Germany there
- was a considerable amount of investigations and hypotheses into these
- mystical phenomena, though rarely by the ordinary routine workers in the
- scientific field. The phenomena where they were discussed were studied and
- interpreted in two directions. Some theorists, like Jung-Stilling,
- Eschenmayer, Schubert, and Kerner, took the more metaphysicist and
- spiritualistic view: they saw in them the witness to a higher truth, to
- the presence and operation in this lower world of a higher and spiritual
- matter, a so-called ether. Thus Animal Magnetism supplied a sort of
- physical theory of the other world and the other life. Jung-Stilling, e.g.
- in his “Theory of Spirit-lore.” (1808), regarded the spiritualistic
- phenomena as a justification of—what he believed to be—the Kantian
- doctrine that in the truly real and persistent world space and time are no
- more. The other direction of inquiry kept more to the physical field.
- Ritter (whose researches interested both Schelling and Hegel) supposed he
- had detected the new force underlying mesmerism and the like, and gave to
- it the name of Siderism (1808); while Amoretti of Milan named the object
- of his experiments Animal Electrometry (1816). Kieser(85), again (1826)
- spoke of Tellurism, and connected animal magnetism with the play of
- general terrestrial forces in the human being.
- At a later date (1857) Schindler, in his “Magical Spirit-life,” expounded
- a theory of mental polarity. The psychical life has two poles or
- centres,—its day-pole, around which revolves our ordinary and superficial
- current of ideas, and its night-pole, round which gathers the
- sub-conscious and deeper group of beliefs and sentiments. Either life has
- a memory, a consciousness, a world of its own: and they flourish to a
- large extent inversely to each other. The day-world has for its organs of
- receiving information the ordinary senses. But the magical or night-world
- of the soul has its feelers also, which set men directly in telepathic
- rapport with influences, however distant, exerted by the whole world: and
- through this “inner sense” which serves to concentrate in itself all the
- telluric forces (—a sense which in its various aspects we name instinct,
- presentiment, conscience) is constructed the fabric of our sub-conscious
- system. Through it man is a sort of résumé of all the cosmic life, in
- secret affinity and sympathy with all natural processes; and by the will
- which stands in response therewith he can exercise a directly creative
- action on external nature. In normal and healthy conditions the two
- currents of psychic life run on harmonious but independent. But in the
- phenomena of somnambulism, clairvoyance, and delirium, the magic region
- becomes preponderant, and comes into collision with the other. The
- dark-world emerges into the realm of day as a portentous power: and there
- is the feeling of a double personality, or of an indwelling genius,
- familiar spirit, or demon.
- To the ordinary physicist the so-called _Actio in distans_ was a hopeless
- stumbling-block. If he did not comprehend the transmission (as it is
- called) of force where there was immediate contact, he was at least
- perfectly familiar with the outer aspect of it as a condition of his
- limited experience. It needed one beyond the mere hodman of science to say
- with Laplace: “We are so far from knowing all the agents of nature, that
- it would be very unphilosophical to deny the existence of phenomena solely
- because they are inexplicable in the present state of our knowledge.”
- Accordingly mesmerism and its allied manifestations were generally
- abandoned to the bohemians of science, and to investigators with dogmatic
- bias. It was still employed as a treatment for certain ailments: and
- philosophers, as different as Fichte and Schopenhauer(86), watched its
- fate with attention. But the herd of professional scientists fought shy of
- it. The experiments of Braid at Manchester in 1841 gradually helped to
- give research into the subject a new character. Under the name of
- Hypnotism (or, rather at first Neuro-hypnotism) he described the phenomena
- of the magnetic sleep (induced through prolonged staring at a bright
- object), such as abnormal rigidity of body, perverted sensibility, and the
- remarkable obedience of the subject to the command or suggestions of the
- operator. Thirty years afterwards, the matter became an object of
- considerable experimental and theoretic work in France, at the rival
- schools of Paris and Nancy; and the question, mainly under the title of
- hypnotism, though the older name is still occasionally heard, has been for
- several years brought prominently under public notice.
- It cannot be said that the net results of these observations and
- hypotheses are of a very definitive character. While a large amount of
- controversy has been waged on the comparative importance of the several
- methods and instruments by which the hypnotic or mesmeric trance may be
- induced, and a scarcely less wide range of divergence prevails with regard
- to the physiological and pathological conditions in connexion with which
- it has been most conspicuously manifested, there has been less anxiety
- shown to determine its precise psychical nature, or its significance in
- mental development. And yet the better understanding of these aspects may
- throw light on several points connected with primitive religion and the
- history of early civilisation, indeed over the whole range of what is
- called _Völkerpsychologie_. Indeed this is one of the points which may be
- said to emerge out of the confusion of dispute. Phenomena at least
- analogous to those styled hypnotic have a wide range in the
- anthropological sphere(87): and the proper characters which belong to them
- will only be caught by an observer who examines them in the widest variety
- of examples. Another feature which has been put in prominence is what has
- been called “psychological automatism.” And in this name two points seem
- to deserve note. The first is the spontaneous and as it were mechanical
- consecution of mental states in the soul whence the interfering effect of
- voluntary consciousness has been removed. And the second is the unfailing
- or accurate regularity, so contrary to the hesitating and uncertain
- procedure of our conscious and reasoned action, which so often is seen in
- the unreflecting and unreasoned movements. To this invariable sequence of
- psychical movement the superior control and direction by the intelligent
- self has to adapt itself, just as it respects the order of physical laws.
- But, perhaps, the chief conclusion to be derived from hypnotic experience
- is the value of suggestion or suggestibility. Even cool thinkers like Kant
- have recognised how much mere mental control has to do with bodily
- state,—how each of us, in this way, is often for good or for ill his own
- physician. An idea is a force, and is only inactive in so far as it is
- held in check by other ideas. “There is no such thing as hypnotism,” says
- one: “there are only different degrees of suggestibility.” This may be to
- exaggerate: yet it serves to impress the comparatively secondary character
- of many of the circumstances on which the specially mesmeric or hypnotic
- experimentalist is apt to lay exclusive stress. The methods may probably
- vary according to circumstances. But the essence of them all is to get the
- patient out of the general frame and system of ideas and perceptions in
- which his ordinary individuality is encased. Considering how for all of us
- the reality of concrete life is bound up with our visual perceptions, how
- largely our sanity depends upon the spatial idea, and how that depends on
- free ocular range, we can understand that darkness and temporary loss of
- vision are powerful auxiliaries in the hypnotic process, as in magical and
- superstitious rites. But a great deal short of this may serve to establish
- influence. The mind of the majority of human beings, but especially of the
- young, may be compared to a vacant seat waiting for some one to fill it.
- In Hegel’s view hypnotic phenomena produce a kind of temporary and
- artificial atavism. Mechanical or chemical means, or morbid conditions of
- body, may cause even for the intelligent adult a relapse into states of
- mind closely resembling those exhibited by the primitive or the infantile
- sensibility. The intelligent personality, where powers are bound up with
- limitations and operate through a chain of means and ends, is reduced to
- its primitively undifferentiated condition. Not that it is restored to its
- infantile simplicity; but that all subsequent acquirements operate only as
- a concentrated individuality, or mass of will and character, released from
- the control of the self-possessed mind, and invested (by the latter’s
- withdrawal) with a new quasi-personality of their own. With the loss of
- the world of outward things, there may go, it is supposed, a clearer
- perception of the inward and particularly of the organic life. The Soul
- contains the form of unity which other experiences had impressed upon it:
- but this form avails in its subterranean existence where it creates a sort
- of inner self. And this inner self is no longer, like the embodied self of
- ordinary consciousness, an intelligence served by organs, and proceeding
- by induction and inference. Its knowledge is not mediated or carried along
- specific channels: it does not build up, piecemeal, by successive steps of
- synthesis and analysis, by gradual idealisation, the organised totality of
- its intellectual world. The somnambulist and the clairvoyant see without
- eyes, and carry their vision directly into regions where the waking
- consciousness of orderly intelligence cannot enter. But that region is not
- the world of our higher ideas,—of art, religion, and philosophy. It is
- still the sensitivity—that realm of sensitivity which is ordinarily
- covered by unconsciousness. Such sensitive clairvoyants may, as it were,
- hear themselves growing; they may discern the hidden quivers and pulses of
- blood and tissue, the seats of secret pain and all the unrevealed workings
- in the dark chambers of the flesh. But always their vision seems confined
- to that region, and will fall short of the world of light and ideal truth.
- It is towards the nature-bond of sensitive solidarity with earth, and
- flowers, and trees, the life that “rolls through all things,” not towards
- the spiritual unity which broods over the world and “impels all thinking
- things,” that these immersions in the selfless universe lead us.
- What Hegel chiefly sees in these phenomena is their indication, even on
- the natural side of man, of that ideality of the material, which it is the
- work of intelligence to produce in the more spiritual life, in the
- fully-developed mind. The latter is the supreme over-soul, that Absolute
- Mind which in our highest moods, aesthetic and religious, we approximate
- to. But mind, as it tends towards the higher end to “merge itself in
- light,” to identify itself yet not wholly lost, but retained, in the
- fullness of undivided intellectual being, so at the lower end it springs
- from a natural and underlying unity, the immense solidarity of
- nether-soul, the great Soul of Nature—the “Substance” which is to be
- raised into the “Subject” which is true divinity. Between these two
- unities, the nature-given nether-soul and the spirit-won over-soul, lies
- the conscious life of man: a process of differentiation which narrows and
- of redintegration which enlarges,—which alternately builds up an isolated
- personality and dissolves it in a common intelligence and sympathy. It is
- because mental or tacit “suggestion”(88) (i.e. will-influence exercised
- without word or sign, or other sensible mode of connexion),
- thought-transference, or thought-reading (which is more than dexterous
- apprehension of delicate muscular signs), exteriorisation or transposition
- of sensibility into objects primarily non-sensitive, clairvoyance (i.e.
- the power of describing, as if from direct perception, objects or events
- removed in space beyond the recognised limits of sensation), and
- somnambulism, so far as it implies lucid vision with sealed eyes,—it is
- because these things seem to show the essential ideality of matter, that
- Hegel is interested in them. The ordinary conditions of consciousness and
- even of practical life in society are a derivative and secondary state; a
- product of processes of individualism, which however are never completed,
- and leave a large margin for idealising intelligence to fulfil. From a
- state which is not yet personality to a state which is more than can be
- described as personality—lies the mental movement. So Fichte, too, had
- regarded the power of the somnambulist as laying open a world underlying
- the development of egoity and self-consciousness(89): “the merely sensuous
- man is still in somnambulism,” only a somnambulism of waking hours: “the
- true waking is the life in God, to be free in him, all else is sleep and
- dream.” “Egoity,” he adds, “is a merely _formal_ principle, utterly, and
- never qualitative (i.e. the essence and universal force).” For
- Schopenhauer, too, the experiences of animal magnetism had seemed to prove
- the absolute supernatural power of the radical will in its superiority to
- the intellectual categories of space, time, and causal sequence: to prove
- the reality of the metaphysical which is at the basis of all conscious
- divisions.
- (iii.) The Development of Inner Freedom.
- The result of the first range in the process of psycho-genesis was to make
- the body a sign and utterance of the Soul, with a fixed and determinate
- type. The “anthropological process” has defined and settled the mere
- general sentiency of soul into an individualised shape, a localised and
- limited self, a bundle of habits. It has made the soul an Ego or self: a
- power which looks out upon the world as a spectator, lifted above
- immanence in the general tide of being, but only so lifted because it has
- made itself one in the world of objects, a thing among things. The Mind
- has reached the point of view of reflection. Instead of a general
- identifiability with all nature, it has encased itself in a limited range,
- from which it looks forth on what is now other than itself. If previously
- it was mere inward sensibility, it is now sense, perceptive of an object
- here and now, of an external world. The step has involved some price: and
- that price is, that it has attained independence and self-hood at the cost
- of surrendering the content it had hitherto held in one with itself. It is
- now a blank receptivity, open to the impressions of an outside world: and
- the changes which take place in its process of apprehension seem to it to
- be given from outside. The world it perceives is a world of isolated and
- independent objects: and it takes them as they are given. But a closer
- insistance on the perception develops the implicit intelligence, which
- makes it possible. The percipient mind is no mere recipiency or
- susceptibility with its forms of time and space: it is spontaneously
- active, it is the source of categories, or is an apperceptive power,—an
- understanding. Consciousness, thus discovered to be a creative or
- constructive faculty, is strictly speaking self-consciousness(90).
- Self-consciousness appears at first in the selfish or narrowly egoistic
- form of appetite and impulse. The intelligence which claims to mould and
- construe the world of objects—which, in Kant’s phrase, professes to give
- us nature—is implicitly the lord of that world. And that supremacy it
- carries out as appetite—as destruction. The self is but a bundle of
- wants—its supremacy over things is really subjection to them: the
- satisfaction of appetite is baffled by a new desire which leaves it as it
- was before. The development of self-consciousness to a more adequate shape
- is represented by Hegel as taking place through the social struggle for
- existence. Human beings, too, are in the first instance to the
- uninstructed appetite or the primitive self-consciousness (which is simply
- a succession of individual desires for satisfaction of natural want) only
- things,—adjectival to that self’s individual existence. To them, too, his
- primary relation is to appropriate and master them. Might precedes right.
- But the social struggle for existence forces him to recognise something
- other which is kindred to himself,—a limiting principle, another self
- which has to form an element in his calculations, not to be neglected. And
- gradually, we may suppose, the result is the division of humanity into two
- levels, a ruling lordly class, and a class of slaves,—a state of
- inequality in which each knows that his appetite is in some measure
- checked by a more or less permanent other. Lastly, perhaps soonest in the
- inferior order, there is fashioned the perception that its self-seeking in
- its isolated appetites is subject to an abiding authority, a continuing
- consciousness. There grows up a social self—a sense of general humanity
- and solidarity with other beings—a larger self with which each identifies
- himself, a common ground. Understanding was selfish intelligence:
- practical in the egoistic sense. In the altruistic or universal sense
- practical, a principle social and unifying character, intelligence is
- Reason.
- Thus, Man, beginning as a percipient consciousness, apprehending single
- objects in space and time, and as an appetitive self bent upon single
- gratifications, has ended as a rational being,—a consciousness purged of
- its selfishness and isolation, looking forward openly and impartially on
- the universe of things and beings. He has ceased to be a mere animal,
- swallowed up in the moment and the individual, using his intelligence only
- in selfish satisfactions. He is no longer bound down by the struggle for
- existence, looking on everything as a mere thing, a mere means. He has
- erected himself above himself and above his environment, but that because
- he occupies a point of view at which he and his environment are no longer
- purely antithetical and exclusive(91). He has reached what is really the
- moral standpoint: the point i.e. at which he is inspired by a universal
- self-consciousness, and lives in that peaceful world where the antitheses
- of individualities and of outward and inward have ceased to trouble. “The
- natural man,” says Hegel(92), “sees in the woman flesh of his flesh: the
- moral and spiritual man sees spirit of his spirit in the moral and
- spiritual being and by its means.” Hitherto we have been dealing with
- something falling below the full truth of mind: the region of immediate
- sensibility with its thorough immersion of mind in body, first of all, and
- secondly its gradual progress to a general standpoint. It is only in the
- third part of Subjective mind that we are dealing with the psychology of a
- being who in the human sense knows and wills, i.e. apprehends general
- truth, and carries out ideal purposes.
- Thus, for the third time, but now on a higher plane, that of intelligence
- and rationality, is traced the process of development or realisation by
- which reason becomes reasoned knowledge and rational will, a free or
- autonomous intelligence. And, as before, the starting-point, alike in
- theoretical and practical mind, is feeling—or immediate knowledge and
- immediate sense of Ought. The basis of thought is an immediate
- perception—a sensuous affection or given something, and the basis of the
- idea of a general satisfaction is the natural claim to determine the
- outward existence conformably to individual feeling. In intelligent
- perception or intuition the important factor is attention, which raises it
- above mere passive acceptance and awareness of a given fact. Attention
- thus involves on one hand the externality of its object, and on the other
- affirms its dependence on the act of the subject: it sets the objects
- before and out of itself, in space and time, but yet in so doing it shows
- itself master of the objects. If perception presuppose attention, in
- short, they cease to be wholly outward: we make them ours, and the space
- and time they fill are projected by us. So attended to, they are
- appropriated, inwardised and recollected: they take their place in a
- mental place and mental time: they receive a general or de-individualised
- character in the memory-image. These are retained as mental property, but
- retained actually only in so far they are revivable and revived. Such
- revival is the work of imagination working by the so-called laws of
- association. But the possession of its ideas thus inwardised and
- recollected by the mind is largely a matter of chance. The mind is not
- really fully master of them until it has been able to give them a certain
- objectivity, by replacing the mental image by a vocal, i.e. a sensible
- sign. By means of words, intelligence turns its ideas or representations
- into quasi-realities: it creates a sort of superior sense-world, the world
- of language, where ideas live a potential, which is also an actual, life.
- Words are sensibles, but they are sensibles which completely lose
- themselves in their meaning. As sensibles, they render possible that
- verbal memory which is the handmaid of thought: but which also as merely
- mechanical can leave thought altogether out of account. It is through
- words that thought is made possible: for it alone permits the movement
- through ideas without being distracted through a multitude of
- associations. In them thought has an instrument completely at its own
- level, but still only a machine, and in memory the working of that
- machine. We think in names, not in general images, but in terms which only
- serve as vehicles for mental synthesis and analysis.
- It is as such a thinking being—a being who can use language, and
- manipulate general concepts or take comprehensive views, that man is a
- rational will. A concept of something to be done—a feeling even of some
- end more or less comprehensive in its quality, is the implication of what
- can be called will. At first indeed its material may be found as
- immediately given and all its volitionality may lie in the circumstance
- that the intelligent being sets this forward as a governing and
- controlling Ought. Its vehicle, in short, may be mere impulse, or
- inclination, and even passion: but it is the choice and the purposive
- adoption of means to the given end. Gradually it attains to the idea of a
- general satisfaction, or of happiness. And this end seems positive and
- definite. It soon turns out however to be little but a prudent and
- self-denying superiority to particular passions and inclinations in the
- interest of a comprehensive ideal. The free will or intelligence has so
- far only a negative and formal value: it is the perfection of an
- autonomous and freely self-developing mind. Such a mind, which in language
- has acquired the means of realising an intellectual system of things
- superior to the restrictions of sense, and which has emancipated reason
- from the position of slave to inclination, is endued with the formal
- conditions of moral conduct. Such a mind will transform its own primarily
- physical dependence into an image of the law of reason and create the
- ethical life: and in the strength of that establishment will go forth to
- conquer the world into a more and more adequate realisation of the eternal
- Idea.
- Essay V. Ethics And Politics.
- “In dealing,” says Hegel, “with the Idea of the State, we must not have
- before our eyes a particular state, or a particular institution: we must
- rather study the Idea, this actual God, on his own account. Every State,
- however bad we may find it according to our principles, however defective
- we may discover this or that feature to be, still contains, particularly
- if it belongs to the mature states of our time, all the essential factors
- of its existence. But as it is easier to discover faults than to
- comprehend the affirmative, people easily fall into the mistake of letting
- individual aspects obscure the intrinsic organism of the State itself. The
- State is no ideal work of art: it stands in the everyday world, in the
- sphere, that is, of arbitrary act, accident, and error, and a variety of
- faults may mar the regularity of its traits. But the ugliest man, the
- criminal, a sick man and a cripple, is after all a living man; the
- affirmative, Life, subsists in spite of the defect: and this affirmative
- is here the theme(93).” “It is the theme of philosophy,” he adds, “to
- ascertain the substance which is immanent in the show of the temporal and
- transient, and the eternal which is present.”
- (i.) Hegel as a Political Critic.
- But if this is true, it is also to be remembered that the philosopher is,
- like other men, the son of his age, and estimates the value of reality
- from preconceptions and aspirations due to his generation. The historical
- circumstances of his nation as well as the personal experiences of his
- life help to determine his horizon, even in the effort to discover the
- hidden pulse and movement of the social organism. This is specially
- obvious in political philosophy. The conception of ethics and politics
- which is presented in the _Encyclopaedia_ was in 1820 produced with more
- detail as the _Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts_. Appearing, as it
- did, two years after his appointment to a professorship at Berlin, and in
- the midst of a political struggle between the various revolutionary and
- conservative powers and parties of Germany, the book became, and long
- remained, a target for embittered criticism. The so-called War of
- Liberation or national movement to shake off the French yoke was due to a
- coalition of parties, and had naturally been in part supported by
- tendencies and aims which went far beyond the ostensive purpose either of
- leaders or of combatants. Aspirations after a freer state were entwined
- with radical and socialistic designs to reform the political hierarchy of
- the Fatherland: high ideals and low vulgarities were closely intermixed:
- and the noble enthusiasm of youth was occasionally played on by criminal
- and anarchic intriguers. In a strong and wise and united Germany some of
- these schemes might have been tolerated. But strength, wisdom, and unity
- were absent. In the existing tension between Austria and Prussia for the
- leadership, in the ill-adapted and effete constitutions of the several
- principalities which were yet expected to realise the advance which had
- taken place in society and ideas during the last thirty years, the outlook
- on every hand seemed darker and more threatening than it might have
- otherwise done. Governments, which had lost touch with their peoples,
- suspected conspiracy and treason: and a party in the nation credited their
- rulers with gratuitous designs against private liberty and rights. There
- was a vast but ill-defined enthusiasm in the breasts of the younger world,
- and it was shared by many of their teachers. It seemed to their immense
- aspirations that the war of liberation had failed of its true object and
- left things much as they were. The volunteers had not fought for the
- political systems of Austria or Prussia, or for the three-and-thirty
- princes of Germany: but for ideas, vague, beautiful, stimulating. To such
- a mood the continuance of the old system was felt as a cruel deception and
- a reaction. The governments on their part had not realised the full
- importance of the spirit that had been aroused, and could not at a
- moment’s notice set their house in order, even had there been a clearer
- outlook for reform than was offered. They too had suffered, and had
- realised their insecurity: and were hardly in a mood to open their gates
- to the enemy.
- Coming on such a situation of affairs, Hegel’s book would have been likely
- in any case to provoke criticism. For it took up a line of political
- theory which was little in accord with the temper of the age. The
- conception of the state which it expounded is not far removed in
- essentials from the conception which now dominates the political life of
- the chief European nations. But in his own time it came upon ears which
- were naturally disposed to misconceive it. It was unacceptable to the
- adherents of the _ancien régime_, as much as to the liberals. It was
- declared by one party to be a glorification of the Prussian state: by
- another to rationalise the sanctities of authority. It was pointed out
- that the new professor was a favourite of the leading minister, that his
- influence was dominant in scholastic appointments, and that occasional
- gratuities from the crown proved his acceptability. A contemporary
- professor, Fries, remarked that Hegel’s theory of the state had grown “not
- in the gardens of science but on the dung-hill of servility.” Hegel
- himself was aware that he had planted a blow in the face of a “shallow and
- pretentious sect,” and that his book had “given great offence to the
- demagogic folk.” Alike in religious and political life he was impatient of
- sentimentalism, of rhetorical feeling, of wordy enthusiasm. A positive
- storm of scorn burst from him at much-promising and little-containing
- declamation that appealed to the pathos of ideas, without sense of the
- complex work of construction and the system of principles which were
- needed to give them reality. His impatience of demagogic gush led him (in
- the preface) into a tactless attack on Fries, who was at the moment in
- disgrace for his participation in the demonstration at the Wartburg. It
- led him to an attack on the bumptiousness of those who held that
- conscientious conviction was ample justification for any proceeding:—an
- attack which opponents were not unwilling to represent as directed against
- the principle of conscience itself.
- Yet Hegel’s views on the nature of political unity were not new. Their
- nucleus had been formed nearly twenty years before. In the years that
- immediately followed the French revolution he had gone through the usual
- anarchic stage of intelligent youth. He had wondered whether humanity
- might not have had a nobler destiny, had fate given supremacy to some
- heresy rather than the orthodox creed of Christendom. He had seen religion
- in the past “teaching what despotism wished,—contempt of the human race,
- its incapacity for anything good(94).” But his earliest reflections on
- political power belong to a later date, and are inspired, not so much by
- the vague ideals of humanitarianism, as by the spirit of national
- patriotism. They are found in a “Criticism of the German Constitution”
- apparently dating from the year 1802(95). It is written after the peace of
- Lunéville had sealed for Germany the loss of her provinces west of the
- Rhine, and subsequent to the disasters of the German arms at Hohenlinden
- and Marengo. It is almost contemporaneous with the measures of 1803 and
- 1804, which affirmed the dissolution of the “Holy Roman Empire” of German
- name. The writer of this unpublished pamphlet sees his country in a
- situation almost identical with that which Macchiavelli saw around him in
- Italy. It is abused by petty despots, distracted by mean particularist
- ambitions, at the mercy of every foreign power. It was such a scene which,
- as Hegel recalls, had prompted and justified the drastic measures proposed
- in the _Prince_,—measures which have been ill-judged by the closet
- moralist, but evince the high statesmanship of the Florentine. In the
- _Prince_, an intelligent reader can see “the enthusiasm of patriotism
- underlying the cold and dispassionate doctrines.” Macchiavelli dared to
- declare that Italy must become a state, and to assert that “there is no
- higher duty for a state than to maintain itself, and to punish
- relentlessly every author of anarchy,—the supreme, and perhaps sole
- political crime.” And like teaching, Hegel adds, is needed for Germany.
- Only, he concludes, no mere demonstration of the insanity of utter
- separation of the particular from his kin will ever succeed in converting
- the particularists from their conviction of the absoluteness of personal
- and private rights. “Insight and intelligence always excite so much
- distrust that force alone avails to justify them; then man yields them
- obedience(96).”
- “The German political edifice,” says the writer, “is nothing else but the
- sum of the rights which the single parts have withdrawn from the whole;
- and this justice, which is ever on the watch to prevent the state having
- any power left, is the essence of the constitution.” The Peace of
- Westphalia had but served to constitute or stereotype anarchy: the German
- empire had by that instrument divested itself of all rights of political
- unity, and thrown itself on the goodwill of its members. What then, it may
- be asked, is, in Hegel’s view, the indispensable minimum essential to a
- state? And the answer will be, organised strength,—a central and united
- force. “The strength of a country lies neither in the multitude of its
- inhabitants and fighting men, nor in its fertility, nor in its size, but
- solely in the way its parts are by reasonable combination made a single
- political force enabling everything to be used for the common defence.”
- Hegel speaks scornfully of “the philanthropists and moralists who decry
- politics as an endeavour and an art to seek private utility at the cost of
- right”: he tells them that “it is foolish to oppose the interest or (as it
- is expressed by the more morally-obnoxious word) the utility of the state
- to its right”: that the “rights of a state are the utility of the state as
- established and recognised by compacts”: and that “war” (which they would
- fain abolish or moralise) “has to decide not which of the rights asserted
- by either party is the true right (—for both parties have a true right),
- but which right has to give way to the other.”
- It is evident from these propositions that Hegel takes that view of
- political supremacy which has been associated with the name of Hobbes. But
- his views also reproduce the Platonic king of men, “who can rule and dare
- not lie.” “All states,” he declares, “are founded by the sublime force of
- great men, not by physical strength. The great man has something in his
- features which others would gladly call their lord. They obey him against
- their will. Their immediate will is his will, but their conscious will is
- otherwise.... This is the prerogative of the great man to ascertain and to
- express the absolute will. All gather round his banner. He is their God.”
- “The state,” he says again, “is the self-certain absolute mind which
- recognises no definite authority but its own: which acknowledges no
- abstract rules of good and bad, shameful and mean, craft and deception.”
- So also Hobbes describes the prerogatives of the sovereign Leviathan. But
- the Hegelian God immanent in the state is a higher power than Hobbes
- knows: he is no mortal, but in his truth an immortal God. He speaks by
- (what in this early essay is called) the Absolute Government(97): the
- government of the Law—the true impersonal sovereign,—distinct alike from
- the single ruler and the multitude of the ruled. “It is absolutely only
- universality as against particular. As this absolute, ideal, universal,
- compared to which everything else is a particular, it is the phenomenon of
- God. Its words are his decision, and it can appear and exist under no
- other form.... The Absolute government is divine, self-sanctioned and not
- made(98).” The real strength—the real connecting-mean which gives life to
- sovereign and to subject—is intelligence free and entire, independent both
- of what individuals feel and believe and of the quality of the ruler. “The
- spiritual bond,” he says in a lower form of speech, “is public opinion: it
- is the true legislative body, national assembly, declaration of the
- universal will which lives in the execution of all commands.” This still
- small voice of public opinion is the true and real parliament: not
- literally making laws, but revealing them. If we ask, where does this
- public opinion appear and how does it disengage itself from the masses of
- partisan judgment? Hegel answers,—and to the surprise of those who have
- not entered into the spirit of his age(99)—it is embodied in the Aged and
- the Priests. Both of these have ceased to live in the real world: they are
- by nature and function disengaged from the struggles of particular
- existence, have risen above the divergencies of social classes. They
- breathe the ether of pure contemplation. “The sunset of life gives them
- mystical lore,” or at least removes from old age the distraction of
- selfishness: while the priest is by function set apart from the divisions
- of human interest. Understood in a large sense, Hegel’s view is that the
- real voice of experience is elicited through those who have attained
- indifference to the distorting influence of human parties, and who see
- life steadily and whole.
- If this utterance shows the little belief Hegel had in the ordinary
- methods of legislation through “representative” bodies, and hints that the
- real _substance_ of political life is deeper than the overt machinery of
- political operation, it is evident that this theory of “divine right” is
- of a different stamp from what used to go under that name. And, again,
- though the power of the central state is indispensable, he is far from
- agreeing with the so-called bureaucratic view that “a state is a machine
- with a single spring which sets in motion all the rest of the machinery.”
- “Everything,” he says, “which is not directly required to organise and
- maintain the force for giving security without and within must be left by
- the central government to the freedom of the citizens. Nothing ought to be
- so sacred in the eyes of a government as to leave alone and to protect,
- without regard to utilities, the free action of the citizens in such
- matters as do not affect its fundamental aim: for this freedom is itself
- sacred(100).” He is no friend of paternal bureaucracy. “The pedantic
- craving to settle every detail, the mean jealousy against estates and
- corporations administrating and directing their own affairs, the base
- fault-finding with all independent action on the part of the citizens,
- even when it has no immediate bearing on the main political interest, has
- been decked out with reasons to show that no penny of public expenditure,
- made for a country of twenty or thirty millions’ population, can be laid
- out, without first being, not permitted, but commanded, controlled and
- revised by the supreme government.” You can see, he remarks, in the first
- village after you enter Prussian territory the lifeless and wooden routine
- which prevails. The whole country suffers also from the way religion has
- been mixed up with political rights, and a particular creed pronounced by
- law indispensable both for sovereign and full-privileged subject. In a
- word, the unity and vigour of the state is quite compatible with
- considerable latitude and divergence in laws and judicature, in the
- imposition and levying of taxes, in language, manners, civilisation and
- religion. Equality in all these points is desirable for social unity: but
- it is not indispensable for political strength.
- This decided preference for the unity of the state against the system of
- checks and counterchecks, which sometimes goes by the name of a
- constitution, came out clearly in Hegel’s attitude in discussing the
- dispute between the Würtembergers and their sovereign in 1815-16.
- Würtemberg, with its complicated aggregation of local laws, had always
- been a paradise of lawyers, and the feudal rights or privileges of the
- local oligarchies—the so-called “good old law”—were the boast of the
- country. All this had however been aggravated by the increase of territory
- received in 1805: and the king, following the examples set by France and
- even by Bavaria, promulgated of his own grace a “constitution” remodelling
- the electoral system of the country. Immediately an outcry burst out
- against the attempt to destroy the ancient liberties. Uhland tuned his
- lyre to the popular cry: Rückert sang on the king’s side. To Hegel the
- contest presented itself as a struggle between the attachment to
- traditional rights, merely because they are old, and the resolution to
- carry out reasonable reform whether it be agreeable to the reformed or
- not: or rather he saw in it resistance of particularism, of separation,
- clinging to use and wont, and basing itself on formal pettifogging
- objections, against the spirit of organisation. Anything more he declined
- to see. And probably he was right in ascribing a large part of the
- opposition to inertia, to vanity and self-interest, combined with the want
- of political perception of the needs of Würtemberg and Germany. But on the
- other hand, he failed to remember the insecurity and danger of such “gifts
- of the Danai”: he forgot the sense of free-born men that a constitution is
- not something to be granted (_octroyé_) as a grace, but something that
- must come by the spontaneous act of the innermost self of the community.
- He dealt rather with the formal arguments which were used to refuse
- progress, than with the underlying spirit which prompted the
- opposition(101).
- The philosopher lives (as Plato has well reminded us) too exclusively
- within the ideal. Bent on the essential nucleus of institutions, he
- attaches but slight importance to the variety of externals, and fails to
- realise the practice of the law-courts. He forgets that what weighs
- lightly in logic, may turn the scale in real life and experience. For
- feeling and sentiment he has but scant respect: he is brusque and
- uncompromising: and cannot realise all the difficulties and dangers that
- beset the Idea in the mazes of the world, and may ultimately quite alter a
- plan which at first seemed independent of petty details. Better than other
- men perhaps he recognises in theory how the mere universal only exists
- complete in an individual shape: but more than other men he forgets these
- truths of insight, when the business of life calls for action or for
- judgment. He cannot at a moment’s notice remember that he is, if not, as
- Cicero says, _in faece Romuli_, the member of a degenerate commonwealth,
- at least living in a world where good and evil are not, as logic
- presupposes, sharply divided but intricately intertwined.
- (ii.) The Ethics and Religion of the State.
- This idealism of political theory is illustrated by the sketch of the
- Ethical Life which he drew up about 1802. Under the name of “Ethical
- System” it presents in concentrated or undeveloped shape the doctrine
- which subsequently swelled into the “Philosophy of Mind.” At a later date
- he worked out more carefully as introduction the psychological genesis of
- moral and intelligent man, and he separated out more distinctly as a
- sequel the universal powers which give to social life its higher
- characters. In the earlier sketch the Ethical Part stands by itself, with
- the consequence that Ethics bears a meaning far exceeding all that had
- been lately called moral. The word “moral” itself he avoids(102). It
- savours of excessive subjectivity, of struggle, of duty and conscience. It
- has an ascetic ring about it—an aspect of negation, which seeks for
- abstract holiness, and turns its back on human nature. Kant’s words
- opposing duty to inclination, and implying that moral goodness involves a
- struggle, an antagonism, a victory, seem to him (and to his time)
- one-sided. That aspect of negation accordingly which Kant certainly began
- with, and which Schopenhauer magnified until it became the all-in-all of
- Ethics, Hegel entirely subordinates. Equally little does he like the
- emphasis on the supremacy of insight, intention, conscience: they lead, he
- thinks, to a view which holds the mere fact of conviction to be
- all-important, as if it mattered not what we thought and believed and did,
- so long as we were sincere in our belief. All this emphasis on the
- good-will, on the imperative of duty, on the rights of conscience, has, he
- admits, its justification in certain circumstances, as against mere
- legality, or mere natural instinctive goodness; but it has been overdone.
- Above all, it errs by an excess of individualism. It springs from an
- attitude of reflection,—in which the individual, isolated in his conscious
- and superficial individuality, yet tries—but probably tries in vain—to get
- somewhat in touch with a universal which he has allowed to slip outside
- him, forgetting that it is the heart and substance of his life. Kant,
- indeed, hardly falls under this condemnation. For he aims at showing that
- the rational will inevitably creates as rational a law or universal; that
- the individual act becomes self-regulative, and takes its part in
- constituting a system or realm of duty.
- Still, on the whole, “morality” in this narrower sense belongs to an age
- of reflection, and is formal or nominal goodness rather than the genuine
- and full reality. It is the protest against mere instinctive or customary
- virtue, which is but compliance with traditional authority, and compliance
- with it as if it were a sort of quasi-natural law. Moralising reflection
- is the awakening of subjectivity and of a deeper personality. The age
- which thus precedes morality is not an age in which kindness, or love, or
- generosity is unknown. And if Hegel says that “Morality,” strictly so
- called, began with Socrates, he does not thereby accuse the pre-Socratic
- Greeks of inhumanity. But what he does say is that such ethical life as
- existed was in the main a thing of custom and law: of law, moreover, which
- was not set objectively forward, but left still in the stage of
- uncontradicted usage, a custom which was a second nature, part of the
- essential and quasi-physical ordinance of life. The individual had not yet
- learned to set his self-consciousness against these usages and ask for
- their justification. These are like the so-called law of the Medes and
- Persians which alters not: customs of immemorial antiquity and
- unquestionable sway. They are part of a system of things with which for
- good or evil the individual is utterly identified, bound as it were hand
- and foot. These are, as a traveller says(103), “oral and unwritten
- traditions which teach that certain rules of conduct are to be observed
- under certain penalties; and without the aid of fixed records, or the
- intervention of a succession of authorised depositaries and expounders,
- these laws have been transmitted to father and son, through unknown
- generations, and are fixed in the minds of the people as sacred and
- unalterable.”
- The antithesis then in Hegel, as in Kant, is between Law and Morality, or
- rather Legality and Morality,—two abstractions to which human development
- is alternately prone to attach supreme importance. The first stage in the
- objectivation of intelligence or in the evolution of personality is the
- constitution of mere, abstract, or strict right. It is the creation of
- institutions and uniformities, i.e. of laws, or rights, which express
- definite and stereotyped modes of behaviour. Or, if we look at it from the
- individual’s standpoint, we may say his consciousness awakes to find the
- world parcelled out under certain rules and divisions, which have
- objective validity, and govern him with the same absolute authority as do
- the circumstances of physical nature. Under their influence every rank and
- individual is alike forced to bow: to each his place and function is
- assigned by an order or system which claims an inviolable and eternal
- supremacy. It is not the same place and function for each: but for each
- the position and duties are predetermined in this metaphysically-physical
- order. The situation and its duties have been created by super-human and
- natural ordinance. As the Platonic myth puts it, each order in the social
- hierarchy has been framed underground by powers that turned out men of
- gold, and silver, and baser metal: or as the Norse legend tells, they are
- the successive offspring of the white God, Heimdal, in his dealings with
- womankind.
- The central idea of the earlier social world is the supremacy of
- rights—but not of right. The sum (for it cannot be properly called a
- system) of rights is a self-subsistent world, to which man is but a
- servant; and a second peculiarity of it is its inequality. If all are
- equal before the laws, this only means here that the laws, with their
- absolute and thorough inequality, are indifferent to the real and personal
- diversities of individuals. Even the so-called equality of primitive law
- is of the “Eye-for-eye, Tooth-for-tooth” kind; it takes no note of special
- circumstances; it looks abstractly and rudely at facts, and maintains a
- hard and fast uniformity, which seems the height of unfairness. Rule
- stands by rule, usage beside usage,—a mere aggregate or multitude of petty
- tyrants, reduced to no unity or system, and each pressing with all the
- weight of an absolute mandate. The pettiest bit of ceremonial law is here
- of equal dignity with the most far-reaching principle of political
- obligation.
- In the essay already referred to, Hegel has designated something analogous
- to this as Natural or Physical Ethics, or as Ethics in its relative or
- comparative stage. Here Man first shows his superiority to nature, or
- enters on his properly ethical function, by transforming the physical
- world into his possession. He makes himself the lord of natural
- objects—stamping them as his, and not their own, making them his permanent
- property, his tools, his instruments of exchange and production. The
- fundamental ethical act is appropriation by labour, and the first ethical
- world is the creation of an economic system, the institution of property.
- For property, or at least possession and appropriation, is the dominant
- idea, with its collateral and sequent principles. And at first, even human
- beings are treated on the same method as other things: as objects in a
- world of objects or aggregate of things: as things to be used and
- acquired, as means and instruments,—not in any sense as ends in
- themselves. It is a world in which the relation of master and slave is
- dominant,—where owner and employer is set in antithesis against his tools
- and chattels. But the Nemesis of his act issues in making the individual
- the servant of his so-called property. He has become an objective power by
- submitting himself to objectivity: he has literally put himself into the
- object he has wrought, and is now a thing among things: for what he owns,
- what he has appropriated, determines what he is. The real powers in the
- world thus established are the laws of possession-holding: the laws
- dominate man: and he is only freed from dependence on casual externals, by
- making himself thoroughly the servant of his possessions.
- The only salvation, and it is but imperfect, that can be reached on this
- stage is by the family union. The sexual tie, is at first entirely on a
- level with the other arrangements of the sphere. The man or woman is but a
- chattel and a tool; a casual appropriation which gradually is transformed
- into a permanent possession and a permanent bond(104). But, as the family
- constituted itself, it helped to afford a promise of better things. An
- ideal interest—the religion of the household—extending beyond the
- individual, and beyond the moment,—binding past and present, and parents
- to offspring, gave a new character to the relation of property. Parents
- and children form a unity, which overrides and essentially permeates their
- “difference” from each other: there is no exchange, no contract, nor, in
- the stricter sense, property between the members. In the property-idea
- they are lifted out of their isolation, and in the continuity of family
- life there is a certain analogue of immortality. But, says Hegel, “though
- the family be the highest totality of which Nature is capable, the
- absolute identity is in it still inward, and is not instituted in absolute
- form; and hence, too, the reproduction of the totality is an appearance,
- the appearance of the children(105).” “The power and the intelligence, the
- ‘difference’ of the parents, stands in inverse proportion to the youth and
- vigour of the child: and these two sides of life flee from and are sequent
- on each other, and are reciprocally external(106).” Or, as we may put it,
- the god of the family is a departed ancestor, a ghost in the land of the
- dead: it has not really a continuous and unified life. In such a state of
- society—a state of nature—and in its supreme form, the family, there is no
- adequate principle which though real shall still give ideality and unity
- to the self-isolating aspects of life. There is wanted something which
- shall give expression to its “indifference,” which shall control the
- tendency of this partial moralisation to sink at every moment into
- individuality, and lift it from its immersion in nature. Family life and
- economic groups (—for these two, which Hegel subsequently separates, are
- here kept close together) need an ampler and wider life to keep them from
- stagnating in their several selfishnesses.
- This freshening and corrective influence they get in the first instance
- from deeds of violence and crime. Here is the “negative unsettling” of the
- narrow fixities, of the determinate conditions or relationships into which
- the preceding processes of labour and acquisition have tended to
- stereotype life. The harsh restriction brings about its own undoing. Man
- may subject natural objects to his formative power, but the wild rage of
- senseless devastation again and again bursts forth to restore the original
- formlessness. He may build up his own pile of wealth, store up his private
- goods, but the thief and the robber with the instincts of barbarian
- socialism tread on his steps: and every stage of appropriation has for its
- sequel a crop of acts of dispossession. He may secure by accumulation his
- future life; but the murderer for gain’s sake cuts it short. And out of
- all this as a necessary consequence stands avenging justice. And in the
- natural world of ethics—where true moral life has not yet arisen—this is
- mere retaliation or the _lex talionis_;—the beginning of an endless series
- of vengeance and counter-vengeance, the blood-feud. Punishment, in the
- stricter sense of the term,—which looks both to antecedents and effects in
- character—cannot yet come into existence; for to punish there must be
- something superior to individualities, an ethical idea embodied in an
- institution, to which the injurer and the injured alike belong. But as yet
- punishment is only vengeance, the personal and natural equivalent, the
- physical reaction against injury, perhaps regulated and formulated by
- custom and usage, but not essentially altered from its purely retaliatory
- character. These crimes—or transgressions—are thus by Hegel quaintly
- conceived as storms which clear the air—which shake the individualist out
- of his slumber. The scene in which transgression thus acts is that of the
- so-called state of nature, where particularism was rampant: where moral
- right was not, but only the right of nature, of pre-occupation, of the
- stronger, of the first maker and discoverer. Crime is thus the “dialectic”
- which shakes the fixity of practical arrangements, and calls for something
- in which the idea of a higher unity, a permanent substance of life, shall
- find realisation.
- The “positive supersession(107)” of individualism and naturalism in ethics
- is by Hegel called “Absolute Ethics.” Under this title he describes the
- ethics and religion of the state—a religion which is immanent in the
- community, and an ethics which rises superior to particularity. The
- picture he draws is a romance fashioned upon the model of the Greek
- commonwealth as that had been idealised by Greek literature and by the
- longings of later ages for a freer life. It is but one of the many modes
- in which Helena—to quote Goethe—has fascinated the German Faust. He dreams
- himself away from the prosaic worldliness of a German municipality to the
- unfading splendour of the Greek city with its imagined coincidence of
- individual will with universal purpose. There is in such a commonwealth no
- pain of surrender and of sacrifice, and no subsequent compensation: for,
- at the very moment of resigning self-will to common aims, he enjoys it
- retained with the added zest of self-expansion. He is not so left to
- himself as to feel from beyond the restraint of a law which controls—even
- if it wisely and well controls—individual effort. There is for his happy
- circumstances no possibility of doing otherwise. Or, it may be, Hegel has
- reminiscences from the ideals of other nations than the Greek. He recalls
- the Israelite depicted by the Law-adoring psalmist, whose delight is to do
- the will of the Lord, whom the zeal of God’s house has consumed, whose
- whole being runs on in one pellucid stream with the universal and eternal
- stream of divine commandment. Such a frame of spirit, where the empirical
- consciousness with all its soul and strength and mind identifies its
- mission into conformity with the absolute order, is the mood of absolute
- Ethics. It is what some have spoken of as the True life, as the Eternal
- life; in it, says Hegel, the individual exists _auf ewige Weise_(108), as
- it were _sub specie aeternitatis_: his life is hid with his fellows in the
- common life of his people. His every act, and thought, and will, get their
- being and significance from a reality which is established in him as a
- permanent spirit. It is there that he, in the fuller sense, attains
- αὐτάρκεια, or finds himself no longer a mere part, but an ideal totality.
- This totality is realised under the particular form of a Nation (_Volk_),
- which in the visible sphere represents (or rather is, as a particular) the
- absolute and infinite. Such a unity is neither the mere sum of isolated
- individuals, nor a mere majority ruling by numbers: but the fraternal and
- organic commonwealth which brings all classes and all rights from their
- particularistic independence into an ideal identity and indifference(109).
- Here all are not merely equal before the laws: but the law itself is a
- living and organic unity, self-correcting, subordinating and organising,
- and no longer merely defining individual privileges and so-called
- liberties. “In such conjunction of the universal with the particularity
- lies the divinity of a nation: or, if we give this universal a separate
- place in our ideas, it is the God of the nation.” But in this complete
- accordance between concept and intuition, between visible and invisible,
- where symbol and significate are one, religion and ethics are
- indistinguishable. It is the old conception (and in its highest sense) of
- Theocracy(110). God is the national head and the national life: and in him
- all individuals have their “difference” rendered “indifferent.” “Such an
- ethical life is absolute truth, for untruth is only in the fixture of a
- single mode: but in the everlasting being of the nation all singleness is
- superseded. It is absolute culture; for in the eternal is the real and
- empirical annihilation and prescription of all limited modality. It is
- absolute disinterestedness: for in the eternal there is nothing private
- and personal. It, and each of its movements, is the highest beauty: for
- beauty is but the eternal made actual and given concrete shape. It is
- without pain, and blessed: for in it all difference and all pain is
- superseded. It is the divine, absolute, real, existing and being, under no
- veil; nor need one first raise it up into the ideality of divinity, and
- extract it from the appearance and empirical intuition; but it is, and
- immediately, absolute intuition(111).”
- If we compare this language with the statement of the Encyclopaedia we can
- see how for the moment Hegel’s eye is engrossed with the glory of the
- ideal nation. In it, the moral life embraces and is co-extensive with
- religion, art and science: practice and theory are at one: life in the
- idea knows none of those differences which, in the un-ideal world, make
- art and morality often antithetical, and set religion at variance with
- science. It is, as we have said, a memory of Greek and perhaps Hebrew
- ideals. Or rather it is by the help of such memories the affirmation of
- the essential unity of life—the true, complete, many-sided life—which is
- the presupposition and idea that culture and morals rest upon and from
- which they get their supreme sanction, i.e. their constitutive principle
- and unity. Even in the Encyclopaedia(112) Hegel endeavours to guard
- against the severance of morality and art and philosophy which may be
- rashly inferred in consequence of his serial order of treatment.
- “Religion,” he remarks, “is the very substance of the moral life itself
- and of the state.... The ethical life is the divine spirit indwelling in
- consciousness, as it is actually present in a nation and its individual
- members.” Yet, as we see, there is a distinction. The process of history
- carries out a judgment on nation after nation, and reveals the divine as
- not only immanent in the ethical life but as ever expanding the limited
- national spirit till it become a spirit of universal humanity. Still—and
- this is perhaps for each time always the more important—the national
- unity—not indeed as a multitude, nor as a majority—is the supreme real
- appearance of the Eternal and Absolute.
- Having thus described the nation as an organic totality, he goes on to
- point out that the political constitution shows this character by forming
- a triplicity of political orders. In one of these there is but a silent,
- practical identity, in faith and trust, with the totality: in the second
- there is a thorough disruption of interest into particularity: and in the
- third, there is a living and intellectual identity or indifference, which
- combines the widest range of individual development with the completest
- unity of political loyalty. This last order is that which lives in
- conscious identification of private with public duty: all that it does has
- a universal and public function. Such a body is the ideal Nobility—the
- nobility which is the _servus servorum Dei_, the supreme servant of
- humanity. Its function is to maintain general interests, to give the other
- orders (peasantry and industrials) security,—receiving in return from
- these others the means of subsistence. _Noblesse oblige_ gives the
- death-blow to particular interests, and imposes the duty of exhibiting, in
- the clearest form, the supreme reality of absolute morality, and of being
- to the rest an unperturbed ideal of aesthetic, ethical, religious, and
- philosophical completeness.
- It is here alone, in this estate which is absolutely disinterested, that
- the virtues appear in their true light. To the ordinary moralising
- standpoint they seem severally to be, in their separation, charged with
- independent value. But from the higher point of view the existence, and
- still more the accentuation of single virtues, is a mark of
- incompleteness. Even quality, it has been said, involves its defects: it
- can only shine by eclipsing or reflecting something else. The completely
- moral is not the sum of the several virtues, but the reduction of them to
- indifference. It is thus that when Plato tries to get at the unity of
- virtue, their aspect of difference tends to be subordinated. “The movement
- of absolute morality runs through all the virtues, but settles fixedly in
- none.” It is more than love _to_ fatherland, and nation, and laws:—that
- still implies a relation to something and involves a difference. For
- love—the mortal passion, where “self is not annulled”—is the process of
- approximation, while unity is not yet attained, but wished and aimed at:
- and when it is complete—and become “such love as spirits know(113)”—it
- gives place to a calmer rest and an active immanence. The absolute
- morality is _life in_ the fatherland and for the nation. In the individual
- however it is the process upward and inward that we see, not the
- consummation. Then the identity appears as an ideal, as a tendency not yet
- accomplished to its end, a possibility not yet made fully actual. At
- bottom—in the divine substance in which the individual inheres—the
- identity is present: but in the appearance, we have only the passage from
- possible to actual, a passage which has the aspect of a struggle. Hence
- the moral act appears as a virtue, with merit or desert. It is accordingly
- the very characteristic of virtue to signalise its own incompleteness: it
- emerges into actuality only through antagonism, and with a taint of
- imperfection clinging to it. Thus, in the field of absolute morality, if
- the virtues appear, it is only in their transiency. If they were
- undisputedly real in morality, they would not separately show. To feel
- that you have done well implies that you have not done wholly well:
- self-gratulation in meritorious deed is the re-action from the shudder at
- feeling that the self was not wholly good.
- The essential unity of virtue—its negative character as regards all the
- empirical variety of virtues—is seen in the excellences required by the
- needs of war. These military requirements demonstrate the mere relativity
- and therefore non-virtuousness of the special virtues. They equally
- protest against the common beliefs in the supreme dignity of labour and
- its utilities. But if bravery or soldierlike virtue be essentially a
- virtue of virtues, it is only a negative virtue after all. It is the blast
- of the universal sweeping away all the habitations and fixed structures of
- particularist life. If it is a unity of virtue, it is only a negative
- unity—an indifference. If it avoid the parcelling of virtue into a number
- of imperfect and sometimes contradictory parts, it does so only to present
- a bare negation. The soldier, therefore, if in potentiality the unity of
- all the virtues, may tend in practice to represent the ability to do
- without any of them(114).
- The home of these “relative” virtues—of morality in the ordinary sense—is
- the life of the second order in the commonwealth: the order of industry
- and commerce. In this sphere the idea of the universal is gradually lost
- to view: it becomes, says Hegel, only a thought or a creature of the mind,
- which does not affect practice. The materialistic worker of civilisation
- does not see further than the empirical existence of individuals: his
- horizon is limited by the family, and his final ideal is a competency of
- comfort in possessions and revenues. The supreme universal to which he
- attains as the climax of his evolution is only money. But it is only with
- the vaster development of commerce that this terrible consequence ensues.
- At first as a mere individual, he has higher aims, though not the highest.
- He has a limited ideal determined by his special sphere of work. To win
- respect—the character for a limited truthfulness and honesty and skilful
- work—is his ambition. He lives in a conceit of his performance—his
- utility—the esteem of his special circle. To his commercial soul the
- military order is a scarecrow and a nuisance: military honour is but
- trash. Yet if his range of idea is narrow and engrossing in details, his
- aim is to get worship, to be recognised as the best in his little sphere.
- But with the growth of the trading spirit his character changes: he
- becomes the mere capitalist, is denationalised, has no definite work and
- can claim no individualised function. Money now measures all things: it is
- the sole ultimate reality. It transforms everything into a relation of
- contract: even vengeance is equated in terms of money. Its motto is, The
- Exchanges must be honoured, though honour and morality may go to the dogs.
- So far as it is concerned, there is no nation, but a federation of
- shopkeepers. Such an one is the _bourgeois_ (the _Bürger_, as distinct
- from the peasant or _Bauer_ and the _Adel_). As an artisan—i.e. a mere
- industrial, he knows no country, but at best the reputation and interest
- of his own guild-union with its partial object. He is narrow, but honest
- and respectable. As a mere commercial agent, he knows no country: his
- field is the world, but the world not in its concreteness and variety, but
- in the abstract aspect of a money-bag and an exchange. The larger totality
- is indeed not altogether out of sight. But if he contribute to the needy,
- either his sacrifice is lifeless in proportion as it becomes general, or
- loses generality as it becomes lively. As regards his general services to
- the great life of his national state(115), they are unintelligently and
- perhaps grudgingly rendered.
- Of the peasant order Hegel has less to say. On one side the “country” as
- opposed to the “town” has a closer natural sympathy with the common and
- general interest: and the peasantry is the undifferentiated, solid and
- sound, basis of the national life. It forms the submerged mass, out of
- which the best soldiers are made, and which out of the depths of earth
- brings forward nourishment as well as all the materials of elementary
- necessity. Faithfulness and loyalty are its virtues: but it is personal
- allegiance to a commanding superior,—not to a law or a general view—for
- the peasant is weak in comprehensive intelligence, though shrewd in
- detailed observation.
- Of the purely political function of the state Hegel in this sketch says
- almost nothing. But under the head of the general government of the state
- he deals with its social functions. For a moment he refers to the
- well-known distinction of the legislative, judicial and executive powers.
- But it is only to remark that “in every governmental act all three are
- conjoined. They are abstractions, none of which can get a reality of its
- own,—which, in other words, cannot be constituted and organised as powers.
- Legislation, judicature, and executive are something completely formal,
- empty, and contentless.... Whether the others are or are not bare
- abstractions, empty activities, depends entirely on the executive power;
- and this is absolutely the government(116).” Treating government as the
- organic movement by which the universal and the particular in the
- commonwealth come into relations, he finds that it presents three forms,
- or gives rise to three systems. The highest and last of these is the
- “educational” system. By this he understands all that activity by which
- the intelligence of the state tries directly to mould and guide the
- character and fortunes of its members: all the means of culture and
- discipline, whether in general or for individuals, all training to public
- function, to truthfulness, to good manners. Under the same head come
- conquest and colonisation as state agencies. The second system is the
- judicial, which instead of, like the former, aiming at the formation or
- reformation of its members is satisfied by subjecting individual
- transgression to a process of rectification by the general principle. With
- regard to the system of judicature, Hegel argues for a variety of
- procedure to suit different ranks, and for a corresponding modification of
- penalties. “Formal rigid equality is just what does not spare the
- character. The same penalty which in one estate brings no infamy causes in
- another a deep and irremediable hurt.” And with regard to the after life
- of the transgressor who has borne his penalty: “Punishment is the
- reconciliation of the law with itself. No further reproach for his crime
- can be addressed to the person who has undergone his punishment. He is
- restored to membership of his estate(117).”
- In the first of the three systems, the economic system, or “System of
- wants,” the state seems at first hardly to appear in its universal and
- controlling function at all. Here the individual depends for the
- satisfaction of his physical needs on a blind, unconscious destiny, on the
- obscure and incalculable properties of supply and demand in the whole
- interconnexion of commodities. But even this is not all. With the
- accumulation of wealth in inequality, and the growth of vast capitals,
- there is substituted for the dependence of the individual on the general
- resultant of a vast number of agencies a dependence on one enormously rich
- individual, who can control the physical destinies of a nation. But a
- nation, truly speaking, is there no more. The industrial order has parted
- into a mere abstract workman on one hand, and the _grande richesse_ on the
- other. “It has lost its capacity of an organic absolute intuition and of
- respect for the divine—external though its divinity be: and there sets in
- the bestiality of contempt for all that is noble. The mere wisdomless
- universal, the mass of wealth, is the essential: and the ethical
- principle, the absolute bond of the nation, is vanished; and the nation is
- dissolved(118).”
- It would be a long and complicated task to sift, in these ill-digested but
- profound suggestions, the real meaning from the formal statement. They
- are, like Utopia, beyond the range of practical politics. The modern
- reader, whose political conceptions are limited by contemporary
- circumstance, may find them archaic, medieval, quixotic. But for those who
- behind the words and forms can see the substance and the idea, they will
- perhaps come nearer the conception of ideal commonwealth than many
- reforming programmes. Compared with the maturer statements of the
- _Philosophy of Law_, they have the faults of the Romantic age to which
- their inception belongs. Yet even in that later exposition there is upheld
- the doctrine of the supremacy of the eternal State against everything
- particular, class-like, and temporary; a doctrine which has made Hegel—as
- it made Fichte—a voice in that “professorial socialism” which is at least
- as old as Plato.
- INTRODUCTION.
- § 377. The knowledge of Mind is the highest and hardest, just because it
- is the most “concrete” of sciences. The significance of that “absolute”
- commandment, _Know thyself_—whether we look at it in itself or under the
- historical circumstances of its first utterance—is not to promote mere
- self-knowledge in respect of the _particular_ capacities, character,
- propensities, and foibles of the single self. The knowledge it commands
- means that of man’s genuine reality—of what is essentially and ultimately
- true and real—of mind as the true and essential being. Equally little is
- it the purport of mental philosophy to teach what is called _knowledge of
- men_—the knowledge whose aim is to detect the _peculiarities_, passions,
- and foibles of other men, and lay bare what are called the recesses of the
- human heart. Information of this kind is, for one thing, meaningless,
- unless on the assumption that we know the _universal_—man as man, and,
- that always must be, as mind. And for another, being only engaged with
- casual, insignificant and _untrue_ aspects of mental life, it fails to
- reach the underlying essence of them all—the mind itself.
- § 378. Pneumatology, or, as it was also called, Rational Psychology, has
- been already alluded to in the Introduction to the Logic as an _abstract_
- and generalising metaphysic of the subject. _Empirical_ (or inductive)
- psychology, on the other hand, deals with the “concrete” mind: and, after
- the revival of the sciences, when observation and experience had been made
- the distinctive methods for the study of concrete reality, such psychology
- was worked on the same lines as other sciences. In this way it came about
- that the metaphysical theory was kept outside the inductive science, and
- so prevented from getting any concrete embodiment or detail: whilst at the
- same time the inductive science clung to the conventional common-sense
- metaphysic, with its analysis into forces, various activities, &c., and
- rejected any attempt at a “speculative” treatment.
- The books of Aristotle on the Soul, along with his discussions on its
- special aspects and states, are for this reason still by far the most
- admirable, perhaps even the sole, work of philosophical value on this
- topic. The main aim of a philosophy of mind can only be to re-introduce
- unity of idea and principle into the theory of mind, and so re-interpret
- the lesson of those Aristotelian books.
- § 379. Even our own sense of the mind’s _living_ unity naturally protests
- against any attempt to break it up into different faculties, forces, or,
- what comes to the same thing, activities, conceived as independent of each
- other. But the craving for a _comprehension_ of the unity is still further
- stimulated, as we soon come across distinctions between mental freedom and
- mental determinism, antitheses between free _psychic_ agency and the
- corporeity that lies external to it, whilst we equally note the intimate
- interdependence of the one upon the other. In modern times especially the
- phenomena of _animal magnetism_ have given, even in experience, a lively
- and visible confirmation of the underlying unity of soul, and of the power
- of its “ideality.” Before these facts, the rigid distinctions of practical
- common sense were struck with confusion; and the necessity of a
- “speculative” examination with a view to the removal of difficulties was
- more directly forced upon the student.
- § 380. The “concrete” nature of mind involves for the observer the
- peculiar difficulty that the several grades and special types which
- develop its intelligible unity in detail are not left standing as so many
- separate existences confronting its more advanced aspects. It is otherwise
- in external nature. There, matter and movement, for example, have a
- manifestation all their own—it is the solar system; and similarly the
- _differentiae_ of sense-perception have a sort of earlier existence in the
- properties of _bodies_, and still more independently in the four elements.
- The species and grades of mental evolution, on the contrary, lose their
- separate existence and become factors, states and features in the higher
- grades of development. As a consequence of this, a lower and more abstract
- aspect of mind betrays the presence in it, even to experience, of a higher
- grade. Under the guise of sensation, e.g., we may find the very highest
- mental life as its modification or its embodiment. And so sensation, which
- is but a mere form and vehicle, may to the superficial glance seem to be
- the proper seat and, as it were, the source of those moral and religious
- principles with which it is charged; and the moral and religious
- principles thus modified may seem to call for treatment as species of
- sensation. But at the same time, when lower grades of mental life are
- under examination, it becomes necessary, if we desire to point to actual
- cases of them in experience, to direct attention to more advanced grades
- for which they are mere forms. In this way subjects will be treated of by
- anticipation which properly belong to later stages of development (e.g. in
- dealing with natural awaking from sleep we speak by anticipation of
- consciousness, or in dealing with mental derangement we must speak of
- intellect).
- What Mind (or Spirit) is.
- § 381. From our point of view Mind has for its _presupposition_ Nature, of
- which it is the truth, and for that reason its _absolute prius_. In this
- its truth Nature is vanished, and mind has resulted as the “Idea” entered
- on possession of itself. Here the subject and object of the Idea are
- one—either is the intelligent unity, the notion. This identity is
- _absolute negativity_—for whereas in Nature the intelligent unity has its
- objectivity perfect but externalised, this self-externalisation has been
- nullified and the unity in that way been made one and the same with
- itself. Thus at the same time it is this identity only so far as it is a
- return out of nature.
- § 382. For this reason the essential, but formally essential, feature of
- mind is Liberty: i.e. it is the notion’s absolute negativity or
- self-identity. Considered as this formal aspect, it _may_ withdraw itself
- from everything external and from its own externality, its very existence;
- it can thus submit to infinite _pain_, the negation of its individual
- immediacy: in other words, it can keep itself affirmative in this
- negativity and possess its own identity. All this is possible so long as
- it is considered in its abstract self-contained universality.
- § 383. This universality is also its determinate sphere of being. Having a
- being of its own, the universal is self-particularising, whilst it still
- remains self-identical. Hence the special mode of mental being is
- “_manifestation_.” The spirit is not some one mode or meaning which finds
- utterance or externality only in a form distinct from itself: it does not
- manifest or reveal _something_, but its very mode and meaning is this
- revelation. And thus in its mere possibility Mind is at the same moment an
- infinite, “absolute,” _actuality_.
- § 384. _Revelation_, taken to mean the revelation of the _abstract_ Idea,
- is an unmediated transition to Nature which _comes_ to be. As Mind is
- free, its manifestation is to _set forth_ Nature as _its_ world; but
- because it is reflection, it, in thus setting forth its world, at the same
- time _presupposes_ the world as a nature independently existing. In the
- intellectual sphere to reveal is thus to create a world as its being—a
- being in which the mind procures the _affirmation_ and _truth_ of its
- freedom.
- _The Absolute is Mind_ (Spirit)—this is the supreme definition of the
- Absolute. To find this definition and to grasp its meaning and burthen
- was, we may say, the ultimate purpose of all education and all philosophy:
- it was the point to which turned the impulse of all religion and science:
- and it is this impulse that must explain the history of the world. The
- word “Mind” (Spirit)—and some glimpse of its meaning—was found at an early
- period: and the spirituality of God is the lesson of Christianity. It
- remains for philosophy in its own element of intelligible unity to get
- hold of what was thus given as a mental image, and what implicitly is the
- ultimate reality: and that problem is not genuinely, and by rational
- methods, solved so long as liberty and intelligible unity is not the theme
- and the soul of philosophy.
- Subdivision.
- § 385. The development of Mind (Spirit) is in three stages:—
- (1) In the form of self-relation: within it it has the _ideal_ totality of
- the Idea—i.e. it has before it all that its notion contains: its being is
- to be self-contained and free. This is _Mind Subjective_.
- (2) In the form of _reality_: realised, i.e. in a _world_ produced and to
- be produced by it: in this world freedom presents itself under the shape
- of necessity. This is _Mind Objective_.
- (3) In that unity of mind as objectivity and, of mind as ideality and
- concept, which essentially and actually is and for ever produces itself,
- mind in its absolute truth. This is _Mind Absolute_.
- § 386. The two first parts of the doctrine of Mind embrace the finite
- mind. Mind is the infinite Idea; thus finitude here means the
- disproportion between the concept and the reality—but with the
- qualification that it is a shadow cast by the mind’s own light—a show or
- illusion which the mind implicitly imposes as a barrier to itself, in
- order, by its removal, actually to realise and become conscious of freedom
- as _its_ very being, i.e. to be fully _manifested_. The several steps of
- this activity, on each of which, with their semblance of being, it is the
- function of the finite mind to linger, and through which it has to pass,
- are steps in its liberation. In the full truth of that liberation is given
- the identification of the three stages—finding a world presupposed before
- us, generating a world as our own creation, and gaining freedom from it
- and in it. To the infinite form of this truth the show purifies itself
- till it becomes a consciousness of it.
- A rigid application of the category of finitude by the abstract logician
- is chiefly seen in dealing with Mind and reason: it is held not a mere
- matter of strict logic, but treated also as a moral and religious concern,
- to adhere to the point of view of finitude, and the wish to go further is
- reckoned a mark of audacity, if not of insanity, of thought. Whereas in
- fact such a _modesty_ of thought, as treats the finite as something
- altogether fixed and _absolute_, is the worst of virtues; and to stick to
- a post which has no sound ground in itself is the most unsound sort of
- theory. The category of finitude was at a much earlier period elucidated
- and explained at its place in the Logic: an elucidation which, as in logic
- for the more specific though still simple thought-forms of finitude, so in
- the rest of philosophy for the concrete forms, has merely to show that the
- finite _is not_, i.e. is not the truth, but merely a transition and an
- emergence to something higher. This finitude of the spheres so far
- examined is the dialectic that makes a thing have its cessation by another
- and in another: but Spirit, the intelligent unity and the _implicit_
- Eternal, is itself just the consummation of that internal act by which
- nullity is nullified and vanity is made vain. And so, the modesty alluded
- to is a retention of this vanity—the finite—in opposition to the true: it
- is itself therefore vanity. In the course of the mind’s development we
- shall see this vanity appear as _wickedness_ at that turning-point at
- which mind has reached its extreme immersion in its subjectivity and its
- most central contradiction.
- SECTION I. MIND SUBJECTIVE.
- § 387. Mind, on the ideal stage of its development, is mind as
- _cognitive_: Cognition, however, being taken here not as a merely logical
- category of the Idea (§ 223), but in the sense appropriate to the
- _concrete_ mind.
- Subjective mind is:—
- (A) Immediate or implicit: a soul—the Spirit in _Nature_—the object
- treated by _Anthropology_.
- (B) Mediate or explicit: still as identical reflection into itself and
- into other things: mind in correlation or particularisation:
- consciousness—the object treated by the _Phenomenology of Mind_.
- (C) Mind defining itself in itself, as an independent subject—the object
- treated by _Psychology_.
- In the Soul is the _awaking of Consciousness_: Consciousness sets itself
- up as Reason, awaking at one bound to the sense of its rationality: and
- this Reason by its activity emancipates itself to objectivity and the
- consciousness of its intelligent unity.
- For an intelligible unity or principle of comprehension each modification
- it presents is an advance of _development_: and so in mind every character
- under which it appears is a stage in a process of specification and
- development, a step forward towards its goal, in order to make itself
- into, and to realise in itself, what it implicitly is. Each step, again,
- is itself such a process, and its product is that what the mind was
- implicitly at the beginning (and so for the observer) it is _for
- itself_—for the special form, viz. which the mind has in that step. The
- ordinary method of psychology is to narrate what the mind or soul is, what
- happens to it, what it does. The soul is presupposed as a ready-made
- agent, which displays such features as its acts and utterances, from which
- we can learn what it is, what sort of faculties and powers it
- possesses—all without being aware that the act and utterance of what the
- soul is really invests it with that character in our conception and makes
- it reach a higher stage of being than it explicitly had before.
- We must, however, distinguish and keep apart from the progress here
- studied what we call education and instruction. The sphere of education is
- the individual’s only: and its aim is to bring the universal mind to exist
- in them. But in the philosophic theory of mind, mind is studied as
- self-instruction and self-education in very essence; and its acts and
- utterances are stages in the process which brings it forward to itself,
- links it in unity with itself, and so makes it actual mind.
- Sub-Section A. Anthropology. The Soul.
- § 388. Spirit (Mind) _came into_ being as the truth of Nature. But not
- merely is it, as such a result, to be held the true and real first of what
- went before: this becoming or transition bears in the sphere of the notion
- the special meaning of “_free judgment_.” Mind, thus come into being,
- means therefore that Nature in its own self realises its untruth and sets
- itself aside: it means that Mind presupposes itself no longer as the
- universality which in corporal individuality is always self-externalised,
- but as a universality which in its concretion and totality is one and
- simple. At such a stage it is not yet mind, but _soul_.
- § 389. The soul is no separate immaterial entity. Wherever there is
- Nature, the soul is its universal immaterialism, its simple “ideal” life.
- Soul is the _substance_ or “absolute” basis of all the particularising and
- individualising of mind: it is in the soul that mind finds the material on
- which its character is wrought, and the soul remains the pervading,
- identical ideality of it all. But as it is still conceived thus
- abstractly, the soul is only the _sleep_ of mind—the passive νοῦς of
- Aristotle, which is potentially all things.
- The question of the immateriality of the soul has no interest, except
- where, on the one hand, matter is regarded as something _true_, and mind
- conceived as a _thing_, on the other. But in modern times even the
- physicists have found matters grow thinner in their hands: they have come
- upon _imponderable_ matters, like heat, light, &c., to which they might
- perhaps add space and time. These “imponderables,” which have lost the
- property (peculiar to matter) of gravity and, in a sense, even the
- capacity of offering resistance, have still, however, a sensible existence
- and outness of part to part; whereas the “vital”_ matter_, which may also
- be found enumerated among them, not merely lacks gravity, but even every
- other aspect of existence which might lead us to treat it as material. The
- fact is that in the Idea of Life the self-externalism of nature is
- _implicitly_ at an end: subjectivity is the very substance and conception
- of life—with this proviso, however, that its existence or objectivity is
- still at the same time forfeited to the sway of self-externalism. It is
- otherwise with Mind. There, in the intelligible unity which exists as
- freedom, as absolute negativity, and not as the immediate or natural
- individual, the object or the reality of the intelligible unity is the
- unity itself; and so the self-externalism, which is the fundamental
- feature of matter, has been completely dissipated and transmuted into
- universality, or the subjective ideality of the conceptual unity. Mind is
- the existent truth of matter—the truth that matter itself has no truth.
- A cognate question is that of the _community of soul and body_. This
- community (interdependence) was assumed as a _fact_, and the only problem
- was how to _comprehend_ it. The usual answer, perhaps, was to call it an
- _incomprehensible_ mystery; and, indeed, if we take them to be absolutely
- antithetical and absolutely independent, they are as impenetrable to each
- other as one piece of matter to another, each being supposed to be found
- only in the pores of the other, i.e. where the other is not: whence
- Epicurus, when attributing to the gods a residence in the pores, was
- consistent in not imposing on them any connexion with the world. A
- somewhat different answer has been given by all philosophers since this
- relation came to be expressly discussed. Descartes, Malebranche, Spinoza,
- and Leibnitz have all indicated God as this _nexus_. They meant that the
- finitude of soul and matter were only ideal and unreal distinctions; and,
- so holding, these philosophers took God, not, as so often is done, merely
- as another word for the incomprehensible, but rather as the sole true
- identity of finite mind and matter. But either this identity, as in the
- case of Spinoza, is too abstract, or, as in the case of Leibnitz, though
- his Monad of monads brings things into being, it does so only by an act of
- judgment or choice. Hence, with Leibnitz, the result is a distinction
- between soul and the corporeal (or material), and the identity is only
- like the _copula_ of a judgment, and does not rise or develop into system,
- into the absolute syllogism.
- § 390. The Soul is at first—
- (_a_) In its immediate natural mode—the natural soul, which only _is_.
- (_b_) Secondly, it is a soul which _feels_, as individualised, enters into
- correlation with its immediate being, and, in the modes of that being,
- retains an abstract independence.
- (_c_) Thirdly, its immediate being—or corporeity—is moulded into it, and
- with that corporeity it exists as _actual_ soul.
- (a) The Physical Soul(119).
- § 391. The soul universal, described, it may be, as an _anima mundi_, a
- world-soul, must not be fixed on that account as a single subject; it is
- rather the universal _substance_ which has its actual truth only in
- individuals and single subjects. Thus, when it presents itself as a single
- soul, it is a single soul which _is_ merely: its only modes are modes of
- natural life. These have, so to speak, behind its ideality a free
- existence: i.e. they are natural objects for consciousness, but objects to
- which the soul as such does not behave as to something external. These
- features rather are _physical qualities_ of which it finds itself
- possessed.
- (α) Physical Qualities(120).
- § 392. While still a “substance” (i.e. a physical soul) the mind (1) takes
- part in the general planetary life, feels the difference of climates, the
- changes of the seasons and the periods of the day, &c. This life of nature
- for the main shows itself only in occasional strain or disturbance of
- mental tone.
- In recent times a good deal has been said of the cosmical, sidereal, and
- telluric life of man. In such a sympathy with nature the animals
- essentially live: their specific characters and their particular phases of
- growth depend, in many cases completely, and always more or less, upon it.
- In the case of man these points of dependence lose importance, just in
- proportion to his civilisation, and the more his whole frame of soul is
- based upon a substructure of mental freedom. The history of the world is
- not bound up with revolutions in the solar system, any more than the
- destinies of individuals with the positions of the planets.
- The difference of climate has a more solid and vigorous influence. But the
- response to the changes of the seasons and hours of the day is found only
- in faint changes of mood, which come expressly to the fore only in morbid
- states (including insanity) and at periods when the self-conscious life
- suffers depression.
- In nations less intellectually emancipated, which therefore live more in
- harmony with nature, we find amid their superstitions and aberrations of
- imbecility _a few_ real cases of such sympathy, and on that foundation
- what seems to be marvellous prophetic vision of coming conditions and of
- events arising therefrom. But as mental freedom gets a deeper hold, even
- these few and slight susceptibilities, based upon participation in the
- common life of nature, disappear. Animals and plants, on the contrary,
- remain for ever subject to such influences.
- § 393. (2) According to the concrete differences of the terrestrial globe,
- the general planetary life of the nature-governed mind specialises itself
- and breaks up into the several nature-governed minds which, on the whole,
- give expression to the nature of the geographical continents and
- constitute the diversities of _race_.
- The contrast between the earth’s poles, the land towards the north pole
- being more aggregated and preponderant over sea, whereas in the southern
- hemisphere it runs out in sharp points, widely distant from each other,
- introduces into the differences of continents a further modification which
- Treviranus (_Biology_, Part II) has exhibited in the case of the flora and
- fauna.
- § 394. This diversity descends into specialities, that may be termed
- _local_ minds—shown in the outward modes of life and occupation, bodily
- structure and disposition, but still more in the inner tendency and
- capacity of the intellectual and moral character of the several peoples.
- Back to the very beginnings of national history we see the several nations
- each possessing a persistent type of its own.
- § 395. (3) The soul is further de-universalised into the individualised
- subject. But this subjectivity is here only considered as a
- differentiation and singling out of the modes which nature gives; we find
- it as the special temperament, talent, character, physiognomy, or other
- disposition and idiosyncrasy, of families or single individuals.
- (β) Physical Alterations.
- § 396. Taking the soul as an individual, we find its diversities, as
- alterations in it, the one permanent subject, and as stages in its
- development. As they are at once physical and mental diversities, a more
- concrete definition or description of them would require us to anticipate
- an acquaintance with the formed and matured mind.
- The (1) first of these is the natural lapse of the ages in man’s life. He
- begins with _Childhood_—mind wrapt up in itself. His next step is the
- fully-developed antithesis, the strain and struggle of a universality
- which is still subjective (as seen in ideals, fancies, hopes, ambitions)
- against his immediate individuality. And that individuality marks both the
- world which, as it exists, fails to meet his ideal requirements, and the
- position of the individual himself, who is still short of independence and
- not fully equipped for the part he has to play (_Youth_). Thirdly, we see
- man in his true relation to his environment, recognising the objective
- necessity and reasonableness of the world as he finds it,—a world no
- longer incomplete, but able in the work which it collectively achieves to
- afford the individual a place and a security for his performance. By his
- share in this collective work he first is really _somebody_, gaining an
- effective existence and an objective value (_Manhood_). Last of all comes
- the finishing touch to this unity with objectivity: a unity which, while
- on its realist side it passes into the _inertia_ of deadening habit, on
- its idealist side gains freedom from the limited interests and
- entanglements of the outward present (_Old Age_).
- § 397. (2) Next we find the individual subject to a _real_ antithesis,
- leading it to seek and find _itself_ in _another_ individual. This—the
- _sexual relation_—on a physical basis, shows, on its one side,
- subjectivity remaining in an instinctive and emotional harmony of moral
- life and love, and not pushing these tendencies to an extreme _universal_
- phase, in purposes political, scientific or artistic; and on the other,
- shows an active half, where the individual is the vehicle of a struggle of
- universal and objective interests with the given conditions (both of his
- own existence and of that of the external world), carrying out these
- universal principles into a unity with the world which is his own work.
- The sexual tie acquires its moral and spiritual significance and function
- in the _family_.
- § 398. (3) When the individuality, or self-centralised being,
- distinguishes itself from its _mere_ being, this immediate judgment is the
- _waking_ of the soul, which confronts its self-absorbed natural life, in
- the first instance, as one natural quality and state confronts another
- state, viz. _sleep_.—The waking is not merely for the observer, or
- externally distinct from the sleep: it is itself the _judgment_ (primary
- partition) of the individual soul—which is self-existing only as it
- relates its self-existence to its mere existence, distinguishing itself
- from its still undifferentiated universality. The waking state includes
- generally all self-conscious and rational activity in which the mind
- realises its own distinct self.—Sleep is an invigoration of this
- activity—not as a merely negative rest from it, but as a return back from
- the world of specialisation, from dispersion into phases where it has
- grown hard and stiff,—a return into the general nature of subjectivity,
- which is the substance of those specialised energies and their absolute
- master.
- The distinction between sleep and waking is one of those _posers_, as they
- may be called, which are often addressed to philosophy:—Napoleon, e.g., on
- a visit to the University of Pavia, put this question to the class of
- ideology. The characterisation given in the section is abstract; it
- primarily treats waking merely as a natural fact, containing the mental
- element _implicite_ but not yet as invested with a special being of its
- own. If we are to speak more concretely of this distinction (in
- fundamentals it remains the same), we must take the self-existence of the
- individual soul in its higher aspects as the Ego of consciousness and as
- intelligent mind. The difficulty raised anent the distinction of the two
- states properly arises, only when we also take into account the dreams in
- sleep and describe these dreams, as well as the mental representations in
- the sober waking consciousness, under one and the same title of mental
- representations. Thus superficially classified as states of mental
- representation the two coincide, because we have lost sight of the
- difference; and in the case of any assignable distinction of waking
- consciousness, we can always return to the trivial remark that all this is
- nothing more than mental idea. But the concrete theory of the waking soul
- in its realised being views it as _consciousness_ and _intellect_: and the
- world of intelligent consciousness is something quite different from a
- picture of mere ideas and images. The latter are in the main only
- externally conjoined, in an unintelligent way, by the laws of the
- so-called _Association of Ideas_; though here and there of course logical
- principles may also be operative. But in the waking state man behaves
- essentially as a concrete ego, an intelligence: and because of this
- intelligence his sense-perception stands before him as a concrete totality
- of features in which each member, each point, takes up its place as at the
- same time determined through and with all the rest. Thus the facts
- embodied in his sensation are authenticated, not by his mere subjective
- representation and distinction of the facts as something external from the
- person, but by virtue of the concrete interconnexion in which each part
- stands with all parts of this complex. The waking state is the concrete
- consciousness of this mutual corroboration of each single factor of its
- content by all the others in the picture as perceived. The consciousness
- of this interdependence need not be explicit and distinct. Still this
- general setting to all sensations is implicitly present in the concrete
- feeling of self.—In order to see the difference of dreaming and waking we
- need only keep in view the Kantian distinction between subjectivity and
- objectivity of mental representation (the latter depending upon
- determination through categories): remembering, as already noted, that
- what is actually present in mind need not be therefore explicitly realised
- in consciousness, just as little as the exaltation of the intellectual
- sense to God need stand before consciousness in the shape of proofs of
- God’s existence, although, as before explained, these proofs only serve to
- express the net worth and content of that feeling.
- (γ) Sensibility(121).
- § 399. Sleep and waking are, primarily, it is true, not mere alterations,
- but _alternating_ conditions (a progression _in infinitum_). This is their
- formal and negative relationship: but in it the _affirmative_ relationship
- is also involved. In the self-certified existence of waking soul its mere
- existence is implicit as an “ideal” factor: the features which make up its
- sleeping nature, where they are implicitly as in their substance, are
- _found_ by the waking soul, in its own self, and, be it noted, for itself.
- The fact that these particulars, though as a mode of mind they are
- distinguished from the self-identity of our self-centred being, are yet
- simply contained in its simplicity, is what we call sensibility.
- § 400. Sensibility (feeling) is the form of the dull stirring, the
- inarticulate breathing, of the spirit through its unconscious and
- unintelligent individuality, where every definite feature is still
- “immediate,”—neither specially developed in its content nor set in
- distinction as objective to subject, but treated as belonging to its most
- special, its natural peculiarity. The content of sensation is thus limited
- and transient, belonging as it does to natural, immediate being,—to what
- is therefore qualitative and finite.
- _Everything is in sensation_ (feeling): if you will, everything that
- emerges in conscious intelligence and in reason has its source and origin
- in sensation; for source and origin just means the first immediate manner
- in which a thing appears. Let it not be enough to have principles and
- religion only in the head: they must also be in the heart, in the feeling.
- What we merely have in the head is in consciousness, in a general way: the
- facts of it are objective—set over against consciousness, so that as it is
- put in me (my abstract ego) it can also be kept away and apart from me
- (from my concrete subjectivity). But if put in the feeling, the fact is a
- mode of my individuality, however crude that individuality be in such a
- form: it is thus treated as my _very own_. My own is something inseparate
- from the actual concrete self: and this immediate unity of the soul with
- its underlying self in all its definite content is just this
- inseparability; which however yet falls short of the ego of developed
- consciousness, and still more of the freedom of rational mind-life. It is
- with a quite different intensity and permanency that the will, the
- conscience, and the character, are our very own, than can ever be true of
- feeling and of the group of feelings (the heart): and this we need no
- philosophy to tell us. No doubt it is correct to say that above everything
- the _heart_ must be good. But feeling and heart is not the form by which
- anything is legitimated as religious, moral, true, just, &c., and an
- appeal to heart and feeling either means nothing or means something bad.
- This should hardly need enforcing. Can any experience be more trite than
- that feelings and hearts are also bad, evil, godless, mean, &c.? That the
- heart is the source only of such feelings is stated in the words: “From
- the heart proceed evil thoughts, murder, adultery, fornication, blasphemy,
- &c.” In such times when “scientific” theology and philosophy make the
- heart and feeling the criterion of what is good, moral, and religious, it
- is necessary to remind them of these trite experiences; just as it is
- nowadays necessary to repeat that thinking is the characteristic property
- by which man is distinguished from the beasts, and that he has feeling in
- common with them.
- § 401. What the sentient soul finds within it is, on one hand, the
- naturally immediate, as “ideally” in it and made its own. On the other
- hand and conversely, what originally belongs to the central individuality
- (which as further deepened and enlarged is the conscious ego and free
- mind) get the features of the natural corporeity, and is so felt. In this
- way we have two spheres of feeling. One, where what at first is a
- corporeal affection (e.g. of the eye or of any bodily part whatever) is
- made feeling (sensation) by being driven inward, memorised in the soul’s
- self-centred part. Another, where affections originating in the mind and
- belonging to it, are in order to be felt, and to be as if found, invested
- with corporeity. Thus the mode or affection gets a place in the subject:
- it is felt in the soul. The detailed specification of the former branch of
- sensibility is seen in the system of the senses. But the other or inwardly
- originated modes of feeling no less necessarily systematise themselves;
- and their corporisation, as put in the living and concretely developed
- natural being, works itself out, following the special character of the
- mental mode, in a special system of bodily organs.
- Sensibility in general is the healthy fellowship of the individual mind in
- the life of its bodily part. The senses form the simple system of
- corporeity specified. (_a_) The “ideal” side of physical things breaks up
- into two—because in it, as immediate and not yet subjective ideality,
- distinction appears as mere variety—the senses of definite _light_, §
- 287—and of _sound_, § 300. The “real” aspect similarly is with its
- difference double: (_b_) the senses of smell and taste, §§ 321, 322; (_c_)
- the sense of solid reality, of heavy matter, of heat and shape. Around the
- centre of the sentient individuality these specifications arrange
- themselves more simply than when they are developed in the natural
- corporeity.
- The system by which the internal sensation comes to give itself specific
- bodily forms would deserve to be treated in detail in a peculiar science—a
- _psychical physiology_. Somewhat pointing to such a system is implied in
- the feeling of the appropriateness or inappropriateness of an immediate
- sensation to the persistent tone of internal sensibility (the pleasant and
- unpleasant): as also in the distinct parallelism which underlies the
- symbolical employment of sensations, e.g. of colours, tones, smells. But
- the most interesting side of a psychical physiology would lie in studying
- not the mere sympathy, but more definitely the bodily form adopted by
- certain mental modifications, especially the passions or emotions. We
- should have, e.g., to explain the line of connexion by which anger and
- courage are felt in the breast, the blood, the “irritable” system, just as
- thinking and mental occupation are felt in the head, the centre of the
- ’sensible’ system. We should want a more satisfactory explanation than
- hitherto of the most familiar connexions by which tears, and voice in
- general, with its varieties of language, laughter, sighs, with many other
- specialisations lying in the line of pathognomy and physiognomy, are
- formed from their mental source. In physiology the viscera and the organs
- are treated merely as parts subservient to the animal organism; but they
- form at the same time a physical system for the expression of mental
- states, and in this way they get quite another interpretation.
- § 402. Sensations, just because they are immediate and are found existing,
- are single and transient aspects of psychic life,—alterations in the
- substantiality of the soul, set in its self-centred life, with which that
- substance is one. But this self-centred being is not merely a formal
- factor of sensation: the soul is virtually a reflected totality of
- sensations—it feels _in itself_ the total substantiality which it
- _virtually_ is—it is a soul which feels.
- In the usage of ordinary language, sensation and feeling are not clearly
- distinguished: still we do not speak of the sensation,—but of the feeling
- (sense) of right, of self; sentimentality (sensibility) is connected with
- sensation: we may therefore say sensation emphasises rather the side of
- passivity—the fact that we find ourselves feeling, i.e. the immediacy of
- mode in feeling—whereas feeling at the same time rather notes the fact
- that it is _we ourselves_ who feel.
- (b) The Feeling Soul.—(Soul as Sentiency.)(122)
- § 403. The feeling or sentient individual is the simple “ideality” or
- subjective side of sensation. What it has to do, therefore, is to raise
- its substantiality, its merely virtual filling-up, to the character of
- subjectivity, to take possession of it, to realise its mastery over its
- own. As sentient, the soul is no longer a mere natural, but an inward,
- individuality: the individuality which in the merely substantial totality
- was only formal to it has to be liberated and made independent.
- Nowhere so much as in the case of the soul (and still more of the mind) if
- we are to understand it, must that feature of “ideality” be kept in view,
- which represents it as the _negation_ of the real, but a negation, where
- the real is put past, virtually retained, although it does not _exist_.
- The feature is one with which we are familiar in regard to our mental
- ideas or to memory. Every individual is an infinite treasury of
- sensations, ideas, acquired lore, thoughts, &c.; and yet the ego is one
- and uncompounded, a deep featureless characterless mine, in which all this
- is stored up, without existing. It is only when _I_ call to mind _an_
- idea, that I bring it out of that interior to existence before
- consciousness. Sometimes, in sickness, ideas and information, supposed to
- have been forgotten years ago, because for so long they had not been
- brought into consciousness, once more come to light. They were not in our
- possession, nor by such reproduction as occurs in sickness do they for the
- future come into our possession; and yet they were in us and continue to
- be in us still. Thus a person can never know how much of things he once
- learned he really has in him, should he have once forgotten them: they
- belong not to his actuality or subjectivity as such, but only to his
- implicit self. And under all the superstructure of specialised and
- instrumental consciousness that may subsequently be added to it, the
- individuality always remains this single-souled inner life. At the present
- stage this singleness is, primarily, to be defined as one of feeling—as
- embracing the corporeal in itself: thus denying the view that this body is
- something material, with parts outside parts and outside the soul. Just as
- the number and variety of mental representations is no argument for an
- extended and real multeity in the ego; so the “real” outness of parts in
- the body has no truth for the sentient soul. As sentient, the soul is
- characterised as immediate, and so as natural and corporeal: but the
- outness of parts and sensible multiplicity of this corporeal counts for
- the soul (as it counts for the intelligible unity) not as anything real,
- and therefore not as a barrier: the soul is this intelligible unity _in
- existence_,—the existent speculative principle. Thus in the body it is one
- simple, omnipresent unity. As to the representative faculty the body is
- but _one_ representation, and the infinite variety of its material
- structure and organisation is reduced to the _simplicity_ of one definite
- conception: so in the sentient soul, the corporeity, and all that outness
- of parts to parts which belongs to it, is reduced to _ideality_ (the
- _truth_ of the natural multiplicity). The soul is virtually the totality
- of nature: as an individual soul it is a monad: it is itself the
- explicitly put totality of its particular world,—that world being included
- in it and filling it up; and to that world it stands but as to itself.
- § 404. As _individual_, the soul is exclusive and always exclusive: any
- difference there is, it brings within itself. What is differentiated from
- it is as yet no external object (as in consciousness), but only the
- aspects of its own sentient totality, &c. In this partition (judgment) of
- itself it is always subject: its object is its substance, which is at the
- same time its predicate. This _substance_ is still the content of its
- natural life, but turned into the content of the individual
- sensation-laden soul; yet as the soul is in that content still particular,
- the content is its particular world, so far as that is, in an implicit
- mode, included in the ideality of the subject.
- By itself, this stage of mind is the stage of its darkness: its features
- are not developed to conscious and intelligent content: so far it is
- formal and only formal. It acquires a peculiar interest in cases where it
- is as a _form_ and appears as a special _state_ of mind (§ 350), to which
- the soul, which has already advanced to consciousness and intelligence,
- may again sink down. But when a truer phase of mind thus exists in a more
- subordinate and abstract one, it implies a want of adaptation, which is
- _disease_. In the present stage we must treat, first, of the abstract
- psychical modifications by themselves, secondly, as morbid states of mind:
- the latter being only explicable by means of the former.
- (α) The Feeling Soul in its Immediacy.
- § 405. (αα) Though the sensitive individuality is undoubtedly a monadic
- individual, it is because immediate, not yet as _its self_ not a true
- subject reflected into itself, and is therefore passive. Hence the
- individuality of its true self is a different subject from it—a subject
- which may even exist as another individual. By the self-hood of the latter
- it—a substance, which is only a non-independent predicate—is then set in
- vibration and controlled without the least resistance on its part. This
- other subject by which it is so controlled may be called its _genius_.
- In the ordinary course of nature this is the condition of the child in its
- mother’s womb:—a condition neither merely bodily nor merely mental, but
- psychical—a correlation of soul to soul. Here are two individuals, yet in
- undivided psychic unity: the one as yet no _self_, as yet nothing
- impenetrable, incapable of resistance: the other is its actuating subject,
- the _single_ self of the two. The mother is the _genius_ of the child; for
- by genius we commonly mean the total mental self-hood, as it has existence
- of its own, and constitutes the subjective substantiality of some one else
- who is only externally treated as an individual and has only a nominal
- independence. The underlying essence of the genius is the sum total of
- existence, of life, and of character, not as a mere possibility, or
- capacity, or virtuality, but as efficiency and realised activity, as
- concrete subjectivity.
- If we look only to the spatial and material aspects of the child’s
- existence as an embryo in its special integuments, and as connected with
- the mother by means of umbilical cord, placenta, &c., all that is
- presented to the senses and reflection are certain anatomical and
- physiological facts—externalities and instrumentalities in the sensible
- and material which are insignificant as regards the main point, the
- psychical relationship. What ought to be noted as regards this psychical
- tie are not merely the striking effects communicated to and stamped upon
- the child by violent emotions, injuries, &c. of the mother, but the whole
- psychical _judgment_ (partition) of the underlying nature, by which the
- female (like the monocotyledons among vegetables) can suffer disruption in
- twain, so that the child has not merely got _communicated_ to it, but has
- originally received morbid dispositions as well as other pre-dispositions
- of shape, temper, character, talent, idiosyncrasies, &c.
- Sporadic examples and traces of this _magic_ tie appear elsewhere in the
- range of self-possessed conscious life, say between friends, especially
- female friends with delicate nerves (a tie which may go so far as to show
- “magnetic” phenomena), between husband and wife and between members of the
- same family.
- The total sensitivity has its self here in a separate subjectivity, which,
- in the case cited of this sentient life in the ordinary course of nature,
- is visibly present as another and a different individual. But this
- sensitive totality is meant to elevate its self-hood out of itself to
- subjectivity in one and the same individual: which is then its indwelling
- consciousness, self-possessed, intelligent, and reasonable. For such a
- consciousness the merely sentient life serves as an underlying and only
- implicitly existent material; and the self-possessed subjectivity is the
- rational, self-conscious, controlling genius thereof. But this sensitive
- nucleus includes not merely the purely unconscious, congenital disposition
- and temperament, but within its enveloping simplicity it acquires and
- retains also (in habit, as to which see later) all further ties and
- essential relationships, fortunes, principles—everything in short
- belonging to the character, and in whose elaboration self-conscious
- activity has most effectively participated. The sensitivity is thus a soul
- in which the whole mental life is condensed. The total individual under
- this concentrated aspect is distinct from the existing and actual play of
- his consciousness, his secular ideas, developed interests, inclinations,
- &c. As contrasted with this looser aggregate of means and methods the more
- intensive form of individuality is termed the genius, whose decision is
- ultimate whatever may be the show of reasons, intentions, means, of which
- the more public consciousness is so liberal. This concentrated
- individuality also reveals itself under the aspect of what is called the
- heart and soul of feeling. A man is said to be heartless and unfeeling
- when he looks at things with self-possession and acts according to his
- permanent purposes, be they great substantial aims or petty and unjust
- interests: a good-hearted man, on the other hand, means rather one who is
- at the mercy of his individual sentiment, even when it is of narrow range
- and is wholly made up of particularities. Of such good nature or goodness
- of heart it may be said that it is less the genius itself than the
- _indulgere genio_.
- § 406. (ββ) The sensitive life, when it becomes a _form_ or _state_ of the
- self-conscious, educated, self-possessed human being is a disease. The
- individual in such a morbid state stands in direct contact with the
- concrete contents of his own self, whilst he keeps his self-possessed
- consciousness of self and of the causal order of things apart as a
- distinct state of mind. This morbid condition is seen in _magnetic
- somnambulism_ and cognate states.
- In this summary encyclopaedic account it is impossible to supply a
- demonstration of what the paragraph states as the nature of the remarkable
- condition produced chiefly by animal magnetism—to show, in other words,
- that it is in harmony with the facts. To that end the phenomena, so
- complex in their nature and so very different one from another, would have
- first of all to be brought under their general points of view. The facts,
- it might seem, first of all call for verification. But such a verification
- would, it must be added, be superfluous for those on whose account it was
- called for: for they facilitate the inquiry for themselves by declaring
- the narratives—infinitely numerous though they be and accredited by the
- education and character of the witnesses—to be mere deception and
- imposture. The _a priori_ conceptions of these inquirers are so rooted
- that no testimony can avail against them, and they have even denied what
- they had seen with their own eyes. In order to believe in this department
- even what one sees with these eyes, and still more to understand it, the
- first requisite is not to be in bondage to the hard and fast categories of
- the practical intellect. The chief points on which the discussion turns
- may here be given:
- (α) To the _concrete_ existence of the individual belongs the aggregate of
- his fundamental _interests_, both the essential and the particular
- empirical ties which connect him with other men and the world at large.
- This totality forms _his_ actuality, in the sense that it lies in fact
- immanent in him; it has already been called his _genius_. This genius is
- not the free mind which wills and thinks: the form of sensitivity, in
- which the individual here appears immersed, is, on the contrary, a
- surrender of his self-possessed intelligent existence. The first
- conclusion to which these considerations lead, with reference to the
- contents of consciousness in the somnambulist stage, is that it is only
- the range of his individually moulded world (of his private interests and
- narrow relationships) which appear there. Scientific theories and
- philosophic conceptions or general truths require a different
- soil,—require an intelligence which has risen out of the inarticulate mass
- of mere sensitivity to free consciousness. It is foolish therefore to
- expect revelations about the higher ideas from the somnambulist state.
- (β) Where a human being’s senses and intellect are sound, he is fully and
- intelligently alive to that reality of his which gives concrete filling to
- his individuality: but he is awake to it in the form of interconnexion
- between himself and the features of that reality conceived as an external
- and a separate world, and he is aware that this world is in itself also a
- complex of interconnexions of a practically intelligible kind. In his
- subjective ideas and plans he has also before him this causally connected
- scheme of things he calls his world and the series of means which bring
- his ideas and his purposes into adjustment with the objective existences,
- which are also means and ends to each other. At the same time, this world
- which is outside him has its threads in him to such a degree that it is
- these threads which make him what he really is: he too would become
- extinct if these externalities were to disappear, unless by the aid of
- religion, subjective reason, and character, he is in a remarkable degree
- self-supporting and independent of them. But, then, in the latter case he
- is less susceptible of the psychical state here spoken of.—As an
- illustration of that identity with the surroundings may be noted the
- effect produced by the death of beloved relatives, friends, &c. on those
- left behind, so that the one dies or pines away with the loss of the
- other. (Thus Cato, after the downfall of the Roman republic, could live no
- longer: his inner reality was neither wider than higher than it.) Compare
- home-sickness, and the like.
- (γ) But when all that occupies the waking consciousness, the world outside
- it and its relationship to that world is under a veil, and the soul is
- thus sunk in sleep (in magnetic sleep, in catalepsy, and other diseases,
- e.g. those connected with female development, or at the approach of death,
- &c.), then that _immanent actuality_ of the individual remains the same
- substantial total as before, but now as a purely sensitive life with an
- inward vision and an inward consciousness. And because it is the adult,
- formed, and developed consciousness which is degraded into this state of
- sensitivity, it retains along with its content a certain nominal
- self-hood, a formal vision and awareness, which however does not go so far
- as the conscious judgment or discernment by which its contents, when it is
- healthy and awake, exist for it as an outward objectivity. The individual
- is thus a monad which is inwardly aware of its actuality—a genius which
- beholds itself. The characteristic point in such knowledge is that the
- very same facts (which for the healthy consciousness are an objective
- practical reality, and to know which, in its sober moods, it needs the
- intelligent chain of means and conditions in all their real expansion) are
- now immediately known and perceived in this immanence. This perception is
- a sort of _clairvoyance_; for it is a consciousness living in the
- undivided substantiality of the genius, and finding itself in the very
- heart of the interconnexion, and so can dispense with the series of
- conditions, external one to another, which lead up to the
- result,—conditions which cool reflection has in succession to traverse and
- in so doing feels the limits of its own individual externality. But such
- clairvoyance—just because its dim and turbid vision does not present the
- facts in a rational interconnexion—is for that very reason at the mercy of
- every private contingency of feeling and fancy, &c.—not to mention that
- foreign _suggestions_ (see later) intrude into its vision. It is thus
- impossible to make out whether what the clairvoyants really see
- preponderates over what they deceive themselves in.—But it is absurd to
- treat this visionary state as a sublime mental phase and as a truer state,
- capable of conveying general truths(123).
- (δ) An essential feature of this sensitivity, with its absence of
- intelligent and volitional personality, is this, that it is a state of
- passivity, like that of the child in the womb. The patient in this
- condition is accordingly made, and continues to be, subject to the power
- of another person, the magnetiser; so that when the two are thus in
- psychical _rapport_, the selfless individual, not really a “person,” has
- for his subjective consciousness the consciousness of the other. This
- latter self-possessed individual is thus the effective subjective soul of
- the former, and the genius which may even supply him with a train of
- ideas. That the somnambulist perceives in himself tastes and smells which
- are present in the person with whom he stands _en rapport_, and that he is
- aware of the other inner ideas and present perceptions of the latter as if
- they were his own, shows the substantial identity which the soul (which
- even in its concreteness is also truly immaterial) is capable of holding
- with another. When the substance of both is thus made one, there is only
- one subjectivity of consciousness: the patient has a sort of
- individuality, but it is empty, not on the spot, not actual: and this
- nominal self accordingly derives its whole stock of ideas from the
- sensations and ideas of the other, in whom it sees, smells, tastes, reads,
- and hears. It is further to be noted on this point that the somnambulist
- is thus brought into _rapport_ with two genii and a twofold set of ideas,
- his own and that of the magnetiser. But it is impossible to say precisely
- which sensations and which visions he, in this nominal perception,
- receives, beholds and brings to knowledge from his own inward self, and
- which from the suggestions of the person with whom he stands in relation.
- This uncertainty may be the source of many deceptions, and accounts among
- other things for the diversity that inevitably shows itself among
- somnambulists from different countries and under _rapport_ with persons of
- different education, as regards their views on morbid states and the
- methods of cure, or medicines for them, as well as on scientific and
- intellectual topics.
- (ε) As in this sensitive substantiality there is no contrast to external
- objectivity, so within itself the subject is so entirely one that all
- varieties of sensation have disappeared, and hence, when the activity of
- the sense-organs is asleep, the “common sense,” or “general feeling”
- specifies itself to several functions; one sees and hears with the
- fingers, and especially with the pit of the stomach, &c.
- To comprehend a thing means in the language of practical intelligence to
- be able to trace the series of means intervening between a phenomenon and
- some other existence on which it depends,—to discover what is called the
- ordinary course of nature, in compliance with the laws and relations of
- the intellect, e.g. causality, reasons, &c. The purely sensitive life, on
- the contrary, even when it retains that mere nominal consciousness, as in
- the morbid state alluded to, is just this form of immediacy, without any
- distinctions between subjective and objective, between intelligent
- personality and objective world, and without the aforementioned finite
- ties between them. Hence to understand this intimate conjunction, which,
- though all-embracing, is without any definite points of attachment, is
- impossible, so long as we assume independent personalities, independent
- one of another and of the objective world which is their content—so long
- as we assume the absolute spatial and material externality of one part of
- being to another.
- (β) Self-feeling (Sense of Self)(124).
- § 407. (αα) The sensitive totality is, in its capacity of individual,
- essentially the tendency to distinguish itself in itself, and to wake up
- to the _judgment in itself_, in virtue of which it has _particular_
- feelings and stands as a _subject_ in respect of these aspects of itself.
- The subject as such gives these feelings a place as _its own_ in itself.
- In these private and personal sensations it is immersed, and at the same
- time, because of the “ideality” of the particulars, it combines itself in
- them with itself as a subjective unit. In this way it is _self-feeling_,
- and is so at the same time only in the _particular feeling_.
- § 408. (ββ) In consequence of the immediacy, which still marks the
- self-feeling, i.e. in consequence of the element of corporeality which is
- still undetached from the mental life, and as the feeling too is itself
- particular and bound up with a special corporeal form, it follows that
- although the subject has been brought to acquire intelligent
- consciousness, it is still susceptible of disease, so far as to remain
- fast in a _special_ phase of its self-feeling, unable to refine it to
- “ideality” and get the better of it. The fully-furnished self of
- intelligent consciousness is a conscious subject, which is consistent in
- itself according to an order and behaviour which follows from its
- individual position and its connexion with the external world, which is no
- less a world of law. But when it is engrossed with a single phase of
- feeling, it fails to assign that phase its proper place and due
- subordination in the individual system of the world which a conscious
- subject is. In this way the subject finds itself in contradiction between
- the totality systematised in its consciousness, and the single phase or
- fixed idea which is not reduced to its proper place and rank. This is
- Insanity or mental Derangement.
- In considering insanity we must, as in other cases, anticipate the
- full-grown and intelligent conscious subject, which is at the same time
- the _natural_ self of _self-feeling_. In such a phase the self can be
- liable to the contradiction between its own free subjectivity and a
- particularity which, instead of being “idealised” in the former, remains
- as a fixed element in self-feeling. Mind as such is free, and therefore
- not susceptible of this malady. But in older metaphysics mind was treated
- as a soul, as a thing; and it is only as a thing, i.e. as something
- natural and existent, that it is liable to insanity—the settled fixture of
- some finite element in it. Insanity is therefore a psychical disease, i.e.
- a disease of body and mind alike: the commencement may appear to start
- from one more than other, and so also may the cure.
- The self-possessed and healthy subject has an active and present
- consciousness of the ordered whole of his individual world, into the
- system of which he subsumes each special content of sensation, idea,
- desire, inclination, &c., as it arises, so as to insert them in their
- proper place. He is the _dominant genius_ over these particularities.
- Between this and insanity the difference is like that between waking and
- dreaming: only that in insanity the dream falls within the waking limits,
- and so makes part of the actual self-feeling. Error and that sort of thing
- is a proposition consistently admitted to a place in the objective
- interconnexion of things. In the concrete, however, it is often difficult
- to say where it begins to become derangement. A violent, but groundless
- and senseless outburst of hatred, &c., may, in contrast to a presupposed
- higher self-possession and stability of character, make its victim seem to
- be beside himself with frenzy. But the main point in derangement is the
- contradiction which a feeling with a fixed corporeal embodiment sets up
- against the whole mass of adjustments forming the concrete consciousness.
- The mind which is in a condition of mere _being_, and where such being is
- not rendered fluid in its consciousness, is diseased. The contents which
- are set free in this reversion to mere nature are the self-seeking
- affections of the heart, such as vanity, pride, and the rest of the
- passions—fancies and hopes—merely personal love and hatred. When the
- influence of self-possession and of general principles, moral and
- theoretical, is relaxed, and ceases to keep the natural temper under lock
- and key, the earthly elements are set free—that evil which is always
- latent in the heart, because the heart as immediate is natural and
- selfish. It is the evil genius of man which gains the upper hand in
- insanity, but in distinction from and contrast to the better and more
- intelligent part, which is there also. Hence this state is mental
- derangement and distress. The right psychical treatment therefore keeps in
- view the truth that insanity is not an abstract _loss_ of reason (neither
- in the point of intelligence nor of will and its responsibility), but only
- derangement, only a contradiction in a still subsisting reason;—just as
- physical disease is not an abstract, i.e. mere and total, loss of health
- (if it were that, it would be death), but a contradiction in it. This
- humane treatment, no less benevolent than reasonable (the services of
- Pinel towards which deserve the highest acknowledgment), presupposes the
- patient’s rationality, and in that assumption has the sound basis for
- dealing with him on this side—just as in the case of bodily disease the
- physician bases his treatment on the vitality which as such still contains
- health.
- (γ) Habit(125).
- § 409. Self-feeling, immersed in the detail of the feelings (in simple
- sensations, and also desires, instincts, passions, and their
- gratification), is undistinguished from them. But in the self there is
- latent a simple self-relation of ideality, a nominal universality (which
- is the truth of these details): and as so universal, the self is to be
- stamped upon, and made appear in, this life of feeling, yet so as to
- distinguish itself from the particular details, and be a realised
- universality. But this universality is not the full and sterling truth of
- the specific feelings and desires; what they specifically contain is as
- yet left out of account. And so too the particularity is, as now regarded,
- equally formal; it counts only as the _particular being_ or immediacy of
- the soul in opposition to its equally formal and abstract realisation.
- This particular being of the soul is the factor of its corporeity; here we
- have it breaking with this corporeity, distinguishing it from
- itself,—itself a _simple_ being,—and becoming the “ideal,” subjective
- substantiality of it,—just as in its latent notion (§ 359) it was the
- substance, and the mere substance, of it.
- But this abstract realisation of the soul in its corporeal vehicle is not
- yet the self—not the existence of the universal which is for the
- universal. It is the corporeity reduced to its mere _ideality_; and so far
- only does corporeity belong to the soul as such. That is to say, as space
- and time—the abstract one-outside-another, as, in short, empty space and
- empty time—are only subjective form—pure act of intuition; so that pure
- being (which through the supersession in it of the particularity of the
- corporeity, or of the immediate corporeity as such has realised itself) is
- mere intuition and no more, lacking consciousness, but the basis of
- consciousness. And consciousness it becomes, when the corporeity, of which
- it is the subjective substance, and which still continues to exist, and
- that as a barrier for it, has been absorbed by it, and it has been
- invested with the character of self-centred subject.
- § 410. The soul’s making itself an abstract universal being, and reducing
- the particulars of feelings (and of consciousness) to a mere feature of
- its being is Habit. In this manner the soul has the contents in
- possession, and contains them in such manner that in these features it is
- not as sentient, nor does it stand in relationship with them as
- distinguishing itself from them, nor is absorbed in them, but has them and
- moves in them, without feeling or consciousness of the fact. The soul is
- freed from them, so far as it is not interested in or occupied with them:
- and whilst existing in these forms as its possession, it is at the same
- time open to be otherwise occupied and engaged—say with feeling and with
- mental consciousness in general.
- This process of building up the particular and corporeal expressions of
- feeling into the being of the soul appears as a _repetition_ of them, and
- the generation of habit as _practice_. For, this being of the soul, if in
- respect of the natural particular phase it be called an abstract
- universality to which the former is transmuted, is a reflexive
- universality (§ 175); i.e. the one and the same, that recurs in a series
- of units of sensation, is reduced to unity, and this abstract unity
- expressly stated.
- Habit, like memory, is a difficult point in mental organisation: habit is
- the mechanism of self-feeling, as memory is the mechanism of intelligence.
- The natural qualities and alterations of age, sleep and waking, are
- “immediately” natural: habit, on the contrary, is the mode of feeling (as
- well as intelligence, will, &c., so far as they belong to self-feeling)
- made into a natural and mechanical existence. Habit is rightly called a
- second nature; nature, because it is an immediate being of the soul; a
- second nature, because it is an immediacy created by the soul, impressing
- and moulding the corporeality which enters into the modes of feeling as
- such and into the representations and volitions so far as they have taken
- corporeal form (§ 401).
- In habit the human being’s mode of existence is “natural,” and for that
- reason not free; but still free, so far as the merely natural phase of
- feeling is by habit reduced to a mere being of _his_, and he is no longer
- involuntarily attracted or repelled by it, and so no longer interested,
- occupied, or dependent in regard to it. The want of freedom in habit is
- partly merely formal, as habit merely attaches to the being of the soul;
- partly only relative, so far as it strictly speaking arises only in the
- case of bad habits, or so far as a habit is opposed by another purpose:
- whereas the habit of right and goodness is an embodiment of liberty. The
- main point about Habit is that by its means man gets emancipated from the
- feelings, even in being affected by them. The different forms of this may
- be described as follows: (α) The _immediate_ feeling is negated and
- treated as indifferent. One who gets inured against external sensations
- (frost, heat, weariness of the limbs, &c., sweet tastes, &c.), and who
- hardens the heart against misfortune, acquires a strength which consists
- in this, that although the frost, &c.—or the misfortune—is felt, the
- affection is deposed to a mere externality and immediacy; the universal
- psychical life keeps its own abstract independence in it, and the
- self-feeling as such, consciousness, reflection, and any other purposes
- and activity, are no longer bothered with it. (β) There is indifference
- towards the satisfaction: the desires and impulses are by the _habit_ of
- their satisfaction deadened. This is the rational liberation from them;
- whereas monastic renunciation and forcible interference do not free from
- them, nor are they in conception rational. Of course in all this it is
- assumed that the impulses are kept as the finite modes they naturally are,
- and that they, like their satisfaction, are subordinated as partial
- factors to the reasonable will. (γ) In habit regarded as _aptitude_, or
- skill, not merely has the abstract psychical life to be kept intact _per
- se_, but it has to be imposed as a subjective aim, to be made a power in
- the bodily part, which is rendered subject and thoroughly pervious to it.
- Conceived as having the inward purpose of the subjective soul thus imposed
- upon it, the body is treated as an immediate externality and a barrier.
- Thus comes out the more decided rupture between the soul as simple
- self-concentration, and its earlier naturalness and immediacy; it has lost
- its original and immediate identity with the bodily nature, and as
- external has first to be reduced to that position. Specific feelings can
- only get bodily shape in a perfectly specific way (§ 401); and the
- immediate portion of body is a particular possibility for a specific aim
- (a particular aspect of its differentiated structure, a particular organ
- of its organic system). To mould such an aim in the organic body is to
- bring out and express the “ideality” which is implicit in matter always,
- and especially so in the specific bodily part, and thus to enable the
- soul, under its volitional and conceptual characters, to exist as
- substance in its corporeity. In this way an aptitude shows the corporeity
- rendered completely pervious, made into an instrument, so that when the
- conception (e.g. a series of musical notes) is in me, then without
- resistance and with ease the body gives them correct utterance.
- The form of habit applies to all kinds and grades of mental action. The
- most external of them, i.e. the spatial direction of an individual, viz.
- his upright posture, has been by will made a habit—a position taken
- without adjustment and without consciousness—which continues to be an
- affair of his persistent will; for the man stands only because and in so
- far as he wills to stand, and only so long as he wills it without
- consciousness. Similarly our eyesight is the concrete habit which, without
- an express adjustment, combines in a single act the several modifications
- of sensation, consciousness, intuition, intelligence, &c., which make it
- up. Thinking, too, however free and active in its own pure element it
- becomes, no less requires habit and familiarity (this impromptuity or form
- of immediacy), by which it is the property of my single self where I can
- freely and in all directions range. It is through this habit that I come
- to realise my _existence_ as a thinking being. Even here, in this
- spontaneity of self-centred thought, there is a partnership of soul and
- body (hence, want of habit and too-long-continued thinking cause
- headache); habit diminishes this feeling, by making the natural function
- an immediacy of the soul. Habit on an ampler scale, and carried out in the
- strictly intellectual range, is recollection and memory, whereof we shall
- speak later.
- Habit is often spoken of disparagingly and called lifeless, casual and
- particular. And it is true that the form of habit, like any other, is open
- to anything we chance to put into it; and it is habit of living which
- brings on death, or, if quite abstract, is death itself: and yet habit is
- indispensable for the _existence_ of all intellectual life in the
- individual, enabling the subject to be a concrete immediacy, an “ideality”
- of soul—enabling the matter of consciousness, religious, moral, &c., to be
- his as _this_ self, _this_ soul, and no other, and be neither a mere
- latent possibility, nor a transient emotion or idea, nor an abstract
- inwardness, cut off from action and reality, but part and parcel of his
- being. In scientific studies of the soul and the mind, habit is usually
- passed over—either as something contemptible—or rather for the further
- reason that it is one of the most difficult questions of psychology.
- (c) The Actual Soul.(126)
- § 411. The Soul, when its corporeity has been moulded and made thoroughly
- its own, finds itself there a _single_ subject; and the corporeity is an
- externality which stands as a predicate, in being related to which, it is
- related to itself. This externality, in other words, represents not
- itself, but the soul, of which it is the _sign_. In this identity of
- interior and exterior, the latter subject to the former, the soul is
- _actual_: in its corporeity it has its free shape, in which it _feels
- itself_ and makes _itself felt_, and which as the Soul’s work of art has
- _human_ pathognomic and physiognomic expression.
- Under the head of human expression are included, e.g., the upright figure
- in general, and the formation of the limbs, especially the hand, as the
- absolute instrument, of the mouth—laughter, weeping, &c., and the note of
- mentality diffused over the whole, which at once announces the body at the
- externality of a higher nature. This note is so slight, indefinite, and
- inexpressible a modification, because the figure in its externality is
- something immediate and natural, and can therefore only be an indefinite
- and quite imperfect sign for the mind, unable to represent it in its
- actual universality. Seen from the animal world, the human figure is the
- supreme phase in which mind makes an appearance. But for the mind it is
- only its first appearance, while language is its perfect expression. And
- the human figure, though its proximate phase of existence, is at the same
- time in its physiognomic and pathognomic quality something contingent to
- it. To try to raise physiognomy and above all cranioscopy (phrenology) to
- the rank of sciences, was therefore one of the vainest fancies, still
- vainer than a _signatura rerum_, which supposed the shape of a plant to
- afford indication of its medicinal virtue.
- § 412. Implicitly the soul shows the untruth and unreality of matter; for
- the soul, in its concentrated self, cuts itself off from its immediate
- being, placing the latter over against it as a corporeity incapable of
- offering resistance to its moulding influence. The soul, thus setting in
- opposition its being to its (conscious) self, absorbing it, and making it
- its own, has lost the meaning of mere soul, or the “immediacy” of mind.
- The actual soul with its sensation and its concrete self-feeling turned
- into habit, has implicitly realised the ’ideality’ of its qualities; in
- this externality it has recollected and inwardised itself, and is infinite
- self-relation. This free universality thus made explicit shows the soul
- awaking to the higher stage of the ego, or abstract universality in so far
- as it is _for_ the abstract universality. In this way it gains the
- position of thinker and subject—specially a subject of the judgment in
- which the ego excludes from itself the sum total of its merely natural
- features as an object, a world external to it,—but with such respect to
- that object that in it it is immediately reflected into itself. Thus soul
- rises to become _Consciousness_.
- Sub-Section B. Phenomenology Of Mind. Consciousness.
- § 413. Consciousness constitutes the reflected or correlational grade of
- mind: the grade of mind as _appearance_. _Ego_ is infinite self-relation
- of mind, but as subjective or as self-certainty. The immediate identity of
- the natural soul has been raised to this pure “ideal” self-identity; and
- what the former _contained_ is for this self-subsistent reflection set
- forth as an _object_. The pure abstract freedom of mind lets go from it
- its specific qualities,—the soul’s natural life—to an equal freedom as an
- independent _object_. It is of this latter, as external to it, that the
- _ego_ is in the first instance aware (conscious), and as such it is
- Consciousness. Ego, as this absolute negativity, is implicitly the
- identity in the otherness: the _ego_ is itself that other and stretches
- over the object (as if that object were implicitly cancelled)—it is one
- side of the relationship and the whole relationship—the light, which
- manifests itself and something else too.
- § 414. The self-identity of the mind, thus first made explicit as the Ego,
- is only its abstract formal identity. As _soul_ it was under the phase of
- _substantial_ universality; now, as subjective reflection in itself, it is
- referred to this substantiality as to its negative, something dark and
- beyond it. Hence consciousness, like reciprocal dependence in general, is
- the contradiction between the independence of the two sides and their
- identity in which they are merged into one. The mind as ego is _essence_;
- but since reality, in the sphere of essence, is represented as in
- immediate being and at the same time as “ideal,” it is as consciousness
- only the _appearance_ (phenomenon) of mind.
- § 415. As the ego is by itself only a formal identity, the dialectical
- movement of its intelligible unity, i.e. the successive steps in further
- specification of consciousness, does not to it seem to be its own
- activity, but is implicit, and to the ego it seems an alteration of the
- object. Consciousness consequently appears differently modified according
- to the difference of the given object; and the gradual specification of
- consciousness appears as a variation in the characteristics of its
- objects. Ego, the subject of consciousness, is thinking: the logical
- process of modifying the object is what is identical in subject and
- object, their absolute interdependence, what makes the object the
- subject’s own.
- The Kantian philosophy may be most accurately described as having viewed
- the mind as consciousness, and as containing the propositions only of a
- _phenomenology_ (not of a _philosophy_) of mind. The Ego Kant regards as
- reference to something away and beyond (which in its abstract description
- is termed the thing-at-itself); and it is only from this finite point of
- view that he treats both intellect and will. Though in the notion of a
- power of _reflective_ judgment he touches upon the _Idea_ of mind—a
- subject-objectivity, an _intuitive intellect_, &c., and even the Idea of
- Nature, still this Idea is again deposed to an appearance, i.e. to a
- subjective maxim (§ 58). Reinhold may therefore be said to have correctly
- appreciated Kantism when he treated it as a theory of consciousness (under
- the name of “faculty of ideation”). Fichte kept to the same point of view:
- his non-ego is only something set over against the ego, only defined as in
- _consciousness_: it is made no more than an infinite “shock,” i.e. a
- thing-in-itself. Both systems therefore have clearly not reached the
- intelligible unity or the mind as it actually and essentially is, but only
- as it is in reference to something else.
- As against Spinozism, again, it is to be noted that the mind in the
- judgment by which it “constitutes” itself an ego (a free subject
- contrasted with its qualitative affection) has emerged from substance, and
- that the philosophy, which gives this judgment as the absolute
- characteristic of mind, has emerged from Spinozism.
- § 416. The aim of conscious mind is to make its appearance identical with
- its essence, to raise its _self-certainty to truth_. The _existence_ of
- mind in the stage of consciousness is finite, because it is merely a
- nominal self-relation, or mere certainty. The object is only abstractly
- characterised as _its_; in other words, in the object it is only as an
- abstract ego that the mind is reflected into itself: hence its existence
- there has still a content, which is not as its own.
- § 417. The grades of this elevation of certainty to truth are three in
- number: first (_a_) consciousness in general, with an object set against
- it; (_b_) self-consciousness, for which _ego_ is the object; (_c_) unity
- of consciousness and self-consciousness, where the mind sees itself
- embodied in the object and sees itself as implicitly and explicitly
- determinate, as Reason, the _notion_ of mind.
- (a) Consciousness Proper(127).
- (α) Sensuous consciousness.
- § 418. Consciousness is, first, _immediate_ consciousness, and its
- reference to the object accordingly the simple and underived certainty of
- it. The object similarly, being immediate, an existent, reflected in
- itself, is further characterised as immediately singular. This is
- sense-consciousness.
- Consciousness—as a case of correlation—comprises only the categories
- belonging to the abstract ego or formal thinking; and these it treats as
- features of the object (§ 415). Sense-consciousness therefore is aware of
- the object as an existent, a something, an existing thing, a singular, and
- so on. It appears as wealthiest in matter, but as poorest in thought. That
- wealth of matter is made out of sensations: they are the _material_ of
- consciousness (§ 414), the substantial and qualitative, what the soul in
- its anthropological sphere is and finds _in itself_. This material the ego
- (the reflection of the soul in itself) separates from itself, and puts it
- first under the category of being. Spatial and temporal Singularness,
- _here_ and _now_ (the terms by which in the Phenomenology of the Mind (W.
- II. p. 73), I described the object of sense-consciousness) strictly
- belongs to _intuition_. At present the object is at first to be viewed
- only in its correlation to _consciousness_, i.e. a something _external_ to
- it, and not yet as external on its own part, or as being beside and out of
- itself.
- § 419. The _sensible_ as somewhat becomes an _other_: the reflection in
- itself of this _somewhat_, the _thing_, has _many_ properties; and as a
- single (thing) in its immediacy has several _predicates_. The muchness of
- the sense-singular thus becomes a breadth—a variety of relations,
- reflectional attributes, and universalities. These are logical terms
- introduced by the thinking principle, i.e. in this case by the Ego, to
- describe the sensible. But the Ego as itself apparent sees in all this
- characterisation a change in the object; and self-consciousness, so
- construing the object, is sense-perception.
- (β) Sense-perception(128).
- § 420. Consciousness, having passed beyond the sensibility, wants to take
- the object in its truth, not as merely immediate, but as mediated,
- reflected in itself, and universal. Such an object is a combination of
- sense qualities with attributes of wider range by which thought defines
- concrete relations and connexions. Hence the identity of consciousness
- with the object passes from the abstract identity of “I am sure” to the
- definite identity of “I know, and am aware.”
- The particular grade of consciousness on which Kantism conceives the mind
- is perception: which is also the general point of view taken by ordinary
- consciousness, and more or less by the sciences. The sensuous certitudes
- of single apperceptions or observations form the starting-point: these are
- supposed to be elevated to truth, by being regarded in their bearings,
- reflected upon, and on the lines of definite categories turned at the same
- time into something necessary and universal, viz. _experiences_.
- § 421. This conjunction of individual and universal is admixture—the
- individual remains at the bottom hard and unaffected by the universal, to
- which however it is related. It is therefore a tissue of
- contradictions—between the single things of sense apperception, which form
- the alleged ground of general experience, and the universality which has a
- higher claim to be the essence and ground—between the individuality of a
- thing which, taken in its concrete content, constitutes its independence
- and the various properties which, free from this negative link and from
- one another, are independent universal _matters_ (§ 123). This
- contradiction of the finite which runs through all forms of the logical
- spheres turns out most concrete, when the somewhat is defined as _object_
- (§ 194 seqq.).
- (γ) The Intellect(129).
- § 422. The proximate _truth_ of perception is that it is the object which
- is an _appearance_, and that the object’s reflection in self is on the
- contrary a self-subsistent inward and universal. The consciousness of such
- an object is _intellect_. This inward, as we called it, of the thing is on
- one hand the suppression of the multiplicity of the sensible, and, in that
- manner, an abstract identity: on the other hand, however, it also for that
- reason contains the multiplicity, but as an interior “simple” difference,
- which remains self-identical in the vicissitudes of appearance. This
- simple difference is the realm of _the laws_ of the phenomena—a copy of
- the phenomenon, but brought to rest and universality.
- § 423. The law, at first stating the mutual dependence of universal,
- permanent terms, has, in so far as its distinction is the inward one, its
- necessity on its own part; the one of the terms, as not externally
- different from the other, lies immediately in the other. But in this
- manner the interior distinction is, what it is in truth, the distinction
- on its own part, or the distinction which is none. With this new
- form-characteristic, on the whole, consciousness _implicitly_ vanishes:
- for consciousness as such implies the reciprocal independence of subject
- and object. The ego in its judgment has an object which is not distinct
- from it,—it has itself. Consciousness has passed into self-consciousness.
- (b) Self-consciousness(130).
- § 424. _Self-consciousness_ is the truth of consciousness: the latter is a
- consequence of the former, all consciousness of an other object being as a
- matter of fact also self-consciousness. The object is my idea: I am aware
- of the object as mine; and thus in it I am aware of me. The formula of
- self-consciousness is I = I:—abstract freedom, pure “ideality.” In so far
- it lacks “reality”: for as it is its own object, there is strictly
- speaking no object, because there is no distinction between it and the
- object.
- § 425. Abstract self-consciousness is the first negation of consciousness,
- and for that reason it is burdened with an external object, or, nominally,
- with the negation of it. Thus it is at the same time the antecedent stage,
- consciousness: it is the contradiction of itself as self-consciousness and
- as consciousness. But the latter aspect and the negation in general is in
- I = I potentially suppressed; and hence as this certitude of self against
- the object it is the _impulse_ to realise its implicit nature, by giving
- its abstract self-awareness content and objectivity, and in the other
- direction to free itself from its sensuousness, to set aside the given
- objectivity and identify it with itself. The two processes are one and the
- same, the identification of its consciousness and self-consciousness.
- (α) Appetite or Instinctive Desire(131).
- § 426. Self-consciousness, in its immediacy, is a singular, and a desire
- (appetite),—the contradiction implied in its abstraction which should yet
- be objective,—or in its immediacy which has the shape of an external
- object and should be subjective. The certitude of one’s self, which issues
- from the suppression of mere consciousness, pronounces the _object_ null:
- and the outlook of self-consciousness towards the object equally qualifies
- the abstract ideality of such self-consciousness as null.
- § 427. Self-consciousness, therefore, knows itself implicit in the object,
- which in this outlook is conformable to the appetite. In the negation of
- the two one-sided moments by the ego’s own activity, this identity comes
- to be _for_ the ego. To this activity the object, which implicitly and for
- self-consciousness is self-less, can make no resistance: the dialectic,
- implicit in it, towards self-suppression exists in this case as that
- activity of the ego. Thus while the given object is rendered subjective,
- the subjectivity divests itself of its one-sidedness and becomes objective
- to itself.
- § 428. The product of this process is the fast conjunction of the ego with
- itself, its satisfaction realised, and itself made actual. On the external
- side it continues, in this return upon itself, primarily describable as an
- individual, and maintains itself as such; because its bearing upon the
- self-less object is purely negative, the latter, therefore, being merely
- consumed. Thus appetite in its satisfaction is always destructive, and in
- its content selfish: and as the satisfaction has only happened in the
- individual (and that is transient) the appetite is again generated in the
- very act of satisfaction.
- § 429. But on the inner side, or implicitly, the sense of self which the
- ego gets in the satisfaction does not remain in abstract
- self-concentration or in mere individuality; on the contrary,—as negation
- of _immediacy_ and individuality the result involves a character of
- universality and of the identity of self-consciousness with its object.
- The judgment or diremption of this self-consciousness is the consciousness
- of a “_free_” object, in which ego is aware of itself as an ego, which
- however is _also_ still outside it.
- (β) Self-consciousness Recognitive(132).
- § 430. Here there is a self-consciousness for a self-consciousness, at
- first immediately as one of two things for another. In that other as ego I
- behold myself, and yet also an immediately existing object, another ego
- absolutely independent of me and opposed to me. (The suppression of the
- singleness of self-consciousness was only a first step in the suppression,
- and it merely led to the characterisation of it as _particular_.) This
- contradiction gives either self-consciousness the impulse to _show_ itself
- as a free self, and to exist as such for the other:—the process of
- _recognition_.
- § 431. The process is a battle. I cannot be aware of me as myself in
- another individual, so long as I see in that other an other and an
- immediate existence: and I am consequently bent upon the suppression of
- this immediacy of his. But in like measure _I_ cannot be recognised as
- immediate, except so far as I overcome the mere immediacy on my own part,
- and thus give existence to my freedom. But this immediacy is at the same
- time the corporeity of self-consciousness, in which as in its sign and
- tool the latter has its own _sense of self_, and its being _for others_,
- and the means for entering into relation with them.
- § 432. The fight of recognition is a life and death struggle: either
- self-consciousness imperils the other’s like, and incurs a like peril for
- its own—but only peril, for either is no less bent on maintaining his
- life, as the existence of his freedom. Thus the death of one, though by
- the abstract, therefore rude, negation of immediacy, it, from one point of
- view, solves the contradiction, is yet, from the essential point of view
- (i.e. the outward and visible recognition), a new contradiction (for that
- recognition is at the same time undone by the other’s death) and a greater
- than the other.
- § 433. But because life is as requisite as liberty to the solution, the
- fight ends in the first instance as a one-sided negation with inequality.
- While the one combatant prefers life, retains his single
- self-consciousness, but surrenders his claim for recognition, the other
- holds fast to his self-assertion and is recognised by the former as his
- superior. Thus arises the status of _master and slave_.
- In the battle for recognition and the subjugation under a master, we see,
- on their phenomenal side, the emergence of man’s social life and the
- commencement of political union. _Force_, which is the basis of this
- phenomenon, is not on that account a basis of right, but only the
- necessary and legitimate factor in the passage from the state of
- self-consciousness sunk in appetite and selfish isolation into the state
- of universal self-consciousness. Force, then, is the external or
- phenomenal commencement of states, not their underlying and essential
- principle.
- § 434. This status, in the first place, implies _common_ wants and common
- concern for their satisfaction,—for the means of mastery, the slave, must
- likewise be kept in life. In place of the rude destruction of the
- immediate object there ensues acquisition, preservation, and formation of
- it, as the instrumentality in which the two extremes of independence and
- non-independence are welded together. The form of universality thus
- arising in satisfying the want, creates a _permanent_ means and a
- provision which takes care for and secures the future.
- § 435. But secondly, when we look to the distinction of the two, the
- master beholds in the slave and his servitude the supremacy of his
- _single_ self-hood, and that by the suppression of immediate self-hood, a
- suppression, however, which falls on another. This other, the slave,
- however, in the service of the master, works off his individualist
- self-will, overcomes the inner immediacy of appetite, and in this
- divestment of self and in “the fear of his lord” makes “the beginning of
- wisdom”—the passage to universal self-consciousness.
- (γ) Universal Self-consciousness.
- § 436. Universal self-consciousness is the affirmative awareness of self
- in an other self: each self as a free individuality has his own “absolute”
- independence, yet in virtue of the negation of its immediacy or appetite
- without distinguishing itself from that other. Each is thus universal
- self-conscious and objective; each has “real” universality in the shape of
- reciprocity, so far as each knows itself recognised in the other freeman,
- and is aware of this in so far as it recognises the other and knows him to
- be free.
- This universal re-appearance of self-consciousness—the notion which is
- aware of itself in its objectivity as a subjectivity identical with itself
- and for that reason universal—is the form of consciousness which lies at
- the root of all true mental or spiritual life—in family, fatherland,
- state, and of all virtues, love, friendship, valour, honour, fame. But
- this appearance of the underlying essence may be severed from that
- essential, and be maintained apart in worthless honour, idle fame, &c.
- § 437. This unity of consciousness and self-consciousness implies in the
- first instance the individuals mutually throwing light upon each other.
- But the difference between those who are thus identified is mere vague
- diversity—or rather it is a difference which is none. Hence its truth is
- the fully and really existent universality and objectivity of
- self-consciousness,—which is _Reason_.
- Reason, as the _Idea_ (§ 213) as it here appears, is to be taken as
- meaning that the distinction between notion and reality which it unifies
- has the special aspect of a distinction between the self-concentrated
- notion or consciousness, and the object subsisting external and opposed to
- it.
- (c) Reason(133).
- § 438. The essential and actual truth which reason is, lies in the simple
- identity of the subjectivity of the notion, with its objectivity and
- universality. The universality of reason, therefore, whilst it signifies
- that the object, which was only given in consciousness _quâ_
- consciousness, is now itself universal, permeating and encompassing the
- ego, also signifies that the pure ego is the pure form which overlaps the
- object, and encompasses it without it.
- § 439. Self-consciousness, thus certified that its determinations are no
- less objective, or determinations of the very being of things, than they
- are its own thoughts, is Reason, which as such an identity is not only the
- absolute _substance_, but the _truth_ that knows it. For truth here has,
- as its peculiar mode and immanent form, the self-centred pure notion, ego,
- the certitude of self as infinite universality. Truth, aware of what it
- is, is mind (spirit).
- Sub-Section C. Psychology. Mind(134).
- § 440. Mind has defined itself as the truth of soul and consciousness,—the
- former a simple immediate totality, the latter now an infinite form which
- is not, like consciousness, restricted by that content, and does not stand
- in mere correlation to it as to its object, but is an awareness of this
- substantial totality, neither subjective nor objective. Mind, therefore,
- starts only from its own being and is in correlation only with its own
- features.
- Psychology accordingly studies the faculties or general modes of mental
- activity _quâ_ mental—mental vision, ideation, remembering, &c., desires,
- &c.—apart both from the content, which on the phenomenal side is found in
- empirical ideation, in thinking also and in desire and will, and from the
- two forms in which these modes exist, viz. in the soul as a physical mode,
- and in consciousness itself as a separately existent object of that
- consciousness. This, however, is not an arbitrary abstraction by the
- psychologist. Mind is just this elevation above nature and physical modes,
- and above the complication with an external object—in one word, above the
- material, as its concept has just shown. All it has now to do is to
- realise this notion of its freedom, and get rid of the _form_ of immediacy
- with which it once more begins. The content which is elevated to
- intuitions is _its_ sensations: it is _its_ intuitions also which are
- transmuted into representations, and its representations which are
- transmuted again into thoughts, &c.
- § 441. The soul is finite, so far as its features are immediate or
- con-natural. Consciousness is finite, in so far as it has an object. Mind
- is finite, in so far as, though it no longer has an object, it has a mode
- in its knowledge; i.e., it is finite by means of its immediacy, or, what
- is the same thing, by being subjective or only a notion. And it is a
- matter of no consequence, which is defined as its notion, and which as the
- reality of that notion. Say that its notion is the utterly infinite
- objective reason, then its reality is knowledge or _intelligence_: say
- that knowledge is its notion, then its reality is that reason, and the
- realisation of knowledge consists in appropriating reason. Hence the
- finitude of mind is to be placed in the (temporary) failure of knowledge
- to get hold of the full reality of its reason, or, equally, in the
- (temporary) failure of reason to attain full manifestation in knowledge.
- Reason at the same time is only infinite so far as it is “absolute”
- freedom; so far, that is, as presupposing itself for its knowledge to work
- upon, it thereby reduces itself to finitude, and appears as everlasting
- movement of superseding this immediacy, of comprehending itself, and being
- a rational knowledge.
- § 442. The progress of mind is _development_, in so far as its existent
- phase, viz. knowledge, involves as its intrinsic purpose and burden that
- utter and complete autonomy which is rationality; in which case the action
- of translating this purpose into reality is strictly only a nominal
- passage over into manifestation, and is even there a return into itself.
- So far as knowledge which has not shaken off its original quality of
- _mere_ knowledge is only abstract or formal, the goal of mind is to give
- it objective fulfilment, and thus at the same time produce its freedom.
- The development here meant is not that of the individual (which has a
- certain _anthropological_ character), where faculties and forces are
- regarded as successively emerging and presenting themselves in external
- existence—a series of steps, on the ascertainment on which there was for a
- long time great stress laid (by the system of Condillac), as if a
- conjectural natural emergence could exhibit the origin of these faculties
- and _explain_ them. In Condillac’s method there is an unmistakable
- intention to show how the _several_ modes of mental activity could be made
- intelligible without losing sight of mental unity, and to exhibit their
- necessary interconnexion. But the categories employed in doing so are of a
- wretched sort. Their ruling principle is that the sensible is taken (and
- with justice) as the _prius_ or the initial basis, but that the later
- phases that follow this starting-point present themselves as emerging in a
- solely _affirmative_ manner, and the negative aspect of mental activity,
- by which this material is transmuted into mind and destroyed _as_ a
- sensible, is misconceived and overlooked. As the theory of Condillac
- states it, the sensible is not merely the empirical first, but is left as
- if it were the true and essential foundation.
- Similarly, if the activities of mind are treated as mere manifestations,
- forces, perhaps in terms stating their utility or suitability for some
- other interest of head or heart, there is no indication of the true final
- aim of the whole business. That can only be the intelligible unity of
- mind, and its activity can only have itself as aim; i.e. its aim can only
- be to get rid of the form of immediacy or subjectivity, to reach and get
- hold of itself, and to liberate itself to itself. In this way the
- so-called faculties of mind as thus distinguished are only to be treated
- as steps of this liberation. And this is the only _rational_ mode of
- studying the mind and its various activities.
- § 443. As consciousness has for its object the stage which preceded it,
- viz. the natural soul (§ 413), so mind has or rather makes consciousness
- its object: i.e. whereas consciousness is only the virtual identity of the
- ego with its other (§ 415), the mind realises that identity as the
- concrete unity which it and it only knows. Its productions are governed by
- the principle of all reason that the contents are at once potentially
- existent, and are the mind’s own, in freedom. Thus, if we consider the
- initial aspect of mind, that aspect is twofold—as _being_ and as _its
- own_: by the one, the mind finds in itself something which _is_, by the
- other it affirms it to be only _its own_. The way of mind is therefore
- (_a_) to be theoretical: it has to do with the rational as its immediate
- affection which it must render its own: or it has to free knowledge from
- its pre-supposedness and therefore from its abstractness, and make the
- affection subjective. When the affection has been rendered its own, and
- the knowledge consequently characterised as free intelligence, i.e. as
- having its full and free characterisation in itself, it is
- (_b_) Will: _practical_ mind, which in the first place is likewise
- formal—i.e. its content is at first _only_ its own, and is immediately
- willed; and it proceeds next to liberate its volition from its
- subjectivity, which is the one-sided form of its contents, so that it
- (_c_) confronts itself as free mind and thus gets rid of both its defects
- of one-sidedness.
- § 444. The theoretical as well as the practical mind still fall under the
- general range of Mind Subjective. They are not to be distinguished as
- active and passive. Subjective mind is productive: but it is a merely
- nominal productivity. Inwards, the theoretical mind produces only its
- “ideal” world, and gains abstract autonomy within; while the practical,
- while it has to do with autonomous products, with a material which is its
- own, has a material which is only nominally such, and therefore a
- restricted content, for which it gains the form of universality. Outwards,
- the subjective mind (which as a unity of soul and consciousness, is thus
- also a reality,—a reality at once anthropological and conformable to
- consciousness) has for its products, in the theoretical range, the _word_,
- and in the practical (not yet deed and action, but) _enjoyment_.
- Psychology, like logic, is one of those sciences which in modern times
- have yet derived least profit from the more general mental culture and the
- deeper conception of reason. It is still extremely ill off. The turn which
- the Kantian philosophy has taken has given it greater importance: it has,
- and that in its empirical condition, been claimed as the basis of
- metaphysics, which is to consist of nothing but the empirical apprehension
- and the analysis of the facts of human consciousness, merely as facts,
- just as they are given. This position of psychology, mixing it up with
- forms belonging to the range of consciousness and with anthropology, has
- led to no improvement in its own condition: but it has had the further
- effect that, both for the mind as such, and for metaphysics and philosophy
- generally, all attempts have been abandoned to ascertain the necessity of
- essential and actual reality, to get at the notion and the truth.
- (a) Theoretical mind.
- § 445. Intelligence(135) _finds_ itself determined: this is its apparent
- aspect from which in its immediacy it starts. But as knowledge,
- intelligence consists in treating what is found as its own. Its activity
- has to do with the empty form—the pretence of _finding_ reason: and its
- aim is to realise its concept or to be reason actual, along with which the
- content is realised as rational. This activity is _cognition_. The nominal
- knowledge, which is only certitude, elevates itself, as reason is
- concrete, to definite and conceptual knowledge. The course of this
- elevation is itself rational, and consists in a necessary passage
- (governed by the concept) of one grade or term of intelligent activity (a
- so-called faculty of mind) into another. The refutation which such
- cognition gives of the semblance that the rational is _found_, starts from
- the certitude or the faith of intelligence in its capability of rational
- knowledge, and in the possibility of being able to appropriate the reason,
- which it and the content virtually is.
- The distinction of Intelligence from Will is often incorrectly taken to
- mean that each has a fixed and separate existence of its own, as if
- volition could be without intelligence, or the activity of intelligence
- could be without will. The possibility of a culture of the intellect which
- leaves the heart untouched, as it is said, and of the heart without the
- intellect—of hearts which in one-sided way want intellect, and heartless
- intellects—only proves at most that bad and radically untrue existences
- occur. But it is not philosophy which should take such untruths of
- existence and of mere imagining for truth—take the worthless for the
- essential nature. A host of other phrases used of intelligence, e.g. that
- it receives and accepts impressions from outside, that ideas arise through
- the causal operations of external things upon it, &c., belong to a point
- of view utterly alien to the mental level or to the position of
- philosophic study.
- A favourite reflectional form is that of powers and faculties of soul,
- intelligence, or mind. Faculty, like power or force, is the fixed quality
- of any object of thought, conceived as reflected into self. Force (§ 136)
- is no doubt the infinity of form—of the inward and the outward: but its
- essential finitude involves the indifference of content to form (ib.
- note). In this lies the want of organic unity which by this reflectional
- form, treating mind as a “lot” of forces, is brought into mind, as it is
- by the same method brought into nature. Any aspect which can be
- distinguished in mental action is stereotyped as an independent entity,
- and the mind thus made a skeleton-like mechanical collection. It makes
- absolutely no difference if we substitute the expression “activities” for
- powers and faculties. Isolate the activities and you similarly make the
- mind a mere aggregate, and treat their essential correlation as an
- external incident.
- The action of intelligence as theoretical mind has been called _cognition_
- (knowledge). Yet this does not mean intelligence _inter alia_
- knows,—besides which it also intuites, conceives, remembers, imagines, &c.
- To take up such a position is in the first instance part and parcel of
- that isolating of mental activity just censured; but it is also in
- addition connected with the great question of modern times, as to whether
- true knowledge or the knowledge of truth is possible,—which, if answered
- in the negative, must lead to abandoning the effort. The numerous aspects
- and reasons and modes of phrase with which external reflection swells the
- bulk of this question are cleared up in their place: the more external the
- attitude of understanding in the question, the more diffuse it makes a
- simple object. At the present place the simple concept of cognition is
- what confronts the quite general assumption taken up by the question, viz.
- the assumption that the possibility of true knowledge in general is in
- dispute, and the assumption that it is possible for us at our will either
- to prosecute or to abandon cognition. The concept or possibility of
- cognition has come out as intelligence itself, as the certitude of reason:
- the act of cognition itself is therefore the actuality of intelligence. It
- follows from this that it is absurd to speak of intelligence and yet at
- the same time of the possibility or choice of knowing or not. But
- cognition is genuine, just so far as it realises itself, or makes the
- concept its own. This nominal description has its concrete meaning exactly
- where cognition has it. The stages of its realising activity are
- intuition, conception, memory, &c.: these activities have no other
- immanent meaning: their aim is solely the concept of cognition (§ 445
- note). If they are isolated, however, then an impression is implied that
- they are useful for something else than cognition, or that they severally
- procure a cognitive satisfaction of their own; and that leads to a
- glorification of the delights of intuition, remembrance, imagination. It
- is true that even as isolated (i.e. as non-intelligent), intuition,
- imagination, &c. can afford a certain satisfaction: what physical nature
- succeeds in doing by its fundamental quality—its
- out-of-selfness,—exhibiting the elements or factors of immanent reason
- external to each other,—that the intelligence can do by voluntary act, but
- the same result may happen where the intelligence is itself only natural
- and untrained. But the _true satisfaction_, it is admitted, is only
- afforded by an intuition permeated by intellect and mind, by rational
- conception, by products of imagination which are permeated by reason and
- exhibit ideas—in a word, by _cognitive_ intuition, cognitive conception,
- &c. The truth ascribed to such satisfaction lies in this, that intuition,
- conception, &c. are not isolated, and exist only as “moments” in the
- totality of cognition itself.
- (α) Intuition (Intelligent Perception)(136).
- § 446. The mind which as soul is physically conditioned,—which as
- consciousness stands to this condition on the same terms as to an outward
- object,—but which as intelligence _finds itself_ so characterised—is (1)
- an inarticulate embryonic life, in which it is to itself as it were
- palpable and has the whole _material_ of its knowledge. In consequence of
- the immediacy in which it is thus originally, it is in this stage only as
- an individual and possesses a vulgar subjectivity. It thus appears as mind
- in the guise of _feeling_.
- If feeling formerly turned up (§ 399) as a mode of the _soul’s_ existence,
- the finding of it or its immediacy was in that case essentially to be
- conceived as a congenital or corporeal condition; whereas at present it is
- only to be taken abstractly in the general sense of immediacy.
- § 447. The characteristic form of feeling is that though it is a mode of
- some “affection,” this mode is simple. Hence feeling, even should its
- import be most sterling and true, has the form of casual
- particularity,—not to mention that its import may also be the most scanty
- and most untrue.
- It is commonly enough assumed that mind has in its feeling the material of
- its ideas, but the statement is more usually understood in a sense the
- opposite of that which it has here. In contrast with the simplicity of
- feeling it is usual rather to assume that the primary mental phase is
- judgment generally, or the distinction of consciousness into subject and
- object; and the special quality of sensation is derived from an
- independent _object_, external or internal. With us, in the truth of mind,
- the mere consciousness point of view, as opposed to true mental
- “idealism,” is swallowed up, and the matter of feeling has rather been
- supposed already as _immanent_ in the mind.—It is commonly taken for
- granted that as regards content there is more in feeling than in thought:
- this being specially affirmed of moral and religious feelings. Now the
- material, which the mind as it feels is to itself, is _here_ the result
- and the mature result of a fully organised reason: hence under the head of
- feeling is comprised all rational and indeed all spiritual content
- whatever. But the form of selfish singleness to which feeling reduces the
- mind is the lowest and worst vehicle it can have—one in which it is not
- found as a free and infinitely universal principle, but rather as
- subjective and private, in content and value entirely contingent. Trained
- and sterling feeling is the feeling of an educated mind which has acquired
- the consciousness of the true differences of things, of their essential
- relationships and real characters; and it is with such a mind that this
- rectified material enters into its feeling and receives this form. Feeling
- is the immediate, as it were the closest, contact in which the thinking
- subject can stand to a given content. Against that content the subject
- re-acts first of all with its particular self-feeling, which though it
- _may_ be of more sterling value and of wider range than a onesided
- intellectual standpoint, may just as likely be narrow and poor; and in any
- case is the form of the particular and subjective. If a man on any topic
- appeals not to the nature and notion of the thing, or at least to
- reasons—to the generalities of common sense—but to his feeling, the only
- thing to do is to let him alone, because by his behaviour he refuses to
- have any lot or part in common rationality, and shuts himself up in his
- own isolated subjectivity—his private and particular self.
- § 448. (2) As this immediate finding is broken up into elements, we have
- the one factor in _Attention_—the abstract _identical_ direction of mind
- (in feeling, as also in all other more advanced developments of it)—an
- active self-collection—the factor of fixing it as our own, but with an as
- yet only nominal autonomy of intelligence. Apart from such attention there
- is nothing for the mind. The other factor is to invest the special quality
- of feeling, as contrasted with this inwardness of mind, with the character
- of something existent, but as a _negative_ or as the abstract otherness of
- itself. Intelligence thus defines the content of sensation as something
- that is out of itself, projects it into time and space, which are the
- forms in which it is intuitive. To the view of consciousness the material
- is only an object of consciousness, a relative other: from mind it
- receives the rational characteristic of being _its very other_ (§§ 147,
- 254).
- § 449. (3) When intelligence reaches a concrete unity of the two factors,
- that is to say, when it is at once self-collected in this externally
- existing material, and yet in this self-collectedness sunk in the
- out-of-selfness, it is _Intuition_ or Mental Vision.
- § 450. At and towards this its own out-of-selfness, intelligence no less
- essentially directs its attention. In this its immediacy it is an awaking
- to itself, a recollection of itself. Thus intuition becomes a concretion
- of the material with the intelligence, which makes it its own, so that it
- no longer needs this immediacy, no longer needs to find the content.
- (β) Representation (or Mental Idea)(137).
- § 451. Representation is this recollected or inwardised intuition, and as
- such is the middle between that stage of intelligence where it finds
- itself immediately subject to modification and that where intelligence is
- in its freedom, or, as thought. The representation is the property of
- intelligence; with a preponderating subjectivity, however, as its right of
- property is still conditioned by contrast with the immediacy, and the
- representation cannot as it stands be said to _be_. The path of
- intelligence in representations is to render the immediacy inward, to
- invest itself with intuitive action in itself, and at the same time to get
- rid of the subjectivity of the inwardness, and inwardly divest itself of
- it; so as to be in itself in an externality of its own. But as
- representation begins from intuition and the ready-found material of
- intuition, the intuitional contrast still continues to affect its
- activity, and makes its concrete products still “syntheses,” which do not
- grow to the concrete immanence of the notion till they reach the stage of
- thought.
- (αα) Recollection(138).
- § 452. Intelligence, as it at first recollects the intuition, places the
- content of feeling in its own inwardness—in a space and a time of its own.
- In this way that content is (1) an _image_ or picture, liberated from its
- original immediacy and abstract singleness amongst other things, and
- received into the universality of the ego. The image loses the full
- complement of features proper to intuition, and is arbitrary or
- contingent, isolated, we may say, from the external place, time, and
- immediate context in which the intuition stood.
- § 453. (2) The image is of itself transient, and intelligence itself is as
- attention its time and also its place, its when and where. But
- intelligence is not only consciousness and actual existence, but _quâ_
- intelligence is the subject and the potentiality of its own
- specialisations. The image when thus kept in mind is no longer existent,
- but stored up out of consciousness.
- To grasp intelligence as this night-like mine or pit in which is stored a
- world of infinitely many images and representations, yet without being in
- consciousness, is from the one point of view the universal postulate which
- bids us treat the notion as concrete, in the way we treat e.g. the germ as
- affirmatively containing, in virtual possibility, all the qualities that
- come into existence in the subsequent development of the tree. Inability
- to grasp a universal like this, which, though intrinsically concrete,
- still continues _simple_, is what has led people to talk about special
- fibres and areas as receptacles of particular ideas. It was felt that what
- was diverse should in the nature of things have a local habitation
- peculiar to itself. But whereas the reversion of the germ from its
- existing specialisations to its simplicity in a purely potential existence
- takes place only in another germ,—the germ of the fruit; intelligence
- _quâ_ intelligence shows the potential coming to free existence in its
- development, and yet at the same time collecting itself in its inwardness.
- Hence from the other point of view intelligence is to be conceived as this
- sub-conscious mine, i.e. as the _existent_ universal in which the
- different has not yet been realised in its separations. And it is indeed
- this potentiality which is the first form of universality offered in
- mental representation.
- § 454. (3) An image thus abstractly treasured up needs, if it is to exist,
- an actual intuition: and what is strictly called Remembrance is the
- reference of the image to an intuition,—and that as a subsumption of the
- immediate single intuition (impression) under what is in point of form
- universal, under the representation (idea) with the same content. Thus
- intelligence recognises the specific sensation and the intuition of it as
- what is already its own,—in them it is still within itself: at the same
- time it is aware that what is only its (primarily) internal image is also
- an immediate object of intuition, by which it is authenticated. The image,
- which in the mine of intelligence was only its _property_, now that it has
- been endued with externality, comes actually into its _possession_. And so
- the image is at once rendered distinguishable from the intuition and
- separable from the blank night in which it was originally submerged.
- Intelligence is thus the force which can give forth its property, and
- dispense with external intuition for its existence in it. This “synthesis”
- of the internal image with the recollected existence is _representation_
- proper: by this synthesis the internal now has the qualification of being
- able to be presented before intelligence and to have its existence in it.
- (ββ) Imagination(139).
- § 455. (1) The intelligence which is active in this possession is the
- _reproductive imagination_, where the images issue from the inward world
- belonging to the ego, which is now the power over them. The images are in
- the first instance referred to this external, immediate time and space
- which is treasured up along with them. But it is solely in the conscious
- subject, where it is treasured up, that the image has the individuality in
- which the features composing it are conjoined: whereas their original
- concretion, i.e. at first only in space and time, as a _unit_ of
- intuition, has been broken up. The content reproduced, belonging as it
- does to the self-identical unity of intelligence, and an out-put from its
- universal mine, has a general idea (representation) to supply the link of
- association for the images which according to circumstances are more
- abstract or more concrete ideas.
- The so-called _laws of the association of ideas_ were objects of great
- interest, especially during that outburst of empirical psychology which
- was contemporaneous with the decline of philosophy. In the first place, it
- is not _Ideas_ (properly so called) which are associated. Secondly, these
- modes of relation are not _laws_, just for the reason that there are so
- many laws about the same thing, as to suggest a caprice and a contingency
- opposed to the very nature of law. It is a matter of chance whether the
- link of association is something pictorial, or an intellectual category,
- such as likeness and contrast, reason and consequence. The train of images
- and representations suggested by association is the sport of vacant-minded
- ideation, where, though intelligence shows itself by a certain formal
- universality, the matter is entirely pictorial.—Image and idea, if we
- leave out of account the more precise definition of those forms given
- above, present also a distinction in content. The former is the more
- consciously-concrete idea, whereas the idea (representation), whatever be
- its content (from image, notion, or idea), has always the peculiarity,
- though belonging to intelligence, of being in respect of its content given
- and immediate. It is still true of this idea or representation, as of all
- intelligence, that it finds its material, as a matter of fact, to _be_ so
- and so; and the universality which the aforesaid material receives by
- ideation is still abstract. Mental representation is the mean in the
- syllogism of the elevation of intelligence, the link between the two
- significations of self-relatedness—viz. _being_ and _universality_, which
- in consciousness receive the title of object and subject. Intelligence
- complements what is merely found by the attribution of universality, and
- the internal and its own by the attribution of being, but a being of its
- own institution. (On the distinction of representations and thoughts, see
- Introd. to the Logic, § 20 note.)
- Abstraction, which occurs in the ideational activity by which general
- ideas are produced (and ideas _quâ_ ideas virtually have the form of
- generality), is frequently explained as the incidence of many similar
- images one upon another and is supposed to be thus made intelligible. If
- this super-imposing is to be no mere accident and without principle, a
- force of attraction in like images must be assumed, or something of the
- sort, which at the same time would have the negative power of rubbing off
- the dissimilar elements against each other. This force is really
- intelligence itself,—the self-identical ego which by its internalising
- recollection gives the images _ipso facto_ generality, and subsumes the
- single intuition under the already internalised image (§ 453).
- § 456. Thus even the association of ideas is to be treated as a
- subsumption of the individual under the universal, which forms their
- connecting link. But here intelligence is more than merely a general form:
- its inwardness is an internally definite, concrete subjectivity with a
- substance and value of its own, derived from some interest, some latent
- concept or Ideal principle, so far as we may by anticipation speak of
- such. Intelligence is the power which wields the stores of images and
- ideas belonging to it, and which thus (2) freely combines and subsumes
- these stores in obedience to its peculiar tenor. Such is creative
- imagination(140)—symbolic, allegoric, or poetical imagination—where the
- intelligence gets a definite embodiment in this store of ideas and informs
- them with its general tone. These more or less concrete, individualised
- creations are still “syntheses”: for the material, in which the subjective
- principles and ideas get a mentally pictorial existence, is derived from
- the data of intuition.
- § 457. In creative imagination intelligence has been so far perfected as
- to need no helps for intuition. Its self-sprung ideas have pictorial
- existence. This pictorial creation of its intuitive spontaneity is
- subjective—still lacks the side of existence. But as the creation unites
- the internal idea with the vehicle of materialisation, intelligence has
- therein _implicitly_ returned both to identical self-relation and to
- immediacy. As reason, its first start was to appropriate the immediate
- datum in itself (§§ 445, 455), i.e. to universalise it; and now its action
- as reason (§ 458) is from the present point directed towards giving the
- character of an existent to what in it has been perfected to concrete
- auto-intuition. In other words, it aims at making itself _be_ and be a
- fact. Acting on this view, it is self-uttering, intuition-producing: the
- imagination which creates signs.
- Productive imagination is the centre in which the universal and being,
- one’s own and what is picked up, internal and external, are completely
- welded into one. The preceding “syntheses” of intuition, recollection,
- &c., are unifications of the same factors, but they are “syntheses”; it is
- not till creative imagination that intelligence ceases to be the vague
- mine and the universal, and becomes an individuality, a concrete
- subjectivity, in which the self-reference is defined both to being and to
- universality. The creations of imagination are on all hands recognised as
- such combinations of the mind’s own and inward with the matter of
- intuition; what further and more definite aspects they have is a matter
- for other departments. For the present this internal studio of
- intelligence is only to be looked at in these abstract
- aspects.—Imagination, when regarded as the agency of this unification, is
- reason, but only a nominal reason, because the matter or theme it embodies
- is to imagination _quâ_ imagination a matter of indifference; whilst
- reason _quâ_ reason also insists upon the _truth_ of its content.
- Another point calling for special notice is that, when imagination
- elevates the internal meaning to an image and intuition, and this is
- expressed by saying that it gives the former the character of an
- _existent_, the phrase must not seem surprising that intelligence makes
- itself _be_ as a _thing_; for its ideal import is itself, and so is the
- aspect which it imposes upon it. The image produced by imagination of an
- object is a bare mental or subjective intuition: in the sign or symbol it
- adds intuitability proper; and in mechanical memory it completes, so far
- as it is concerned, this form of _being_.
- § 458. In this unity (initiated by intelligence) of an independent
- representation with an intuition, the matter of the latter is, in the
- first instance, something accepted, somewhat immediate or given (e.g. the
- colour of the cockade, &c.). But in the fusion of the two elements, the
- intuition does not count positively or as representing itself, but as
- representative of something else. It is an image, which has received as
- its soul and meaning an independent mental representation. This intuition
- is the _Sign_.
- The sign is some immediate intuition, representing a totally different
- import from what naturally belongs to it; it is the pyramid into which a
- foreign soul has been conveyed, and where it is conserved. The _sign_ is
- different from the _symbol_: for in the symbol the original characters (in
- essence and conception) of the visible object are more or less identical
- with the import which it bears as symbol; whereas in the sign, strictly
- so-called, the natural attributes of the intuition, and the connotation of
- which it is a sign, have nothing to do with each other. Intelligence
- therefore gives proof of wider choice and ampler authority in the use of
- intuitions when it treats them as designatory (significative) rather than
- as symbolical.
- In logic and psychology, signs and language are usually foisted in
- somewhere as an appendix, without any trouble being taken to display their
- necessity and systematic place in the economy of intelligence. The right
- place for the sign is that just given: where intelligence—which as
- intuiting generates the form of time and space, but is apparently
- recipient of sensible matter, out of which it forms ideas—now gives its
- own original ideas a definite existence from itself, treating the
- intuition (or time and space as filled full) as its own property, deleting
- the connotation which properly and naturally belongs to it, and conferring
- on it an other connotation as its soul and import. This sign-creating
- activity may be distinctively named “productive” Memory (the primarily
- abstract “Mnemosyne”); since memory, which in ordinary life is often used
- as interchangeable and synonymous with remembrance (recollection), and
- even with conception and imagination, has always to do with signs only.
- § 459. The intuition—in its natural phase a something given and given in
- space—acquires, when employed as a sign, the peculiar characteristic of
- existing only as superseded and sublimated. Such is the negativity of
- intelligence; and thus the truer phase of the intuition used as a sign is
- existence in _time_ (but its existence vanishes in the moment of being),
- and if we consider the rest of its external psychical quality, its
- _institution_ by intelligence, but an institution growing out of its
- (anthropological) own naturalness. This institution of the natural is the
- vocal note, where the inward idea manifests itself in adequate utterance.
- The vocal note which receives further articulation to express specific
- ideas—speech and, its system, language—gives to sensations, intuitions,
- conceptions, a second and higher existence than they naturally
- possess,—invests them with the right of existence in the ideational realm.
- Language here comes under discussion only in the special aspect of a
- product of intelligence for manifesting its ideas in an external medium.
- If language had to be treated in its concrete nature, it would be
- necessary for its vocabulary or material part to recall the
- anthropological or psycho-physiological point of view (§ 401), and for the
- grammar or formal portion to anticipate the standpoint of analytic
- understanding. With regard to the elementary _material_ of language, while
- on one hand the theory of mere accident has disappeared, on the other the
- principle of imitation has been restricted to the slight range it actually
- covers—that of vocal objects. Yet one may still hear the German language
- praised for its wealth—that wealth consisting in its special expression
- for special sounds—_Rauschen_, _Sausen_, _Knarren_, &c.;—there have been
- collected more than a hundred such words, perhaps: the humour of the
- moment creates fresh ones when it pleases. Such superabundance in the
- realm of sense and of triviality contributes nothing to form the real
- wealth of a cultivated language. The strictly raw material of language
- itself depends more upon an inward symbolism than a symbolism referring to
- external objects; it depends, i.e. on anthropological articulation, as it
- were the posture in the corporeal act of oral utterance. For each vowel
- and consonant accordingly, as well as for their more abstract elements
- (the posture of lips, palate, tongue in each) and for their combinations,
- people have tried to find the appropriate signification. But these dull
- sub-conscious beginnings are deprived of their original importance and
- prominence by new influences, it may be by external agencies or by the
- needs of civilisation. Having been originally sensuous intuitions, they
- are reduced to signs, and thus have only traces left of their original
- meaning, if it be not altogether extinguished. As to the _formal_ element,
- again, it is the work of analytic intellect which informs language with
- its categories: it is this logical instinct which gives rise to grammar.
- The study of languages still in their original state, which we have first
- really begun to make acquaintance with in modern times, has shown on this
- point that they contain a very elaborate grammar and express distinctions
- which are lost or have been largely obliterated in the languages of more
- civilised nations. It seems as if the language of the most civilised
- nations has the most imperfect grammar, and that the same language has a
- more perfect grammar when the nation is in a more uncivilised state than
- when it reaches a higher civilisation. (Cf. W. von Humboldt’s _Essay on
- the Dual_.)
- In speaking of vocal (which is the original) language, we may touch, only
- in passing, upon written language,—a further development in the particular
- sphere of language which borrows the help of an externally practical
- activity. It is from the province of immediate spatial intuition to which
- written language proceeds that it takes and produces the signs (§ 454). In
- particular, hieroglyphics uses spatial figures to designate _ideas_;
- alphabetical writing, on the other hand, uses them to designate vocal
- notes which are already signs. Alphabetical writing thus consists of signs
- of signs,—the words or concrete signs of vocal language being analysed
- into their simple elements, which severally receive
- designation.—Leibnitz’s practical mind misled him to exaggerate the
- advantages which a complete written language, formed on the hieroglyphic
- method (and hieroglyphics are used even where there is alphabetic writing,
- as in our signs for the numbers, the planets, the chemical elements, &c.),
- would have as a universal language for the intercourse of nations and
- especially of scholars. But we may be sure that it was rather the
- intercourse of nations (as was probably the case in Phoenicia, and still
- takes place in Canton—see _Macartney’s Travels_ by Staunton) which
- occasioned the need of alphabetical writing and led to its formation. At
- any rate a comprehensive hieroglyphic language for ever completed is
- impracticable. Sensible objects no doubt admit of permanent signs; but, as
- regards signs for mental objects, the progress of thought and the
- continual development of logic lead to changes in the views of their
- internal relations and thus also of their nature; and this would involve
- the rise of a new hieroglyphical denotation. Even in the case of
- sense-objects it happens that their names, i.e. their signs in vocal
- language, are frequently changed, as e.g. in chemistry and mineralogy. Now
- that it has been forgotten what names properly are, viz. externalities
- which of themselves have no sense, and only get signification as signs,
- and now that, instead of names proper, people ask for terms expressing a
- sort of definition, which is frequently changed capriciously and
- fortuitously, the denomination, i.e. the composite name formed of signs of
- their generic characters or other supposed characteristic properties, is
- altered in accordance with the differences of view with regard to the
- genus or other supposed specific property. It is only a stationary
- civilisation, like the Chinese, which admits of the hieroglyphic language
- of that nation; and its method of writing moreover can only be the lot of
- that small part of a nation which is in exclusive possession of mental
- culture.—The progress of the vocal language depends most closely on the
- habit of alphabetical writing; by means of which only does vocal language
- acquire the precision and purity of its articulation. The imperfection of
- the Chinese vocal language is notorious: numbers of its words possess
- several utterly different meanings, as many as ten and twenty, so that, in
- speaking, the distinction is made perceptible merely by accent and
- intensity, by speaking low and soft or crying out. The European, learning
- to speak Chinese, falls into the most ridiculous blunders before he has
- mastered these absurd refinements of accentuation. Perfection here
- consists in the opposite of that _parler sans accent_ which in Europe is
- justly required of an educated speaker. The hieroglyphic mode of writing
- keeps the Chinese vocal language from reaching that objective precision
- which is gained in articulation by alphabetic writing.
- Alphabetic writing is on all accounts the more intelligent: in it the
- _word_—the mode, peculiar to the intellect, of uttering its ideas most
- worthily—is brought to consciousness and made an object of reflection.
- Engaging the attention of intelligence, as it does, it is analysed; the
- work of sign-making is reduced to its few simple elements (the primary
- postures of articulation) in which the sense-factor in speech is brought
- to the form of universality, at the same time that in this elementary
- phase it acquires complete precision and purity. Thus alphabetic writing
- retains at the same time the advantage of vocal language, that the ideas
- have names strictly so called: the name is the simple sign for the exact
- idea, i.e. the simple plain idea, not decomposed into its features and
- compounded out of them. Hieroglyphics, instead of springing from the
- direct analysis of sensible signs, like alphabetic writing, arise from an
- antecedent analysis of ideas. Thus a theory readily arises that all ideas
- may be reduced to their elements, or simple logical terms, so that from
- the elementary signs chosen to express these (as, in the case of the
- Chinese _Koua_, the simple straight stroke, and the stroke broken into two
- parts) a hieroglyphic system would be generated by their composition. This
- feature of hieroglyphic—the analytical designations of ideas—which misled
- Leibnitz to regard it as preferable to alphabetic writing is rather in
- antagonism with the fundamental desideratum of language,—the name. To want
- a name means that for the immediate idea (which, however ample a
- connotation it may include, is still for the mind simple in the name), we
- require a simple immediate sign which for its own sake does not suggest
- anything, and has for its sole function to signify and represent sensibly
- the simple idea as such. It is not merely the image-loving and
- image-limited intelligence that lingers over the simplicity of ideas and
- redintegrates them from the more abstract factors into which they have
- been analysed: thought too reduces to the form of a simple thought the
- concrete connotation which it “resumes” and reunites from the mere
- aggregate of attributes to which analysis has reduced it. Both alike
- require such signs, simple in respect of their meaning: signs, which
- though consisting of several letters or syllables and even decomposed into
- such, yet do not exhibit a combination of several ideas.—What has been
- stated is the principle for settling the value of these written languages.
- It also follows that in hieroglyphics the relations of concrete mental
- ideas to one another must necessarily be tangled and perplexed, and that
- the analysis of these (and the proximate results of such analysis must
- again be analysed) appears to be possible in the most various and
- divergent ways. Every divergence in analysis would give rise to another
- formation of the written name; just as in modern times (as already noted,
- even in the region of sense) muriatic acid has undergone several changes
- of name. A hieroglyphic written language would require a philosophy as
- stationary as is the civilisation of the Chinese.
- What has been said shows the inestimable and not sufficiently appreciated
- educational value of learning to read and write an alphabetic character.
- It leads the mind from the sensibly concrete image to attend to the more
- formal structure of the vocal word and its abstract elements, and
- contributes much to give stability and independence to the inward realm of
- mental life. Acquired habit subsequently effaces the peculiarity by which
- alphabetic writing appears, in the interest of vision, as a roundabout way
- to ideas by means of audibility; it makes them a sort of hieroglyphic to
- us, so that in using them we need not consciously realise them by means of
- tones, whereas people unpractised in reading utter aloud what they read in
- order to catch its meaning in the sound. Thus, while (with the faculty
- which transformed alphabetic writing into hieroglyphics) the capacity of
- abstraction gained by the first practice remains, hieroglyphic reading is
- of itself a deaf reading and a dumb writing. It is true that the audible
- (which is in time) and the visible (which is in space), each have their
- own basis, one no less authoritative than the other. But in the case of
- alphabetic writing there is only a _single_ basis: the two aspects occupy
- their rightful relation to each other: the visible language is related to
- the vocal only as a sign, and intelligence expresses itself immediately
- and unconditionally by speaking.—The instrumental function of the
- comparatively non-sensuous element of tone for all ideational work shows
- itself further as peculiarly important in memory which forms the passage
- from representation to thought.
- § 460. The name, combining the intuition (an intellectual production) with
- its signification, is primarily a single transient product; and
- conjunction of the idea (which is inward) with the intuition (which is
- outward) is itself outward. The reduction of this outwardness to
- inwardness is (verbal) Memory.
- (γγ) Memory(141).
- § 461. Under the shape of memory the course of intelligence passes through
- the same inwardising (recollecting) functions, as regards the intuition of
- the _word_, as representation in general does in dealing with the first
- immediate intuition (§ 451). (1) Making its own the synthesis achieved in
- the sign, intelligence, by this inwardising (memorising) elevates the
- _single_ synthesis to a universal, i.e. permanent, synthesis, in which
- name and meaning are for it objectively united, and renders the intuition
- (which the name originally is) a representation. Thus the import
- (connotation) and sign, being identified, form one representation: the
- representation in its inwardness is rendered concrete and gets existence
- for its import: all this being the work of memory which retains names
- (retentive Memory).
- § 462. The name is thus the thing so far as it exists and counts in the
- ideational realm. (2) In the name, _Reproductive_ memory has and
- recognises the thing, and with the thing it has the name, apart from
- intuition and image. The name, as giving an _existence_ to the content in
- intelligence, is the externality of intelligence to itself; and the
- inwardising or recollection of the name, i.e. of an intuition of
- intellectual origin, is at the same time a self-externalisation to which
- intelligence reduces itself on its own ground. The association of the
- particular names lies in the meaning of the features sensitive,
- representative, or cogitant,—series of which the intelligence traverses as
- it feels, represents, or thinks.
- Given the name lion, we need neither the actual vision of the animal, nor
- its image even: the name alone, if we _understand_ it, is the unimaged
- simple representation. We _think_ in names.
- The recent attempts—already, as they deserved, forgotten—to rehabilitate
- the Mnemonic of the ancients, consist in transforming names into images,
- and thus again deposing memory to the level of imagination. The place of
- the power of memory is taken by a permanent tableau of a series of images,
- fixed in the imagination, to which is then attached the series of ideas
- forming the composition to be learned by rote. Considering the
- heterogeneity between the import of these ideas and those permanent
- images, and the speed with which the attachment has to be made, the
- attachment cannot be made otherwise than by shallow, silly, and utterly
- accidental links. Not merely is the mind put to the torture of being
- worried by idiotic stuff, but what is thus learnt by rote is just as
- quickly forgotten, seeing that the same tableau is used for getting by
- rote every other series of ideas, and so those previously attached to it
- are effaced. What is mnemonically impressed is not like what is retained
- in memory really got by heart, i.e. strictly produced from within
- outwards, from the deep pit of the ego, and thus recited, but is, so to
- speak, read off the tableau of fancy.—Mnemonic is connected with the
- common prepossession about memory, in comparison with fancy and
- imagination; as if the latter were a higher and more intellectual activity
- than memory. On the contrary, memory has ceased to deal with an image
- derived from intuition,—the immediate and incomplete mode of intelligence;
- it has rather to do with an object which is the product of intelligence
- itself,—such a _without book_(142) as remains locked up in the
- _within-book_(143) of intelligence, and is, within intelligence, only its
- outward and existing side.
- § 463. (3) As the interconnexion of the names lies in the meaning, the
- conjunction of their meaning with the reality as names is still an
- (external) synthesis; and intelligence in this its externality has not
- made a complete and simple return into self. But intelligence is the
- universal,—the single plain truth of its particular self-divestments; and
- its consummated appropriation of them abolishes that distinction between
- meaning and name. This extreme inwardising of representation is the
- supreme self-divestment of intelligence, in which it renders itself the
- mere _being_, the universal space of names as such, i.e. of meaningless
- words. The ego, which is this abstract being, is, because subjectivity, at
- the same time the power over the different names,—the link which, having
- nothing in itself, fixes in itself series of them and keeps them in stable
- order. So far as they merely _are_, and intelligence is here itself this
- _being_ of theirs, its power is a merely abstract subjectivity,—memory;
- which, on account of the complete externality in which the members of such
- series stand to one another, and because it is itself this externality
- (subjective though that be), is called mechanical (§ 195).
- A composition is, as we know, not thoroughly conned by rote, until one
- attaches no meaning to the words. The recitation of what has been thus got
- by heart is therefore of course accentless. The correct accent, if it is
- introduced, suggests the meaning: but this introduction of the
- signification of an idea disturbs the mechanical nexus and therefore
- easily throws out the reciter. The faculty of conning by rote series of
- words, with no principle governing their succession, or which are
- separately meaningless, e.g. a series of proper names, is so supremely
- marvellous, because it is the very essence of mind to have its wits about
- it; whereas in this case the mind is estranged in itself, and its action
- is like machinery. But it is only as uniting subjectivity with objectivity
- that the mind has its wits about it. Whereas in the case before us, after
- it has in intuition been at first so external as to pick up its facts
- ready-made, and in representation inwardises or recollects this datum and
- makes it its own,—it proceeds as memory to make itself external in itself,
- so that what is its own assumes the guise of something found. Thus one of
- the two dynamic factors of thought, viz. objectivity, is here put in
- intelligence itself as a quality of it.—It is only a step further to treat
- memory as mechanical—the act implying no intelligence—in which case it is
- only justified by its uses, its indispensability perhaps for other
- purposes and functions of mind. But by so doing we overlook the proper
- signification it has in the mind.
- § 464. If it is to be the fact and true objectivity, the mere name as an
- existent requires something else,—to be interpreted by the representing
- intellect. Now in the shape of mechanical memory, intelligence is at once
- that external objectivity and the meaning. In this way intelligence is
- explicitly made an _existence_ of this identity, i.e. it is explicitly
- active as such an identity which as reason it is implicitly. Memory is in
- this manner the passage into the function of _thought_, which no longer
- has a _meaning_, i.e. its objectivity is no longer severed from the
- subjective, and its inwardness does not need to go outside for its
- existence.
- The German language has etymologically assigned memory (_Gedächtniß_), of
- which it has become a foregone conclusion to speak contemptuously, the
- high position of direct kindred with thought (_Gedanke_).—It is not matter
- of chance that the young have a better memory than the old, nor is their
- memory solely exercised for the sake of utility. The young have a good
- memory because they have not yet reached the stage of reflection; their
- memory is exercised with or without design so as to level the ground of
- their inner life to pure being or to pure space in which the fact, the
- implicit content, may reign and unfold itself with no antithesis to a
- subjective inwardness. Genuine ability is in youth generally combined with
- a good memory. But empirical statements of this sort help little towards a
- knowledge of what memory intrinsically is. To comprehend the position and
- meaning of memory and to understand its organic interconnexion with
- thought is one of the hardest points, and hitherto one quite unregarded in
- the theory of mind. Memory _quâ_ memory is itself the merely _external_
- mode, or merely _existential_ aspect of thought, and thus needs a
- complementary element. The passage from it to thought is to our view and
- implicitly the identity of reason with this existential mode: an identity
- from which it follows that reason only exists in a subject, and as the
- function of that subject. Thus active reason is _Thinking_.
- (γ) Thinking(144).
- § 465. Intelligence is recognitive: it cognises an intuition, but only
- because that intuition is already its own (§ 454); and in the name it
- re-discovers the fact (§ 462): but now it finds _its_ universal in the
- double signification of the universal as such, and of the universal as
- immediate or as being,—finds i.e. the genuine universal which is its own
- unity overlapping and including its other, viz. being. Thus intelligence
- is explicitly, and on its own part cognitive: _virtually_ it is the
- universal,—its product (the thought) is the thing: it is a plain identity
- of subjective and objective. It knows that what is _thought_, _is_, and
- that what _is_, only _is_ in so far as it is a thought (§ 521); the
- thinking of intelligence is to _have thoughts_: these are as its content
- and object.
- § 466. But cognition by thought is still in the first instance formal: the
- universality and its being is the plain subjectivity of intelligence. The
- thoughts therefore are not yet fully and freely determinate, and the
- representations which have been inwardised to thoughts are so far still
- the given content.
- § 467. As dealing with this given content, thought is (α) _understanding_
- with its formal identity, working up the representations, that have been
- memorised, into species, genera, laws, forces, &c., in short into
- categories,—thus indicating that the raw material does not get the truth
- of its being save in these thought-forms. As intrinsically infinite
- negativity, thought is (β) essentially an act of partition,—_judgment_,
- which however does not break up the concept again into the old antithesis
- of universality and being, but distinguishes on the lines supplied by the
- interconnexions peculiar to the concept. Thirdly (γ), thought supersedes
- the formal distinction and institutes at the same time an identity of the
- differences,—thus being nominal _reason_ or inferential understanding.
- Intelligence, as the act of thought, cognises. And (α) understanding out
- of its generalities (the categories) _explains_ the individual, and is
- then said to comprehend or understand itself: (β) in the judgment it
- explains the individual to be an universal (species, genus). In these
- forms the _content_ appears as given: (γ) but in inference (syllogism) it
- characterises a content from itself, by superseding that form-difference.
- With the perception of the necessity, the last immediacy still attaching
- to formal thought has vanished.
- In _Logic_ there was thought, but in its implicitness, and as reason
- develops itself in this distinction-lacking medium. So in _consciousness_
- thought occurs as a stage (§ 437 note). Here reason is as the truth of the
- antithetical distinction, as it had taken shape within the mind’s own
- limits. Thought thus recurs again and again in these different parts of
- philosophy, because these parts are different only through the medium they
- are in and the antithesis they imply; while thought is this one and the
- same centre, to which as to their truth the antithesis return.
- § 468. Intelligence which as theoretical appropriates an immediate mode of
- being, is, now that it has completed _taking possession_, in its own
- _property_: the last negation of immediacy has implicitly required that
- the intelligence shall itself determine its content. Thus thought, as free
- notion, is now also free in point of _content_. But when intelligence is
- aware that it is determinative of the content, which is _its_ mode no less
- than it is a mode of being, it is Will.
- (b) Mind Practical(145).
- § 469. As will, the mind is aware that it is the author of its own
- conclusions, the origin of its self-fulfilment. Thus fulfilled, this
- independency or individuality form the side of existence or of _reality_
- for the Idea of mind. As will, the mind steps into actuality; whereas as
- cognition it is on the soil of notional generality. Supplying its own
- content, the will is self-possessed, and in the widest sense free: this is
- its characteristic trait. Its finitude lies in the formalism that the
- spontaneity of its self-fulfilment means no more than a general and
- abstract ownness, not yet identified with matured reason. It is the
- function of the essential will to bring liberty to exist in the formal
- will, and it is therefore the aim of that formal will to fill itself with
- its essential nature, i.e. to make liberty its pervading character,
- content, and aim, as well as its sphere of existence. The essential
- freedom of will is, and must always be, a thought: hence the way by which
- will can make itself objective mind is to rise to be a thinking will,—to
- give itself the content which it can only have as it thinks itself.
- True liberty, in the shape of moral life, consists in the will finding its
- purpose in a universal content, not in subjective or selfish interests.
- But such a content is only possible in thought and through thought: it is
- nothing short of absurd to seek to banish thought from the moral,
- religious, and law-abiding life.
- § 470. Practical mind, considered at first as formal or immediate will,
- contains a double ought—(1) in the contrast which the new mode of being
- projected outward by the will offers to the immediate positivity of its
- old existence and condition,—an antagonism which in consciousness grows to
- correlation with external objects. (2) That first self-determination,
- being itself immediate, is not at once elevated into a thinking
- universality: the latter, therefore, virtually constitutes an obligation
- on the former in point of form, as it may also constitute it in point of
- matter;—a distinction which only exists for the observer.
- (α) Practical Sense or Feeling(146).
- § 471. The autonomy of the practical mind at first is immediate and
- therefore formal, i.e. it _finds_ itself as an _individuality_ determined
- in _its_ inward _nature_. It is thus “practical feeling,” or instinct of
- action. In this phase, as it is at bottom a subjectivity simply identical
- with reason, it has no doubt a rational content, but a content which as it
- stands is individual, and for that reason also natural, contingent and
- subjective,—a content which may be determined quite as much by mere
- personalities of want and opinion, &c., and by the subjectivity which
- selfishly sets itself against the universal, as it may be virtually in
- conformity with reason.
- An appeal is sometimes made to the sense (feeling) of right and morality,
- as well as of religion, which man is alleged to possess,—to his benevolent
- dispositions,—and even to his heart generally,—i.e. to the subject so far
- as the various practical feelings are in it all combined. So far as this
- appeal implies (1) that these ideas are immanent in his own self, and (2)
- that when feeling is opposed to the logical understanding, it, and not the
- partial abstractions of the latter, _may_ be the _totality_—the appeal has
- a legitimate meaning. But on the other hand feeling too _may_ be onesided,
- unessential and bad. The rational, which exists in the shape of
- rationality when it is apprehended by thought, is the same content as the
- _good_ practical feeling has, but presented in its universality and
- necessity, in its objectivity and truth.
- Thus it is on the one hand _silly_ to suppose that in the passage from
- feeling to law and duty there is any loss of import and excellence; it is
- this passage which lets feeling first reach its truth. It is equally silly
- to consider intellect as superfluous or even harmful to feeling, heart,
- and will; the truth and, what is the same thing, the actual rationality of
- the heart and will can only be at home in the universality of intellect,
- and not in the singleness of feeling as feeling. If feelings are of the
- right sort, it is because of their quality or content,—which is right only
- so far as it is intrinsically universal or has its source in the thinking
- mind. The difficulty for the logical intellect consists in throwing off
- the separation it has arbitrarily imposed between the several faculties of
- feeling and thinking mind, and coming to see that in the human being there
- is only _one_ reason, in feeling, volition, and thought. Another
- difficulty connected with this is found in the fact that the Ideas which
- are the special property of the thinking mind, viz. God, law and morality,
- can also be _felt_. But feeling is only the form of the immediate and
- peculiar individuality of the subject, in which these facts, like any
- other objective facts (which consciousness also sets over against itself),
- may be placed.
- On the other hand, it is _suspicious_ or even worse to cling to feeling
- and heart in place of the intelligent rationality of law, right and duty;
- because all that the former holds more than the latter is only the
- particular subjectivity with its vanity and caprice. For the same reason
- it is out of place in a scientific treatment of the feelings to deal with
- anything beyond their form, and to discuss their content; for the latter,
- when thought, is precisely what constitutes, in their universality and
- necessity, the rights and duties which are the true works of mental
- autonomy. So long as we study practical feelings and dispositions
- specially, we have only to deal with the selfish, bad, and evil; it is
- these alone which belong to the individuality which retains its opposition
- to the universal: their content is the reverse of rights and duties, and
- precisely in that way do they—but only in antithesis to the latter—retain
- a speciality of their own.
- § 472. The “Ought” of practical feeling is the claim of its essential
- autonomy to control some existing mode of fact—which is assumed to be
- worth nothing save as adapted to that claim. But as both, in their
- immediacy, lack objective determination, this relation of the
- _requirement_ to existent fact is the utterly subjective and superficial
- feeling of pleasant or unpleasant.
- Delight, joy, grief, &c., shame, repentance, contentment, &c., are partly
- only modifications of the formal “practical feeling” in _general_, but are
- partly different in the features that give the special tone and character
- mode to their “Ought.”
- The celebrated question as to the origin of evil in the world, so far at
- least as evil is understood to mean what is disagreeable and painful
- merely, arises on this stage of the formal practical feeling. Evil is
- nothing but the incompatibility between what is and what ought to be.
- “Ought” is an ambiguous term,—indeed infinitely so, considering that
- casual aims may also come under the form of Ought. But where the objects
- sought are thus casual, evil only executes what is rightfully due to the
- vanity and nullity of their planning: for they themselves were radically
- evil. The finitude of life and mind is seen in their judgment: the
- contrary which is separated from them they also have as a negative in
- them, and thus they are the contradiction called evil. In the dead there
- is neither evil nor pain: for in inorganic nature the intelligible unity
- (concept) does not confront its existence and does not in the difference
- at the same time remain its permanent subject. Whereas in life, and still
- more in mind, we have this immanent distinction present: hence arises the
- Ought: and this negativity, subjectivity, ego, freedom are the principles
- of evil and pain. Jacob Böhme viewed egoity (selfhood) as pain and
- torment, and as the fountain of nature and of spirit.
- (β) The Impulses and Choice(147).
- § 473. The practical ought is a “real” judgment. Will, which is
- essentially self-determination, finds in the conformity—as immediate and
- merely _found_ to hand—of the existing mode to its requirement a negation,
- and something inappropriate to it. If the will is to satisfy itself, if
- the implicit unity of the universality and the special mode is to be
- realised, the conformity of its inner requirement and of the existent
- thing ought to be its act and institution. The will, as regards the form
- of its content, is at first still a natural will, directly identical with
- its specific mode:—natural _impulse_ and _inclination_. Should, however,
- the totality of the practical spirit throw itself into a single one of the
- many restricted forms of impulse, each being always in conflict to
- another, it is _passion_.
- § 474. Inclinations and passions embody the same constituent features as
- the practical feeling. Thus, while on one hand they are based on the
- rational nature of the mind; they on the other, as part and parcel of the
- still subjective and single will, are infected with contingency, and
- appear as particular to stand to the individual and to each other in an
- external relation and with a necessity which creates bondage.
- The special note in _passion_ is its restriction to one special mode of
- volition, in which the whole subjectivity of the individual is merged, be
- the value of that mode what it may. In consequence of this formalism,
- passion is neither good nor bad; the title only states that a subject has
- thrown his whole soul,—his interests of intellect, talent, character,
- enjoyment,—on one aim and object. Nothing great has been and nothing great
- can be accomplished without passion. It is only a dead, too often, indeed,
- a hypocritical moralising which inveighs against the form of passion as
- such.
- But with regard to the inclinations, the question is directly raised,
- Which are good and bad?—Up to what degree the good continue good;—and (as
- there are many, each with its private range) In what way have they, being
- all in one subject and hardly all, as experience shows, admitting of
- gratification, to suffer at least reciprocal restriction? And, first of
- all, as regards the numbers of these impulses and propensities, the case
- is much the same as with the psychical powers, whose aggregate is to form
- the mind theoretical,—an aggregate which is now increased by the host of
- impulses. The nominal rationality of impulse and propensity lies merely in
- their general impulse not to be subjective merely, but to get realised,
- overcoming the subjectivity by the subject’s own agency. Their genuine
- rationality cannot reveal its secret to a method of outer reflection which
- pre-supposes a number of _independent_ innate tendencies and immediate
- instincts, and therefore is wanting in a single principle and final
- purpose for them. But the immanent “reflection” of mind itself carries it
- beyond their particularity and their natural immediacy, and gives their
- contents a rationality and objectivity, in which they exist as necessary
- ties of social relation, as rights and duties. It is this objectification
- which evinces their real value, their mutual connexions, and their truth.
- And thus it was a true perception when Plato (especially including as he
- did the mind’s whole nature under its right) showed that the full reality
- of justice could be exhibited only in the _objective_ phase of justice,
- viz. in the construction of the State as the ethical life.
- The answer to the question, therefore, What are the good and rational
- propensities, and how they are to be co-ordinated with each other?
- resolves itself into an exposition of the laws and forms of common life
- produced by the mind when developing itself as _objective_ mind—a
- development in which the _content_ of autonomous action loses its
- contingency and optionality. The discussion of the true intrinsic worth of
- the impulses, inclinations, and passions is thus essentially the theory of
- legal, moral, and social _duties_.
- § 475. The subject is the act of satisfying impulses, an act of (at least)
- formal rationality, as it translates them from the subjectivity of content
- (which so far is _purpose_) into objectivity, where the subject is made to
- close with itself. If the content of the impulse is distinguished as the
- thing or business from this act of carrying it out, and we regard the
- thing which has been brought to pass as containing the element of
- subjective individuality and its action, this is what is called the
- _interest_. Nothing therefore is brought about without interest.
- An action is an aim of the subject, and it is his agency too which
- executes this aim: unless the subject were in this way in the most
- disinterested action, i.e. unless he had an interest in it, there would be
- no action at all.—The impulses and inclinations are sometimes depreciated
- by being contrasted with the baseless chimera of a happiness, the free
- gift of nature, where wants are supposed to find their satisfaction
- without the agent doing anything to produce a conformity between immediate
- existence and his own inner requirements. They are sometimes contrasted,
- on the whole to their disadvantage, with the morality of duty for duty’s
- sake. But impulse and passion are the very life-blood of all action: they
- are needed if the agent is really to be in his aim and the execution
- thereof. The morality concerns the content of the aim, which as such is
- the universal, an inactive thing, that finds its actualising in the agent;
- and finds it only when the aim is immanent in the agent, is his interest
- and—should it claim to engross his whole efficient subjectivity—his
- passion.
- § 476. The will, as thinking and implicitly free, distinguishes itself
- from the particularity of the impulses, and places itself as simple
- subjectivity of thought above their diversified content. It is thus
- “reflecting” will.
- § 477. Such a particularity of impulse has thus ceased to be a mere datum:
- the reflective will now sees it as its own, because it closes with it and
- thus gives itself specific individuality and actuality. It is now on the
- standpoint of _choosing_ between inclinations, and is option or _choice_.
- § 478. Will as choice claims to be free, reflected into itself as the
- negativity of its merely immediate autonomy. However, as the content, in
- which its former universality concludes itself to actuality, is nothing
- but the content of the impulses and appetites, it is actual only as a
- subjective and contingent will. It realises itself in a particularity,
- which it regards at the same time as a nullity, and finds a satisfaction
- in what it has at the same time emerged from. As thus contradictory, it is
- the process of distracting and suspending one desire or enjoyment by
- another,—and one satisfaction, which is just as much no satisfaction, by
- another, without end. But the truth of the particular satisfactions is the
- universal, which under the name of _happiness_ the thinking will makes its
- aim.
- (γ) Happiness(148).
- § 479. In this idea, which reflection and comparison have educed, of a
- universal satisfaction, the impulses, so far as their particularity goes,
- are reduced to a mere negative; and it is held that in part they are to be
- sacrificed to each other for the behoof that aim, partly sacrificed to
- that aim directly, either altogether or in part. Their mutual limitation,
- on one hand, proceeds from a mixture of qualitative and quantitative
- considerations: on the other hand, as happiness has its sole _affirmative_
- contents in the springs of action, it is on them that the decision turns,
- and it is the subjective feeling and good pleasure which must have the
- casting vote as to where happiness is to be placed.
- § 480. Happiness is the mere abstract and merely imagined universality of
- things desired,—a universality which only ought to be. But the
- particularity of the satisfaction which just as much _is_ as it is
- abolished, and the abstract singleness, the option which gives or does not
- give itself (as it pleases) an aim in happiness, find their truth in the
- intrinsic _universality_ of the will, i.e. its very autonomy or freedom.
- In this way choice is will only as pure subjectivity, which is pure and
- concrete at once, by having for its contents and aim only that infinite
- mode of being—freedom itself. In this truth of its autonomy, where concept
- and object are one, the will is an _actually free will_.
- Free Mind(149).
- § 481. Actual free will is the unity of theoretical and practical mind: a
- free will, which realises its own freedom of will now that the formalism,
- fortuitousness, and contractedness of the practical content up to this
- point have been superseded. By superseding the adjustments of means
- therein contained, the will is the _immediate individuality_
- self-instituted,—an individuality, however, also purified of all that
- interferes with its universalism, i.e. with freedom itself. This
- universalism the will has as its object and aim, only so far as it thinks
- itself, knows this its concept, and is _will_ as free _intelligence_.
- § 482. The mind which knows itself as free and wills itself as this its
- object, i.e. which has its true being for characteristic and aim, is in
- the first instance the rational will in general, or _implicit_ Idea, and
- because implicit only the _notion_ of absolute mind. As _abstract_ Idea
- again, it is existent only in the _immediate_ will—it is the _existential_
- side of reason,—the _single_ will as aware of this its universality
- constituting its contents and aim, and of which it is only the formal
- activity. If the will, therefore, in which the Idea thus appears is only
- finite, that will is also the act of developing the Idea, and of investing
- its self-unfolding content with an existence which, as realising the idea,
- is _actuality_. It is thus “Objective” Mind.
- No Idea is so generally recognised as indefinite, ambiguous, and open to
- the greatest misconceptions (to which therefore it actually falls a
- victim) as the idea of Liberty: none in common currency with so little
- appreciation of its meaning. Remembering that free mind is _actual_ mind,
- we can see how misconceptions about it are of tremendous consequence in
- practice. When individuals and nations have once got in their heads the
- abstract concept of full-blown liberty, there is nothing like it in its
- uncontrollable strength, just because it is the very essence of mind, and
- that as its very actuality. Whole continents, Africa and the East, have
- never had this idea, and are without it still. The Greeks and Romans,
- Plato and Aristotle, even the Stoics, did not have it. On the contrary,
- they saw that it is only by birth (as e.g. an Athenian or Spartan
- citizen), or by strength of character, education, or philosophy (—the sage
- is free even as a slave and in chains) that the human being is actually
- free. It was through Christianity that this idea came into the world.
- According to Christianity, the individual _as such_ has an infinite value
- as the object and aim of divine love, destined as mind to live in absolute
- relationship with God himself, and have God’s mind dwelling in him: i.e.
- man is implicitly destined to supreme freedom. If, in religion as such,
- man is aware of this relationship to the absolute mind as his true being,
- he has also, even when he steps into the sphere of secular existence, the
- divine mind present with him, as the substance of the state of the family,
- &c. These institutions are due to the guidance of that spirit, and are
- constituted after its measure; whilst by their existence the moral temper
- comes to be indwelling in the individual, so that in this sphere of
- particular existence, of present sensation and volition, he is _actually_
- free.
- If to be aware of the idea—to be aware, i.e. that men are aware of freedom
- as their essence, aim, and object—is matter of _speculation_, still this
- very idea itself is the actuality of men—not something which they _have_,
- as men, but which they _are_. Christianity in its adherents has realised
- an ever-present sense that they are not and cannot be slaves; if they are
- made slaves, if the decision as regards their property rests with an
- arbitrary will, not with laws or courts of justice, they would find the
- very substance of their life outraged. This will to liberty is no longer
- an _impulse_ which demands its satisfaction, but the permanent
- character—the spiritual consciousness grown into a non-impulsive nature.
- But this freedom, which the content and aim of freedom has, is itself only
- a notion—a principle of the mind and heart, intended to develope into an
- objective phase, into legal, moral, religious, and not less into
- scientific actuality.
- SECTION II. MIND OBJECTIVE.
- § 483. The objective Mind is the absolute Idea, but only existing _in
- posse_: and as it is thus on the territory of finitude, its actual
- rationality retains the aspect of external apparency. The free will finds
- itself immediately confronted by differences which arise from the
- circumstance that freedom is its _inward_ function and aim, and is in
- relation to an external and already subsisting objectivity, which splits
- up into different heads: viz. anthropological data (i.e. private and
- personal needs), external things of nature which exist for consciousness,
- and the ties of relation between individual wills which are conscious of
- their own diversity and particularity. These aspects constitute the
- external material for the embodiment of the will.
- § 484. But the purposive action of this will is to realise its concept,
- Liberty, in these externally-objective aspects, making the latter a world
- moulded by the former, which in it is thus at home with itself, locked
- together with it: the concept accordingly perfected to the Idea. Liberty,
- shaped into the actuality of a world, receives the _form of Necessity_ the
- deeper substantial nexus of which is the system or organisation of the
- principles of liberty, whilst its phenomenal nexus is power or authority,
- and the sentiment of obedience awakened in consciousness.
- § 485. This unity of the rational will with the single will (this being
- the peculiar and immediate medium in which the former is actualised)
- constitutes the simple actuality of liberty. As it (and its content)
- belongs to thought, and is the virtual _universal_, the content has its
- right and true character only in the form of universality. When invested
- with this character for the intelligent consciousness, or instituted as an
- authoritative power, it is a _Law_(150). When, on the other hand, the
- content is freed from the mixedness and fortuitousness, attaching to it in
- the practical feeling and in impulse, and is set and grafted in the
- individual will, not in the form of impulse, but in its universality, so
- as to become its habit, temper and character, it exists as manner and
- custom, or _Usage_(151).
- § 486. This “reality,” in general, where free will has _existence_, is the
- _Law_ (Right),—the term being taken in a comprehensive sense not merely as
- the limited juristic law, but as the actual body of all the conditions of
- freedom. These conditions, in relation to the _subjective_ will, where
- they, being universal, ought to have and can only have their existence,
- are its _Duties_; whereas as its temper and habit they are _Manners_. What
- is a right is also a duty, and what is a duty, is also a right. For a mode
- of existence is a right, only as a consequence of the free substantial
- will: and the same content of fact, when referred to the will
- distinguished as subjective and individual, is a duty. It is the same
- content which the subjective consciousness recognises as a duty, and
- brings into existence in these several wills. The finitude of the
- objective will thus creates the semblance of a distinction between rights
- and duties.
- In the phenomenal range right and duty are _correlata_, at least in the
- sense that to a right on my part corresponds a duty in some one else. But,
- in the light of the concept, my right to a thing is not merely possession,
- but as possession by a _person_ it is _property_, or legal possession, and
- it is a _duty_ to possess things as _property_, i.e. to be as a person.
- Translated into the phenomenal relationship, viz. relation to another
- person—this grows into the duty of some one _else_ to respect _my_ right.
- In the morality of the conscience, duty in general is in me—a free
- subject—at the same time a right of my subjective will or disposition. But
- in this individualist moral sphere, there arises the division between what
- is only inward purpose (disposition or intention), which only has its
- being in me and is merely subjective duty, and the actualisation of that
- purpose: and with this division a contingency and imperfection which makes
- the inadequacy of mere individualistic morality. In social ethics these
- two parts have reached their truth, their absolute unity; although even
- right and duty return to one another and combine by means of certain
- adjustments and under the guise of necessity. The rights of the father of
- the family over its members are equally duties towards them; just as the
- children’s duty of obedience is their right to be educated to the liberty
- of manhood. The penal judicature of a government, its rights of
- administration, &c., are no less its duties to punish, to administer, &c.;
- as the services of the members of the State in dues, military services,
- &c., are duties and yet their right to the protection of their private
- property and of the general substantial life in which they have their
- root. All the aims of society and the State are the private aim of the
- individuals. But the set of adjustments, by which their duties come back
- to them as the exercise and enjoyment of right, produces an appearance of
- diversity: and this diversity is increased by the variety of shapes which
- value assumes in the course of exchange, though it remains intrinsically
- the same. Still it holds fundamentally good that he who has no rights has
- no duties and _vice versa_.
- Distribution.
- § 487. The free will is
- A. itself at first immediate, and hence as a single being—the _person_:
- the existence which the person gives to its liberty is _property_. The
- _Right as_ right (law) is _formal, abstract right_.
- B. When the will is reflected into self, so as to have its existence
- inside it, and to be thus at the same time characterised as a
- _particular_, it is the right of the _subjective_ will, _morality_ of the
- individual conscience.
- C. When the free will is the substantial will, made actual in the subject
- and conformable to its concept and rendered a totality of necessity,—it is
- the ethics of actual life in family, civil society, and state.
- Sub-Section A. Law.(152)
- (a) Property.
- § 488. Mind, in the immediacy of its self-secured liberty, is an
- individual, but one that knows its individuality as an absolutely free
- will: it is a _person_, in whom the inward sense of this freedom, as in
- itself still abstract and empty, has its particularity and fulfilment not
- yet on its own part, but on an external _thing_. This thing, as something
- devoid of will, has no rights against the subjectivity of intelligence and
- volition, and is by that subjectivity made adjectival to it, the external
- sphere of its liberty;—_possession_.
- § 489. By the judgment of possession, at first in the outward
- appropriation, the thing acquires the predicate of “mine.” But this
- predicate, on its own account merely “practical,” has here the
- signification that I import my personal will into the thing. As so
- characterised, possession is _property_, which as possession is a _means_,
- but as existence of the personality is an _end_.
- § 490. In his property the person is brought into union with itself. But
- the thing is an abstractly external thing, and the I in it is abstractly
- external. The concrete return of me into me in the externality is that I,
- the infinite self-relation, am as a person the repulsion of me from
- myself, and have the existence of my personality in the _being of other
- persons_, in my relation to them and in my recognition by them, which is
- thus mutual.
- § 491. The thing is the _mean_ by which the extremes meet in one. These
- extremes are the persons who, in the knowledge of their identity as free,
- are simultaneously mutually independent. For them my will has its
- _definite recognisable existence_ in the thing by the immediate bodily act
- of taking possession, or by the formation of the thing or, it may be, by
- mere designation of it.
- § 492. The casual aspect of property is that I place my will in _this_
- thing: so far my will is _arbitrary_, I can just as well put it in it as
- not,—just as well withdraw it as not. But so far as my will lies in a
- thing, it is only I who can withdraw it: it is only with my will that the
- thing can pass to another, whose property it similarly becomes only with
- his will:—_Contract_.
- (b) Contract.
- § 493. The two wills and their agreement in the contract are as an
- _internal_ state of mind different from its realisation in the
- _performance_. The comparatively “ideal” utterance (of contract) in the
- _stipulation_ contains the actual surrender of a property by the one, its
- changing hands, and its acceptance by the other will. The contract is thus
- thoroughly binding: it does not need the performance of the one or the
- other to become so—otherwise we should have an infinite regress or
- infinite division of thing, labour, and time. The utterance in the
- stipulation is complete and exhaustive. The inwardness of the will which
- surrenders and the will which accepts the property is in the realm of
- ideation, and in that realm the word is deed and thing (§ 462)—the full
- and complete deed, since here the conscientiousness of the will does not
- come under consideration (as to whether the thing is meant in earnest or
- is a deception), and the will refers only to the external thing.
- § 494. Thus in the stipulation we have the _substantial_ being of the
- contract standing out in distinction from its real utterance in the
- performance, which is brought down to a mere sequel. In this way there is
- put into the thing or performance a distinction between its immediate
- specific _quality_ and its substantial being or _value_, meaning by value
- the quantitative terms into which that qualitative feature has been
- translated. One piece of property is thus made comparable with another,
- and may be made equivalent to a thing which is (in quality) wholly
- heterogeneous. It is thus treated in general as an abstract, universal
- thing or commodity.
- § 495. The contract, as an agreement which has a voluntary origin and
- deals with a casual commodity, involves at the same time the giving to
- this “accidental” will a positive fixity. This will may just as well not
- be conformable to law (right), and, in that case, produces a _wrong_: by
- which however the absolute law (right) is not superseded, but only a
- relationship originated of right to wrong.
- (c) Right versus Wrong.
- § 496. Law (right) considered as the realisation of liberty in externals,
- breaks up into a multiplicity of relations to this external sphere and to
- other persons (§§ 491, 493 seqq.). In this way there are (1) several
- titles or grounds at law, of which (seeing that property both on the
- personal and the real side is exclusively individual) only one is the
- right, but which, because they face each other, each and all are invested
- with a _show_ of right, against which the former is defined as the
- intrinsically right.
- § 497. Now so long as (compared against this show) the one intrinsically
- right, still presumed identical with the several titles, is affirmed,
- willed, and recognised, the only diversity lies in this, that the special
- thing is subsumed under the one law or right by the _particular_ will of
- _these_ several persons. This is naïve, non-malicious wrong. Such wrong in
- the several claimants is a simple _negative judgment_, expressing the
- _civil suit_. To settle it there is required a third judgment, which, as
- the judgment of the intrinsically right, is disinterested, and a power of
- giving the one right existence as against that semblance.
- § 498. But (2) if the semblance of right is willed as such _against_ right
- intrinsical by the particular will, which thus becomes _wicked_, then the
- external _recognition_ of right is separated from the right’s true value;
- and while the former only is respected, the latter is violated. This gives
- the wrong of _fraud_—the infinite judgment as identical (§ 173),—where the
- nominal relation is retained, but the sterling value is let slip.
- § 499. (3) Finally, the particular will sets itself in opposition to the
- intrinsic right by negating that right itself as well as its recognition
- or semblance. [Here there is a negatively infinite judgment (§ 173) in
- which there is denied the class as a whole, and not merely the particular
- mode—in this case the apparent recognition.] Thus the will is violently
- wicked, and commits a _crime_.
- § 500. As an outrage on right, such an action is essentially and actually
- null. In it the agent, as a volitional and intelligent being, sets up a
- law—a law however which is nominal and recognised by him only—a universal
- which holds good _for him_, and under which he has at the same time
- subsumed himself by his action. To display the nullity of such an act, to
- carry out simultaneously this nominal law and the intrinsic right, in the
- first instance by means of a subjective individual will, is the work of
- _Revenge_. But, revenge, starting from the interest of an immediate
- particular personality, is at the same time only a new outrage; and so on
- without end. This progression, like the last, abolishes itself in a third
- judgment, which is disinterested—_punishment_.
- § 501. The instrumentality by which authority is given to intrinsic right
- is (α) that a particular will, that of the judge, being conformable to the
- right, has an interest to turn against the crime (—which in the first
- instance, in revenge, is a matter of chance), and (β) that an executive
- power (also in the first instance casual) negates the negation of right
- that was created by the criminal. This negation of right has its existence
- in the will of the criminal; and consequently revenge or punishment
- directs itself against the person or property of the criminal and
- exercises _coercion_ upon him. It is in this legal sphere that coercion in
- general has possible scope,—compulsion against the thing, in seizing and
- maintaining it against another’s seizure: for in this sphere the will has
- its existence immediately in externals as such, or in corporeity, and can
- be seized only in this quarter. But more than _possible_ compulsion is
- not, so long as I can withdraw myself as free from every mode of
- existence, even from the range of all existence, i.e. from life. It is
- legal only as abolishing a first and original compulsion.
- § 502. A distinction has thus emerged between the law (right) and the
- subjective will. The “reality” of right, which the personal will in the
- first instance gives itself in immediate wise, is seen to be due to the
- instrumentality of the subjective will,—whose influence as on one hand it
- gives existence to the essential right, so may on the other cut itself off
- from and oppose itself to it. Conversely, the claim of the subjective will
- to be in this abstraction a power over the law of right is null and empty
- of itself: it gets truth and reality essentially only so far as that will
- in itself realises the reasonable will. As such it is _morality_(153)
- proper.
- The phrase “Law of Nature,” or Natural Right(154), in use for the
- philosophy of law involves the ambiguity that it may mean either right as
- something existing ready-formed in nature, or right as governed by the
- nature of things, i.e. by the notion. The former used to be the common
- meaning, accompanied with the fiction of a _state of nature_, in which the
- law of nature should hold sway; whereas the social and political state
- rather required and implied a restriction of liberty and a sacrifice of
- natural rights. The real fact is that the whole law and its every article
- are based on free personality alone,—on self-determination or autonomy,
- which is the very contrary of determination by nature. The law of
- nature—strictly so called—is for that reason the predominance of the
- strong and the reign of force, and a state of nature a state of violence
- and wrong, of which nothing truer can be said than that one ought to
- depart from it. The social state, on the other hand, is the condition in
- which alone right has its actuality: what is to be restricted and
- sacrificed is just the wilfulness and violence of the state of nature.
- Sub-Section B. The Morality Of Conscience(155).
- § 503. The free individual, who, in mere law, counts only as a _person_,
- is now characterised as a _subject_, a will reflected into itself so that,
- be its affection what it may, it is distinguished (as existing in it) as
- _its own_ from the existence of freedom in an external thing. Because the
- affection of the will is thus inwardised, the will is at the same time
- made a particular, and there arise further particularisations of it and
- relations of these to one another. This affection is partly the essential
- and implicit will, the reason of the will, the essential basis of law and
- moral life: partly it is the existent volition, which is before us and
- throws itself into actual deeds, and thus comes into relationship with the
- former. The subjective will is _morally_ free, so far as these features
- are its inward institution, its own, and willed by it. Its utterance in
- deed with this freedom is an _action_, in the externality of which it only
- admits as its own, and allows to be imputed to it, so much as it has
- consciously willed.
- This subjective or “moral” freedom is what a European especially calls
- freedom. In virtue of the right thereto a man must possess a personal
- knowledge of the distinction between good and evil in general: ethical and
- religious principles shall not merely lay their claim on him as external
- laws and precepts of authority to be obeyed, but have their assent,
- recognition, or even justification in his heart, sentiment, conscience,
- intelligence, &c. The subjectivity of the will in itself is its supreme
- aim and absolutely essential to it.
- The “moral” must be taken in the wider sense in which it does not signify
- the morally good merely. In French _le moral_ is opposed to _le physique_,
- and means the mental or intellectual in general. But here the moral
- signifies volitional mode, so far as it is in the interior of the will in
- general; it thus includes purpose and intention,—and also moral
- wickedness.
- a. Purpose(156).
- § 504. So far as the action comes into immediate touch with _existence_,
- _my part_ in it is to this extent formal, that external existence is also
- _independent_ of the agent. This externality can pervert his action and
- bring to light something else than lay in it. Now, though any alteration
- as such, which is set on foot by the subject’s action, is its _deed_(157),
- still the subject does not for that reason recognise it as its
- _action_(158), but only admits as its own that existence in the deed which
- lay in its knowledge and will, which was its _purpose_. Only for that does
- it hold itself _responsible_.
- b. Intention and Welfare(159).
- § 505. As regards its empirically concrete _content_ (1) the action has a
- variety of particular aspects and connexions. In point of _form_, the
- agent must have known and willed the action in its essential feature,
- embracing these individual points. This is the right of _intention_. While
- _purpose_ affects only the immediate fact of existence, _intention_
- regards the underlying essence and aim thereof. (2) The agent has no less
- the right to see that the particularity of content in the action, in point
- of its matter, is not something external to him, but is a particularity of
- his own,—that it contains his needs, interests, and aims. These aims, when
- similarly comprehended in a single aim, as in happiness (§ 479),
- constitute his _well-being_. This is the right to well-being. Happiness
- (good fortune) is distinguished from well-being only in this, that
- happiness implies no more than some sort of immediate existence, whereas
- well-being regards it as also justified as regards morality.
- § 506. But the essentiality of the intention is in the first instance the
- abstract form of generality. Reflection can put in this form this and that
- particular aspect in the empirically-concrete action, thus making it
- essential to the intention or restricting the intention to it. In this way
- the supposed essentiality of the intention and the real essentiality of
- the action may be brought into the greatest contradiction—e.g. a good
- intention in case of a crime. Similarly well-being is abstract and may be
- set on this or that: as appertaining to this single agent, it is always
- something particular.
- c. Goodness and Wickedness(160).
- § 507. The truth of these particularities and the concrete unity of their
- formalism is the content of the universal, essential and actual, will,—the
- law and underlying essence of every phase of volition, the essential and
- actual good. It is thus the absolute final aim of the world, and _duty_
- for the agent who _ought_ to have _insight_ into the _good_, make it his
- _intention_ and bring it about by his activity.
- § 508. But though the good is the universal of will—a universal determined
- in itself,—and thus including in it particularity,—still so far as this
- particularity is in the first instance still abstract, there is no
- principle at hand to determine it. Such determination therefore starts up
- also outside that universal; and as heteronomy or determinance of a will
- which is free and has rights of its own, there awakes here the deepest
- contradiction. (α) In consequence of the indeterminate determinism of the
- good, there are always _several sorts_ of good and _many kinds of duties_,
- the variety of which is a dialectic of one against another and brings them
- into _collision_. At the same time because good is one, they _ought_ to
- stand in harmony; and yet each of them, though it is a particular duty, is
- as good and as duty absolute. It falls upon the agent to be the dialectic
- which, superseding this absolute claim of each, concludes such a
- combination of them as excludes the rest.
- § 509. (β) To the agent, who in his existent sphere of liberty is
- essentially as a _particular_, his _interest and welfare_ must, on account
- of that existent sphere of liberty, be essentially an aim and therefore a
- duty. But at the same time in aiming at the good, which is the
- not-particular but only universal of the will, the particular interest
- _ought not_ to be a constituent motive. On account of this independency of
- the two principles of action, it is likewise an accident whether they
- harmonise. And yet they _ought_ to harmonise, because the agent, as
- individual and universal, is always fundamentally one identity.
- (γ) But the agent is not only a mere particular in his existence; it is
- also a form of his existence to be an abstract self-certainty, an abstract
- reflection of freedom into himself. He is thus distinct from the reason in
- the will, and capable of making the universal itself a particular and in
- that way a semblance. The good is thus reduced to the level of a mere “may
- happen” for the agent, who can therefore resolve itself to somewhat
- opposite to the good, can be wicked.
- § 510. (δ) The external objectivity, following the distinction which has
- arisen in the subjective will (§ 503), constitutes a peculiar world of its
- own,—another extreme which stands in no rapport with the internal
- will-determination. It is thus a matter of chance, whether it harmonises
- with the subjective aims, whether the good is realised, and the wicked, an
- aim essentially and actually null, nullified in it: it is no less matter
- of chance whether the agent finds in it his well-being, and more precisely
- whether in the world the good agent is happy and the wicked unhappy. But
- at the same time the world _ought_ to allow the good action, the essential
- thing, to be carried out in it; it _ought_ to grant the good agent the
- satisfaction of his particular interest, and refuse it to the wicked; just
- as it _ought_ also to make the wicked itself null and void.
- § 511. The all-round contradiction, expressed by this repeated _ought_,
- with its absoluteness which yet at the same time is _not_—contains the
- most abstract ’analysis’ of the mind in itself, its deepest descent into
- itself. The only relation the self-contradictory principles have to one
- another is in the abstract certainty of self; and for this infinitude of
- subjectivity the universal will, good, right, and duty, no more exist than
- not. The subjectivity alone is aware of itself as choosing and deciding.
- This pure self-certitude, rising to its pitch, appears in the two directly
- inter-changing forms—of _Conscience_ and _Wickedness_. The former is the
- will of goodness; but a goodness which to this pure subjectivity is the
- _non-objective_, non-universal, the unutterable; and over which the agent
- is conscious that _he_ in his _individuality_ has the decision. Wickedness
- is the same awareness that the single self possesses the decision, so far
- as the single self does not merely remain in this abstraction, but takes
- up the content of a subjective interest contrary to the good.
- § 512. This supreme pitch of the “_phenomenon_” of will,—sublimating
- itself to this absolute vanity—to a goodness, which has no objectivity,
- but is only sure of itself, and a self-assurance which involves the
- nullification of the universal—collapses by its own force. Wickedness, as
- the most intimate reflection of subjectivity itself, in opposition to the
- objective and universal, (which it treats as mere sham,) is the same as
- the good sentiment of abstract goodness, which reserves to the
- subjectivity the determination thereof:—the utterly abstract semblance,
- the bare perversion and annihilation of itself. The result, the truth of
- this semblance, is, on its negative side, the absolute nullity of this
- volition which would fain hold its own against the good, and of the good,
- which would only be abstract. On the affirmative side, in the notion, this
- semblance thus collapsing is the same simple universality of the will,
- which is the good. The subjectivity, in this its _identity_ with the good,
- is only the infinite form, which actualises and developes it. In this way
- the standpoint of bare reciprocity between two independent sides,—the
- standpoint of the _ought_, is abandoned, and we have passed into the field
- of ethical life.
- Sub-Section C. The Moral Life, Or Social Ethics(161).
- § 513. The moral life is the perfection of spirit objective—the truth of
- the subjective and objective spirit itself. The failure of the latter
- consists—partly in having its freedom _immediately_ in reality, in
- something external therefore, in a thing,—partly in the abstract
- universality of its goodness. The failure of spirit subjective similarly
- consists in this, that it is, as against the universal, abstractly
- self-determinant in its inward individuality. When these two imperfections
- are suppressed, subjective _freedom_ exists as the covertly and overtly
- _universal_ rational will, which is sensible of itself and actively
- disposed in the consciousness of the individual subject, whilst its
- practical operation and immediate universal _actuality_ at the same time
- exist as moral usage, manner and custom,—where self-conscious _liberty_
- has become _nature_.
- § 514. The consciously free substance, in which the absolute “ought” is no
- less an “is,” has actuality as the spirit of a nation. The abstract
- disruption of this spirit singles it out into _persons_, whose
- independence it however controls and entirely dominates from within. But
- the person, as an intelligent being, feels that underlying essence to be
- his own very being—ceases when so minded to be a mere accident of it—looks
- upon it as his absolute final aim. In its actuality he sees not less an
- achieved present, than somewhat he brings it about by his action,—yet
- somewhat which without all question _is_. Thus, without any selective
- reflection, the person performs its duty as _his own_ and as something
- which _is_; and in this necessity _he_ has himself and his actual freedom.
- § 515. Because the substance is the absolute unity of individuality and
- universality of freedom, it follows that the actuality and action of each
- individual to keep and to take care of his own being, while it is on one
- hand conditioned by the pre-supposed total in whose complex alone he
- exists, is on the other a transition into a universal product.—The social
- disposition of the individuals is their sense of the substance, and of the
- identity of all their interests with the total; and that the other
- individuals mutually know each other and are actual only in this identity,
- is confidence (trust)—the genuine ethical temper.
- § 516. The relations between individuals in the several situations to
- which the substance is particularised form their _ethical duties_. The
- ethical personality, i.e. the subjectivity which is permeated by the
- substantial life, is _virtue_. In relation to the bare facts of external
- being, to _destiny_, virtue does not treat them as a mere negation, and is
- thus a quiet repose in itself: in relation to substantial objectivity, to
- the total of ethical actuality, it exists as confidence, as deliberate
- work for the community, and the capacity of sacrificing self thereto;
- whilst in relation to the incidental relations of social circumstance, it
- is in the first instance justice and then benevolence. In the latter
- sphere, and in its attitude to its own visible being and corporeity, the
- individuality expresses its special character, temperament, &c. as
- personal _virtues_.
- § 517. The ethical substance is
- AA. as “immediate” or _natural_ mind,—the _Family_.
- BB. The “relative” totality of the “relative” relations of the individuals
- as independent persons to one another in a formal universality—_Civil
- Society_.
- CC. The self-conscious substance, as the mind developed to an organic
- actuality—the _Political Constitution_.
- AA. The Family.
- § 518. The ethical spirit, in its _immediacy_, contains the _natural_
- factor that the individual has its substantial existence in its natural
- universal, i.e. in its kind. This is the sexual tie, elevated however to a
- spiritual significance,—the unanimity of love and the temper of trust. In
- the shape of the family, mind appears as feeling.
- § 519. (1) The physical difference of sex thus appears at the same time as
- a difference of intellectual and moral type. With their exclusive
- individualities these personalities combine to form a _single person_: the
- subjective union of hearts, becoming a “substantial” unity, makes this
- union an ethical tie—_Marriage_. The ’substantial’ union of hearts makes
- marriage an indivisible personal bond—monogamic marriage: the bodily
- conjunction is a sequel to the moral attachment. A further sequel is
- community of personal and private interests.
- § 520. (2) By the community in which the various members constituting the
- family stand in reference to property, that property of the one person
- (representing the family) acquires an ethical interest, as do also its
- industry, labour, and care for the future.
- § 521. The ethical principle which is conjoined with the natural
- generation of the children, and which was assumed to have primary
- importance in first forming the marriage union, is actually realised in
- the second or spiritual birth of the children,—in educating them to
- independent personality.
- § 522. (3) The children, thus invested with independence, leave the
- concrete life and action of the family to which they primarily belong,
- acquire an existence of their own, destined however to found anew such an
- actual family. Marriage is of course broken up by the _natural_ element
- contained in it, the death of husband and wife: but even their union of
- hearts, as it is a mere “substantiality” of feeling, contains the germ of
- liability to chance and decay. In virtue of such fortuitousness, the
- members of the family take up to each other the status of persons; and it
- is thus that the family finds introduced into it for the first time the
- element, originally foreign to it, of _legal_ regulation.
- BB. Civil Society(162).
- § 523. As the substance, being an intelligent substance, particularises
- itself abstractly into many persons (the family is only a single person),
- into families or individuals, who exist independent and free, as private
- persons, it loses its ethical character: for these persons as such have in
- their consciousness and as their aim not the absolute unity, but their own
- petty selves and particular interests. Thus arises the system of
- _atomistic_: by which the substance is reduced to a general system of
- adjustments to connect self-subsisting extremes and their particular
- interests. The developed totality of this connective system is the state
- as civil society, or _state external_.
- a. The System of Wants(163).
- § 524. (α) The particularity of the persons includes in the first instance
- their wants. The possibility of satisfying these wants is here laid on the
- social fabric, the general stock from which all derive their satisfaction.
- In the condition of things in which this method of satisfaction by
- indirect adjustment is realised, immediate seizure (§ 488) of external
- objects as means thereto exists barely or not at all: the objects are
- already property. To acquire them is only possible by the intervention, on
- one hand, of the possessors’ will, which as particular has in view the
- satisfaction of their variously defined interests; while on the other hand
- it is conditioned by the ever continued production of fresh means of
- exchange by the exchangers’ _own labour_. This instrument, by which the
- labour of all facilitates satisfaction of wants, constitutes the general
- stock.
- § 525. (β) The glimmer of universal principle in this particularity of
- wants is found in the way intellect creates differences in them, and thus
- causes an indefinite multiplication both of wants and of means for their
- different phases. Both are thus rendered more and more abstract. This
- “morcellement” of their content by abstraction gives rise to the _division
- of labour_. The habit of this abstraction in enjoyment, information,
- feeling and demeanour, constitutes training in this sphere, or nominal
- culture in general.
- § 526. The labour which thus becomes more abstract tends on one hand by
- its uniformity to make labour easier and to increase production,—on
- another to limit each person to a single kind of technical skill, and thus
- produce more unconditional dependence on the social system. The skill
- itself becomes in this way mechanical, and gets the capability of letting
- the machine take the place of human labour.
- § 527. (γ) But the concrete division of the general stock—which is also a
- general business (of the whole society)—into particular masses determined
- by the factors of the notion,—masses each of which possesses its own basis
- of subsistence, and a corresponding mode of labour, of needs, and of means
- for satisfying them, besides of aims and interests, as well as of mental
- culture and habit—constitutes the difference of Estates (orders or ranks).
- Individuals apportion themselves to these according to natural talent,
- skill, option and accident. As belonging to such a definite and stable
- sphere, they have their actual existence, which as existence is
- essentially a particular; and in it they have their social morality, which
- is _honesty_, their recognition and their _honour_.
- Where civil society, and with it the State, exists, there arise the
- several estates in their difference: for the universal substance, as
- vital, _exists_ only so far as it organically _particularises_ itself. The
- history of constitutions is the history of the growth of these estates, of
- the legal relationships of individuals to them, and of these estates to
- one another and to their centre.
- § 528. To the “substantial,” natural estate the fruitful soil and ground
- supply a natural and stable capital; its action gets direction and content
- through natural features, and its moral life is founded on faith and
- trust. The second, the “reflected” estate has as its allotment the social
- capital, the medium created by the action of middlemen, of mere agents,
- and an ensemble of contingencies, where the individual has to depend on
- his subjective skill, talent, intelligence and industry. The third,
- “thinking” estate has for its business the general interests; like the
- second it has a subsistence procured by means of its own skill, and like
- the first a certain subsistence, certain however because guaranteed
- through the whole society.
- b. Administration of Justice(164).
- § 529. When matured through the operation of natural need and free option
- into a system of universal relationships and a regular course of external
- necessity, the principle of casual particularity gets that stable
- articulation which liberty requires in the shape of _formal right_. (1)
- The actualisation which right gets in this sphere of mere practical
- intelligence is that it be brought to consciousness as the stable
- universal, that it be known and stated in its specificality with the voice
- of authority—the _Law_(165).
- The _positive_ element in laws concerns only their form of _publicity_ and
- _authority_—which makes it possible for them to be known by all in a
- customary and external way. Their content _per se_ may be reasonable—or it
- may be unreasonable and so wrong. But when right, in the course of
- definite manifestation, is developed in detail, and its content analyses
- itself to gain definiteness, this analysis, because of the finitude of its
- materials, falls into the falsely infinite progress: the _final_
- definiteness, which is absolutely essential and causes a break in this
- progress of unreality, can in this sphere of finitude be attained only in
- a way that savours of contingency and arbitrariness. Thus whether three
- years, ten thalers, or only 2-1/2, 2-3/4, 2-4/5 years, and so on _ad
- infinitum_, be the right and just thing, can by no means be decided on
- intelligible principles,—and yet it should be decided. Hence, though of
- course only at the final points of deciding, on the side of external
- existence, the “positive” principle naturally enters law as contingency
- and arbitrariness. This happens and has from of old happened in all
- legislations: the only thing wanted is clearly to be aware of it, and not
- be misled by the talk and the pretence as if the ideal of law were, or
- could be, to be, at _every_ point, determined through reason or legal
- intelligence, on purely reasonable and intelligent grounds. It is a futile
- perfectionism to have such expectations and to make such requirements in
- the sphere of the finite.
- There are some who look upon laws as an evil and a profanity, and who
- regard governing and being governed from natural love, hereditary,
- divinity or nobility, by faith and trust, as the genuine order of life,
- while the reign of law is held an order of corruption and injustice. These
- people forget that the stars—and the cattle too—are governed and well
- governed too by laws;—laws however which are only internally in these
- objects, not _for them_, not as laws _set to_ them:—whereas it is man’s
- privilege to _know_ his law. They forget therefore that he can truly obey
- only such known law,—even as his law can only be a just law, as it is a
- _known_ law;—though in other respects it must be in its essential content
- contingency and caprice, or at least be mixed and polluted with such
- elements.
- The same empty requirement of perfection is employed for an opposite
- thesis—viz. to support the opinion that a code is impossible or
- impracticable. In this case there comes in the additional absurdity of
- putting essential and universal provisions in one class with the
- particular detail. The finite material is definable on and on to the false
- infinite: but this advance is not, as in the mental images of space, a
- generation of new spatial characteristics of the same quality as those
- preceding them, but an advance into greater and ever greater speciality by
- the acumen of the analytic intellect, which discovers new distinctions,
- which again make new decisions necessary. To provisions of this sort one
- may give the name of _new_ decisions or _new_ laws; but in proportion to
- the gradual advance in specialisation the interest and value of these
- provisions declines. They fall within the already subsisting
- “substantial,” general laws, like improvements on a floor or a door,
- within the house—which though something _new_, are not a new _house_. But
- there is a contrary case. If the legislation of a rude age began with
- single provisos, which go on by their very nature always increasing their
- number, there arises, with the advance in multitude, the need of a simpler
- code,—the need i.e. of embracing that lot of singulars in their general
- features. To find and be able to express these principles well beseems an
- intelligent and civilised nation. Such a gathering up of single rules into
- general forms, first really deserving the name of laws, has lately been
- begun in some directions by the English Minister Peel, who has by so doing
- gained the gratitude, even the admiration, of his countrymen.
- § 530. (2) The positive form of Laws—to be _promulgated and made known_ as
- laws—is a condition of the _external obligation_ to obey them; inasmuch
- as, being laws of strict right, they touch only the abstract will,—itself
- at bottom external—not the moral or ethical will. The subjectivity to
- which the will has in this direction a right is here only publicity. This
- subjective existence is as existence of the essential and developed truth
- in this sphere of Right at the same time an externally objective
- existence, as universal authority and necessity.
- The legality of property and of private transactions concerned
- therewith—in consideration of the principle that all law must be
- promulgated, recognised, and thus become authoritative—gets its universal
- guarantee through _formalities_.
- § 531. (3) Legal forms get the necessity, to which objective existence
- determines itself, in the _judicial __ system_. Abstract right has to
- exhibit itself to the _court_—to the individualised right—as _proven_:—a
- process in which there may be a difference between what is abstractly
- right and what is provably right. The court takes cognisance and action in
- the interest of right as such, deprives the existence of right of its
- contingency, and in particular transforms this existence,—as this exists
- as revenge—into _punishment_ (§ 500).
- The comparison of the two species, or rather two elements in the judicial
- conviction, bearing on the actual state of the case in relation to the
- accused,—(1) according as that conviction is based on mere circumstances
- and other people’s witness alone,—or (2) in addition requires the
- confession of the accused, constitutes the main point in the question of
- the so-called jury-courts. It is an essential point that the two
- ingredients of a judicial cognisance, the judgment as to the state of the
- fact, and the judgment as application of the law to it, should, as at
- bottom different sides, be exercised as _different functions_. By the said
- institution they are allotted even to bodies differently qualified,—from
- the one of which individuals belonging to the official judiciary are
- expressly excluded. To carry this separation of functions up to this
- separation in the courts rests rather on extra-essential considerations:
- the main point remains only the separate performance of these essentially
- different functions.—It is a more important point whether the confession
- of the accused is or is not to be made a condition of penal judgment. The
- institution of the jury-court loses sight of this condition. The point is
- that on this ground certainty is completely inseparable from truth: but
- the confession is to be regarded as the very acmé of certainty-giving
- which in its nature is subjective. The final decision therefore lies with
- the confession. To this therefore the accused has an absolute right, if
- the proof is to be made final and the judges to be convinced. No doubt
- this factor is incomplete, because it is only one factor; but still more
- incomplete is the other when no less abstractly taken,—viz. mere
- circumstantial evidence. The jurors are essentially judges and pronounce a
- judgment. In so far, then, as all they have to go on are such objective
- proofs, whilst at the same time their defect of certainty (incomplete in
- so far as it is only _in them_) is admitted, the jury-court shows traces
- of its barbaric origin in a confusion and admixture between objective
- proofs and subjective or so-called “moral” conviction.—It is easy to call
- _extraordinary_ punishments an absurdity; but the fault lies rather with
- the shallowness which takes offence at a mere name. Materially the
- principle involves the difference of objective probation according as it
- goes with or without the factor of absolute certification which lies in
- confession.
- § 532. The function of judicial administration is only to actualise to
- necessity the abstract side of personal liberty in civil society. But this
- actualisation rests at first on the particular subjectivity of the judge,
- since here as yet there is not found the necessary unity of it with right
- in the abstract. Conversely, the blind necessity of the system of wants is
- not lifted up into the consciousness of the universal, and worked from
- that period of view.
- c. Police and Corporation(166).
- § 533. Judicial administration naturally has no concern with such part of
- actions and interests as belongs only to particularity, and leaves to
- chance not only the occurrence of crimes but also the care for public
- weal. In civil society the sole end is to satisfy want—and that, because
- it is man’s want, in a uniform general way, so as to _secure_ this
- satisfaction. But the machinery of social necessity leaves in many ways a
- casualness about this satisfaction. This is due to the variability of the
- wants themselves, in which opinion and subjective good-pleasure play a
- great part. It results also from circumstances of locality, from the
- connexions between nation and nation, from errors and deceptions which can
- be foisted upon single members of the social circulation and are capable
- of creating disorder in it,—as also and especially from the unequal
- capacity of individuals to take advantage of that general stock. The
- onward march of this necessity also sacrifices the very particularities by
- which it is brought about, and does not itself contain the affirmative aim
- of securing the satisfaction of individuals. So far as concerns them, it
- _may_ be far from beneficial: yet here the individuals are the
- morally-justifiable end.
- § 534. To keep in view this general end, to ascertain the way in which the
- powers composing that social necessity act, and their variable
- ingredients, and to maintain that end in them and against them, is the
- work of an institution which assumes on _one_ hand, to the concrete of
- civil society, the position of an external universality. Such an order
- acts with the power of an external state, which, in so far as it is rooted
- in the higher or substantial state, appears as state “police.” On the
- _other_ hand, in this sphere of particularity the only recognition of the
- aim of substantial universality and the only carrying of it out is
- restricted to the business of particular branches and interests. Thus we
- have the _corporation_, in which the particular citizen in his private
- capacity finds the securing of his stock, whilst at the same time he in it
- emerges from his single private interest, and has a conscious activity for
- a comparatively universal end, just as in his legal and professional
- duties he has his social morality.
- CC. The State.
- § 535. The State is the _self-conscious_ ethical substance, the
- unification of the family principle with that of civil society. The same
- unity, which is in the family as a feeling of love, is its essence,
- receiving however at the same time through the second principle of
- conscious and spontaneously active volition the _form_ of conscious
- universality. This universal principle, with all its evolution in detail,
- is the absolute aim and content of the knowing subject, which thus
- identifies itself in its volition with the system of reasonableness.
- § 536. The state is (α) its inward structure as a self-relating
- development—constitutional (inner-state) law: (β) a particular individual,
- and therefore in connexion with other particular
- individuals,—international (outer-state) law; (γ) but these particular
- minds are only stages in the general development of mind in its actuality:
- universal history.
- α. Constitutional Law(167).
- § 537. The essence of the state is the universal, self-originated and
- self-developed,—the reasonable spirit of will; but, as self-knowing and
- self-actualising, sheer subjectivity, and—as an actuality—one individual.
- Its _work_ generally—in relation to the extreme of individuality as the
- multitude of individuals—consists in a double function. First it maintains
- them as persons, thus making right a necessary actuality, then it promotes
- their welfare, which each originally takes care of for himself, but which
- has a thoroughly general side; it protects the family and guides civil
- society. Secondly, it carries back both, and the whole disposition and
- action of the individual—whose tendency is to become a centre of his
- own—into the life of the universal substance; and, in this direction, as a
- free power it interferes with those subordinate spheres and retains them
- in substantial immanence.
- § 538. The laws express the special provisions for objective freedom.
- First, to the immediate agent, his independent self-will and particular
- interest, they are restrictions. But, secondly, they are an absolute final
- end and the universal work: hence they are a product of the “functions” of
- the various orders which parcel themselves more and more out of the
- general particularising, and are a fruit of all the acts and private
- concerns of individuals. Thirdly, they are the substance of the volition
- of individuals—which volition is thereby free—and of their disposition:
- being as such exhibited as current usage.
- § 539. As a living mind, the state only is as an organised whole,
- differentiated into particular agencies, which, proceeding from the one
- notion (though not known as notion) of the reasonable will, continually
- produce it as their result. The _constitution_ is this articulation or
- organisation of state-power. It provides for the reasonable will,—in so
- far as it is in the individuals only _implicitly_ the universal
- will,—coming to a consciousness and an understanding of itself and being
- _found_; also for that will being put in actuality, through the action of
- the government and its several branches, and not left to perish, but
- protected both against _their_ casual subjectivity and against that of the
- individuals. The constitution is existent _justice_,—the actuality of
- liberty in the development all its reasonable provisions.
- Liberty and Equality are the simple rubrics into which is frequently
- concentrated what should form the fundamental principle, the final aim and
- result of the constitution. However true this is, the defect of these
- terms is their utter abstractness: if stuck to in this abstract form, they
- are principles which either prevent the rise of the concreteness of the
- state, i.e. its articulation into a constitution and a government in
- general, or destroy them. With the state there arises inequality, the
- difference of governing powers and of governed, magistracies, authorities,
- directories, &c. The principle of equality, logically carried out, rejects
- all differences, and thus allows no sort of political condition to exist.
- Liberty and equality are indeed the foundation of the state, but as the
- most abstract also the most superficial, and for that very reason
- naturally the most familiar. It is important therefore to study them
- closer.
- As regards, first, Equality, the familiar proposition, All men are by
- nature equal, blunders by confusing the “natural” with the “notion.” It
- ought rather to read: _By nature_ men are only unequal. But the notion of
- liberty, as it exists as such, without further specification and
- development, is abstract subjectivity, as a person capable of property (§
- 488). This single abstract feature of personality constitutes the actual
- _equality_ of human beings. But that this freedom should exist, that it
- should be _man_ (and not as in Greece, Rome, &c. _some_ men) that is
- recognised and legally regarded as a person, is so little _by nature_,
- that it is rather only a result and product of the consciousness of the
- deepest principle of mind, and of the universality and expansion of this
- consciousness. That the citizens are equal before the law contains a great
- truth, but which so expressed is a tautology: it only states that the
- legal status in general exists, that the laws rule. But, as regards the
- concrete, the citizens—besides their personality—are equal before the law
- only in these points when they are otherwise equal _outside the law_. Only
- that equality which (in whatever way it be) they, as it happens, otherwise
- have in property, age, physical strength, talent, skill, &c.—or even in
- crime, can and ought to make them deserve equal treatment before the
- law:—only it can make them—as regards taxation, military service,
- eligibility to office, &c.—punishment, &c.—equal in the concrete. The laws
- themselves, except in so far as they concern that narrow circle of
- personality, presuppose unequal conditions, and provide for the unequal
- legal duties and appurtenances resulting therefrom.
- As regards Liberty, it is originally taken partly in a negative sense
- against arbitrary intolerance and lawless treatment, partly in the
- affirmative sense of subjective freedom; but this freedom is allowed great
- latitude both as regards the agent’s self-will and action for his
- particular ends, and as regards his claim to have a personal intelligence
- and a personal share in general affairs. Formerly the legally defined
- rights, private as well as public rights of a nation, town, &c. were
- called its “liberties.” Really, every genuine law is a liberty: it
- contains a reasonable principle of objective mind; in other words, it
- embodies a liberty. Nothing has become, on the contrary, more familiar
- than the idea that each must _restrict_ his liberty in relation to the
- liberty of others: that the state is a condition of such reciprocal
- restriction, and that the laws are restrictions. To such habits of mind
- liberty is viewed as only casual good-pleasure and self-will. Hence it has
- also been said that “modern” nations are only susceptible of equality, or
- of equality more than liberty: and that for no other reason than that,
- with an assumed definition of liberty (chiefly the participation of all in
- political affairs and actions), it was impossible to make ends meet in
- actuality—which is at once more reasonable and more powerful than abstract
- presuppositions. On the contrary, it should be said that it is just the
- great development and maturity of form in modern states which produces the
- supreme concrete inequality of individuals in actuality: while, through
- the deeper reasonableness of laws and the greater stability of the legal
- state, it gives rise to greater and more stable liberty, which it can
- without incompatibility allow. Even the superficial distinction of the
- words liberty and equality points to the fact that the former tends to
- inequality: whereas, on the contrary, the current notions of liberty only
- carry us back to equality. But the more we fortify liberty,—as security of
- property, as possibility for each to develop and make the best of his
- talents and good qualities, the more it gets taken for granted: and then
- the sense and appreciation of liberty especially turns in a _subjective_
- direction. By this is meant the liberty to attempt action on every side,
- and to throw oneself at pleasure in action for particular and for general
- intellectual interests, the removal of all checks on the individual
- particularity, as well as the inward liberty in which the subject has
- principles, has an insight and conviction of his own, and thus gains moral
- independence. But this liberty itself on one hand implies that supreme
- differentiation in which men are unequal and make themselves more unequal
- by education; and on another it only grows up under conditions of that
- objective liberty, and is and could grow to such height only in modern
- states. If, with this development of particularity, there be simultaneous
- and endless increase of the number of wants, and of the difficulty of
- satisfying them, of the lust of argument and the fancy of detecting
- faults, with its insatiate vanity, it is all but part of that
- indiscriminating relaxation of individuality in this sphere which
- generates all possible complications, and must deal with them as it can.
- Such a sphere is of course also the field of restrictions, because liberty
- is there under the taint of natural self-will and self-pleasing, and has
- therefore to restrict itself: and that, not merely with regard to the
- naturalness, self-will and self-conceit, of others, but especially and
- essentially with regard to reasonable liberty.
- The term political liberty, however, is often used to mean formal
- participation in the public affairs of state by the will and action even
- of those individuals who otherwise find their chief function in the
- particular aims and business of civil society. And it has in part become
- usual to give the title constitution only to the side of the state which
- concerns such participation of these individuals in general affairs, and
- to regard a state, in which this is not formally done, as a state without
- a constitution. On this use of the term, the only thing to remark is that
- by constitution must be understood the determination of rights, i.e. of
- liberties in general, and the organisation of the actualisation of them;
- and that political freedom in the above sense can in any case only
- constitute a part of it. Of it the following paragraphs will speak.
- § 540. The guarantee of a constitution (i.e. the necessity that the laws
- be reasonable, and their actualisation secured) lies in the collective
- spirit of the nation,—especially in the specific way in which it is itself
- conscious of its reason. (Religion is that consciousness in its absolute
- substantiality.) But the guarantee lies also at the same time in the
- actual organisation or development of that principle in suitable
- institutions. The constitution presupposes that consciousness of the
- collective spirit, and conversely that spirit presupposes the
- constitution: for the actual spirit only has a definite consciousness of
- its principles, in so far as it has them actually existent before it.
- The question—To whom (to what authority and how organised) belongs the
- power to make a constitution? is the same as the question, Who has to make
- the spirit of a nation? Separate our idea of a constitution from that of
- the collective spirit, as if the latter exists or has existed without a
- constitution, and your fancy only proves how superficially you have
- apprehended the nexus between the spirit in its self-consciousness and in
- its actuality. What is thus called “making” a “constitution,” is—just
- because of this inseparability—a thing that has never happened in history,
- just as little as the making of a code of laws. A constitution only
- develops from the national spirit identically with that spirit’s own
- development, and runs through at the same time with it the grades of
- formation and the alterations required by its concept. It is the
- indwelling spirit and the history of the nation (and, be it added, the
- history is only that spirit’s history) by which constitutions have been
- and are made.
- § 541. The really living totality,—that which preserves, in other words
- continually produces the state in general and its constitution, is the
- _government_. The organisation which natural necessity gives is seen in
- the rise of the family and of the ’estates’ of civil society. The
- government is the _universal_ part of the constitution, i.e. the part
- which intentionally aims at preserving those parts, but at the same time
- gets hold of and carries out those general aims of the whole which rise
- above the function of the family and of civil society. The organisation of
- the government is likewise its differentiation into powers, as their
- peculiarities have a basis in principle; yet without that difference
- losing touch with the _actual unity_ they have in the notion’s
- subjectivity.
- As the most obvious categories of the notion are those of _universality_
- and _individuality_ and their relationship that of _subsumption_ of
- individual under universal, it has come about that in the state the
- legislative and executive power have been so distinguished as to make the
- former exist apart as the absolute superior, and to subdivide the latter
- again into administrative (government) power and judicial power, according
- as the laws are applied to public or private affairs. The _division_ of
- these powers has been treated as _the_ condition of political equilibrium,
- meaning by division their _independence_ one of another in
- existence,—subject always however to the above-mentioned subsumption of
- the powers of the individual under the power of the general. The theory of
- such “division” unmistakably implies the elements of the notion, but so
- combined by “understanding” as to result in an absurd collocation, instead
- of the self-redintegration of the living spirit. The one essential canon
- to make liberty deep and real is to give every business belonging to the
- general interests of the state a separate organisation wherever they are
- essentially distinct. Such real division must be: for liberty is only deep
- when it is differentiated in all its fullness and these differences
- manifested in existence. But to make the business of legislation an
- independent power—to make it the first power, with the further proviso
- that all citizens shall have part therein, and the government be merely
- executive and dependent, presupposes ignorance that the true idea, and
- therefore the living and spiritual actuality, is the self-redintegrating
- notion, in other words, the subjectivity which contains in it universality
- as only one of its moments. (A mistake still greater, if it goes with the
- fancy that the constitution and the fundamental laws were still one day to
- make,—in a state of society, which includes an already existing
- development of differences.) Individuality is the first and supreme
- principle _which_ makes itself fall through the state’s organisation. Only
- through the government, and by its embracing in itself the particular
- businesses (including the abstract legislative business, which taken apart
- is also particular), is the state _one_. These, as always, are the terms
- on which the different elements essentially and alone truly stand towards
- each other in the logic of “reason,” as opposed to the external footing
- they stand on in ’understanding,’ which never gets beyond subsuming the
- individual and particular under the universal. What disorganises the unity
- of logical reason, equally disorganises actuality.
- § 542. In the government—regarded as organic totality—the sovereign power
- (principate) is (_a_) _subjectivity_ as the _infinite_ self-unity of the
- notion in its development;—the all-sustaining, all-decreeing will of the
- state, its highest peak and all-pervasive unity. In the perfect form of
- the state, in which each and every element of the notion has reached free
- existence, this subjectivity is not a so-called “moral person,” or a
- decree issuing from a majority (forms in which the unity of the decreeing
- will has not an _actual_ existence), but an actual individual,—the will of
- a decreeing individual,—_monarchy_. The monarchical constitution is
- therefore the constitution of developed reason: all other constitutions
- belong to lower grades of the development and realisation of reason.
- The unification of all concrete state-powers into one existence, as in the
- patriarchal society,—or, as in a democratic constitution, the
- participation of all in all affairs—impugns the principle of the division
- of powers, i.e. the developed liberty of the constituent factors of the
- Idea. But no whit less must the division (the working out of these factors
- each to a free totality) be reduced to “ideal” unity, i.e. to
- _subjectivity_. The mature differentiation or realisation of the Idea
- means, essentially, that this subjectivity should grow to be a _real_
- “moment,” an _actual_ existence; and this actuality is not otherwise than
- as the individuality of the monarch—the subjectivity of abstract and final
- decision existent in _one_ person. All those forms of collective decreeing
- and willing,—a common will which shall be the sum and the resultant (on
- aristocratical or democratical principles) of the atomistic of single
- wills, have on them the mark of the unreality of an abstraction. Two
- points only are all-important, first to see the necessity of each of the
- notional factors, and secondly the form in which it is actualised. It is
- only the nature of the speculative notion which can really give light on
- the matter. That subjectivity—being the “moment” which emphasises the need
- of abstract deciding in general—partly leads on to the proviso that the
- name of the monarch appear as the bond and sanction under which everything
- is done in the government;—partly, being simple self-relation, has
- attached to it the characteristic of _immediacy_, and then of
- _nature_—whereby the destination of individuals for the dignity of the
- princely power is fixed by inheritance.
- § 543. (_b_) In the _particular_ government-power there emerges, first,
- the division of state-business into its branches (otherwise defined),
- legislative power, administration of justice or judicial power,
- administration and police, and its consequent distribution between
- particular boards or offices, which having their business appointed by
- law, to that end and for that reason, possess independence of action,
- without at the same time ceasing to stand under higher supervision.
- Secondly, too, there arises the participation of _several_ in
- state-business, who together constitute the “general order” (§ 528) in so
- far as they take on themselves the charge of universal ends as the
- essential function of their particular life;—the further condition for
- being able to take individually part in this business being a certain
- training, aptitude, and skill for such ends.
- § 544. The estates-collegium or provincial council is an institution by
- which all such as belong to civil society in general, and are to that
- degree private persons, participate in the governmental power, especially
- in legislation—viz. such legislation as concerns the universal scope of
- those interests which do not, like peace and war, involve the, as it were,
- personal interference and action of the State as one man, and therefore do
- not belong specially to the province of the sovereign power. By virtue of
- this participation subjective liberty and conceit, with their general
- opinion, can show themselves palpably efficacious and enjoy the
- satisfaction of feeling themselves to count for something.
- The division of constitutions into democracy, aristocracy and monarchy, is
- still the most definite statement of their difference in relation to
- sovereignty. They must at the same time be regarded as necessary
- structures in the path of development,—in short, in the history of the
- State. Hence it is superficial and absurd to represent them as an object
- of _choice_. The pure forms—necessary to the process of evolution—are, in
- so far as they are finite and in course of change, conjoined both with
- forms of their degeneration,—such as ochlocracy, &c., and with earlier
- transition-forms. These two forms are not to be confused with those
- legitimate structures. Thus, it may be—if we look only to the fact that
- the will of one individual stands at the head of the state—oriental
- despotism is included under the vague name monarchy,—as also feudal
- monarchy, to which indeed even the favourite name of “constitutional
- monarchy” cannot be refused. The true difference of these forms from
- genuine monarchy depends on the true value of those principles of right
- which are in vogue and have their actuality and guarantee in the
- state-power. These principles are those expounded earlier, liberty of
- property, and above all personal liberty, civil society, with its industry
- and its communities, and the regulated efficiency of the particular
- bureaux in subordination to the laws.
- The question which is most discussed is in what sense we are to understand
- the participation of private persons in state affairs. For it is as
- private persons that the members of bodies of estates are primarily to be
- taken, be they treated as mere individuals, or as representatives of a
- number of people or of the nation. The aggregate of private persons is
- often spoken of as the _nation_: but as such an aggregate it is _vulgus_,
- not _populus_: and in this direction, it is the one sole aim of the state
- that a nation should _not_ come to existence, to power and action, _as
- such an aggregate_. Such a condition of a nation is a condition of
- lawlessness, demoralisation, brutishness: in it the nation would only be a
- shapeless, wild, blind force, like that of the stormy, elemental sea,
- which however is not self-destructive, as the nation—a spiritual
- element—would be. Yet such a condition may be often heard described as
- that of true freedom. If there is to be any sense in embarking upon the
- question of the participation of private persons in public affairs, it is
- not a brutish mass, but an already organised nation—one in which a
- governmental power exists—which should be presupposed. The desirability of
- such participation however is not to be put in the superiority of
- particular intelligence, which private persons are supposed to have over
- state officials—the contrary may be the case—nor in the superiority of
- their good will for the general best. The members of civil society as such
- are rather people who find their nearest duty in their private interest
- and (as especially in the feudal society) in the interest of their
- privileged corporation. Take the case of _England_ which, because private
- persons have a predominant share in public affairs, has been regarded as
- having the freest of all constitutions. Experience shows that that
- country—as compared with the other civilised states of Europe—is the most
- backward in civil and criminal legislation, in the law and liberty of
- property, in arrangements for art and science, and that objective freedom
- or rational right is rather _sacrificed_ to formal right and particular
- private interest; and that this happens even in the institutions and
- possessions supposed to be dedicated to religion. The desirability of
- private persons taking part in public affairs is partly to be put in their
- concrete, and therefore more urgent, sense of general wants. But the true
- motive is the right of the collective spirit to appear as an _externally
- universal_ will, acting with orderly and express efficacy for the public
- concerns. By this satisfaction of this right it gets its own life
- quickened, and at the same time breathes fresh life in the administrative
- officials; who thus have it brought home to them that not merely have they
- to enforce duties but also to have regard to rights. Private citizens are
- in the state the incomparably greater number, and form the multitude of
- such as are recognised as persons. Hence the will-reason exhibits its
- existence in them as a preponderating majority of freemen, or in its
- “reflectional” universality, which has its actuality vouchsafed it as a
- participation in the sovereignty. But it has already been noted as a
- “moment” of civil society (§§ 527, 534) that the individuals rise from
- external into substantial universality, and form a _particular_ kind,—the
- Estates: and it is not in the inorganic form of mere individuals as such
- (after the _democratic_ fashion of election), but as organic factors, as
- estates, that they enter upon that participation. In the state a power or
- agency must never appear and act as a formless, inorganic shape, i.e.
- basing itself on the principle of multeity and mere numbers.
- Assemblies of Estates have been wrongly designated as the _legislative
- power_, so far as they form only one branch of that power,—a branch in
- which the special government-officials have an _ex officio_ share, while
- the sovereign power has the privilege of final decision. In a civilised
- state moreover legislation can only be a further modification of existing
- law, and so-called new laws can only deal with minutiae of detail and
- particularities (cf. § 529, note), the main drift of which has been
- already prepared or preliminarily settled by the practice of the
- law-courts. The so-called _financial law_, in so far as it requires the
- assent of the estates, is really a government affair: it is only
- improperly called a law, in the general sense of embracing a wide, indeed
- the whole, range of the external means of government. The finances deal
- with what in their nature are only particular needs, ever newly recurring,
- even if they touch on the sum total of such needs. If the main part of the
- requirement were—as it very likely is—regarded as permanent, the provision
- for it would have more the nature of a law: but to be a law, it would have
- to be made once for all, and not be made yearly, or every few years,
- afresh. The part which varies according to time and circumstances concerns
- in reality the smallest part of the amount, and the provisions with regard
- to it have even less the character of a law: and yet it is and may be only
- this slight variable part which is matter of dispute, and can be subjected
- to a varying yearly estimate. It is this last then which falsely bears the
- high-sounding name of the “_Grant_” of the _Budget_, i.e. of the whole of
- the finances. A law for one year and made each year has even to the plain
- man something palpably absurd: for he distinguishes the essential and
- developed universal, as content of a true law, from the reflectional
- universality which only externally embraces what in its nature is many. To
- give the name of a law to the annual fixing of financial requirements only
- serves—with the presupposed separation of legislative from executive—to
- keep up the illusion of that separation having real existence, and to
- conceal the fact that the legislative power, when it makes a decree about
- finance, is really engaged with strict executive business. But the
- importance attached to the power of from time to time granting “supply,”
- on the ground that the assembly of estates possesses in it a _check_ on
- the government, and thus a guarantee against injustice and violence,—this
- importance is in one way rather plausible than real. The financial
- measures necessary for the state’s subsistence cannot be made conditional
- on any other circumstances, nor can the state’s subsistence be put yearly
- in doubt. It would be a parallel absurdity if the government were e.g. to
- grant and arrange the judicial institutions always for a limited time
- merely; and thus, by the threat of suspending the activity of such an
- institution and the fear of a consequent state of brigandage, reserve for
- itself a means of coercing private individuals. Then again, the pictures
- of a condition of affairs, in which it might be useful and necessary to
- have in hand means of compulsion, are partly based on the false conception
- of a contract between rulers and ruled, and partly presuppose the
- possibility of such a divergence in spirit between these two parties as
- would make constitution and government quite out of the question. If we
- suppose the empty possibility of getting _help_ by such compulsive means
- brought into existence, such help would rather be the derangement and
- dissolution of the state, in which there would no longer be a government,
- but only parties, and the violence and oppression of one party would only
- be helped away by the other. To fit together the several parts of the
- state into a constitution after the fashion of mere understanding—i.e. to
- adjust within it the machinery of a balance of powers external to each
- other—is to contravene the fundamental idea of what a state is.
- § 545. The final aspect of the state is to appear in immediate actuality
- as a single nation marked by physical conditions. As a single individual
- it is exclusive against other like individuals. In their mutual relations,
- waywardness and chance have a place; for each person in the aggregate is
- autonomous: the universal of law is only postulated between them, and not
- actually existent. This independence of a central authority reduces
- disputes between them to terms of mutual violence, a _state of war_, to
- meet which the general estate in the community assumes the particular
- function of maintaining the state’s independence against other states, and
- becomes the estate of bravery.
- § 546. This state of war shows the omnipotence of the state in its
- individuality—an individuality that goes even to abstract negativity.
- Country and fatherland then appear as the power by which the particular
- independence of individuals and their absorption in the external existence
- of possession and in natural life is convicted of its own nullity,—as the
- power which procures the maintenance of the general substance by the
- patriotic sacrifice on the part of these individuals of this natural and
- particular existence,—so making nugatory the nugatoriness that confronts
- it.
- β. External Public Law(168).
- § 547. In the game of war the independence of States is at stake. In one
- case the result may be the mutual recognition of free national
- individualities (§ 430): and by peace-conventions supposed to be for ever,
- both this general recognition, and the special claims of nations on one
- another, are settled and fixed. External state-rights rest partly on these
- positive treaties, but to that extent contain only rights falling short of
- true actuality (§ 545): partly on so-called _international_ law, the
- general principle of which is its presupposed recognition by the several
- States. It thus restricts their otherwise unchecked action against one
- another in such a way that the possibility of peace is left; and
- distinguishes individuals as private persons (non-belligerents) from the
- state. In general, international law rests on social usage.
- γ. Universal History(169).
- § 548. As the mind of a special nation is actual and its liberty is under
- natural conditions, it admits on this nature-side the influence of
- geographical and climatic qualities. It is in time; and as regards its
- range and scope, has essentially a _particular_ principle on the lines of
- which it must run through a development of its consciousness and its
- actuality. It has, in short, a history of its own. But as a restricted
- mind its independence is something secondary; it passes into universal
- world-history, the events of which exhibit the dialectic of the several
- national minds,—the judgment of the world.
- § 549. This movement is the path of liberation for the spiritual
- substance, the deed by which the absolute final aim of the world is
- realised in it, and the merely implicit mind achieves consciousness and
- self-consciousness. It is thus the revelation and actuality of its
- essential and completed essence, whereby it becomes to the outward eye a
- universal spirit—a world-mind. As this development is in time and in real
- existence, as it is a history, its several stages and steps are the
- national minds, each of which, as single and endued by nature with a
- specific character, is appointed to occupy only one grade, and accomplish
- one task in the whole deed.
- The presupposition that history has an essential and actual end, from the
- principles of which certain characteristic results logically flow, is
- called an _a priori_ view of it, and philosophy is reproached with _a
- priori_ history-writing. On this point, and on history-writing in general,
- this note must go into further detail. That history, and above all
- universal history, is founded on an essential and actual aim, which
- actually is and will be realised in it—the plan of Providence; that, in
- short, there is Reason in history, must be decided on strictly
- philosophical ground, and thus shown to be essentially and in fact
- necessary. To presuppose such aim is blameworthy only when the assumed
- conceptions or thoughts are arbitrarily adopted, and when a determined
- attempt is made to force events and actions into conformity with such
- conceptions. For such _a priori_ methods of treatment at the present day,
- however, those are chiefly to blame who profess to be purely historical,
- and who at the same time take opportunity expressly to raise their voice
- against the habit of philosophising, first in general, and then in
- history. Philosophy is to them a troublesome neighbour: for it is an enemy
- of all arbitrariness and hasty suggestions. Such _a priori_
- history-writing has sometimes burst out in quarters where one would least
- have expected it, especially on the philological side, and in Germany more
- than in France and England, where the art of historical writing has gone
- through a process of purification to a firmer and maturer character.
- Fictions, like that of a primitive age and its primitive people, possessed
- from the first of the true knowledge of God and all the sciences,—of
- sacerdotal races,—and, when we come to minutiae, of a Roman epic, supposed
- to be the source of the legends which pass current for the history of
- ancient Rome, &c., have taken the place of the pragmatising which detected
- psychological motives and associations. There is a wide circle of persons
- who seem to consider it incumbent on a _learned_ and _ingenious_ historian
- drawing from the original sources to concoct such baseless fancies, and
- form bold combinations of them from a learned rubbish-heap of
- out-of-the-way and trivial facts, in defiance of the best-accredited
- history.
- Setting aside this subjective treatment of history, we find what is
- properly the opposite view forbidding us to import into history an
- _objective purpose_. This is after all synonymous with what _seems_ to be
- the still more legitimate demand that the historian should proceed with
- _impartiality_. This is a requirement often and especially made on the
- _history of philosophy_: where it is insisted there should be no
- prepossession in favour of an idea or opinion, just as a judge should have
- no special sympathy for one of the contending parties. In the case of the
- judge it is at the same time assumed that he would administer his office
- ill and foolishly, if he had not an interest, and an exclusive interest in
- justice, if he had not that for his aim and one sole aim, or if he
- declined to judge at all. This requirement which we may make upon the
- judge may be called _partiality_ for justice; and there is no difficulty
- here in distinguishing it from _subjective_ partiality. But in speaking of
- the impartiality required from the historian, this self-satisfied insipid
- chatter lets the distinction disappear, and rejects both kinds of
- interest. It demands that the historian shall bring with him no definite
- aim and view by which he may sort out, state and criticise events, but
- shall narrate them exactly in the casual mode he finds them, in their
- incoherent and unintelligent particularity. Now it is at least admitted
- that a history must have an object, e.g. Rome and its fortunes, or the
- Decline of the grandeur of the Roman empire. But little reflection is
- needed to discover that this is the presupposed end which lies at the
- basis of the events themselves, as of the critical examination into their
- comparative importance, i.e. their nearer or more remote relation to it. A
- history without such aim and such criticism would be only an imbecile
- mental divagation, not as good as a fairy tale, for even children expect a
- _motif_ in their stories, a purpose at least dimly surmiseable with which
- events and actions are put in relation.
- In the existence of a _nation_ the substantial aim is to be a state and
- preserve itself as such. A nation with no state formation, (a _mere
- nation_), has strictly speaking no history,—like the nations which existed
- before the rise of states and others which still exist in a condition of
- savagery. What happens to a nation, and takes place within it, has its
- essential significance in relation to the state: whereas the mere
- particularities of individuals are at the greatest distance from the true
- object of history. It is true that the general spirit of an age leaves its
- imprint in the character of its celebrated individuals, and even their
- particularities are but the very distant and the dim media through which
- the collective light still plays in fainter colours. Ay, even such
- singularities as a petty occurrence, a word, express not a subjective
- particularity, but an age, a nation, a civilisation, in striking
- portraiture and brevity; and to select such trifles shows the hand of a
- historian of genius. But, on the other hand, the main mass of
- singularities is a futile and useless mass, by the painstaking
- accumulation of which the objects of real historical value are overwhelmed
- and obscured. The essential characteristic of the spirit and its age is
- always contained in the great events. It was a correct instinct which
- sought to banish such portraiture of the particular and the gleaning of
- insignificant traits, into the _Novel_ (as in the celebrated romances of
- Walter Scott, &c.). Where the picture presents an unessential aspect of
- life it is certainly in good taste to conjoin it with an unessential
- material, such as the romance takes from private events and subjective
- passions. But to take the individual pettinesses of an age and of the
- persons in it, and, in the interest of so-called truth, weave them into
- the picture of general interests, is not only against taste and judgment,
- but violates the principles of objective truth. The only truth for mind is
- the substantial and underlying essence, and not the trivialities of
- external existence and contingency. It is therefore completely indifferent
- whether such insignificancies are duly vouched for by documents, or, as in
- the romance, invented to suit the character and ascribed to this or that
- name and circumstances.
- The point of interest of _Biography_—to say a word on that here—appears to
- run directly counter to any universal scope and aim. But biography too has
- for its background the historical world, with which the individual is
- intimately bound up: even purely personal originality, the freak of
- humour, &c. suggests by allusion that central reality and has its interest
- heightened by the suggestion. The mere play of sentiment, on the contrary,
- has another ground and interest than history.
- The requirement of impartiality addressed to the history of philosophy
- (and also, we may add, to the history of religion, first in general, and
- secondly, to church history) generally implies an even more decided bar
- against presupposition of any objective aim. As the State was already
- called the point to which in political history criticism had to refer all
- events, so here the “_Truth_” must be the object to which the several
- deeds and events of the spirit would have to be referred. What is actually
- done is rather to make the contrary presupposition. Histories with such an
- object as religion or philosophy are understood to have only subjective
- aims for their theme, i.e. only opinions and mere ideas, not an essential
- and realised object like the truth. And that with the mere excuse that
- there is no truth. On this assumption the sympathy with truth appears as
- only a partiality of the usual sort, a partiality for opinion and mere
- ideas, which all alike have no stuff in them, and are all treated as
- indifferent. In that way historical truth means but correctness—an
- accurate report of externals, without critical treatment save as regards
- this correctness—admitting, in this case, only qualitative and
- quantitative judgments, no judgments of necessity or notion (cf. notes to
- §§ 172 and 175). But, really, if Rome or the German empire, &c. are an
- actual and genuine object of political history, and the aim to which the
- phenomena are to be related and by which they are to be judged; then in
- universal history the genuine spirit, the consciousness of it and of its
- essence, is even in a higher degree a true and actual object and theme,
- and an aim to which all other phenomena are essentially and actually
- subservient. Only therefore through their relationship to it, i.e. through
- the judgment in which they are subsumed under it, while it inheres in
- them, have they their value and even their existence. It is the spirit
- which not merely broods _over_ history as over the waters, but lives in it
- and is alone its principle of movement: and in the path of that spirit,
- liberty, i.e. a development determined by the notion of spirit, is the
- guiding principle and only its notion its final aim, i.e. truth. For
- Spirit is consciousness. Such a doctrine—or in other words that Reason is
- in history—will be partly at least a plausible faith, partly it is a
- cognition of philosophy.
- § 550. This liberation of mind, in which it proceeds to come to itself and
- to realise its truth, and the business of so doing, is the supreme right,
- the absolute Law. The self-consciousness of a particular nation is a
- vehicle for the contemporary development of the collective spirit in its
- actual existence: it is the objective actuality in which that spirit for
- the time invests its will. Against this absolute will the other particular
- natural minds have no rights: _that_ nation dominates the world: but yet
- the universal will steps onward over its property for the time being, as
- over a special grade, and then delivers it over to its chance and doom.
- § 551. To such extent as this business of actuality appears as an action,
- and therefore as a work of _individuals_, these individuals, as regards
- the substantial issue of their labour, are _instruments_, and their
- subjectivity, which is what is peculiar to them, is the empty form of
- activity. What they personally have gained therefore through the
- individual share they took in the substantial business (prepared and
- appointed independently of them) is a formal universality or subjective
- mental idea—_Fame_, which is their reward.
- § 552. The national spirit contains nature-necessity, and stands in
- external existence (§ 423): the ethical substance, potentially infinite,
- is actually a particular and limited substance (§§ 549, 550); on its
- subjective side it labours under contingency, in the shape of its
- unreflective natural usages, and its content is presented to it as
- something _existing_ in time and tied to an external nature and external
- world. The spirit, however, (which _thinks_ in this moral organism)
- overrides and absorbs within itself the finitude attaching to it as
- national spirit in its state and the state’s temporal interests, in the
- system of laws and usages. It rises to apprehend itself in its
- essentiality. Such apprehension, however, still has the immanent
- limitedness of the national spirit. But the spirit which thinks in
- universal history, stripping off at the same time those limitations of the
- several national minds and its own temporal restrictions, lays hold of its
- concrete universality, and rises to apprehend the absolute mind, as the
- eternally actual truth in which the contemplative reason enjoys freedom,
- while the necessity of nature and the necessity of history are only
- ministrant to its revelation and the vessels of its honour.
- The strictly technical aspects of the Mind’s elevation to God have been
- spoken of in the Introduction to the Logic (cf. especially § 51, note). As
- regards the starting-point of that elevation, Kant has on the whole
- adopted the most correct, when he treats belief in God as proceeding from
- the practical Reason. For that starting-point contains the material or
- content which constitutes the content of the notion of God. But the true
- concrete material is neither Being (as in the cosmological) nor mere
- action by design (as in the physico-theological proof) but the Mind, the
- absolute characteristic and function of which is effective reason, i.e.
- the self-determining and self-realising notion itself,—Liberty. That the
- elevation of subjective mind to God which these considerations give is by
- Kant again deposed to a _postulate_—a mere “ought”—is the peculiar
- perversity, formerly noticed, of calmly and simply reinstating as true and
- valid that very antithesis of finitude, the supersession of which into
- truth is the essence of that elevation.
- As regards the “mediation” which, as it has been already shown (§ 192, cf.
- § 204 note), that elevation to God really involves, the point specially
- calling for note is the “moment” of negation through which the essential
- content of the starting-point is purged of its finitude so as to come
- forth free. This factor, abstract in the formal treatment of logic, now
- gets its most concrete interpretation. The finite, from which the start is
- now made, is the real ethical self-consciousness. The negation through
- which that consciousness raises its spirit to its truth, is the
- purification, _actually_ accomplished in the ethical world, whereby its
- conscience is purged of subjective opinion and its will freed from the
- selfishness of desire. Genuine religion and genuine religiosity only issue
- from the moral life: religion is that life rising to think, i.e. becoming
- aware of the free universality of its concrete essence. Only from the
- moral life and by the moral life is the Idea of God seen to be free
- spirit: outside the ethical spirit therefore it is vain to seek for true
- religion and religiosity.
- But—as is the case with all speculative process—this development of one
- thing out of another means that what appears as sequel and derivative is
- rather the absolute _prius_ of what it appears to be mediated by, and what
- is here in mind known as its truth.
- Here then is the place to go more deeply into the reciprocal relations
- between the state and religion, and in doing so to elucidate the
- terminology which is familiar and current on the topic. It is evident and
- apparent from what has preceded that moral life is the state retracted
- into its inner heart and substance, while the state is the organisation
- and actualisation of moral life; and that religion is the very substance
- of the moral life itself and of the state. At this rate, the state rests
- on the ethical sentiment, and that on the religious. If religion then is
- the consciousness of “absolute”_ truth_, then whatever is to rank as right
- and justice, as law and duty, i.e. as _true_ in the world of free will,
- can be so esteemed only as it is participant in that truth, as it is
- subsumed under it and is its sequel. But if the truly moral life is to be
- a sequel of religion, then perforce religion must have the _genuine_
- content; i.e. the idea of God it knows must be the true and real. The
- ethical life is the divine spirit as indwelling in self-consciousness, as
- it is actually present in a nation and its individual members. This
- self-consciousness retiring upon itself out of its empirical actuality and
- bringing its truth to consciousness, has in its _faith_ and in its
- _conscience_ only what it has consciously secured in its spiritual
- actuality. The two are inseparable: there cannot be two kinds of
- conscience, one religious and another ethical, differing from the former
- in body and value of truth. But in point of form, i.e. for thought and
- knowledge—(and religion and ethical life belong to intelligence and are a
- thinking and knowing)—the body of religious truth, as the pure
- self-subsisting and therefore supreme truth, exercises a sanction over the
- moral life which lies in empirical actuality. Thus for self-consciousness
- religion is the “basis” of moral life and of the state. It has been the
- monstrous blunder of our times to try to look upon these inseparables as
- separable from one another, and even as mutually indifferent. The view
- taken of the relationship of religion and the state has been that, whereas
- the state had an independent existence of its own, springing from some
- force and power, religion was a later addition, something desirable
- perhaps for strengthening the political bulwarks, but purely subjective in
- individuals:—or it may be, religion is treated as something without effect
- on the moral life of the state, i.e. its reasonable law and constitution
- which are based on a ground of their own.
- As the inseparability of the two sides has been indicated, it may be worth
- while to note the separation as it appears on the side of religion. It is
- primarily a point of form: the attitude which self-consciousness takes to
- the body of truth. So long as this body of truth is the very substance or
- indwelling spirit of self-consciousness in its actuality, then
- self-consciousness in this content has the certainty of itself and is
- free. But if this present self-consciousness is lacking, then there may be
- created, in point of form, a condition of spiritual slavery, even though
- the _implicit_ content of religion is absolute spirit. This great
- difference (to cite a specific case) comes out within the Christian
- religion itself, even though here it is not the nature-element in which
- the idea of God is embodied, and though nothing of the sort even enters as
- a factor into its central dogma and sole theme of a God who is known in
- spirit and in truth. And yet in Catholicism this spirit of all truth is in
- actuality set in rigid opposition to the self-conscious spirit. And, first
- of all, God is in the “host” presented to religious adoration as an
- _external thing_. (In the Lutheran Church, on the contrary, the host as
- such is not at first consecrated, but in the moment of enjoyment, i.e. in
- the annihilation of its externality, and in the act of faith, i.e. in the
- free self-certain spirit: only then is it consecrated and exalted to be
- present God.) From that first and supreme status of externalisation flows
- every other phase of externality,—of bondage, non-spirituality, and
- superstition. It leads to a laity, receiving its knowledge of divine
- truth, as well as the direction of its will and conscience from without
- and from another order—which order again does not get possession of that
- knowledge in a spiritual way only, but to that end essentially requires an
- external consecration. It leads to the non-spiritual style of
- praying—partly as mere moving of the lips, partly in the way that the
- subject foregoes his right of directly addressing God, and prays others to
- pray—addressing his devotion to miracle-working images, even to bones, and
- expecting miracles from them. It leads, generally, to justification by
- external works, a merit which is supposed to be gained by acts, and even
- to be capable of being transferred to others. All this binds the spirit
- under an externalism by which the very meaning of spirit is perverted and
- misconceived at its source, and law and justice, morality and conscience,
- responsibility and duty are corrupted at their root.
- Along with this principle of spiritual bondage, and these applications of
- it in the religious life, there can only go in the legislative and
- constitutional system a legal and moral bondage, and a state of
- lawlessness and immorality in political life. Catholicism has been loudly
- praised and is still often praised—logically enough—as the one religion
- which secures the stability of governments. But in reality this applies
- only to governments which are bound up with institutions founded on the
- bondage of the spirit (of that spirit which should have legal and moral
- liberty), i.e. with institutions that embody injustice and with a morally
- corrupt and barbaric state of society. But these governments are not aware
- that in fanaticism they have a terrible power, which does not rise in
- hostility against them, only so long as and only on condition that they
- remain sunk in the thraldom of injustice and immorality. But in mind there
- is a very different power available against that externalism and
- dismemberment induced by a false religion. Mind collects itself into its
- inward free actuality. Philosophy awakes in the spirit of governments and
- nations the wisdom to discern what is essentially and actually right and
- reasonable in the real world. It was well to call these products of
- thought, and in a special sense Philosophy, the wisdom of the world(170);
- for thought makes the spirit’s truth an actual present, leads it into the
- real world, and thus liberates it in its actuality and in its own self.
- Thus set free, the content of religion assumes quite another shape. So
- long as the form, i.e. our consciousness and subjectivity, lacked liberty,
- it followed necessarily that self-consciousness was conceived as not
- immanent in the ethical principles which religion embodies, and these
- principles were set at such a distance as to seem to have true being only
- as negative to actual self-consciousness. In this unreality ethical
- content gets the name of _Holiness_. But once the divine spirit introduces
- itself into actuality, and actuality emancipates itself to spirit, then
- what in the world was a postulate of holiness is supplanted by the
- actuality of _moral_ life. Instead of the vow of chastity, _marriage_ now
- ranks as the ethical relation; and, therefore, as the highest on this side
- of humanity stands the family. Instead of the vow of poverty (muddled up
- into a contradiction of assigning merit to whosoever gives away goods to
- the poor, i.e. whosoever enriches them) is the precept of action to
- acquire goods through one’s own intelligence and industry,—of honesty in
- commercial dealing, and in the use of property,—in short moral life in the
- socio-economic sphere. And instead of the vow of obedience, true religion
- sanctions obedience to the law and the legal arrangements of the state—an
- obedience which is itself the true freedom, because the state is a
- self-possessed, self-realising reason—in short, moral life in the state.
- Thus, and thus only, can law and morality exist. The precept of religion,
- “Give to Caesar what is Caesar’s and to God what is God’s” is not enough:
- the question is to settle what is Caesar’s, what belongs to the secular
- authority: and it is sufficiently notorious that the secular no less than
- the ecclesiastical authority have claimed almost everything as their own.
- The divine spirit must interpenetrate the entire secular life: whereby
- wisdom is concrete within it, and it carries the terms of its own
- justification. But that concrete indwelling is only the aforesaid ethical
- organisations. It is the morality of marriage as against the sanctity of a
- celibate order;—the morality of economic and industrial action against the
- sanctity of poverty and its indolence;—the morality of an obedience
- dedicated to the law of the state as against the sanctity of an obedience
- from which law and duty are absent and where conscience is enslaved. With
- the growing need for law and morality and the sense of the spirit’s
- essential liberty, there sets in a conflict of spirit with the religion of
- unfreedom. It is no use to organise political laws and arrangements on
- principles of equity and reason, so long as in religion the principle of
- unfreedom is not abandoned. A free state and a slavish religion are
- incompatible. It is silly to suppose that we may try to allot them
- separate spheres, under the impression that their diverse natures will
- maintain an attitude of tranquillity one to another and not break out in
- contradiction and battle. Principles of civil freedom can be but abstract
- and superficial, and political institutions deduced from them must be, if
- taken alone, untenable, so long as those principles in their wisdom
- mistake religion so much as not to know that the maxims of the reason in
- actuality have their last and supreme sanction in the religious conscience
- in subsumption under the consciousness of “absolute” truth. Let us suppose
- even that, no matter how, a code of law should arise, so to speak _a
- priori_, founded on principles of reason, but in contradiction with an
- established religion based on principles of spiritual unfreedom; still, as
- the duty of carrying out the laws lies in the hands of individual members
- of the government, and of the various classes of the administrative
- _personnel_, it is vain to delude ourselves with the abstract and empty
- assumption that the individuals will act only according to the letter or
- meaning of the law, and not in the spirit of their religion where their
- inmost conscience and supreme obligation lies. Opposed to what religion
- pronounces holy, the laws appear something made by human hands: even
- though backed by penalties and externally introduced, they could offer no
- lasting resistance to the contradiction and attacks of the religious
- spirit. Such laws, however sound their provisions may be, thus founder on
- the conscience, whose spirit is different from the spirit of the laws and
- refuses to sanction them. It is nothing but a modern folly to try to alter
- a corrupt moral organisation by altering its political constitution and
- code of laws without changing the religion,—to make a revolution without
- having made a reformation, to suppose that a political constitution
- opposed to the old religion could live in peace and harmony with it and
- its sanctities, and that stability could be procured for the laws by
- external guarantees, e.g. so-called “chambers,” and the power given them
- to fix the budget, &c. (cf. § 544 note). At best it is only a temporary
- expedient—when it is obviously too great a task to descend into the depths
- of the religious spirit and to raise that same spirit to its truth—to seek
- to separate law and justice from religion. Those guarantees are but rotten
- bulwarks against the consciences of the persons charged with administering
- the laws—among which laws these guarantees are included. It is indeed the
- height and profanity of contradiction to seek to bind and subject to the
- secular code the religious conscience to which mere human law is a thing
- profane.
- The perception had dawned upon Plato with great clearness of the gulf
- which in his day had commenced to divide the established religion and the
- political constitution, on one hand, from those deeper requirements which,
- on the other hand, were made upon religion and politics by liberty which
- had learnt to recognise its inner life. Plato gets hold of the thought
- that a genuine constitution and a sound political life have their deeper
- foundation on the Idea,—on the essentially and actually universal and
- genuine principles of eternal righteousness. Now to see and ascertain what
- these are is certainly the function and the business of _philosophy_. It
- is from this point of view that Plato breaks out into the celebrated or
- notorious passage where he makes Socrates emphatically state that
- philosophy and political power must coincide, that the Idea must be
- regent, if the distress of nations is to see its end. What Plato thus
- definitely set before his mind was that the Idea—which implicitly indeed
- is the free self-determining thought—could not get into consciousness save
- only in the form of a thought; that the substance of the thought could
- only be true when set forth as a universal, and as such brought to
- consciousness under its most abstract form.
- To compare the Platonic standpoint in all its definiteness with the point
- of view from which the relationship of state and religion is here
- regarded, the notional differences on which everything turns must be
- recalled to mind. The first of these is that in natural things their
- substance or genus is different from their existence in which that
- substance is as subject: further that this subjective existence of the
- genus is distinct from that which it gets, when specially set in relief as
- genus, or, to put it simply, as the universal in a mental concept or idea.
- This additional “individuality”—the soil on which the universal and
- underlying principle _freely_ and expressly exists,—is the intellectual
- and thinking _self_. In the case of _natural_ things their truth and
- reality does not get the form of universality and essentiality through
- themselves, and their “individuality” is not itself the form: the form is
- only found in subjective thinking, which in philosophy gives that
- universal truth and reality an existence of its own. In man’s case it is
- otherwise: his truth and reality is the free mind itself, and it comes to
- existence in his self-consciousness. This absolute nucleus of man—mind
- intrinsically concrete—is just this—to have the form (to have thinking)
- itself for a content. To the height of the thinking consciousness of this
- principle Aristotle ascended in his notion of the entelechy of thought,
- (which is νοῆσις τῆς νοήσεως), thus surmounting the Platonic Idea (the
- genus, or essential being). But thought always—and that on account of this
- very principle—contains the immediate self-subsistence of subjectivity no
- less than it contains universality; the genuine Idea of the intrinsically
- concrete mind is just as essentially under the one of its terms
- (subjective consciousness) as under the other (universality): and in the
- one as in the other it is the same substantial content. Under the
- subjective form, however, fall feeling, intuition, pictorial
- representation: and it is in fact necessary that in point of time the
- consciousness of the absolute Idea should be first reached and apprehended
- in this form: in other words, it must exist in its immediate reality as
- religion, earlier than it does as philosophy. Philosophy is a later
- development from this basis (just as Greek philosophy itself is later than
- Greek religion), and in fact reaches its completion by catching and
- comprehending in all its definite essentiality that principle of spirit
- which first manifests itself in religion. But Greek philosophy could set
- itself up only in opposition to Greek religion: the unity of thought and
- the substantiality of the Idea could take up none but a hostile attitude
- to an imaginative polytheism, and to the gladsome and frivolous humours of
- its poetic creations. The _form_ in its infinite truth, the _subjectivity_
- of mind, broke forth at first only as a subjective free _thinking_, which
- was not yet identical with the _substantiality_ itself,—and thus this
- underlying principle was not yet apprehended as _absolute mind_. Thus
- religion might appear as first purified only through philosophy,—through
- pure self-existent thought: but the form pervading this underlying
- principle—the form which philosophy attacked—was that creative
- imagination.
- Political power, which is developed similarly, but earlier than
- philosophy, from religion, exhibits the onesidedness, which in the actual
- world may infect its _implicitly_ true Idea, as demoralisation. Plato, in
- common with all his thinking contemporaries, perceived this demoralisation
- of democracy and the defectiveness even of its principle; he set in relief
- accordingly the underlying principle of the state, but could not work into
- his idea of it the infinite form of subjectivity, which still escaped his
- intelligence. His state is therefore, on its own showing, wanting in
- subjective liberty (§ 503 note, § 513, &c.). The truth which should be
- immanent in the state, should knit it together and control it, he, for
- these reasons, got hold of only the form of thought-out truth, of
- philosophy; and hence he makes that utterance that “so long as
- philosophers do not rule in the states, or those who are now called kings
- and rulers do not soundly and comprehensively philosophise, so long
- neither the state nor the race of men can be liberated from evils,—so long
- will the idea of the political constitution fall short of possibility and
- not see the light of the sun.” It was not vouchsafed to Plato to go on so
- far as to say that so long as true religion did not spring up in the world
- and hold sway in political life, so long the genuine principle of the
- state had not come into actuality. But so long too this principle could
- not emerge even in thought, nor could thought lay hold of the genuine idea
- of the state,—the idea of the substantial moral life, with which is
- identical the liberty of an independent self-consciousness. Only in the
- principle of mind, which is aware of its own essence, is implicitly in
- absolute liberty, and has its actuality in the act of self-liberation,
- does the absolute possibility and necessity exist for political power,
- religion, and the principles of philosophy coinciding in one, and for
- accomplishing the reconciliation of actuality in general with the mind, of
- the state with the religious conscience as well as with the philosophical
- consciousness. Self-realising subjectivity is in this case absolutely
- identical with substantial universality. Hence religion as such, and the
- state as such,—both as forms in which the principle exists—each contain
- the absolute truth: so that the truth, in its philosophic phase, is after
- all only in one of its forms. But even religion, as it grows and expands,
- lets other aspects of the Idea of humanity grow and expand also (§ 500
- sqq.). As it is left therefore behind, in its first immediate, and so also
- one-sided phase, Religion may, or rather _must_, appear in its existence
- degraded to sensuous externality, and thus in the sequel become an
- influence to oppress liberty of spirit and to deprave political life.
- Still the principle has in it the infinite “elasticity” of the “absolute”
- form, so as to overcome this depraving of the form-determination (and of
- the content by these means), and to bring about the reconciliation of the
- spirit in itself. Thus ultimately, in the Protestant conscience the
- principles of the religious and of the ethical conscience come to be one
- and the same: the free spirit learning to see itself in its reasonableness
- and truth. In the Protestant state, the constitution and the code, as well
- as their several applications, embody the principle and the development of
- the moral life, which proceeds and can only proceed from the truth of
- religion, when reinstated in its original principle and in that way as
- such first become actual. The moral life of the state and the religious
- spirituality of the state are thus reciprocal guarantees of strength.
- SECTION III. ABSOLUTE MIND(171).
- § 553. The _notion_ of mind has its _reality_ in the mind. If this reality
- in identity with that notion is to exist as the consciousness of the
- absolute Idea, then the necessary aspect is that the _implicitly_ free
- intelligence be in its actuality liberated to its notion, if that
- actuality is to be a vehicle worthy of it. The subjective and the
- objective spirit are to be looked on as the road on which this aspect of
- _reality_ or existence rises to maturity.
- § 554. The absolute mind, while it is self-centred _identity_, is always
- also identity returning and ever returned into itself: if it is the one
- and universal _substance_ it is so as a spirit, discerning itself into a
- self and a consciousness, for which it is as substance. _Religion_, as
- this supreme sphere may be in general designated, if it has on one hand to
- be studied as issuing from the subject and having its home in the subject,
- must no less be regarded as objectively issuing from the absolute spirit
- which as spirit is in its community.
- That here, as always, belief or faith is not opposite to consciousness or
- knowledge, but rather to a sort of knowledge, and that belief is only a
- particular form of the latter, has been remarked already (§ 63 note). If
- nowadays there is so little consciousness of God, and his objective
- essence is so little dwelt upon, while people speak so much more of the
- subjective side of religion, i.e. of God’s indwelling in us, and if that
- and not the truth as such is called for,—in this there is at least the
- correct principle that God must be apprehended as spirit in his community.
- § 555. The subjective consciousness of the absolute spirit is essentially
- and intrinsically a process, the immediate and substantial unity of which
- is the _Belief_ in the witness of the spirit as the _certainty_ of
- objective truth. Belief, at once this immediate unity and containing it as
- a reciprocal dependence of these different terms, has in _devotion_—the
- implicit or more explicit act of worship (_cultus_)—passed over into the
- process of superseding the contrast till it becomes spiritual liberation,
- the process of authenticating that first certainty by this intermediation,
- and of gaining its concrete determination, viz. reconciliation, the
- actuality of the spirit.
- Sub-Section A. Art.
- § 556. As this consciousness of the Absolute first takes shape, its
- immediacy produces the factor of finitude in Art. On one hand that is, it
- breaks up into a work of external common existence, into the subject which
- produces that work, and the subject which contemplates and worships it.
- But, on the other hand, it is the concrete _contemplation_ and mental
- picture of implicitly absolute spirit as the _Ideal_. In this ideal, or
- the concrete shape born of the subjective spirit, its natural immediacy,
- which is only a _sign_ of the Idea, is so transfigured by the informing
- spirit in order to express the Idea, that the figure shows it and it
- alone:—the shape or form of _Beauty_.
- § 557. The sensuous externality attaching to the beautiful,—the _form of
- immediacy_ as such,—at the same time _qualifies_ what it _embodies_: and
- the God (of art) has with his spirituality at the same time the stamp upon
- him of a natural medium or natural phase of existence—He contains the
- so-called _unity_ of nature and spirit—i.e. the immediate unity in
- sensuously intuitional form—hence not the spiritual unity, in which the
- natural would be put only as “ideal,” as superseded in spirit, and the
- spiritual content would be only in self-relation. It is not the absolute
- spirit which enters this consciousness. On the subjective side the
- community has of course an ethical life, aware, as it is, of the
- spirituality of its essence: and its self-consciousness and actuality are
- in it elevated to substantial liberty. But with the stigma of immediacy
- upon it, the subject’s liberty is only a _manner of life_, without the
- infinite self-reflection and the subjective inwardness of _conscience_.
- These considerations govern in their further developments the devotion and
- the worship in the religion of fine art.
- § 558. For the objects of contemplation it has to produce, Art requires
- not only an external given material—(under which are also included
- subjective images and ideas), but—for the expression of spiritual
- truth—must use the given forms of nature with a significance which art
- must divine and possess (cf. § 411). Of all such forms the human is the
- highest and the true, because only in it can the spirit have its
- corporeity and thus its visible expression.
- This disposes of the principle of the _imitation of nature_ in art: a
- point on which it is impossible to come to an understanding while a
- distinction is left thus abstract,—in other words, so long as the natural
- is only taken in its externality, not as the “characteristic” meaningful
- nature-form which is significant of spirit.
- § 559. In such single shapes the “absolute” mind cannot be made explicit:
- in and to art therefore the spirit is a limited natural spirit whose
- implicit universality, when steps are taken to specify its fullness in
- detail, breaks up into an indeterminate polytheism. With the essential
- restrictedness of its content, Beauty in general goes no further than a
- penetration of the vision or image by the spiritual principle,—something
- formal, so that the thought embodied, or the idea, can, like the material
- which it uses to work in, be of the most diverse and unessential kind, and
- still the work be something beautiful and a work of art.
- § 560. The one-sidedness of _immediacy_ on the part of the Ideal involves
- the opposite one-sidedness (§ 556) that it is something _made_ by the
- artist. The subject or agent is the mere technical activity: and the work
- of art is only then an expression of the God, when there is no sign of
- subjective particularity in it, and the net power of the indwelling spirit
- is conceived and born into the world, without admixture and unspotted from
- its contingency. But as liberty only goes as far as there is thought, the
- action inspired with the fullness of this indwelling power, the artist’s
- _enthusiasm_, is like a foreign force under which he is bound and passive;
- the artistic _production_ has on its part the form of natural immediacy,
- it belongs to the _genius_ or particular endowment of the artist,—and is
- at the same time a labour concerned with technical cleverness and
- mechanical externalities. The work of art therefore is just as much a work
- due to free option, and the artist is the master of the God.
- § 561. In work so inspired the reconciliation appears so obvious in its
- initial stage that it is without more ado accomplished in the subjective
- self-consciousness, which is thus self-confident and of good cheer,
- without the depth and without the sense of its antithesis to the absolute
- essence. On the further side of the perfection (which is reached in such
- reconciliation, in the beauty of _classical art_) lies the art of
- sublimity,—_symbolic art_, in which the figuration suitable to the Idea is
- not yet found, and the thought as going forth and wrestling with the
- figure is exhibited as a negative attitude to it, and yet all the while
- toiling to work itself into it. The meaning or theme thus shows it has not
- yet reached the infinite form, is not yet known, not yet conscious of
- itself, as free spirit. The artist’s theme only is as the abstract God of
- pure thought, or an effort towards him,—a restless and unappeased effort
- which throws itself into shape after shape as it vainly tries to find its
- goal.
- § 562. In another way the Idea and the sensuous figure it appears in are
- incompatible; and that is where the infinite form, subjectivity, is not as
- in the first extreme a mere superficial personality, but its inmost depth,
- and God is known not as only seeking his form or satisfying himself in an
- external form, but as only finding himself in himself, and thus giving
- himself his adequate figure in the spiritual world alone. _Romantic art_
- gives up the task of showing him as such in external form and by means of
- beauty: it presents him as only condescending to appearance, and the
- divine as the heart of hearts in an externality from which it always
- disengages itself. Thus the external can here appear as contingent towards
- its significance.
- The Philosophy of Religion has to discover the logical necessity in the
- progress by which the Being, known as the Absolute, assumes fuller and
- firmer features; it has to note to what particular feature the kind of
- cultus corresponds,—and then to see how the secular self-consciousness,
- the consciousness of what is the supreme vocation of man,—in short how the
- nature of a nation’s moral life, the principle of its law, of its actual
- liberty, and of its constitution, as well as of its art and science,
- corresponds to the principle which constitutes the substance of a
- religion. That all these elements of a nation’s actuality constitute one
- systematic totality, that one spirit creates and informs them, is a truth
- on which follows the further truth that the history of religions coincides
- with the world-history.
- As regards the close connexion of art with the various religions it may be
- specially noted that _beautiful_ art can only belong to those religions in
- which the spiritual principle, though concrete and intrinsically free, is
- not yet absolute. In religions where the Idea has not yet been revealed
- and known in its free character, though the craving for art is felt in
- order to bring in imaginative visibility to consciousness the idea of the
- supreme being, and though art is the sole organ in which the abstract and
- radically indistinct content,—a mixture from natural and spiritual
- sources,—can try to bring itself to consciousness;—still this art is
- defective; its form is defective because its subject-matter and theme is
- so,—for the defect in subject-matter comes from the form not being
- immanent in it. The representations of this symbolic art keep a certain
- tastelessness and stolidity—for the principle it embodies is itself stolid
- and dull, and hence has not the power freely to transmute the external to
- significance and shape. Beautiful art, on the contrary, has for its
- condition the self-consciousness of the free spirit,—the consciousness
- that compared with it the natural and sensuous has no standing of its own:
- it makes the natural wholly into the mere expression of spirit, which is
- thus the inner form that gives utterance to itself alone.
- But with a further and deeper study, we see that the advent of art, in a
- religion still in the bonds of sensuous externality, shows that such
- religion is on the decline. At the very time it seems to give religion the
- supreme glorification, expression and brilliancy, it has lifted the
- religion away over its limitation. In the sublime divinity to which the
- work of art succeeds in giving expression the artistic genius and the
- spectator find themselves at home, with their personal sense and feeling,
- satisfied and liberated: to them the vision and the consciousness of free
- spirit has been vouchsafed and attained. Beautiful art, from its side, has
- thus performed the same service as philosophy: it has purified the spirit
- from its thraldom. The older religion in which the need of fine art, and
- just for that reason, is first generated, looks up in its principle to an
- other-world which is sensuous and unmeaning: the images adored by its
- devotees are hideous idols regarded as wonder-working talismans, which
- point to the unspiritual objectivity of that other world,—and bones
- perform a similar or even a better service than such images. But even fine
- art is only a grade of liberation, not the supreme liberation itself.—The
- genuine objectivity, which is only in the medium of thought,—the medium in
- which alone the pure spirit is for the spirit, and where the liberation is
- accompanied with reverence,—is still absent in the sensuous beauty of the
- work of art, still more in that external, unbeautiful sensuousness.
- § 563. Beautiful Art, like the religion peculiar to it, has its future in
- true religion. The restricted value of the Idea passes utterly and
- naturally into the universality identical with the infinite form;—the
- vision in which consciousness has to depend upon the senses passes into a
- self-mediating knowledge, into an existence which is itself
- knowledge,—into _revelation_. Thus the principle which gives the Idea its
- content is that it embody free intelligence, and as “absolute” _spirit it
- is for the spirit_.
- Sub-Section B. Revealed Religion(172).
- § 564. It lies essentially in the notion of religion,—the religion i.e.
- whose content is absolute mind—that it be _revealed_, and, what is more,
- revealed _by God_. Knowledge (the principle by which the substance is
- mind) is a self-determining principle, as infinite self-realising form,—it
- therefore is manifestation out and out. The spirit is only spirit in so
- far as it is for the spirit, and in the absolute religion it is the
- absolute spirit which manifests no longer abstract elements of its being
- but itself.
- The old conception—due to a one-sided survey of human life—of Nemesis,
- which made the divinity and its action in the world only a levelling
- power, dashing to pieces everything high and great,—was confronted by
- Plato and Aristotle with the doctrine that God is not _envious_. The same
- answer may be given to the modern assertions that man cannot ascertain
- God. These assertions (and more than assertions they are not) are the more
- illogical, because made within a religion which is expressly called the
- revealed; for according to them it would rather be the religion in which
- nothing of God was revealed, in which he had not revealed himself, and
- those belonging to it would be the heathen “who know not God.” If the word
- of God is taken in earnest in religion at all, it is from Him, the theme
- and centre of religion, that the method of divine knowledge may and must
- begin: and if self-revelation is refused Him, then the only thing left to
- constitute His nature would be to ascribe envy to Him. But clearly if the
- word Mind is to have a meaning, it implies the revelation of Him.
- If we recollect how intricate is the knowledge of the divine Mind for
- those who are not content with the homely pictures of faith but proceed to
- thought,—at first only “rationalising” reflection, but afterwards, as in
- duty bound, to speculative comprehension, it may almost create surprise
- that so many, and especially theologians whose vocation it is to deal with
- these Ideas, have tried to get off their task by gladly accepting anything
- offered them for this behoof. And nothing serves better to shirk it than
- to adopt the conclusion that man knows nothing of God. To know what God as
- spirit is—to apprehend this accurately and distinctly in thoughts—requires
- careful and thorough speculation. It includes, in its fore-front, the
- propositions: God is God only so far as he knows himself: his
- self-knowledge is, further, his self-consciousness in man, and man’s
- knowledge _of_ God, which proceeds to man’s self-knowledge in God.—See the
- profound elucidation of these propositions in the work from which they are
- taken: _Aphorisms on Knowing and Not-knowing, &c._, by C. F. G—l.: Berlin
- 1829.
- § 565. When the immediacy and sensuousness of shape and knowledge is
- superseded, God is, in point of content, the essential and actual spirit
- of nature and spirit, while in point of form he is, first of all,
- presented to consciousness as a mental representation. This
- quasi-pictorial representation gives to the elements of his content, on
- one hand, a separate being, making them presuppositions towards each
- other, and phenomena which succeed each other; their relationship it makes
- a series of events according to finite reflective categories. But, on the
- other hand, such a form of finite representationalism is also overcome and
- superseded in the faith which realises one spirit and in the devotion of
- worship.
- § 566. In this separating, the form parts from the content: and in the
- form the different functions of the notion part off into special spheres
- or media, in each of which the absolute spirit exhibits itself; (α) as
- eternal content, abiding self-centred, even in its manifestation; (β) as
- distinction of the eternal essence from its manifestation, which by this
- difference becomes the phenomenal world into which the content enters; (γ)
- as infinite return, and reconciliation with the eternal being, of the
- world it gave away—the withdrawal of the eternal from the phenomenal into
- the unity of its fullness.
- § 567. (α) Under the “moment” of _Universality_,—the sphere of pure
- thought or the abstract medium of essence,—it is therefore the absolute
- spirit, which is at first the presupposed principle, not however staying
- aloof and inert, but (as underlying and essential power under the
- reflective category of causality) creator of heaven and earth: but yet in
- this eternal sphere rather only begetting himself as his _son_, with whom,
- though different, he still remains in original identity,—just as, again,
- this differentiation of him from the universal essence eternally
- supersedes itself, and, though this mediating of a self-superseding
- mediation, the first substance is essentially as _concrete individuality_
- and subjectivity,—is the _Spirit_.
- § 568. (β) Under the “moment” of _particularity_, or of judgment, it is
- this concrete eternal being which is presupposed: its movement is the
- creation of the phenomenal world. The eternal “moment” of mediation—of the
- only Son—divides itself to become the antithesis of two separate worlds.
- On one hand is heaven and earth, the elemental and the concrete nature,—on
- the other hand, standing in action and reaction with such nature, the
- spirit, which therefore is finite. That spirit, as the extreme of inherent
- negativity, completes its independence till it becomes wickedness, and is
- that extreme through its connexion with a confronting nature and through
- its own naturalness thereby investing it. Yet, amid that naturalness, it
- is, when it thinks, directed towards the Eternal, though, for that reason,
- only standing to it in an external connexion.
- § 569. (γ) Under the “moment” of _individuality_ as such,—of subjectivity
- and the notion itself, in which the contrast of universal and particular
- has sunk to its identical ground, the place of presupposition (1) is taken
- by the _universal_ substance, as actualised out of its abstraction into an
- _individual_ self-consciousness. This individual, who as such is
- identified with the essence,—(in the Eternal sphere he is called the
- Son)—is transplanted into the world of time, and in him wickedness is
- implicitly overcome. Further, this immediate, and thus sensuous, existence
- of the absolutely concrete is represented as putting himself in judgment
- and expiring in the pain of _negativity_, in which he, as infinite
- subjectivity, keeps himself unchanged, and thus, as absolute return from
- that negativity and as universal unity of universal and individual
- essentiality, has realised his being as the Idea of the spirit, eternal,
- but alive and present in the world.
- § 570. (2) This objective totality of the divine man who is the Idea of
- the spirit is the implicit presupposition for the _finite_ immediacy of
- the single subject. For such subject therefore it is at first an Other, an
- object of contemplating vision,—but the vision of implicit truth, through
- which witness of the spirit in him, he, on account of his immediate
- nature, at first characterised himself as nought and wicked. But,
- secondly, after the example of his truth, by means of the faith on the
- unity (in that example implicitly accomplished) of universal and
- individual essence, he is also the movement to throw off his immediacy,
- his natural man and self-will, to close himself in unity with that example
- (who is his implicit life) in the pain of negativity, and thus to know
- himself made one with the essential Being. Thus the Being of Beings (3)
- through this mediation brings about its own indwelling in
- self-consciousness, and is the actual presence of the essential and
- self-subsisting spirit who is all in all.
- § 571. These three syllogisms, constituting the one syllogism of the
- absolute self-mediation of spirit, are the revelation of that spirit whose
- life is set out as a cycle of concrete shapes in pictorial thought. From
- this its separation into parts, with a temporal and external sequence, the
- unfolding of the mediation contracts itself in the result,—where the
- spirit closes in unity with itself,—not merely to the simplicity of faith
- and devotional feeling, but even to thought. In the immanent simplicity of
- thought the unfolding still has its expansion, yet is all the while known
- as an indivisible coherence of the universal, simple, and eternal spirit
- in itself. In this form of truth, truth is the object of _philosophy_.
- If the result—the realised Spirit in which all meditation has superseded
- itself—is taken in a merely formal, contentless sense, so that the spirit
- is not also at the same time known as _implicitly_ existent and
- objectively self-unfolding;—then that infinite subjectivity is the merely
- formal self-consciousness, knowing itself in itself as absolute,—Irony.
- Irony, which can make every objective reality nought and vain, is itself
- the emptiness and vanity, which from itself, and therefore by chance and
- its own good pleasure, gives itself direction and content, remains master
- over it, is not bound by it,—and, with the assertion that it stands on the
- very summit of religion and philosophy, falls rather back into the vanity
- of wilfulness. It is only in proportion as the pure infinite form, the
- self-centred manifestation, throws off the one-sidedness of subjectivity
- in which it is the vanity of thought, that it is the free thought which
- has its infinite characteristic at the same time as essential and actual
- content, and has that content as an object in which it is also free.
- Thinking, so far, is only the formal aspect of the absolute content.
- Sub-Section C. Philosophy.
- § 572. This science is the unity of Art and Religion. Whereas the
- vision-method of Art, external in point of form, is but subjective
- production and shivers the substantial content into many separate shapes,
- and whereas Religion, with its separation into parts, opens it out in
- mental picture, and mediates what is thus opened out; Philosophy not
- merely keeps them together to make a total, but even unifies them into the
- simple spiritual vision, and then in that raises them to self-conscious
- thought. Such consciousness is thus the intelligible unity (cognised by
- thought) of art and religion, in which the diverse elements in the content
- are cognised as necessary, and this necessary as free.
- § 573. Philosophy thus characterises itself as a cognition of the
- necessity in the content of the absolute picture-idea, as also of the
- necessity in the two forms—on one hand, immediate vision and its poetry,
- and the objective and external revelation presupposed by
- representation,—on the other hand, first the subjective retreat inwards,
- then the subjective movement of faith and its final identification with
- the presupposed object. This cognition is thus the _recognition_ of this
- content and its form; it is the liberation from the one-sidedness of the
- forms, elevation of them into the absolute form, which determines itself
- to content, remains identical with it, and is in that the cognition of
- that essential and actual necessity. This movement, which philosophy is,
- finds itself already accomplished, when at the close it seizes its own
- notion,—i.e. only _looks back_ on its knowledge.
- Here might seem to be the place to treat in a definite exposition of the
- reciprocal relations of philosophy and religion. The whole question turns
- entirely on the difference of the forms of speculative thought from the
- forms of mental representation and “reflecting” intellect. But it is the
- whole cycle of philosophy, and of logic in particular, which has not
- merely taught and made known this difference, but also criticised it, or
- rather has let its nature develop and judge itself by these very
- categories. It is only by an insight into the value of these forms that
- the true and needful conviction can be gained, that the content of
- religion and philosophy is the same,—leaving out, of course, the further
- details of external nature and finite mind which fall outside the range of
- religion. But religion is the truth _for all men_: faith rests on the
- witness of the spirit, which as witnessing is the spirit in man. This
- witness—the underlying essence in all humanity—takes, when driven to
- expound itself, its first definite form under those acquired habits of
- thought which his secular consciousness and intellect otherwise employs.
- In this way the truth becomes liable to the terms and conditions of
- finitude in general. This does not prevent the spirit, even in employing
- sensuous ideas and finite categories of thought, from retaining its
- content (which as religion is essentially speculative,) with a tenacity
- which does violence to them, and acts _inconsistently_ towards them. By
- this inconsistency it corrects their defects. Nothing easier therefore for
- the “Rationalist” than to point out contradictions in the exposition of
- the faith, and then to prepare triumphs for its principle of formal
- identity. If the spirit yields to this finite reflection, which has
- usurped the title of reason and philosophy—(“Rationalism”)—it strips
- religious truth of its infinity and makes it in reality nought. Religion
- in that case is completely in the right in guarding herself against such
- reason and philosophy and treating them as enemies. But it is another
- thing when religion sets herself against comprehending reason, and against
- philosophy in general, and specially against a philosophy of which the
- doctrine is speculative, and so religious. Such an opposition proceeds
- from failure to appreciate the difference indicated and the value of
- spiritual form in general, and particularly of the logical form; or, to be
- more precise, still from failure to note the distinction of the
- content—which may be in both the same—from these forms. It is on the
- ground of form that philosophy has been reproached and accused by the
- religious party; just as conversely its speculative content has brought
- the same charges upon it from a self-styled philosophy—and from a pithless
- orthodoxy. It had too little of God in it for the former; too much for the
- latter.
- The charge of _Atheism_, which used often to be brought against philosophy
- (that it has _too little_ of God), has grown rare: the more wide-spread
- grows the charge of Pantheism, that it has _too much_ of him:—so much so,
- that it is treated not so much as an imputation, but as a proved fact, or
- a sheer fact which needs no proof. Piety, in particular, which with its
- pious airs of superiority fancies itself free to dispense with proof, goes
- hand in hand with empty rationalism—(which means to be so much opposed to
- it, though both repose really on the same habit of mind)—in the wanton
- assertion, almost as if it merely mentioned a notorious fact, that
- Philosophy is the All-one doctrine, or Pantheism. It must be said that it
- was more to the credit of piety and theology when they accused a
- philosophical system (e.g. Spinozism) of Atheism than of Pantheism, though
- the former imputation at the first glance looks more cruel and insidious
- (cf. § 71 note). The imputation of Atheism presupposes a definite idea of
- a full and real God, and arises because the popular idea does not detect
- in the philosophical notion the peculiar form to which it is attached.
- Philosophy indeed can recognise its own forms in the categories of
- religious consciousness, and even its own teaching in the doctrine of
- religion—which therefore it does not disparage. But the converse is not
- true: the religious consciousness does not apply the criticism of thought
- to itself, does not comprehend itself, and is therefore, as it stands,
- exclusive. To impute Pantheism instead of Atheism to Philosophy is part of
- the modern habit of mind—of the new piety and new theology. For them
- philosophy has too much of God:—so much so, that, if we believe them, it
- asserts that God is everything and everything is God. This new theology,
- which makes religion only a subjective feeling and denies the knowledge of
- the divine nature, thus retains nothing more than a God in general without
- objective characteristics. Without interest of its own for the concrete,
- fulfilled notion of God, it treats it only as an interest which _others_
- once had, and hence treats what belongs to the doctrine of God’s concrete
- nature as something merely historical. The indeterminate God is to be
- found in all religions; every kind of piety (§ 72)—that of the Hindoo to
- asses, cows,—or to dalai-lamas,—that of the Egyptians to the ox—is always
- adoration of an object which, with all its absurdities, also contains the
- generic abstract, God in General. If this theory needs no more than such a
- God, so as to find God in everything called religion, it must at least
- find such a God recognised even in philosophy, and can no longer accuse it
- of Atheism. The mitigation of the reproach of Atheism into that of
- Pantheism has its ground therefore in the superficial idea to which this
- mildness has attenuated and emptied God. As that popular idea clings to
- its abstract universality, from which all definite quality is excluded,
- all such definiteness is only the non-divine, the secularity of things,
- thus left standing in fixed undisturbed substantiality. On such a
- presupposition, even after philosophy has maintained God’s absolute
- universality, and the consequent untruth of the being of external things,
- the hearer clings as he did before to his belief that secular things still
- keep their being, and form all that is definite in the divine
- universality. He thus changes that universality into what he calls the
- pantheistic:—_Everything is_—(empirical things, without distinction,
- whether higher or lower in the scale, _are_)—all possess substantiality;
- and so—thus he understands philosophy—each and every secular thing is God.
- It is only his own stupidity, and the falsifications due to such
- misconception, which generate the imagination and the allegation of such
- pantheism.
- But if those who give out that a certain philosophy is Pantheism, are
- unable and unwilling to see this—for it is just to see the notion that
- they refuse—they should before everything have verified the alleged fact
- that _any one philosopher, or any one man_, had really ascribed
- substantial or objective and inherent reality to _all_ things and regarded
- them as God:—that such an idea had ever come into the hand of any body but
- themselves. This allegation I will further elucidate in this exoteric
- discussion: and the only way to do so is to set down the evidence. If we
- want to take so-called Pantheism in its most poetical, most sublime, or if
- you will, its grossest shape, we must, as is well known, consult the
- oriental poets: and the most copious delineations of it are found in
- Hindoo literature. Amongst the abundant resources open to our disposal on
- this topic, I select—as the most authentic statement accessible—the
- Bhagavat-Gita, and amongst its effusions, prolix and reiterative _ad
- nauseam_, some of the most telling passages. In the 10th Lesson (in
- Schlegel, p. 162) Krishna says of himself(173):—“I am the self, seated in
- the hearts of all beings. I am the beginning and the middle and the end
- also of all beings ... I am the beaming sun amongst the shining ones, and
- the moon among the lunar mansions.... Amongst the Vedas I am the
- Sâma-Veda: I am mind amongst the senses: I am consciousness in living
- beings. And I am Sankara (Siva) among the Rudras, ... Meru among the
- high-topped mountains, ... the Himalaya among the firmly-fixed
- (mountains).... Among beasts I am the lord of beasts.... Among letters I
- am the letter A.... I am the spring among the seasons.... I am also that
- which is the seed of all things: there is nothing moveable or immoveable
- which can exist without me.”
- Even in these totally sensuous delineations, Krishna (and we must not
- suppose there is, besides Krishna, still God, or a God besides; as he said
- before he was Siva, or Indra, so it is afterwards said that Brahma too is
- in him) makes himself out to be—not everything, but only—the most
- excellent of everything. Everywhere there is a distinction drawn between
- external, unessential existences, and one essential amongst them, which he
- is. Even when, at the beginning of the passage, he is said to be the
- beginning, middle, and end of living things, this totality is
- distinguished from the living things themselves as single existences. Even
- such a picture which extends deity far and wide in its existence cannot be
- called pantheism: we must rather say that in the infinitely multiple
- empirical world, everything is reduced to a limited number of essential
- existences, to a polytheism. But even what has been quoted shows that
- these very substantialities of the externally-existent do not retain the
- independence entitling them to be named Gods; even Siva, Indra, &c. melt
- into the one Krishna.
- This reduction is more expressly made in the following scene (7th Lesson,
- p. 7 sqq.). Krishna says: “I am the producer and the destroyer of the
- whole universe. There is nothing else higher than myself; all this is
- woven upon me, like numbers of pearls upon a thread. I am the taste in
- water;... I am the light of the sun and the moon; I am ‘Om’ in all the
- Vedas.... I am life in all beings.... I am the discernment of the
- discerning ones.... I am also the strength of the strong.” Then he adds:
- “The whole universe deluded by these three states of mind developed from
- the qualities [sc. goodness, passion, darkness] does not know me who am
- beyond them and inexhaustible: for this delusion of mine,” [even the Maya
- is _his_, nothing independent], “developed from the qualities is divine
- and difficult to transcend. Those cross beyond this delusion who resort to
- me alone.” Then the picture gathers itself up in a simple expression: “At
- the end of many lives, the man possessed of knowledge approaches me,
- (believing) that Vasudeva is everything. Such a high-souled mind is very
- hard to find. Those who are deprived of knowledge by various desires
- approach other divinities... Whichever form of deity one worships with
- faith, from it he obtains the beneficial things he desires really given by
- me. But the fruit thus obtained by those of little judgment is
- perishable.... The undiscerning ones, not knowing my transcendent and
- inexhaustible essence, than which there is nothing higher, think me who am
- unperceived to have become perceptible.”
- This “All,” which Krishna calls himself, is not, any more than the Eleatic
- One, and the Spinozan Substance, the Every-thing. This every-thing,
- rather, the infinitely-manifold sensuous manifold of the finite is in all
- these pictures, but defined as the “accidental,” without essential being
- of its very own, but having its truth in the substance, the One which, as
- different from that accidental, is alone the divine and God. Hindooism
- however has the higher conception of Brahma, the pure unity of thought in
- itself, where the empirical everything of the world, as also those
- proximate substantialities, called Gods, vanish. On that account
- Colebrooke and many others have described the Hindoo religion as at bottom
- a Monotheism. That this description is not incorrect is clear from these
- short citations. But so little concrete is this divine unity—spiritual as
- its idea of God is—so powerless its grip, so to speak—that Hindooism, with
- a monstrous inconsistency, is also the maddest of polytheisms. But the
- idolatry of the wretched Hindoo, when he adores the ape, or other
- creature, is still a long way from that wretched fancy of a Pantheism, to
- which everything is God, and God everything. Hindoo monotheism moreover is
- itself an example how little comes of mere monotheism, if the Idea of God
- is not deeply determinate in itself. For that unity, if it be
- intrinsically abstract and therefore empty, tends of itself to let
- whatever is concrete, outside it—be it as a lot of Gods or as secular,
- empirical individuals—keep its independence. That pantheism indeed—on the
- shallow conception of it—might with a show of logic as well be called a
- monotheism: for if God, as it says, is identical with the world, then as
- there is only one world there would be in that pantheism only one God.
- Perhaps the empty numerical unity must be predicated of the world: but
- such abstract predication of it has no further special interest; on the
- contrary, a mere numerical unity just means that its _content_ is an
- infinite multeity and variety of finitudes. But it is that delusion with
- the empty unity, which alone makes possible and induces the wrong idea of
- pantheism. It is only the picture—floating in the indefinite blue—of the
- world as _one thing_, _the all_, that could ever be considered capable of
- combining with God: only on that assumption could philosophy be supposed
- to teach that God is the world: for if the world were taken as it is, as
- everything, as the endless lot of empirical existence, then it would
- hardly have been even held possible to suppose a pantheism which asserted
- of such stuff that it is God.
- But to go back again to the question of fact. If we want to see the
- consciousness of the One—not as with the Hindoos split between the
- featureless unity of abstract thought, on one hand, and on the other, the
- long-winded weary story of its particular detail, but—in its finest purity
- and sublimity, we must consult the Mohammedans. If e.g. in the excellent
- Jelaleddin-Rumi in particular, we find the unity of the soul with the One
- set forth, and that unity described as love, this spiritual unity is an
- exaltation above the finite and vulgar, a transfiguration of the natural
- and the spiritual, in which the externalism and transitoriness of
- immediate nature, and of empirical secular spirit, is discarded and
- absorbed(174).
- I refrain from accumulating further examples of the religious and poetic
- conceptions which it is customary to call pantheistic. Of the philosophies
- to which that name is given, the Eleatic, or Spinozist, it has been
- remarked earlier (§ 50, note) that so far are they from identifying God
- with the world and making him finite, that in these systems this
- “everything” has no truth, and that we should rather call them
- monotheistic, or, in relation to the popular idea of the world, acosmical.
- They are most accurately called systems which apprehend the Absolute only
- as substance. Of the oriental, especially the Mohammedan, modes of
- envisaging God, we may rather say that they represent the Absolute as the
- utterly universal genus which dwells in the species or existences, but
- dwells so potently that these existences have no actual reality. The fault
- of all these modes of thought and systems is that they stop short of
- defining substance as subject and as mind.
- These systems and modes of pictorial conception originate from the one
- need common to all philosophies and all religions of getting an idea of
- God, and, secondly, of the relationship of God and the world. (In
- philosophy it is specially made out that the determination of God’s nature
- determines his relations with the world.) The “reflective” understanding
- begins by rejecting all systems and modes of conception, which, whether
- they spring from heart, imagination or speculation, express the
- interconnexion of God and the world: and in order to have God pure in
- faith or consciousness, he is as essence parted from appearance, as
- infinite from the finite. But, after this partition, the conviction arises
- also that the appearance has a relation to the essence, the finite to the
- infinite, and so on: and thus arises the question of reflection as to the
- nature of this relation. It is in the reflective form that the whole
- difficulty of the affair lies, and that causes this relation to be called
- incomprehensible by the agnostic. The close of philosophy is not the
- place, even in a general exoteric discussion, to waste a word on what a
- “notion” means. But as the view taken of this relation is closely
- connected with the view taken of philosophy generally and with all
- imputations against it, we may still add the remark that though philosophy
- certainly has to do with unity in general, it is not however with abstract
- unity, mere identity, and the empty absolute, but with concrete unity (the
- notion), and that in its whole course it has to do with nothing else;—that
- each step in its advance is a peculiar term or phase of this concrete
- unity, and that the deepest and last expression of unity is the unity of
- absolute mind itself. Would-be judges and critics of philosophy might be
- recommended to familiarise themselves with these phases of unity and to
- take the trouble to get acquainted with them, at least to know so much
- that of these terms there are a great many, and that amongst them there is
- great variety. But they show so little acquaintance with them—and still
- less take trouble about it—that, when they hear of unity—and relation
- _ipso facto_ implies unity—they rather stick fast at quite abstract
- indeterminate unity, and lose sight of the chief point of interest—the
- special mode in which the unity is qualified. Hence all they can say about
- philosophy is that dry identity is its principle and result, and that it
- is the system of identity. Sticking fast to the undigested thought of
- identity, they have laid hands on, not the concrete unity, the notion and
- content of philosophy, but rather its reverse. In the philosophical field
- they proceed, as in the physical field the physicist; who also is well
- aware that he has before him a variety of sensuous properties and
- matters—or usually matters alone, (for the properties get transformed into
- matters also for the physicist)—and that these matters (elements) _also_
- stand in _relation_ to one another. But the question is, Of what kind is
- this relation? Every peculiarity and the whole difference of natural
- things, inorganic and living, depend solely on the different modes of this
- unity. But instead of ascertaining these different modes, the ordinary
- physicist (chemist included) takes up only one, the most external and the
- worst, viz. _composition_, applies only it in the whole range of natural
- structures, which he thus renders for ever inexplicable.
- The aforesaid shallow pantheism is an equally obvious inference from this
- shallow identity. All that those who employ this invention of their own to
- accuse philosophy gather from the study of God’s _relation_ to the world
- is that the one, but only the one factor of this category of relation—and
- that the factor of indeterminateness—is identity. Thereupon they stick
- fast in this half-perception, and assert—falsely as a fact—that philosophy
- teaches the identity of God and the world. And as in their judgment either
- of the two,—the world as much as God—has the same solid substantiality as
- the other, they infer that in the philosophic Idea God is _composed_ of
- God and the world. Such then is the idea they form of pantheism, and which
- they ascribe to philosophy. Unaccustomed in their own thinking and
- apprehending of thoughts to go beyond such categories, they import them
- into philosophy, where they are utterly unknown; they thus infect it with
- the disease against which they subsequently raise an outcry. If any
- difficulty emerge in comprehending God’s relation to the world, they at
- once and very easily escape it by admitting that this relation contains
- for them an inexplicable contradiction; and that hence, they must stop at
- the vague conception of such relation, perhaps under the more familiar
- names of, e.g. omnipresence, providence, &c. Faith in their use of the
- term means no more than a refusal to define the conception, or to enter on
- a closer discussion of the problem. That men and classes of untrained
- intellect are satisfied with such indefiniteness, is what one expects; but
- when a trained intellect and an interest for reflective study is
- satisfied, in matters admitted to be of superior, if not even of supreme
- interest, with indefinite ideas, it is hard to decide whether the thinker
- is really in earnest with the subject. But if those who cling to this
- crude “rationalism” were in earnest, e.g. with God’s omnipresence, so far
- as to realise their faith thereon in a definite mental idea, in what
- difficulties would they be involved by their belief in the true reality of
- the things of sense! They would hardly like, as Epicurus does, to let God
- dwell in the interspaces of things, i.e. in the pores of the
- physicists,—said pores being the negative, something supposed to exist
- _beside_ the material reality. This very “Beside” would give their
- pantheism its spatiality,—their everything, conceived as the mutual
- exclusion of parts in space. But in ascribing to God, in his relation to
- the world, an action on and in the space thus filled on the world and in
- it, they would endlessly split up the divine actuality into infinite
- materiality. They would really thus have the misconception they call
- pantheism or all-one-doctrine, only as the necessary sequel of their
- misconceptions of God and the world. But to put that sort of thing, this
- stale gossip of oneness or identity, on the shoulders of philosophy, shows
- such recklessness about justice and truth that it can only be explained
- through the difficulty of getting into the head thoughts and notions, i.e.
- not abstract unity, but the many-shaped modes specified. If statements as
- to facts are put forward, and the facts in question are thoughts and
- notions, it is indispensable to get hold of their meaning. But even the
- fulfilment of this requirement has been rendered superfluous, now that it
- has long been a foregone conclusion that philosophy is pantheism, a system
- of identity, an All-one doctrine, and that the person therefore who might
- be unaware of this fact is treated either as merely unaware of a matter of
- common notoriety, or as prevaricating for a purpose. On account of this
- chorus of assertions, then, I have believed myself obliged to speak at
- more length and exoterically on the outward and inward untruth of this
- alleged fact: for exoteric discussion is the only method available in
- dealing with the external apprehension of notions as mere facts,—by which
- notions are perverted into their opposite. The esoteric study of God and
- identity, as of cognitions and notions, is philosophy itself.
- § 574. This notion of philosophy is the self-thinking Idea, the truth
- aware of itself (§ 236),—the logical system, but with the signification
- that it is universality approved and certified in concrete content as in
- its actuality. In this way the science has gone back to its beginning: its
- result is the logical system but as a spiritual principle: out of the
- presupposing judgment, in which the notion was only implicit and the
- beginning an immediate,—and thus out of the _appearance_ which it had
- there—it has risen into its pure principle and thus also into its proper
- medium.
- § 575. It is this appearing which originally gives the motive of the
- further development. The first appearance is formed by the syllogism,
- which is based on the Logical system as starting-point, with Nature for
- the middle term which couples the Mind with it. The Logical principle
- turns to Nature and Nature to Mind. Nature, standing between the Mind and
- its essence, sunders itself, not indeed to extremes of finite abstraction,
- nor itself to something away from them and independent,—which, as other
- than they, only serves as a link between them: for the syllogism is _in
- the Idea_ and Nature is essentially defined as a transition-point and
- negative factor, and as implicitly the Idea. Still the mediation of the
- notion has the external form of _transition_, and the science of Nature
- presents itself as the course of necessity, so that it is only in the one
- extreme that the liberty of the notion is explicit as a self-amalgamation.
- § 576. In the second syllogism this appearance is so far superseded, that
- that syllogism is the standpoint of the Mind itself, which—as the
- mediating agent in the process—presupposes Nature and couples it with the
- Logical principle. It is the syllogism where Mind reflects on itself in
- the Idea: philosophy appears as a subjective cognition, of which liberty
- is the aim, and which is itself the way to produce it.
- § 577. The third syllogism is the Idea of philosophy, which has
- self-knowing reason, the absolutely-universal, for its middle term: a
- middle, which divides itself into Mind and Nature, making the former its
- presupposition, as process of the Idea’s subjective activity, and the
- latter its universal extreme, as process of the objectively and implicitly
- existing Idea. The self-judging of the Idea into its two appearances (§§
- 575, 576) characterises both as its (the self-knowing reason’s)
- manifestations: and in it there is a unification of the two aspects:—it is
- the nature of the fact, the notion, which causes the movement and
- development, yet this same movement is equally the action of cognition.
- The eternal Idea, in full fruition of its essence, eternally sets itself
- to work, engenders and enjoys itself as absolute Mind.
- Ἡ δὲ νόησις ἡ καθ᾽ αὑτὴν τοῦ καθ᾽ αὑτὸ ἀρίστου, καὶ ἡ μάλιστα τοῦ
- μάλιστα. Αὑτὸν δὲ νοεῖ ὁ νοῦς κατὰ μετάληψιν τοῦ νοητοῦ νοητὸς γὰρ
- γίγνεται θιγγάνων καὶ νοῶν, ὥστε ταὐτὸν νοῦς καὶ νοητόν. Τὸ γὰρ
- δεκτικὸν τοῦ νοητοῦ καὶ τῆς οὐσίας νοῦς. Ἐνεργεῖ δὲ ἔχων. Ὥστ᾽
- ἐκεῖνο μᾶλλον τούτου ὂ δοκεῖ ὁ νοῦς θεῖον ἔχειν, καὶ ἡ θεωρία τὸ
- ἥδιστον καὶ ἄριστον. Εἰ οὖν οὕτως εὖ ἔχει, ὡς ἡμεῖς ποτέ, ὁ θεὸς
- ἀεί, θαυμαστόν; εἰ δὲ μᾶλλον, ἔτι θαυμασιώτερον. Ἔχει δὲ ὡδί. Καὶ
- ζωὴ δέ γε ὑπάρχει; ἡ γὰρ νοῦ ἐνέργεια ζωή, ἐκεῖνος δὲ ἡ ἐνέργεια;
- ἐνέργεια δὲ ἡ καθ᾽ αὑτὴν ἐκείνου ζωὴ ἀρίστη καὶ ἀΐδιος. Φαμὲν δὲ
- τὸν θεὸν εἶναι ζῷον ἀΐδιον ἄριστον, ὥστε ζωὴ αἰὼν συνεχὴς καὶ
- ἀΐδιος ὑπάρχει τῷ θεῷ; τοῦτο γὰρ ὁ θεός. (ARIST. _Met._ XI. 7.)
- INDEX.
- Absolute (the), xlviii, 7.
- Abstraction, 74.
- Accent, 81, 87.
- Ages of man, 17.
- Alphabets, 81.
- Altruism, 57.
- Animal magnetism, clxi, 5, 29 seqq.
- Anthropology, xxv, lxxxviii, 12 seqq.
- Appetite, 53.
- _Aristotle_, liii, cxxxiii, 4, 63, 163.
- Art, xxxix seqq., 169 seqq.
- Asceticism, cxv, cxliii, clxxxvii, 159.
- Association of ideas, 73.
- Atheism, 183.
- Athens, cxxx.
- Attention, clxxiii, 69.
- Automatism (psychological), clxv.
- _Bacon_ (Fr.), xxi, lii, lix, clx.
- _Bain_ (A.), cxxi.
- Beauty, 169.
- Bhagavat-Gita, 186 seqq.
- Biography, 151.
- Body and Soul (relations of), lxxxii, cxvi, clvi, 13.
- _Boëthius_, l.
- _Böhme_ (J.), 95.
- _Braid_ (J.), clxiv.
- Bravery, cxcix.
- Budget, 144.
- Capitalism, cci seqq.
- Cardinal virtues, cxxxii.
- Categories, lx.
- Catholicism, 157.
- Children, lxxxvii, cii.
- Chinese language, 81 seqq.
- Choice, 98.
- Christianity, xliv, cxli, clxxix, 7, 101, 157.
- Clairvoyance, clviii, clxi, 33.
- Cognition, 64.
- Commercial morality, cci.
- _Comte_ (C.), xcix.
- _Condillac_, lxxviii, 61.
- Conscience, xxx, cxxii, clxxxvii, 117, 156, 161.
- Consciousness, xxv, xcix, 47 seqq.
- Constitution of the State, 132.
- Contract, 108.
- Corporation, 130.
- Crime, cxciii, 109.
- Criticism, xvi, cxxxviii, 149.
- Custom, clxxxix, 104.
- _Dante_, cxxxiv.
- Deduction (Kantian and Fichtean), cx seqq.
- Democracy, 141.
- Development, 60.
- Disease (mental), 27, 37.
- Duty, cxiv, cxix, cxxi seqq., cxxxi, cxxxix, 97, 104, 116.
- Economics, 122.
- Education, xcii, cxxxvii, 11.
- Ego (the), lxiv seqq., 47 seqq.
- Egoism, 55.
- Eleaticism, 190.
- England, 143.
- Epicureanism, cxli, 195.
- Epistemology, ciii.
- Equality (political and social), cxc, 133.
- Equity, xxxi.
- Estates, 123.
- Ethics, xv, xix, xxx seqq., xcv, cxiii seqq., cxc seqq., 113 seqq.
- Experience, 51.
- Experimental psychology, lxxxi seqq., c.
- Expression (mental), 23, 45.
- Faculties of Mind, lxxiii seqq., xcvii, cxxvi, 58, 65.
- Faith, cvii.
- Faith-cure, clxi, 35.
- Fame, 153.
- Family, xxxii, cxcii, 121.
- _Fechner_ (G. T.), cli.
- Feeling, 22, 68, 92.
- _Fichte_ (J. G.), cvi, cix seqq., clxiv, clxix, 49.
- Finance, 144.
- Finitude, 8.
- Fraud, 110.
- Freedom, cxxv seqq., clxxv, 6, 99, 113, 133 seqq.
- _Fries_, clxxix.
- Genius (the), clvii, 28.
- German language, 78, 88:
- politics, clxxvii;
- empire, clxxxi.
- God, xxxiv, xli, cxxii, 20, 154, 176.
- _Goethe_, cliv, clxix.
- Goodness, 115.
- Government, 137;
- forms of, 141.
- Greek ethics, cxxix seqq., cxciv;
- religion, 164.
- Habit, clviii, 39.
- Happiness, 99.
- _Herbart_, lxii seqq., lxxxv, cxxvii.
- Hieroglyphics, 80.
- History, xxxiv, xlvii, xci, 147 seqq.
- _Hobbes_, lxxvi, clxxxii.
- Holiness, 159.
- Honour, 124.
- _Humboldt_ (W. v.), 79.
- _Hume_, lxxi, cxx.
- Hypnotism, clxiv seqq., 31 seqq.
- Idea (Platonic), 163.
- Idealism, civ; political, clxxxvi.
- Ideality, clxviii, 25.
- Ideas, lxix seqq., ci seqq.
- Imagination, 72.
- Immaterialism, clii, 12, 45.
- Impulse, 95.
- Individualist ethics, cxx seqq.
- Individuality in the State, 139.
- Industrialism, cc, 123.
- Insanity, 37.
- Intention, 114.
- International Law, 147.
- Intuition, 67.
- Irony, 179.
- _Jelaleddin-Rumi_, 189.
- Judgment, 89.
- Judicial system, 127.
- _Jung-Stilling_, clxii.
- Juries, 128.
- _Kant_ (I.), xv, lxiv, lxxi, xcvi, cvii, cxxviii, clxxxviii, 20, 48, 51,
- 63, 154.
- _Kieser_, clxiii.
- Knowledge, cv, cxxxv, cxli, 64.
- Krishna, 186 seqq.
- Labour, 123.
- Language, clxxiv, 79 seqq.
- _Laplace_, clxiv.
- Law, xxix, xcvi, cxc, 104, 125.
- Legality, xxx, clxxxix.
- Legislation, 125.
- _Leibniz_, lxxii, lxxvii, cxlvi, 14, 80, 82.
- Liberty, see Freedom.
- Life, 13.
- Logic, xiv, xvii, lxi, xcv, 196.
- Lutheranism, 157.
- _Macchiavelli_, clxxx.
- Magic, clxi, 29.
- Manifestation, 7.
- Manners, 104.
- Marriage, 121, 159.
- Master and slave, 56.
- Mathematics in psychology, lxviii.
- Medium, 34.
- Memory, clxxiv, 70, 84.
- _Mesmer_, clxi.
- Metaphysic, lviii seqq.
- _Mill_ (James), lxxix.
- Mind (= Spirit), xlix seqq., 58, 196.
- Mnemonics, 85.
- Monarchy, 139.
- Monasticism, 159.
- Monotheism, 188.
- Morality, xxx, xxxviii, cxxi, clxxxviii seqq., cxcviii, 113 seqq.
- _Münsterberg_ (H.), lxxxiii.
- _Napoleon_, 19.
- Nationality, 142, 150, 154, cxcv.
- Natural Philosophy, xv, xvii, xxii.
- Natural rights, 112.
- Nature, cxx, cxxiv, 12, 133, 196.
- Nemesis, 174.
- _Nietzsche_ (F.), cxxviii.
- Nobility, cxcvii.
- Observation, lxxxix.
- Orders (social), cxcvii seqq., 124.
- Ought, clxxv, 94, 116.
- Pain, 6, 94.
- Pantheism, 184, 194.
- Parliament, 142.
- Passion, 95.
- Peasantry, cci.
- _Peel_ (Sir R.), 127.
- Perception, 67.
- Perfection, cxxvii, cxxix.
- Person, 107, 119.
- Personality, lxiv, clxvii.
- Philosophy, xiv, cxvii, cxxxviii, 159 seqq., 179 seqq.
- Phrenology, 35.
- Physiology, lxxxi, c.
- _Pinel_, 39.
- _Plato_, xcviii, cxxxi, cxxxv, 33, 97, 102, 162.
- Pleasure, cxxxvi, 94.
- _Plotinus_, cxliv.
- Police, 130.
- _Porphyry_, xx.
- Positivity of laws, 125.
- Powers (political), ccii, 138.
- Practice, 92.
- Property, xxix, cxcii, 107.
- Protestantism, 166.
- Prussia, clxxviii, clxxxiv.
- Psychiatry, 33.
- Psychology, xxii, xxiv, lii seqq., lxiii, lxxxvi, xcv, cxvii, 4, 58, 63.
- Psycho-physics, clvi, 23.
- Punishment, cxciii, cciii, 111.
- Purpose, 97, 114.
- Races, 16.
- Rationalism, clxv, 183.
- Reason, cxv, cxliii, clxxii, 58.
- Recollection, 70.
- _Reinhold_, 49.
- Religion, xxxvii seqq., cxcvi, 155 seqq., 167 seqq.
- Representation, cxi, 70;
- political, clxxxiii, 142.
- Responsibility, 114.
- Revelation, 7, 175.
- Right, xxix, 104 (see Law).
- _Ritter_, clxi, clxiii.
- Romances, 151:
- romantic art, 172.
- Savages, lxxxvii, cii.
- _Schelling_, clxi.
- _Schindler_, clxiii.
- _Schopenhauer_, cvi, cxvi, cli, clxiv, clxix, clxxxvii.
- Science, xviii.
- _Scott_ (Sir W.), 151.
- Self-consciousness, clxxi, 53 seqq.
- Sensibility and sensation, 20, 50.
- Sex, 18.
- Siderism, clxiii, 15.
- Signs (in language), 76.
- Skill (acquired), 42.
- Slavery, 56, 101.
- Sleep, 18.
- Society, xxxii, 56.
- Sociology, xxiii.
- Somnambulism, 30.
- Soul, liv, lxix, lxxv, 26.
- _Spencer_ (H.), xxi seqq., cxi, cxxiii, cxliv.
- _Spinoza_, lxxvi, ci, cxix, cl, 14, 49, 188.
- Spiritualism, clxii.
- State, xxxii seqq., clxxvi, clxxxiii, 131 seqq.
- Stoicism, cxix, cxxiv, cxi, cxliii.
- Suggestion, clxv seqq., 33.
- Superstition, 158.
- Syllogism, 90.
- Symbol, 77, 171.
- Sympathy, clv.
- Telepathy, clxi, 34.
- Tellurism, clxiii, 15.
- Theology, 155.
- Thinking, clxxiv, 89.
- _Tholuck_, 191.
- Trinity, 177 seqq.
- Truth, cv, 182.
- Unconscious (the), cxlvi.
- Understanding, 52, 89.
- Universalising, cxxviii.
- Utilitarianism, cxxxvi.
- Value, 109.
- Virtues, cxxxi, cxcviii, 120.
- War, cxcix, 146.
- Wartburg, clxxix.
- Welfare, 114.
- Wickedness, 9, 94, 117.
- Will, xxviii, cxxv, clxxv, 62, 90.
- _Wolff_, lxxiii.
- Words, clxxiv, 79.
- _Wordsworth_, li, clxviii.
- Written language, 81 seqq.
- Wrong, 109.
- Würtemberg, clxxxv.
- FOOTNOTES
- 1 Plato, _Rep._ 527.
- 2 The prospectus of the _System of Synthetic Philosophy_ is dated
- 1860. Darwin’s _Origin of Species_ is 1859. But such ideas, both in
- Mr. Spencer and others, are earlier than Darwin’s book.
- 3 Hegel’s _Verhältniss_, the supreme category of what is called
- actuality: where object is necessitated by outside object.
- 4 Cf. Herbart, _Werke_ (ed. Kehrbach), iv. 372. This consciousness
- proper is what Leibniz called _« __Apperception,__ »__ la
- connaissance réflexive de l’état intérieur (Nouveaux Essais)_.
- 5 Herbart, _Werke_, vi. 55 (ed. Kehrbach).
- 6 p. 59 (§ 440).
- 7 p. 63 (§ 440).
- 8 These remarks refer to four out of the five Herbartian ethical
- ideas. See also Leibniz, who (in 1693, _De Notionibus juris et
- justitiae_) had given the following definitions: “Caritas est
- benevolentia universalis. Justitia est caritas sapientis. Sapientia
- est scientia felicitatis.” The jus naturae has three grades: the
- lowest, jus strictum; the second, aequitas (or caritas, in the
- narrower sense); and the highest, pietas, which is honeste, i.e. pie
- vivere.
- 9 To which the Greek πόλις, the Latin civitas or respublica, were only
- approximations. Hegel _is not writing a history_. If he were, it
- would be necessary for him to point out how far the individual
- instance, e.g. Rome, or Prussia, corresponded to its Idea.
- 10 Shakespeare’s phrase, as in _Othello_, iii. 2; _Lover’s Complaint_,
- v. 24.
- _ 11 Iliad_, xii. 243.
- 12 See Hegel’s _Logic_, pp. 257 seq.
- 13 See p. 153 (§ 550).
- 14 Cf. _Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel_, chaps. xviii, xxvi.
- 15 As stated in p. 167 (_Encycl._ § 554). Cf. _Phenom. d. Geistes_,
- cap. vii, which includes the Religion of Art, and the same point of
- view is explicit in the first edition of the _Encyclopaedia_.
- _ 16 Philosophie der Religion_ (_Werke_, xi. 5).
- 17 Hegel, _Phenomenologie des Geistes_ (_Werke_, ii. 545). The
- meeting-ground of the Greek spirit, as it passed through Rome, with
- Christianity.
- 18 Ib., p. 584.
- _ 19 Phenomenologie des Geistes_ (_Werke_, ii. 572). Thus Hegelian
- idealism claims to be the philosophical counterpart of the central
- dogma of Christianity.
- 20 From the old Provençal _Lay of Boëthius_.
- 21 It is the doctrine of the _intellectus agens_, or _in actu_; the
- _actus purus_ of the Schoolmen.
- _ 22 Einleitung in die Philosophie_, §§ 1, 2.
- _ 23 Psychologie als Wissenschaft_, Vorrede.
- _ 24 Einleitung in die Philosophie_, §§ 11, 12.
- _ 25 Einleitung in die Philosophie_, § 18: cf. _Werke_, ed. Kehrbach, v.
- 108.
- 26 Cf. Plato’s remarks on the problem in the word Self-control.
- _Republ._ 430-1.
- _ 27 Lehrbuch der Psychologie_, §§ 202, 203.
- _ 28 Allgemeine Metaphysik_, Vorrede.
- _ 29 Hauptpunkte der Metaphysik_ (1806), § 13.
- _ 30 Werke_, ed. Kehrbach (_Ueber die Möglichkeit_, &c), v. 96.
- _ 31 Ibid._, p. 100.
- 32 One might almost fancy Herbart was translating into a general
- philosophic thesis the words in which Goethe has described how he
- overcame a real trouble by transmuting it into an ideal shape, e.g.
- _Wahrheit und Dichtung_, cap. xii.
- 33 Herbart’s language is almost identical with Hegel’s: _Encycl._ § 389
- (p. 12). Cf. Spencer, _Psychology_, i. 192. “Feelings are in all
- cases the materials out of which the superior tracts of
- consciousness and intellect are evolved.”
- _ 34 Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel_, ch. xvii.
- _ 35 Psychologia Empirica_, § 29.
- 36 As is also the case with Herbart’s metaphysical reality of the Soul.
- _ 37 Human Nature_, vii. 2. “Pleasure, Love, and appetite, which is also
- called desire, are divers names for divers considerations of the
- same thing....” Deliberation is (ch. xii. 1) the “alternate
- succession of appetite and fears.”
- _ 38 Eth._ ii. 48 Schol.
- _ 39 Eth._ ii. 43 Schol.: cf. 49 Schol.
- 40 This wide scope of thinking (_cogitatio_, _penser_) is at least as
- old as the Cartesian school: and should be kept in view, as against
- a tendency to narrow its range to the mere intellect.
- 41 e.g. _Analysis of the Human Mind_, ch. xxiv. “Attention is but
- another name for the interesting character of the idea;” ch. xix.
- “Desire and the idea of a pleasurable sensation are convertible
- terms.”
- 42 As Mr. Spencer says (_Psychology_, i. 141), “Objective psychology
- can have no existence as such without borrowing its data from
- subjective psychology.”
- 43 The same failure to note that experiment is valuable only where
- general points of view are defined, is a common fault in biology.
- 44 Münsterberg, _Aufgaben und Methoden der Psychologie_, p. 144.
- _ 45 Lehrbuch der Psychologie_, § 54 (2nd ed.), or § 11 (1st ed.).
- 46 See p. 11 (§ 387).
- 47 Cf. Nietzsche, _Also sprach Zarathustra_, i. 43. “There is more
- reason in thy body than in thy best wisdom.”
- 48 This language is very characteristic of the physicists who dabble in
- psychology and imagine they are treading in the steps of Kant, if
- not even verifying what they call his guesswork: cf. Ziehen,
- _Physiol. Psychologie_, 2nd ed. p. 212. “In every case there is
- given us only the psychical series of sensations and their
- memory-images, and it is only a universal hypothesis if we assume
- beside this psychical series a material series standing in causal
- relation to it.... The material series is not given equally
- originally with the psychical.”
- 49 It is the same radical feature of consciousness which is thus noted
- by Mr. Spencer, _Psychology_, i. 475. “Perception and sensation are
- ever tending to exclude each other but never succeed.” “Cognition
- and feeling are antithetical and inseparable.” “Consciousness
- continues only in virtue of this conflict.” Cf. Plato’s resolution
- in the _Philebus_ of the contest between intelligence and feeling
- (pleasure).
- 50 It is the quasi-Aristotelian ἀπαγωγή, defined as the step from one
- proposition to another, the knowledge of which will set the first
- proposition in a full light.
- _ 51 Grundlage des Naturrechts_, § 5.
- _ 52 System der Sittenlehre_, § 8, iv.
- 53 Even though religion (according to Kant) conceive them as divine
- commands.
- 54 Cf. Hegel’s _Werke_, vii. 2, p. 236 (Lecture-note on § 410). “We
- must treat as utterly empty the fancy of those who suppose that
- properly man should have no organic body,” &c.; and see p. 159 of
- the present work.
- _ 55 Criticism of Pure Reason_, Architectonic.
- 56 Spencer, _Psychology_, i. 291: “Mind can be understood only by
- observing how mind is evolved.”
- 57 Cf. Spencer, _Principles of Ethics_, i. 339: “The ethical sentiment
- proper is, in the great mass of cases, scarcely discernible.”
- _ 58 Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel_, p. 143.
- 59 Windelband (W.), _Präludien_ (1884), p. 288.
- 60 Cf. Plato, _Republic_, p. 486.
- _ 61 Human Nature: Morals_, Part III.
- _ 62 Emotion and Will_, ch. xv. § 23.
- 63 It is characteristic of the Kantian doctrine to absolutise the
- conception of Duty and make it express the essence of the whole
- ethical idea.
- 64 Which are still, as the Socialist Fourier says, states of social
- incoherence, specially favourable to falsehood.
- _ 65 Rechtsphilosophie_, § 4.
- 66 Cf. Schelling, ii. 12: “There are no _born_ sons of freedom.”
- 67 Simmel (G.), _Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft_, i. 184.
- _ 68 Jenseits von Gut und Böse_, p. 225.
- 69 Aristot. _Polit._ i. 6.
- 70 Plato, _Phaedo_.
- 71 Carus, _Psyche_, p. 1.
- 72 See Arist., _Anal. Post._ ii. 19 (ed. Berl. 100, a. 10).
- 73 Cf. _The Logic of Hegel_, notes &c., p. 421.
- 74 “Omnia individua corpora quamvis diversis gradibus animata sunt.”
- _Eth._ ii. 13. schol.
- _ 75 Nanna_ (1848): _Zendavesta_ (1851): _Ueber die Seelenfrage_ (1861).
- 76 Described by S. as the rise from mere physical _cause_ to
- physiological _stimulus_ (Reiz), to psychical _motive_.
- 77 Infra, p. 12.
- 78 Aristot., _De Anima_, i. c. 4, 5.
- _ 79 Wilhelm Meister’s Wanderjahre_, i. 10.
- _ 80 Wilhelm Meister’s Wanderjahre_, iv. 18.
- 81 Works like Preyer’s _Seele des Kindes_ illustrate this aspect of
- mental evolution; its acquirement of definite and correlated
- functions.
- 82 Cf. the end of Caleb Balderstone (in _The Bride of Lammermoor_):
- “With a fidelity sometimes displayed by the canine race, but seldom
- by human beings, he pined and died.”
- 83 See Windischmann’s letters in _Briefe von und an Hegel_.
- 84 Cf. _Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel_, chaps. xii-xiv.
- 85 Kieser’s _Tellurismus_ is, according to Schopenhauer, “the fullest
- and most thorough text-book of Animal Magnetism.”
- 86 Cf. Fichte, _Nachgelassene Werke_, iii. 295 (_Tagebuch über den
- animalischen Magnetismus_, 1813), and Schopenhauer, _Der Wille in
- der Natur_.
- 87 Bernheim: _La suggestion domine toute l’histoire de l’humanité_.
- 88 An instance from an unexpected quarter, in Eckermann’s conversations
- with Goethe: “In my young days I have experienced cases enough,
- where on lonely walks there came over me a powerful yearning for a
- beloved girl, and I thought of her so long till she actually came to
- meet me.” (Conversation of Oct. 7, 1827.)
- _ 89 Gleichsam in einer Vorwelt, einer diese Welt schaffenden Welt_
- (_Nachgelassene Werke_, iii. 321).
- _ 90 Selbst-bewusstsein_ is not self-consciousness, in the vulgar sense
- of brooding over feelings and self: but consciousness which is
- active and outgoing, rather than receptive and passive. It is
- practical, as opposed to theoretical.
- 91 The more detailed exposition of this Phenomenology of Mind is given
- in the book with that title: Hegel’s _Werke_, ii. pp. 71-316.
- _ 92 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 15 (see Essay V).
- 93 Hegel’s _Werke_, viii. 313, and cf. the passage quoted in my _Logic
- of Hegel_, notes, pp. 384, 385.
- 94 Hegel’s _Briefe_, i. 15.
- _ 95 Kritik der Verfassung Deutschlands_, edited by G. Mollat (1893).
- Parts of this were already given by Haym and Rosenkranz. The same
- editor has also in this year published, though not quite in full,
- Hegel’s _System der Sittlichkeit_, to which reference is made in
- what follows.
- 96 In which some may find a prophecy of the effects of “blood and iron”
- in 1866.
- _ 97 Die Absolute Regierung_: in the _System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 32:
- cf. p. 55. Hegel himself compares it to Fichte’s _Ephorate_.
- _ 98 Die Absolute Regierung_, l.c. pp. 37, 38.
- 99 Some idea of his meaning may perhaps be gathered by comparison with
- passages in _Wilhelm Meister’s Wanderjahre_, ii. 1, 2.
- _ 100 Kritik der Verfassung_, p. 20.
- 101 In some respects Bacon’s attitude in the struggle between royalty
- and parliament may be compared.
- 102 Just as Schopenhauer, on the contrary, always says _moralisch_—never
- _sittlich_.
- 103 Grey (G.), _Journals of two Expeditions of Discovery in North-West
- and Western Australia_, ii. 220.
- 104 With some variation of ownership, perhaps, according to the
- prevalence of so-called matriarchal or patriarchal households.
- 105 Cf. the custom in certain tribes which names the father after his
- child: as if the son first gave his father legitimate position in
- society.
- _ 106 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 8.
- _ 107 Aufhebung_ (_positive_) as given in _absolute Sittlichkeit_.
- _ 108 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 15.
- 109 This phraseology shows the influence of Schelling, with whom he was
- at this epoch associated. See _Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel_,
- ch. xiv.
- 110 Cf. the intermediate function assigned (see above, p. clxxxiii) to
- the priests and the aged.
- _ 111 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 19.
- 112 See _infra_, p. 156.
- 113 Wordsworth’s _Laodamia_.
- 114 “For it’s Tommy this, an’ Tommy that, an’ ‘Chuck him out, the
- brute!’
- But it’s ‘Saviour of ’is country’ when the guns begin to shoot.”
- 115 “I can assure you,” said Werner (the merchant), “that I never
- reflected on the State in my life. My tolls, charges and dues I have
- paid for no other reason than that it was established usage.”
- (_Wilh. Meisters Lehrjahre_, viii. 2.)
- _ 116 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 40.
- _ 117 System der Sittlichkeit_, p. 65.
- _ 118 Ibid._ p. 46.
- _ 119 Natürliche Seele._
- _ 120 Natürliche Qualitäten._
- _ 121 Empfindung._
- _ 122 Die fühlende Seele._
- 123 Plato had a better idea of the relation of prophecy generally to the
- state of sober consciousness than many moderns, who supposed that
- the Platonic language on the subject of enthusiasm authorised their
- belief in the sublimity of the revelations of somnambulistic vision.
- Plato says in the _Timaeus_ (p. 71), “The author of our being so
- ordered our inferior parts that they too might obtain a measure of
- truth, and in the liver placed their oracle (the power of divination
- by dreams). And herein is a proof that God has given the art of
- divination, not to the wisdom, but, to the foolishness of man; for
- no man when in his wits attains prophetic truth and inspiration; but
- when he receives the inspired word, either his intelligence is
- enthralled by sleep, or he is demented by some distemper or
- possession (enthusiasm).” Plato very correctly notes not merely the
- bodily conditions on which such visionary knowledge depends, and the
- possibility of the truth of the dreams, but also the inferiority of
- them to the reasonable frame of mind.
- _ 124 Selbstgefühl._
- _ 125 Gewohnheit._
- _ 126 Die wirkliche Seele._
- _ 127 Das Bewußtsein als solches_: (a) _Das sinnliche Bewußtsein._
- _ 128 Wahrnehmung._
- _ 129 Der Verstand._
- _ 130 Selbstbewußtsein._
- _ 131 Die Begierde._
- _ 132 Das anerkennende Selbstbewußtsein._
- _ 133 Die Vernunft._
- _ 134 Der Geist._
- _ 135 Die Intelligenz._
- _ 136 Anschauung._
- _ 137 Vorstellung._
- _ 138 Die Erinnerung._
- _ 139 Die Einbildungskraft._
- _ 140 Phantasie._
- _ 141 Gedächtniß._
- _ 142 Auswendiges._
- _ 143 Inwendiges._
- _ 144 Das Denken._
- _ 145 Der praktische Geist._
- _ 146 Der praktische Gefühl._
- _ 147 Der Triebe und die Willkühr._
- _ 148 Die Glückseligkeit._
- _ 149 Der freie Geist._
- _ 150 Gesess._
- _ 151 Sitte._
- _ 152 Das Recht._
- _ 153 Moralität._
- _ 154 Naturrecht._
- _ 155 Moralität._
- _ 156 Der Vorsatz._
- _ 157 That._
- _ 158 Handlung._
- _ 159 Die Absicht und das Wohl._
- _ 160 Das Gute und das Böse._
- _ 161 Die Sittlichkeit._
- _ 162 Die bürgerliche Gesellschaft._
- _ 163 Das System der Bedürfnisse._
- _ 164 Die Rechtspflege._
- _ 165 Geseß._
- _ 166 Die Polizei und die Corporation._
- _ 167 Inneres Staatsrecht._
- _ 168 Das äußere Staatsrecht._
- _ 169 Die Weltgeschichte._
- _ 170 Weltweisheit._
- _ 171 Der absolute Geist._
- _ 172 Die geoffenbarte Religion._
- 173 [The citation given by Hegel from Schlegel’s translation is here
- replaced by the version (in one or two points different) in the
- _Sacred Books of the East_, vol. viii.]
- 174 In order to give a clearer impression of it, I cannot refrain from
- quoting a few passages, which may at the same time give some
- indication of the marvellous skill of Rückert, from whom they are
- taken, as a translator. [For Rückert’s verses a version is here
- substituted in which I have been kindly helped by Miss May Kendall.]
- III.
- I saw but One through all heaven’s starry spaces gleaming:
- I saw but One in all sea billows wildly streaming.
- I looked into the heart, a waste of worlds, a sea,—
- I saw a thousand dreams,—yet One amid all dreaming.
- And earth, air, water, fire, when thy decree is given,
- Are molten into One: against thee none hath striven.
- There is no living heart but beats unfailingly
- In the one song of praise to thee, from earth and heaven.
- V.
- As one ray of thy light appears the noonday sun,
- But yet thy light and mine eternally are one.
- As dust beneath thy feet the heaven that rolls on high:
- Yet only one, and one for ever, thou and I.
- The dust may turn to heaven, and heaven to dust decay;
- Yet art thou one with me, and shalt be one for aye.
- How may the words of life that fill heaven’s utmost part
- Rest in the narrow casket of one poor human heart?
- How can the sun’s own rays, a fairer gleam to fling,
- Hide in a lowly husk, the jewel’s covering?
- How may the rose-grove all its glorious bloom unfold,
- Drinking in mire and slime, and feeding on the mould?
- How can the darksome shell that sips the salt sea stream
- Fashion a shining pearl, the sunlight’s joyous beam?
- Oh, heart! should warm winds fan thee, should’st thou floods
- endure,
- One element are wind and flood; but be thou pure.
- IX.
- I’ll tell thee how from out the dust God moulded man,—
- Because the breath of Love He breathed into his clay:
- I’ll tell thee why the spheres their whirling paths began,—
- They mirror to God’s throne Love’s glory day by day:
- I’ll tell thee why the morning winds blow o’er the grove,—
- It is to bid Love’s roses bloom abundantly:
- I’ll tell thee why the night broods deep the earth above,—
- Love’s bridal tent to deck with sacred canopy:
- All riddles of the earth dost thou desire to prove?—
- To every earthly riddle is Love alone the key.
- XV.
- Life shrinks from Death in woe and fear,
- Though Death ends well Life’s bitter need:
- So shrinks the heart when Love draws near,
- As though ’twere Death in very deed:
- For wheresoever Love finds room,
- There Self, the sullen tyrant, dies.
- So let him perish in the gloom,—
- Thou to the dawn of freedom rise.
- In this poetry, which soars over all that is external and sensuous,
- who would recognise the prosaic ideas current about so-called
- pantheism—ideas which let the divine sink to the external and the
- sensuous? The copious extracts which Tholuck, in his work _Anthology
- from the Eastern Mystics_, gives us from the poems of Jelaleddin and
- others, are made from the very point of view now under discussion.
- In his Introduction, Herr Tholuck proves how profoundly his soul has
- caught the note of mysticism; and there, too, he points out the
- characteristic traits of its oriental phase, in distinction from
- that of the West and Christendom. With all their divergence,
- however, they have in common the mystical character. The conjunction
- of Mysticism with so-called Pantheism, as he says (p. 53), implies
- that inward quickening of soul and spirit which inevitably tends to
- annihilate that external _Everything_, which Pantheism is usually
- held to adore. But beyond that, Herr Tholuck leaves matters standing
- at the usual indistinct conception of Pantheism; a profounder
- discussion of it would have had, for the author’s emotional
- Christianity, no direct interest; but we see that personally he is
- carried away by remarkable enthusiasm for a mysticism which, in the
- ordinary phrase, entirely deserves the epithet Pantheistic. Where,
- however, he tries philosophising (p. 12), he does not get beyond the
- standpoint of the “rationalist” metaphysic with its uncritical
- categories.
- ***END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HEGEL’S PHILOSOPHY OF MIND***
- CREDITS
- March 5, 2012
- Project Gutenberg TEI edition 1
- Produced by Odessa Paige Turner, David King, and the Online
- Distributed Proofreading Team at . (This
- book was produced from scanned images of public domain
- material from the Google Print project.)
- A WORD FROM PROJECT GUTENBERG
- This file should be named 39064‐0.txt or 39064‐0.zip.
- This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
- http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/3/9/0/6/39064/
- Updated editions will replace the previous one — the old editions will be
- renamed.
- Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no one
- owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and
- you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission
- and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the
- General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and
- distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the Project
- Gutenberg™ concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered
- trademark, and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you
- receive specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of
- this eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook
- for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports,
- performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given away
- — you may do practically _anything_ with public domain eBooks.
- Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
- redistribution.
- THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
- _Please read this before you distribute or use this work._
- To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free
- distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
- any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project Gutenberg”),
- you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg™
- License (available with this file or online at
- http://www.gutenberg.org/license).
- Section 1.
- General Terms of Use & Redistributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
- 1.A.
- By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™ electronic work,
- you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the
- terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright)
- agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this
- agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of
- Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee
- for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work
- and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may
- obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set
- forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
- 1.B.
- “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or
- associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be
- bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can
- do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic works even without complying
- with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are
- a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you
- follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to
- Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
- 1.C.
- The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the Foundation” or
- PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
- Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
- collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual
- work is in the public domain in the United States and you are located in
- the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying,
- distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on
- the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
- course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of
- promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project
- Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for
- keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can
- easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
- same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you
- share it without charge with others.
- 1.D.
- The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you
- can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant
- state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of
- your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before
- downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating
- derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work.
- The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of
- any work in any country outside the United States.
- 1.E.
- Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
- 1.E.1.
- The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access
- to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear prominently whenever
- any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase
- “Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg”
- is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or
- distributed:
- This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
- almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
- or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
- included with this eBook or online at http://www.gutenberg.org
- 1.E.2.
- If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived from the
- public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with
- permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and
- distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or
- charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the
- phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you
- must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7
- or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg™
- trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.3.
- If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted with the
- permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply
- with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed
- by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project
- Gutenberg™ License for all works posted with the permission of the
- copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
- 1.E.4.
- Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™ License
- terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any
- other work associated with Project Gutenberg™.
- 1.E.5.
- Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic
- work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying
- the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with active links or immediate
- access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg™ License.
- 1.E.6.
- You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed,
- marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word
- processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
- distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format other than
- “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official version posted
- on the official Project Gutenberg™ web site (http://www.gutenberg.org),
- you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
- copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
- request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form.
- Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as
- specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
- 1.E.7.
- Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing,
- copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works unless you comply
- with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
- 1.E.8.
- You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or
- distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works provided that
- - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
- the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method you
- already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to
- the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has agreed to
- donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60
- days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally
- required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments
- should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4,
- “Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
- Archive Foundation.”
- - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
- you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
- does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™ License.
- You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the
- works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and
- all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™ works.
- - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
- any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
- electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
- receipt of the work.
- - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
- distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
- 1.E.9.
- If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™ electronic
- work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this
- agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from both the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael Hart, the owner of the
- Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in
- Section 3 below.
- 1.F.
- 1.F.1.
- Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to
- identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread public domain
- works in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these
- efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they
- may be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
- incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright
- or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk
- or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot
- be read by your equipment.
- 1.F.2.
- LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES — Except for the “Right of
- Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg
- Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™
- trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™
- electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for
- damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE
- NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH
- OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
- FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT
- WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
- PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY
- OF SUCH DAMAGE.
- 1.F.3.
- LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND — If you discover a defect in this
- electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund
- of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to
- the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a
- physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation.
- The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect
- to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the
- work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose
- to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
- lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a
- refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.
- 1.F.4.
- Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
- paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ’AS-IS,’ WITH NO OTHER
- WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
- WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
- 1.F.5.
- Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the
- exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or
- limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state
- applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make
- the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state
- law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement
- shall not void the remaining provisions.
- 1.F.6.
- INDEMNITY — You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark
- owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of
- Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and
- any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
- of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs
- and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from
- any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of
- this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or
- additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect
- you cause.
- Section 2.
- Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™
- Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic
- works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including
- obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the
- efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks
- of life.
- Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance
- they need, is critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring
- that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will remain freely available for
- generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
- Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for
- Project Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations
- can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation web page at
- http://www.pglaf.org.
- Section 3.
- Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
- The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
- 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of
- Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service.
- The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541.
- Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
- http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/pglaf. Contributions to the Project
- Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full
- extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.
- The Foundation’s principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr.
- S. Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
- throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at 809 North
- 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
- business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact information
- can be found at the Foundation’s web site and official page at
- http://www.pglaf.org
- For additional contact information:
- Dr. Gregory B. Newby
- Chief Executive and Director
- gbnewby@pglaf.org
- Section 4.
- Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
- Foundation
- Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without wide spread
- public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the
- number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed
- in machine readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment
- including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are
- particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.
- The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
- charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States.
- Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable
- effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these
- requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not
- received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or
- determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit
- http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/donate
- While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have
- not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against
- accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us
- with offers to donate.
- International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any
- statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the
- United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
- Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation methods
- and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including
- checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please
- visit: http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/donate
- Section 5.
- General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works.
- Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg™
- concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with
- anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg™
- eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
- Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed editions,
- all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S. unless a copyright
- notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance
- with any particular paper edition.
- Each eBook is in a subdirectory of the same number as the eBook’s eBook
- number, often in several formats including plain vanilla ASCII, compressed
- (zipped), HTML and others.
- Corrected _editions_ of our eBooks replace the old file and take over the
- old filename and etext number. The replaced older file is renamed.
- _Versions_ based on separate sources are treated as new eBooks receiving
- new filenames and etext numbers.
- Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
- http://www.gutenberg.org
- This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg™, including how
- to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation,
- how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email
- newsletter to hear about new eBooks.
- ***FINIS***