Quotations.ch
  Directory : Lesser Logic, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences Part 1
GUIDE SUPPORT US BLOG
  • The Project Gutenberg EBook of The Logic of Hegel, by G. W. F. Hegel
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most
  • other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
  • whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of
  • the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you'll have
  • to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this ebook.
  • Title: The Logic of Hegel
  • Author: G. W. F. Hegel
  • Contributor: William Wallace
  • Translator: William Wallace
  • Release Date: July 13, 2017 [EBook #55108]
  • Language: English
  • Character set encoding: UTF-8
  • *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE LOGIC OF HEGEL ***
  • Produced by Marc D'Hooghe at Free Literature (online soon
  • in an extended version, also linking to free sources for
  • education worldwide ... MOOC's, educational materials,...)
  • Images generously made available by the Hathi Trust.
  • THE LOGIC OF HEGEL
  • _TRANSLATED FROM_
  • _THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF THE
  • PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES_
  • WILLIAM WALLACE, M.A, LL.D.
  • FELLOW OF MERTON COLLEGE
  • AND WHYTE'S PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY
  • IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD
  • SECOND EDITION, REVISED AND AUGMENTED
  • OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
  • 1892
  • NOTE
  • The present volume contains a translation, which has been revised
  • throughout and compared with the original, of the Logic as given in the
  • first part of Hegel's _Encyclopaedia,_ preceded by a bibliographical
  • account of the three editions and extracts from the prefaces of that
  • work, and followed by notes and illustrations of a philological rather
  • than a philosophical character on the text. This introductory chapter
  • and these notes were not included in the previous edition.
  • The volume containing my Prolegomena is under revision and will be
  • issued shortly.
  • W. W.
  • CONTENTS
  • BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTICE ON THE THREE EDITIONS AND THREE PREFACES OF THE
  • ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES
  • _THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC._
  • CHAPTER I.
  • INTRODUCTION
  • CHAPTER II.
  • PRELIMINARY NOTION
  • CHAPTER III.
  • FIRST ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY
  • CHAPTER IV.
  • SECOND ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY:
  • I. _Empiricism_
  • II. _The Critical Philosophy_
  • CHAPTER V.
  • THIRD ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY:--
  • _Immediate or Intuitive Knowledge_
  • CHAPTER VI.
  • LOGIC FURTHER DEFINED AND DIVIDED
  • CHAPTER VII.
  • FIRST SUBDIVISION OF LOGIC:--_The Doctrine of Being_
  • CHAPTER VIII.
  • SECOND SUBDIVISION OF LOGIC:--_The Doctrine of Essence_
  • CHAPTER IX.
  • THIRD SUBDIVISION OF LOGIC:--_The Doctrine of the Notion_
  • NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS.
  • ON CHAPTER
  • I
  • II
  • III
  • IV
  • V
  • VI
  • VII
  • VIII
  • IX
  • BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTICE
  • ON THE THREE EDITIONS AND THREE PREFACES OF THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA
  • THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES IN OUTLINE is the third
  • in time of the four works which Hegel published. It was preceded by
  • the _Phenomenology of Spirit,_ in 1807, and the _Science of Logic_ (in
  • two volumes), in 1812-16, and was followed by the _Outlines of the
  • Philosophy of Law_ in 1820. The only other works which came directly
  • from his hand are a few essays, addresses, and reviews. The earliest
  • of these appeared in the _Critical Journal of Philosophy,_ issued by
  • his friend Schelling and himself, in 1802--when Hegel was one and
  • thirty, which, as Bacon thought, 'is a great deal of sand in the
  • hour-glass'; and the latest were his contributions to the _Jahrbücher
  • für wissenschaftliche Kritik,_ in the year of his death (1831).
  • This _Encyclopaedia_ is the only complete, matured, and authentic
  • statement of Hegel's philosophical system. But, as the title-page
  • bears, it is only an outline; and its primary aim is to supply a manual
  • for the guidance of his students. In its mode of exposition the free
  • flight of speculation is subordinated to the needs of the professorial
  • class-room. Pegasus is put in harness. Paragraphs concise in form and
  • saturated with meaning postulate and presuppose the presiding spirit
  • of the lecturer to fuse them into continuity and raise them to higher
  • lucidity. Yet in two directions the works of Hegel furnish a supplement
  • to the defects of the _Encyclopaedia._
  • One of these aids to comprehension is the _Phenomenology of Spirit,_
  • published in his thirty-seventh year. It may be going too far to say
  • with David Strauss that it is the Alpha and Omega of Hegel, and his
  • later writings only extracts from it.[1] Yet here the Pegasus of mind
  • soars free through untrodden fields of air, and tastes the joys of
  • first love and the pride of fresh discovery in the quest for truth. The
  • fire of young enthusiasm has not yet been forced to hide itself and
  • smoulder away in apparent calm. The mood is Olympian--far above the
  • turmoil and bitterness of lower earth, free from the bursts of temper
  • which emerge later, when the thinker has to mingle in the fray and
  • endure the shafts of controversy. But the _Phenomenology,_ if not less
  • than the _Encyclopaedia_ it contains the diamond purity of Hegelianism,
  • is a key which needs consummate patience and skill to use with
  • advantage. If it commands a larger view, it demands a stronger wing of
  • him who would join its voyage through the atmosphere of thought up to
  • its purest empyrean. It may be the royal road to the Idea, but only a
  • kingly soul can retrace its course.
  • The other commentary on the _Encyclopaedia_ is supplied partly by
  • Hegel's other published writings, and partly by the volumes (IX-XV in
  • the Collected works) in which his editors have given his Lectures on
  • the Philosophy of History, on Aesthetic, on the Philosophy of Religion,
  • and on the History of Philosophy. All of these lectures, as well as
  • the _Philosophy of Law,_ published by himself, deal however only with
  • the third part of the philosophic system. That system (p. 28) includes
  • (i) Logic, (ii) Philosophy of Nature, and (iii) Philosophy of Spirit.
  • It is this third part--or rather it is the last two divisions therein
  • (embracing the great general interests of humanity, such as law and
  • morals, religion and art, as well as the development of philosophy
  • itself) which form the topics of Hegel s most expanded teaching. It
  • is in this region that he has most appealed to the liberal culture of
  • the century, and influenced (directly or by reaction) the progress of
  • that philosophical history and historical philosophy of which our own
  • generation is reaping the fast-accumulating fruit. If one may foist
  • such a category into systematic philosophy, we may say that the study
  • of the 'Objective' and 'Absolute Spirit' is the most _interesting_ part
  • of Hegel.
  • Of the second part of the system there is less to be said. For nearly
  • half a century the study of nature has passed almost completely out
  • of the hands of the philosophers into the care of the specialists of
  • science. There are signs indeed everywhere--and among others Helmholtz
  • has lately reminded us--that the higher order of scientific students
  • are ever and anon driven by the very logic of their subject into the
  • precincts or the borders of philosophy. But the name of a Philosophy
  • of Nature still recalls a time of hasty enthusiasms and over-grasping
  • ambition of thought which, in its eagerness to understand the mystery
  • of the universe jumped to conclusions on insufficient grounds, trusted
  • to bold but fantastic analogies, and lavished an unwise contempt on the
  • plodding industry of the mere hodman of facts and experiments. Calmer
  • retrospection will perhaps modify this verdict, and sift the various
  • contributions (towards a philosophical unity of the sciences) which
  • are now indiscriminately damned by the title of _Naturphilosophie._
  • For the present purpose it need only be said that, for the second
  • part of the Hegelian system, we are restricted for explanations
  • to the notes collected by the editors of Vol. VII. part i. of the
  • Collected works--notes derived from the annotations which Hegel himself
  • supplied in the eight or more courses of lectures which he gave on the
  • Philosophy of Nature between 1804 and 1830.
  • Quite other is the case with the Logic--the first division of the
  • _Encyclopaedia._ There we have the collateral authority of the
  • 'Science of Logic,' the larger Logic which appeared whilst Hegel was
  • schoolmaster at Nürnberg. The idea of a new Logic formed the natural
  • sequel to the publication of the _Phenomenology_ in 1807. In that
  • year Hegel was glad to accept, as a stop-gap and pot-boiler, the post
  • of editor of the Bamberg Journal. But his interests lay in other
  • directions, and the circumstances of the time and country helped to
  • determine their special form. 'In Bavaria,' he says in a letter[2],
  • 'it looks as if organisation were the current business.' A very mania
  • of reform, says another, prevailed. Hegel's friend and fellow-Swabian,
  • Niethammer, held an important position in the Bavarian education
  • office, and wished to employ the philosopher in the work of carrying
  • out his plans of re-organising the higher education of the Protestant
  • subjects of the crown. He asked if Hegel would write a logic for school
  • use, and if he cared to become rector of a grammar school. Hegel, who
  • was already at work on his larger Logic, was only half-attracted by
  • the suggestion. 'The traditional Logic,' he replied[3], 'is a subject
  • on which there are text-books enough, but at the same time it is one
  • which can by no means remain as it is: it is a thing nobody can make
  • anything of: 'tis dragged along like an old heirloom, only because
  • a substitute--of which the want is universally felt--is not yet in
  • existence. The whole of its rules, still current, might be written
  • on two pages: every additional detail beyond these two is perfectly
  • fruitless scholastic subtlety;--or if this logic is to get a thicker
  • body, its expansion must come from psychological paltrinesses,' Still
  • less did he like the prospect of instructing in theology, as then
  • rationalised. 'To write a logic and to be theological instructor is as
  • bad as to be white-washer and chimney-sweep at once.' 'Shall he, who
  • for many long years built his eyry on the wild rock beside the eagle
  • and learned to breathe the free air of the mountains, now learn to feed
  • on the carcases of dead thoughts or the still-born thoughts of the
  • moderns, and vegetate in the leaden air of mere babble[4]?'
  • At Nürnberg he found the post of rector of the 'gymnasium' by no
  • means a sinecure. The school had to be made amid much lack of funds
  • and general bankruptcy of apparatus:--all because of an all-powerful
  • and unalterable destiny which is called the course of business.' One
  • of his tasks was 'by graduated exercises to introduce his pupils to
  • speculative thought,'--and that in the space of four hours weekly[5].
  • Of its practicability--and especially with himself as instrument--he
  • had grave doubts. In theory, he held that an intelligent study of
  • the ancient classics was the best introduction to philosophy; and
  • practically he preferred starting his pupils with the principles
  • of law, morality and religion, and reserving the logic and higher
  • philosophy for the highest class. Meanwhile he continued to work on
  • his great Logic, the first volume of which appeared in two parts, 1812,
  • 1813, and the second in 1816.
  • This is the work which is the real foundation of the Hegelian
  • philosophy. Its aim is the systematic reorganisation of the
  • commonwealth of thought. It gives not a criticism, like Kant; not
  • a principle, like Fichte; not a bird's eye view of the fields of
  • nature and history, like Schelling; it attempts the hard work of
  • re-constructing, step by step, into totality the fragments of the
  • organism of intelligence. It is scholasticism, if scholasticism means
  • an absolute and all-embracing system; but it is a protest against
  • the old school-system and those who tried to rehabilitate it through
  • their comprehensions of the Kantian theory. Apropos of the logic of
  • his contemporary Fries (whom he did not love), published in 1811, he
  • remarks: 'His paragraphs are mindless, quite shallow, bald, trivial;
  • the explanatory notes are the dirty linen of the professorial chair,
  • utterly slack and unconnected.'[6] Of himself he thus speaks: 'I am
  • a schoolmaster who has to teach philosophy,--who, possibly for that
  • reason, believes that philosophy like geometry is teachable, and
  • must no less than geometry have a regular structure. But again, a
  • knowledge of the facts in geometry and philosophy is one thing, and the
  • mathematical or philosophical talent which procreates and discovers is
  • another: my province is to discover that scientific form, or to aid
  • in the formation of it[7].' So he writes to an old college friend;
  • and in a letter to the rationalist theologian Paulus, in 1814[8], he
  • professes: 'You know that I have had too much to do not merely with
  • ancient literature, but even with mathematics, latterly with the higher
  • analysis, differential calculus, chemistry, to let myself be taken in
  • by the humbug of Naturphilosophie, philosophising without knowledge of
  • fact and by mere force of imagination, and treating mere fancies, even
  • imbecile fancies, as Ideas.'
  • In the autumn of 1816 Hegel became professor of philosophy at
  • Heidelberg. In the following year appeared the first edition of his
  • _Encyclopaedia_: two others appeared in his lifetime (in 1827 and
  • 1830). The first edition is a thin octavo volume of pp. xvi. 288,
  • published (like the others) at Heidelberg. The Logic in it occupies
  • pp. 1-126 (of which 12 pp. are Einleitung and 18 pp. Vorbegriff); the
  • Philosophy of Nature, pp. 127-204; and the Philosophy of Mind (Spirit),
  • pp. 205-288.
  • In the Preface the book is described (p. iv) as setting forth 'a new
  • treatment of philosophy on a method which will, as I hope, yet be
  • recognised as the only genuine method identical with the content.'
  • Contrasting his own procedure with a mannerism of the day which
  • used an assumed set of formulas to produce in the facts a show of
  • symmetry even more arbitrary and mechanical than the arrangements
  • imposed _ab extra_ in the sciences, he goes on: 'This wilfulness we
  • saw also take possession of the contents of philosophy and ride out
  • on an intellectual knight-errantry--for a while imposing on honest
  • true-hearted workers, though elsewhere it was only counted grotesque,
  • and grotesque even to the pitch of madness. But oftener and more
  • properly its teachings--far from seeming imposing or mad--were found
  • out to be familiar trivialities, and its form seen to be a mere trick
  • of wit, easily acquired, methodical and premeditated, with its quaint
  • combinations and strained eccentricities,--the mien of earnestness only
  • covering self-deception and fraud upon the public. On the other side,
  • again, we saw shallowness and unintelligence assume the character of
  • a scepticism wise in its own eyes and of a criticism modest in its
  • claims for reason, enhancing their vanity and conceit in proportion
  • as their ideas grew more vacuous. For a space of time these two
  • intellectual tendencies have befooled German earnestness, have tired
  • out its profound craving for philosophy, and have been succeeded by
  • an indifference and even a contempt for philosophic science, till at
  • length a self-styled modesty has the audacity to let its voice be heard
  • in controversies touching the deepest philosophical problems, and to
  • deny philosophy its right to that cognition by reason, the form of
  • which was what formerly was called _demonstration._'
  • 'The first of these phenomena may be in part explained as the youthful
  • exuberance of the new age which has risen in the realm of science no
  • less than in the world of politics. If this exuberance greeted with
  • rapture the dawn of the intellectual renascence, and without profounder
  • labour at once set about enjoying the Idea and revelling for a while in
  • the hopes and prospects which it offered, one can more readily forgive
  • its excesses; because it is sound at heart, and the surface vapours
  • which it had suffused around its solid worth must spontaneously clear
  • off. But the other spectacle is more repulsive; because it betrays
  • exhaustion and impotence, and tries to conceal them under a hectoring
  • conceit which acts the censor over the philosophical intellects of all
  • the centuries, mistaking them, but most of all mistaking itself.
  • 'So much the more gratifying is another spectacle yet-to be noted; the
  • interest in philosophy and the earnest love of higher knowledge which
  • in the presence of both tendencies has kept itself single-hearted and
  • without affectation. Occasionally this interest may have taken too
  • much to the language of intuition and feeling; yet its appearance
  • proves the existence of that inward and deeper-reaching impulse of
  • reasonable intelligence which alone gives man his dignity,--proves it
  • above all, because that standpoint can only be gained as a _result_
  • of philosophical consciousness; so that what it seems to disdain is
  • at least admitted and recognised as a condition. To this interest
  • in ascertaining the truth I dedicate this attempt to supply an
  • introduction and a contribution towards its satisfaction.'
  • The second edition appeared in 1827. Since the autumn of 1818 Hegel
  • had been professor at Berlin: and the manuscript was sent thence (from
  • August 1826 onwards) to Heidelberg, where Daub, his friend--himself
  • a master in philosophical theology--attended to the revision of the
  • proofs. 'To the Introduction,' writes Hegel[9], 'I have given perhaps
  • too great an amplitude: but it, above all, would have cost me time and
  • trouble to bring within narrower compass. Tied down and distracted
  • by lectures, and sometimes here in Berlin by other things too, I
  • have--without a general survey--allowed myself so large a swing that
  • the work has grown upon me, and there was a danger of its turning into
  • a book. I have gone through it several times. The treatment of the
  • attitudes (of thought) which I have distinguished in it was to meet an
  • interest of the day. The rest I have sought to make more definite, and
  • so far as may be clearer; but the main fault is not mended--to do which
  • would require me to limit the detail more, and on the other hand make
  • the whole more surveyable, so that the contents should better answer
  • the title of an Encyclopaedia.' Again, in Dec. 1826, he writes[10]: 'In
  • the Naturphilosophie I have made essential changes, but could not help
  • here and there going too far into a detail which is hardly in keeping
  • with the tone of the whole. The second half of the Geistesphilosophie
  • I shall have to modify entirely.' In May 1827, Hegel offers his
  • explanation of delay in the preface, which, like the concluding
  • paragraphs, touches largely on contemporary theology. By August of that
  • year the book was finished, and Hegel off to Paris for a holiday.
  • In the second edition, which substantially fixed the form of the
  • _Encyclopaedia_, the pages amount to xlii, 534--nearly twice as many
  • as the first, which, however, as Professor Caird remarks, 'has a
  • compactness, a brief energy and conclusiveness of expression, which
  • he never surpassed.' The Logic now occupies pp. 1214, Philosophy of
  • Nature 215-354, and Philosophy of Spirit from 355-534. The second part
  • therefore has gained least; and in the third part the chief single
  • expansions occur towards the close and deal with the relations of
  • philosophy, art, and religion in the State; viz. § 563 (which in the
  • third edition is transposed to § 552), and § 573 (where two pages are
  • enlarged to 18). In the first part, or the Logic, the main increase
  • and alteration falls within the introductory chapters, where 96 pages
  • take the place of 30. The Vorbegriff (preliminary notion) of the first
  • edition had contained the distinction of the three logical 'moments'
  • (see p. 142), with a few remarks on the methods, first, of metaphysic,
  • and then (after a brief section on empiricism), of the 'Critical
  • Philosophy through which philosophy has reached its close.' Instead
  • of this the second edition deals at length, under this head, with the
  • three 'attitudes (or positions) of thought to objectivity;' where,
  • besides a more lengthy criticism of the Critical philosophy, there is a
  • discussion of the doctrines of Jacobi and other Intuitivists.
  • The Preface, like much else in this second edition, is an assertion
  • of the right and the duty of philosophy to treat independently of
  • the things of God, and an emphatic declaration that the result of
  • scientific investigation of the truth is, not the subversion of
  • the faith, but 'the restoration of that sum of absolute doctrine
  • which thought at first would have put behind and beneath itself--a
  • restoration of it however in the most characteristic and the freest
  • element of the mind.' Any opposition that may be raised against
  • philosophy on religious grounds proceeds, according to Hegel, from a
  • religion which has abandoned its true basis and entrenched itself in
  • formulae and categories that pervert its real nature. 'Yet,' he adds
  • (p. vii), 'especially where religious subjects are under discussion,
  • philosophy is expressly set aside, as if in that way all mischief were
  • banished and security against error and illusion attained;' ... 'as if
  • philosophy--the mischief thus kept at a distance--were anything but
  • the investigation of Truth, but with a full sense of the nature and
  • value of the intellectual links which give unity and form to all fact
  • whatever.' 'Lessing,' he continues (p. xvi), 'said in his time that
  • people treat Spinoza like a dead dog[11]. It cannot be said that in
  • recent times Spinozism and speculative philosophy in general have been
  • better treated.'
  • The time was one of feverish unrest and unwholesome irritability. Ever
  • since the so-called Carlsbad decrees of 1819 all the agencies of the
  • higher literature and education had been subjected to an inquisitorial
  • supervision which everywhere surmised political insubordination and
  • religious heresy. A petty provincialism pervaded what was then still
  • the small Residenz-Stadt Berlin; and the King, Frederick William
  • III, cherished to the full that paternal conception of his position
  • which has not been unusual in the royal house of Prussia. Champions
  • of orthodoxy warned him that Hegelianism was unchristian, if not even
  • anti-christian. Franz von Baader, the Bavarian religious philosopher
  • (who had spent some months at Berlin during the winter of 1823-4,
  • studying the religious and philosophical teaching of the universities
  • in connexion with the revolutionary doctrines which he saw fermenting
  • throughout Europe), addressed the king in a communication which
  • described the prevalent Protestant theology as infidel in its very
  • source, and as tending directly to annihilate the foundations of
  • the faith. Hegel himself had to remind the censor of heresy that
  • 'all speculative philosophy on religion maybe carried to atheism:
  • all depends on who carries it; the peculiar piety of our times and
  • the malevolence of demagogues will not let us want carriers[12].'
  • His own theology was suspected both by the Rationalists and by the
  • Evangelicals. He writes to his wife (in 1827) that he had looked at
  • the university buildings in Louvain and Liège with the feeling that
  • they might one day afford him a resting-place 'when the parsons in
  • Berlin make the Kupfergraben completely intolerable for him[13].' 'The
  • Roman Curia,' he adds, 'would be a more honourable opponent than the
  • miserable cabals of a miserable boiling of parsons in Berlin.' Hence
  • the tone in which the preface proceeds (p. xviii).
  • 'Religion is the kind and mode of consciousness in which the Truth
  • appeals to all men, to men of every degree of education; but the
  • scientific ascertainment of the Truth is a special kind of this
  • consciousness, involving a labour which not all but only a few
  • undertake. The substance of the two is the same; but as Homer says of
  • some stars that they have two names, the one in the language of the
  • gods, the other in the language of ephemeral men--so for that substance
  • there are two languages,--the one of feeling, of pictorial thought,
  • and of the limited intellect that makes its home in finite categories
  • and inadequate abstractions, the other the language of the concrete
  • notion. If we propose then to talk of and to criticise philosophy from
  • the religious point of view, there is more requisite than to possess
  • a familiarity with the language of the ephemeral consciousness. The
  • foundation of scientific cognition is the substantiality at its core,
  • the indwelling idea with its stirring intellectual life; just as the
  • essentials of religion are a heart fully disciplined, a mind awake to
  • self-collectedness, a wrought and refined substantiality. In modern
  • times religion has more and more contracted the intelligent expansion
  • of its contents and withdrawn into the intensiveness of piety, or even
  • of feeling,--a feeling which betrays its own scantiness and emptiness.
  • So long however as it still has a creed, a doctrine, a system of dogma,
  • it has what philosophy can occupy itself with and where it can find for
  • itself a point of union with religion. This however is not to be taken
  • in the wrong separatist sense (so dominant in our modern religiosity)
  • representing the two as mutually exclusive, or as at bottom so capable
  • of separation that their union is only imposed from without. Rather,
  • even in what has gone before, it is implied that religion may well
  • exist without philosophy, but philosophy not without religion--which
  • it rather includes. True religion--intellectual and spiritual
  • religion--must have body and substance, for spirit and intellect are
  • above all consciousness, and consciousness implies an _objective_ body
  • and substance.
  • 'The contracted religiosity which narrows itself to a point in the
  • heart must make that heart's softening and contrition the essential
  • factor of its new birth; but it must at the same time recollect that it
  • has to do with the heart of a spirit, that the spirit is the appointed
  • authority over the heart, and that it can only have such authority so
  • far as it is itself born again. This new birth of the spirit out of
  • natural ignorance and natural error takes place through instruction and
  • through that faith in objective truth and substance which is due to the
  • witness of the spirit. This new birth of the spirit is besides _ipso
  • facto_ a new birth of the heart out of that vanity of the one-sided
  • intellect (on which it sets so much) and its discoveries that finite is
  • different from infinite, that philosophy must either be polytheism, or,
  • in acuter minds, pantheism, &c. It is, in short, a new birth out of the
  • wretched discoveries on the strength of which pious humility holds its
  • head so high against philosophy and theological science. If religiosity
  • persists in clinging to its unexpanded and therefore unintelligent
  • intensity, then it can be sensible only of the contrast which divides
  • this narrow and narrowing form from the intelligent expansion of
  • doctrine as such, religious not less than philosophical.'
  • After an appreciative quotation from Franz von Baader, and noting his
  • reference to the theosophy of Böhme, as a work of the past from which
  • the present generation might learn the speculative interpretation of
  • Christian doctrines, he reverts to the position that the only mode in
  • which thought will admit a reconciliation with religious doctrines, is
  • when these doctrines have learned to 'assume their worthiest phase--the
  • phase of the notion, of necessity, which binds, and thus also makes
  • free everything, fact no less than thought.' But it is not from Böhme
  • or his kindred that we are likely to get the example of a philosophy
  • equal to the highest theme--to the comprehension of divine things. 'If
  • old things are to be revived--an old phase, that is; for the burden
  • of the theme is ever young--the phase of the Idea such as Plato and,
  • still better, as Aristotle conceived it, is far more deserving of being
  • recalled,--and for the further reason that the disclosure of it, by
  • assimilating it into our system of ideas, is, _ipso facto,_ not merely
  • an interpretation of it, but a progress of the science itself. But
  • to interpret such forms of the Idea by no means lies so much on the
  • surface as to get hold of Gnostic and Cabbalistic phantasmagorias; and
  • to develope Plato and Aristotle is by no means the sinecure that it is
  • to note or to hint at echoes of the Idea in the medievalists.'
  • The third edition of the _Encyclopaedia,_ which appeared in 1830,
  • consists of pp. lviii, 600--a slight additional increase. The increase
  • is in the Logic, eight pages; in the Philosophy of Nature, twenty-three
  • pages; and in the Philosophy of Spirit, thirty-four pages. The concrete
  • topics, in short, gain most.
  • The preface begins by alluding to several criticisms on his
  • philosophy,--'which for the most part have shown little vocation for
  • the business'--and to his discussion of them in the _Jahrbücher_ of
  • 1829 (_Vermischte Schriften,_ ii. 149). There is also a paragraph
  • devoted to the quarrel originated by the attack in Hengstenberg's
  • Evangelical Journal on the rationalism of certain professors at Halle
  • (notably Gesenius and Wegscheider),--(an attack based on the evidence
  • of students' note-books), and by the protest of students and professors
  • against the insinuations. 'It seemed a little while ago,' says Hegel
  • (p. xli), 'as if there was an initiation, in a scientific spirit
  • and on a wider range, of a more serious inquiry, from the region of
  • theology and even of religiosity, touching God, divine things, and
  • reason. But the very beginning of the movement checked these hopes;
  • the issue turned on personalities, and neither the pretensions of the
  • accusing pietists nor the pretensions of the free reason they accused,
  • rose to the real subject, still less to a sense that the subject
  • could only be discussed on philosophic soil. This personal attack, on
  • the basis of very special externalities of religion, displayed the
  • monstrous assumption of seeking to decide by arbitrary decree as to
  • the Christianity of individuals, and to stamp them accordingly with
  • the seal of temporal and eternal reprobation. Dante, in virtue of the
  • enthusiasm of divine poesy, has dared to handle the keys of Peter, and
  • to condemn by name to the perdition of hell many--already deceased
  • however--of his contemporaries, even Popes and Emperors. A modern
  • philosophy has been made the subject of the infamous charge that in
  • it human individuals usurp the rank of God; but such a fictitious
  • charge--reached by a false logic--pales before the actual assumption
  • of behaving like judges of the world, prejudging the Christianity of
  • individuals, and announcing their utter reprobation. The Shibboleth
  • of this absolute authority is the name of the Lord Christ, and the
  • assertion that the Lord dwells in the hearts of these judges.' But the
  • assertion is ill supported by the fruits they exhibit,--the monstrous
  • insolence with which they reprobate and condemn.
  • But the evangelicals are not alone to blame for the bald and
  • undeveloped nature of their religious life; the same want of free and
  • living growth in religion characterises their opponents. 'By their
  • formal, abstract, nerveless reasoning, the rationalists have emptied
  • religion of all power and substance, no less than the pietists by the
  • reduction of all faith to the Shibboleth of Lord! Lord! One is no
  • whit better than the other: and when they meet in conflict there is
  • no material on which they could come into contact, no common ground,
  • and no possibility of carrying on an inquiry which would lead to
  • knowledge and truth. "Liberal" theology on its side has not got beyond
  • the formalism of appeals to liberty of conscience, liberty of thought,
  • liberty of teaching, to reason itself and to science. Such liberty no
  • doubt describes the _infinite right_ of the spirit, and the second
  • special condition of truth, supplementary to the first, faith. But
  • the rationalists steer clear of the material point: they do not tell
  • us the reasonable principles and laws involved in a free and genuine
  • conscience, nor the import and teaching of free faith and free thought;
  • they do not get beyond a bare negative formalism and the liberty to
  • embody their liberty at their fancy and pleasure--whereby in the end
  • it matters not how it is embodied. There is a further reason for
  • their failure to reach a solid doctrine. The Christian community must
  • be, and ought always to be, unified by the tie of a doctrinal idea,
  • a confession of faith; but the generalities and abstractions of the
  • stale, not living, waters of rationalism forbid the specificality of
  • an inherently definite and fully developed body of Christian doctrine.
  • Their opponents, again, proud of the name Lord! Lord! frankly and
  • openly disdain carrying out the faith into the fulness of spirit,
  • reality, and truth.'
  • In ordinary moods of mind there is a long way from logic to religion.
  • But almost every page of what Hegel has called Logic is witness to
  • the belief in their ultimate identity. It was no new principle of
  • later years for him. He had written in post-student days to his
  • friend Schelling: 'Reason and freedom remain our watch-word, and our
  • point of union the invisible church[14].' His parting token of faith
  • with another youthful comrade, the poet Hölderlin, had been 'God's
  • kingdom[15].'
  • But after 1827 this religious appropriation of philosophy becomes
  • more apparent, and in 1829 Hegel seemed deliberately to accept the
  • position of a Christian philosopher which Göschel had marked out for
  • him. 'A philosophy without heart and a faith without intellect,' he
  • remarks[16], 'are abstractions from the true life of knowledge and
  • faith. The man whom philosophy leaves cold, and the man whom real faith
  • does not illuminate may be assured that the fault lies in them, not in
  • knowledge and faith. The former is still an alien to philosophy, the
  • latter an alien to faith.'
  • This is not the place--in a philological chapter--to discuss the issues
  • involved in the announcement that the truth awaits us ready to hand[17]
  • 'in all genuine consciousness, in all religions and philosophies.'
  • Yet one remark may be offered against hasty interpretations of a
  • 'speculative' identity. If there is a double edge to the proposition
  • that the actual is the reasonable, there is no less caution necessary
  • in approaching and studying from both sides the far-reaching import
  • of that equation to which Joannes Scotus Erigena gave expression ten
  • centuries ago: '_Non alia est philosophia, i.e. sapientiae studium,
  • et alia religio. Quid est aliud de philosophia tractare nisi verae
  • religionis regulas exponere?_'
  • [1] _Christian Märklin,_ cap. 3.
  • [2] Hegel's _Briefe,_ i. 141.
  • [3] _Ibid._ i. 172.
  • [4] Hegel's _Briefe,_ i. 138.
  • [5] _Ibid._ i. 339.
  • [6] Hegel's _Briefe,_ i. 328.
  • [7] _Ibid._ i. 273.
  • [8] _Ibid._ i. 373.
  • [9] Hegel's _Briefe,_ ii. 204.
  • [10] _Ibid._ ii. 230.
  • [11] Jacobi's _Werke,_ iv. A, p. 63.
  • [12] Hegel's _Briefe,_ ii. 54.
  • [13] _Ibid._ ii. 276.
  • [14] Hegel's _Briefe,_ i. 13.
  • [15] Hölderlin's _Leben_ (Litzmann), p. 183.
  • [16] _Verm. Sehr._ ii. 144.
  • [17] Hegel's _Briefe,_ ii. 80.
  • * * * * *
  • _The following Errata in the Edition of the Logic as given in the
  • Collected Works (Vol. VI.) are corrected in the translation. The
  • references in brackets are to the_ German text.
  • Page 95, line 1. Und Objektivität has dropped out after der
  • Subjektivität. [VI. 98, l. 10 from bottom.]
  • P. 97, l. 2. The 2nd ed. reads (die Gedanken) nicht in Solchem, instead
  • of nicht als in Solchem (3rd ed.). [VI. p. 100, l. 3 from bottom.]
  • P. 169, l. 13 from bottom. Instead of the reading of the _Werke_ and of
  • the 3rd ed. read as in ed. II. Also ist dieser Gegenstand nichts. [VI.
  • p. 178, l. 11.]
  • P. 177, l. 3 from bottom. Verstandes; Gegenstandes is a mistake for
  • Verstandes; Gegensatzes, as in edd. II and III. [VI. p. 188, l. 2.]
  • P. 231, l. 19. weiten should be weitern. [VI. p. 251, l. 3 from bottom.]
  • P. 316, l. 15. Dinglichkeit is a misprint for Dingheit, as in Hegel's
  • own editions. [VI. p. 347, l. 1.]
  • P. 352, l. 14 from bottom, for seine Realität read seiner Realität.
  • [VI. p. 385, l. 8.]
  • THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC
  • (_THE FIRST PART OF THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES IN
  • OUTLINE_)
  • BY G. W. F. HEGEL
  • THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC
  • CHAPTER I.
  • INTRODUCTION.
  • 1.] PHILOSOPHY misses an advantage enjoyed by the other sciences. It
  • cannot like them rest the existence of its objects on the natural
  • admissions of consciousness, nor can it assume that its method of
  • cognition, either for starting or for continuing, is one already
  • accepted. The objects of philosophy, it is true, are upon the whole the
  • same as those of religion. In both the object is Truth, in that supreme
  • sense in which God and God only is the Truth. Both in like manner go on
  • to treat of the finite worlds of Nature and the human Mind, with their
  • relation to each other and to their truth in God. Some _acquaintance_
  • with its objects, therefore, philosophy may and even must presume, that
  • and a certain interest in them to boot, were it for no other reason
  • than this: that in point of time the mind makes general _images_ of
  • objects, long before it makes _notions_ of them, and that it is only
  • through these mental images, and by recourse to them, that the thinking
  • mind rises to know and comprehend _thinkingly._
  • But with the rise of this thinking study of things, it soon becomes
  • evident that thought will be satisfied with nothing short of showing
  • the _necessity_ of its facts, of demonstrating the existence of
  • its objects, as well as their nature and qualities. Our original
  • acquaintance with them is thus discovered to be inadequate. We can
  • assume nothing, and assert nothing dogmatically; nor can we accept the
  • assertions and assumptions of others. And yet we must make a beginning:
  • and a beginning, as primary and underived, makes an assumption, or
  • rather is an assumption. It seems as if it were impossible to make a
  • beginning at all.
  • 2.] This _thinking study of things_ may serve, in a general way, as
  • a description of philosophy. But the description is too wide. If it
  • be correct to say, that thought makes the distinction between man and
  • the lower animals, then everything human is human, for the sole and
  • simple reason that it is due to the operation of thought. Philosophy,
  • on the other hand, is a peculiar mode of thinking--a mode in which
  • thinking becomes knowledge, and knowledge through notions. However
  • great therefore may be the identity and essential unity of the two
  • modes of thought, the philosophic mode gets to be different from the
  • more general thought which acts in all that is human, in all that gives
  • humanity its distinctive character. And this difference connects itself
  • with the fact that the strictly human and thought-induced phenomena of
  • consciousness do not originally appear in the form of a thought, but as
  • a feeling, a perception, or mental image--all of which aspects must be
  • distinguished from the form of thought proper.
  • According to an old preconceived idea, which has passed into a trivial
  • proposition, it is thought which marks the man off from the animals.
  • Yet trivial as this old belief may seem, it must, strangely enough,
  • be recalled to mind in presence of certain preconceived ideas of the
  • present day. These ideas would put feeling and thought so far apart as
  • to make them opposites, and would represent them as so antagonistic,
  • that feeling, particularly religious feeling, is supposed to be
  • contaminated, perverted, and even annihilated by thought. They also
  • emphatically hold that religion and piety grow out of, and rest upon
  • something else, and not on thought. But those who make this separation
  • forget meanwhile that only man has the capacity for religion, and that
  • animals no more have religion than they have law and morality.
  • Those who insist on this separation of religion from thinking usually
  • have before their minds the sort of thought that may be styled
  • _after-thought._ They mean 'reflective' thinking, which has to deal
  • with thoughts as thoughts, and brings them into consciousness.
  • Slackness to perceive and keep in view this distinction which
  • philosophy definitely draws in respect of thinking is the source of
  • the crudest objections and reproaches against philosophy. Man,--and
  • that just because it is his nature to think,--is the only being that
  • possesses law, religion, and morality. In these spheres of human life,
  • therefore, thinking, under the guise of feeling, faith, or generalised
  • image, has not been inactive: its action and its productions are
  • there present and therein contained. But it is one thing to have such
  • feelings and generalised images that have been moulded and permeated by
  • thought, and another thing to have thoughts about them. The thoughts,
  • to which after-thought upon those modes of consciousness gives rise,
  • are what is comprised under reflection, general reasoning, and the
  • like, as well as under philosophy itself.
  • The neglect of this distinction between thought in general and the
  • reflective thought of philosophy has also led to another and more
  • frequent misunderstanding. Reflection of this kind has been often
  • maintained to be the condition, or even the only way, of attaining a
  • consciousness and certitude of the Eternal and True. The (now somewhat
  • antiquated) metaphysical proofs of God's existence, for example, have
  • been treated, as if a knowledge of them and a conviction of their truth
  • were the only and essential means of producing a belief and conviction
  • that there is a God. Such a doctrine would find its parallel, if we
  • said that eating was impossible before we had acquired a knowledge
  • of the chemical, botanical, and zoological characters of our food;
  • and that we must delay digestion till we had finished the study of
  • anatomy and physiology. Were it so, these sciences in their field,
  • like philosophy in its, would gain greatly in point of utility; in
  • fact, their utility would rise to the height of absolute and universal
  • indispensableness. Or rather, instead of being indispensable, they
  • would not exist at all.
  • 3.] The _Content,_ of whatever kind it be, with which our consciousness
  • is taken up, is what constitutes the qualitative character of our
  • feelings, perceptions, fancies, and ideas; of our aims and duties;
  • and of our thoughts and notions. From this point of view, feeling,
  • perception, &c. are the _forms_ assumed by these contents. The contents
  • remain one and the same, whether they are felt, seen, represented, or
  • willed, and whether they are merely felt, or felt with an admixture of
  • thoughts, or merely and simply thought. In any one of these forms, or
  • in the admixture of several, the contents confront consciousness, or
  • are its _object._ But when they are thus objects of consciousness, the
  • modes of the several forms ally themselves with the contents; and each
  • form of them appears in consequence to give rise to a special object.
  • Thus what is the same at bottom, may look like a different sort of
  • fact.
  • The several modes of feeling, perception, desire, and will, so far
  • as we are _aware_ of them, are in general called ideas (mental
  • representations): and it may be roughly said, that philosophy puts
  • thoughts, categories, or, in more precise language, adequate _notions,_
  • in the place of the generalised images we ordinarily call ideas. Mental
  • impressions such as these may be regarded as the metaphors of thoughts
  • and notions. But to have these figurate conceptions does not imply
  • that we appreciate their intellectual significance, the thoughts and
  • rational notions to which they correspond. Conversely, it is one thing
  • to have thoughts and intelligent notions, and another to know what
  • impressions, perceptions, and feelings correspond to them.
  • This difference will to some extent explain what people call the
  • unintelligibility of philosophy. Their difficulty lies partly in an
  • incapacity--which in itself is nothing but want of habit--for abstract
  • thinking; _i.e._ in an inability to get hold of pure thoughts and move
  • about in them. In our ordinary state of mind, the thoughts are clothed
  • upon and made one with the sensuous or spiritual material of the hour;
  • and in reflection, meditation, and general reasoning, we introduce a
  • blend of thoughts into feelings, percepts, and mental images. (Thus,
  • in propositions where the subject-matter is due to the senses--_e.g._
  • 'This leaf is green'--we have such categories introduced, as being and
  • individuality.) But it is a very different thing to make the thoughts
  • pure and simple our object.
  • But their complaint that philosophy is unintelligible is as much due to
  • another reason; and that is an impatient wish to have before them as a
  • mental picture that which is in the mind as a thought or notion. When
  • people are asked to apprehend some notion, they often complain that
  • they do not know what they have to think. But the fact is that in a
  • notion there is nothing further to be thought than the notion itself.
  • What the phrase reveals, is a hankering after an image with which we
  • are already familiar. The mind, denied the use of its familiar ideas,
  • feels the ground where it once stood firm and at home taken away from
  • beneath it, and, when transported into the region of pure thought,
  • cannot tell where in the world it is.
  • One consequence of this weakness is that authors, preachers, and
  • orators are found most intelligible, when they speak of things which
  • their readers or hearers already know by rote,--things which the latter
  • are conversant with, and which require no explanation.
  • 4.] The philosopher then has to reckon with popular modes of thought,
  • and with the objects of religion. In dealing with the ordinary modes
  • of mind, he will first of all, as we saw, have to prove and almost
  • to awaken the need for his peculiar method of knowledge. In dealing
  • with the objects of religion, and with truth as a whole, he will have
  • to show that philosophy is capable of apprehending them from its own
  • resources; and should a difference from religious conceptions come to
  • light, he will have to justify the points in which it diverges.
  • 5.] To give the reader a preliminary explanation of the distinction
  • thus made, and to let him see at the same moment that the real import
  • of our consciousness is retained, and even for the first time put
  • in its proper light, when translated into the form of thought and
  • the notion of reason, it may be well to recall another of these old
  • unreasoned beliefs. And that is the conviction that to get at the truth
  • of any object or event, even of feelings, perceptions, opinions, and
  • mental ideas, we must think it over. Now in any case to think things
  • over is at least to transform feelings, ordinary ideas, &c. into
  • thoughts.
  • Nature has given every one a faculty of thought. But thought is all
  • that philosophy claims as the form proper to her business: and thus
  • the inadequate view which ignores the distinction stated in § 3, leads
  • to a new delusion, the reverse of the complaint previously mentioned
  • about the unintelligibility of philosophy. In other words, this science
  • must often submit to the slight of hearing even people who have never
  • taken any trouble with it talking as if they thoroughly understood all
  • about it. With no preparation beyond an ordinary education they do
  • not hesitate, especially under the influence of religious sentiment,
  • to philosophise and to criticise philosophy. Everybody allows that
  • to know any other science you must have first studied it, and that
  • you can only claim to express a judgment upon it in virtue of such
  • knowledge. Everybody allows that to make a shoe you must have learned
  • and practised the craft of the shoemaker, though every man has a model
  • in his own foot, and possesses in his hands the natural endowments for
  • the operations required. For philosophy alone, it seems to be imagined,
  • such study, care, and application are not in the least requisite.
  • This comfortable view of what is required for a philosopher has
  • recently received corroboration through the theory of immediate or
  • intuitive knowledge.
  • 6.] So much for the form of philosophical knowledge. It is no less
  • desirable, on the other hand, that philosophy should understand that
  • its content is no other than _actuality,_ that core of truth which,
  • originally produced and producing itself within the precincts of the
  • mental life, has become the _world,_ the inward and outward world, of
  • consciousness. At first we become aware of these contents in what we
  • call Experience. But even Experience, as it surveys the wide range
  • of inward and outward existence, has sense enough to distinguish
  • the mere appearance, which is transient and meaningless, from what
  • in itself really deserves the name of actuality. As it is only in
  • form that philosophy is distinguished from other modes of attaining
  • an acquaintance with this same sum of being, it must necessarily be
  • in harmony with actuality and experience. In fact, this harmony may
  • be viewed as at least an extrinsic means of testing the truth of a
  • philosophy. Similarly it may be held the highest and final aim of
  • philosophic science to bring about, through the ascertainment of this
  • harmony, a reconciliation of the self-conscious reason with the reason
  • which _is_ in the world,--in other words, with actuality.
  • In the preface to my Philosophy of Law, p. xix, are found the
  • propositions:
  • What is reasonable is actual;
  • and, What is actual is reasonable.
  • These simple statements have given rise to expressions of surprise and
  • hostility, even in quarters where it would be reckoned an insult to
  • presume absence of philosophy, and still more of religion. Religion
  • at least need not be brought in evidence; its doctrines of the divine
  • government of the world affirm these propositions too decidedly. For
  • their philosophic sense, we must pre-suppose intelligence enough to
  • know, not only that God is actual, that He is the supreme actuality,
  • that He alone is truly actual; but also, as regards the logical
  • bearings of the question, that existence is in part mere appearance,
  • and only in part actuality. In common life, any freak of fancy, any
  • error, evil and everything of the nature of evil, as well as every
  • degenerate and transitory existence whatever, gets in a casual way
  • the name of actuality. But even our ordinary feelings are enough to
  • forbid a casual (fortuitous) existence getting the emphatic name of an
  • actual; for by fortuitous we mean an existence which has no greater
  • value than that of something possible, which may as well not be as
  • be. As for the term Actuality, these critics would have done well to
  • consider the sense in which I employ it. In a detailed Logic I had
  • treated amongst other things of actuality, and accurately distinguished
  • it not only from the fortuitous, which, after all, has existence,
  • but even from the cognate categories of existence and the other
  • modifications of being.
  • The actuality of the rational stands opposed by the popular fancy
  • that Ideas and ideals are nothing but chimeras, and philosophy a mere
  • system of such phantasms. It is also opposed by the very different
  • fancy that Ideas and ideals are something far too excellent to have
  • actuality, or something too impotent to procure it for themselves. This
  • divorce between idea and reality is especially dear to the analytic
  • understanding which looks upon its own abstractions, dreams though they
  • are, as something true and real, and prides itself on the imperative
  • 'ought,' which it takes especial pleasure in prescribing even on the
  • field of politics. As if the world had waited on it to learn how it
  • ought to be, and was not! For, if it were as it ought to be, what would
  • come of the precocious wisdom of that 'ought'? When understanding
  • turns this 'ought' against trivial external and transitory objects,
  • against social regulations or conditions, which very likely possess a
  • great relative importance for a certain time and special circles, it
  • may often be right. In such a case the intelligent observer may meet
  • much that fails to satisfy the general requirements of right; for
  • who is not acute enough to see a great deal in his own surroundings
  • which is really far from being as it ought to be? But such acuteness
  • is mistaken in the conceit that, when it examines these objects and
  • pronounces what they ought to be, it is dealing with questions of
  • philosophic science. The object of philosophy is the Idea: and the Idea
  • is not so impotent as merely to have a right or an obligation to exist
  • without actually existing. The object of philosophy is an actuality of
  • which those objects, social regulations and conditions, are only the
  • superficial outside.
  • 7.] Thus reflection--thinking things over--in a general way involves
  • the principle (which also means the beginning) of philosophy. And when
  • the reflective spirit arose again in its independence in modern times,
  • after the epoch of the Lutheran Reformation, it did not, as in its
  • beginnings among the Greeks, stand merely aloof, in a world of its own,
  • but at once turned its energies also upon the apparently illimitable
  • material of the phenomenal world. In this way the name philosophy came
  • to be applied to all those branches of knowledge, which are engaged
  • in ascertaining the standard and Universal in the ocean of empirical
  • individualities, as well as in ascertaining the Necessary element, or
  • Laws, to be found in the apparent disorder of the endless masses of
  • the fortuitous. It thus appears that modern philosophy derives its
  • materials from our own personal observations and perceptions of the
  • external and internal world, from nature as well as from the mind and
  • heart of man, when both stand in the immediate presence of the observer.
  • This principle of Experience carries with it the unspeakably important
  • condition that, in order to accept and believe any fact, we must be
  • in contact with it; or, in more exact terms, that we must find the
  • fact united and combined with the certainty of our own selves. We must
  • be in touch with our subject-matter, whether it be by means of our
  • external senses, or, else, by our profounder mind and our intimate
  • self-consciousness.--This principle is the same as that which has in
  • the present day been termed faith, immediate knowledge, the revelation
  • in the outward world, and, above all, in our own heart.
  • Those sciences, which thus got the name of philosophy, we call
  • _empirical_ sciences, for the reason that they take their departure
  • from experience. Still the essential results which they aim at and
  • provide, are laws, general propositions, a theory--the thoughts of what
  • is found existing. On this ground the Newtonian physics was called
  • Natural Philosophy. Hugo Grotius, again, by putting together and
  • comparing the behaviour of states towards each other as recorded in
  • history, succeeded, with the help of the ordinary methods of general
  • reasoning, in laying down certain general principles, and establishing
  • a theory which may be termed the Philosophy of International Law. In
  • England this is still the usual signification of the term philosophy.
  • Newton continues to be celebrated as the greatest of philosophers: and
  • the name goes down as far as the price-lists of instrument-makers.
  • All instruments, such as the thermometer and barometer, which do not
  • come under the special head of magnetic or electric apparatus, are
  • styled philosophical instruments[1]. Surely thought, and not a mere
  • combination of wood, iron, &c. ought to be called the instrument of
  • philosophy! The recent science of Political Economy in particular,
  • which in Germany is known as Rational Economy of the State, or
  • intelligent national economy, has in England especially appropriated
  • the name of philosophy.[2]
  • 8.] In its own field this empirical knowledge may at first give
  • satisfaction; but in two ways it is seen to come short. In the first
  • place there is another circle of objects which it does not embrace.
  • These are Freedom, Spirit, and God. They belong to a different
  • sphere, not because it can be said that they have nothing to do with
  • experience; for though they are certainly not experiences of the
  • senses, it is quite an identical proposition to say that whatever is
  • in consciousness is experienced. The real ground for assigning them to
  • another field of cognition is that in their scope and _content_ these
  • objects evidently show themselves as infinite.
  • There is an old phrase often wrongly attributed to Aristotle, and
  • supposed to express the general tenor of his philosophy. '_Nihil
  • est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu_': there is nothing in
  • thought which has not been in sense and experience. If speculative
  • philosophy refused to admit this maxim, it can only have done so from
  • a misunderstanding. It will, however, on the converse side no less
  • assert: '_Nihil est in sensu quod non fuerit in intellectu._' And this
  • may be taken in two senses. In the general sense it means that νοῦς or
  • spirit (the more profound idea of νοῦς in modern thought) is the cause
  • of the world. In its special meaning (see § 2) it asserts that the
  • sentiment of right, morals, and religion is a sentiment (and in that
  • way an experience) of such scope and such character that it can spring
  • from and rest upon thought alone.
  • 9.] But in the second place in point of _form_ the subjective reason
  • desires a further satisfaction than empirical knowledge gives; and
  • this form, is, in the widest sense of the term, Necessity (§ 1). The
  • method of empirical science exhibits two defects. The first is that the
  • Universal or general principle contained in it, the genus, or kind, &c,
  • is, on its own account, indeterminate and vague, and therefore not on
  • its own account connected with the Particulars or the details. Either
  • is external and accidental to the other; and it is the same with the
  • particular facts which are brought into union: each is external and
  • accidental to the others. The second defect is that the beginnings are
  • in every case data and postulates, neither accounted for nor deduced.
  • In both these points the form of necessity fails to get its due. Hence
  • reflection, whenever it sets itself to remedy these defects, becomes
  • speculative thinking, the thinking proper to philosophy. As a species
  • of reflection, therefore, which, though it has a certain community
  • of nature with the reflection already mentioned, is nevertheless
  • different from it, philosophic thought thus possesses, in addition to
  • the common forms, some forms of its own, of which the Notion may be
  • taken as the type.
  • The relation of speculative science to the other sciences may be
  • stated in the following terms. It does not in the least neglect the
  • empirical facts contained in the several sciences, but recognises and
  • adopts them: it appreciates and applies towards its own structure the
  • universal element in these sciences, their laws and classifications:
  • but besides all this, into the categories of science it introduces, and
  • gives currency to, other categories. The difference, looked at in this
  • way, is only a change of categories. Speculative Logic contains all
  • previous Logic and Metaphysics: it preserves the same forms of thought,
  • the same laws and objects,--while at the same time remodelling and
  • expanding them with wider categories.
  • From _notion_ in the speculative sense we should distinguish what
  • is ordinarily called a notion. The phrase, that no notion can ever
  • comprehend the Infinite, a phrase which has been repeated over and over
  • again till it has grown axiomatic, is based upon this narrow estimate
  • of what is meant by notions.
  • 10.] This thought, which is proposed as the instrument of philosophic
  • knowledge, itself calls for further explanation. We must understand in
  • what way it possesses necessity or cogency: and when it claims to be
  • equal to the task of apprehending the absolute objects (God, Spirit,
  • Freedom), that claim must be substantiated. Such an explanation,
  • however, is itself a lesson in philosophy, and properly falls within
  • the scope of the science itself. A preliminary attempt to make matters
  • plain would only be unphilosophical, and consist of a tissue of
  • assumptions, assertions, and inferential pros and cons, _e.g._ of
  • dogmatism without cogency, as against which there would be an equal
  • right of counter-dogmatism.
  • A main line of argument in the Critical Philosophy bids us pause before
  • proceeding to inquire into God or into the true being of things, and
  • tells us first of all to examine the faculty of cognition and see
  • whether it is equal to such an effort. We ought, says Kant, to become
  • acquainted with the instrument, before we undertake the work for which
  • it is to be employed; for if the instrument be insufficient, all our
  • trouble will be spent in vain. The plausibility of this suggestion has
  • won for it general assent and admiration; the result of which has been
  • to withdraw cognition from an interest in its objects and absorption in
  • the study of them, and to direct it back upon itself; and so turn it to
  • a question of form. Unless we wish to be deceived bywords, it is easy
  • to see what this amounts to. In the case of other instruments, we can
  • try and criticise them in other ways than by setting about the special
  • work for which they are destined. But the examination of knowledge can
  • only be carried out by an act of knowledge. To examine this so-called
  • instrument is the same thing as to know it. But to seek to know before
  • we know is as absurd as the wise resolution of Scholasticus, not to
  • venture into the water until he had learned to swim.
  • Reinhold saw the confusion with which this style of commencement is
  • chargeable, and tried to get out of the difficulty by starting with a
  • hypothetical and problematical stage of philosophising. In this way he
  • supposed that it would be possible, nobody can tell how, to get along,
  • until we found ourselves, further on, arrived at the primary truth
  • of truths. His method, when closely looked into, will be seen to be
  • identical with a very common practice. It starts from a substratum
  • of experiential fact, or from a provisional assumption which has
  • been brought into a definition; and then proceeds to analyse this
  • starting-point. We can detect in Reinhold's argument a perception of
  • the truth, that the usual course which proceeds by assumptions and
  • anticipations is no better than a hypothetical and problematical mode
  • of procedure. But his perceiving this does not alter the character of
  • this method; it only makes clear its imperfections.
  • 11.] The special conditions which call for the existence of philosophy
  • maybe thus described. The mind or spirit, when it is sentient or
  • perceptive, finds its object in something sensuous; when it imagines,
  • in a picture or image; when it wills, in an aim or end. But in contrast
  • to, or it may be only in distinction from, these forms of its existence
  • and of its objects, the mind has also to gratify the cravings of
  • its highest and most inward life. That innermost self is thought.
  • Thus the mind renders thought its object. In the best meaning of the
  • phrase, it comes to itself; for thought is its principle, and its
  • very unadulterated self. But while thus occupied, thought entangles
  • itself in contradictions, _e.g._ loses itself in the hard-and-fast
  • non-identity of its thoughts, and so, instead of reaching itself,
  • is caught and held in its counterpart. This result, to which honest
  • but narrow thinking leads the mere understanding, is resisted by the
  • loftier craving of which we have spoken. That craving expresses the
  • perseverance of thought, which continues true to itself, even in this
  • conscious loss of its native rest and independence, 'that it may
  • overcome' and work out in itself the solution of its own contradictions.
  • To see that thought in its very nature is dialectical, and that, as
  • understanding, it must fall into contradiction,--the negative of
  • itself, will form one of the main lessons of logic. When thought
  • grows hopeless of ever achieving, by its own means, the solution of
  • the contradiction which it has by its own action brought upon itself,
  • it turns back to those solutions of the question with which the mind
  • had learned to pacify itself in some of its other modes and forms.
  • Unfortunately, however, the retreat of thought has led it, as Plato
  • noticed even in his time, to a very uncalled-for hatred of reason
  • (misology); and it then takes up against its own endeavours that
  • hostile attitude of which an example is seen in the doctrine that
  • 'immediate' knowledge, as it is called, is the exclusive form in which
  • we become cognisant of truth.
  • 12.] The rise of philosophy is due to these cravings of thought. Its
  • point of departure is Experience; including under that name both our
  • immediate consciousness and the inductions from it. Awakened, as it
  • were, by this stimulus, thought is vitally characterised by raising
  • itself above the natural state of mind, above the senses and inferences
  • from the senses into its own unadulterated element, and by assuming,
  • accordingly, at first a stand-aloof and negative attitude towards
  • the point from which it started. Through this state of antagonism to
  • the phenomena of sense its first satisfaction is found in itself, in
  • the Idea of the universal essence of these phenomena: an Idea (the
  • Absolute, or God) which may be more or less abstract. Meanwhile, on
  • the other hand, the sciences, based on experience, exert upon the
  • mind a stimulus to overcome the form in which their varied contents
  • are presented, and to elevate these contents to the rank of necessary
  • truth. For the facts of science have the aspect of a vast conglomerate,
  • one thing coming side by side with another, as if they were merely
  • given and presented,--as in short devoid of all essential or necessary
  • connexion. In consequence of this stimulus thought is dragged out
  • of its unrealised universality and its fancied or merely possible
  • satisfaction, and impelled onwards to a development from itself. On
  • one hand this development only means that thought incorporates the
  • contents of science, in all their speciality of detail as submitted. On
  • the other it makes these contents imitate the action of the original
  • creative thought, and present the aspect of a free evolution determined
  • by the logic of the fact alone.
  • On the relation between 'immediacy' and 'mediation' in consciousness
  • we shall speak later, expressly and with more detail. Here it may be
  • sufficient to premise that, though the two 'moments' or factors present
  • themselves as distinct, still neither of them can be absent, nor can
  • one exist apart from the other. Thus the knowledge of God, as of every
  • supersensible reality, is in its true character an exaltation above
  • sensations or perceptions: it consequently involves a negative attitude
  • to the initial data of sense, and to that extent implies mediation.
  • For to mediate is to take something as a beginning and to go onward to
  • a second thing; so that the existence of this second thing depends on
  • our having reached it from something else contradistinguished from it.
  • In spite of this, the knowledge of God is no mere sequel, dependent
  • on the empirical phase of consciousness: in fact, its independence is
  • essentially secured through this negation and exaltation.--No doubt, if
  • we attach an unfair prominence to the fact of mediation, and represent
  • it as implying a state of conditionedness, it may be said--not that the
  • remark would mean much--that philosophy is the child of experience, and
  • owes its rise to _a posteriori_ fact. (As a matter of fact, thinking
  • is always the negation of what we have immediately before us.) With
  • as much truth however we may be said to owe eating to the means of
  • nourishment, so long as we can have no eating without them. If we take
  • this view, eating is certainly represented as ungrateful: it devours
  • that to which it owes itself. Thinking, upon this view of its action,
  • is equally ungrateful.
  • But there is also an _a priori_ aspect of thought, where by a
  • mediation, not made by anything external but by a reflection into self,
  • we have that immediacy which is universality, the self-complacency
  • of thought which is so much at home with itself that it feels an
  • innate indifference to descend to particulars, and in that way to the
  • development of its own nature. It is thus also with religion, which,
  • whether it be rude or elaborate, whether it be invested with scientific
  • precision of detail or confined to the simple faith of the heart,
  • possesses, throughout, the same intensive nature of contentment and
  • felicity. But if thought never gets further than the universality of
  • the Ideas, as was perforce the case in the first philosophies (when
  • the Eleatics never got beyond Being, or Heraclitus beyond Becoming),
  • it is justly open to the charge of formalism. Even in a more advanced
  • phase of philosophy, we may often find a doctrine which has mastered
  • merely certain abstract propositions or formulae, such as, 'In the
  • absolute all is one,' 'Subject and object are identical,'--and only
  • repeating the same thing when it comes to particulars. Bearing in
  • mind this first period of thought, the period of mere generality, we
  • may safely say that experience is the real author of _growth_ and
  • _advance_ in philosophy. For, firstly, the empirical sciences do not
  • stop short at the mere observation of the individual features of a
  • phenomenon. By the aid of thought, they are able to meet philosophy
  • with materials prepared for it, in the shape of general uniformities,
  • _i.e._ laws, and classifications of the phenomena. When this is done,
  • the particular facts which they contain are ready to be received into
  • philosophy. This, secondly, implies a certain compulsion on thought
  • itself to proceed to these concrete specific truths. The reception into
  • philosophy of these scientific materials, now that thought has removed
  • their immediacy and made them cease to be mere data, forms at the same
  • time a development of thought out of itself. Philosophy, then, owes
  • its development to the empirical sciences. In return it gives their
  • contents what is so vital to them, the freedom of thought,--gives them,
  • in short, an _a priori_ character. These contents are now warranted
  • necessary, and no longer depend on the evidence of facts merely, that
  • they were so found and so experienced. The fact as experienced thus
  • becomes an illustration and a copy of the original and completely
  • self-supporting activity of thought.
  • 13.] Stated in exact terms, such is the origin and development of
  • philosophy. But the History of Philosophy gives us the same process
  • from an historical and external point of view. The stages in the
  • evolution of the Idea there seem to follow each other by accident, and
  • to present merely a number of different and unconnected principles,
  • which the several systems of philosophy carry out in their own way.
  • But it is not so. For these thousands of years the same Architect has
  • directed the work: and that Architect is the one living Mind whose
  • nature is to think, to bring to self-consciousness what it is, and,
  • with its being thus set as object before it, to be at the same time
  • raised above it, and so to reach a higher stage of its own being.
  • The different systems which the history of philosophy presents are
  • therefore not irreconcilable with unity. We may either say, that it
  • is one philosophy at different degrees of maturity: or that the
  • particular principle, which is the groundwork of each system, is
  • but a branch of one and the same universe of thought. In philosophy
  • the latest birth of time is the result of all the systems that have
  • preceded it, and must include their principles; and so, if, on other
  • grounds, it deserve the title of philosophy, will be the fullest, most
  • comprehensive, and most adequate system of all.
  • The spectacle of so many and so various systems of philosophy suggests
  • the necessity of defining more exactly the relation of Universal to
  • Particular. When the universal is made a mere form and co-ordinated
  • with the particular, as if it were on the same level, it sinks into a
  • particular itself. Even common sense in every-day matters is above the
  • absurdity of setting a universal _beside_ the particulars. Would any
  • one, who wished for fruit, reject cherries, pears, and grapes, on the
  • ground that they were cherries, pears, or grapes, and not fruit? But
  • when philosophy is in question, the excuse of many is that philosophies
  • are so different, and none of them is _the_ philosophy,--that each is
  • only _a_ philosophy. Such a plea is assumed to justify any amount of
  • contempt for philosophy. And yet cherries too are fruit. Often, too, a
  • system, of which the principle is the universal, is put on a level with
  • another of which the principle is a particular, and with theories which
  • deny the existence of philosophy altogether. Such systems are said to
  • be only different views of philosophy. With equal justice, light and
  • darkness might be styled different kinds of light.
  • 14.] The same evolution of thought which is exhibited in the history
  • of philosophy is presented in the System of Philosophy itself. Here,
  • instead of surveying the process, as we do in history, from the
  • outside, we see the movement of thought clearly defined in its native
  • medium. The thought, which is genuine and self-supporting, must be
  • intrinsically concrete; it must be an Idea; and when it is viewed in
  • the whole of its universality, it is the Idea, or the Absolute. The
  • science of this Idea must form a system. For the truth is concrete;
  • that is, whilst it gives a bond and principle of unity, it also
  • possesses an internal source of development. Truth, then, is only
  • possible as a universe or totality of thought; and the freedom of the
  • whole, as well as the necessity of the several sub-divisions, which it
  • implies, are only possible when these are discriminated and defined.
  • Unless it is a system, a philosophy is not a scientific production.
  • Unsystematic philosophising can only be expected to give expression to
  • personal peculiarities of mind, and has no principle for the regulation
  • of its contents. Apart from their interdependence and organic union,
  • the truths of philosophy are valueless, and must then be treated as
  • baseless hypotheses, or personal convictions. Yet many philosophical
  • treatises confine themselves to such an exposition of the opinions and
  • sentiments of the author.
  • The term _system_ is often misunderstood. It does not denote a
  • philosophy, the principle of which is narrow and to be distinguished
  • from others. On the contrary, a genuine philosophy makes it a principle
  • to include every particular principle.
  • 15.] Each of the parts of philosophy is a philosophical whole, a circle
  • rounded and complete in itself. In each of these parts, however, the
  • philosophical Idea is found in a particular specificality or medium.
  • The single circle, because it is a real totality, bursts through the
  • limits imposed by its special medium, and gives rise to a wider circle.
  • The whole of philosophy in this way resembles a circle of circles. The
  • Idea appears in each single circle, but, at the same time, the whole
  • Idea is constituted by the system of these peculiar phases, and each is
  • a necessary member of the organisation.
  • 16.] In the form of an Encyclopaedia, the science has no room for a
  • detailed exposition of particulars, and must be limited to setting
  • forth the commencement of the special sciences and the notions of
  • cardinal importance in them.
  • How much of the particular parts is requisite to constitute a
  • particular branch of knowledge is so far indeterminate, that the part,
  • if it is to be something true, must be not an isolated member merely,
  • but itself an organic whole. The entire field of philosophy therefore
  • really forms a single science; but it may also be viewed as a total,
  • composed of several particular sciences.
  • The encyclopaedia of philosophy must not be confounded with ordinary
  • encyclopaedias. An ordinary encyclopaedia does not pretend to be more
  • than an aggregation of sciences, regulated by no principle, and merely
  • as experience offers them. Sometimes it even includes what merely bear
  • the name of sciences, while they are nothing more than a collection of
  • bits of information. In an aggregate like this, the several branches of
  • knowledge owe their place in the encyclopaedia to extrinsic reasons,
  • and their unity is therefore artificial: they are _arranged,_ but we
  • cannot say they form a _system._ For the same reason, especially as the
  • materials to be combined also depend upon no one rule or principle,
  • the arrangement is at best an experiment, and will always exhibit
  • inequalities.
  • An encyclopaedia of philosophy excludes three kinds of partial science.
  • I. It excludes mere aggregates of bits of information. Philology in
  • its _prima facie_ aspect belongs to this class. II. It rejects the
  • quasi-sciences, which are founded on an act of arbitrary will alone,
  • such as Heraldry. Sciences of this class are positive from beginning to
  • end. III. In another class of sciences, also styled positive, but which
  • have a rational basis and a rational beginning, philosophy claims that
  • constituent as its own. The positive features remain the property of
  • the sciences themselves.
  • The positive element in the last class of sciences is of different
  • sorts. (I) Their commencement, though rational at bottom, yields to the
  • influence of fortuitousness, when they have to bring their universal
  • truth into contact with actual facts and the single phenomena of
  • experience. In this region of chance and change, the adequate notion
  • of science must yield its place to reasons or grounds of explanation.
  • Thus, _e.g._ in the science of jurisprudence, or in the system of
  • direct and indirect taxation, it is necessary to have certain points
  • precisely and definitively settled which lie beyond the competence of
  • the absolute lines laid down by the pure notion. A certain latitude
  • of settlement accordingly is left: and each point may be determined
  • in one way on one principle, in another way on another, and admits of
  • no definitive certainty. Similarly the Idea of Nature, when parcelled
  • out in detail, is dissipated into contingencies. Natural history,
  • geography, and medicine stumble upon descriptions of existence, upon
  • kinds and distinctions, which are not determined by reason, but by
  • sport and adventitious incidents. Even history comes under the same
  • category. The Idea is its essence and inner nature; but, as it appears,
  • everything is under contingency and in the field of voluntary action.
  • (II) These sciences are positive also in failing to recognise the
  • finite nature of what they predicate, and to point out how these
  • categories and their whole sphere pass into a higher. They assume their
  • statements to possess an authority beyond appeal. Here the fault lies
  • in the finitude of the form, as in the previous instance it lay in
  • the matter. (III) In close sequel to this, sciences are positive in
  • consequence of the inadequate grounds on which their conclusions rest:
  • based as these are on detached and casual inference, upon feeling,
  • faith, and authority, and, generally speaking, upon the deliverances
  • of inward and outward perception. Under this head we must also class
  • the philosophy which proposes to build upon anthropology,' facts of
  • consciousness, inward sense, or outward experience. It may happen,
  • however, that empirical is an epithet applicable only to the form of
  • scientific exposition; whilst intuitive sagacity has arranged what are
  • mere phenomena, according to the essential sequence of the notion. In
  • such a case the contrasts between the varied and numerous phenomena
  • brought together serve to eliminate the external and accidental
  • circumstances of their conditions, and the universal thus comes clearly
  • into view. Guided by such an intuition, experimental physics will
  • present the rational science of Nature,--as history will present the
  • science of human affairs and actions--in an external picture, which
  • mirrors the philosophic notion.
  • 17.] It may seem as if philosophy, in order to start on its course,
  • had, like the rest of the sciences, to begin with a subjective
  • presupposition. The sciences postulate their respective objects, such
  • as space, number, or whatever it be; and it might be supposed that
  • philosophy had also to postulate the existence of thought. But the
  • two cases are not exactly parallel. It is by the free act of thought
  • that it occupies a point of view, in which it is for its own self, and
  • thus gives itself an object of its own production. Nor is this all.
  • The very point of view, which originally is taken on its own evidence
  • only, must in the course of the science be converted to a result,--the
  • ultimate result in which philosophy returns into itself and reaches
  • the point with which it began. In this manner philosophy exhibits the
  • appearance of a circle which closes with itself, and has no beginning
  • in the same way as the other sciences have. To speak of a beginning of
  • philosophy has a meaning only in relation to a person who proposes to
  • commence the study, and not in relation to the science as science. The
  • same thing may be thus expressed. The notion of science--the notion
  • therefore with which we start--which, for the very reason that it is
  • initial, implies a separation between the thought which is our object,
  • and the subject philosophising which is, as it were, external to the
  • former, must be grasped and comprehended by the science itself. This
  • is in short the one single aim, action, and goal of philosophy--to
  • arrive at the notion of its notion, and thus secure its return and its
  • satisfaction.
  • 18.] As the whole science, and only the whole, can exhibit what the
  • Idea or system of reason is, it is impossible to give in a preliminary
  • way a general impression of a philosophy. Nor can a division of
  • philosophy into its parts be intelligible, except in connexion with the
  • system. A preliminary division, like the limited conception from which
  • it comes, can only be an anticipation. Here however it is premised that
  • the Idea turns out to be the thought which is completely identical
  • with itself, and not identical simply in the abstract, but also in its
  • action of setting itself over against itself, so as to gain a being of
  • its own, and yet of being in full possession of itself while it is in
  • this other. Thus philosophy is subdivided into three parts:
  • I. Logic, the science of the Idea in and for itself.
  • II. The Philosophy of Nature: the science of the Idea in its otherness.
  • III. The Philosophy of Mind: the science of the Idea come back to
  • itself out of that otherness.
  • As observed in § 15, the differences between the several philosophical
  • sciences are only aspects or specialisations of the one Idea or system
  • of reason, which and which alone is alike exhibited in these different
  • media. In Nature nothing else would have to be discerned, except the
  • Idea: but the Idea has here divested itself of its proper being. In
  • Mind, again, the Idea has asserted a being of its own, and is on the
  • way to become absolute. Every such form in which the Idea is expressed,
  • is at the same time a passing or fleeting stage: and hence each of
  • these subdivisions has not only to know its contents as an object which
  • has being for the time, but also in the same act to expound how these
  • contents pass into their higher circle. To represent the relation
  • between them as a division, therefore, leads to misconception; for it
  • co-ordinates the several parts or sciences one beside another, as if
  • they had no innate development, but were, like so many species, really
  • and radically distinct.
  • [1] The journal, too, edited by Thomson is called 'Annals of
  • Philosophy; or, Magazine of Chemistry, Mineralogy, Mechanics, Natural
  • History, Agriculture, and Arts.' We can easily guess from the title
  • what sort of subjects are here to be understood under the term
  • 'philosophy.' Among the advertisements of books just published, I
  • lately found the following notice in an English newspaper: 'The Art of
  • Preserving the Hair, on Philosophical Principles, neatly printed in
  • post 8vo, price seven shillings.' By philosophical principles for the
  • preservation of the hair are probably meant chemical or physiological
  • principles.
  • [2] In connexion with the general principles of Political Economy,
  • the term 'philosophical' is frequently heard from the lips of English
  • statesmen, even in their public speeches. In the House of Commons, on
  • the 2nd Feb. 1825, Brougham, speaking oh the address in reply to the
  • speech from the throne, talked of 'the statesman-like and philosophical
  • principles of Free-trade,--for philosophical they undoubtedly are--upon
  • the acceptance of which his majesty this day congratulated the House.'
  • Nor is this language confined to members of the Opposition. At the
  • shipowners' yearly dinner in the same month, under the chairmanship
  • of the Premier Lord Liverpool, supported by Canning the Secretary of
  • State, and Sir C. Long the Paymaster-General of the Army, Canning
  • in reply to the toast which had been proposed said: 'A period has
  • just begun, in which ministers have it in their power to apply to
  • the administration of this country the sound maxims of a profound
  • philosophy.' Differences there may be between English and German
  • philosophy: still, considering that elsewhere the name of philosophy
  • is used only as a nickname and insult, or as something odious, it is
  • a matter of rejoicing to see it still honoured in the mouth of the
  • English Government.
  • CHAPTER II.
  • PRELIMINARY NOTION.
  • 19.] LOGIC IS THE SCIENCE OF THE PURE IDEA; pure, that is, because the
  • Idea is in the abstract medium of Thought.
  • This definition, and the others which occur in these introductory
  • outlines, are derived from a survey of the whole system, to which
  • accordingly they are subsequent. The same remark applies to all
  • prefatory notions whatever about philosophy.
  • Logic might have been defined as the science of thought, and of its
  • laws and characteristic forms. But thought, as thought, constitutes
  • only the general medium, or qualifying circumstance, which renders
  • the Idea distinctively logical. If we identify the Idea with thought,
  • thought must not be taken in the sense of a method or form, but in the
  • sense of the self-developing totality of its laws and peculiar terms.
  • These laws are the work of thought itself, and not a fact which it
  • finds and must submit to.
  • From different points of view, Logic is either the hardest or the
  • easiest of the sciences, Logic is hard, because it has to deal not with
  • perceptions, nor, like geometry, with abstract representations of the
  • senses, but with pure abstractions; and because it demands a force and
  • facility of withdrawing into pure thought, of keeping firm hold on it,
  • and of moving in such an element. Logic is easy, because its facts are
  • nothing but our own thought and its familiar forms or terms: and these
  • are the acme of simplicity, the abc of everything else. They are also
  • what we are best acquainted with: such as, 'Is' and 'Is not': quality
  • and magnitude: being potential and being actual: one, many, and so on.
  • But such an acquaintance only adds to the difficulties of the study;
  • for while, on the one hand, we naturally think it is not worth our
  • trouble to occupy ourselves any longer with things so familiar, on the
  • other hand, the problem is to become acquainted with them in a new way,
  • quite opposite to that in which we know them already.
  • The utility of Logic is a matter which concerns its bearings upon the
  • student, and the training it may give for other purposes. This logical
  • training consists in the exercise in thinking which the student has
  • to go through (this science is the thinking of thinking): and in the
  • fact that he stores his head with thoughts, in their native unalloyed
  • character. It is true that Logic, being the absolute form of truth, and
  • another name for the very truth itself, is something more than merely
  • useful. Yet if what is noblest, most liberal and most independent is
  • also most useful, Logic has some claim to the latter character. Its
  • utility must then be estimated at another rate than exercise in thought
  • for the sake of the exercise.
  • (1) The first question is: What is the object of our science? The
  • simplest and most intelligible answer to this question is that Truth
  • is the object of Logic. Truth is a noble word, and the thing is nobler
  • still. So long as man is sound at heart and in spirit, the search for
  • truth must awake all the enthusiasm of his nature. But immediately
  • there steps in the objection--Are _we_ able to know truth? There
  • seems to be a disproportion between finite beings like ourselves and
  • the truth which is absolute: and doubts suggest themselves whether
  • there is any bridge between the finite and the infinite. God is
  • truth: how shall we know Him? Such an undertaking appears to stand in
  • contradiction with the graces of lowliness and humility.--Others who
  • ask whether we can know the truth have a different purpose. They want
  • to justify themselves in living on contented with their petty, finite
  • aims. And humility of this stamp is a poor thing.
  • But the time is past when people asked: How shall I, a poor worm of the
  • dust, be able to know the truth? And in its stead we find vanity and
  • conceit: people claim, without any trouble on their part, to breathe
  • the very atmosphere of truth. The young have been flattered into the
  • belief that they possess a natural birthright of moral and religious
  • truth. And in the same strain, those of riper years are declared to
  • be sunk, petrified, ossified in falsehood. Youth, say these teachers,
  • sees the bright light of dawn: but the older generation lies in the
  • slough and mire of the common day. They admit that the special sciences
  • are something that certainly ought to be cultivated, but merely as
  • the means to satisfy the needs of outer life. In all this it is not
  • humility which holds back from the knowledge and study of the truth,
  • but a conviction that we are already in full possession of it. And no
  • doubt the young carry with them the hopes of their elder compeers; on
  • them rests the advance of the world and science. But these hopes are
  • set upon the young, only on the condition that, instead of remaining as
  • they are, they undertake the stern labour of mind.
  • This modesty in truth-seeking has still another phase: and that is the
  • genteel indifference to truth, as we see it in Pilate's conversation
  • with Christ. Pilate asked 'What is truth?' with the air of a man who
  • had settled accounts with everything long ago, and concluded that
  • nothing particularly matters:--he meant much the same as Solomon when
  • he says: 'All is vanity.' When it comes to this, nothing is left but
  • self-conceit.
  • The knowledge of the truth meets an additional obstacle in timidity.
  • A slothful mind finds it natural to say: 'Don't let it be supposed
  • that we mean to be in earnest with our philosophy. We shall be glad
  • _inter alia_ to study Logic: but Logic must be sure to leave us as
  • we were before.' People have a feeling that, if thinking passes the
  • ordinary range of our ideas and impressions, it cannot but be on the
  • evil road. They seem to be trusting themselves to a sea on which they
  • will be tossed to and fro by the waves of thought, till at length they
  • again reach the sandbank of this temporal scene, as utterly poor as
  • when they left it. What coines of such a view, we see in the world. It
  • is possible within these limits to gain varied information and many
  • accomplishments, to become a master of official routine, and to be
  • trained for special purposes. But it is quite another thing to educate
  • the spirit for the higher life and to devote our energies to its
  • service. In our own day it may be hoped a longing for something better
  • has sprung up among the young, so that they will not be contented with
  • the mere straw of outer knowledge.
  • (2) It is universally agreed that thought is the object of Logic. But
  • of thought our estimate may be very mean, or it may be very high. On
  • one hand, people say: 'It is _only_ a thought.' In their view thought
  • is subjective, arbitrary and accidental--distinguished from the thing
  • itself, from the true and the real. On the other hand, a very high
  • estimate may be formed of thought; when thought alone is held adequate
  • to attain the highest of all things, the nature of God, of which the
  • senses can tell us nothing. God is a spirit, it is said, and must be
  • worshipped in spirit and in truth. But the merely felt and sensible,
  • we admit, is not the spiritual; its heart of hearts is in thought;
  • and only spirit can know spirit. And though it is true that spirit
  • can demean itself as feeling and sense--as is the case in religion,
  • the mere feeling, as a mode of consciousness, is one thing, and its
  • contents another. Feeling, as feeling, is the general form of the
  • sensuous nature which we have in common with the brutes. This form,
  • viz. feeling, may possibly seize and appropriate the full organic
  • truth: but the form has no real congruity with its contents. The form
  • of feeling is the lowest in which spiritual truth can be expressed.
  • The world of spiritual existences, God himself, exists in proper
  • truth, only in thought and as thought. If this be so, there fore,
  • thought, far from being a mere thought, is the highest and, in strict
  • accuracy, the sole mode of apprehending the eternal and absolute.
  • As of thought, so also of the science of thought, a very high or a
  • very low opinion may be formed. Any man, it is supposed, can think
  • without Logic, as he can digest without studying physiology. If he
  • have studied Logic, he thinks afterwards as he did before, perhaps
  • more methodically, but with little alteration. If this were all, and
  • if Logic did no more than make men acquainted with the action of
  • thought as the faculty of comparison and classification, it would
  • produce nothing which had not been done quite as well before. And in
  • point of fact Logic hitherto had no other idea of its duty than this.
  • Yet to be well-informed about thought, even as a mere activity of the
  • subject-mind, is honourable and interesting for man. It is in knowing
  • what he is and what he does, that man is distinguished from the brutes.
  • But we may take the higher estimate of thought--as what alone can get
  • really in touch with the supreme and true. In that case, Logic as the
  • science of thought occupies a high ground. If the science of Logic
  • then considers thought in its action and its productions (and thought
  • being no resultless energy produces thoughts and the particular thought
  • required), the theme of Logic is in general the supersensible world,
  • and to deal with that theme is to dwell for a while in that world.
  • Mathematics is concerned with the abstractions of time and space. But
  • these are still the object of sense, although the sensible is abstract
  • and idealised. Thought bids adieu even to this last and abstract
  • sensible: it asserts its own native independence, renounces the field
  • of the external and internal sense, and puts away the interests and
  • inclinations of the individual. When Logic takes this ground, it is a
  • higher science than we are in the habit of supposing.
  • (3) The necessity of understanding Logic in a deeper sense than as
  • the science of the mere form of thought is enforced by the interests
  • of religion and politics, of law and morality. In earlier days men
  • meant no harm by thinking: they thought away freely and fearlessly.
  • They thought about God, about Nature, and the State; and they felt
  • sure that a knowledge of the truth was obtainable through thought
  • only, and not through the senses or any random ideas or opinions.
  • But while they so thought, the principal ordinances of life began
  • to be seriously affected by their conclusions. Thought deprived
  • existing institutions of their force. Constitutions fell a victim to
  • thought: religion was assailed by thought: firm religious beliefs
  • which had been always looked upon as revelations were undermined, and
  • in many minds the old faith was upset. The Greek philosophers, for
  • example, became antagonists of the old religion, and destroyed its
  • beliefs. Philosophers were accordingly banished or put to death, as
  • revolutionists who had subverted religion and the state, two things
  • which were inseparable. Thought, in short, made itself a power in the
  • real world, and exercised enormous influence. The matter ended by
  • drawing attention to the influence of thought, and its claims were
  • submitted to a more rigorous scrutiny, by which the world professed to
  • find that thought arrogated too much and was unable to perform what
  • it had undertaken. It had not--people said--learned the real being of
  • God, of Nature and Mind. It had not learned what the truth was. What
  • it had done, was to overthrow religion and the state. It became urgent
  • therefore to justify thought, with reference to the results it had
  • produced: and it is this examination into the nature of thought and
  • this justification which in recent times has constituted one of the
  • main problems of philosophy.
  • 20.] If we take our _prima facie_ impression of thought, we find on
  • examination first (a) that, in its usual subjective acceptation,
  • thought is one out of many activities or faculties of the mind,
  • co-ordinate with such others as sensation, perception, imagination,
  • desire, volition, and the like. The product of this activity, the form
  • or character peculiar to thought, is the UNIVERSAL, or, in general,
  • the abstract. Thought, regarded as an _activity,_ may be accordingly
  • described as the _active_ universal, and, since the deed, its product,
  • is the universal once more, may be called a self-actualising universal.
  • Thought conceived as a _subject_ (agent) is a thinker, and the subject
  • existing as a thinker is simply denoted by the term 'I.'
  • The propositions giving an account of thought in this and the following
  • sections are not offered as assertions or opinions of mine on the
  • matter. But in these preliminary chapters any deduction or proof would
  • be impossible, and the statements may be taken as matters in evidence.
  • In other words, every man, when he thinks and considers his thoughts,
  • will discover by the experience of his consciousness that they possess
  • the character of universality as well as the other aspects of thought
  • to be afterwards enumerated. We assume of course that his powers of
  • attention and abstraction have undergone a previous training, enabling
  • him to observe correctly the evidence of his consciousness and his
  • conceptions.
  • This introductory exposition has already alluded to the distinction
  • between Sense, Conception, and Thought. As the distinction is of
  • capital importance for understanding the nature and kinds of knowledge,
  • it will help to explain matters if we here call attention to it. For
  • the explanation of _Sense,_ the readiest method certainly is, to refer
  • to its external source--the organs of sense. But to name the organ
  • does not help much to explain what is apprehended by it. The real
  • distinction between sense and thought lies in this--that the essential
  • feature of the sensible is individuality, and as the individual (which,
  • reduced to its simplest terms, is the atom) is also a member of a
  • group, sensible existence presents a number of mutually exclusive
  • units,--of units, to speak in more definite and abstract formulae,
  • which exist side by side with, and after, one another. _Conception_ or
  • picture-thinking works with materials from the same sensuous source.
  • But these materials when _conceived_ are expressly characterised as in
  • me and therefore mine: and secondly, as universal, or simple, because
  • only referred to self. Nor is sense the only source of materialised
  • conception. There are conceptions constituted by materials emanating
  • from self-conscious thought, such as those of law, morality, religion,
  • and even of thought itself, and it requires some effort to detect
  • wherein lies the difference between such conceptions and thoughts
  • having the same import. For it is a thought of which such conception is
  • the vehicle, and there is no want of the form of universality, without
  • which no content could be in me, or be a conception at all. Yet here
  • also the peculiarity of conception is, generally speaking, to be sought
  • in the individualism or isolation of its contents. True it is that, for
  • example, law and legal provisions do not exist in a sensible space,
  • mutually excluding one another. Nor as regards time, though they appear
  • to some extent in succession, are their contents themselves conceived
  • as affected by time, or as transient and changeable in it. The fault
  • in conception lies deeper. These ideas, though implicitly possessing
  • the organic unity of mind, stand isolated here and there on the broad
  • ground of conception, with its inward and abstract generality. Thus
  • cut adrift, each is simple, unrelated: Right, Duty, God. Conception in
  • these circumstances either rests satisfied with declaring that Right
  • is Right, God is God: or in a higher grade of culture, it proceeds to
  • enunciate the attributes; as, for instance, God is the Creator of the
  • world, omniscient, almighty, &c. In this way several isolated, simple
  • predicates are strung together: but in spite of the link supplied
  • by their subject, the predicates never get beyond mere contiguity.
  • In this point Conception coincides with Understanding: the only
  • distinction being that the latter introduces relations of universal
  • and particular, of cause and effect, &c., and in this way supplies a
  • necessary connexion to the isolated ideas of conception; which last has
  • left them side by side in its vague mental spaces, connected only by a
  • bare 'and.'
  • The difference between conception and thought is of special importance:
  • because philosophy may be said to do nothing but transform conceptions
  • into thoughts,--though it works the further transformation of a mere
  • thought into a notion.
  • Sensible existence has been characterised by the attributes of
  • individuality and mutual exclusion of the members. It is well to
  • remember that these very attributes of sense are thoughts and general
  • terms. It will be shown in the Logic that thought (and the universal)
  • is not a mere opposite of sense: it lets nothing escape it, but,
  • outflanking its other, is at once that other and itself. Now language
  • is the work of thought: and hence all that is expressed in language
  • must be universal. What I only mean or suppose is mine: it belongs
  • to me,--this particular individual. But language expresses nothing
  • but universality; and so I cannot say what I merely _mean._ And the
  • unutterable,--feeling or sensation,--far from being the highest truth,
  • is the most unimportant and untrue. If I say 'The individual,' 'This
  • individual,' 'here,' 'now,' all these are universal terms. Everything
  • and anything is an individual, a 'this,' and if it be sensible, is
  • here and now. Similarly when I say, 'I,' I _mean_ my single self to
  • the exclusion of all others: but what I _say,_ viz. 'I,' is just
  • every 'I,' which in like manner excludes all others from itself. In
  • an awkward expression which Kant used, he said that I _accompany_
  • all my conceptions,--sensations, too, desires, actions, &c. 'I' is
  • in essence and act the universal: and such partnership is a form,
  • though an external form, of universality. All other men have it in
  • common with me to be 'I': just as it is common to all my sensations
  • and conceptions to be mine. But 'I,' in the abstract, as such, is the
  • mere act of self-concentration or self-relation, in which we make
  • abstraction from all conception and feeling, from every state of mind
  • and every peculiarity of nature, talent, and experience. To this
  • extent, 'I' is the existence of a wholly _abstract_ universality, a
  • principle of abstract freedom. Hence thought, viewed as a subject, is
  • what is expressed by the word 'I': and since I am at the same time in
  • all my sensations, conceptions, and states of consciousness, thought
  • is everywhere present, and is a category that runs through all these
  • modifications.
  • Our first impression when we use the term thought is of a subjective
  • activity--one amongst many similar faculties, such as memory,
  • imagination and will. Were thought merely an activity of the
  • subject-mind and treated under that aspect by logic, logic would
  • resemble the other sciences in possessing a well-marked object. It
  • might in that case seem arbitrary to devote a special science to
  • thought, whilst will, imagination and the rest were denied the same
  • privilege. The selection of one faculty however might even in this view
  • be very well grounded on a certain authority acknowledged to belong to
  • thought, and on its claim to be regarded as the true nature of man, in
  • which consists his distinction from the brutes. Nor is it unimportant
  • to study thought even as a subjective energy. A detailed analysis
  • of its nature would exhibit rules and laws, a knowledge of which is
  • derived from experience. A treatment of the laws of thought, from this
  • point of view, used once to form the body of logical science. Of that
  • science Aristotle was the founder. He succeeded in assigning to thought
  • what properly belongs to it. Our thought is extremely concrete: but
  • in its composite contents we must distinguish the part that properly
  • belongs to thought, or to the abstract mode of its action. A subtle
  • spiritual bond, consisting in the agency of thought, is what gives
  • unity to all these contents, and it was this bond, the form as form,
  • that Aristotle noted and described. Up to the present day, the logic
  • of Aristotle continues to be the received system. It has indeed been
  • spun out to greater length, especially by the labours of the medieval
  • Schoolmen who, without making any material additions, merely refined
  • in details. The moderns also have left their mark upon this logic,
  • partly by omitting many points of logical doctrine due to Aristotle and
  • the Schoolmen, and partly by foisting in a quantity of psychological
  • matter. The purport of the science is to become acquainted with the
  • procedure of finite thought: and, if it is adapted to its pre-supposed
  • object, the science is entitled to be styled correct. The study of this
  • formal logic undoubtedly has its uses. It sharpens the wits, as the
  • phrase goes, and teaches us to collect our thoughts and to abstract
  • --whereas in common consciousness we have to deal with sensuous
  • conceptions which cross and perplex one another. Abstraction moreover
  • implies the concentration of the mind on a single point, and thus
  • induces the habit of attending to our inward selves. An acquaintance
  • with the forms of finite thought may be made a means of training the
  • mind for the empirical sciences, since their method is regulated by
  • these forms: and in this sense logic has been designated Instrumental.
  • It is true, we may be still more liberal, and say: Logic is to be
  • studied not for its utility, but for its own sake; the super-excellent
  • is not to be sought for the sake of mere utility. In one sense this is
  • quite correct: but it may be replied that the super-excellent is also
  • the most useful: because it is the all-sustaining principle which,
  • having a subsistence of its own, may therefore serve as the vehicle of
  • special ends which it furthers and secures. And thus, special ends,
  • though they have no right to be set first, are still fostered by the
  • presence of the highest good. Religion, for instance, has an absolute
  • value of its own; yet at the same time other ends flourish and succeed
  • in its train. As Christ says: 'Seek ye first the kingdom of God, and
  • all these things shall be added unto you.' Particular ends can be
  • attained only in the attainment of what absolutely is and exists in its
  • own right.
  • 21.] (b) Thought was described as active. We now, in the second place,
  • consider this action in its bearings upon objects, or as reflection
  • upon something. In this case the universal or product of its operation
  • contains the value of the thing--is the essential, inward, and true.
  • In § 5 the old belief was quoted that the reality in object,
  • circumstance, or event, the intrinsic worth or essence, the thing on
  • which everything depends, is not a self-evident datum of consciousness,
  • or coincident with the first appearance and impression of the object;
  • that, on the contrary, Reflection is required in order to discover the
  • real constitution of the object--and that by such reflection it will be
  • ascertained.
  • To reflect is a lesson which even the child has to learn. One of his
  • first lessons is to join adjectives with substantives. This obliges
  • him to attend and distinguish: he has to remember a rule and apply it
  • to the particular case. This rule is nothing but a universal: and the
  • child must see that the particular adapts itself to this universal.
  • In life, again, we have ends to attain. And with regard to these we
  • ponder which is the best way to secure them. The end here represents
  • the universal or governing principle: and we have means and instruments
  • whose action we regulate in conformity to the end. In the same way
  • reflection is active in questions of conduct. To reflect here means to
  • recollect the right, the duty,--the universal which serves as a fixed
  • rule' to guide our behaviour in the given case. Our particular act
  • must imply and recognise the universal law.--We find the same thing
  • exhibited in our study of natural phenomena. For instance, we observe
  • thunder and lightning. The phenomenon is a familiar one, and we often
  • perceive it. But man is not content with a bare acquaintance, or with
  • the fact as it appears to the senses; he would like to get behind the
  • surface, to know what it is, and to comprehend it. This leads him to
  • reflect: he seeks to find out the cause as something distinct from
  • the mere phenomenon: he tries to know the inside in its distinction
  • from the outside. Hence the phenomenon becomes double, it splits into
  • inside and outside, into force and its manifestation, into cause and
  • effect. Once more we find the inside or the force identified with the
  • universal and permanent: not this or that flash of lightning, this
  • or that plant--but that which continues the same in them all. The
  • sensible appearance is individual and evanescent: the permanent in
  • it is discovered by. reflection. Nature shows us a countless number
  • of individual forms and phenomena. Into this variety we feel a need
  • of introducing unity: we compare, consequently, and try to find the
  • universal of each single case. Individuals are born and perish: the
  • species abides and recurs in them all: and its existence is only
  • visible to reflection. Under the same head fall such laws as those
  • regulating the motion of the heavenly bodies. To-day we see the stars
  • here, and to-morrow there: and our mind finds something incongruous, in
  • this chaos--something in which it can put no faith, because it believes
  • in order and in a simple, constant, and universal law. Inspired by this
  • belief, the mind has directed its reflection towards the phenomena,
  • and learnt their laws. In other words, it has established the movement
  • of the heavenly bodies to be in accordance with a universal law from
  • which every change of position may be known and predicted. The case is
  • the same with the influences which make themselves felt in the infinite
  • complexity of human conduct. There, too, man has the belief in the sway
  • of a general principle.--From all these examples it may be gathered
  • how reflection is always seeking for something fixed and permanent,
  • definite in itself and governing the particulars. This universal which
  • cannot be apprehended by the senses counts as the true and essential.
  • Thus, duties and rights are all-important in the matter of conduct: and
  • an action is true when it conforms to those universal formulae.
  • In thus characterising the universal, we become aware of its antithesis
  • to something else. This something else is the merely immediate,
  • outward and individual, as opposed to the mediate, inward and
  • universal. The universal does not exist externally to the outward eye
  • as a universal. The kind as kind cannot be perceived: the laws of the
  • celestial motions are not written on the sky. The universal is neither
  • seen nor heard, its existence is only for the mind. Religion leads us
  • to a universal, which embraces all else within itself, to an Absolute
  • by which all else is brought into being: and this Absolute is an object
  • not of the senses but of the mind and of thought.
  • 22.] (c) By the act of reflection something is _altered_ in the way in
  • which the fact was originally presented in sensation, perception, or
  • conception. Thus, as it appears, an alteration of the object must be
  • interposed before its true nature can be discovered.
  • What reflection elicits, is a product of our thought. Solon, for
  • instance, produced out of his head the laws he gave to the Athenians.
  • This is half of the truth: but we must not on that account forget
  • that the universal (in Solon's case, the laws) is the very reverse of
  • merely subjective, or fail to note that it is the essential, true,
  • and objective being of things. To discover the truth in things,
  • mere attention is not enough; we must call in the action of our own
  • faculties to transform what is immediately before us. Now, at first
  • sight, this seems an inversion of the natural order, calculated to
  • thwart the very purpose on which knowledge is bent. But the method is
  • not so irrational as it seems. It has been the conviction of every age
  • that the only way of reaching the permanent substratum was to transmute
  • the given phenomenon by means of reflection. In modern times a doubt
  • has for the first time been raised on this point in connexion with the
  • difference alleged to exist between the products of our thought and the
  • things in their own nature. This real nature of things, it is said,
  • is very different from what we make out of them. The divorce between
  • thought and thing is mainly the work of the Critical Philosophy,
  • and runs counter to the conviction of all previous ages, that their
  • agreement was a matter of course. The antithesis between them is
  • the hinge on which modern philosophy turns. Meanwhile the natural
  • belief of men gives the lie to it. In common life we reflect, without
  • particularly reminding ourselves that this is the process of arriving
  • at the truth, and we think without hesitation, and in the firm belief
  • that thought coincides with thing. And this belief is of the greatest
  • importance. It marks the diseased state of the age when we see it adopt
  • the despairing creed that our knowledge is only subjective, and that
  • beyond this subjective we cannot go. Whereas, rightly understood, truth
  • is objective, and ought so to regulate the conviction of every one,
  • that the conviction of the individual is stamped as wrong when it does
  • not agree with this rule. Modern views, on the contrary, put great
  • value on the mere fact of conviction, and hold that to be convinced is
  • good for its own sake, whatever be the burden of our conviction,--there
  • being no standard by which we can measure its truth.
  • We said above that, according to the old belief, it was the
  • characteristic right of the mind to know the truth. If this be so, it
  • also implies that everything we know both of outward and inward nature,
  • in one word, the objective world, is in its own self the same as it is
  • in thought, and that to think is to bring out the truth of our object,
  • be it what it may. The business of philosophy is only to bring into
  • explicit consciousness what the world in all ages has believed about
  • thought. Philosophy therefore advances nothing new; and our present
  • discussion has led us to a conclusion which agrees with the natural
  • belief of mankind.
  • 23.] (d) The real nature of the object is brought to light in
  • reflection; but it is no less true that this exertion of thought is
  • _my_ act. If this be so, the real nature is a _product_ of _my_ mind,
  • in its character of thinking subject--generated by me in my simple
  • universality, self-collected and removed from extraneous influences,
  • --in one word, in my Freedom.
  • Think for yourself, is a phrase which people often use as if it had
  • some special significance. The fact is, no man can think for another,
  • any more than he can eat or drink for him: and the expression is a
  • pleonasm. To think is in fact _ipso facto_ to be free, for thought as
  • the action of the universal is an abstract relating of self to self,
  • where, being at home with ourselves, and as regards our subjectivity,
  • utterly blank, our consciousness is, in the matter of its contents,
  • only in the fact and its characteristics. If this be admitted, and
  • if we apply the term humility or modesty to an attitude where our
  • subjectivity is not allowed to interfere by act or quality, it is
  • easy to appreciate the question touching the humility or modesty and
  • pride of philosophy. For in point of contents, thought is only true in
  • proportion as it sinks itself in the facts; and in point of form it
  • is no private or particular state or act of the subject, but rather
  • that attitude of consciousness where the abstract self, freed from
  • all the special limitations to which its ordinary states or qualities
  • are liable, restricts itself to that universal action in which it is
  • identical with all individuals. In these circumstances philosophy may
  • be acquitted of the charge of pride. And when Aristotle summons the
  • mind to rise to the dignity of that attitude, the dignity he seeks is
  • won by letting slip all our individual opinions and prejudices, and
  • submitting to the sway of the fact.
  • 24.] With these explanations and qualifications, thoughts may be termed
  • Objective Thoughts,--among which are also to be included the forms
  • which are more especially discussed in the common logic, where they are
  • usually treated as forms of conscious thought only. _Logic therefore
  • coincides with Metaphysics, the science of things set and held in
  • thoughts,_--thoughts accredited able to express the essential reality
  • of things.
  • An exposition of the relation in which such forms as notion, judgment,
  • and syllogism stand to others, such as causality, is a matter for the
  • science itself. But this much is evident beforehand. If thought tries
  • to form a notion of things, this notion (as well as its proximate
  • phases, the judgment and syllogism) cannot be composed of articles and
  • relations which are alien and irrelevant to the things. Reflection, it
  • was said above, conducts to the universal of things: which universal
  • is itself one of the constituent factors of a notion. To say that
  • Reason or Understanding is in the world, is equivalent in its import
  • to the phrase 'Objective Thought.' The latter phrase however has the
  • inconvenience that thought is usually confined to express what belongs
  • to the mind or consciousness only, while objective is a term applied,
  • at least primarily, only to the non-mental.
  • (1) To speak of thought or objective thought as the heart [and soul
  • of the world, may seem to be ascribing consciousness to the things of
  • nature. We feel a certain repugnance against making thought the inward
  • function of things, especially as we speak of thought as marking the
  • divergence of man from nature. It would be necessary, therefore, if
  • we use the term thought at all, to speak of nature as the system of
  • unconscious thought, or, to use Schelling's expression, a petrified
  • intelligence. And in order to prevent misconception, thought-form or
  • thought-type should be substituted for the ambiguous term thought.
  • From what has been said the principles of logic are to be sought
  • in a system of thought-types or fundamental categories, in which
  • the opposition between subjective and objective, in its usual
  • sense, vanishes. The signification thus attached to thought and its
  • characteristic forms may be illustrated by the ancient saying that
  • 'νοῧς governs the world,' or by our own phrase that 'Reason is in the
  • world: which means that Reason is the soul of the world it inhabits,
  • its immanent principle, its most proper and inward nature, its
  • universal. Another illustration is offered by the circumstance that
  • in speaking of some definite animal we say it is (an) animal. Now,
  • the animal, _quâ_ animal, cannot be shown; nothing can be pointed out
  • excepting some special animal. Animal, _quâ_ animal, does not exist: it
  • is merely the universal nature of the individual animals, whilst each
  • existing animal is a more concretely, defined and particularised thing.
  • But to be an animal,--the law of kind which is the universal in this
  • case,--is the property of the particular animal, and constitutes its
  • definite essence. Take away from the dog its animality, and it becomes
  • impossible to say what it is. All things have a permanent inward
  • nature, as well as an outward existence. They live and die, arise and
  • pass away; but their essential and universal part is the kind; and this
  • means much more than something _common_ to them all.
  • If thought is the constitutive substance of external things, it is also
  • the universal substance of what is spiritual. In all human perception
  • thought is present; so too thought is the universal in all the acts of
  • conception and recollection; in short, in every mental activity, in
  • willing, wishing and the like. All these faculties are only further,
  • specialisations of thought. When it is presented in this light, thought
  • has a different part to play from what it has if we speak of a faculty
  • of thought, one among a crowd of other faculties, such as perception,
  • conception and will, with which it stands on the same level. When it
  • is seen, to be the true universal of all that nature and mind contain,
  • it extends its scope far beyond all these, and becomes the basis of
  • everything. From this view of thought, in its objective meaning as
  • [greek: nous], we may next pass to consider the subjective sense of the
  • term. We say first, Man is a being that thinks; but we also say at the
  • same time, Man is a being that perceives and wills. Man is a thinker,
  • and is universal: but he is a thinker only because he feels his own
  • universality. The animal too is by implication universal, but the
  • universal is not consciously felt by it to be universal: it feels only
  • the individual. The animal sees a singular object, for instance, its
  • food, or a man. For the animal all this never goes beyond an individual
  • thing. Similarly, sensation has to do with nothing but singulars, such
  • as _this_ pain or _this_ sweet taste. Nature does not bring its "νοῦς"
  • into consciousness: it is man who first makes himself double so as
  • to be a universal for a universal. This first happens when man knows
  • that he is 'I.' By the term 'I' I mean myself, a single and altogether
  • determinate person. And yet I really utter nothing peculiar to myself,
  • for every one else is an 'I' or 'Ego,' and when I call myself 'I,'
  • though I indubitably mean the single person myself, I express a
  • thorough universal. 'I,' therefore, is mere being-for-self, in which
  • everything peculiar or marked is renounced and buried out of sight;
  • it is as it were the ultimate and unanalysable point of consciousness
  • We may say 'I' I and thought are the same, or, more definitely, 'I'
  • is thought as a thinker. What I have in my consciousness, is for me.
  • 'I' is the vacuum or receptacle for anything and everything: for which
  • everything is and which stores up everything in itself. Every man is a
  • whole world of conceptions, that lie buried in the night of the 'Ego.'
  • It follows that the 'Ego' is the universal in which we leave aside all
  • that is particular, and in which at the same time all the particulars
  • have a latent existence. In other words, it is not a mere universality
  • and nothing more, but the universality which includes in it everything.
  • Commonly we use the word 'I' without attaching much importance to it,
  • nor is it an object of study except to philosophical analysis. In the
  • 'Ego,' we have thought before us in its utter purity. While the brute
  • cannot say 'I,' man can, because it is his nature to think. Now in the
  • 'Ego' there are a variety of contents, derived both from within and
  • from, without, and according to the nature of these contents our state
  • may be described as perception, or conception, or reminiscence. But
  • in all of them the 'I' is found: or in them all thought is present.
  • Man, therefore, is always thinking, even in his perceptions: if he
  • observes anything, he always observes it as a universal, fixes on a
  • single point which he places in relief, thus withdrawing his attention
  • from other points, and takes it as abstract and universal, even if the
  • universality be only in form.
  • In the case of our ordinary conceptions, two things may happen. Either
  • the contents are moulded by thought, but not the form: or, the form
  • belongs to thought and not the contents. In using such terms, for
  • instance, as anger, rose, hope, I am speaking of things which I have
  • learnt in the way of sensation, but I express these contents in a
  • universal mode, that is, in the form of thought. I have left out much
  • that is particular and given the contents in their generality: but
  • still the contents remain sense-derived. On the other hand, when I
  • represent God, the content is undeniably a product of pure thought,
  • but the form still retains the sensuous limitations which it has as
  • I find it immediately present in myself. In these generalised images
  • the content is not merely and simply sensible, as it is in a visual
  • inspection; but either the content is sensuous and the form appertains
  • to thought, or _vice versâ._ In the first case the material is given to
  • us, and our thought supplies the form: in the second case the content
  • which has its source in thought is by means of the form turned into a
  • something given, which accordingly reaches the mind from without.
  • (2) Logic is the study of thought pure and simple, or of the pure
  • thought-forms. In the ordinary sense of the term, by thought we
  • generally represent to ourselves something more than simple and
  • unmixed thought; we mean some thought, the material of which is from
  • experience. Whereas in logic a thought is understood to include nothing
  • else but what depends on thinking and what thinking has brought into
  • existence. It is in these circumstances that thoughts are _pure_
  • thoughts. The mind is then in its own home-element and therefore free:
  • for freedom means that the other thing with which you deal is a second
  • self--so that you never leave your own ground but give the law to
  • yourself. In the impulses or appetites the beginning is from something
  • else, from something which we feel to be external. In this case then
  • we speak of dependence. For freedom it is necessary that we should
  • feel no presence of something else which is not ourselves. The natural
  • man, whose motions follow the rule only of his appetites, is not his
  • own master. Be he as self-willed as he may, the constituents of his
  • will and opinion are not his own, and his freedom is merely formal.
  • But when we _think,_ we renounce our selfish and particular being,
  • sink ourselves in the thing, allow thought to follow its own course,
  • and,--if we add anything of our own, we think ill.
  • If in pursuance of the foregoing remarks we consider-, Logic to be
  • the system of the pure types of thought, we find that the other
  • philosophical sciences, the Philosophy of I Nature and the Philosophy
  • of Mind, take the place, as it were, of an Applied Logic, and that
  • Logic is the soul which animates them both. Their problem in that
  • case is only to recognise the logical forms under the shapes they
  • assume in Nature and Mind,--shapes which are only a particular mode
  • of expression for the forms of pure thought. If for instance we take
  • the syllogism (not as it was understood in the old formal logic, but
  • at its real value), we shall find it gives expression to the law that
  • the particular is the middle term which fuses together the extremes of
  • the universal and the singular. The syllogistic form is a universal
  • form of all things. Everything that exists is a particular, which
  • couples together the universal and the singular. But Nature is weak
  • and fails to exhibit the logical forms in their purity. Such a feeble
  • exemplification of the syllogism may be seen in the magnet. In the
  • middle or point of indifference of a magnet, its two poles, however
  • they may be distinguished, are brought into one. Physics also teaches
  • us to see the universal or essence in Nature: and the only difference
  • between it and the Philosophy of Nature is that the latter brings
  • before our mind the adequate forms of the notion in the physical world.
  • It will now be understood that Logic is the all-animating spirit of
  • all the sciences, and its categories the spiritual hierarchy. They
  • are the heart and centre of things: and yet at the same time they
  • are always on our lips, and, apparently at least, perfectly familiar
  • objects. But things thus familiar are usually the greatest strangers.
  • Being, for example, is a category of pure thought: but to make 'Is'
  • an object of investigation never occurs to us. Common fancy puts the
  • Absolute far away in a world beyond. The Absolute is rather directly
  • before us, so present that so long as we think, we must, though without
  • express consciousness of it, always carry it with us and always use it.
  • Language is the main depository of these types of thought; and one use
  • of the grammatical instruction which children receive is unconsciously
  • to turn their attention to distinctions of thought.
  • Logic is usually said to be concerned with forms _only_ and to derive
  • the material for them from elsewhere. But this 'only,' which assumes
  • that the logical thoughts are nothing in comparison with the rest
  • of the contents, is not the word to use about forms which are the
  • absolutely-real ground of everything. Everything else rather is an
  • 'only' compared with these thoughts. To make such abstract forms a
  • problem pre-supposes in the inquirer a higher level of culture than
  • ordinary; and to study them in themselves and for their own sake
  • signifies in addition that these thought-types must be deduced out of
  • thought itself, and their truth or reality examined by the light of
  • their own laws. We do not assume them as data from without, and then
  • define them or exhibit their value and authority by comparing them with
  • the shape they take in our minds. If we thus acted, we should proceed
  • from observation and experience, and should, for instance, say we
  • habitually employ the term 'force' in such a case, and such a meaning.
  • A definition like that would be called correct, if it agreed with the
  • conception of its object present in our ordinary state of mind. The
  • defect of this empirical method is that a notion is not defined as it
  • is in and for itself, but in terms of something assumed, which is then
  • used as a criterion and standard of correctness. No such test need be
  • applied: we have merely to let the thought-forms follow the impulse of
  • their own organic life.
  • To ask if a category is true or not, must sound strange to the ordinary
  • mind: for a category apparently becomes true only when it is applied
  • to a given object, and apart from this application it would seem
  • meaningless to inquire into its truth. But this is the very question on
  • which everything turns. We must however in the first place understand
  • clearly what we mean by Truth. In common life truth means the agreement
  • of an object with our conception of it. We thus pre-suppose an object
  • to which our conception must conform. In the philosophical sense of the
  • word, on the other hand, truth may be described, in general abstract
  • terms, as the agreement of a thought-content with itself. This meaning
  • is quite different from the one given above. At the same time the
  • deeper and philosophical meaning of truth can be partially traced even
  • in the ordinary usage of language. Thus we speak of a true friend; by
  • which we mean a friend whose manner of conduct accords with the notion
  • of friendship. In the same way we speak of a true work of Art. Untrue
  • in this sense means the same as bad, or self-discordant. In this sense
  • a bad state is an untrue state; and evil and untruth may be said to
  • consist in the contradiction subsisting between the function or notion
  • and the existence of the object. Of such a bad object we may form
  • a correct representation, but the import of such representation is
  • inherently false. Of these correctnesses; which are at the same time
  • untruths, we may have many in our heads.--God alone is the thorough
  • harmony of notion and reality. All finite things involve an untruth:
  • they have a notion and an existence, but their existence does not meet
  • the requirements of the notion. For this reason they must perish, and
  • then the incompatibility between their notion and their existence
  • becomes manifest. It is in the kind that the individual animal has its
  • notion: and the kind liberates itself from this individuality by death.
  • The study of truth, or, as it is here explained to mean, consistency,
  • constitutes the proper problem of logic. In our every-day mind we
  • are never troubled with questions about the truth of the forms of
  • thought.--We may also express the problem of logic by saying that it
  • examines the forms of thought touching their capability to hold truth.
  • And the question comes to this: What are the forms of the infinite, and
  • what are the forms of the finite? Usually no suspicion attaches to the
  • finite forms of thought; they are allowed to pass unquestioned. But it
  • is from conforming to finite categories in thought and action that all
  • deception originates.
  • (3) Truth may be ascertained by several methods, each of which however
  • is no more than a form. Experience is the first of these methods. But
  • the method is only a form: it has no intrinsic value of its own. For
  • in experience everything depends upon the mind we bring to bear upon
  • actuality. A great mind is great in its experience; and in the motley
  • play of phenomena at once perceives the point of real significance. The
  • idea is present, in actual shape, not something, as it were, over the
  • hill and far away. The genius of a Goethe, for example, looking into
  • nature or history, has great experiences, catches sight of the living
  • principle, and gives expression to it. A second method of apprehending
  • the truth is Reflection, which defines it by intellectual relations of
  • condition and conditioned. But in these two modes the absolute truth
  • has not yet found its appropriate form. The most perfect method of
  • knowledge proceeds in the pure form of thought: and here the attitude
  • of man is one of entire freedom.
  • That the form of thought is the perfect form, and that it presents
  • the truth as it intrinsically and actually is, is the general dogma
  • of all philosophy. To give a proof of the dogma there is, in the
  • first instance, nothing to do but show that these other forms of
  • knowledge are finite. The grand Scepticism of antiquity accomplished
  • this task when it exhibited the contradictions contained in every
  • one of these forms. That Scepticism indeed went further: but when
  • it ventured to assail the forms of reason, it began by insinuating
  • under them something finite upon which it might fasten. All the
  • forms of finite thought will make their appearance in the course of
  • logical development, the order in which they present themselves being
  • determined by necessary laws. Here in the introduction they could only
  • be unscientifically assumed as something given. In the theory of logic
  • itself these forms will be exhibited, not only on their negative, but
  • also on their positive side.
  • When we compare the different forms of ascertaining truth with one
  • another, the first of them, immediate knowledge, may perhaps seem the
  • finest, noblest and most appropriate. It includes everything which
  • the moralists term innocence as well as religious feeling, simple
  • trust, love, fidelity, and natural faith. The two other forms, first
  • reflective, and secondly philosophical cognition, must leave that
  • unsought natural harmony behind. And so far as they have this in
  • common, the methods which claim to apprehend the truth by thought
  • may naturally be regarded as part and parcel of the pride which leads
  • man to trust to his own powers for a knowledge of the truth. Such a
  • position involves a thorough-going disruption, and, viewed in that
  • light, might be regarded as the source of all evil and wickedness--the
  • original transgression. Apparently therefore they only way of being
  • reconciled and restored to peace is to surrender all claims to think or
  • know.
  • This lapse from natural unity has not escaped notice, and nations from
  • the earliest times have asked the meaning of the wonderful division of
  • the spirit against itself. No such inward disunion is found in nature:
  • natural things do nothing wicked.
  • The Mosaic legend of the Fall of Man has preserved an ancient picture
  • representing the origin and consequences of this disunion. The
  • incidents of the legend form the basis of an essential article of the
  • creed, the doctrine of original sin in man and his consequent need of
  • succour. It may be well at the commencement of logic to examine the
  • story which treats of the origin and the bearings of the very knowledge
  • which logic has to discuss. For, though philosophy must not allow
  • herself to be overawed by religion, or accept the position of existence
  • on sufferance, she cannot afford to neglect these popular conceptions.
  • The tales and allegories of religion, which have enjoyed for thousands
  • of years the veneration of nations, are not to be set aside as
  • antiquated even now.
  • Upon a closer inspection of the story of the Fall we find, as was
  • already said, that it exemplifies the universal bearings of knowledge
  • upon the spiritual life. In its instinctive and natural stage,
  • spiritual life wears the garb of innocence and confiding simplicity:
  • but the very essence of spirit implies the absorption of this immediate
  • condition in something higher. The spiritual is distinguished from the
  • natural, and more especially from the animal, life, in the circumstance
  • that it does not continue a mere stream of tendency, but sunders itself
  • to self-realisation. But this position of severed life has in its turn
  • to be suppressed, and the spirit has by its own act to win its way
  • to concord again. The final concord then is spiritual; that is, the
  • principle of restoration is found in thought, and thought only. The
  • hand that inflicts the wound is also the hand which heals it.
  • We are told in our story that Adam and Eve, the first human beings,
  • the types of humanity, were placed in a garden, where grew a tree of
  • life and a tree of the knowledge of good and evil. God, it is said,
  • had forbidden them to eat of the fruit of this latter tree: of the
  • tree of life for the present nothing further is said. These words
  • evidently assume that man is not intended to seek knowledge, and ought
  • to remain in the state of innocence. Other meditative races, it may
  • be remarked, have held the same belief that the primitive state of
  • mankind was one of innocence and harmony. Now all this is to a certain
  • extent correct. The disunion that appears throughout humanity is not
  • a condition to rest in. But it is a mistake to regard the natural and
  • immediate harmony as the right state. The mind is not mere instinct:
  • on the contrary, it essentially involves the tendency to reasoning
  • and meditation. Childlike innocence no doubt has in it something
  • fascinating and attractive: but only because it reminds us of what the
  • spirit must win for itself. The harmoniousness of childhood is a gift
  • from the hand of nature: the second harmony must spring from the labour
  • and culture of the spirit. And so the words of Christ, 'Except ye
  • _become_ as little children,' &c., are very far from telling us that we
  • must always remain children.
  • Again, we find in the narrative of Moses that the occasion which led
  • man to leave his natural unity is attributed to solicitation from
  • without. The serpent was the tempter. But the truth is, that the step
  • into opposition, the awakening of consciousness, follows from the
  • very nature of man: and the same history repeats itself in every son
  • of Adam. The serpent represents likeness to God as consisting in the
  • knowledge of good and evil: and it is just this knowledge in which man
  • participates when he breaks with the unity of his instinctive being
  • and eats of the forbidden fruit. The first reflection of awakened
  • consciousness in men told them that they were naked. This is a naïve
  • and profound trait. For the sense of shame bears evidence to the
  • separation of man from his natural and sensuous life. The beasts never
  • get so far as this separation, and they feel no shame. And it is in
  • the human feeling of shame that we are to seek the spiritual and moral
  • origin of dress, compared with which the merely physical need is a
  • secondary matter.
  • Next comes the Curse, as it is called, which God pronounced upon
  • man. The prominent point in that curse turns chiefly on the contrast
  • between man and nature. Man must work in the sweat of his brow: and
  • woman bring forth in sorrow. As to work, if it is the result of the
  • disunion, it is also the victory over it. The beasts have nothing more
  • to do but to pick up the materials required to satisfy their wants: man
  • on the contrary can only satisfy his wants by himself producing and
  • transforming the necessary means. Thus even in these outside things man
  • is dealing with himself.
  • The story does not close with the expulsion from Paradise. We are
  • further told, God said, 'Behold Adam is become as one of us, to
  • know good and evil.' Knowledge is now spoken of as divine, and not,
  • as before, as something wrong and forbidden. Such words contain a
  • confutation of the idle talk that philosophy pertains only to the
  • finitude of the mind. Philosophy is knowledge, and it is through
  • knowledge that man first realises his original vocation, to be the
  • image of God. When the record adds that God drove men out of the Garden
  • of Eden to prevent their eating of the tree of life, it only means
  • that on his natural side certainly man is finite and mortal, but in
  • knowledge infinite.
  • We all know the theological dogma that man's nature is evil, tainted
  • with what is called Original Sin. Now while we accept the dogma, we
  • must give up the setting of incident which represents original sin as
  • consequent upon an accidental act of the first man. For the very notion
  • of spirit is enough to show that man is evil by nature, and it is an
  • error to imagine that he could ever be otherwise. To such extent as man
  • is and acts like a creature of nature, his whole behaviour is what it
  • ought not to be. For the spirit it is a duty to be free, and to realise
  • itself by its own act. Nature is for man only the starting-point which
  • he has to transform. The theological doctrine of original sin is a
  • profound truth; but modern enlightenment prefers to believe that man is
  • naturally good, and that he acts right so long as he continues true to
  • nature.
  • The hour when man leaves the path of mere natural being marks the
  • difference between him, a self-conscious agent, and the natural world.
  • But this schism, though it forms a necessary element in the very notion
  • of spirit, is not the final goal of man. It is to this state of inward
  • breach that the whole finite action of thought and will belongs.
  • In that finite sphere man pursues ends of his own and draws from
  • himself the material of his conduct. While he pursues these aims to
  • the uttermost, while his knowledge and his will seek himself, his own
  • narrow self apart from the universal, he is evil; and his evil is to be
  • subjective.
  • We seem at first to have a double evil here: but both are really the
  • same. Man in so far as he is spirit is not the creature of nature: and
  • when he behaves as such, and follows the cravings of appetite, he wills
  • to be so. The natural wickedness of man is therefore unlike the natural
  • life of animals. A mere natural life may be more exactly defined by
  • saying that the natural man as such is an individual: for nature in
  • every part is in the bonds of individualism. Thus when man wills to be
  • a creature of nature, he wills in the Same degree to be an individual
  • simply. Yet against such impulsive and appetitive action, due to
  • the individualism of nature, there also steps in the law or general
  • principle. This law may either be an external force, or have the form
  • of divine authority. So long as he continues in his natural state, man
  • is in bondage to the law.--It is true that among the instincts and
  • affections of man, there are social or benevolent inclinations, love,
  • sympathy, and others, reaching beyond his selfish isolation. But so
  • long as these tendencies are instinctive, their virtual universality
  • of scope and purport is vitiated by the subjective form which always
  • allows free play to self-seeking and random action.
  • 25.] The term 'Objective Thoughts' indicates the _truth_--the truth
  • which is to be the absolute _object_ of philosophy, and not merely the
  • goal at which it aims. But the very expression cannot fail to suggest
  • an opposition, to characterise and appreciate which is the main motive
  • of the philosophical attitude of the present time, and which forms the
  • real problem of the question about truth and our means of ascertaining
  • it. If the thought-forms are vitiated by a fixed antithesis, _i.
  • e._ if they are only of a finite character, they are unsuitable for
  • the self-centred universe of truth, and truth can find no adequate
  • receptacle in thought. Such thought, which--- can produce only limited
  • and partial categories and I proceed by their means; is what in the
  • stricter sense of the word is termed Understanding. The finitude,
  • further, of these categories lies in two points. Firstly, they are only
  • subjective, and the antithesis of an objective permanently clings to
  • them. Secondly, they are always of restricted content, and so persist
  • in antithesis to one another and still more to the Absolute. In order
  • more fully to explain the position and import here attributed to logic,
  • the attitudes in which thought is supposed to stand to objectivity will
  • next be examined by way of further introduction.
  • In my Phenomenology of the Spirit, which on that account was at its
  • publication described as the first part of the System of Philosophy,
  • the method adopted was to begin with the first and simplest phase of
  • mind, immediate consciousness, and to show how that stage gradually
  • of necessity worked onward to the philosophical point of view, the
  • necessity of that view being proved by the process. But in these
  • circumstances it was impossible to restrict the quest to the mere form
  • of consciousness. For the stage of philosophical knowledge is the
  • richest in material and organisation, and therefore, as it came before
  • us in the shape of a result, it pre-supposed the existence of the
  • concrete formations of consciousness, such as individual and social
  • morality, art and religion. In the development of consciousness, which
  • at first sight appears limited to the point of form merely, there is
  • thus at the same time included the development of the matter or of the
  • objects discussed in the special branches of philosophy. But the latter
  • process must, so to speak, go on behind consciousness, since those
  • facts are the essential nucleus which is raised into consciousness.
  • The exposition accordingly is rendered more intricate, because so much
  • that properly belongs to the concrete branches is prematurely dragged
  • into the introduction. The survey which follows in the present work has
  • even more the inconvenience of being only historical and inferential in
  • its method. But it tries especially to show how the questions men have
  • proposed, outside the school, on the nature of Knowledge, Faith and the
  • like,--questions which they imagine to have no connexion with abstract
  • thoughts,--are really reducible to the simple categories, which first
  • get cleared up in Logic.
  • CHAPTER III.
  • FIRST ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY.
  • 28.] The first of these attitudes of thought is seen in the method
  • which has no doubts and no sense of the contradiction in thought, or of
  • the hostility of thought against itself. It entertains an unquestioning
  • belief that reflection is the means of ascertaining the truth, and of
  • bringing the objects before the mind as they really are. And in this
  • belief it advances straight upon its objects, takes the materials
  • furnished by sense and perception, and reproduces them from itself as
  • facts of thought; and then, believing this result to be the truth, the
  • method is content. Philosophy in its earliest stages, all the sciences,
  • and even the daily action and movement of consciousness, live in this
  • faith.
  • 27.] This method of thought has never become aware, of the antithesis
  • of subjective and objective: and to that extent there is nothing to
  • prevent its statements from possessing a genuinely philosophical and
  • speculative character, though it is just as possible that they may
  • never get beyond finite categories, or the stage where the antithesis
  • is still unresolved. In the present introduction the main question
  • for us is to observe this attitude of thought in its extreme form;
  • and we shall accordingly first of all examine its second and inferior
  • aspect as a philosophic system. One of the clearest instances of it,
  • and one lying nearest to ourselves, may be found in the Metaphysic of
  • the Past as it subsisted among us previous to the philosophy of Kant.
  • It is however only in reference to the history of philosophy that this
  • Metaphysic can be said to belong to the past: the thing is always and
  • at all places to be found, as the view which the abstract understanding
  • takes of the objects of reason. And it is in this point that the real
  • and immediate good lies of a closer examination of its main scope and
  • its _modus operandi._
  • 28.] This metaphysical system took the laws and forms of thought to be
  • the fundamental laws and forms of things. It assumed that to think a
  • thing was the means of finding its very self and nature: and to that
  • extent it occupied higher ground than the Critical. Philosophy which
  • succeeded it. But in the first instance (i) _these terms of thought
  • were cut off from their connexion,_ their solidarity; each was believed
  • valid by itself and capable of serving as a predicate of the truth. It
  • was the general assumption of this metaphysic that a knowledge of the
  • Absolute was gained by assigning predicates to it. It neither inquired
  • what the terms of the understanding specially meant or what they were
  • worth, nor did it test the method which characterises the Absolute by
  • the assignment of predicates.
  • As an example of such predicates may be taken; Existence, in the
  • proposition, 'God has existence:' Finitude or Infinity, as in the
  • question, 'Is the world-finite or infinite?': Simple and Complex,
  • in the proposition, 'The soul is simple,'--or again, 'The thing is
  • a unity, a whole,' &c. Nobody asked whether such predicates had any
  • intrinsic and independent truth, or if the propositional form could be
  • a form of truth.
  • The Metaphysic of the past assumed, as unsophisticated belief always
  • does that thought apprehends the very self of things, and that things,
  • to become what they truly are, require to be thought. For Nature and
  • the human soul are a very Proteus in their perpetual transformations;
  • and it soon occurs to the observer that the first crude impression of
  • things is not their essential being.--This is a point of view the very
  • reverse of the result arrived at by the Critical Philosophy; a result,
  • of which it may be said, that it bade man go and feed on mere husks and
  • chaff.
  • We must look more closely into the procedure of that old metaphysic.
  • In the first place it never went beyond the province of the analytic
  • understanding. Without preliminary inquiry it adopted the abstract
  • categories of thought and let them rank as predicates of truth. But in
  • using the term thought we must not forget the difference between finite
  • or discursive thinking and the thinking which is infinite and rational.
  • The categories, as they meet us _prima facie_ and in isolation, are
  • finite forms. But truth is always infinite, and cannot be expressed
  • or presented to consciousness in finite terms. The phrase _infinite
  • thought_ may excite surprise, if we adhere to the modern conception
  • that thought is always limited. But it is, speaking rightly, the very
  • essence of thought to be infinite. The nominal explanation of calling
  • a thing finite is that it has an end, that it exists up to a certain
  • point only, where it comes into contact with, and is limited by, its
  • other. The finite therefore subsists in reference to its other, which
  • is its negation and presents itself as its limit. Now thought is always
  • in its own sphere; its relations are with itself, and it is its own
  • object. In having a thought for object, I am at home with myself.
  • The thinking power, the 'I,' is therefore infinite, because, when it
  • thinks, it is in relation to an object which is itself. Generally
  • speaking, an object means a something else, a negative confronting me.
  • But in the case where thought thinks itself, it has an object which
  • is at the same time no object: in other words, its objectivity is
  • suppressed and transformed into an idea. Thought, as thought, therefore
  • in its unmixed nature involves no limits; it is finite only when it
  • keeps to limited categories, which it believes to be ultimate. Infinite
  • or speculative thought, on the contrary, while it no less defines,
  • does in the very act of limiting and defining make that defect vanish.
  • And so infinity is not, as most frequently happens, to be conceived as
  • an abstract away and away for ever and ever, but in the simple manner
  • previously indicated.
  • The thinking of the old metaphysical system was finite. Its whole mode
  • of action was regulated by categories, the limits of which it believed
  • to be permanently fixed and not subject to any further negation. Thus,
  • one of its questions was: Has God existence? The question supposes that
  • existence is an altogether positive term, a sort of _ne plus ultra._
  • We shall see however at a later point that existence is by no means a
  • merely positive term, but one which is toe low for the Absolute Idea,
  • and unworthy of God. A second question in these metaphysical systems
  • was: Is the world finite or infinite? The very terms of the question
  • assume that the finite is a permanent contradictory to the infinite:
  • and one can easily see that, when they are so opposed, the infinite,
  • which of course ought to be the whole, only appears as a single aspect
  • and suffers restriction from the finite. But a restricted infinity is
  • itself only a finite. In the same way it was asked whether the soul was
  • simple or composite. Simpleness was, in other words, taken to be an
  • ultimate characteristic, giving expression to a whole truth. Far from
  • being so, simpleness is the expression of a half-truth, as one-sided
  • and abstract as existence:--a term of thought, which, as we shall
  • hereafter see, is itself untrue and hence unable to hold truth. If the
  • soul be viewed as merely and abstractly simple, it is characterised in
  • an inadequate and finite way.
  • It was therefore the main question of the pre-Kantian metaphysic to
  • discover whether predicates of the kind mentioned were to be ascribed
  • to its objects. Now these predicates are after all only limited
  • formulae of the understanding which, instead of expressing the truth,
  • merely impose a limit. More than this, it should be noted that the
  • chief feature of the method lay in 'assigning' or 'attributing'
  • predicates to the object that was to be cognised, for example, to
  • God. But attribution is no more than an external reflection about the
  • object: the predicates by which the object is to be determined are
  • supplied from the resources of picture-thought, and are applied in
  • a mechanical way. Whereas, if we are to have genuine cognition, the
  • object must characterise its own self and not derive its predicates
  • from without. Even supposing we follow the method of predicating, the
  • mind cannot help feeling that predicates of this sort fail to exhaust
  • the object. From the same point of view the Orientals are quite correct
  • in calling God the many-named or the myriad-named One. One after
  • another of these finite categories leaves the soul unsatisfied, and
  • the Oriental sage is compelled unceasingly to seek for more and more
  • of such predicates. In finite things it is no doubt the case that they
  • have to be characterised through finite predicates: and with these
  • things the understanding finds proper scope for its special action.
  • Itself finite, it knows only the nature of the finite. Thus, when
  • I call some action a theft, I have characterised the action in its
  • essential facts: and such a knowledge is sufficient for the judge.
  • Similarly, finite things stand to each other as cause and effect,
  • force and exercise, and when they are apprehended in these categories,
  • they are known in their finitude. But the objects of reason cannot be
  • defined by these finite predicates. To try to do so was the defect of
  • the old metaphysic.
  • 29.] Predicates of this kind, taken individually, have but a limited
  • range of meaning, and no one can fail to perceive how inadequate they
  • are, and how far they fall below the fulness of detail which our
  • imaginative thought gives, in the case, for example, of God, Mind, or
  • Nature. Besides, though the fact of their being all predicates of one
  • subject supplies them with a certain connexion, their several meanings
  • keep them apart: and consequently each is brought in as a stranger in
  • relation to the others.
  • The first of these defects the Orientals sought to remedy, when, for
  • example, they defined God by attributing to Him many names; but still
  • they felt that the number of names would have had to be infinite.
  • 30.] (2) In the second place, _the metaphysical systems adopted a
  • wrong criterion._ Their objects were no doubt totalities which in
  • their own proper selves belong to reason,--that is, to the organised
  • and systematically-developed universe, of thought. But these
  • totalities--God, the Soul, the World,--were taken by the metaphysician
  • as subjects made and ready, to form the basis for an application of
  • the categories of the understanding. They were assumed from popular
  • conception. Accordingly popular conception was the only canon for
  • settling whether or not the predicates were suitable and sufficient.
  • 31.] The common conceptions of God, the Soul, the World, may be
  • supposed to afford thought a firm and fast footing. They do not really
  • do so. Besides having, a particular and subjective character clinging
  • to them, and thus leaving room for great variety of interpretation,
  • they themselves first of all require a firm and fast definition by
  • thought. This may be seen in any of these propositions where the
  • predicate, or in philosophy the category, is needed to indicate what
  • the subject, or the conception we start with, is.
  • In such a sentence as 'God is eternal,' we begin with the conception of
  • God, not knowing as yet what he is: to tell us that, is the business of
  • the predicate. In the principles of logic, accordingly, where the terms
  • formulating the subject-matter are those of thought only, it is not
  • merely superfluous to make these categories predicates to propositions
  • in which God, or, still vaguer, the Absolute, is the subject, but it
  • would also have the disadvantage of suggesting another canon than
  • the nature of thought. Besides, the propositional form (and for
  • proposition, it would be more correct to substitute judgment) is not
  • suited to express the concrete--and the true is always concrete--or
  • the speculative. Every judgment is by its form one-sided and, to that
  • extent, false.
  • This metaphysic was not free or objective thinking. Instead of letting
  • the object freely and spontaneously expound its own characteristics,
  • metaphysic pre-supposed it ready-made. If any one wishes to know what
  • free thought means, he must go to Greek philosophy: for Scholasticism,
  • like these metaphysical systems, accepted its facts, and accepted them
  • as a dogma from the authority of the Church. We moderns, too, by our
  • whole up-bringing, have been initiated into ideas which it is extremely
  • difficult to overstep, on account of their far-reaching significance.
  • But the ancient philosophers were in a different position. They were
  • men who lived wholly in the perceptions of the senses, and who,
  • after their rejection of mythology and its fancies, pre-supposed
  • nothing but the heaven above and the earth around. In these material,
  • non-metaphysical surroundings, thought is free and enjoys its own
  • privacy,--cleared of everything material, and thoroughly at home. This
  • feeling that we are all our own is characteristic of free thought--of
  • that voyage into the open, where nothing is below us or above us, and
  • we stand in solitude with ourselves alone.
  • 32.] (3) In the third place, _this system of metaphysic turned into
  • Dogmatism._ When our thought never ranges beyond narrow and rigid
  • terms, we are forced to assume that of two opposite assertions, such as
  • were the above propositions, the one must be true and the other false.
  • Dogmatism may be most simply described as the contrary of Scepticism.
  • The ancient Sceptics gave the name of Dogmatism to every philosophy
  • whatever holding a system of definite doctrine. In this large sense
  • Scepticism may apply the name even to philosophy which is properly
  • Speculative. But in the narrower sense, Dogmatism consists in the
  • tenacity which draws a hard and fast line between certain terms
  • and others opposite to them. We may see this clearly in the strict
  • 'Either--or': for instance, The world is either finite or infinite;
  • but one of these two it must be. The contrary of this rigidity is the
  • characteristic of all Speculative truth. There no such inadequate
  • formulae are allowed, nor can they possibly exhaust it. These formulae
  • Speculative truth holds in union as a totality, whereas, Dogmatism
  • invests them in their isolation with a title to fixity and truth.
  • It often happens in philosophy that the half-truth takes its place
  • beside the whole truth and assumes on its own account the position
  • of something permanent. But the fact is that the half-truth, instead
  • of being a fixed or self-subsistent principle, is a mere element
  • absolved and included in the whole. The metaphysic of understanding is
  • dogmatic, because it maintains half-truths in their isolation: whereas
  • the idealism of speculative philosophy carries out the principle of
  • totality and shows that it can reach beyond the inadequate formularies
  • of abstract thought. Thus idealism would say:--The soul is neither
  • finite only, nor infinite only; it is really the one just as much as
  • the other, and in that way neither the one nor the other. In other
  • words; such formularies in their isolation are inadmissible, and only
  • come into account as formative elements in a larger notion. Such
  • idealism we see even in the ordinary phases of consciousness. Thus we
  • say of sensible things, that they are changeable: that is, they _are,_
  • but it is equally true that they are _not._ We show more obstinacy
  • in dealing with the categories of the understanding. These are terms
  • which we believe to be somewhat firmer--or even absolutely firm and
  • fast. We look upon them as separated from each other by an infinite
  • chasm, so that opposite categories can never get at each other. The
  • battle of reason is the struggle to break up the rigidity to which the
  • understanding has reduced everything.
  • 33.] The _first_ part of this metaphysic in its systematic form is
  • Ontology, or the doctrine of the abstract characteristics of Being.
  • The multitude of these characteristics, and the limits set to their
  • applicability, are not founded upon any principle. They have in
  • consequence to be enumerated as experience and circumstances direct,
  • and the import ascribed to them is founded only upon common sensualised
  • conceptions, upon assertions that particular words are used in a
  • particular sense, and even perhaps upon etymology. If experience
  • pronounces the list to be complete, and if the usage of language, by
  • its agreement, shows the analysis to be correct, the metaphysician is
  • satisfied; and the intrinsic and independent truth and necessity of
  • such characteristics is never made a matter of investigation at all.
  • To ask if being, existence, finitude, simplicity, complexity, &c. are
  • notions intrinsically and independently true, must surprise those who
  • believe that a question about truth can only concern propositions (as
  • to whether a notion is or is not with truth to be attributed, as the
  • phrase is, to a subject), and that falsehood lies in the contradiction
  • existing between the subject in our ideas, and the notion to be
  • predicated of it. Now as the notion is concrete, it and every character
  • of it in general is essentially a self-contained unity of distinct
  • characteristics. If truth then were nothing more than the absence
  • of contradiction, it would be first of all necessary in the case of
  • every-notion to examine whether it, taken individually, did not contain
  • this sort of intrinsic contradiction.
  • 34.] The _second_ branch of the metaphysical system was Rational
  • Psychology or Pneumatology. It dealt with the metaphysical nature of
  • the Soul,--that is, of the Mind regarded as a thing. It expected to
  • find immortality in a sphere dominated by the laws of composition,
  • time, qualitative change, and quantitative increase or decrease.
  • The name 'rational,' given to this species of psychology, served
  • to contrast it with empirical modes of observing the phenomena of
  • the soul. Rational psychology viewed the soul in its metaphysical
  • nature, and through the categories supplied by abstract thought. The
  • rationalists endeavoured to ascertain the inner nature of the soul as
  • it is in itself and as it is for thought.--In philosophy at present we
  • hear little of the soul: the favourite term now is mind (spirit). The
  • two are distinct, soul being as it were the middle term between body
  • and spirit, or the bond between the two. The mind, as soul, is immersed
  • in corporeity, and the soul is the animating principle of the body.
  • The pre-Kantian metaphysic, we say, viewed the soul as a thing. 'Thing'
  • is a very ambiguous word. By a thing, we mean, firstly, an immediate
  • existence, something we represent in sensuous form: and in this meaning
  • the term has been applied to the soul. Hence the question regarding the
  • seat of the soul. Of course, if the soul have a seat, it is in space
  • and sensuously envisaged. So, too, if the soul be viewed as a thing,
  • we can ask whether the soul is simple or composite. The question is
  • important as bearing on the immortality of the soul, which is supposed
  • to depend on the absence of composition. But the fact is, that in
  • abstract simplicity we have a category, which as little corresponds to
  • the nature of the soul, as that of compositeness.
  • One word on the relation of rational to empirical psychology. The
  • former, because it sets itself to apply thought to cognise mind and
  • even to demonstrate the result of such thinking, is the higher; whereas
  • empirical psychology starts from perception, and only recounts and
  • describes what perception supplies. But if we propose to think the
  • mind, we must not be quite so shy of its special phenomena. Mind is
  • essentially active in the same sense as the Schoolmen said that God
  • is 'absolute actuosity.' But if the mind is active it must as it were
  • utter itself. It is wrong therefore to take the mind for a processless
  • _ens,_ as did the old metaphysic which divided the processless inward
  • life of the mind from its outward life. The mind, of all things, must
  • be looked at in its concrete actuality, in its energy; and in such a
  • way that its manifestations are seen to be determined by its inward
  • force.
  • 35.] The _third_ branch of metaphysics was Cosmology. The topics
  • it embraced were the world, its contingency, necessity, eternity,
  • limitation in time and space: the laws (only formal) of its changes:
  • the freedom of man and the origin of evil.
  • To these topics it applied what were believed to be thorough-going
  • contrasts: such as contingency and necessity; external and internal
  • necessity; efficient and final cause, or causality in general and
  • design; essence or substance and phenomenon; form and matter; freedom
  • and necessity; happiness and pain; good and evil.
  • The object of Cosmology comprised not merely Nature, but Mind too, in
  • its external complication in its phenomenon--in fact, existence in
  • general, or the sum of finite things. This object however it viewed not
  • as a concrete whole, but only under certain abstract points of view.
  • Thus the questions Cosmology attempted to solve were such as these: Is
  • accident or necessity dominant in the world? Is the world eternal or
  • created? It was therefore a chief concern of this study to lay down
  • what were called general Cosmological laws: for instance, that Nature
  • does not act by fits and starts. And by fits and starts (_saltus_) they
  • meant a qualitative difference or qualitative alteration showing itself
  • without any antecedent determining mean: whereas, on the contrary, a
  • gradual change (of quantity) is obviously not without intermediation.
  • In regard to Mind as it makes itself felt in the world, the questions
  • which Cosmology chiefly discussed turned upon the freedom of man and
  • the origin of evil. Nobody can deny that these are questions of the
  • highest importance. But to give them a satisfactory answer, it is above
  • all things necessary not to claim finality for the abstract formulae
  • of understanding, or to suppose that each of the two terms in an
  • antithesis has an independent-subsistence or can be treated in its
  • isolation as a complete and self-centred truth. This however is the
  • general position taken by the metaphysicians before Kant, and appears
  • in their cosmological discussions, which for that reason were incapable
  • of compassing their purpose, to understand the phenomena of the world.
  • Observe how they proceed with the distinction between freedom and
  • necessity, in their application of these categories to Nature and
  • Mind. Nature they regard as subject in its workings to necessity;
  • Mind they hold to be free. No doubt there is a real foundation for
  • this distinction in the very core of the Mind itself: but freedom and
  • necessity, when thus abstractly opposed, are terms applicable only in
  • the finite world to which, as such, they belong. A freedom involving no
  • necessity, and mere necessity without freedom, are abstract and in this
  • way untrue formulae of [thought. Freedom is no blank indeterminateness:
  • essentially concrete, and unvaryingly self-determinate, it is so far at
  • the same time necessary. Necessity, again, in the ordinary acceptation
  • of the term in popular philosophy, means determination from without
  • only,--as in finite mechanics, where a body moves only when it is
  • struck by another body, and moves in the direction communicated to it
  • by the impact.--This however is a merely external necessity, not the
  • real inward necessity which is identical with freedom.
  • The case is similar with the contrast of Good and Evil,--the favourite
  • contrast of the introspective modern world. If we regard Evil as
  • possessing a fixity of its own, apart and distinct from Good, we are
  • to a certain extent right: there is an opposition between them: nor
  • do those who maintain the apparent and relative character of the
  • opposition mean that Evil and Good in the Absolute are one, or, in
  • accordance with the modern phrase, that a thing first becomes evil
  • from our way of looking at it. The error arises when we take Evil as a
  • permanent positive, instead of--what it really is--a negative which,
  • though it would fain assert itself, has no real persistence, and is, in
  • fact, only the absolute sham-existence of negativity in itself.
  • 36.] The _fourth_ branch of metaphysics is Natural or Rational
  • Theology. The notion of God, or God as a possible being, the proofs of
  • his existence, and his properties, formed the study of this branch.
  • (a) When understanding thus discusses the Deity, its main purpose is
  • to find what predicates correspond or not to the fact we have in our
  • imagination as God. And in so doing it assumes the contrast between
  • positive and negative to be absolute; and hence, in the long run,
  • nothing is left for the notion as understanding takes it, but the empty
  • abstraction of indeterminate Being, of mere reality or positivity, the
  • lifeless product of modern 'Deism.'
  • (b) The method of demonstration employed in finite knowledge must
  • always lead to an inversion of the true order. For it requires the
  • statement of some objective ground for God's being, which thus acquires
  • the appearance of being derived from something else. This mode of
  • proof, guided as it is by the canon of mere analytical identity,
  • is embarrassed by the difficulty of passing from the finite to the
  • infinite. Either the finitude of the existing world, which is left as
  • much a fact as it was before, clings to the notion of Deity, and God
  • has to be defined as the immediate substance of that world,--which is
  • Pantheism: or He remains an object set over against the subject, and in
  • this way, finite,--which is Dualism.
  • (c) The attributes of God which ought to be various and precise, had,
  • properly speaking, sunk and disappeared in the abstract notion of pure
  • reality, of indeterminate Being. Yet in our material thought, the
  • finite world continues, meanwhile, to have a real being, with God as a
  • sort of antithesis: and thus arises the further picture of different
  • relations of God to the world. These, formulated as properties, must,
  • on the one hand, as relations to finite circumstances, themselves
  • possess a finite character (giving us such properties as just,
  • gracious, mighty, wise, &c.); on the other hand they must be infinite.
  • Now on this level of thought the only means, and a hazy one, of
  • reconciling these opposing requirements was quantitative exaltation
  • of the properties, forcing them into indeterminateness,--into the
  • _sensus eminentior._ But it was an expedient which really destroyed the
  • property and left a mere name.
  • The object of the old metaphysical theology was to see how far
  • unassisted reason could go in the knowledge of God. Certainly a
  • reason-derived knowledge of God is the highest problem of philosophy.
  • The earliest teachings of religion are figurate conceptions of God.
  • These conceptions, as the Creed arranges them, are imparted to us in
  • youth. They are the doctrines of our religion, and in so far as the
  • individual rests his faith on these doctrines and feels them to be
  • the truth, he has all he needs as a Christian. Such is faith: and the
  • science of this faith is Theology. But until Theology is something more
  • than a bare enumeration and compilation of these doctrines _ab extra,_
  • it has no right to the title of science. Even the method so much in
  • vogue at present--the purely historical mode of treatment--which for
  • example reports what has been said by this or the other Father of the
  • Church--does not invest theology with a scientific character. To get
  • that, we must go on to comprehend the facts by thought,--which is the
  • business of philosophy. Genuine theology is thus at the same time a
  • real philosophy of religion, as it was, we may add, in the Middle Ages.
  • And now let us examine this rational theology more narrowly. It was
  • a science which approached God not by reason but by understanding,
  • and, in its mode of thought, employed the terms without any sense of
  • their mutual limitations and connexions. The notion of God formed the
  • subject of discussion; and yet the criterion of our knowledge was
  • derived from such an extraneous source as the materialised conception
  • of God. Now thought must be free in its movements. It is no doubt to
  • be remembered, that the result of independent thought harmonises with
  • the import of the Christian religion:--for the Christian religion is
  • a revelation of reason. But such a harmony surpassed the efforts of
  • rational theology. It proposed to define the figurate conception of God
  • in terms of thought; but it resulted in a notion of God which was what
  • we may call the abstract of positivity or reality, to the exclusion
  • of all negation. God was accordingly defined to be the most real of
  • all beings. Any one can see however that this most real of beings, in
  • which negation forms no part, is the very opposite of what it ought
  • to be and of what understanding supposes it to be. Instead of being
  • rich and full above all measure, it is so narrowly conceived that it
  • is, on the contrary, extremely poor and altogether empty. It is with
  • reason that the heart craves a concrete body of truth; but without
  • definite feature, that is, without negation, contained in the notion,
  • there can only be an abstraction. When the notion of God is apprehended
  • only as that of the abstract or most real being, God is, as it were,
  • relegated to another world beyond: and to speak of a knowledge of him
  • would be meaningless. Where there is no definite quality, knowledge is
  • impossible. Mere light is mere darkness.
  • The second problem of rational theology was to prove the existence
  • of God. Now, in this matter, the main point to be noted is
  • that demonstration, as the understanding employs it, means the
  • dependence of one truth on another. In such proofs we have a
  • pre-supposition--something firm and fast, from which something else
  • follows; we exhibit the dependence of some truth from an assumed
  • starting-point. Hence, if this mode of demonstration is applied to the
  • existence of God, it can only mean that the being of God is to depend
  • on other terms, which will then constitute the ground of his being.
  • It is at once evident that this will lead I to some mistake: for God
  • must be simply and solely the I ground of everything, and in so far
  • not dependent upon anything else. And a perception of this danger has
  • in modern times led some to say that God's existence is not capable
  • of proof, but must be immediately or intuitively apprehended. Reason,
  • however, and even sound common sense give demonstration a meaning quite
  • different from that of the understanding. The demonstration of reason
  • no doubt starts from something which is not God. But, as it advances,
  • it does not leave the starting-point a mere unexplained fact, which is
  • what it was. On the contrary it exhibits that point as derivative and
  • called into being, and then God is seen to be primary, truly immediate
  • and self-subsisting, with the means of derivation wrapt up and absorbed
  • in himself. Those who say: 'Consider Nature, and Nature will-lead you
  • to God; you will find an absolute final cause: 'do not mean that God
  • is something derivative: they mean that it is we who proceed to God
  • himself from another; and in this way God, though the consequence, is
  • also the absolute' ground of the initial step. The relation of the two
  • things is reversed; and what came as a consequence, being shown to be
  • an antecedent, the original antecedent is reduced to a consequence.
  • This is always the way, moreover, whenever reason demonstrates.
  • If in the light of the present discussion we cast one glance more on
  • the metaphysical method as a whole, we find its main characteristic
  • was to make abstract identity its principle and to try to apprehend
  • the objects of reason by the abstract and finite categories of the
  • understanding. But this infinite of the understanding, this pure
  • essence, is still finite: it has excluded all the variety of particular
  • things, which thus limit and deny it. Instead of winning a concrete,
  • this metaphysic stuck fast on an abstract, identity. Its good point was
  • the perception that thought alone constitutes the essence of all that
  • is. It derived its materials from earlier philosophers, particularly
  • the Schoolmen. In speculative philosophy the understanding undoubtedly
  • forms a stage, but not a stage at which we should keep for ever
  • standing. Plato is no metaphysician of this imperfect type, still less
  • Aristotle, although the contrary is generally believed.
  • CHAPTER IV.
  • SECOND ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY.
  • I. _Empiricism._
  • 37.] Under these circumstances a double want began to be felt. Partly
  • it was the need of a concrete subject-matter, as a counterpoise to the
  • abstract theories of the understanding, which is unable to advance
  • unaided from its generalities to specialisation and determination.
  • Partly, too, it was the demand for something fixed and secure, so as
  • to exclude the possibility of proving anything and everything in the
  • sphere, and according to the method, of the finite formulae of thought.
  • Such was the genesis of Empirical philosophy, which abandons the search
  • for truth in thought itself, and goes to fetch it from Experience, the
  • outward and the inward present.
  • The rise of Empiricism is due to the need thus stated of concrete
  • contents, and a firm footing--needs which the abstract metaphysic of
  • the understanding failed to satisfy. Now by concreteness of contents
  • it is meant that we must know the objects of consciousness as
  • intrinsically determinate and as the unity of distinct characteristics.
  • But, as we have already seen, this is by no means the case with the
  • metaphysic of understanding, if it conform to its principle. With the
  • mere understanding, thinking is limited to the form of an abstract
  • universal, and can never advance to the particularisation of this
  • universal. Thus we find the metaphysicians engaged in an attempt to
  • elicit by the instrumentality of thought, what was the essence or
  • fundamental attribute of the Soul The Soul, they said, is simple.
  • The simplicity thus ascribed to the Soul meant a mere and utter
  • simplicity, from which difference is excluded: difference, or in other
  • words composition, being made the fundamental attribute of body, or
  • of matter in general. Clearly, in simplicity of this narrow type we
  • have a very shallow category, quite incapable of embracing the wealth
  • of the soul or of the mind. When it thus appeared that abstract
  • metaphysical thinking was inadequate, it was felt that resource must be
  • had to empirical psychology. The same happened in the case of Rational
  • Physics. The current phrases there were, for instance, that space is
  • infinite, that Nature makes no leap, &c. Evidently this phraseology was
  • wholly unsatisfactory in presence of the plenitude and life of nature.
  • 38.] To some extent this source from which Empiricism draws is common
  • to it with metaphysic. It is in our materialised conceptions, _i.e._
  • in facts which emanate, in the first instance, from experience,
  • that metaphysic also finds the guarantee for the correctness of its
  • definitions (including both its initial assumptions and its more
  • detailed body of doctrine). But, on the other hand, it must be noted
  • that the single sensation is not the same thing as experience, and
  • that the Empirical School elevates the facts included under sensation,
  • feeling, and perception into the form of general ideas, propositions or
  • laws. This, however, it does with the reservation that these general
  • principles (such as force), are to have no further import or validity
  • of their own beyond that taken from the sense-impression, and that
  • no connexion shall be deemed legitimate except what can be shown to
  • exist in phenomena. And on the subjective side Empirical cognition has
  • its stable footing in the fact that in a sensation consciousness is
  • directly present and certain of itself.
  • In Empiricism lies the great principle that whatever is true must
  • be in the actual world and present to sensation. This principle
  • contradicts that 'ought to be' on the strength of which 'reflection'
  • is vain enough to treat the actual present with scorn and to point to
  • a scene beyond--a scene which is assumed to have place and being only
  • in the understanding of those who talk of it. No less than Empiricism,
  • philosophy (§ 7) recognises only what is, and has nothing to do with
  • what merely ought to be and what is thus confessed not to exist. On the
  • subjective side, too, it is right to notice the valuable principle of
  • freedom involved in Empiricism. For the main lesson of Empiricism is
  • that man must see for himself and feel that he is present in every fact
  • of knowledge which he has to accept.
  • When it is carried out to its legitimate consequences,
  • Empiricism--being in its facts limited to the finite sphere--denies the
  • super-sensible in general, or at least any knowledge of it which would
  • define its nature; it leaves thought no powers except abstraction and
  • formal universality and identity. But there is a fundamental delusion
  • in all scientific empiricism. It employs the metaphysical categories of
  • matter, force, those of one, many, generality, infinity, &c.; following
  • the clue given by these categories it proceeds to draw conclusions, and
  • in so doing pre-supposes and applies the syllogistic form. And all the
  • while it is unaware that it contains metaphysics--in wielding which, it
  • makes use of those categories and their combinations in a style utterly
  • thoughtless and uncritical.
  • * * * * *
  • From Empiricism came the cry: 'Stop roaming in empty abstractions, keep
  • your eyes open, lay hold on man and nature as they are here before
  • you, enjoy the present moment.' Nobody can deny that there is a good
  • deal of truth in these words. The every-day world, what is here and
  • now, was a good exchange for the futile other-world--for the mirages
  • and the chimeras of the abstract understanding. And thus was acquired
  • an infinite principle,--that solid footing so much missed in the old
  • metaphysic. Finite principles are the most that the understanding
  • can pick out--and these being essentially unstable and tottering,
  • the structure they supported must collapse with a crash. Always the
  • instinct of reason was to find an infinite principle. As yet, the
  • time had not come for finding it in thought. Hence, this instinct
  • seized upon the present, the Here, the This,--where doubtless there is
  • implicit infinite form, but not in the genuine existence of that form.
  • The external world is the truth, if it could but know it: for the truth
  • is actual and must exist. The infinite principle, the self-centred
  • truth, therefore, is in the world for reason to discover: though it
  • exists in an individual and sensible shape, and not in its truth.
  • Besides, this school makes sense-perception the form in which fact
  • is to be apprehended: and in this consists the defect of Empiricism.
  • Sense-perception as such is always individual, always transient: not
  • indeed that the process of knowledge stops short at sensation: on the
  • contrary, it proceeds to find out the universal and permanent element
  • in the individual apprehended by sense. This is the process leading
  • from simple perception to experience.
  • In order to form experiences, Empiricism makes especial use of the
  • form of Analysis. In the impression of sense we have a concrete of
  • many elements, the several attributes of which we are expected to
  • peel off one by one, like the coats of an onion. In thus dismembering
  • the thing, it is understood that we disintegrate and take to pieces
  • these attributes which have coalesced, and add nothing but our own
  • act of disintegration. Yet analysis is the process from the immediacy
  • of sensation to thought: those attributes, which the object analysed
  • contains in union, acquire the form of universality by being separated.
  • Empiricism therefore labours under a delusion, if it supposes that,
  • while analysing the objects, it leaves them as they were: it really
  • transforms the concrete into an abstract. And as a consequence of this
  • change the living thing is killed: life can exist only in the concrete
  • and one. Not that we can do without this division, if it be our
  • intention to comprehend. Mind itself is an inherent division. The error
  • lies in forgetting that this is only one-half of the process, and that
  • the main point is the re-union of what has been parted. And it is where
  • analysis never gets beyond the stage of partition that the words of the
  • poet are true:
  • _'Encheiresin Naturae_ nennt's die Chemie,
  • Spottet ihrer Selbst, und weiss nicht, wie:
  • Hat die Teile in Ihrer Hand
  • Fehlt leider nur das geistige Band.'
  • Analysis starts from the concrete; and the possession of this material
  • gives it a considerable advantage over the abstract thinking of the
  • old metaphysics. It establishes the differences in things: and this is
  • very important: but these very differences are nothing after all but
  • abstract attributes, _e.g._ thoughts. These thoughts, it is assumed,
  • contain the real essence of the objects; and thus once more we see the
  • axiom of bygone metaphysics reappear, that the truth of things lies in
  • thought.
  • Let us next compare the empirical theory with that of metaphysics in
  • the matter of their respective contents. We find the latter, as already
  • stated, taking for its theme the universal objects of the reason, viz.
  • God, the Soul, and the World: and these themes, accepted from popular
  • conception, it was the problem of philosophy to reduce into the form
  • of thoughts. Another specimen of the same method was the Scholastic
  • philosophy, the theme pre-supposed by which was formed by the dogmas
  • of the Christian Church: and it aimed at fixing their meaning and
  • giving them a systematic arrangement through thought.--The facts on
  • which Empiricism is based are of entirely different kind. They are
  • the sensible facts of nature and the facts of the finite mind. In
  • other words, Empiricism deals with a finite material--and the old
  • metaphysicians had an infinite,--though, let us add, they made this
  • infinite content finite by the finite form of the understanding. The
  • same finitude of form reappears in Empiricism--but here the facts are
  • finite also. To this exigent, then, both modes of philosophising have
  • the same method; both proceed from data or assumptions, which they
  • accept as ultimate. Generally speaking, Empiricism finds the truth in
  • the outward world; and even if it allow a super-sensible world, it
  • holds knowledge of that world to be impossible, and would restrict us
  • to the province of sense-perception. This doctrine when systematically
  • carried out produces what has been latterly termed Materialism.
  • Materialism of this stamp looks upon matter, _quâ_ matter, as the
  • genuine objective world. But with matter we are at once introduced
  • to an abstraction, which as such cannot be perceived: and it may be
  • maintained that there is no matter, because, as it exists, it is always
  • something definite and concrete. Yet the abstraction we term matter is
  • supposed to lie at the basis of the whole world of sense, and expresses
  • the sense-world in its simplest terms as out-and-out individualisation,
  • and hence a congeries of points in mutual exclusion. So long then as
  • this sensible sphere is and continues to be for Empiricism a mere
  • datum, we have a doctrine of bondage: for we become free, when we
  • are confronted by no absolutely alien world, but depend upon a fact
  • which we ourselves are. Consistently with the empirical point of view,
  • besides, reason and unreason can only be subjective: in other words,
  • we must take what is given just as it is, and we have no right to ask
  • whether and to what extent it is rational in its own nature.
  • 39.] Touching this principle it has been justly observed that in
  • what we call Experience, as distinct from mere single perception of
  • single facts, there are two elements. The one is the matter, infinite
  • in its multiplicity, and as it stands a mere set of singulars: the
  • other is the form, the characteristics of universality and necessity.
  • Mere experience no doubt offers many, perhaps innumerable cases of
  • similar perceptions: but, after all, no multitude, however great,
  • can be the same thing as universality. Similarly, mere experience
  • affords perceptions of changes succeeding each other and of objects in
  • juxtaposition; but it presents no necessary connexion. If perception,
  • therefore, is to maintain its claim to be the sole basis of what
  • men hold for truth, universality and necessity appear something
  • illegitimate: they become an accident of our minds, a mere custom, the
  • content of which might be otherwise constituted than it is.
  • It is an important corollary of this theory, that on this empirical
  • mode of treatment legal and ethical principles and laws, as well as the
  • truths of religion, are exhibited as the work of chance, and stripped
  • of their objective character and inner truth.
  • The scepticism of Hume, to which this conclusion was chiefly due,
  • should be clearly marked off from Greek scepticism. Hume assumes the
  • truth of the empirical element, feeling and sensation, and proceeds to
  • challenge universal principles and laws, because they have no warranty
  • from sense-perception. So far was ancient scepticism from making
  • feeling and sensation the canon of truth, that it turned against the
  • deliverances of sense first of all. (On Modern Scepticism as compared
  • with Ancient, see Schelling and Hegel's Critical Journal of Philosophy:
  • 1802, vol. I. i.)
  • II. _The Critical Philosophy._
  • 40.] In common with Empiricism the Critical Philosophy assumes that
  • experience affords the one sole foundation for cognitions; which
  • however it does not allow to rank as truths, but only as knowledge of
  • phenomena.
  • The Critical theory starts originally from the distinction of elements
  • presented in the analysis of experience, viz. the matter of sense, and
  • its universal relations. Taking into account Hume's criticism on this
  • distinction as given in the preceding section, viz. that sensation
  • does not explicitly apprehend more than an individual or more than a
  • mere event, it insists at the same time on the _fact_ that universality
  • and necessity are seen to perform a function equally essential in
  • constituting what is called experience. This element, not being derived
  • from the empirical facts as such, must belong to the spontaneity of
  • thought; in other words, it is _a priori._ The Categories or Notions
  • of the Understanding constitute the _objectivity_ of experiential
  • cognitions. In every case they involve a connective reference, and
  • hence through their means are formed synthetic judgments _a priori,_
  • that is, primary and underivative connexions of opposites.
  • Even Hume's scepticism does not deny that the characteristics of
  • universality and necessity are found in cognition. And even in Kant
  • this fact remains a presupposition after all; it may be said, to use
  • the ordinary phraseology of the sciences, that Kant did no more than
  • offer another _explanation_ of the fact.
  • 41.] The Critical Philosophy proceeds to test the value of the
  • categories employed in metaphysic, as well as in other sciences
  • and in ordinary conception. This scrutiny however is not directed
  • to the content of these categories, nor does it inquire into the
  • exact relation they bear to one another: but simply considers them
  • as affected by the contrast between subjective and objective. The
  • contrast, as we are to understand it here, bears upon the distinction
  • (see preceding §) of the two elements in experience. The name of
  • objectivity is here given to the element of universality and necessity,
  • _i.e._ to the categories themselves, or what is called the _a priori_
  • constituent. The Critical Philosophy however widened the contrast in
  • such away, that the subjectivity comes to embrace the _ensemble_ of
  • experience, including both of the aforesaid elements; and nothing
  • remains on the other side but the 'thing-in-itself.'
  • The special forms of the _a priori_ element, in other words, of
  • thought, which in spite of its objectivity is looked upon as a purely
  • subjective act, present themselves as follows in a systematic order
  • which, it may be remarked, is solely based upon psychological and
  • historical grounds.
  • * * * * *
  • (1) A very important step was undoubtedly made, when the terms of the
  • old metaphysic were subjected to scrutiny. The plain thinker pursued
  • his unsuspecting way in those categories which had offered themselves
  • naturally. It never occurred to him to ask to what extent these
  • categories had a value and authority of their own. If, as has been
  • said, it is characteristic of free thought to allow no assumptions to
  • pass unquestioned, the old metaphysicians were not free thinkers. They
  • accepted their categories as they were, without further trouble, as an
  • _a priori_ datum, not yet tested by reflection. The Critical philosophy
  • reversed this. Kant undertook to examine how far the forms of thought
  • were capable of leading to the knowledge of truth. In particular he
  • demanded a criticism of the faculty of cognition as preliminary to
  • its exercise. That is a fair demand, if it mean that even the forms
  • of thought must be made an object of investigation. Unfortunately
  • there soon creeps in the misconception of already knowing before _you_
  • know,--the error of refusing to enter the water until you have learnt
  • to swim. True, indeed, the forms of thought should be subjected to a
  • scrutiny before they are used: yet what is this scrutiny but _ipso
  • facto_ a cognition? So that what we want is to combine in our process
  • of inquiry the action of the forms of thought with a criticism of
  • them. The forms of thought must be studied in their essential nature
  • and complete development: they are at once the object of research and
  • the action of that object. Hence they examine themselves: in their own
  • action they must determine their limits, and point out their defects.
  • This is that action of thought, which will hereafter be specially
  • considered under the name of Dialectic, and regarding which we need
  • only at the outset observe that, instead of being brought to bear upon
  • the categories from without, it is immanent in their own action.
  • We may therefore state the first point in Kant's philosophy as follows:
  • Thought must itself investigate its own capacity of knowledge. People
  • in the present day have got over Kant and his philosophy: everybody
  • wants to get further. But there are two ways of going further--a
  • back-, ward and a forward. The light of criticism soon shows that many
  • of our modern essays in philosophy are mere repetitions of the old
  • metaphysical method, an endless and uncritical thinking in a groove
  • determined by the natural bent of each man's mind.
  • (2) Kant's examination of the categories suffers from the grave defect
  • of viewing them, not absolutely and for their own sake, but in order to
  • see whether they are _subjective_ or _objective._ In the language of
  • common life we mean by objective what exists outside of us and reaches
  • us from without by means of sensation. What Kant did, was to deny that
  • the categories, such as cause and effect, were, in this sense of the
  • word, objective, or given in sensation, and to maintain on the contrary
  • that they belonged to our own thought itself, to the spontaneity of
  • thought. To that extent therefore, they were subjective. And yet in
  • spite of this, Kant gives the name objective to what is thought, to the
  • universal and necessary, while he describes as subjective whatever is
  • merely felt. This arrangement apparently reverses the first-mentioned
  • use of the word, and has caused Kant to be charged with confusing
  • language. But the charge is unfair if we more narrowly consider the
  • facts of the case. The vulgar believe that the objects of perception
  • which confront them, such as an individual animal, or a single star,
  • are independent and permanent existences, compared with which, thoughts
  • are unsubstantial and dependent on something else. In fact however
  • the perceptions of sense are the properly dependent and secondary
  • feature, while the thoughts are really independent and primary. This
  • being so, Kant gave the title objective to the intellectual factor, to
  • the universal and necessary: and he was quite justified in so doing.
  • Our sensations on the other hand are subjective; for sensations lack
  • stability in their own nature, and are no less fleeting and evanescent
  • than thought is permanent and self-subsisting. At the present day, the
  • special line of distinction established by Kant between the subjective
  • and objective is adopted by the phraseology of the educated world. Thus
  • the criticism of a work of art ought, it is said, to be not subjective,
  • but objective; in other words, instead of springing from the particular
  • and accidental feeling or temper of the moment, it should keep its eye
  • on those general points of view which the laws of art establish. In
  • the same acceptation we can distinguish in any scientific pursuit the
  • objective and the subjective interest of the investigation.
  • But after all, objectivity of thought, in Kant's sense, is again to
  • a certain extent subjective. Thoughts, according to Kant, although
  • universal and necessary categories, are _only our_ thoughts--separated
  • by an impassable gulf from the thing, as it exists apart from our
  • knowledge. But the true, objectivity of thinking means that the
  • thoughts, far from being merely ours, must at the same time be the real
  • essence of the things, and of whatever is an object to us.
  • Objective and subjective are convenient expressions in current use,
  • the employment of which may easily lead to confusion. Up to this
  • point, the discussion has shown three meanings of objectivity. First,
  • it means what has external existence, in distinction from which the
  • subjective is what is only supposed, dreamed, &c. Secondly, it has
  • the meaning, attached to it by Kant, of the universal and necessary,
  • as distinguished from the particular, subjective and occasional
  • element which belongs to our sensations. Thirdly, as has been just
  • explained, it means the thought-apprehended essence of the existing
  • thing, in contradistinction from what is merely _our_ thought, and what
  • consequently is still separated from the thing itself, as it exists in
  • independent essence.
  • 42.] (a) The Theoretical Faculty.--Cognition _quâ_ cognition.
  • The specific ground of the categories is declared by the Critical
  • system to lie in the primary identity of the 'I' in thought,--what
  • Kant calls the 'transcendental unity of self-consciousness.'
  • The impressions from feeling and perception are, if we look to
  • their contents, a multiplicity or miscellany of elements: and the
  • multiplicity is equally conspicuous in their form. For sense is marked
  • by a mutual exclusion of members; and that under two aspects, namely
  • space and time, which, being the forms, that is to say, the universal
  • type of perception, are themselves _a priori._ This congeries,
  • afforded by sensation and perception, must however be reduced to an
  • identity or primary synthesis. To accomplish this the 'I' brings it in
  • relation to itself and unites it there in _one_ consciousness which
  • Kant calls 'pure apperception.' The specific modes in which the Ego
  • refers to itself the multiplicity of sense are the pure concepts of the
  • understanding, the Categories.
  • Kant, it is well known, did not put himself to much trouble in
  • discovering the categories. 'I,' the unity of self-consciousness,
  • being quite abstract and completely indeterminate, the question
  • arises, how are we to get at the specialised forms of the 'I,' the
  • categories? Fortunately, the common logic offers to our hand an
  • empirical classification of the kinds of _judgment._ Now, to judge
  • is the same as to _think_ of a determinate object. Hence the various
  • modes of judgment, as enumerated to our hand, provide us with the
  • several categories of thought. To the philosophy of Fichte belongs
  • the great merit of having called attention to the need of exhibiting
  • the _necessity_ of these categories and giving a genuine _deduction_
  • of them. Fichte ought to have produced at least one effect on the
  • method of logic. One might have expected that the general laws of
  • thought, the usual stock-in-trade of logicians, or the classification
  • of notions, judgments, and syllogisms, would be no longer taken merely
  • from observation and so only empirically treated, but be deduced from
  • thought itself. If thought is to be capable of proving anything at all,
  • if logic must insist upon the necessity of proofs, and if it proposes
  • to teach the theory of demonstration, its first care should be to give
  • a reason for its own subject-matter, and to see that it is necessary.
  • (i) Kant therefore holds that the categories have their source in the
  • 'Ego,' and that the 'Ego' consequently supplies the characteristics
  • of universality and necessity. If we observe what we have before us
  • primarily, we may describe it as a congeries or diversity: and in the
  • categories we find the simple points or units, to which this congeries
  • is made to converge. The world of sense is a scene of mutual exclusion:
  • its being is outside itself. That is the fundamental feature of the
  • sensible. 'Now' has no meaning except in reference to a before and a
  • hereafter. Red, in the same way, only subsists by being opposed to
  • yellow and blue. Now this other thing is outside the sensible; which
  • latter is, only in so far as it is not the other, and only in so far
  • as that other is. But thought, or the 'Ego,' occupies a position the
  • very reverse of the sensible, with its mutual exclusions, and its
  • being outside itself. The 'I' is the primary identity--at one with
  • itself and all at home in itself. The word 'I' expresses the mere act
  • of bringing-to-bear-upon-self: and whatever is placed in this unit or
  • focus, is affected _by_ it and transformed into it. The 'I' is as it
  • were the crucible and the fire which consumes the loose plurality of
  • sense and reduces it to unity. This is the process which Kant calls
  • pure apperception in distinction from the common apperception, to
  • which the plurality it receives is a plurality still; whereas pure
  • apperception is rather an act by which the 'I' makes the materials
  • 'mine.'
  • This view has at least the merit of giving a correct expression to the
  • nature of all consciousness. The tendency of all man's endeavours is to
  • understand the world, to appropriate and subdue it to himself: and to
  • this end the positive reality of the world must be as it were crushed
  • and pounded, in other words, idealised. At the same time we must note
  • that it is not the mere act of _our_ personal self-consciousness, which
  • introduces an absolute unity into the variety of sense. Rather, this
  • identity is itself the absolute. The absolute is, as it were, so kind
  • as to leave individual things to their own enjoyment, and it again
  • drives them back to the absolute unity.
  • (2) Expressions like 'transcendental unity of self-consciousness' have
  • an ugly look about them, and suggest a monster in the background:
  • but their meaning is not so abstruse as it looks. Kant's meaning of
  • transcendental may be gathered by the way he distinguishes it from
  • transcendent. The _transcendent_ may be said to be what steps out
  • beyond the categories of the understanding: a sense in which the term
  • is first employed in mathematics. Thus in geometry you are told to
  • conceive the circumference of a circle as formed of an infinite number
  • of infinitely small straight lines. In other words, characteristics
  • which the understanding holds to be totally different, the straight
  • line and the curve, are expressly invested with identity. Another
  • transcendent of the same kind is the self-consciousness which is
  • identical with itself and infinite in itself, as distinguished from
  • the ordinary consciousness which derives its form and tone from finite
  • materials. That unity of self-consciousness, however, Kant called
  • _transcendental_ only; and he meant thereby that the unity was only in
  • our minds and did not attach to the objects apart from our knowledge of
  • them.
  • (3) To regard the categories as subjective only, _i.e._ as a part
  • of ourselves, must seem very odd to the natural mind; and no doubt
  • there is something queer about it. It is quite true however that the
  • categories are not contained in the sensation as it is given us. When,
  • for instance, we look at a piece of sugar, we find it is hard, white,
  • sweet, &c. All these properties we say are united in one object. Now
  • it is this unity that is not found in the sensation. The same thing
  • happens if we conceive two events to stand in the relation of cause
  • and effect. The senses only inform us of the two several occurrences
  • which follow each other in time. But that the one is cause, the other
  • effect,--in other words, the causal nexus between the two,--is not
  • perceived by sense; it is only evident to thought. Still, though the
  • categories, such as unity, or cause and effect, are strictly the
  • property of thought, it by no means follows that they must be ours
  • merely and not also characteristics of the objects. Kant however
  • confines them to the subject-mind, and his philosophy may be styled
  • subjective idealism: for he holds that both the form and the matter of
  • knowledge are supplied by the Ego--or knowing subject--the form by our
  • intellectual, the matter by our sentient ego.
  • So far as regards the content of this subjective idealism, not a word
  • need be wasted. It might perhaps at first sight be imagined, that
  • objects would lose their reality when their unity was transferred to
  • the subject. But neither we nor the objects would have anything to gain
  • by the mere fact that they possessed being. The main point is not,
  • that they are, but what they are, and whether or not their content
  • is true. It does no good to the things to say merely that they have
  • being. What has being, will also cease to be when time creeps over it.
  • It might also be alleged that subjective idealism tended to promote
  • self-conceit. But surely if a man's world be the sum of his sensible
  • perceptions, he has no reason to be vain of such a world. Laying aside
  • therefore as unimportant this distinction between subjective and
  • objective, we are chiefly interested in knowing what a thing is: _i.e._
  • its content, which is no more objective than it is subjective. If mere
  • existence be enough to make objectivity, even a crime is objective: but
  • it is an existence which is nullity at the core, as is definitely made
  • apparent when the day of punishment comes.
  • 43.] The Categories may be viewed in two aspects. On the one hand it
  • is by their instrumentality that the mere perception of sense rises to
  • objectivity and experience. On the other hand these notions are unities
  • in our consciousness merely: they are consequently conditioned by the
  • material given to them, and having nothing of their own they can be
  • applied to use only within the range of experience. But the other
  • constituent of experience, the impressions of feeling and perception,
  • is not one whit less subjective than the categories.
  • To assert that the categories taken by themselves are empty can
  • scarcely be right, seeing that they have a content, at all events, in
  • the special stamp and significance which they possess. Of course the
  • content of the categories is not perceptible to the senses, nor is it
  • in time and space: but that is rather a merit than a defect. A glimpse
  • of this meaning of _content_ may be observed to affect our ordinary
  • thinking. _A_ book or a speech for example is said to have a great
  • deal in it, to be full of content, in proportion to the greater number
  • of thoughts and general results to be found in it: whilst, on the
  • contrary, we should never say that any book, _e.g._ novel, had much in
  • it, because it included a great number of single incidents, situations,
  • and the like. Even the popular voice thus recognises that something
  • more than the facts of sense is needed to make a work pregnant with
  • matter. And what is this additional desideratum but thoughts, or in the
  • first instance the categories? And yet it is not altogether wrong, it
  • should be added, to call the categories of themselves empty, if it be
  • meant that they and the logical Idea, of which they are the members, do
  • not constitute the whole of philosophy, but necessarily lead onwards in
  • due progress to the real departments of Nature and Mind. Only let the
  • progress not be misunderstood. The logical Ideal does not thereby come
  • into possession of a content originally foreign to it: but by its own
  • native action is specialised and developed to Nature and Mind.
  • 44.] It follows that the categories are no fit terms to express
  • the Absolute--the Absolute not being given in perception;--and
  • Understanding, or knowledge by means of the categories, is consequently
  • incapable of knowing the Things-in-themselves.
  • The Thing-in-itself (and under 'thing' is embraced even Mind and God)
  • expresses the object when we leave out of sight all that consciousness
  • makes of it, all its emotional aspects, and all specific thoughts
  • of it. It is easy to see what is left,--utter abstraction, total
  • emptiness, only described still as an 'other-world'--the negative of
  • every image, feeling, and definite thought. Nor does it require much
  • penetration to see that this _caput mortuum_ is still only a product
  • of thought, such as accrues when thought is carried on to abstraction
  • unalloyed: that it is the work of the empty 'Ego,' which makes an
  • object out of this empty self-identity of its own. The _negative_
  • characteristic which this abstract identity receives as an _object,_ is
  • also enumerated among the categories of Kant, and is no less familiar
  • than the empty identity aforesaid. Hence one can only read with
  • surprise the perpetual remark that we do not know the Thing-in-itself.
  • On the contrary there is nothing we can know so easily.
  • 45.] It is Reason, the faculty of the Unconditioned, which discovers
  • the conditioned nature of the knowledge comprised in experience. What
  • is thus called the object of Reason, the Infinite or Unconditioned,
  • is nothing but self-sameness, or the primary identity of the 'Ego'
  • in thought (mentioned in § 42). Reason itself is the name given to
  • the abstract 'Ego' or thought, which makes this pure identity its aim
  • or object (cf. note to the preceding §). Now this identity, having
  • no definite attribute at all, can receive no illumination from the
  • truths of experience, for the reason that these refer always to
  • definite facts. Such is the sort of Unconditioned that is supposed to
  • be the absolute truth of Reason,--what is termed the _Idea;_ whilst
  • the cognitions of experience are reduced to the level of untruth and
  • declared to be appearances.
  • Kant was the first definitely to signalise the distinction between
  • Reason and Understanding. The object of the former, as he applied the
  • term, was the infinite and unconditioned, of the latter the finite
  • and conditioned. Kant did valuable service when he enforced the finite
  • character of the cognitions of the understanding founded merely upon
  • experience, and stamped their contents with the name of appearance.
  • But his mistake was to stop at the purely negative point of view, and
  • to limit the unconditionality of Reason to an abstract self-sameness
  • without any shade of distinction. It degrades Reason to a finite and
  • conditioned thing, to identify it with a mere stepping beyond the
  • finite and conditioned range of understanding. The real infinite,
  • far from being a mere transcendence of the finite, always involves
  • the absorption of the finite into its own fuller nature. In the same
  • way Kant restored the Idea to its proper dignity: vindicating it for
  • Reason, as a thing distinct from abstract analytic determinations or
  • from the merely sensible conceptions which usually appropriate to
  • themselves the name of ideas. But as respects the Idea also, he never
  • got beyond its negative aspect, as what ought to be but is not.
  • The view that the objects of immediate consciousness, which constitute
  • the body of experience, are mere appearances (phenomena), was another
  • important result of the Kantian philosophy. Common Sense, that mixture
  • of sense and understanding, believes the objects of which it has
  • knowledge to be severally independent and self-supporting; and when
  • it becomes evident that they tend towards and limit one another, the
  • interdependence of one upon another is reckoned something foreign to
  • them and to their true nature. The very opposite is the truth. The
  • things immediately known are mere appearances--in other words, the
  • ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else.
  • But then comes the important step of defining what this something
  • else is. According to Kant, the things that we know about are _to us_
  • appearances only, and we can never know their essential nature, which
  • belongs to another world we cannot approach. Plain minds have not
  • unreasonably taken exception to this subjective idealism, with its
  • reduction of the facts of consciousness to a purely personal world,
  • created by ourselves alone. For the true statement of the case is
  • rather as follows. The things of which we have direct consciousness
  • are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their own nature; and the
  • true and proper case of these things, finite as they are, is to have
  • their existence founded not in themselves but in the universal divine
  • Idea. This view of things, it is true, is as idealist as Kant's;
  • but in contradistinction to the subjective idealism of the Critical
  • philosophy should be termed absolute idealism. Absolute idealism,
  • however, though it is far in advance of vulgar realism, is by no means
  • merely restricted to philosophy. It lies at the root of all religion;
  • for religion too believes the actual world we see, the sum total of
  • existence, to be created and governed by God.
  • 46.] But it is not enough simply to indicate the existence of the
  • object of Reason. Curiosity impels us to seek for knowledge of this
  • identity, this empty thing-in-itself. Now _knowledge_ means such
  • an acquaintance with the object as apprehends its distinct and
  • special subject-matter. But such subject-matter involves a complex
  • inter-connexion in the object itself, and supplies a ground of
  • connexion with many other objects. In the present case, to express the
  • nature of the features of the Infinite or Thing-in-itself, Reason would
  • have nothing except the categories: and in any endeavour so to employ
  • them Reason becomes over-soaring or 'transcendent.'
  • Here begins the second stage of the Criticism of Reason--which, as
  • an independent piece of work, is more valuable than the first. The
  • first part, as has been explained above, teaches that the categories
  • originate in the unity of self-consciousness; that any knowledge which
  • is gained by their means has nothing objective in it, and that the
  • very objectivity claimed for them is only subjective. So far as this
  • goes, the Kantian Criticism presents that 'common' type of idealism
  • known as Subjective Idealism. It asks no questions about the meaning
  • or scope of the categories, but simply considers the abstract form of
  • subjectivity and objectivity, and that even in such a partial way, that
  • the former aspect, that of subjectivity, is retained as a final and
  • purely affirmative term of thought. In the second part, however, when
  • Kant examines the _application,_ as it is called, which Reason makes
  • of the categories in order to know its objects, the content of the
  • categories, at least in some points of view, comes in for discussion:
  • or, at any rate, an opportunity presented itself for a discussion of
  • the question. It is worth while to see what decision Kant arrives at on
  • the subject of metaphysic, as this application of the categories to the
  • unconditioned is called. His method of procedure we shall here briefly
  • state and criticise.
  • 47.] (a) The first of the unconditioned entities which Kant examines
  • is the Soul (see above, § 34). 'In my consciousness,' he says, 'I
  • always find that I (1) am the determining subject: (2) am singular, or
  • abstractly simple: (3) am identical, or one and the same, in all the
  • variety of what I am conscious of: (4) distinguish myself as thinking
  • from all the things outside me.'
  • Now the method of the old metaphysic, as Kant correctly states it,
  • consisted in substituting for these statements of experience the
  • corresponding categories or metaphysical terms. Thus arise these four
  • new propositions: _(a)_ the Soul is a substance: _(b)_ it is a simple
  • substance: _(c)_ it is numerically identical at the various periods of
  • existence: _(d)_ it stands in relation to space.
  • Kant discusses this translation, and draws attention to the Paralogism
  • or mistake of confounding one kind of truth with another. He points out
  • that empirical attributes have here been replaced by categories: and
  • shows that we are not entitled to argue from the former to the latter,
  • or to put the latter in place of the former.
  • This criticism obviously but repeats the observation of Hume
  • (§ 39) that the categories as a whole,--ideas of universality
  • and necessity,--are entirely absent from sensation; and that the
  • empirical fact both in form and contents differs from its intellectual
  • formulation.
  • If the purely empirical fact were held to constitute the credentials
  • of the thought, then no doubt it would be indispensable to be able
  • precisely to identify the 'idea' in the 'impression.'
  • And in order to make out, in his criticism of the metaphysical
  • psychology, that the soul cannot be described as substantial, simple,
  • self-same, and as maintaining its independence in intercourse with
  • the material world, Kant argues from the single ground, that the
  • several attributes of the soul, which consciousness lets us feel in
  • _experience,_ are not exactly the same attributes as result from the
  • action of _thought_ thereon. But we have seen above, that according
  • to Kant all knowledge, even experience, consists in thinking our
  • impressions--in other words, in transforming into intellectual
  • categories the attributes primarily belonging to sensation.
  • Unquestionably one good result of the Kantian criticism was that
  • it emancipated mental philosophy from the 'soul-thing,' from the
  • categories, and, consequently, from questions about the simplicity,
  • complexity, materiality, &c. of the soul. But even for the common sense
  • of ordinary men, the true point of view, from which the inadmissibility
  • of these forms best appears, will be, not that they are thoughts, but
  • that thoughts of such a stamp neither can nor do contain truth.
  • If thought and phenomenon do not perfectly correspond to one another,
  • we are free at least to choose which of the two shall be held the
  • defaulter. The Kantian idealism, where it touches on the world of
  • Reason, throws the blame on the thoughts; saying that the thoughts are
  • defective, as not being exactly fitted to the sensations and to a mode
  • of mind wholly restricted within the range of sensation, in which as
  • such there are no traces of the presence of these thoughts. But as to
  • the actual content of the thought, no question is raised.
  • Paralogisms are a species of unsound syllogism, the especial vice of
  • which consists in employing one and the same word in the two premisses
  • with a different meaning. According to Kant the method adopted by the
  • rational psychology of the old metaphysicians, when they assumed that
  • the qualities of the phenomenal soul, as given in experience, formed
  • part of its own real essence, was based upon such a Paralogism. Nor
  • can it be denied that predicates like simplicity, permanence, &c, are
  • inapplicable to the soul. But their unfitness is not due to the ground
  • assigned by Kant, that Reason, by applying them, would exceed its
  • appointed bounds. The true ground is that this style of abstract terms
  • is not good enough for the soul, which is very; much more than a mere
  • simple or unchangeable sort of thing. And thus, for example, while the
  • soul may be admitted to be simple self-sameness, it is at the same time
  • active and institutes distinctions in its own nature. But whatever
  • is merely or abstractly simple is as such also a mere dead thing. By
  • his polemic against the metaphysic of the past Kant discarded those
  • predicates from the soul or mind. He did well; but when he came to
  • state his reasons, his failure is apparent.
  • 48.] (ß) The second unconditioned object is the World (§ 35). In the
  • attempt which reason makes to comprehend the unconditioned nature of
  • the World, it falls into what are called Antinomies. In other words
  • it maintains two opposite propositions about the same object, and in
  • such a way that each of them has to be maintained with equal necessity.
  • From this it follows that the body of cosmical fact, the specific
  • statements descriptive of which run into contradiction, cannot be a
  • self-subsistent reality, but only an appearance. The explanation
  • offered by Kant alleges that the contradiction does not affect the
  • object in its own proper essence, but attaches only to the Reason which
  • seeks to comprehend it.
  • In this way the suggestion was broached that the contradiction is
  • occasioned by the subject-matter itself, or by the intrinsic quality
  • of the categories. And to offer the idea that the contradiction
  • introduced into the world of Reason by the categories of Understanding
  • is inevitable and essential, was to make one of the most important
  • steps in the progress of Modern Philosophy. But the more important the
  • issue thus raised the more trivial was the solution. Its only motive
  • was an excess of tenderness for the things of the world. The blemish
  • of contradiction, it seems, could not be allowed to mar the essence of
  • the world: but there could be no objection to attach it to the thinking
  • Reason, to the essence of mind. Probably nobody will feel disposed to
  • deny that the phenomenal world presents contradictions to the observing
  • mind; meaning by 'phenomenal' the world as it presents itself to the
  • senses and understanding, to the subjective mind. But if a comparison
  • is instituted between the essence of the world and the essence of the
  • mind, it does seem strange to hear how calmly and confidently the
  • modest dogma has been advanced by one, and repeated by others, that
  • thought or Reason, and not the World, is the seat of contradiction.
  • It is no escape to turn round and explain that Reason falls into
  • contradiction only by applying the categories. For this application
  • of the categories is maintained to be necessary, and Reason is not
  • supposed to be equipped with any other forms but the categories for
  • the purpose of cognition. But cognition is determining and determinate
  • thinking: so that, if Reason be mere empty indeterminate thinking, it
  • thinks nothing. And if in the end Reason be reduced to mere identity
  • without diversity (see next §), it will in the end also win a happy
  • release from contradiction at the slight sacrifice of all its facts and
  • contents.
  • It may also be noted that his failure to make a more thorough study
  • of Antinomy was one of the reasons why Kant enumerated only _four_
  • Antinomies. These four attracted his notice, because, as may be seen
  • in his discussion of the so-called Paralogisms of Reason, he assumed
  • the list of the categories as a basis of his argument. Employing
  • what has subsequently become a favourite fashion, he simply put the
  • object under a rubric otherwise ready to hand, instead of deducing
  • its characteristics from its notion. Further deficiencies in the
  • treatment of the Antinomies I have pointed out, as occasion offered,
  • in my 'Science of Logic' Here it will be sufficient to say that
  • the Antinomies are not confined to the four special objects taken
  • from Cosmology: they appear in all objects of every kind, in all
  • conceptions, notions and Ideas. To be aware of this and to know objects
  • in this property of theirs, makes a vital part in a philosophical
  • theory. For the property thus indicated is what we shall afterwards
  • describe as the Dialectical influence in logic.
  • * * * * *
  • The principles of the metaphysical philosophy gave rise to the belief
  • that, when cognition lapsed into contradictions, it was a mere
  • accidental aberration, due to some subjective mistake in argument
  • and inference. According to Kant, however, thought has a natural
  • tendency to issue in contradictions or antinomies, whenever it seeks
  • to apprehend the infinite. We have in the latter part of the above
  • paragraph referred to the philosophical importance of the antinomies of
  • reason, and shown how the recognition of their existence helped largely
  • to get rid of the rigid dogmatism of the metaphysic of understanding,
  • and to direct attention to the Dialectical movement of thought. But
  • here too Kant, as we must add, never got beyond the negative result
  • that the thing-in-itself is unknowable, and never penetrated to the
  • discovery of what the antinomies really and positively mean. That true
  • and positive meaning of the antinomies is this: that every actual
  • thing involves a coexistence of opposed, elements. Consequently to
  • know, or, in other words, to comprehend an object is equivalent to
  • being conscious of it as a concrete unity of opposed determinations.
  • The old. metaphysic, as we have already seen, when it studied the
  • objects of which it sought a metaphysical knowledge, went to work by
  • applying categories abstractly and to the exclusion of their opposites.
  • Kant, on the other hand, tried to prove that the statements, issuing
  • through this method, could be met by other statements of contrary
  • import with equal warrant and equal necessity. In the enumeration of
  • these antinomies he narrowed his ground to the cosmology of the old
  • metaphysical system, and in his discussion made out four antinomies, a
  • number which rests upon the list of the categories. The first antinomy
  • is on the question: Whether we are or are not to think the world
  • limited in space and time. In the second antinomy we have a discussion
  • of the dilemma: Matter must be conceived either as endlessly divisible,
  • or as consisting of atoms. The third antinomy bears upon the antithesis
  • of freedom and necessity, to such extent as it is embraced in the
  • question, Whether everything in the world must be supposed subject to
  • the condition of causality, or if we can also assume free beings, in
  • other words, absolute initial points of action, in the world. Finally,
  • the fourth antinomy is the dilemma: Either the world as a whole has a
  • cause or it is uncaused.
  • The method which Kant follows in discussing these antinomies is as
  • follows. He puts the two propositions implied in the dilemma over
  • against each other as thesis and antithesis, and seeks to prove both:
  • that is to say he tries to exhibit them as inevitably issuing from
  • reflection on the question. He particularly protests against the charge
  • of being a special pleader and of grounding his reasoning on illusions.
  • Speaking honestly, however, the arguments which Kant offers for his
  • thesis and antithesis are mere shams of demonstration. The thing to
  • be proved is invariably implied in the assumption he starts from, and
  • the speciousness of his proofs is only due to his prolix and apagogic
  • mode of procedure. Yet it was, and still is, a great achievement for
  • the Critical philosophy, when it exhibited these antinomies: for
  • in this way it gave some expression (at first certainly subjective
  • and unexplained) to the actual unity of those categories which are
  • kept persistently separate by the understanding. The first of the
  • cosmological antinomies, for example, implies a recognition of the
  • doctrine that space and time present a discrete as well as a continuous
  • aspect: whereas the old metaphysic, laying exclusive emphasis on the
  • continuity, had been led to treat the world as unlimited in space
  • and time. It is quite correct to say that we can go beyond every
  • _definite_ space and beyond every _definite_ time: but it is no less
  • correct that space and time are real and actual only when they are
  • defined or specialised into 'here' and 'now,'--a specialisation which
  • is involved in the very notion of them. The same observations apply to
  • the rest of the antinomies. Take, for example, the antinomy of freedom
  • and necessity. The main gist of itis that freedom and necessity as
  • understood by abstract thinkers are not independently real, as these
  • thinkers suppose, but merely ideal factors (moments) of the true
  • freedom and the true necessity, and that to abstract and isolate either
  • conception is to make it false.
  • 49.] (y) The third object of the Reason is God (§36): He also must
  • be known and defined in terms of thought. But in comparison with
  • an unalloyed identity, every defining term as such seems to the
  • understanding to be only a limit and a negation: every reality
  • accordingly must be taken as limitless, _i.e._ undefined. Accordingly
  • God, when He is defined to be the sum of all realities, the most real
  • of beings, turns into a _mere abstract._ And the only term under which
  • that most real of real, things can be defined is that of Being--itself
  • the height of abstraction. These are the two elements, abstract
  • identity, on one hand, which is spoken of in this place as the notion;
  • and Being on the other,--which Reason seeks to unify. And their union
  • is the _Ideal_ of Reason.
  • 50.] To carry out this unification two ways or two forms are
  • admissible. Either we may begin with Being and proceed to the
  • _abstraction_ of Thought: or the movement may begin with the
  • abstraction and end in Being.
  • We shall, in the first place, start from Being. But Being, in its
  • natural aspect, presents itself to view as a Being of infinite variety,
  • a World in all its plenitude. And this world may be regarded in two
  • ways: first, as a collection of innumerable unconnected facts; and
  • second, as a collection of innumerable facts in mutual relation,
  • giving evidence of design. The first aspect is emphasised in the
  • Cosmological proof: the latter in the proofs of Natural Theology.
  • Suppose now that this fulness of being passes under the agency of
  • thought. Then it is stripped of its isolation and unconnectedness, and
  • viewed as a universal and absolutely necessary being which determines
  • itself and acts by general purposes or laws. And this necessary and
  • self-determined being, different from the being at the commencement, is
  • God.
  • The main force of Kant's criticism on this process attacks it for being
  • a syllogising, _i.e._ a transition. Perceptions, and that aggregate
  • of perceptions we call the world, exhibit as they stand no traces of
  • that universality which they afterwards receive from the purifying act
  • of thought. The empirical conception of the world therefore gives no
  • warrant for the idea of universality. And so any attempt on the part
  • of thought to ascend from the empirical conception of the world to
  • God is checked by the argument of Hume (as in the paralogisms, § 47),
  • according to which we have no right to think sensations, that is, to
  • elicit universality and necessity from them.
  • Man is essentially a thinker: and therefore sound Common Sense, as well
  • as Philosophy, will not yield up their right of rising to God from
  • and out of the empirical view of the world. The only basis on which
  • this rise is possible is the thinking study of the world, not the bare
  • sensuous, animal, attuition of it. Thought and thought alone has eyes
  • for the essence, substance, universal power, and ultimate design of the
  • world. And what men call the proofs of God's existence are, rightly
  • understood, ways of describing and analysing the native course of the
  • mind, the course of _thought_ thinking the _data_ of the senses. The
  • rise of thought beyond the world of sense, its passage from the finite
  • to the infinite, the leap into the super-sensible which it takes when
  • it snaps asunder the chain of sense, all this transition is thought and
  • nothing but thought. Say there is no such passage, and you say there is
  • to be no thinking. And in sooth, animals make no such transition. They
  • never get further than sensation and the perception of the senses, and
  • in consequence they have no religion.
  • Both on general grounds, and in the particular case, there are two
  • remarks to be made upon the criticism of this exaltation in thought.
  • The first remark deals with the question of form. When the exaltation
  • is exhibited in a syllogistic process, in the shape of what we call
  • _proofs_ of the being of God, these reasonings cannot but start from
  • some sort of theory of the world, which makes it an aggregate either
  • of contingent facts or of final causes and relations involving design.
  • The merely syllogistic thinker may deem this starting-point a solid
  • basis and suppose that it remains throughout in the same empirical
  • light, left at last as it was at the first. In this case, the bearing
  • of the beginning upon the conclusion to which it leads has a purely
  • affirmative aspect, as if we were only reasoning from one thing which
  • _is_ and continues to _be,_ to another thing which in like manner
  • is. But the great error is to restrict our notions of the nature
  • of thought to its form in understanding alone. To think think the
  • phenomenal world rather, means to re-cast its form, and transmute it
  • into a universal. And thus the action-of-thought, has also, _negative_
  • effect upon its basis: and the matter of sensation, when it receives
  • the stamp of universality, at once loses its first and phenomenal
  • shape. By the removal and negation of the shell, the kernel within the
  • sense; v percept is brought to the light (§§ 13 and 23). And it is
  • because they do not, with sufficient prominence, express the negative
  • features implied in the exaltation of the mind from the world to God,
  • that the metaphysical proofs of the being of a God are defective
  • interpretations and descriptions of the process. If the world is only a
  • sum of incidents, it follows that it is also deciduous and phenomenal,
  • in _esse_ and _posse_ null. That upward spring of the mind signifies,
  • that the being which the world has is only a semblance, no real being,
  • no absolute truth; it signifies that, beyond and above that appearance,
  • truth abides in God, so that true being is another name for God. The
  • process of exaltation might thus appear to be transition and to involve
  • a means, but it is not a whit less true, that every trace of transition
  • and means is absorbed; since the world, which might have seemed to be
  • the means of reaching God, is explained to be a nullity. Unless the
  • being of the world is nullified, the _point d'appui_ for the exaltation
  • is lost. In this way the apparent means vanishes, and the process
  • of derivation is cancelled in the very act by which it proceeds. It
  • is the affirmative aspect of this relation, as supposed to subsist
  • between two things, either of which _is_ as much as the other, which
  • Jacobi mainly has in his eye when he attacks the demonstrations of the
  • understanding. Justly censuring them for seeking conditions (_i.e._
  • the world) for the unconditioned, he remarks that the Infinite or
  • God must on such a method be presented as dependent and derivative.
  • But that elevation, as it takes place in the mind, serves to correct
  • this semblance: in fact, it has no other meaning than to correct that
  • semblance. Jacobi, however, failed to recognise the genuine nature of
  • essential thought--by which it cancels the mediation in the very act of
  • mediating; and consequently, his objection, though it tells against the
  • merely 'reflective' understanding, is false when applied to thought as
  • a whole, and in particular to reasonable thought.
  • To explain what we mean by the neglect of the negative factor in
  • thought, we may refer by way of illustration to the charges of
  • Pantheism and Atheism brought against the doctrines of Spinoza. The
  • absolute Substance of Spinoza certainly falls short of absolute spirit,
  • and it is a right and proper requirement that God should be defined
  • as absolute spirit. But when the definition in Spinoza is said to
  • identify the world with God, and to confound God with nature and the
  • finite world, it is implied that the finite world possesses a genuine
  • actuality and affirmative reality. If this assumption be admitted, of
  • course a union of God with the world renders God completely finite,
  • and degrades Him to the bare finite and adventitious congeries of
  • existence. But there are two objections to be noted. In the first place
  • Spinoza does not define God as the unity of God with the world, but as
  • the union of thought with extension, that is, with the material world.
  • And secondly, even if we accept this awkward popular statement as to
  • this unity, it would still be true that the system of Spinoza was not
  • Atheism but Acosmism, defining the world to be an appearance lacking in
  • true reality. A philosophy, which affirms that God and God-alone is,
  • should not be stigmatised as atheistic, when even those nations which
  • worship the ape, the cow, or images of stone and brass, are credited
  • with some religion. But as things stand the imagination of ordinary men
  • feels a vehement reluctance to surrender its dearest conviction, that
  • this aggregate of finitude, which it calls a world, has actual reality;
  • and to hold that there is no world is a way of thinking they are fain
  • to believe impossible, or at least much less possible than to entertain
  • the idea that there is no God. Human nature, not much to its credit, is
  • more ready to believe that a system denies God, than that it denies the
  • world. A denial of God seems so much more intelligible than a denial of
  • the world.
  • The second remark bears on the criticism of the material propositions
  • to which that elevation in thought in the first instance leads. If
  • these propositions have for their predicate such terms as substance of
  • the world, its necessary essence, cause which regulates and directs it
  • according to design, they are certainly inadequate to express what is
  • or ought to be understood by God. Yet apart from the trick of adopting
  • a preliminary popular conception of God, and criticising a result by
  • this assumed standard, it is certain that these characteristics have
  • great value, and are necessary factors in the idea of God. But if we
  • wish in this way to bring before thought the genuine idea of God,
  • and give its true value and expression to the central truth, we must
  • be careful not to start from a subordinate level of facts. To speak
  • of the 'merely contingent' things of the world is a very inadequate
  • description of the premisses. The organic structures, and the evidence
  • they afford of mutual adaptation, belong to a higher province, the
  • province of animated nature. But even without taking into consideration
  • the possible blemish which the study of animated nature and of the
  • other teleological aspects of existing things may contract from the
  • pettiness of the final causes, and from puerile instances of them and
  • their bearings, merely animated nature is, at the best, incapable of
  • supplying the material for a truthful expression to the idea of God.
  • God is more than life: He is Spirit. And therefore if the thought of
  • the Absolute takes a starting-point for its rise, and desires to take
  • the nearest, the most true and adequate starting-point will be found in
  • the nature of spirit alone.
  • 51.] The other way of unification by which to realise the Ideal of
  • Reason is to set out from the _abstractum_ of Thought and seek to
  • characterise it: for which purpose Being is the only available term.
  • This is the method of the Ontological proof. The opposition, here
  • presented from a merely subjective point of view, lies between Thought
  • and Being; whereas in the first way of junction, being is common to the
  • two sides of the antithesis, and the contrast lies only between its
  • individualisation and universality. Understanding meets this second way
  • with what is implicitly the same objection, as it made to the first.
  • It denied that the empirical involves the universal: so it denies that
  • the universal involves the specialisation, which specialisation in this
  • instance is being. In other words it says: Being cannot be deduced from
  • the notion by any analysis.
  • The uniformly favourable reception and acceptance which attended
  • Kant's criticism of the Ontological proof was undoubtedly due to the
  • illustration which he made use of. To explain the difference between
  • thought and being, he took the instance of a hundred sovereigns,
  • which, for anything it matters to the notion, are the same hundred
  • whether they are real or only possible, though the difference of the
  • two cases is very perceptible in their effect on a man's purse. Nothing
  • can be more obvious than that anything we only think or conceive is not
  • on that account actual: that mental representation, and even notional
  • comprehension, always falls short of being. Still it may not unfairly
  • be styled a barbarism in language, when the name of notion is given
  • to things like a hundred sovereigns. And, putting that mistake aside,
  • those who perpetually urge against the philosophic Idea the difference
  • between Being and Thought, might have admitted that philosophers
  • were not wholly ignorant of the fact. Can there be any proposition
  • more trite than this? But after all, it is well to remember, when we
  • speak of God, that we have an object of another kind than any hundred
  • sovereigns, and unlike any one particular notion, representation, or
  • however else it may be styled. It is in fact this and this alone which
  • marks everything finite:--its being in time and space is discrepant
  • from its notion. God, on the contrary, expressly has to be what can
  • only be 'thought as existing'; His notion involves being. It is this
  • unity of the notion and being that constitutes the notion of God.
  • If this were all, we should have only a formal expression of the divine
  • nature which would not really go beyond a statement of the nature of
  • the notion itself. And that the notion, in its most abstract terms,
  • involves being is plain. For the notion, whatever other determination
  • it may receive, is at least reference back on itself, which results
  • by abolishing the intermediation, and thus is immediate. And what is
  • that reference to self, but being? Certainly it would be strange if the
  • notion, the very inmost of mind, if even the 'Ego,' or above all, the
  • concrete totality we call God, were not rich enough to include so poor
  • a category as being, the very poorest and most abstract of all. For,
  • if we look at the thought it holds, nothing can be more insignificant
  • than being. And yet there may be something still more insignificant
  • than being,--that which at first sight is perhaps supposed to _be,_ an
  • external and sensible existence, like that of the paper lying before
  • me. However, in this matter, nobody proposes to speak of the sensible
  • existence of a limited and perishable thing. Besides, the petty
  • stricture of the _Kritik_ that 'thought and being are different' can at
  • most molest the path of the human mind from the thought of God to the
  • certainty that He _is_: it cannot take it away. It is this process of
  • transition, depending on the absolute inseparability of the _thought_
  • of God from His being, for which its proper authority has been
  • re-vindicated in the theory of faith or immediate knowledge,--whereof
  • hereafter.
  • 52.] In this way thought, at its highest pitch, has to go outside for
  • any determinateness: and although it is continually termed Reason, is
  • out-and-out abstract thinking. And the result of all is that Reason
  • supplies nothing beyond the formal unity required to simplify and
  • systematise experiences; it is a _canon,_ not an _organon_ of truth,
  • and can furnish only a _criticism_ of knowledge, not a _doctrine_ of
  • the infinite. In its final analysis this criticism is summed up in the
  • assertion that in strictness thought is only the indeterminate unity
  • and the action of this indeterminate unity.
  • Kant undoubtedly held reason to be the faculty of the
  • unconditioned; but if reason be reduced to abstract identity
  • only, it by implication renounces its unconditionality and is
  • in reality no better than empty understanding. For reason is
  • unconditioned, only in so far as its character and quality are not
  • due to an extraneous and foreign content, only in so far as it
  • is self-characterising, and thus, in point of content, is its own
  • master. Kant, however, expressly explains that the action of reason
  • consists solely in applying the categories to systematise the
  • matter given by perception, _e._ to place it in an outside order,
  • under the guidance of the principle of non-contradiction.
  • 53.] (b) The Practical Reason is understood by Kant to mean a
  • _thinking_ Will, _i.e._ a Will that determines itself on universal
  • principles. Its office is to give objective, imperative laws of
  • freedom,--laws, that is, which state what ought to happen. The warrant
  • for thus assuming thought to be an activity which makes itself felt
  • objectively, that is, to be really a Reason, is the alleged possibility
  • of proving practical freedom by experience, that is, of showing it in
  • the phenomenon of self-consciousness. This experience in consciousness
  • is at once met by all that the Necessitarian produces from contrary
  • experience, particularly by the sceptical induction (employed amongst
  • others by Hume) from the endless diversity of what men regard as right
  • and duty,--_i.e._ from the diversity apparent in those professedly
  • objective laws of freedom.
  • 54.] What, then, is to serve as the law which the Practical
  • Reason embraces and obeys, and as the criterion in its act of
  • self-determination? There is no rule at hand but the same abstract
  • identity of understanding as before: There must be no contradiction in
  • the act of self-determination. Hence the Practical Reason never shakes
  • off the formalism which is represented as the climax of the Theoretical
  • Reason.
  • But this Practical Reason does not confine the universal principle of
  • the Good to its own inward regulation: it first becomes _practical,_
  • in the true sense of the word, when it insists on the Good being
  • manifested in the world with an outward objectivity, and requires that
  • the thought shall be objective throughout, and not merely subjective.
  • We shall speak of this postulate of the Practical Reason afterwards.
  • The free self-determination which Kant denied to the speculative,
  • he has expressly vindicated for the practical reason. To many minds
  • this particular aspect of the Kantian philosophy made it welcome;
  • and that for good reasons. To estimate rightly what we owe to
  • Kant in the matter, we ought to set before our minds the form of
  • practical philosophy and in particular of 'moral philosophy,' which
  • prevailed in his time. It may be generally described as a system
  • of Eudaemonism, which, when asked what man's chief end ought to
  • be, replied Happiness. And by happiness Eudaemonism understood the
  • satisfaction of the private appetites, wishes and wants of the
  • man: thus raising the contingent and particular into a principle
  • for the will and its actualisation. To this Eudaemonism, which was
  • destitute of stability and consistency, and which left the 'door
  • and gate' wide open for every whim and caprice, Kant opposed the
  • practical reason, and thus emphasised the need for a principle
  • of will which should be universal and lay the same obligation
  • on all. The theoretical reason, as has been made evident in the
  • preceding paragraphs, is identified by Kant with the negative
  • faculty of the infinite; and as it has no positive content of its
  • own, it is restricted to the function of detecting the finitude of
  • experiential knowledge. To the practical reason, on the contrary,
  • he has expressly allowed a positive infinity, by ascribing to the
  • will the power of modifying itself in universal modes, _i.e._ by
  • thought. Such a power the will undoubtedly has: and it is well
  • to remember that man is free only in so far as he possesses it
  • and avails himself of it in his conduct. But a recognition of the
  • existence of this power is not enough and does not avail to tell
  • us what are the contents of the will or practical reason. Hence to
  • say, that a man must make the Good the content of his will, raises
  • the question, what that content is, and what are the means of
  • ascertaining what good is. Nor does one get over the difficulty by
  • the principle that the will must be consistent with itself, or by
  • the precept to do duty for the sake of duty.
  • 55.] (c) The Reflective Power of Judgment is invested by Kant
  • with the function of an Intuitive Understanding. That is to say,
  • whereas the particulars had hitherto appeared, so far as the universal
  • or abstract identity was concerned, adventitious and incapable of
  • being deduced from it, the _Intuitive_ Understanding apprehends the
  • particulars as moulded and formed by the universal itself. Experience
  • presents such universalised particulars in the products of Art and of
  • _organic_ nature.
  • The capital feature in Kant's Criticism of the Judgment is, that in
  • it he gave a representation and a name, if not even an intellectual
  • expression, to the Idea. Such a representation, as an Intuitive
  • Understanding, or an inner adaptation, suggests a universal which
  • is at the same time apprehended as essentially a concrete unity, It
  • is in these aperçus alone that the Kantian philosophy rises to the
  • speculative height. Schiller, and others, have found in the idea of
  • artistic beauty, where thought and sensuous conception have grown
  • together into one, a way of escape from the abstract and separatist
  • understanding. Others have found the same relief in the perception
  • and consciousness of life and of living things, whether that life
  • be natural or intellectual.--The work of Art, as well as the living
  • individual, is, it must be owned, of limited content. But in the
  • postulated harmony of nature (or necessity) and free purpose,--in the
  • final purpose of the world conceived as realised, Kant has put before
  • us the Idea, comprehensive even in its content. Yet what may be called
  • the laziness of thought, when dealing with this supreme Idea, finds a
  • too easy mode of evasion in the 'ought to be': instead of the actual
  • realisation of the ultimate end, it clings hard to the disjunction
  • of the notion from reality. Yet if thought will not _think_ the ideal
  • realised, the senses and the intuition can at any rate _see_ it in the
  • present reality of living organisms and of the beautiful in Art. And
  • consequently Kant's remarks on these objects were well adapted to lead
  • the mind on to grasp and think the concrete Idea.
  • 56.] We are thus led to conceive a different relation between the
  • universal of understanding and the particular of perception, than that
  • on which the theory of the Theoretical and Practical Reason is founded.
  • But while this is so, it is not supplemented by a recognition that the
  • former is the genuine relation and the very truth. Instead of that,
  • the unity (of universal with particular) is accepted only as it exists
  • in finite phenomena, and is adduced only as a fact of experience.
  • Such experience, at first only personal, may come from two sources.
  • It may spring from Genius, the faculty which produces 'aesthetic
  • ideas'; meaning by aesthetic ideas, the picture-thoughts of the free
  • imagination which subserve an idea and suggest thoughts, although their
  • content is not expressed in a notional form, and even admits of no
  • such expression. It may also be due to Taste, the feeling of congruity
  • between the free play of intuition or imagination and the uniformity of
  • understanding.
  • 57.] The principle by which the Reflective faculty of Judgment
  • regulates and arranges the products of animated nature is described
  • as the End or final cause,--the notion in action, the universal at
  • once determining and determinate in itself. At the same time Kant is
  • careful to discard the conception of external or finite adaptation, in
  • which the End is only an adventitious form for the means and material
  • in which it is realised. In the living organism, on the contrary, the
  • final cause is a moulding principle and an energy immanent in the
  • matter, and every member is in its turn a means as well as an end.
  • 58.] Such an Idea evidently radically transforms the relation which the
  • understanding institutes between means and ends, between subjectivity
  • and objectivity. And yet in the face of this unification, the End or
  • design is subsequently explained to be a cause which exists and acts
  • subjectively, _i.e._ as our idea only: and teleology is accordingly
  • explained to be only a principle of criticism, purely personal to _our_
  • understanding.
  • After the Critical philosophy had settled that Reason can know
  • phenomena only, there would still have been an option for animated
  • nature between two equally subjective modes of thought. Even according
  • to Kant's own exposition, there would have been an obligation to admit,
  • in the case of natural productions, a knowledge not confined to the
  • categories of quality, cause and effect, composition, constituents,
  • and so on. The principle of inward adaptation or design, had it been
  • kept to and carried out in scientific application, would have led to a
  • different and a higher method of observing nature.
  • 59.] If we adopt this principle, the Idea, when all limitations were
  • removed from it, would appear as follows. The universality moulded by
  • Reason, and described as the absolute and final end or the Good, would
  • be realised in the world, and realised moreover by means of a third
  • thing, the power which proposes this End as well as realises it,--that
  • is, God. Thus in Him, who is the absolute truth, those oppositions of
  • universal and individual, subjective and objective, are solved and
  • explained to be neither self-subsistent nor true.
  • 80.] But Good,--which is thus put forward as the final cause of the
  • world,--has been already described as only _our_ good, the moral law
  • of _our_ Practical Reason. This being so, the unity in question
  • goes no further than make the state of the world and the course of
  • its events harmonise with our moral standards.[1] Besides, even with
  • this limitation, the final cause, or Good, is a vague abstraction,
  • and the same vagueness attaches to what is to be Duty. But, further,
  • this harmony is met by the revival and re-assertion of the antithesis,
  • which it by its own principle had nullified. The harmony is then
  • described as merely subjective, something which merely ought to be,
  • and which at the same time is not real,--a mere article of faith,
  • possessing a subjective certainty, but without truth, or that
  • objectivity which is proper to the Idea. This contradiction may seem
  • to be disguised by adjourning the realisation of the Idea to a future,
  • to a _time_ when the Idea will also be. But a sensuous condition like
  • time is the reverse of a reconciliation of the discrepancy; and an
  • infinite progression--which is the corresponding image adopted by the
  • understanding--on the very face of it only repeats and re-enacts the
  • contradiction.
  • A general remark may still be offered on the result to which the
  • Critical philosophy led as to the nature of knowledge; a result
  • which has grown one of the current 'idols' or axiomatic beliefs of
  • the day. In every dualistic system, and especially in that of Kant,
  • the fundamental defect makes itself visible in the inconsistency of
  • unifying at one moment, what a moment before had been explained to
  • be independent and therefore incapable of unification. And then, at
  • the very moment after unification has been alleged to be the truth,
  • we suddenly come upon the doctrine that the two elements, which, in
  • their true status of unification, had been refused all independent
  • subsistence, are only true and actual in their state of separation.
  • Philosophising of this kind wants the little penetration needed to
  • discover, that this shuffling only evidences how unsatisfactory each
  • one of the two terms is. And it fails simply because it is incapable
  • of bringing two thoughts together. (And in point of form there are
  • never more than two.) It argues an utter want of consistency to say,
  • on the one hand, that the understanding only knows phenomena, and, on
  • the other, assert the absolute character of this knowledge, by such
  • statements as 'Cognition can go no further'; 'Here is the _natural_ and
  • absolute limit of human knowledge.' But 'natural' is the wrong word
  • here. The things of nature are limited and are natural things only to
  • such extent as they are not aware of their universal limit, or to such
  • extent as their mode or quality is a limit from our point of view,
  • and not from their own. No one knows, or even feels, that anything
  • is a limit or defect, until he is at the same time above and beyond
  • it. Living beings, for example, possess the privilege of pain which
  • is denied to the inanimate: even with living beings, a single mode or
  • quality passes into the feeling of a negative. For living beings as
  • such possess within them a universal vitality, which overpasses and
  • includes the single mode; and thus, as they maintain themselves in
  • the negative of themselves, they feel the contradiction to _exist_
  • within them. But the contradiction is within them, only in so far as
  • one and the same subject includes both the universality of their sense
  • of life, and the individual mode which is in negation with it. This
  • illustration will show how a limit or imperfection in knowledge comes
  • to be termed a limit or imperfection, only when it is compared with the
  • actually-present Idea of the universal, of a total and perfect. A very
  • little consideration might show, that to call a thing finite or limited
  • proves by implication the very presence of the infinite and unlimited,
  • and that our knowledge of a limit can only be when the unlimited is _on
  • this side_ in consciousness.
  • The result however of Kant's view of cognition suggests a second
  • remark. The philosophy of Kant could have no influence on the method of
  • the sciences. It leaves the categories and method of ordinary knowledge
  • quite unmolested. Occasionally, it may be, in the first sections of a
  • scientific work of that period, we find propositions borrowed from the
  • Kantian philosophy: but the course of the treatise renders it apparent
  • that these propositions were superfluous decoration, and that the few
  • first pages might have been omitted without producing the least change
  • in the empirical contents.[2]
  • We may next institute a comparison of Kant with the metaphysics of the
  • empirical school. Natural plain Empiricism, though it unquestionably
  • insists most upon sensuous perception, still allows a super-sensible
  • world or spiritual reality, whatever may be its structure and
  • constitution, and whether derived from intellect, or from imagination,
  • &c. So far as form goes, the facts of this super-sensible world rest on
  • the authority of mind, in the same way as the other facts, embraced
  • in empirical knowledge, rest on the authority of external perception.
  • But when Empiricism becomes reflective and logically consistent, it
  • turns its arms against this dualism in the ultimate and highest species
  • of fact; it denies the independence of the thinking principle and of
  • a spiritual world which developes itself in thought. Materialism or
  • Naturalism, therefore, is the consistent and thorough-going system
  • of Empiricism. In direct opposition to such an Empiricism, Kant
  • asserts the principle of thought and freedom, and attaches himself
  • to the first-mentioned form of empirical doctrine, the general
  • principles of which he never departed from. There is a dualism in
  • his philosophy also. On one side stands the world of sensation, and
  • of the understanding which reflects upon it. This world, it is true,
  • he alleges to be a world of appearances. But that is only a title
  • or formal description; for the source, the facts, and the modes of
  • observation continue quite the same as in Empiricism. On the other side
  • and independent stands a self-apprehending thought, the principle of
  • freedom, which Kant has in common with ordinary and bygone metaphysic,
  • but emptied of all that it held, and without his being able to infuse
  • into it anything new. For, in the Critical doctrine, thought, or, as it
  • is there called, Reason, is divested of every specific form, and thus
  • bereft of all authority. The main effect of the Kantian philosophy has
  • been to revive the consciousness of Reason, or the absolute inwardness
  • of thought. Its abstractness indeed prevented that inwardness from
  • developing into anything, or from originating any special forms,
  • whether cognitive principles or moral laws; but nevertheless it
  • absolutely refused to accept or indulge anything possessing the
  • character of an externality. Henceforth the principle of the
  • independence of Reason, or of its absolute self-subsistence, is made
  • a general principle of philosophy, as well as a foregone conclusion of
  • the time.
  • (1) The Critical philosophy has one great negative merit. It has
  • brought home the conviction that the categories of understanding are
  • finite in their range, and that any cognitive process confined within
  • their pale falls short of the truth. But Kant had only a sight of
  • half the truth. He explained the finite nature of the categories to
  • mean that they were subjective only, valid only for our thought, from
  • which the thing-in-itself was divided by an impassable gulf. In fact,
  • however, it is not because they are subjective, that the categories are
  • finite: they are finite by their very nature, and it is on their own
  • selves that it is requisite to exhibit their finitude. Kant however
  • holds that what we think is false, because it is we who think it. A
  • further deficiency in the system is that it gives only an historical
  • description of thought, and a mere enumeration of the factors of
  • consciousness. The enumeration is in the main correct: but not a word
  • touches upon the necessity of what is thus empirically colligated. The
  • observations, made on the various stages of consciousness, culminate
  • in the summary statement, that the content of all we are acquainted
  • with is only an appearance. And as it is true at least that all finite
  • thinking is concerned with appearances, so far the conclusion is
  • justified. This stage of 'appearance' however--the phenomenal world--is
  • not the terminus of thought: there is another and a higher region. But
  • that region was to the Kantian philosophy an inaccessible 'other world.'
  • (2) After all it was only formally, that the Kantian system established
  • the principle that thought is spontaneous and self-determining. Into
  • details of the manner and the extent of this self-determination of
  • thought, Kant never went. It was Fichte who first noticed the omission;
  • and who, after he had called attention to the want of a deduction for
  • the categories, endeavoured really to supply something of the kind.
  • With Fichte, the 'Ego' is the starting-point in the philosophical
  • development: and the outcome of its action is supposed to be visible
  • in the categories. But in Fichte the 'Ego' is not really presented
  • as a free, spontaneous energy; it is supposed to receive its first
  • excitation by a shock or impulse from without. Against this shock
  • the 'Ego' will, it is assumed, react, and only through this reaction
  • does it first become conscious of itself. Meanwhile, the nature of
  • the impulse remains a stranger beyond our pale: and the 'Ego,' with
  • something else always confronting it, is weighted with a condition.
  • Fichte, in consequence, never advanced beyond Kant's conclusion, that
  • the finite only is knowable, while the infinite transcends the range
  • of thought. What Kant calls the thing-by-itself, Fichte calls the
  • impulse from without--that abstraction of something else than 'I,' not
  • otherwise describable or definable than as the negative or non-Ego in
  • general. The 'I' is thus looked at as standing in essential relation
  • with the not-I, through which its act of self-determination is first
  • awakened. And in this manner the 'I' is but the continuous act of
  • self-liberation from this impulse, never gaining a real freedom,
  • because with the surcease of the impulse the 'I,' whose being is
  • its action, would also cease to be. Nor is the content produced by
  • the action of the 'I' at all different from the ordinary content of
  • experience, except by the supplementary remark, that this content is
  • mere appearance.
  • [1] Even Hermann's 'Handbook of Prosody' begins with paragraphs of
  • Kantian philosophy. In § 8 it is argued that a law of rhythm must be
  • (1) objective, (a) formal, and (3) determined _à priori._ With these
  • requirements and with the principles of Causality and Reciprocity which
  • follow later, it were well to compare the treatment of the various
  • measures, upon which those formal principles do not exercise the
  • slightest influence.
  • [2] In Kant's own words (Criticism of the Power of Judgment, p. 427):
  • 'Final Cause is merely a notion of our practical reason. It cannot
  • be deduced from any data of experience as a theoretical criterion of
  • nature, nor can it be applied to know nature. No employment of this
  • notion is possible except solely for the practical reason, by moral
  • laws. The final purpose of the Creation is that constitution of the
  • world which harmonises with that to which alone we can give definite
  • expression on universal principles, viz. the final purpose of our pure
  • practical reason, and with that in so far as it means to be practical.'
  • CHAPTER V.
  • THIRD ATTITUDE OF THOUGHT TO OBJECTIVITY.
  • _Immediate or Intuitive Knowledge._
  • 61.] If we are to believe the Critical philosophy, thought is
  • subjective, and its ultimate and invincible mode is _abstract
  • universality_ or formal identity. Thought is thus set in opposition
  • to Truth, which is no abstraction, but concrete universality. In this
  • highest mode of thought, which is entitled Reason, the Categories
  • are left out of account.--The extreme theory on the opposite side
  • holds thought to be an act of the _particular_ only, and on that
  • ground declares it incapable of apprehending the Truth. This is the
  • Intuitional theory.
  • 62.] According to this theory, thinking, a private and particular
  • operation, has its whole scope and product in the Categories. But,
  • these Categories, as arrested by the understanding, are limited
  • vehicles of thought, forms of the conditioned, of the dependent
  • and derivative. A thought limited to these modes has no sense of
  • the Infinite and the True, and cannot bridge over the gulf that
  • separates it from them. (This stricture refers to the proofs of God's
  • existence.) These inadequate modes or categories are also spoken of as
  • _notions_: and to get a notion of an object therefore can only mean,
  • in this language, to grasp it under the form of being conditioned and
  • derivative. Consequently, if the object in question be the True, the
  • Infinite, the Unconditioned, we change it by our notions into a finite
  • and conditioned; whereby, instead of apprehending the truth by thought,
  • we have perverted it into untruth.
  • Such is the one simple line of argument advanced for the thesis that
  • the knowledge of God and of truth must be immediate, or intuitive. At
  • an earlier period all sort of anthropomorphic conceptions, as they
  • are termed, were banished from God, as being finite and therefore
  • unworthy of the infinite; and in this way God had been reduced to
  • a tolerably blank being. But in those days the thought-forms were
  • in general not supposed to come under the head of anthropomorphism.
  • Thought was believed rather to strip finitude from the conceptions of
  • the Absolute,--in agreement with the above-mentioned conviction of all
  • ages, that reflection is the only road to truth. But now, at length,
  • even the thought-forms are pronounced anthropomorphic, and thought
  • itself is described as a mere faculty of finitisation.
  • Jacobi has stated this charge most distinctly in the seventh supplement
  • to his Letters on Spinoza,--borrowing his line of argument from the
  • works of Spinoza himself, and applying it as a weapon against knowledge
  • in general. In his attack knowledge is taken to mean knowledge of
  • the finite only, a process of thought from one condition in a series
  • to another, each of which is at once conditioning and conditioned.
  • According to such a view, to explain and to get the notion of
  • anything, is the same as to show it to be derived from something else.
  • Whatever such knowledge embraces, consequently, is partial, dependent
  • and finite, while the infinite or true, _i.e._ God, lies outside
  • of the mechanical inter-connexion to which knowledge is said to be
  • confined.--It is important to observe that, while Kant makes the finite
  • nature of the Categories consist mainly in the formal circumstance
  • that they are subjective, Jacobi discusses the Categories in their
  • own proper character, and pronounces them to be in their very import
  • finite. What Jacobi chiefly had before his eyes, when he thus described
  • science, was the brilliant successes of the physical or 'exact'
  • sciences in ascertaining natural forces and laws. It is certainly not
  • on the finite ground occupied by these sciences that we can expect to
  • meet the in-dwelling presence of the infinite. Lalande was right when
  • he said he had swept the whole heaven with his glass, and seen no God.
  • (See note to § 60.) In the field of physical science, the universal,
  • which is the final result of analysis, is only the indeterminate
  • aggregate,--of the external finite,--in one word, Matter: and Jacobi
  • well perceived that there was no other issue obtainable in the way of a
  • mere advance from one explanatory clause or law to another.
  • 63.] All the while the doctrine that truth exists for the mind was so
  • strongly maintained by Jacobi, that Reason alone is declared to be that
  • by which man lives. This Reason is the knowledge of God. But, seeing
  • that derivative knowledge is restricted to the compass of finite facts,
  • Reason is knowledge underivative, or Faith.
  • Knowledge, Faith, Thought, Intuition are the categories that we meet
  • with on this line of reflection. These terms, as presumably familiar to
  • every one, are only too frequently subjected to an arbitrary use, under
  • no better guidance than the conceptions and distinctions of psychology,
  • without any investigation into their nature and notion, which is the
  • main question after all. Thus, we often find knowledge contrasted with
  • faith, and faith at the same time explained to be an underivative
  • or intuitive knowledge:--so that it must be at least some sort of
  • knowledge. And, besides, it is unquestionably a fact of experience,
  • firstly, that what we believe is in our consciousness,---which implies
  • that we _know about it;_ and secondly, that this belief is a certainty
  • in our consciousness,--which implies that we _know it._ Again, and
  • especially, we find thought opposed to immediate knowledge and faith,
  • and, in particular, to intuition. But if this intuition be qualified
  • as intellectual, we must really mean intuition which thinks, unless,
  • in a question about the nature of God, we are willing to interpret
  • intellect to mean images and representations of imagination. The word
  • faith or belief, in the dialect of this system, comes to be employed
  • even with reference to common objects that are present to the senses.
  • We believe, says Jacobi, that we have a body,--we believe in the
  • existence of the things of sense. But if we are speaking of faith in
  • the True and Eternal, and saying that God is given and revealed to us
  • in immediate knowledge OF intuition, we are concerned not with the
  • things of sense, but with objects special to our thinking mind, with
  • truths of inherently universal significance. And when the individual
  • 'I,' or in other words personality, is under discussion--not the 'I' of
  • experience, or a single private person--above all, when the personality
  • of God is before us, we are speaking of personality unalloyed,--of a
  • personality in its own nature universal. Such personality is a thought,
  • and falls within the province of thought only. More than this. Pure and
  • simple intuition is completely the same as pure and simple thought.
  • Intuition and belief, in the first instance, denote the definite
  • conceptions we attach to these words in our ordinary employment of
  • them: and to this extent they differ from thought in certain points
  • which nearly every one can understand. But here they are taken in a
  • higher sense, and must be interpreted to mean a belief in God, or an
  • intellectual intuition of God; in short, we must put aside all that
  • especially distinguishes thought on the one side from belief and
  • intuition on the other. How belief and intuition, when transferred to
  • these higher regions, differ from thought, it is impossible for any one
  • to say. And yet, such are the barren distinctions of words, with which
  • men fancy that they assert an important truth: even while the formulae
  • they maintain are identical with those which they impugn.
  • The term _Faith_ brings with it the special advantage of suggesting
  • the faith of the Christian religion; it seems to include Christian
  • faith, or perhaps even to coincide with it; and thus the Philosophy of
  • Faith has a thoroughly orthodox and Christian look, on the strength of
  • which it takes the liberty of uttering its arbitrary dicta with greater
  • pretension and authority. But we must not let ourselves be deceived by
  • the semblance surreptitiously secured by a merely verbal similarity.
  • The two things are radically distinct. Firstly, the Christian faith
  • comprises in it an authority of the Church: but the faith of Jacobi's
  • philosophy has no other authority than that of a personal revelation.
  • And, secondly, the Christian faith is a copious body of objective
  • truth, a system of knowledge and doctrine: while the scope of the
  • philosophic faith is so utterly indefinite, that, while it has room for
  • the faith of the Christian, it equally admits a belief in the divinity
  • of the Dalai-lama, the ox, or the monkey,--thus, so far as it goes,
  • narrowing Deity down to its simplest terms, a 'Supreme Being.' Faith
  • itself, taken in this professedly philosophical sense, is nothing but
  • the sapless abstract of immediate knowledge,--a purely formal category
  • applicable to very different facts; and it ought never to be confused
  • or identified with the spiritual fulness of Christian faith, whether we
  • look at that faith in the heart of the believer and the in-dwelling of
  • the Holy Spirit, or in the system of theological doctrine.
  • With what is here called faith or immediate knowledge must also be
  • identified inspiration, the heart's revelations, the truths implanted
  • in man by nature, and also in particular, healthy reason or Common
  • Sense, as it is called. All these forms agree in adopting as their
  • leading principle the immediacy, or self-evident way, in which a fact
  • or body of truths is presented in consciousness.
  • 84.] This immediate knowledge consists in knowing that the Infinite,
  • the Eternal, the God which is in our idea, really _is_: or, it asserts
  • that in our consciousness there is immediately and inseparably bound up
  • with this idea the certainty of its actual being.
  • To seek to controvert these maxims of immediate knowledge is the last
  • thing philosophers would think of. They may rather find occasion for
  • self-gratulation when these ancient doctrines, expressing as they
  • do the general tenor of philosophic teaching, have, even in this
  • unphilosophical fashion, become to some extent universal convictions
  • of the age. The true marvel rather is that any one could suppose that
  • these principles were opposed to philosophy,--the maxims, viz., that
  • whatever is held to be true is immanent in the mind, and that there
  • is truth for the mind (§ 63). From a formal point of view, there is a
  • peculiar interest in the maxim that the being of God is immediately and
  • inseparably bound up with the thought of God, that objectivity is bound
  • up with the subjectivity which the thought originally presents. Not
  • content with that, the philosophy of immediate knowledge goes so far in
  • its one-sided view, as to affirm that the attribute of existence, even
  • in perception, is quite as inseparably connected with the conception
  • we have of our own bodies and of external things, as it is with the
  • thought of God. Now it is the endeavour of philosophy to _prove_ such
  • a unity, to show that it lies in the very nature of thought and
  • subjectivity, to be inseparable from being and objectivity. In these
  • circumstances therefore, philosophy, whatever estimate may be formed of
  • the character of these proofs, must in any case be glad to see it shown
  • and maintained that its maxims are facts of consciousness, and thus
  • in harmony with experience. The difference between philosophy and the
  • asseverations of immediate knowledge rather centres in the exclusive
  • attitude which immediate knowledge adopts, when it sets itself up
  • against philosophy.
  • And yet it was as a self-evident or immediate truth that the 'Cogito,
  • ergo sum,' of Descartes, the maxim on which may be said to hinge the
  • whole interest of Modern Philosophy, was first stated by its author.
  • The man who calls this a syllogism, must know little more about a
  • syllogism than that the word 'Ergo' occurs in it. Where shall we look
  • for the middle term? And a middle term is a much more essential point
  • of a syllogism than the word 'Ergo.' If we try to justify the name, by
  • calling the combination of ideas in Descartes an 'immediate' syllogism,
  • this superfluous variety of syllogism is a mere name for an utterly
  • unmediated synthesis of distinct terms of thought. That being so, the
  • synthesis of being with our ideas, as stated in the maxim of immediate
  • knowledge, has no more and no less claim to the title of syllogism than
  • the axiom of Descartes has. From Hotho's 'Dissertation on the Cartesian
  • Philosophy' (published 1826), I borrow the quotation in which Descartes
  • himself distinctly declares that the maxim 'Cogito, ergo sum,' is no
  • syllogism. The passages are Respons. ad II Object.: De Methodo IV:
  • Ep. I. 118. From the first passage I quote the words more immediately
  • to the point. Descartes says: 'That we are thinking beings is "_prima
  • quaedam notio quae ex nullo syllogismo concluditur_"' (a certain
  • primary notion, which is deduced from no syllogism); and goes on:
  • _'neque cum quis dicit; Ego cogito, ergo sum sive existo, existentiam
  • ex cogitatione per syllogismum deducit.'_ (Nor, when one says, I think,
  • therefore I am or exist, does he deduce existence from thought by means
  • of a syllogism.) Descartes knew what it implied in a syllogism, and
  • so he adds that, in order to make the maxim admit of a deduction by
  • syllogism, we should have to add the major premiss: _'Illud omne quod
  • cogitat, est sive existit.'_ (Everything which thinks, is or exists.)
  • Of course, he remarks, this major premiss itself has to be deduced from
  • the original statement.
  • The language of Descartes on the maxim that the 'I' which _thinks_ must
  • also at the same time _be,_ his saying that this connexion is given and
  • implied in the simple perception of consciousness,--that this connexion
  • is the absolute first, the principle, the most certain and evident of
  • all things, so that no scepticism can be conceived so monstrous as not
  • to admit it:--all this language is so vivid and distinct, that the
  • modern statements of Jacobi and others on this immediate connexion can
  • only pass for needless repetitions.
  • 65.] The theory of which we are speaking is not satisfied when it has
  • shown that mediate knowledge taken separately is an adequate vehicle
  • of truth. Its distinctive doctrine is that immediate knowledge alone,
  • to the total exclusion of mediation, can possess a content which is
  • true. This exclusiveness is enough to show that the theory is a relapse
  • into the metaphysical understanding, with its pass-words 'Either--or.'
  • And thus it is really a relapse into the habit of external mediation,
  • the gist of which consists in clinging to those narrow and one-sided
  • categories of the finite, which it falsely imagined itself to have left
  • for ever behind. This point, however, we shall not at present discuss
  • in detail. An exclusively immediate knowledge is asserted as a fact
  • only, and in the present Introduction we can only study it from this
  • external point of view. The real significance of such knowledge will
  • be explained, when we come to the logical question of the opposition
  • between mediate and immediate. But it is characteristic of the view
  • before us to decline to examine the nature of the fact, that is, the
  • notion of it; for such an examination would itself be a step towards
  • mediation and even towards knowledge. The genuine discussion on logical
  • ground, therefore, must be deferred till we come to the proper province
  • of Logic itself.
  • The whole of the second part of Logic, the Doctrine of Essential Being,
  • is a discussion of the intrinsic and self-affirming unity of immediacy
  • and mediation.
  • 66.] Beyond this point then we need not go: immediate knowledge is
  • to be accepted as a _fact._ Under these circumstances examination is
  • directed to the field of experience, to a psychological phenomenon. If
  • that be so, we need only note, as the commonest of experiences, that
  • truths, which we well know to be results of complicated and highly
  • mediated trains of thought, present themselves immediately and without
  • effort to the mind of any man who is familiar with the subject. The
  • mathematician, like every one who has mastered a particular science,
  • meets any problem with ready-made solutions which pre-suppose most
  • complicated analyses: and every educated man has a number of general
  • views and maxims which he can muster without trouble, but which
  • can only have sprung from frequent reflection and long experience.
  • The facility we attain in any sort of knowledge, art, or technical
  • expertness, consists in having the particular knowledge or kind of
  • action present to our mind in any case that occurs, even we may say,
  • immediate in our very limbs, in an out-going activity. In all these
  • instances, immediacy of knowledge is so far from excluding mediation,
  • that the two things are linked together,--immediate knowledge being
  • actually the product and result of mediated knowledge.
  • It is no less obvious that immediate _existence_ is bound up with
  • its mediation. The seed and the parents are immediate and initial
  • existences in respect of the off-spring which they generate. But the
  • seed and the parents, though they exist and are therefore immediate,
  • are yet in their turn generated: and the child, without prejudice to
  • the mediation of its existence, is immediate, because it _is._ The fact
  • that I am in Berlin, my immediate presence here, is mediated by my
  • having made the journey hither.
  • 67.] One thing may be observed with reference to the immediate
  • knowledge of God, of legal and ethical principles (including under
  • the head of immediate knowledge, what is otherwise termed Instinct,
  • Implanted or Innate Ideas, Common Sense, Natural Reason, or whatever
  • form, in short, we give to the original spontaneity). It is a matter
  • of general experience that education or development is required to
  • bring out into consciousness what is therein contained. It was so even
  • with the Platonic reminiscence; and the Christian rite of baptism,
  • although a sacrament, involves the additional obligation of a Christian
  • up-bringing. In short, religion and morals, however much they may be
  • faith or immediate knowledge, are still on every side conditioned by
  • the mediating process which is termed development, education, training.
  • The adherents, no less than the assailants, of the doctrine of Innate
  • Ideas have been guilty throughout of the like exclusiveness and
  • narrowness as is here noted. They have drawn a hard and fast line
  • between the essential and immediate union (as it may be described) of
  • certain universal principles with the soul, and another union which has
  • to be brought about in an external fashion, and through the channel of
  • _given_ objects and conceptions, There is one objection, borrowed from
  • experience, which was raised against the doctrine of Innate ideas. All
  • men, it was said, must have these ideas; they must have, for example,
  • the maxim of contradiction, present in the mind,--they must be aware
  • of it; for this maxim and others like it were included in the class
  • of Innate ideas. The objection may be set down to misconception; for
  • the principles in question, though innate, need not on that account
  • have the form of ideas or conceptions of something we are aware of.
  • Still, the objection completely meets and overthrows the crude theory
  • of immediate knowledge, which expressly maintains its formulae in so
  • far as they are in consciousness.--Another point calls for notice. We
  • may suppose it admitted by the intuitive school, that the special case
  • of religious faith involves supplementing by a Christian or religious
  • education and development. In that case it is acting capriciously when
  • it seeks to ignore this admission when speaking about faith, or it
  • betrays a want of reflection not to know, that, if the necessity of
  • education be once admitted, mediation is pronounced indispensable.
  • The reminiscence of ideas spoken of by Plato is equivalent to
  • saying that ideas implicitly exist in man, instead of being, as
  • the Sophists assert, a foreign importation into his mind. But to
  • conceive knowledge as reminiscence does not interfere with, or
  • set aside as useless, the development of what is implicitly in
  • man;--which development is another word for mediation. The same
  • holds good of the innate ideas that we find in Descartes and the
  • Scotch philosophers. These ideas are only potential in the first
  • instance, and should be looked at as being a sort of mere capacity
  • in man.
  • 88.] In the case of these experiences the appeal turns upon something
  • that shows itself bound up with immediate consciousness. Even if
  • this combination be in the first instance taken as an external and
  • empirical connexion, still, even for empirical observation, the fact
  • of its being constant shows it to be essential and inseparable. But,
  • again, if this immediate consciousness, as exhibited in experience,
  • be taken separately, so far as it is a consciousness of God and
  • the divine nature, the state of mind which it implies is generally
  • described as an exaltation above the finite, above the senses, and
  • above the instinctive desires and affections of the natural heart:
  • which exaltation passes over into, and terminates in, faith in God and
  • a divine order. It is apparent, therefore, that, though faith may be an
  • immediate knowledge and certainty, it equally implies the interposition
  • of this process as its antecedent and condition.
  • It has been already observed, that the so-called proofs of the being
  • of God, which start from finite being, give an expression to this
  • exaltation. In that light they are no inventions of an over-subtle
  • reflection, but the necessary and native channel in which the movement
  • of mind runs: though it may be that, in their ordinary form, these
  • proofs have not their correct and adequate expression.
  • 69.] It is the passage (§ 64) from the subjective Idea to being which
  • forms the main concern of the doctrine of immediate knowledge. A
  • primary and self-evident inter-connexion is declared to exist between
  • our Idea and being. Yet precisely this central point of transition,
  • utterly irrespective of any connexions which show in experience,
  • clearly involves a mediation. And the mediation is of no imperfect or
  • unreal kind, where the mediation takes place with and through something
  • external, but one comprehending both antecedent and conclusion.
  • 70.] For, what this theory asserts is that truth lies neither in the
  • Idea as a merely subjective thought, nor in mere being on its own
  • account;--that mere being _per se,_ a being that is not of the Idea,
  • is the sensible finite being of the world. Now all this only affirms,
  • without demonstration, that the Idea has truth only by means of being,
  • and being has truth only by means of the Idea. The maxim of immediate
  • knowledge rejects an indefinite empty immediacy (and such is abstract
  • being, or pure unity taken by itself), and affirms in its stead the
  • unity of the Idea with being. And it acts rightly in so doing. But it
  • is stupid not to see that the unity of distinct terms or modes is not
  • merely a purely immediate unity, _i.e._ unity empty and indeterminate,
  • but that--with equal emphasis--the one term is shown to have truth only
  • as mediated through the other;--or, if the phrase be preferred, that
  • either term is only mediated with truth through the other. That the
  • quality of mediation is involved in the very immediacy of intuition
  • is thus exhibited as a fact, against which understanding, conformably
  • to the fundamental maxim of immediate knowledge that the evidence of
  • consciousness is infallible, can have nothing to object. It is only
  • ordinary abstract understanding which takes the terms of mediation and
  • immediacy, each by itself absolutely, to represent an inflexible line
  • of distinction, and thus draws upon its own head the hopeless task of
  • reconciling them. The difficulty, as we have shown, has no existence in
  • the fact, and it vanishes in the speculative notion.
  • 71.] The one-sidedness of the intuitional school has certain
  • characteristics attending upon it, which we shall proceed to point out
  • in their main features, now that we have discussed the fundamental
  • principle. The _first_ of these corollaries is as follows. Since the
  • criterion of truth is found, not in the nature of the content, but in
  • the mere fact of consciousness, every alleged truth has no other basis
  • than subjective certitude and the assertion that we discover a certain
  • fact in our consciousness. What I discover in my consciousness is thus
  • exaggerated into a fact of the consciousness of all, and even passed
  • off for the very nature of consciousness.
  • Among the so-called proofs of the existence of God, there used to stand
  • the _consensus gentium,_ to which appeal is made as early as Cicero.
  • The _consensus gentium_ is a weighty authority, and the transition is
  • easy and natural, from the circumstance that a certain fact is found
  • in the consciousness of every one, to the conclusion that it is a
  • necessary element in the very nature of consciousness. In this category
  • of general agreement there was latent the deep-rooted perception, which
  • does not escape even the least cultivated mind, that the consciousness
  • of the individual is at the same time particular and accidental. Yet
  • unless we examine the nature of this consciousness itself, stripping
  • it of its particular and accidental elements and, by the toilsome
  • operation of reflection, disclosing the universal in its entirety and
  • purity, it is only a _unanimous_ agreement upon a given point that can
  • authorize a decent presumption that that point is part of the very
  • nature of consciousness. Of course, if thought insists on seeing the
  • necessity of what is presented as a fact of general occurrence, the
  • _consensus gentium_ is certainly not sufficient. Yet even granting the
  • universality of the fact to be a satisfactory proof, it has been found
  • impossible to establish the belief in God on such an argument, because
  • experience shows that there are individuals and nations without any
  • such faith.[1] But there can be nothing shorter and more convenient
  • than to have the bare assertion to make, that we discover a fact in
  • our consciousness, and are certain that it is true: and to declare
  • that this certainty, instead of proceeding from our particular mental
  • constitution only, belongs to the very nature of the mind.
  • 72.] A _second_ corollary which results from holding immediacy of
  • consciousness to be the criterion of truth is that all superstition
  • or idolatry is allowed to be truth, and that an apology is prepared
  • for any contents of the will, however wrong and immoral. It is because
  • he believes in them, and not from the reasoning and syllogism of
  • what is termed mediate knowledge, that the Hindoo finds God in the
  • cow, the monkey, the Brahmin, or the Lama. But the natural desires
  • and affections spontaneously carry and deposit their interests in
  • consciousness, where also immoral aims make themselves naturally at
  • home: the good or bad character would thus express the _definite being_
  • of the will, which would be known, and that most immediately, in the
  • interests and aims.
  • 73.] _Thirdly_ and lastly, the immediate consciousness of God goes no
  • further than to tell us _that_ He is: to tell us _what_ He is, would be
  • an act of cognition, involving mediation. So that God as an object of
  • religion is expressly narrowed down to the indeterminate supersensible,
  • God in general: and the significance of religion is reduced to a
  • minimum.
  • If it were really needful to win back and secure the bare belief that
  • there is a God, or even to create it, we might well wonder at the
  • poverty of the age which can see a gain in the merest pittance of
  • religious consciousness, and which in its church has sunk so low as to
  • worship at the altar that stood in Athens long ago, dedicated to the
  • 'Unknown God.'
  • 74.] We have still briefly to indicate the general nature of the
  • form of immediacy. For it is the essential one-sidedness of the
  • category, which makes whatever comes under it one sided and, for
  • that reason, finite. And, first, it makes the universal no better
  • than an abstraction external to the particulars, and God a being
  • without determinate quality. But God can only be called a spirit
  • when He is known to be at once the beginning and end, as well as
  • the mean, in the process of mediation. Without this unification of
  • elements He is neither concrete, nor living, nor a spirit. Thus the
  • knowledge of God as a spirit necessarily implies mediation. The form
  • of immediacy, secondly, invests the particular with the character of
  • independent or self-centred being. But such predicates contradict the
  • very essence of the particular,--which is to be referred to something
  • else outside. They thus invest the finite with the character of an
  • absolute. But, besides, the form of immediacy is altogether abstract:
  • it has no preference for one set of contents more than another,
  • but is equally susceptible of all: it may as well sanction what is
  • idolatrous and immoral as the reverse. Only when we discern that the
  • content,--the particular, is not self-subsistent, but derivative from
  • something else, are its finitude and untruth shown in their proper
  • light. Such discernment, where the content we discern carries with
  • it the ground of its dependent nature, is a knowledge which involves
  • mediation. The only content which can be held to be the truth is one
  • not mediated with something else, not limited by other things: or,
  • otherwise expressed, it is one mediated by itself, where mediation and
  • immediate reference-to-self coincide. The understanding that fancies
  • it has got clear of finite knowledge, the identity of the analytical
  • metaphysicians and the old 'rationalists,' abruptly takes again as
  • principle and criterion of truth that immediacy which, as an abstract
  • reference-to-self, is the same as abstract identity. Abstract thought
  • (the scientific form used by 'reflective' metaphysic) and abstract
  • intuition (the form used by immediate knowledge) are one and the same.
  • The stereotyped opposition between the form of immediacy and that
  • of mediation gives to the former a halfness and inadequacy, that
  • affects every content which is brought under it. Immediacy means,
  • upon the whole, an abstract reference-to-self, that is, an abstract
  • identity or abstract universality. Accordingly the essential and
  • real universal, when taken merely in its immediacy, is a mere
  • abstract universal; and from this point of view God is conceived
  • as a being altogether without determinate quality. To call God
  • spirit is in that case only a phrase: for the consciousness and
  • self-consciousness, which spirit implies, are impossible without a
  • distinguishing of it from itself and from something else, _i.e._
  • without mediation.
  • 75.] It was impossible for us to criticise this, the third attitude,
  • which thought has been made to take towards objective truth, in any
  • other mode than what is naturally indicated and admitted in the
  • doctrine itself. The theory asserts that immediate knowledge is a
  • fact. It has been shown to be untrue in fact to say that there is an
  • immediate knowledge, a knowledge without mediation either by means of
  • something else or in itself. It has also been explained to be false
  • in fact to say that thought advances through finite and conditioned
  • categories only, which are always mediated by a something else, and to
  • forget that in the very act of mediation the mediation itself vanishes.
  • And to show that, in point of fact, there is a knowledge which advances
  • neither by unmixed immediacy nor by unmixed mediation, we can point to
  • the example of Logic and the whole of philosophy.
  • 76.] If we view the maxims of immediate knowledge in connexion with the
  • uncritical metaphysic of the past from which we started, we shall learn
  • from the comparison the reactionary nature of the school of Jacobi. His
  • doctrine is a return to the modern starting-point of this metaphysic
  • in the Cartesian philosophy. Both Jacobi and Descartes maintain the
  • following three points:
  • (1) The simple inseparability of the thought and being of the
  • thinker. '_Cogito, ergo sum_' is the same doctrine as that the being,
  • reality, and existence of the 'Ego' is immediately revealed to me
  • in consciousness. (Descartes, in fact, is careful to state that by
  • thought he means consciousness in general. Princip. Phil. I. 9.) This
  • inseparability is the absolutely first and most certain knowledge, not
  • mediated or demonstrated.
  • (2) The inseparability of existence from the conception of God: the
  • former is necessarily implied in the latter, or the conception never
  • can be without the attribute of existence, which is thus necessary and
  • eternal.[2]
  • (3) The immediate consciousness of the existence of external things.
  • By this nothing more is meant than sense-consciousness. To have such
  • a thing is the slightest of all cognitions: and the only thing worth
  • knowing about it is that such immediate knowledge of the being of
  • things external is error and delusion, that the sensible world as such
  • is altogether void of truth; that the being of these external things is
  • accidental and passes away as a show; and that their very nature is to
  • have only an existence which is separable from their essence and notion.
  • 77.] There is however a distinction between the two points of view:
  • (1) The Cartesian philosophy, from these unproved postulates, which
  • it assumes to be unprovable, proceeds to wider and wider details of
  • knowledge, and thus gave rise to the sciences of modern times. The
  • modern theory (of Jacobi), on the contrary, (§ 62) has come to what is
  • intrinsically a most important conclusion that cognition, proceeding
  • as it must by finite mediations, can know only the finite, and never
  • embody the truth; and would fain have the consciousness of God go no
  • further than the aforesaid very abstract belief that God _is_.[3]
  • (2) The modern doctrine on the one hand makes no change in the
  • Cartesian method of the usual scientific knowledge, and conducts on
  • the same plan the experimental and finite sciences that have sprung
  • from it. But, on the other hand, when it comes to the science which
  • has infinity for its scope, it throws aside that method, and thus,
  • as it knows no other, it rejects all methods. It abandons itself to
  • wild vagaries of imagination and assertion, to a moral priggishness
  • and sentimental arrogance, or to a reckless dogmatising and lust
  • of argument, which is loudest against philosophy and philosophic
  • doctrines. Philosophy of course tolerates no mere assertions or
  • conceits, and checks the free play of argumentative see-saw.
  • 78.] We must then reject the opposition between an independent
  • immediacy in the contents or facts of consciousness and an equally
  • independent mediation, supposed incompatible with the former. The
  • incompatibility is a mere assumption, an arbitrary assertion. All other
  • assumptions and postulates must in like manner be left behind at the
  • entrance to philosophy, whether they are derived from the intellect or
  • the imagination. For philosophy is the science, in which every such
  • proposition must first be scrutinised and its meaning and oppositions
  • be ascertained.
  • Scepticism, made a negative science and systematically applied to all
  • forms of knowledge, might seem a suitable introduction, as pointing out
  • the nullity of such assumptions. But a sceptical introduction would
  • be not only an ungrateful but also a useless course; and that because
  • Dialectic, as we shall soon make appear, is itself an essential element
  • of affirmative science. Scepticism, besides, could only get hold of
  • the finite forms as they were suggested by experience, taking them
  • as given, instead of deducing them scientifically. To require such
  • a scepticism accomplished is the same as to insist on science being
  • preceded by universal doubt, or a total absence of presupposition.
  • Strictly speaking, in the resolve that _wills pure thought,_ this
  • requirement is accomplished by freedom which, abstracting from
  • everything, grasps its pure abstraction, the simplicity of thought.
  • [1] In order to judge of the greater or less extent lo which Experience
  • shows cases of Atheism or of the belief in God, it is all-important
  • to know if the mere general conception of deity suffices, or if a
  • more definite knowledge of God is required. The Christian world would
  • certainly refuse the title of God to the idols of the Hindoos and the
  • Chinese, to the fetiches of the Africans, and even to the gods of
  • Greece themselves. If so, a believer in these idols would not be a
  • believer in God. If it were contended, on the other hand, that such
  • a belief in idols implies some sort of belief in God, as the species
  • implies the genus, then idolatry would argue not faith in an idol
  • merely, but faith in God. The Athenians took an opposite view. The
  • poets and philosophers who explained Zeus to be a cloud, and maintained
  • that there was only one God, were treated as atheists at Athens.
  • The danger in these questions lies in looking at what the mind may make
  • out of an object, and not what that object actually and explicitly
  • is. If we fail to note this distinction, the commonest perceptions of
  • men's senses will be religion: for every such perception, and indeed
  • every act of mind, implicitly contains the principle which, when it
  • is purified and developed, rises to religion. But to be capable of
  • religion is one thing, to have it another. And religion yet implicit is
  • only a capacity or a possibility.
  • Thus in modern times, travellers have found tribes (as Captains Ross
  • and Parry found the Esquimaux) which, as they tell us, have not even
  • that small modicum of religion possessed by African sorcerers, the
  • _goëtes_ of Herodotus. On the other hand, an Englishman, who spent the
  • first months of the last Jubilee at Rome, says, in his account of the
  • modern Romans, that the common people are bigots, whilst those who can
  • read and write are atheists to a man.
  • The charge of Atheism is seldom heard in modern times: principally
  • because the facts and the requirements of religion are reduced to a
  • minimum. (See § 73.)
  • [2] Descartes, Princip. Phil. I. 15: _Magis hoc (ens summe perfectum
  • existere) credet, si attendat, nullius alterius rei ideam apud
  • se inveniri, in qua eodem modo necessariam existentiam contineri
  • animadveriat;--intelliget illam ideam exhibere veram et immutabilem
  • naturam, quaeque non potest non existere, cum necessaria existentia in
  • ea contineatur._ (The reader will be more disposed to _believe_ that
  • there exists a being supremely perfect, if he notes that in the case
  • of nothing else is there found in him an idea, in which he notices
  • necessary existence to be contained in the same way. He will see that
  • that idea exhibits a true and unchangeable nature,--a nature which
  • _cannot but exist,_ since necessary existence is _contained in it._) A
  • remark which immediately follows, and which sounds like mediation or
  • demonstration, does not really prejudice the original principle.
  • In Spinoza we come upon the same statement that the essence or
  • abstract conception of God implies existence. The first of Spinoza's
  • definitions, that of the _Causa Sui_ (or Self-Cause), explains it to
  • be _cujus essentia involvit existentiam, sive id cujus natura non
  • potest concipi nisi existens_ (that of which the essence involves
  • existence, or that whose nature cannot be conceived except as
  • existing). The inseparability of the notion from being is the main
  • point and fundamental hypothesis in his system. But what notion is
  • thus inseparable from being? Not the notion of finite things, for they
  • are so constituted as to have a contingent and a created existence.
  • Spinoza's 11th proposition, which follows with a proof that God exists
  • necessarily, and his 20th, showing that God's existence and his essence
  • are one and the same, are really superfluous, and the proof is more
  • in form than in reality. To say, that God is Substance, the only
  • Substance, and that, as Substance is _Causa Sui,_ God therefore exists
  • necessarily, is merely stating that God is that of which the notion and
  • the being are inseparable.
  • [3] Anselm on the contrary says: _Negligentiae mihi videtur, si
  • post-quam confirmati sumus in fide, non studemus, quod credimus,
  • intelligere._ (Methinks it is _carelessness,_ if, after we have been
  • confirmed in the faith, we do not _exert ourselves to see the meaning
  • of what we believe._) [Tractat. Cur Deus Homo?] These words of Anselm,
  • in connexion with the concrete truths of Christian doctrine, offer a
  • far harder problem for investigation, than is contemplated by this
  • modern faith.
  • CHAPTER VI.
  • LOGIC FURTHER DEFINED AND DIVIDED.
  • 79.] In point of form Logical doctrine has three sides: (α) the
  • Abstract side, or that of understanding: (_ß_) the Dialectical, or that
  • of negative reason: (y) the Speculative, or that of positive reason.
  • These three sides do not make three _parts_ of logic, but are stages
  • or 'moments' in every logical entity, that is, of every notion and
  • truth whatever. They may all be put under the first stage, that of
  • understanding, and so kept isolated from each other; but this would
  • give an inadequate conception of them.--The statement of the dividing
  • lines and the characteristic aspects of logic is at this point no more
  • than historical and anticipatory.
  • 80.] (α) Thought, as _Understanding,_ sticks to fixity of characters
  • and their distinctness from one another: every such limited abstract it
  • treats as having a subsistence and being of its own.
  • In our ordinary usage of the term thought and even notion, we often
  • have before our eyes nothing more than the operation of Understanding.
  • And no doubt thought is primarily an exercise of Understanding:--only
  • it goes further, and the notion is not a function of Understanding
  • merely. The action of Understanding may be in general described as
  • investing its subject-matter with the form of universality. But this
  • universal is an abstract universal: that is to say, its opposition to
  • the particular is so rigorously maintained, that it is at the same
  • time also reduced to the character of a particular again. In this
  • separating and abstracting attitude towards its objects, Understanding
  • is the reverse of immediate perception and sensation, which, as such,
  • keep completely to their native sphere of action in the concrete.
  • It is by referring to this opposition of Understanding to sensation or
  • feeling that we must explain the frequent attacks made upon thought
  • for being hard and narrow, and for leading, if consistently developed,
  • to ruinous and pernicious results. The answer to these charges, in so
  • far as they are warranted by their facts, is, that they do not touch
  • thinking in general, certainly not the thinking of Reason, but only the
  • exercise of Understanding. It must be added however, that the merit and
  • rights of the mere Understanding should unhesitatingly be admitted. And
  • that merit lies in the fact, that apart from Understanding there is no
  • fixity or accuracy in the region either of theory or of practice.
  • Thus, in theory, knowledge begins by apprehending existing objects in
  • their specific differences. In the study of nature, for example, we
  • distinguish matters, forces, genera and the like, and stereotype each
  • in its isolation. Thought is here acting in its analytic capacity,
  • where its canon is identity, a simple reference of each attribute to
  • itself. It is under the guidance of the same identity that the process
  • in knowledge is effected from one scientific truth to another. Thus,
  • for example, in mathematics magnitude is the feature which, to the
  • neglect of any other, determines our advance. Hence in geometry we
  • compare one figure with another, so as to bring out their identity.
  • Similarly in other fields of knowledge, such as jurisprudence, the
  • advance is primarily regulated by identity. In it we argue from one
  • specific law or precedent to another: and what is this but to proceed
  • on the principle of identity?
  • But Understanding is as indispensable in practice as it is in theory.
  • Character is an essential in conduct, and a man of character is an
  • understanding man, who in that capacity has definite ends in view and
  • undeviatingly pursues them. The man who will do something great must
  • learn, as Goethe says, to limit himself. The man who, on the contrary,
  • would do everything, really would do nothing, and fails. There is a
  • host of interesting things in the world: Spanish poetry, chemistry,
  • politics, and music are all very interesting, and if any one takes
  • an interest in them we need not find fault. But for a person in a
  • given situation to accomplish anything, he must stick to one definite
  • point, and not dissipate his' forces in many directions. In every
  • calling, too, the great thing is to pursue it with understanding. Thus
  • the judge must stick to the law, and give his verdict in accordance
  • with, it, undeterred by one motive or another, allowing no excuses;
  • and looking neither left nor right. Understanding, too, is always an
  • element in thorough training. The trained-intellect is not satisfied
  • with cloudy and indefinite impressions, but grasps the objects in their
  • fixed character: whereas the uncultivated man wavers unsettled, and it
  • often costs a deal of trouble to come to an understanding with him on
  • the matter under discussion, and to bring him to fix his eye on the
  • definite point in question.
  • It has been already explained that the Logical principle in general,
  • far from being merely a subjective action in our minds, is rather the
  • very universal, which as such is also objective. This doctrine is
  • illustrated in the case of understanding, the first form of logical
  • truths. Understanding in this larger sense corresponds to what we call
  • the goodness of God, so far as that means that finite things are and
  • subsist. In nature, for example, we recognise the goodness of God in
  • the fact that the various classes or species of animals and plants are
  • provided with whatever they need for their preservation and welfare.
  • Nor is man excepted, who, both as an individual and as a nation,
  • possesses partly in the given circumstances of climate, of quality
  • and products of soil, and partly in his natural parts or talents, all
  • that is required for his maintenance and development. Under this shape
  • Understanding is visible in every department of the objective world;
  • and no object in that world can ever be wholly perfect which does
  • not give full satisfaction to the canons of understanding. A state,
  • for example, is imperfect, so long as it has not reached a clear
  • differentiation of orders and callings, and so long as those functions
  • of politics and government, which are different in principle, have not
  • evolved for themselves special organs, in the same way as we see, for
  • example, the developed animal organism provided with separate organs
  • for the functions of sensation, motion, digestion, &c.
  • The previous course of the discussion may serve to show, that
  • understanding is indispensable even in those spheres and regions of
  • action which the popular fancy would deem furthest from it, and that in
  • proportion as understanding, is absent from them, imperfection is the
  • result. This particularly holds good of Art, Religion, and Philosophy.
  • In Art, for example, understanding is visible where the forms of
  • beauty, which differ in principle, are kept distinct and exhibited in
  • their purity. The same thing holds good also of single works of art.
  • It is part of the beauty and perfection of a dramatic poem that the
  • characters of the several persons should be closely and faithfully
  • maintained, and that the different aims and interests involved should
  • be plainly and decidedly exhibited. Or again, take the province of
  • Religion. The superiority of Greek over Northern mythology (apart from
  • other differences of subject-matter and conception) mainly consists in
  • this: that in the former the individual gods are fashioned into forms
  • of sculpture-like distinctness of outline, while in the latter the
  • figures fade away vaguely and hazily into one another. Lastly comes
  • Philosophy. That Philosophy never can get on without the understanding
  • hardly calls for special remark after what has been said. Its foremost
  • requirement is that every thought shall be grasped in its full
  • precision, and nothing allowed to remain vague and indefinite.
  • It is usually added that understanding must not go too far. Which is
  • so far correct, that understanding is not an ultimate, but on the
  • contrary finite, and so constituted that when carried to extremes it
  • veers round to its opposite. It is the fashion of youth to dash about
  • in abstractions: but the man who has learnt to know life steers clear
  • of the abstract 'either--or,' and keeps to the concrete.
  • 81.] (ß) In the Dialectical stage these finite characterisations or
  • formulae supersede themselves, and pass into their opposites.
  • (1) But when the Dialectical principle is employed by the understanding
  • separately and independently,--especially as seen in its application
  • to philosophical theories, Dialectic becomes Scepticism; in which the
  • result that ensues from its action is presented as a mere negation.
  • (2) It is customary to treat Dialectic as an adventitious art, which
  • for very wantonness introduces confusion and a mere semblance of
  • contradiction into definite notions. And in that light, the semblance
  • is the nonentity, while the true reality is supposed to belong to the
  • original dicta of understanding. Often, indeed, Dialectic is nothing
  • more than a subjective see-saw of arguments _pro_ and _con,_ where
  • the absence of sterling thought is disguised by the subtlety which
  • gives birth to such arguments. But in its true and proper character.
  • Dialectic is the very nature and essence of everything predicated by
  • mere understanding,--the law of things and of the finite as a whole.
  • Dialectic is different from 'Reflection.' In the first instance,
  • Reflection is that movement out beyond the isolated predicate of a
  • thing which gives it some reference, and brings out its relativity,
  • while still in other respects leaving it its isolated validity. But
  • by Dialectic is meant the in-dwelling tendency outwards by which the
  • one-sidedness and limitation of the predicates of understanding is seen
  • in its true light, and shown to be the negation of them. For anything
  • to be finite is just to suppress itself and put itself aside. Thus
  • understood the Dialectical principle constitutes the life and soul of
  • scientific progress, the dynamic which alone gives immanent connexion
  • and necessity to the body of science; and, in a word, is seen to
  • constitute the real and true, as opposed to the external, exaltation
  • above the finite.
  • (1) It is of the highest importance to ascertain and understand rightly
  • the nature of Dialectic. Wherever there is movement, wherever there is
  • life, wherever anything is carried into effect in the actual world,
  • there Dialectic is at work. It is also the soul of all knowledge
  • which is truly scientific. In the popular way of looking at things,
  • the refusal to be bound by the abstract deliverances of understanding
  • appears as fairness, which, according to the proverb Live and let
  • live, demands that each should have its turn; we admit the one, but
  • we admit the other also. But when we look more closely, we find that
  • the limitations of the finite do not merely come from without; that
  • its own nature is the cause of its abrogation, and that by its own
  • act it passes into its counterpart. We say, for instance, that man is
  • mortal, and seem to think that the ground of his death is in external
  • circumstances only; so that if this way of looking were correct, man
  • would have two special properties, vitality and--also--mortality. But
  • the true view of the matter is that life, as life, involves the germ
  • of death, and that the finite, being radically self-contradictory,
  • involves its own self-suppression.
  • Nor, again, is Dialectic to be confounded with mere Sophistry. The
  • essence of Sophistry lies in giving authority to a partial and abstract
  • principle, in its isolation, as may suit the interest and particular
  • situation of the individual at the time. For example, a regard to my
  • existence, and my having the means of existence, is a vital motive
  • of conduct, but if I exclusively emphasise this consideration or
  • motive of my welfare, and draw the conclusion that I may steal or
  • betray my country, we have a case of Sophistry. Similarly, it is a
  • vital principle in conduct that I should be subjectively free, that
  • is to say, that I should have an insight into what I am doing, and
  • a conviction that it is right. But if my pleading insists on this
  • principle alone I fall into Sophistry, such as would overthrow all the
  • principles of morality. From this sort of party-pleading Dialectic is
  • wholly different; its purpose is to study things in their own being and
  • movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories
  • of understanding.
  • Dialectic, it may be added, is no novelty in philosophy. Among the
  • ancients Plato is termed the inventor of Dialectic; and his right to
  • the name rests on the fact, that the Platonic philosophy first gave
  • the free scientific, and thus at the same time the objective, form to
  • Dialectic. Socrates, as we should expect from the general character
  • of his philosophising, has the dialectical element in a predominantly
  • subjective shape, that of Irony. He used to turn his Dialectic,
  • first against ordinary consciousness, and then especially against
  • the Sophists. In his conversations he used to simulate the wish for
  • some clearer knowledge about the subject under discussion, and after
  • putting all sorts of questions with that intent, he drew on those with
  • whom he conversed to the opposite of what their first impressions
  • had pronounced correct. If, for instance, the Sophists claimed to
  • be teachers, Socrates by a series of questions forced the Sophist
  • Protagoras to confess that all learning is only recollection. In his
  • more strictly scientific dialogues Plato employs the dialectical method
  • to show the finitude of all hard and fast terms of understanding.
  • Thus in the Parmenides he deduces the many from the one, and shows
  • nevertheless that the many cannot but define itself as the one. In
  • this grand style did Plato treat Dialectic. In modern times it was,
  • more than any other, Kant who resuscitated the name of Dialectic, and
  • restored it to its post of honour. He did it, as we have seen (§ 48),
  • by working out the Antinomies of the reason. The problem of these
  • Antinomies is no mere subjective piece of work oscillating between
  • one set of grounds and another; it really serves to show that every
  • abstract proposition of understanding, taken precisely as it is given,
  • naturally veers round into its opposite.
  • However reluctant Understanding may be to admit the action of
  • Dialectic, we must not suppose that the recognition if its existence
  • is peculiarly confined to the philosopher. It would be truer to say
  • that Dialectic gives expression to a law which is felt in all other
  • grades of consciousness, and in general experience. Everything that
  • surrounds us may be viewed as an instance of Dialectic. We are aware
  • that everything finite, instead of being stable and ultimate, is rather
  • changeable and transient; and this is exactly what we mean by that
  • Dialectic of the finite, by which the finite, as implicitly other than
  • what it is, is forced beyond its own immediate or natural being to
  • turn suddenly into its opposite. We have before this (§ 80) identified
  • Understanding with what is implied in the popular idea of the goodness
  • of God; we may now remark of Dialectic, in the same objective
  • signification, that its principle answers to the idea of his power.
  • All things, we say,--that is, the finite world as such,--are doomed;
  • and in saying so, we have a vision of Dialectic as the universal and
  • irresistible power before which nothing can stay, however secure and
  • stable it may deem itself. The category of power does not, it is true,
  • exhaust the depth of the divine nature or the notion of God; but it
  • certainly forms a vital element in all religious consciousness.
  • Apart from this general objectivity of Dialectic, we find traces of its
  • presence in each of the particular provinces and phases of the natural
  • and the spiritual world. Take as an illustration the motion of the
  • heavenly bodies. At this moment the planet stands in this spot, but
  • implicitly it is the possibility of being in another spot; and that
  • possibility of being otherwise the planet brings into existence by
  • moving. Similarly the 'physical' elements prove to be Dialectical. The
  • process of meteorological action is the exhibition of their Dialectic.
  • It is the same dynamic that lies at the root of every other natural
  • process, and, as it were, forces nature out of itself. To illustrate
  • the presence of Dialectic in the spiritual world, especially in the
  • provinces of law and morality, we have only to recollect how general
  • experience shows us the extreme of one state or action suddenly
  • shifting into its opposite: a Dialectic which is recognised in many
  • ways in common proverbs. Thus _summum jus summa injuria:_ which means,
  • that to drive an abstract right to its extremity is to do a wrong.
  • In political life, as every one knows, extreme anarchy and extreme
  • despotism naturally lead to one another. The perception of Dialectic
  • in the province of individual Ethics is seen in the well-known adages,
  • Pride comes before a fall: Too much wit outwits itself. Even feeling,
  • bodily as well as mental, has its Dialectic. Every one knows how
  • the extremes of pain and pleasure pass into each other: the heart
  • overflowing with joy seeks relief in tears, and the deepest melancholy
  • will at times betray its presence by a smile.
  • (2) Scepticism should not be looked upon merely as a doctrine of doubt.
  • It would be more correct to say that the Sceptic has no doubt of his
  • point, which is the nothingness of all finite existence. He who only
  • doubts still clings to the hope that his doubt may be resolved, and
  • that one or other of the definite views, between which he wavers,
  • will turn out solid and true. Scepticism properly so called is a
  • very different thing: it is complete hopelessness about all which
  • understanding counts stable, and the feeling to which it gives birth
  • is one of unbroken calmness and inward repose. Such at least is the
  • noble Scepticism of antiquity, especially as exhibited in the writings
  • of Sextus Empiricus, when in the later times of Rome it had been
  • systematised as a complement to the dogmatic systems of Stoic and
  • Epicurean. Of far other stamp, and to be strictly distinguished from
  • it, is the modern Scepticism already mentioned § (39), which partly
  • preceded the Critical Philosophy, and partly sprung out of it. That
  • later Scepticism consisted solely in denying the truth and certitude
  • of the super-sensible, and in pointing to the facts of sense and of
  • immediate sensations as what we have to keep to.
  • Even to this day Scepticism is often spoken of as the irresistible
  • enemy of all positive knowledge, and hence of philosophy, in so far
  • as philosophy is concerned with positive knowledge. But in these
  • statements there is a misconception. It is only the finite thought
  • of abstract understanding which has to fear Scepticism, because
  • unable to withstand it: philosophy includes the sceptical principle
  • as a subordinate function of its own, in the shape of Dialectic. In
  • contradistinction to mere Scepticism, however, philosophy does not
  • remain content with the purely negative result of Dialectic. The
  • sceptic mistakes the true value of his result, when he supposes it to
  • be no more than a negation pure and simple. For the negative, which
  • emerges as the result of dialectic, is, because a result, at the same
  • time the positive: it contains what it results from, absorbed into
  • itself, and made part of its own nature. Thus conceived, however, the
  • dialectical stage has the features characterising the third grade of
  • logical truth, the speculative form, or form of positive reason.
  • 82.] (y) The Speculative stage, or stage of Positive Reason,
  • apprehends the unity of terms (propositions) in their opposition,--the
  • affirmative, which is involved in their disintegration and in their
  • transition.
  • (1) The result of Dialectic is positive, because it has a definite
  • content, or because its result is not empty and abstract nothing, but
  • the negation of certain specific propositions which are contained in
  • the result,--for the very reason that it is a resultant and not an
  • immediate nothing. (2) It follows from this that the 'reasonable'
  • result, though it be only a thought and abstract, is still a concrete,
  • being not a plain formal unity, but a unity of distinct propositions.
  • Bare abstractions or formal thoughts are therefore no business of
  • philosophy, which has to deal only with concrete thoughts. (3) The
  • logic of mere Understanding is involved in Speculative logic, and
  • can at will be elicited from it, by the simple process of omitting
  • the dialectical and 'reasonable' element. When that is done, it
  • becomes what the common logic is, a descriptive collection of sundry
  • thought-forms and rules which, finite though they are, are taken to be
  • something infinite.
  • If we consider only what it contains, and not how it contains it,
  • the true reason-world, so far from being the exclusive property of
  • philosophy, is the right of every human being on whatever grade of
  • culture or mental growth he may stand; which would justify man's
  • ancient title of rational being. The general mode by which experience
  • first makes us aware of the reasonable order of things is by accepted
  • and unreasoned belief; and the character of the rational, as already
  • noted (§ 45), is to be unconditioned, and thus to be self-contained,
  • self-determining. In this sense man above all things becomes aware of
  • the reasonable order, when he knows of God, and knows Him to be the
  • completely self-determined. Similarly, the consciousness a citizen has
  • of his country and its laws is a perception of the reason-world, so
  • long as he looks up to them as unconditioned and likewise universal
  • powers, to which he must subject his individual will. And in the same
  • sense, the knowledge and will of the child is rational, when he knows
  • his parents' will, and wills it.
  • Now, to turn these rational (of course positively-rational) realities
  • into speculative principles, the only thing needed is that they be
  • _thought._ The expression 'Speculation' in common life is often used
  • with a very vague and at the same time secondary sense, as when we
  • speak of a matrimonial or a commercial speculation. By this we only
  • mean two things: first, that what is immediately at hand has to be
  • passed and left behind; and secondly, that the subject-matter of such
  • speculations, though in the first place only subjective, must not
  • remain so, but be realised or translated into objectivity.
  • What was some time ago remarked respecting the Idea, may be applied
  • to this common usage of the term 'speculation': and we may add that
  • people who rank themselves amongst the educated expressly speak of
  • speculation even as if it were something purely subjective. A certain
  • theory of some conditions and circumstances of nature or mind may be,
  • say these people, very fine and correct as a matter of speculation,
  • but it contradicts experience and nothing of the sort is admissible in
  • reality. To this the answer is, that the speculative is in its true
  • signification, neither preliminarily nor even definitively, something
  • merely subjective: that, on the contrary, it expressly rises above
  • such oppositions as that between subjective and objective, which the
  • understanding cannot get over, and absorbing them in itself, evinces
  • its own concrete and all-embracing nature. A one-sided proposition
  • therefore can never even give expression to a speculative truth. If
  • we say, for example, that the absolute is the unity of subjective and
  • objective, we are undoubtedly in the right, but so far one-sided, as we
  • enunciate the unity only and lay the accent upon it, forgetting that in
  • reality the subjective and objective are not merely identical but also
  • distinct.
  • Speculative truth, it may also be noted, means very much the same as
  • what, in special connexion with religious experience and doctrines,
  • used to be called Mysticism. The term Mysticism is at present used,
  • as a rule, to designate what is mysterious and incomprehensible: and
  • in proportion as their general culture and way of thinking vary, the
  • epithet is applied by one class to denote the real and the true, by
  • another to name everything connected with superstition and deception.
  • On which we first of all remark that there is mystery in the mystical,
  • only however for the understanding which is ruled by the principle
  • of abstract identity; whereas the mystical, as synonymous with the
  • speculative, is the concrete unity of those propositions, which
  • understanding only accepts in their separation and opposition. And if
  • those who recognise Mysticism as the highest truth are content to leave
  • it in its original utter mystery, their conduct only proves that for
  • them too, as well as for their antagonists, thinking means abstract
  • identification, and that in their opinion, therefore, truth can only be
  • won by renouncing thought, or as it is frequently expressed, by leading
  • the reason captive. But, as we have seen, the abstract thinking of
  • understanding is so far from being either ultimate or stable, that it
  • shows a perpetual tendency to work its own dissolution and swing round
  • into its opposite. Reasonableness, on the contrary, just, consists in
  • embracing within itself these opposites as unsubstantial elements. Thus
  • the reason-world may be equally styled mystical,--not however because
  • thought cannot both reach and comprehend it, but merely because it lies
  • beyond the compass of understanding.
  • 83.] Logic is subdivided into three parts:--
  • I. The Doctrine of Being:
  • II. The Doctrine of Essence:
  • III. The Doctrine of Notion and Idea.
  • That is, into the Theory of Thought:
  • I. In its immediacy: the notion implicit and in germ.
  • II. In its reflection and mediation: the being-for-self and show of the
  • notion.
  • III. In its return into itself, and its developed abiding by itself:
  • the notion in and for itself.
  • The division of Logic now given, as well as the whole of the previous
  • discussion on the nature of thought, is anticipatory: and the
  • justification, or proof of it, can only result from the detailed
  • treatment of thought itself. For in philosophy, to prove means to
  • show how the subject by and from itself makes itself what it is. The
  • relation in which these three leading grades of thought, or of the
  • logical Idea, stand to each other must be conceived as follows. Truth
  • comes only with the notion: or, more precisely, the notion is the
  • truth of being and essence, both of which, when separately maintained
  • in their isolation, cannot but be untrue, the former because it is
  • exclusively immediate, and the latter because it is exclusively
  • mediate. Why then, it may be asked, begin with the false and not at
  • once with the true? To which we answer that truth, to deserve the name,
  • must authenticate its own truth: which authentication, here within the
  • sphere of logic, is given, when the notion demonstrates itself to be
  • what is mediated by and with itself, and thus at the same time to be
  • truly immediate. This relation between the three stages of the logical
  • Idea appears in a real and concrete shape thus: God, who is the truth,
  • is known by us in His truth, that is, as absolute spirit, only in so
  • far as we at the same time recognise that the world which He created,
  • nature and the finite spirit, are, in their difference from God,
  • untrue.
  • CHAPTER VII.
  • FIRST SUB-DIVISION OF LOGIC.
  • THE DOCTRINE OF BEING.
  • 84.] Being is the notion implicit only: its special forms have the
  • predicate 'is'; when they are distinguished they are each of them an
  • 'other': and the shape which dialectic takes in them, _i.e._ their
  • further specialisation, is a passing over into another. This further
  • determination, or specialisation, is at once a forth-putting and in
  • that way a disengaging of the notion implicit in being; and at the
  • same time the withdrawing of being inwards, its sinking deeper into
  • itself. Thus the explication of the notion in the sphere of being does
  • two things: it brings out the totality of being, and it abolishes the
  • immediacy of being, or the form of being as such.
  • 85.] Being itself and the special sub-categories of it which
  • follow, as well as those of logic in general, may be looked upon as
  • definitions of the Absolute, or metaphysical definitions of God: at
  • least the first and third category in every triad may,--the first,
  • where the thought-form of the triad is formulated in its simplicity,
  • and the third, being the return from differentiation to a simple
  • self-reference. For a metaphysical definition of God is the expression
  • of His nature in thoughts as such: and logic embraces all thoughts so
  • long as they continue in the thought-form. The second sub-category in
  • each triad, where the grade of thought is in its differentiation,
  • gives, on the other hand, a definition of the finite. The objection to
  • the form of definition is that it implies a something in the mind's eye
  • on which these predicates may fasten. Thus even the Absolute (though
  • it purports to express God in the style and character of thought) in
  • comparison with its predicate (which really and distinctly expresses
  • in thought what the subject does not), is as yet only an inchoate
  • pretended thought--the indeterminate subject of predicates yet to
  • come. The thought, which is here the matter of sole importance, is
  • contained only in the predicate: and hence the propositional form, like
  • the said subject, viz. the Absolute, is a mere superfluity (cf. § 31,
  • and below, on the Judgment).
  • Each of the three spheres of the logical idea proves to be a systematic
  • whole of thought-terms, and a phase of the Absolute. This is the case
  • with Being, containing the three grades of quality, quantity, and
  • measure. Quality is, in the first place, the character identical with
  • being: so identical, that a thing ceases to be what it is, if it loses
  • its quality. Quantity, on the contrary, is the character external
  • to being, and does not affect the being at all. Thus _e.g._ a house
  • remains what it is, whether it be greater or smaller; and red remains
  • red, whether it be brighter or darker. Measure, the third grade of
  • being, which is the unity of the first two, is a qualitative quantity.
  • All things have their measure: _i.e._ the quantitative terms of their
  • existence, their being so or so great, does not matter within certain
  • limits; but when these limits are exceeded by an additional more or
  • less, the things cease to be what they were. From measure follows the
  • advance to the second sub-division of the idea, Essence.
  • The three forms of being here mentioned, just because they are the
  • first, are also the poorest, _i.e._ the most abstract. Immediate
  • (sensible) consciousness, in so far as it simultaneously includes
  • an intellectual element, is especially restricted to the abstract
  • categories of quality and quantity. The sensuous consciousness is in
  • ordinary estimation the most concrete and thus also the richest; but
  • that is only true as regards materials, whereas, in reference to the
  • thought it contains, it is really the poorest and most abstract.
  • A.--QUALITY.
  • (a) Being.
  • 86.] Pure Being makes the beginning: because it is on one hand pure
  • thought, and on the other immediacy itself, simple and indeterminate;
  • and the first beginning cannot be mediated by anything, or be further
  • determined.
  • All doubts and admonitions, which might be brought against beginning
  • the science with abstract empty being, will disappear, if we only
  • perceive what a beginning naturally implies. It is possible to define
  • being as 'I = I,' as 'Absolute Indifference' or Identity, and so on.
  • Where it is felt necessary to begin either with what is absolutely
  • certain, _i.e._ the certainty of oneself, or with a definition or
  • intuition of the absolute truth, these and other forms of the kind
  • may be looked on as if they must be the first. But each of these
  • forms contains a mediation, and hence cannot be the real first: for
  • all mediation implies advance made from a first on to a second, and
  • proceeding from something different. If I = I, or even the intellectual
  • intuition, are really taken to mean no more than the first, they are in
  • this mere immediacy identical with being: while conversely, pure being,
  • if abstract no longer, but including in it mediation, is pure thought
  • or intuition.
  • If we enunciate Being as a predicate of the Absolute, we get the first
  • definition of the latter. The Absolute is Being. This is (in thought)
  • the absolutely initial definition, the most abstract and stinted.
  • It is the definition given by the Eleatics, but at the same time is
  • also the well-known definition of God as the sum of all realities. It
  • means, in short, that we are to set aside that limitation which is in
  • every reality, so that God shall be only the real in all reality, the
  • superlatively real. Or, if we reject reality, as implying a reflection,
  • we get a more immediate or unreflected statement of the same thing,
  • when Jacobi says that the God of Spinoza is the _principium_ of being
  • in all existence.
  • (1) When thinking is to begin, we have nothing but thought in its
  • merest indeterminateness: for we cannot determine unless there is
  • both one and another; and in the beginning there is yet no other. The
  • indeterminate, as we here have it, is the blank we begin with, not a
  • featurelessness reached by abstraction, not the elimination of all
  • character, but the original featurelessness which precedes all definite
  • character and is the very first of all. And this we call Being. It is
  • not to be felt, or perceived by sense, or pictured in imagination:
  • it is only and merely thought, and as such it forms the beginning.
  • Essence also is indeterminate, but in another sense: it has traversed
  • the process of mediation and contains implicit the determination it has
  • absorbed.
  • (2) In the history of philosophy the different stages of the logical
  • Idea assume the shape of successive systems, each based on a particular
  • definition of the Absolute. As the logical Idea is seen to unfold
  • itself in a process from the abstract to the concrete, so in the
  • history of philosophy the earliest systems are the most abstract, and
  • thus at the same time the poorest. The relation too of the earlier
  • to the later; systems of philosophy is much like the relation of the
  • corresponding stages of the logical Idea: in other words, the earlier
  • are preserved in the later; but subordinated and submerged. This is
  • the true meaning of a much misunderstood phenomenon in the history of
  • philosophy--the refutation of one system by another, of an earlier by
  • a later. Most commonly the refutation is taken in a purely negative
  • sense to mean that the system refuted has ceased to count for anything,
  • has been set aside and done for. Were it so, the history of philosophy
  • would be of all studies most saddening, displaying, as it does,
  • the refutation of every system which time has brought forth. Now,
  • although it may be admitted that every philosophy has been refuted,
  • it must be in an equal degree maintained, that no philosophy has been
  • refuted, nay, or can be refuted. And that in two ways. For first,
  • every philosophy that deserves the name always embodies the Idea: and
  • secondly, every system represents one particular factor or particular
  • stage in the evolution of the Idea. The refutation of a philosophy,
  • therefore, only means that its barriers are crossed, and its special
  • principle reduced to a factor in the completer principle that follows.
  • Thus the history of philosophy, in its true meaning, deals not with a
  • past, but with an eternal and veritable present: and, in its results,
  • resembles not a museum of the aberrations of the human intellect,
  • but a Pantheon of Godlike figures. These figures of Gods are the
  • various stages of the Idea, as they come forward one after another in
  • dialectical development. To the historian of philosophy it belongs to
  • point out more precisely, how far the gradual evolution of his theme
  • coincides with, or swerves from, the dialectical unfolding of the pure
  • logical Idea. It is sufficient to mention here, that logic begins
  • where the proper history of philosophy begins. Philosophy began in the
  • Eleatic school, especially with Parmenides. Parmenides, who conceives
  • the absolute as Being, says that 'Being alone is and Nothing is not.'
  • Such was the true starting-point of philosophy, which is always
  • knowledge by thought: and here for the first time we find pure thought
  • seized and made an object to itself.
  • Men indeed thought from the beginning: (for thus only were they
  • distinguished from the animals). But thousands of years had to elapse
  • before they came to apprehend thought in its purity, and to see in it
  • the truly objective. The Eleatics are celebrated as daring thinkers.
  • But this nominal admiration is often accompanied by the remark that
  • they went too far, when they made Being alone true, and denied the
  • truth of every other object of consciousness. We must go further than
  • mere Being, it is true: and yet it is absurd to speak of the other
  • contents of our consciousness as somewhat as it were outside and beside
  • Being, or to say that there are other things, as well as Being. The
  • true state of the case is rather as follows. Being, as Being, is
  • nothing fixed or ultimate: it yields to dialectic and sinks into its
  • opposite, which, also taken immediately, is Nothing. After all, the
  • point is, that Being is the first pure Thought; whatever else you may
  • begin with (the I = I, the absolute indifference, or God Himself),
  • you begin with a figure of materialised conception, not a product of
  • thought; and that, so far as its thought content is concerned, such
  • beginning is merely Being.
  • 87.] But this mere Being, as it is mere abstraction, is therefore the
  • absolutely negative: which, in a similarly immediate aspect, is just
  • Nothing.
  • (1) Hence was derived the second definition of the Absolute; the
  • Absolute is the Nought. In fact this definition is implied in saying
  • that the thing-in-itself is the indeterminate, utterly without form
  • and so without content,--or in saying that God is only the supreme
  • Being and nothing more; for this is really declaring Him to be the same
  • negativity as above. The Nothing which the Buddhists make the universal
  • principle, as well as the final aim and goal of everything, is the same
  • abstraction.
  • (2) If the opposition in thought is stated in this immediacy as Being
  • and Nothing, the shock of its nullity is too great not to stimulate
  • the attempt to fix Being and secure it against the transition into
  • Nothing. With this intent, reflection has recourse to the plan of
  • discovering some fixed predicate for Being, to mark it off from
  • Nothing. Thus we find Being identified with what persists amid all
  • change, with _matter,_ susceptible of innumerable determinations,--or
  • even, unreflectingly, with a single existence, any chance object of
  • the senses or of the mind. But every additional and more concrete
  • characterisation causes Being to lose that integrity and simplicity it
  • has in the beginning. Only in, and by virtue of, this mere generality
  • is it Nothing, something inexpressible, whereof the distinction from
  • Nothing is a mere intention or _meaning._
  • All that is wanted is to realise that these beginnings are nothing but
  • these empty abstractions, one as empty as the other. The instinct that
  • induces us to attach a settled import to Being, or to both, is the very
  • necessity which leads to the onward movement of Being and Nothing,
  • and gives them a true or concrete significance. This advance is the
  • logical deduction and the movement of thought exhibited in the sequel.
  • The reflection which finds a profounder connotation for Being and
  • Nothing is nothing but logical thought, through which such connotation
  • is evolved, not, however, in an accidental, but a necessary way. Every
  • signification, therefore, in which they afterwards appear, is only a
  • more precise specification and truer definition of the Absolute. And
  • when that is done, the mere abstract Being and Nothing are replaced
  • by a concrete in which both these elements form an organic part.--The
  • supreme form of Nought as a separate principle would be Freedom: but
  • Freedom is negativity in that stage, when it sinks self-absorbed to
  • supreme intensity, and is itself an affirmation, and even absolute
  • affirmation.
  • The distinction between Being and Nought is, in the first place,
  • only implicit, and not yet actually made: they only _ought_ to be
  • distinguished. A distinction of course implies two things, and that one
  • of them possesses an attribute which is not found in the other. Being
  • however is an absolute absence of attributes, and so is Nought. Hence
  • the distinction between the two is only meant to be; it is a quite
  • nominal distinction, which is at the same time no distinction. In all
  • other cases of difference there is some common point which comprehends
  • both things. Suppose _e.g._ we speak of two different species: the
  • genus forms a common ground for both. But in the case of mere Being and
  • Nothing, distinction is without a bottom to stand upon: hence there can
  • be no distinction, both determinations being the same bottomlessness.
  • If it be replied that Being and Nothing are both of them thoughts, so
  • that thought may be reckoned common ground, the objector forgets that
  • Being is not a particular or definite thought, and hence, being quite
  • indeterminate, is a thought not to be distinguished from Nothing.--It
  • is natural too for us to represent Being as absolute riches, and
  • Nothing as absolute poverty. But if when we view the whole world we
  • can only say that everything _is,_ and nothing more, we are neglecting
  • all speciality and, instead of absolute plenitude, we have absolute
  • emptiness. The same stricture is applicable to those who define God
  • to be mere Being; a definition not a whit better than that of the
  • Buddhists, who make God to be Nought, and who from that principle draw
  • the further conclusion that self-annihilation is the means by which man
  • becomes God.
  • 88.] Nothing, if it be thus immediate and equal to itself, is also
  • conversely the same as Being is. The truth of Being and of Nothing is
  • accordingly the unity of the two: and this unity is Becoming.
  • (1) The proposition that Being and Nothing is the same seems so
  • paradoxical to the imagination or understanding, that it is perhaps
  • taken for a joke. And indeed it is one of the hardest things thought
  • expects itself to do: for Being and Nothing exhibit the fundamental
  • contrast in all its immediacy,--that is, without the one term being
  • invested with any attribute which would involve its connexion with
  • the other. This attribute however, as the above paragraph points out,
  • is implicit in them--the attribute which is just the same in both. So
  • far the deduction of their unity is completely analytical: indeed the
  • whole progress of philosophising in every case, if it be a methodical,
  • that is to say a necessary, progress, merely renders explicit what
  • is implicit in a notion.--It is as correct however to say that Being
  • and Nothing are altogether different, as to assert their unity. The
  • one is _not_ what the other is. But since the distinction has not at
  • this point assumed definite shape (Being and Nothing are still the
  • immediate), it is, in the way that they have it, something unutterable,
  • which we merely _mean._
  • (2) No great expenditure of wit is needed to make fun of the maxim that
  • Being and Nothing are the same, or rather to adduce absurdities which,
  • it is erroneously asserted, are the consequences and illustrations of
  • that maxim.
  • If Being and Nought are identical, say these objectors, it follows that
  • it makes no difference whether my home, my property, the air I breathe,
  • this city, the sun, the law, mind, God, are or are not. Now in some of
  • these cases, the objectors foist in private aims, the utility a thing
  • has for me, and then ask, whether it be all the same to me if the
  • thing exist and if it do not. For that matter indeed, the teaching of
  • philosophy is precisely what frees man from the endless crowd of finite
  • aims and intentions, by making him so insensible to them, that their
  • existence or non-existence is to him a matter of indifference. But it
  • is never to be forgotten that, once mention something substantial, and
  • you thereby create a connexion with other existences and other purposes
  • which are _ex hypothesi_ worth having: and on such hypothesis it comes
  • to depend whether the Being and not-Being of a determinate subject are
  • the same or not. A substantial distinction is in these cases secretly
  • substituted for the empty distinction of Being and Nought. In others
  • of the cases referred to, it is virtually absolute existences and
  • vital ideas and aims, which are placed under the mere category of
  • Being or not-Being. But there is more to be said of these concrete
  • objects, than that they merely are or are not. Barren abstractions,
  • like Being and Nothing--the initial categories which, for that reason,
  • are the scantiest anywhere to be found--are utterly inadequate to
  • the nature of these objects. Substantial truth is something far
  • above these abstractions and their oppositions.--And always when a
  • concrete existence is disguised under the name of Being and not-Being,
  • empty-headedness makes its usual mistake of speaking about, and having
  • in the mind an image of, something else than what is in question: and
  • in this place the question is about abstract Being and Nothing.
  • (3) It may perhaps be said that nobody can form a notion of the
  • unity of Being and Nought. As for that, the notion of the unity is
  • stated in the sections preceding, and that is all: apprehend that,
  • and you have comprehended this unity. What the objector really means
  • by comprehension--by a notion--is more than his language properly
  • implies: he wants a richer and more complex state of mind, a pictorial
  • conception which will propound the notion as a concrete case and one
  • more familiar to the ordinary operations of thought. And so long as
  • incomprehensibility means only the want of habituation for the effort
  • needed to grasp an abstract thought, free from all sensuous admixture,
  • and to seize a speculative truth, the reply to the criticism is, that
  • philosophical knowledge is undoubtedly distinct in kind from the
  • mode of knowledge best known in common life, as well as from that
  • which reigns in the other sciences. But if to have no notion merely
  • means that we cannot represent in imagination the oneness of Being
  • and Nought, the statement is far from being true; for every one has
  • countless ways of envisaging this unity. To say that we have no such
  • conception can only mean, that in none of these images do we recognise
  • the notion in question, and that we are not aware that they exemplify
  • it. The readiest example of it is Becoming.; Every one has a mental
  • idea of Becoming, and will even allow that it is _one_ idea: he will
  • further allow that, when it is analysed, it involves the attribute
  • of Being, and also what is the very reverse of Being, viz. Nothing:
  • and that these two attributes lie undivided in the one idea: so that
  • Becoming is the unity of Being and Nothing.--Another tolerably plain
  • example is a Beginning. In its beginning, the thing is not yet, but
  • it is more than merely nothing, for its Being is already in the
  • beginning. Beginning is itself a case of Becoming; only the former term
  • is employed with an eye to the further advance.--If we were to adapt
  • logic to the more usual method of the sciences, we might start with the
  • representation of a Beginning as abstractly thought, or with Beginning
  • as such, and then analyse this representation, and perhaps people
  • would more readily admit, as a result of this analysis, that Being and
  • Nothing present themselves as undivided in unity.
  • (4) It remains to note that such phrases as 'Being and Nothing are
  • the same,' or 'The unity of Being and Nothing'--like all other
  • such unities, that of subject and object, and others--give rise to
  • reasonable objection. They misrepresent the facts, by giving an
  • exclusive prominence to the unity, and leaving the difference which
  • undoubtedly exists in it (because it is Being and Nothing, for example,
  • the unity of which is declared) without any express mention or notice.
  • It accordingly seems as if the diversity had been unduly put out of
  • court and neglected. The fact is, no speculative principle can be
  • correctly expressed by any such propositional form, for the unity has
  • to be conceived _in_ the diversity, which is all the while present and
  • explicit. 'To become' is the true expression for the resultant of 'To
  • be' and 'Not to be'; it is the unity of the two; but not only is it
  • the unity, it is also inherent unrest,--the unity, which is no mere
  • reference-to-self and therefore without movement, but which, through
  • the diversity of Being and Nothing that is in it, is at war within
  • itself.--Determinate being, on the other hand, is this unity, or
  • Becoming in this form of unity: hence all that 'is there and so,' is
  • one-sided and finite. The opposition between the two factors seems to
  • have vanished; it is only implied in the unity, it is not explicitly
  • put in it.
  • (5) The maxim of Becoming, that Being is the passage into Nought,
  • and Nought the passage into Being, is controverted by the maxim of
  • Pantheism, the doctrine of the eternity of matter, that from nothing
  • comes nothing, and that something can only come out of something. The
  • ancients saw plainly that the maxim, 'From nothing comes nothing,
  • from something something,' really abolishes Becoming: for what it
  • comes from and what it becomes are one and the same. Thus explained,
  • the proposition is the maxim of abstract identity as upheld by the
  • understanding. It cannot but seem strange, therefore, to hear such
  • maxims as, 'Out of nothing comes nothing: Out of something comes
  • something,' calmly taught in these days, without the teacher being in
  • the least aware that they are the basis of Pantheism, and even without
  • his knowing that the ancients have exhausted all that is to be said
  • about them.
  • Becoming is the first concrete thought, and therefore the first
  • notion: whereas Being and Nought are empty abstractions. The notion
  • of Being, therefore, of which we sometimes speak, must mean Becoming;
  • not the mere point of Being, which is empty Nothing, any more than
  • Nothing, which is empty Being. In Being then we have Nothing, and in
  • Nothing Being: but this Being which does not lose itself in Nothing
  • is Becoming. Nor must we omit the distinction, while we emphasise the
  • unity of Becoming: without that distinction we should once more return
  • to abstract Being. Becoming is only the explicit statement of what
  • Being is in its truth.
  • We often hear it maintained that thought is opposed to being. Now in
  • the face of such a statement, our first question ought to be, what is
  • meant by being. If we understand being as it is defined by reflection,
  • all that we can say of it is that it is what is wholly identical and
  • affirmative. And if we then look at thought, it cannot escape us that
  • thought also is at least what is absolutely identical with itself. Both
  • I therefore, being as well as thought, have the same attribute.
  • This identity of being and thought is not however to be I taken in
  • a concrete sense, as if we could say that a stone, so far as it has
  • being, is the same as a thinking man. A concrete thing is always very
  • different from the abstract category as such. And in the case of being,
  • we are speaking of nothing concrete: for being is the utterly abstract.
  • So far then the question regarding the _being_ of God--a being which is
  • in itself concrete above all measure--is of slight importance.
  • As the first concrete thought-term, Becoming is the first adequate
  • vehicle of truth. In the history of philosophy, this stage of the
  • logical Idea finds its analogue in the system of Heraclitus. When
  • Heraclitus says 'All is flowing' (πάντα ῥεῖ), he enunciates Becoming
  • as the fundamental feature of all existence, whereas the Eleatics,
  • as already remarked, saw the only truth in Being, rigid processless
  • Being. Glancing at the principle of the Eleatics, Heraclitus then goes
  • on to say: Being no more is than not-Being (οὐδὲν μᾶλλon τὸ όν τοῦ μὴ
  • ὅντos ἐστί): a statement expressing the negativity of abstract Being,
  • and its identity with not-Being, as made explicit in Becoming: both
  • abstractions being alike untenable. This maybe looked at as an instance
  • of the real refutation of one system by another. To refute a Philosophy
  • is to exhibit the dialectical movement in its principle, and thus
  • reduce it to a constituent member of a higher concrete form of the?
  • Idea. Even Becoming however, taken at its best on its own ground, is an
  • extremely poor term: it needs to grow in depth and weight of meaning.
  • Such deepened force we find _e.g._ in Life. Life is a Becoming; but
  • that is not enough to exhaust the notion of life. A still higher form
  • is found in Mind. Here too is Becoming, but richer and more intensive
  • than mere logical Becoming. The elements, whose unity constitutes
  • mind, are not the bare abstracts of Being and of Nought, but the system
  • of the logical Idea and of Nature.
  • (b) _Being Determinate._
  • 89.] In Becoming the Being which is one with Nothing, and the Nothing
  • which is one with Being, are only vanishing factors; they are and
  • they are not. Thus by its inherent contradiction Becoming collapses
  • into the unity in which the two elements are absorbed. This result is
  • accordingly Being Determinate (Being there and so).
  • In this first example we must call to mind, once for all, what was
  • stated in § 82 and in the note there: the only way to secure any growth
  • and progress in knowledge is to hold results fast in their truth. There
  • is absolutely nothing whatever in which we cannot and must not point
  • to contradictions or opposite attributes; and the abstraction made by
  • understanding therefore means a forcible insistence on a single aspect,
  • and a real effort to obscure and remove all consciousness of the other
  • attribute which is involved. Whenever such contradiction, then, is
  • discovered in any object or notion, the usual inference is, _Hence_
  • this object is _nothing._ Thus Zeno, who first showed the contradiction
  • native to motion, concluded that there is no motion: and the ancients,
  • who recognised origin and decease, the two species of Becoming, as
  • untrue categories, made use of the expression that the One or Absolute
  • neither arises nor perishes. Such a style of dialectic looks only at
  • the negative aspect of its result, and fails to notice, what is at the
  • same time really present, the definite result, in the present case a
  • pure nothing, but a Nothing which includes Being, and, in like manner,
  • a Being which includes Nothing. Hence Being Determinate is (1) the
  • unity of Being and Nothing, in which we get rid of the immediacy in
  • these determinations, and their contradiction vanishes in their mutual
  • connexion,--the unity in which they are only constituent elements. And
  • (2) since the result is the abolition of the contradiction, it comes
  • in the shape of a simple unity with itself: that is to say, it also
  • is Being, but Being with negation or determinateness: it is Becoming
  • expressly put in the form of one of its elements, viz. Being.
  • Even our ordinary conception of Becoming implies that somewhat
  • comes out of it, and that Becoming therefore has a result. But this
  • conception gives rise to the question, how Becoming does not remain
  • mere Becoming, but has a result The answer to this question follows
  • from what Becoming has already shown itself to be. Becoming always
  • contains Being and Nothing in such a way, that these two are always
  • changing into each other, and reciprocally cancelling each other.
  • Thus Becoming stands before us in utter restlessness--unable however
  • to maintain itself in this abstract restlessness: for since Being and
  • Nothing vanish in Becoming (and that is the very notion of Becoming),
  • the latter must vanish also. Becoming is as it were a fire, which
  • dies out in itself, when it consumes its material. The result of this
  • process however is not an empty Nothing but Being identical with the
  • negation,--what we call Being Determinate (being then and there): the
  • primary import of which evidently is that it _has become._
  • 90.] (α) Determinate Being is Being with a character or mode--which
  • simply _is_; and such un-mediated character is Quality. And as
  • reflected into itself in this its character or mode, Determinate Being
  • is a somewhat, an existent.--The categories, which issue by a closer
  • analysis of Determinate Being, need only be mentioned briefly.
  • Quality may be described as the determinate mode immediate and
  • identical with Being--as distinguished from Quantity (to come
  • afterwards), which, although a mode of Being, is no longer immediately
  • identical with Being, but a mode indifferent and external to it. A
  • Something is what it is in virtue of its quality, and losing its
  • quality it ceases to be what it is. Quality, moreover, is completely a
  • category only of the finite, and for that reason too it has its proper
  • place in Nature, not in the world of Mind. Thus, for example, in Nature
  • what are styled the elementary bodies, oxygen, nitrogen, &c, should
  • be regarded as existing qualities. But in the sphere of mind, Quality
  • appears in a subordinate way only, and not as if its qualitativeness
  • could exhaust any specific aspect of mind. If, for example, we consider
  • the subjective mind, which forms the object of psychology, we may
  • describe what is called (moral and mental) character, as in logical
  • language identical with Quality. This however does not mean that
  • character is a mode of being which pervades the soul and is immediately
  • identical with it, as is the case in the natural world with the
  • elementary bodies before mentioned. Yet a more distinct manifestation
  • of Quality as such, in mind even, is found in the case of besotted or
  • morbid conditions, especially in states of passion and when the passion
  • rises to derangement. The state of mind of a deranged person, being one
  • mass of jealousy, fear, &c, may suitably be described as Quality.
  • 91.] Quality, as determinateness which _is,_ as contrasted with the
  • Negation which is involved in it but distinguished from it, is
  • Reality. Negation is no longer an abstract nothing, but, as
  • a determinate being and somewhat, is only a form on such being--it
  • is as Otherness. Since this otherness, though a determination of
  • Quality itself, is in the first instance distinct from it, Quality is
  • Being-for-another--an expansion of the mere point of Determinate
  • Being, or of Somewhat. The Being as such of Quality, contrasted with
  • this reference to somewhat else, is Being-by-self.
  • The foundation of all determinateness is negation (as Spinoza says,
  • _Omnis determinatio est negatio_). The unreflecting observer supposes
  • that determinate things are merely positive, and pins them down under
  • the form of being. Mere being however is not the end of the matter:--it
  • is, as we have already seen, utter emptiness and instability besides.
  • Still, when abstract being is contused in this way with being modified
  • and determinate, it implies some perception of the fact that, though
  • in determinate being there is involved an element of negation, this
  • element is at first wrapped up, as it were, and only comes to the
  • front and receives its due in Being-for-self.--If we go on to consider
  • determinate Being as a determinateness which _is,_ we get in this way
  • what is called Reality. We speak, for example, of the reality of a
  • plan or a purpose, meaning thereby that they are no longer inner and
  • subjective, but have passed into being-there-and-then. In the same
  • sense the body may be called the reality of the soul, and the law the
  • reality of freedom, and the world altogether the reality of the divine
  • idea. The word 'reality' is however used in another acceptation to mean
  • that something behaves conformably to its essential characteristic or
  • notion. For example, we use the expression: This is a real occupation:
  • This is a real man. Here the term does not merely mean outward and
  • immediate existence: but rather that some existence agrees with its
  • notion. In which sense, be it added, reality is not distinct from the
  • ideality which we shall in the first instance become acquainted with in
  • the shape of Being-for-self.
  • 92.] (ß) Being, if kept distinct and apart from its determinate
  • mode, as it is in Being-by-self (Being implicit), would be only the
  • vacant abstraction of Being. In Being (determinate there and then),
  • the determinateness is one with Being; yet at the same time, when
  • explicitly made a negation, it is a Limit, a Barrier. Hence the
  • otherness is not something indifferent and outside it, but a function
  • proper to it. Somewhat is by its quality,--firstly finite,--secondly
  • alterable; so that finitude and variability appertain to its being.
  • In Being-there-and-then, the negation is still directly one with the
  • Being, and this negation is what we call a Limit (Boundary). A thing
  • is what it is, only in and by reason of its limit. We cannot therefore
  • regard the limit as only paternal to being which is then and there. It
  • rather goes through and through the whole of such existence. The view
  • of limit, as merely an external characteristic of being-there-and-then,
  • arises from a confusion of quantitative with qualitative limit. Here
  • we are speaking primarily of the qualitative limit. If, for example,
  • we observe a piece of ground, three acres large, that circumstance is
  • its quantitative limit. But, in addition, the ground is, it may be, a
  • meadow, not a wood or a pond. This is its qualitative limit.--Man,
  • if he wishes to be actual, must be-there-and-then, and to this end he
  • must set a limit to himself. People who are too fastidious towards the
  • finite never reach actuality, but linger lost in abstraction, and their
  • light dies away.
  • If we take a closer look at what a limit implies, we see it involving a
  • contradiction in itself, and thus evincing its dialectical nature. On
  • the one side the limit makes the reality of a thing; on the other it
  • is its negation. But, again, the limit, as the negation of something,
  • is not an abstract nothing but a nothing which _is,--_what we call an
  • 'other.' Given something, and up starts an other to us: we know that
  • there is not something only, but an other as well. Nor, again, is the
  • other of such a nature that we can think something apart from it; a
  • something is implicitly the other of itself, and the somewhat sees
  • its limit become objective to it in the other. If we now ask for the
  • difference between something and another, it turns out that they are
  • the same: which sameness is expressed in Latin by calling the pair
  • _aliud--aliud._ The other, as opposed to the something, is itself a
  • something, and hence we say some other, or something else; and so on
  • the other hand the first something when opposed to the other, also
  • defined as something, is itself an other. When we say 'something
  • else' our first impression is that something taken separately is only
  • something, and that the quality of being another attaches to it only
  • from outside considerations. Thus we suppose that the moon, being
  • something else than the sun, might very well exist without the sun.
  • But really the moon, as a something, has its other implicit in it:
  • Plato says: God made the world out of the nature of the 'one' and the
  • 'other' (τοῦ ἑτέρου): having brought these together, he formed from
  • them a third, which is of the nature of the 'one' and the 'other.'
  • In these words we have in general terms a statement of the nature
  • of the finite, which, as something, does not meet the nature of the
  • other as if it had no affinity to it, but, being implicitly the other
  • of itself, thus undergoes alteration. Alteration thus exhibits the
  • inherent contradiction which originally attaches to determinate being,
  • and which forces it out of its own bounds. To materialised conception
  • existence stands in the character of something solely positive, and
  • quietly abiding within its own limits: though we also know, it is
  • true, that everything finite (such as existence) is subject to change.
  • Such changeableness in existence is to the superficial eye a mere
  • possibility, the realisation of which is not a consequence of its own
  • nature. But the fact is, mutability lies in the notion of existence,
  • and change is only the manifestation of what it implicitly is. The
  • living die, simply because as living they bear in themselves the germ
  • of death.
  • 93.] Something becomes an other: this other is itself somewhat:
  • therefore it likewise becomes an other, and so on _ad infinitum._
  • 94.] This Infinity is the wrong or negative infinity: it is only a
  • negation of a finite: but the finite rises again the same as ever, and
  • is never got rid of and absorbed. In other words, this infinite only
  • expresses the _ought-to-be_ elimination of the finite. The progression
  • to infinity never gets further than a statement of the contradiction
  • involved in the finite, viz. that it is somewhat as well as somewhat
  • else. It sets up with endless iteration the alternation between these
  • two terms, each of which calls up the other.
  • If we let somewhat and another, the elements of determinate Being,
  • fall asunder, the result is that some becomes other, and this other
  • is itself a somewhat, which then as such changes likewise, and so
  • on _ad infinitum._ This result seems to superficial reflection
  • something very grand, the grandest possible. Besuch a progression to
  • infinity is not the real infinite. That consists in being at home
  • with itself in its other, or, if enunciated as a process, in coming
  • to itself in its other. Much depends on rightly apprehending the
  • notion of infinity, and not stopping short at the wrong infinity of
  • endless progression. When time and space, for example, are spoken of
  • as infinite, it is in the first place the infinite progression on
  • which our thoughts fasten. We say, Now, This time, and then we keep
  • continually going forwards and backwards beyond this limit. The case
  • is the same with space, the infinity of which has formed the theme of
  • barren declamation to astronomers with a talent for edification. In the
  • attempt to contemplate such an infinite, our thought, we are commonly
  • informed, must sink exhausted. It is true indeed that we must abandon
  • the unending contemplation, not however because the occupation is too
  • sublime, but because it is too tedious. It is tedious to expatiate in
  • the contemplation of this infinite progression, because the same thing
  • is constantly recurring. We lay down a limit: then we pass it: next we
  • have a limit once more, and so on for ever. All this is but superficial
  • alternation, which never leaves the region of the finite behind. To
  • suppose that by stepping out and away into that infinity we release
  • ourselves from the finite, is in truth but to seek the release which
  • comes by flight. But the man who flees is not yet free: in fleeing he
  • is still conditioned by that from which he flees. If it be also said,
  • that the infinite is unattainable, the statement is true, but only
  • because to the idea of infinity has been attached the circumstance
  • of being simply and solely negative. With such empty and other world
  • stuff philosophy has nothing to do. What philosophy has to do with is
  • always--something concrete and in the highest sense present.
  • No doubt philosophy has also sometimes been set the task of finding
  • an answer to the question, how the infinite comes to the resolution
  • of issuing out of itself. This question, founded, as it is, upon the
  • assumption of a rigid opposition between finite and infinite, may be
  • answered by saying that the opposition is false, and that in point
  • of fact the infinite eternally proceeds out of itself, and yet does
  • not proceed out of itself. If we further say that the infinite is the
  • not-finite, we have in point of fact virtually expressed the truth:
  • for as the finite itself is the first negative, the not-finite is the
  • negative of that negation, the negation which is identical with itself
  • and thus at the same time a true affirmation.
  • The infinity of reflection here discussed is only an _attempt_ to
  • reach the true Infinity, a wretched neither-one-thing-nor-another.
  • Generally speaking, it is the point of view which has in recent times
  • been emphasised in Germany. The finite, this theory tells us, _ought_
  • to be absorbed; the infinite _ought_ not to be a negative merely, but
  • also a positive. That 'ought to be' betrays the incapacity of actually
  • making good a claim which is at the same time recognised to be right.
  • This stage was never passed by the systems of Kant and Fichte, so far
  • as ethics are concerned. The utmost to which this way brings us is only
  • the postulate of a never-ending approximation to the law of Reason:
  • which postulate has been made an argument for the immortality of the
  • soul.
  • 95.] (γ) What we now in point of fact have before us, is that somewhat
  • comes to be an other, and that the other generally comes to be an
  • other. Thus essentially relative to another, somewhat is virtually an
  • other against it: and since what is passed into is quite the same as
  • what passes over, since both have one and the same attribute, viz.
  • to be an other, it follows that something in its passage into other
  • only joins with itself. To be thus self-related in the passage, and
  • in the other, is the genuine Infinity. Or, under a negative aspect:
  • what is altered is the other, it becomes the other of the other. Thus
  • Being, but as negation of the negation, is restored again: it is now
  • Being-for-self.
  • Dualism, in putting an insuperable opposition between finite and
  • infinite, fails to note the simple circumstance that the infinite is
  • thereby only one of two, and is reduced to a particular, to which the
  • finite forms the other particular. Such an infinite, which is only a
  • particular, is co-terminous with the finite which makes for it a limit
  • and a barrier: it is not what it ought to be, that is, the infinite,
  • but is only finite. In such circumstances, where the finite is on this
  • side, and the infinite on that,--this world as the finite and the other
  • world as the infinite,--an equal dignity of permanence and independence
  • is ascribed to finite and to infinite. The being of the finite is made
  • an absolute being, and by this dualism gets independence and stability.
  • Touched, so to speak, by the infinite, it would be annihilated. But
  • it must not be touched by the infinite. There must be an abyss, an
  • impassable gulf between the two, with the infinite abiding on yonder
  • side and the finite steadfast on this. Those who attribute to the
  • finite this inflexible persistence in comparison with the infinite
  • are not, as they imagine, far above metaphysic: they are still on the
  • level of the most ordinary metaphysic of understanding. For the same
  • thing occurs here as in the infinite progression. At one time it is
  • admitted that the finite has no independent actuality, no absolute
  • being, no root and development of its own, but is only a transient.
  • But next moment this is straightway forgotten; the finite, made a mere
  • counterpart to the infinite, wholly separated from it, and rescued from
  • annihilation, is conceived to be persistent in its independence. While
  • thought thus imagines itself elevated to the infinite, it meets with
  • the opposite fate: it comes to an infinite which is only a finite, and
  • the finite, which it had left behind, has always to be retained and
  • made into an absolute.
  • After this examination (with which it were well to compare Plato's
  • Philebus), tending to show the nullity of the distinction made by
  • understanding between the finite and the infinite, we are liable
  • to glide into the statement that the infinite and the finite are
  • therefore one, and that the genuine infinity, the truth, must be
  • defined and enunciated as the unity of the finite and infinite. Such
  • a statement would be to some extent correct; but is just as open to
  • perversion and falsehood as the unity of Being and Nothing already
  • noticed. Besides it may very fairly be charged with reducing the
  • infinite to finitude and making a finite infinite. For, so far as
  • the expression goes, the finite seems left in its place,--it is not
  • expressly stated to be absorbed. Or, if we reflect that the finite,
  • when identified with the infinite, certainly cannot remain what it
  • was out of such unity, and will at least suffer some change in its
  • characteristics--as an alkali, when combined with an acid, loses some
  • of its properties, we must see that, the same fate awaits the infinite,
  • which, as the negative, will on its part likewise have its edge, as
  • it were, taken off on the other. And this does really happen with the
  • abstract one-sided infinite of understanding. The genuine infinite
  • however is not merely in the position of the one-sided acid, and so
  • does not lose itself. The negation of negation is not a neutralisation:
  • the infinite is the affirmative, and it is only the finite which is
  • absorbed.
  • In Being-for-self enters the category of Ideality.
  • Being-there-and-then, as in the first instance apprehended in its being
  • or affirmation, has reality (§ 91): and thus even finitude in the first
  • instance is in the category of reality. But the truth of the finite is
  • rather its ideality. Similarly, the infinite of understanding, which
  • is co-ordinated with the finite, is itself only one of two finites,
  • no whole truth, but a non-substantial element. This ideality of the
  • finite is the chief maxim of philosophy; and for that reason every
  • genuine philosophy is idealism. But everything depends upon not taking
  • for the infinite what, in the very terms of its characterisation, is.
  • at the same time made a particular and finite.--For this reason we
  • have bestowed a greater amount of attention on this distinction. The
  • fundamental notion of philosophy, the genuine infinite, depends upon
  • it. The distinction is cleared up by the simple, and for that reason
  • seemingly insignificant, but incontrovertible reflections, contained in
  • the first paragraph of this section.
  • (c) _Being-for-self._
  • 96.] (α) Being-for self, as reference to itself, is immediacy, and
  • as reference of the negative to itself, is a self-subsistent, the
  • One. This unit, being without distinction in itself, thus
  • excludes the other from itself.
  • To be for self--to be one--is completed Quality, and as such, contains
  • abstract Being and Being modified as non-substantial elements. As
  • simple Being, the One is simple self-reference; as Being modified it
  • is determinate: but the determinateness is not in this case a finite
  • determinateness--a somewhat in distinction from an other--but infinite,
  • because it contains distinction absorbed and annulled in itself.
  • The readiest instance of Being-for-self is found in the 'I.' We know
  • ourselves as existents, distinguished in the first place from other
  • existents, and with certain relations thereto. But we also come to
  • know this expansion of existence (in these relations) reduced, as it
  • were, to a point in the simple form of being-for-self. When we say 'I,'
  • we express the reference-to-self which is infinite, and at the same
  • time negative. Man, it may be said, is distinguished from the animal
  • world, and in that way from nature altogether, by knowing himself as
  • 'I': which amounts to saying that natural things never attain a free
  • Being-for-self, but as limited to Being-there-and-then, are always and
  • only Being for an other.--Again, Being-for-self may be described as
  • ideality, just as Being-there-and-then was described as reality. It is
  • said, that besides reality there is _also_ an ideality. Thus the two
  • categories are made equal and parallel. Properly speaking, ideality is
  • not somewhat outside of and beside reality: the notion of ideality
  • just lies in its being the truth of reality. That is to say, when
  • reality is explicitly put as what it implicitly is, it is at once seen
  • to be ideality. Hence ideality has not received its proper estimation,
  • when you allow that reality is not all in all, but that an ideality
  • must be recognised outside of it. Such an ideality, external to or it
  • may be even beyond reality, would be no better than an empty name.
  • Ideality only has a meaning when it is the ideality of something: but
  • this something is not a mere indefinite this or that, but existence
  • characterised as reality, which, if retained in isolation, possesses
  • no truth. The distinction between Nature and Mind is not improperly
  • conceived, when the former is traced back to reality, and the latter
  • to ideality as a fundamental category. Nature however is far from
  • being so fixed and complete, as to subsist even without Mind: in Mind
  • it first, as it were, attains its goal and its truth. And similarly,
  • Mind on its part is not merely a world beyond Nature and nothing more:
  • it is really, and with full proof, seen to be mind, only when it
  • involves Nature as absorbed in itself.--_Apropos_ of this, we should
  • note the double meaning of the German word _aufheben_ (to put by, or
  • set aside). We mean by it (1) to clear away, or annul: thus, we say, a
  • law or a regulation is set aside: (2) to keep, or preserve: in which
  • sense we use it when we say: something is well put by. This double
  • usage of language, which gives to the same word a positive and negative
  • meaning, is not an accident, and gives no ground for reproaching
  • language as a cause of confusion. We should rather recognise in it the
  • speculative spirit of our language rising above the mere 'Either--or'
  • of understanding.
  • 97.] (β) The relation of the negative to itself is a negative relation,
  • and so a distinguishing of the One from itself, the repulsion of
  • the One; that is, it makes Many Ones. So far as regards the
  • immediacy of the self-existents, these Many _are:_ and the repulsion of
  • every One of them becomes to that extent their repulsion against each
  • other as existing units,--in other words, their reciprocal exclusion.
  • Whenever we speak of the One, the Many usually come into our mind at
  • the same time. Whence, then, we are forced to ask, do the Many come?
  • This question is unanswerable by the consciousness which pictures the
  • Many as a primary datum, and-treats the One as only one among the Many.
  • But the philosophic notion teaches, contrariwise, that the One forms
  • the pre-supposition of the Many: and in the thought of the One is
  • implied that it explicitly make itself Many. The self-existing unit is
  • not, like Being, void of all connective reference: it is a reference,
  • as well as Being-there-and-then was, not however a reference connecting
  • somewhat with an other, but, as unity of the some and the other, it is
  • a connexion with itself, and this connexion be it noted is a negative
  • connexion. Hereby the One manifests an utter incompatibility with
  • itself, a self-repulsion: and what it makes itself explicitly be, is
  • the Many. We may denote this side in the process of Being-for-self
  • by the figurative term Repulsion. Repulsion is a term originally
  • employed in the study of matter, to mean that matter, as a Many, in
  • each of these many Ones, behaves as exclusive to all the others. It
  • would be wrong however to view the process of repulsion, as if the
  • One were the repellent and the Many the repelled. The One, as already
  • remarked, just is self-exclusion and explicit putting itself as the
  • Many. Each of the Many however is itself a One, and in virtue of its so
  • behaving, this all-round repulsion is by one stroke converted into its
  • opposite,--Attraction.
  • 98.] (γ) But the Many are one the same as another: each is One, or
  • even one of the Many; they are consequently one and the same. Or when
  • we study all that Repulsion involves, we see that as a negative
  • attitude of many Ones to one another, it is just as essentially a
  • connective reference of them to each other; and as those to which the
  • One is related in its act of repulsion are ones, it is in them thrown
  • into relation with itself. The repulsion therefore has an equal right
  • to be called Attraction; and the exclusive One, or Being-for-self,
  • suppresses itself. The qualitative character, which in the One or unit
  • has reached the extreme point of its characterisation, has thus passed
  • over into determinateness (quality) suppressed, _i.e._ into Being as
  • Quantity.
  • The philosophy of the Atomists is the doctrine in which the Absolute
  • is formulated as Being-for-self, as One, and many ones. And it is
  • the repulsion, which shows itself in the notion of the One, which
  • is assumed as the fundamental force in these atoms. But instead of
  • attraction, it is Accident, that is, mere unintelligence, which
  • is expected to bring them together. So long as the One is fixed
  • as one, it is certainly impossible to regard its congression with
  • others as anything but external and mechanical. The Void, which is
  • assumed as the complementary principle to the atoms, is repulsion
  • and nothing else, presented under the image of the nothing existing
  • between the atoms.--Modern Atomism--and physics is still in principle
  • atomistic--has surrendered the atoms so far as to pin its faith
  • on molecules or particles. In so doing, science has come closer
  • to sensuous conception, at the cost of losing the precision of
  • thought.--To put an attractive by the side of a repulsive force, as
  • the moderns have done, certainly gives completeness to the contrast:
  • and the discovery of this natural force, as it is called, has been a
  • source of much pride. But the mutual implication of the two, which
  • makes what is true and concrete in them, would have to be wrested from
  • the obscurity and confusion in which they were left even in Kant's
  • Metaphysical Rudiments of Natural Science.--In modern times the
  • importance of the atomic theory is even more evident in political than
  • in physical science. According to it, the will of individuals as such
  • is the creative principle of the State: the attracting force is the
  • special wants and inclinations of individuals; and the Universal, or
  • the State itself, is the external nexus of a compact.
  • (1) The Atomic philosophy forms a vital stage in the historical
  • evolution of the Idea. The principle of that system may be described
  • as Being-for-self in the shape of the Many. At present, students of
  • nature who are anxious to avoid metaphysics turn a favourable ear to
  • Atomism. But it is not possible to escape metaphysics and cease to
  • trace nature back to terms of thought, by throwing ourselves into the
  • arms of Atomism. The atom, in fact, is itself a thought; and hence the
  • theory which holds matter to consist of atoms is a metaphysical theory.
  • Newton gave physics an express warning to beware of metaphysics, it is
  • true; but, to his honour be it said, he did not by any means obey his
  • own warning. The only mere physicists are the animals: they alone do
  • not think: while man is a thinking being and a born metaphysician. The
  • real question is not whether we shall apply metaphysics, but whether
  • our metaphysics are of the right kind: in other words, whether we are
  • not, instead of the concrete logical Idea, adopting one-sided forms of
  • thought, rigidly fixed by understanding, and making these the basis of
  • our theoretical as well as our practical work. It is on this ground
  • that one objects to the Atomic philosophy. The old Atomists viewed the
  • world as a many, as their successors often do to this day. On chance
  • they laid the task of collecting the atoms which float about in the
  • void. But, after all, the nexus binding the many with one another is
  • by no means a mere accident: as we have already remarked, the nexus is
  • founded on their very nature. To Kant we owe the completed theory of
  • matter as the unity of repulsion and attraction. The theory is correct,
  • so far as it recognises attraction to be the other of the two elements
  • involved in the notion of Being-for-self: and to be an element no less
  • essential than repulsion to constitute matter. Still this dynamical
  • construction of matter, as it is termed, has the fault of taking for
  • granted, instead of deducing, attraction and repulsion. Had they been
  • deduced, we should then have seen the How and the Why of a unity which
  • is merely asserted. Kant indeed was careful to inculcate that Matter
  • must not be taken to be in existence _per se,_ and then as it were
  • incidentally to be provided with the two forces mentioned, but must
  • be regarded as consisting solely in their unity. German physicists
  • for some time accepted this pure dynamic. But in spite of this, the
  • majority of these physicists i n modern times have found it more
  • convenient to return to the Atomic point of view, and in spite of the
  • warnings of Kästner, one of their number, have begun to regard Matter
  • as consisting of infinitesimally small particles, termed 'atoms'--which
  • atoms have then to be brought into relation with one another by the
  • play of forces attaching to them,--attractive, repulsive, or whatever
  • they may be. This too is metaphysics; and metaphysics which, for its
  • utter unintelligence, there would be sufficient reason to guard against.
  • (2) The transition from Quality to Quantity, indicated in the paragraph
  • before us, is not found in our ordinary way of thinking, which deems
  • each of these categories to exist independently beside the other. We
  • are in the habit of saying that things are not merely qualitatively,
  • but also quantitatively defined; but whence these categories originate,
  • and how they are related to each other, are questions not further
  • examined. The fact is, quantity just means quality superseded and
  • absorbed: and it is by the dialectic of quality here examined that this
  • supersession is effected. First of all, we had Being: as the truth of
  • Being, came Becoming: which formed the passage to Being Determinate:
  • and the truth of that we found to be Alteration. And in its result
  • Alteration showed itself to be Being-for-self, exempt from implication
  • of another and from passage into another;--which Being-for-self,
  • finally, in the two sides of its process, Repulsion and Attraction,
  • was clearly seen to annul itself, and thereby to annul quality in the
  • totality of its stages. Still this superseded and absorbed quality is
  • neither an abstract nothing, nor an equally abstract and featureless
  • being: it is only being as indifferent to determinateness or character.
  • This aspect of being is also what appears as quantity in our ordinary
  • conceptions. We observe things, first of all, with an eye to their
  • quality--which we take to be the character identical with the being
  • of the thing. If we proceed to consider their quantity, we get the
  • conception of an indifferent and external character or mode, of such a
  • kind that a thing remains what it is, though its quantity is altered,
  • and the thing becomes greater or less.
  • B.--QUANTITY.
  • (α) _Pure Quantity._
  • 99.] Quantity is pure being, where the mode or character is
  • no longer taken as one with the being itself, but explicitly put as
  • superseded or indifferent.
  • (i) The expression Magnitude especially marks _determinate_
  • Quantity, and is for that reason not a suitable name for Quantity
  • in general. (2) Mathematics usually define magnitude as what can be
  • increased or diminished. This definition has the defect of containing
  • the thing to be defined over again: but it may serve to show that the
  • category of magnitude is explicitly understood to be changeable and
  • indifferent, so that, in spite of its being altered by an increased
  • extension or intension, the thing, a house, for example, does not cease
  • to be a house, and red to be red. (3) The Absolute is pure Quantity.
  • This point of view is upon the whole the same as when the Absolute is
  • defined to be Matter, in which, though form undoubtedly is present, the
  • form is a characteristic of no importance one way or another. Quantity
  • too constitutes the main characteristic of the Absolute, when the
  • Absolute is regarded as absolute indifference, and only admitting of
  • quantitative distinction.--Otherwise pure space, time, &c. may be taken
  • as examples of Quantity, if we allow ourselves to regard the real as
  • whatever fills up space and time, it matters not with what.
  • The mathematical definition of magnitude as what may be increased
  • or diminished, appears at first sight to be more plausible and
  • perspicuous than the exposition of the notion in the present
  • section. When closely examined, however, it involves, under cover
  • of pre-suppositions and images, the same elements as appear in the
  • notion of quantity reached by the method of logical development. In
  • other words, when we say that the notion of magnitude lies in the
  • possibility of being increased or diminished, we state that magnitude
  • (or more correctly, quantity), as distinguished from quality, is a
  • characteristic of such kind that the characterised thing is not in the
  • least affected by any change in it. What then, it may be asked, is
  • the fault which we have to find with this definition? It is that to
  • increase and to diminish is the same thing as to characterise magnitude
  • otherwise. If this aspect then were an adequate account of it, quantity
  • would be described merely as whatever can be altered. But quality is
  • no less than quantity open to alteration; and the distinction here
  • given between quantity and quality is expressed by saying increase
  • _or_ diminution: the meaning being that, towards whatever side the
  • determination of magnitude be altered, the thing still remains what it
  • is.
  • One remark more. Throughout philosophy we do not seek merely for
  • correct, still less for plausible definitions, whose correctness
  • appeals directly to the popular imagination; we seek approved or
  • verified definitions, the content of which is not assumed merely as
  • given, but is seen and known to warrant itself, because warranted
  • by the free self-evolution of thought. To apply this to the present
  • case. However correct and self-evident the definition of quantity
  • usual in Mathematics may be, it will still fail to satisfy the wish to
  • see how far this particular thought is founded in universal thought,
  • and in that way necessary. This difficulty, however, is not the only
  • one. If quantity is not reached through the action of thought, but
  • taken uncritically from our generalised image of it, we are liable
  • to exaggerate the range of its validity, or even to raise it to the
  • height of an absolute category. And that such a danger is real, we see
  • when the title of exact science is restricted to those sciences the
  • objects of which can be submitted to mathematical calculation. Here we
  • have another trace of the bad metaphysics (mentioned in § 98, note)
  • which replace the concrete idea by partial and inadequate categories of
  • understanding. Our knowledge would be in a very awkward predicament if
  • such objects as freedom, law, morality, or even God Himself, because
  • they cannot be measured and calculated, or expressed in a mathematical
  • formula, were to be reckoned beyond the reach of exact knowledge, and
  • we had to put up with a vague generalised image of them, leaving their
  • details or particulars to the pleasure of each individual, to make
  • out of them what he will. The pernicious consequences, to which such
  • a theory gives rise in practice, are at once evident. And this mere
  • mathematical view, which identifies with the Idea one of its special
  • stages, viz. quantity, is no other than the principle of Materialism.
  • Witness the history of the scientific modes of thought, especially in
  • France since the middle of last century. Matter, in the abstract, is
  • just what, though of course there is form in it, has that form only as
  • an indifferent and external attribute.
  • The present explanation would be utterly misconceived if it were
  • supposed to disparage mathematics. By calling the quantitative
  • characteristic merely external and indifferent, we provide no excuse
  • for indolence and superficiality, nor do we assert that quantitative
  • characteristics may be left to mind themselves, or at least require no
  • very careful handling. Quantity, of course, is a stage of the Idea: and
  • as such it must have its due, first as a logical category, and then
  • in the world of objects, natural as well as spiritual. Still even so,
  • there soon emerges the different importance attaching to the category
  • of quantity according as its objects belong to the natural or to the
  • spiritual world. For in Nature, where the form of the Idea is to be
  • other than, and at the same time outside, itself, greater importance is
  • for that very reason attached to quantity than in the spiritual world,
  • the world of free inwardness. No doubt we regard even spiritual facts
  • under a quantitative point of view; but it is at once apparent that in
  • speaking of God as a Trinity, the number three has by no means the same
  • prominence, as when we consider the three dimensions of space or the
  • three sides of a triangle;--the fundamental feature of which last is
  • just to be a surface bounded by three lines. Even inside the realm of
  • Nature we find the same distinction of greater or less importance of
  • quantitative features. In the inorganic world, Quantity plays, so to
  • say, a more prominent part than in the organic. Even in organic nature
  • when we distinguish mechanical functions from what are called chemical,
  • and in the narrower sense, physical, there is the same difference.
  • Mechanics is of all branches of science, confessedly, that in which the
  • aid of mathematics can be least dispensed with,--where indeed we cannot
  • take one step without them. On that account mechanics is regarded next
  • to mathematics as the science _par excellence_; which leads us to
  • repeat the remark about the coincidence of the materialist with the
  • exclusively mathematical point of view. After all that has been said,
  • we cannot but hold it, in the interest of exact and thorough knowledge,
  • one of the most hurtful prejudices, to seek all distinction and
  • determinateness of objects merely in quantitative considerations. Mind
  • to be sure is more than Nature and the animal is more than the plant:
  • but we know very little of these objects and the distinction between
  • them, if a more and less is enough for us, and if we do not proceed to
  • comprehend them in their peculiar, that is their qualitative character.
  • 100.] Quantity, as we saw, has two sources: the exclusive unit, and
  • the identification or equalisation of these units. When we look
  • therefore at its immediate relation to self, or at the characteristic
  • of self-sameness made explicit by attraction, quantity is Continuous
  • magnitude; but when we look at the other characteristic, the One
  • implied in it, it is Discrete magnitude. Still continuous quantity has
  • also a certain discreteness, being but a continuity of the Many: and
  • discrete quantity is no less continuous, its continuity being the One
  • or Unit, that is, the self-same point of the many Ones.
  • (1) Continuous and Discrete magnitude, therefore, must not be supposed
  • two species of magnitude, as if the characteristic of the one did not
  • attach to the other. The only distinction between them is that the
  • same whole (of quantity) is at one time explicitly put under the one,
  • at another under the other of its characteristics. (2) The Antinomy of
  • space, of time, or of matter, which discusses the question of their
  • being divisible for ever, or of consisting of indivisible units, just
  • means that we maintain quantity as at one time Discrete, at
  • another Continuous. If we explicitly invest time, space, or matter with
  • the attribute of Continuous quantity alone, they are divisible _ad
  • infinitum._ When, on the contrary, they are invested with the attribute
  • of Discrete quantity, they are potentially divided already, and consist
  • of indivisible units. The one view is as inadequate as the other.
  • Quantity, as the proximate result of Being-for-self, involves the
  • two sides in the process of the latter, attraction and repulsion, as
  • constitutive elements of its own idea. It is consequently Continuous
  • as well as Discrete. Each of these two elements involves the other
  • also, and hence there is no such thing as a merely Continuous or a
  • merely Discrete quantity. We may speak of the two as two particular and
  • opposite species of magnitude; but that is merely the result of our
  • abstracting reflection, which in viewing definite magnitudes waives now
  • the one, now the other, of the elements contained in inseparable unity
  • in the notion of quantity. Thus, it may be said, the space occupied by
  • this room is a continuous magnitude, and the hundred men, assembled
  • in it, form a discrete magnitude. And yet the space is continuous and
  • discrete at the same time; hence we speak of points of space, or we
  • divide space, a certain length, into so many feet, inches, &c, which
  • can be done only on the hypothesis that space is also potentially
  • discrete. Similarly, on the other hand, the discrete magnitude, made
  • up of a hundred men, is also continuous: and the circumstance on which
  • this continuity depends, is the common element, the species man, which
  • pervades all the individuals and unites them with each other.
  • (b) _Quantum (How Much)._
  • 101.] Quantity, essentially invested with the exclusionist character
  • which it involves, is Quantum (or How Much): _i.e._ limited
  • quantity.
  • Quantum is, as it were, the determinate Being of quantity: whereas mere
  • quantity corresponds to abstract Being, and the Degree, which is next
  • to be considered, corresponds to Being-for-self. As for the details
  • of the advance from mere quantity to quantum, it is founded on this:
  • that whilst in mere quantity the distinction, as a distinction of
  • continuity and discreteness, is at first only implicit, in a quantum
  • the distinction is actually made, so that quantity in general now
  • appears as distinguished or limited. But in this way the quantum breaks
  • up at the same time into an indefinite multitude of Quanta or definite
  • magnitudes. Each of these definite magnitudes, as distinguished from
  • the others, forms a unity, while on the other hand, viewed _per se,_ it
  • is a many. And, when that is done, the quantum is described as Number.
  • 102.] In Number the quantum reaches its development and perfect
  • mode. Like the One, the medium in which it exists, Number involves two
  • qualitative factors or functions; Annumeration or Sum, which depends on
  • the factor discreteness, and Unity, which depends on continuity.
  • In arithmetic the several kinds of operation are usually presented as
  • accidental modes of dealing with numbers. If necessity and meaning
  • is to be found in these operations, it must be by a principle: and
  • that must come from the characteristic elements in the notion of
  • number itself. (This principle must here be briefly exhibited.) These
  • characteristic elements are Annumeration on the one hand, and Unity on
  • the other, which together constitute number. But Unity, when applied
  • to empirical numbers, is only the equality of these numbers: hence the
  • principle of arithmetical operations must be to put numbers in the
  • ratio of Unity and Sum (or amount), and to elicit the equality of these
  • two modes.
  • The Ones or the numbers themselves are indifferent towards each other,
  • and hence the unity into which they are translated by the arithmetical
  • operation takes the aspect of an external colligation. All reckoning is
  • therefore making up the tale: and the difference between the species of
  • it lies only in the qualitative constitution of the numbers of which we
  • make up the tale. The principle for this constitution is given by the
  • way we fix Unity and Annumeration.
  • Numeration comes first: what we may call, making number; a colligation
  • of as many units as we please. But to get a _species_ of calculation,
  • it is necessary that what we count up should be numbers already, and no
  • longer a mere unit.
  • First, and as they naturally come to hand, Numbers are quite vaguely
  • numbers in general, and so, on the whole, unequal. The colligation, or
  • telling the tale of these, is Addition.
  • The second point of view under which we regard numbers is as equal,
  • so that they make one unity, and of such there is an annumeration or
  • sum before us. To tell the tale of these is Multiplication. It makes
  • no matter in the process, how the functions of Sum and Unity are
  • distributed between the two numbers, or factors of the product; either
  • may be Sum and either may be Unity.
  • The third and final point of view is the equality of Sum (amount) and
  • Unity. To number together numbers when so characterised is Involution;
  • and in the first instance raising them to the square power. To
  • raise the number to ä higher power means in point of form to go on
  • multiplying a number with itself an indefinite amount of times.--Since
  • this third type of calculation exhibits the complete equality of the
  • sole existing distinction in number, viz. the distinction between Sum
  • or amount and Unity, there can be no more than these three modes of
  • calculation. Corresponding to the integration we have the dissolution
  • of numbers according to the same features. Hence besides the three
  • species mentioned, which may to that extent be called positive, there
  • are three negative species of arithmetical operation.
  • Number, in general, is the quantum in its complete specialisation.
  • Hence we may employ it not only to determine what we call discrete, but
  • what are called continuous magnitudes as well. For that reason even
  • geometry must call in the aid of number, when it is required to specify
  • definite figurations of space and their ratios.
  • (c) _Degree._
  • 103.] The limit (in a quantum) is identical with the whole of the
  • quantum itself. As _in itself_ multiple, the limit is Extensive
  • magnitude; as in itself _simple_ determinateness (qualitative
  • simplicity), it is Intensive magnitude or Degree.
  • The distinction between Continuous and Discrete magnitude differs
  • from that between Extensive and Intensive in the circumstance that
  • the former apply to quantity in general, while the latter apply to
  • the limit or determinateness of it as such. Intensive and Extensive
  • magnitude are not, any more than the other, two species, of which the
  • one involves a character not possessed by the other: what is Extensive
  • magnitude is just as much Intensive, and _vice versâ._
  • Intensive magnitude or Degree is in its notion distinct from Extensive
  • magnitude or the Quantum. It is therefore inadmissible to refuse,
  • as many do, to recognise this distinction, and without scruple to
  • identify the two forms of magnitude. They are so identified in
  • physics, when difference of specific gravity is explained by saying,
  • that a body, with a specific gravity twice that of another, contains
  • within the same space twice as many material parts (or atoms) as the
  • other. So with heat and light, if the various degrees of temperature
  • and brilliancy were to be explained by the greater or less number of
  • particles (or molecules) of heat and light. No doubt the physicists,
  • who employ such a mode of explanation, usually excuse themselves, when
  • they are remonstrated with on its untenableness, by saying that the
  • expression is without prejudice to the confessedly unknowable essence
  • of such phenomena, and employed merely for greater convenience. This
  • greater convenience is meant to point to the easier application of the
  • calculus: but it is hard to see why Intensive magnitudes, having, as
  • they do, a definite numerical expression of their own, should not be
  • as convenient for calculation as Extensive magnitudes. If convenience
  • be all that is desired, surely it would be more convenient to banish
  • calculation and thought altogether. A further point against the apology
  • offered by the physicists is, that, to engage in explanations of this
  • kind, is to overstep the sphere of perception and experience, and
  • resort to the realm of metaphysics and of what at other times would be
  • called idle or even pernicious speculation. It is certainly a fact of
  • experience that, if one of two purses filled with shillings is twice
  • as heavy as the other, the reason must be, that the one contains, say
  • two hundred, and the other only one hundred shillings. These pieces
  • of money we can see and feel with our senses: atoms, molecules, and
  • the like, are on the contrary beyond the range of sensuous perception;
  • and thought alone can decide whether they are admissible, and have
  • a meaning. But (as already noticed in § 98, note) it is abstract
  • understanding which stereotypes the factor of multeity (involved in the
  • notion of Being-for-self) in the shape of atoms, and adopts it as an
  • ultimate principle. It is the same abstract understanding which, in
  • the present instance, at equal variance with unprejudiced perception
  • and with real concrete thought, regards Extensive magnitude as the
  • sole form of quantity, and, where Intensive magnitudes occur, does not
  • recognise them in their own character, but makes a violent attempt by a
  • wholly untenable hypothesis to reduce them to Extensive magnitudes.
  • Among the charges made against modern philosophy, one is heard more
  • than another. Modern philosophy, it is said, reduces everything to
  • identity. Hence its nickname, the Philosophy of Identity. But the
  • present discussion may teach that it is philosophy, and philosophy
  • alone, which insists on distinguishing what is logically as well as
  • in experience different; while the professed devotees of experience
  • are the people who erect abstract identity into the chief principle
  • of knowledge. It is their philosophy which might more appropriately
  • be termed one of identity. Besides it is quite correct that there are
  • no merely Extensive and merely Intensive magnitudes, just as little
  • as there are merely continuous and merely discrete magnitudes. The
  • two characteristics of quantity are not opposed as independent kinds.
  • Every Intensive magnitude is also Extensive, and _vice versâ._ Thus a
  • certain degree of temperature is an Intensive magnitude, which has a
  • perfectly simple sensation corresponding to it as such. If we look at a
  • thermometer, we find this degree of temperature has a certain expansion
  • of the column of mercury corresponding to it; which Extensive magnitude
  • changes simultaneously with the temperature or Intensive magnitude. The
  • case is similar in the world of mind: a more intensive character has a
  • wider range with its effects than a less intensive.
  • 104.] In Degree the notion of quantum is explicitly put. It is
  • magnitude as indifferent on its own account and simple: but in such
  • a way that the character (or modal being) which makes it a quantum
  • lies quite outside it in other magnitudes. In this contradiction,
  • where the _independent_ indifferent limit is absolute _externality,_
  • the Infinite Quantitative Progression is made explicit--an immediacy
  • which immediately veers round into its counterpart, into mediation (the
  • passing beyond and over the quantum just laid down), and _vice versâ._
  • Number is a thought, but thought in its complete self-externalisation.
  • Because it is a thought, it does not belong to perception: but it is a
  • thought which is characterised by the externality of perception.--Not
  • only therefore _may_ the quantum be increased or diminished without
  • end: the very notion of quantum is thus to push out and out beyond
  • itself. The infinite quantitative progression is only the meaningless
  • repetition of one and the same contradiction, which attaches to the
  • quantum, both generally and, when explicitly invested with its special
  • character, as degree. Touching the futility of enunciating this
  • contradiction in the form of infinite progression, Zeno, as quoted by
  • Aristotle, rightly says, 'It is the same to say a thing once, and to
  • say it for ever.'
  • (1) If we follow the usual definition of the mathematicians, given in
  • § 99, and say that magnitude is what can be increased or diminished,
  • there may be nothing to urge against the correctness of the perception
  • on which it is founded; but the question remains, how we come to
  • assume such a capacity of increase or diminution. If we simply appeal
  • for an answer to experience, we try an unsatisfactory course; because
  • apart from the fact that we should merely have a material image of
  • magnitude, and not the thought of it, magnitude would come out as a
  • bare possibility (of increasing or diminishing) and we should have no
  • key to the necessity for its exhibiting this behaviour. In the way of
  • our logical evolution, on the contrary, quantity is obviously a grade
  • the process of self-determining thought; and it has been shown that it
  • lies in the very notion of quantity to shoot out beyond itself. In that
  • way, the increase or diminution (of which we have heard) is not merely
  • possible, but necessary.
  • (2) The quantitative infinite progression is what the reflective
  • understanding usually relies upon when it is engaged with the
  • general question of Infinity. The same thing however holds good of
  • this progression, as was already remarked on the occasion of the
  • qualitatively, infinite progression. As was then said, it is not the
  • expression of a true, but of a wrong infinity; it never gets further
  • than a bare 'ought,' and thus really remains within the limits
  • of finitude. The quantitative form of this infinite progression,
  • which Spinoza rightly calls a mere imaginary infinity (_infinitum
  • imaginationis,_) is an image often employed by poets, such as Haller
  • and Klopstock, to depict the infinity, not of Nature merely, but even
  • of God Himself. Thus we find Haller, in a famous description of God's
  • infinity, saying:
  • Ich häufe ungeheure Zahlen,
  • Gebirge Millionen auf,
  • Ich sesse Zeit auf Zeit
  • Und Welt auf Welt zu Hauf,
  • Und wenn ich von der grausen Höh'
  • Mit Schwindel wieder nach Dir seh:
  • Ist alle Macht der Zahl,
  • Vermehrt zu Tausendmal,
  • Noch nicht ein Theil von Dir.
  • [I heap up monstrous numbers, mountains of millions; I pile time upon
  • time, and world on the top of world; and when from the awful height I
  • cast a dizzy look towards Thee, all the power of number, multiplied a
  • thousand times, is not yet one part of Thee.]
  • Here then we meet, in the first place, that continual extrusion of
  • quantity, and especially of number, beyond itself, which Kant describes
  • as 'eery.' The only really 'eery' thing about it is the wearisomeness
  • of ever fixing, and anon unfixing a limit, without advancing a single
  • step. The same poet however well adds to that description of false
  • infinity the closing line:
  • Ich zieh sie ab, und Du liegst ganz vor mir.
  • [These I remove, and Thou liest all before me.]
  • Which means, that the true infinite is more than a mere world beyond
  • the finite, and that we, in order to become conscious of it, must
  • renounce that _progressus in infinitum._
  • (3) Pythagoras, as is well known, philosophised in numbers, and
  • conceived number as the fundamental principle of things. To the
  • ordinary mind this view must at first glance seem an utter paradox,
  • perhaps a mere craze. What, then, are we to think of it? To answer
  • this question, we must, in the first place, remember that the problem
  • of philosophy consists in tracing back things to thoughts, and, of
  • course, to definite thoughts. Now, number is undoubtedly a thought: it
  • is the thought nearest the sensible, or, more precisely expressed, it
  • is the thought of the sensible itself, if we take the sensible to mean
  • what is many, and in reciprocal exclusion. The attempt to apprehend
  • the universe as number is therefore the first step to metaphysics. In
  • the history of philosophy, Pythagoras, as we know, stands between the
  • Ionian philosophers and the Eleatics. While the former, as Aristotle
  • says, never get beyond viewing the essence of things as material (ὕλη),
  • and the latter, especially Parmenides, advanced as far as pure thought,
  • in the shape of Being, the principle of the Pythagorean philosophy
  • forms, as it were, the bridge from the sensible to the super-sensible.
  • We may gather from this, what is to be said of those who suppose that
  • Pythagoras undoubtedly went too far, when he conceived the essence
  • of things as mere number. It is true, they admit, that we can number
  • things; but, they contend, things are far more than mere numbers. But
  • in what respect are they more? The ordinary sensuous consciousness,
  • from its own point of view, would not hesitate to answer the question
  • by handing us over to sensuous perception, and remarking, that things
  • are not merely numerable, but also visible, odorous, palpable, &c. In
  • the phrase of modern times, the fault of Pythagoras would be described
  • as an excess of idealism. As may be gathered from what has been said
  • on the historical position of the Pythagorean school, the real state
  • of the case is quite the reverse. Let it be conceded that things are
  • more than numbers; but the meaning of that admission must be that the
  • bare thought of number is still insufficient to enunciate the definite
  • notion or essence of things. Instead, then, of saying that Pythagoras
  • went too far with his philosophy of number, it would be nearer the
  • truth to say that he did not go far enough; and in fact the Eleatics
  • were the first to take the further step to pure thought.
  • Besides, even if there are not things, there are states of things, and
  • phenomena of nature altogether, the character of which mainly rests on
  • definite numbers and proportions. This is especially the case with the
  • difference of tones and their harmonic concord, which, according to a
  • well-known tradition, first suggested to Pythagoras to conceive the
  • essence of things as number. Though it is unquestionably important to
  • science to trace back these phenomena to the definite numbers on which
  • they are based, it is wholly inadmissible to view the characterisation
  • by thought as a whole, as merely numerical. We may certainly feel
  • ourselves prompted to associate the most general characteristics of
  • thought with the first numbers: saying, 1 is the simple and immediate;
  • 2 is difference and mediation; and 3 the unity of both of these. Such
  • associations however are purely external: there is nothing in the mere
  • numbers to make them express these definite thoughts. With every step
  • in this method, the more arbitrary grows the association of definite
  • numbers with definite thoughts. Thus, we may view 4 as the unity of
  • 1 and 3, and of the thoughts associated with them, but 4 is just as
  • much the double of 2; similarly 9 is not merely the square of 3, but
  • also the sum of 8 and I, of 7 and 2, and so on. To attach, as do some
  • secret societies of modern times, importance to all sorts of numbers
  • and figures, is to some extent an innocent amusement, but it is also a
  • sign of deficiency of intellectual resource. These numbers, it is said,
  • conceal a profound meaning, and suggest a deal to think about. But the
  • point in philosophy is, not what you may think, but what you do think:
  • and the genuine air of thought is to be sought in thought itself, and
  • not in arbitrarily selected symbols.
  • 105.] That the Quantum in its independent character is external to
  • itself, is what constitutes its quality. In that externality it
  • is itself and referred connectively to itself. There is a union in
  • it of externality, _i.e._ the quantitative, and of independency
  • (Being-for-self),--the qualitative. The Quantum when explicitly put
  • thus in its own self, is the Quantitative Ratio, a mode of being
  • which, while, in its Exponent, it is an immediate quantum, is also
  • mediation, viz. the reference of some one quantum to another, forming
  • the two sides of the ratio. But the two quanta are not reckoned at
  • their immediate value: their value is only in this relation.
  • The quantitative infinite progression appears at first as a continual
  • extrusion of number beyond itself. On looking closer, it is, however,
  • apparent that in this progression quantity returns to itself: for
  • the meaning of this progression, so far as thought goes, is the fact
  • that number is determined by number. And this gives the quantitative
  • ratio. Take, for example, the ratio 2:4. Here we have two magnitudes
  • (not counted in their several immediate values) in which we are only
  • concerned with their mutual relations. This relation of the two terms
  • (the exponent of the ratio) is itself a magnitude, distinguished from
  • the related magnitudes by this, that a change in it is followed by a
  • change of the ratio, whereas the ratio is unaffected by the change of
  • both its sides, and remains the same so long as the exponent is not
  • changed. Consequently, in place of 2:4, we can put 3:6 without changing
  • the ratio; as the exponent 2 remains the same in both cases.
  • 106.] The two sides of the ratio are still immediate quanta: and the
  • qualitative and quantitative characteristics still external to one
  • another. But in their truth, seeing that the quantitative itself in its
  • externality is relation to self, or seeing that the independence and
  • the indifference of the character are combined, it is Measure.
  • Thus quantity by means of the dialectical movement so far studied
  • through its several stages, turns out to be a return to quality. The
  • first notion of quantity presented to us was that of quality abrogated
  • and absorbed. That is to say, quantity seemed an external character not
  • identical with Being, to which it is quite immaterial. This notion, as
  • we have seen, underlies the mathematical definition of magnitude as
  • what can be increased or diminished. At first sight this definition
  • may create the impression that quantity is merely whatever can be
  • altered:--increase and diminution alike implying determination of
  • magnitude otherwise--and may tend to confuse it with determinate Being,
  • the second stage of quality, which in its notion is similarly conceived
  • as alterable. We can, however, complete the definition by adding, that
  • in quantity we have an alterable, which in spite of alterations still
  • remains the same. The notion of quantity, it thus turns out, implies an
  • inherent contradiction. This, contradiction is what forms the dialectic
  • of quantity. The result of the dialectic however is not a mere return
  • to quality, as if that were the true and quantity the false notion, but
  • an advance to the unity and truth of both, to qualitative quantity, or
  • Measure.
  • It may be well therefore at this point to observe that whenever in
  • our study of the objective world we are engaged in quantitative
  • determinations, it is in all cases Measure which we have in view, as
  • the goal of our operations. This is hinted at even in language, when
  • the ascertainment of quantitative features and relations is called
  • measuring. We measure, _e.g._ the length of different chords that have
  • been put into a state of vibration, with an eye to the qualitative
  • difference of the tones caused by their vibration, corresponding to
  • this difference of length. Similarly, in chemistry, we try to ascertain
  • the quantity of the matters brought into combination, in order to find
  • out the measures or proportions conditioning such combinations, that
  • is to say, those quantities which give rise to definite qualities.
  • In statistics, too, the numbers with which the study is engaged are
  • important only from the qualitative results conditioned by them. Mere
  • collection of numerical facts, prosecuted without regard to the ends
  • here noted, is justly called an exercise of idle curiosity, of neither
  • theoretical nor practical interest.
  • 107.] Measure is the qualitative quantum, in the first place as
  • immediate,--a quantum, to which a determinate being or a quality is
  • attached.
  • Measure, where quality and quantity are in one, is thus the completion
  • of Being. Being, as we first apprehend it, is something utterly
  • abstract and characterless: but it is the very essence of Being to
  • characterise itself, and its complete characterisation is reached
  • in Measure. Measure, like the other stages of Being, may serve as a
  • definition of the Absolute: God, it has been said, is the Measure of
  • all things. It is this idea which forms the ground-note of many of the
  • ancient Hebrew hymns, in which the glorification of God tends in the
  • main to show that He has appointed to everything its bound: to the
  • sea and the solid land, to the rivers and mountains; and also to the
  • various kinds of plants and animals. To the religious sense of the
  • Greeks the divinity of measure, especially in respect of social ethics,
  • was represented by Nemesis. That conception implies a general theory
  • that all human things, riches, honour, and power, as well as joy and
  • pain, have their definite measure, the transgression of which brings
  • ruin and destruction. In the world of objects, too, we have measure. We
  • see, in the first place, existences in Nature, of which measure forms
  • the essential structure. This is the case, for example, with the solar
  • system, which may be described as the realm of free measures. As we
  • next proceed to the study of inorganic nature, measure retires, as it
  • were, into the background; at least we often find the quantitative and
  • qualitative characteristics showing indifference to each other. Thus
  • the quality of a rock or a river is not tied to a definite magnitude.
  • But even these objects when closely inspected are found not to be quite
  • measureless: the water of a river, and the single constituents of a
  • rock, when chemically analysed, are seen to be qualities conditioned
  • by quantitative ratios between the matters they contain. In organic
  • nature, however, measure again rises full into immediate perception.
  • The various kinds of plants and animals, in the whole as well as in
  • their parts, have a certain measure: though it is worth noticing that
  • the more imperfect forms, those which are least removed from inorganic
  • nature, are partly distinguished from the higher forms by the greater
  • indefiniteness of their measure. Thus among fossils, we find some
  • ammonites discernible only by the microscope, and others as large as a
  • cart-wheel. The same vagueness of measure appears in several plants,
  • which stand on a low level of organic development,--for instance, ferns.
  • 108.] In so far as in Measure quality and quantity are only in
  • _immediate_ unity, to that extent their difference presents itself in
  • a manner equally immediate. Two cases are then possible. Either the
  • specific quantum or measure is a bare quantum, and the definite being
  • (there-and-then) is capable of an increase or a diminution, without
  • Measure (which to that extent is a Rule) being thereby set completely
  • aside. Or the alteration of the quantum is also an alteration of the
  • quality.
  • The identity between quantity and quality, which is found in Measure,
  • is at first only implicit, and not yet explicitly realised. In other
  • words, these two categories, which unite in Measure, each claim an
  • independent authority. On the one hand, the quantitative features of
  • existence may be altered, without affecting its quality. On the other
  • hand, this increase and diminution, immaterial though it be, has
  • its limit, by exceeding which the quality suffers change. Thus the
  • temperature of water is, in the first place, a point of no consequence
  • in respect of its liquidity: still with the increase or diminution
  • of the temperature of the liquid water, there comes a point where
  • this state of cohesion suffers a qualitative change, and the water
  • is converted into steam or ice. A quantitative change takes place,
  • apparently without any further significance: but there is something
  • lurking behind, and a seemingly innocent change of quantity acts as a
  • kind of snare, to catch hold of the quality. The antinomy of Measure
  • which this implies was exemplified under more than one garb among the
  • Greeks. It was asked, for example, whether a single grain makes a heap
  • of wheat, or whether it makes a bald-tail to tear out a single hair
  • from the horse's tail. At first, no doubt, looking at the nature of
  • quantity as an indifferent and external character of Being, we are
  • disposed to answer these questions in the negative. And yet, as we
  • must admit, this indifferent increase and diminution has its limit:
  • a point is finally reached, where a single additional grain makes a
  • heap of wheat; and the bald-tail is produced, if we continue plucking
  • out single hairs. These examples find a parallel in the story of the
  • peasant who, as his ass trudged cheerfully along, went on adding ounce
  • after ounce to its load, till at length it sunk under the unendurable
  • burden. It would be a mistake to treat these examples as pedantic
  • futility; they really turn on thoughts, an acquaintance with which is
  • of great importance in practical life, especially in ethics. Thus in
  • the matter of expenditure, there is a certain latitude within which
  • a more or less does not matter; but when the Measure, imposed by the
  • individual circumstances of the special case, is exceeded on the one
  • side or the other, the qualitative nature of Measure (as in the above
  • examples of the different temperature of water) makes itself felt,
  • and a course, which a moment before was held good economy, turns into
  • avarice or prodigality. The same principle may be applied in politics,
  • when the constitution of a state has to be looked at as independent of,
  • no less than as dependent on, the extent of its territory, the number
  • of its inhabitants, and other quantitative points of the same kind. If
  • we look _e.g._ at a state with a territory of ten thousand square miles
  • and a population of four millions, we should, without hesitation, admit
  • that a few square miles of land or a few thousand inhabitants more or
  • less could exercise no essential influence on the character of its
  • constitution. But, on the other hand, we must not forget, that by the
  • continual increase or diminishing of a state, we finally get to a point
  • where, apart from all other circumstances, this quantitative alteration
  • alone necessarily draws with it an alteration in the quality of the
  • constitution. The constitution of a little Swiss canton does not suit
  • a great kingdom; and, similarly, the constitution of the Roman republic
  • was unsuitable when transferred to the small imperial towns of Germany.
  • 109.] In this second case, when a measure through its quantitative
  • nature has gone in excess of its qualitative character, we meet, what
  • is at first an absence of measure, the Measureless. But seeing
  • that the second quantitative ratio, which in comparison with the first
  • is measureless, is none the less qualitative, the measureless is also a
  • measure. These two transitions, from quality to quantum, and from the
  • latter back again to quality, may be represented under the image of an
  • infinite progression--as the self-abrogation and restoration of measure
  • in the measureless.
  • Quantity, as we have seen, is not only capable of alteration, _i.e._
  • of increase or diminution: it is naturally and necessarily a tendency
  • to exceed itself. This tendency is maintained even in measure. But if
  • the quantity present in measure exceeds a certain limit, the quality
  • corresponding to it is also put in abeyance. This however is not a
  • negation of quality altogether, but only of this definite quality, the
  • place of which is at once occupied by another. This process of measure,
  • which appears alternately as a mere change in quantity, and then as a
  • sudden revulsion of quantity into quality, may be envisaged under the
  • figure of a nodal (knotted) line. Such lines we find in Nature under
  • a variety of forms. We have already referred to the qualitatively
  • different states of aggregation water exhibits under increase or
  • diminution of temperature. The same phenomenon is presented by the
  • different degrees in the oxidation of metals. Even the difference of
  • musical notes may be regarded as an example of what takes place in
  • the process of measure,--the revulsion from what is at first merely
  • quantitative into qualitative alteration.
  • 110.] What really takes place here is that the immediacy, which still
  • attaches to measure as such, is set aside. In measure, at first,
  • quality and quantity itself are immediate, and measure is only their
  • 'relative' identity. But measure shows itself absorbed and superseded
  • in the measureless: yet the measureless, although it be the negation
  • of measure, is itself a unity of quantity and quality. Thus in the
  • measureless the measure is still seen to meet only with itself.
  • 111.] Instead of the more abstract factors, Being and Nothing, some
  • and other, &c., the Infinite, which is affirmation as a negation
  • of negation, now finds its factors in quality and quantity. These
  • (α) have in the first place passed over, quality into quantity, (§
  • 98), and quantity into quality (§ 105), and thus are both shown up
  • as negations, (ß) But in their unity, that is, in measure, they are
  • originally distinct, and the one is only through the instrumentality of
  • the other. And (γ) after the immediacy of this unity has turned out to
  • be self-annulling, the unity is explicitly put as what it implicitly
  • is, simple relation-to-self, which contains in it being and all its
  • forms absorbed.--Being or immediacy, which by the negation of itself
  • is a mediation with self and a reference to self,--which consequently
  • is also a mediation which cancels itself into reference-to-self, or
  • immediacy,--is Essence.
  • The process of measure, instead of being only the wrong infinite of
  • an endless progression, in the shape of an ever-recurrent recoil
  • from quality to quantity, and from quantity to quality, is also
  • the true infinity of coincidence with self in another. In measure,
  • quality and quantity originally confront each other, like some and
  • other. But quality is implicitly quantity, and conversely quantity
  • is implicitly quality. In the process of measure, therefore, these
  • two pass into each other: each of them becomes what it already was
  • implicitly: and thus we get Being thrown into abeyance and absorbed,
  • with its several characteristics negatived. Such Being is Essence.
  • Measure is implicitly Essence; and its process consists in realising
  • what it is implicitly.--The ordinary consciousness conceives things
  • as being, and studies them in quality, quantity, and measure. These
  • immediate characteristics however soon show themselves to be not fixed
  • but transient; and Essence is the result of their dialectic. In the
  • sphere of Essence one category does not pass into another, but refers
  • to another merely. In Being, the form of reference is purely due to
  • our reflection on what takes place: but it is the special and proper
  • characteristic of Essence. In the sphere of Being, when somewhat
  • becomes another, the somewhat has vanished. Not so in Essence: here
  • there is no real other, but only diversity, reference of the one
  • to _its_ other. The transition of Essence is therefore at the same
  • time no transition: for in the passage of different into different,
  • the different does not vanish: the different terms remain in their
  • relation. When we speak of Being and Nought, Being is independent, so
  • is Nought. The case is otherwise with the Positive and the Negative.
  • No doubt these possess the characteristic of Being and Nought. But
  • the positive by itself has no sense; it is wholly in reference to the
  • negative. And it is the same with the negative. In the sphere of Being
  • the reference of one term to another is only implicit; in Essence on
  • the contrary it is explicit And this in general is the distinction
  • between the forms of Being and Essence: in Being everything is
  • immediate, in Essence everything is relative.
  • CHAPTER VIII.
  • SECOND SUB-DIVISION OF LOGIC.
  • THE DOCTRINE OF ESSENCE.
  • 112.] The terms in Essence are always mere pairs of correlatives, and
  • not yet absolutely reflected in themselves: hence in essence the actual
  • unity of the notion is not realised, but only postulated by reflection.
  • Essence,--which is Being coming into mediation with itself through the
  • negativity of itself--is self-relatedness, only in so far as it is
  • relation to an Other,--this Other however coming to view at first not
  • as something which _is,_ but as postulated and hypothetised.--Being has
  • not vanished: but, firstly, Essence, as simple self-relation, is Being,
  • and secondly as regards its one-sided characteristic of immediacy,
  • Being is deposed to a mere negative, to a seeming or reflected
  • light--Essence accordingly is Being thus reflecting light into itself.
  • The Absolute is the Essence. This is the same definition as the
  • previous one that the Absolute is Being, in so far as Being likewise
  • is simple self-relation. But it is at the same time higher, because
  • Essence is Being that has gone into itself: that is to say, the
  • simple self-relation (in Being) is expressly put as negation of
  • the negative, as immanent self-mediation.--Unfortunately when the
  • Absolute is defined to be the Essence, the negativity which this
  • implies is often taken only to mean the withdrawal of all determinate
  • predicates. This negative action of withdrawal or abstraction thus
  • falls outside of the Essence--which is thus left as a mere result apart
  • from its premisses,--the _caput mortuum_ of abstraction. But as this
  • negativity, instead of being external to Being, is its own dialectic,
  • the truth of the latter, viz. Essence, will be Being as retired within
  • itself,--immanent Being. That reflection, or light thrown into itself,
  • constitutes the distinction between Essence and immediate Being, and is
  • the peculiar characteristic of Essence itself.
  • * * * * *
  • Any mention of Essence implies that we distinguish it from Being:
  • the latter is immediate, and, compared with the Essence, we look upon
  • it as mere seeming. But this seeming is not an utter nonentity and
  • nothing at all, but Being superseded and put by. The point of view
  • given by the Essence is in general the standpoint of 'Reflection.'
  • This word 'reflection' is originally applied, when a ray of light in
  • a straight line impinging upon the surface of a mirror is thrown back
  • from it. In this phenomenon we have two things,--first an immediate
  • fact which is, and secondly the deputed, derivated, or transmitted
  • phase of the same.--Something of this sort takes place when we reflect,
  • or think upon an object; for here we want to know the object, not in
  • its immediacy, but as derivative or mediated. The problem or aim of
  • philosophy is often represented as the ascertainment of the essence of
  • things: a phrase which only means that things instead of being left
  • in their immediacy, must be shown to be mediated by, or based upon,
  • something else. The immediate Being of things is thus conceived under
  • the image of a rind or curtain behind which the Essence lies hidden.
  • Everything, it is said, has an Essence; that is, things really are not
  • what they immediately show themselves. There is therefore something
  • more to be done than merely rove from one quality to another, and
  • merely to advance from qualitative to quantitative, and _vice versâ:_
  • there is a permanent in things, and that permanent is in the first
  • instance their Essence. With respect to other meanings and uses of the
  • category of Essence, we may note that in the German auxiliary verb
  • _'sein'_ the past tense is expressed by the term for Essence (_Wesen_):
  • we designate past being as _gewesen._ This anomaly of language implies
  • to some extent a correct perception of the relation between Being and
  • Essence. Essence we may certainly regard as past Being, remembering
  • however meanwhile that the past is not utterly denied, but only laid
  • aside and thus at the same time preserved. Thus, to say, Caesar _was_
  • in Gaul, only denies the immediacy of the event, but not his sojourn
  • in Gaul altogether. That sojourn is just what forms the import of
  • the proposition, in which however it is represented as over and
  • gone.--'_Wesen_' in ordinary life frequently means only a collection
  • or aggregate: Zeitungswesen (the Press), Postwesen (the Post-Office),
  • Steuerwesen (the Revenue). All that these terms mean is that the things
  • in question are not to be taken single, in their immediacy, but as a
  • complex, and then, perhaps, in addition, in their various bearings.
  • This usage of the term is not very different in its implication from
  • our own.
  • People also speak of _finite_ Essences, such as man. But the very term
  • Essence implies that we have made a step beyond finitude: and the title
  • as applied to man is so far inexact. It is often added that there is
  • a supreme Essence (Being): by which is meant God. On this two remarks
  • may be made. In the first place the phrase 'there is' suggests a
  • finite only: as when we say, there are so many planets, or, there are
  • plants of such a constitution and plants of such an other. In these
  • cases we are speaking of something which has other things beyond and
  • beside it. But God, the absolutely infinite, is not something outside
  • and beside whom there are other essences. All else outside f God, if
  • separated from Him, possesses no essentiality: in its I isolation it
  • becomes a mere show or seeming, without stay or essence of its own.
  • But, secondly, it is a poor way of talking to call God the _highest_
  • or supreme Essence. The category of quantity which the phrase employs
  • has its proper place within the compass of the finite. When we call
  • one mountain the highest on the earth, we have a vision of other
  • high mountains beside it. So too when we call any one the richest or
  • most learned in his country. But God, far from being _a_ Being, even
  • the highest, is _the_ Being. This definition, however, though such
  • a representation of God is an important and necessary stage in the
  • growth of the religious consciousness, does not by any means exhaust
  • the depth of the ordinary Christian idea of God. If we consider God as
  • the Essence only, and nothing more, we know Him only as the universal
  • and irresistible Power; in other words, as the Lord. Now the fear of
  • the Lord is, doubtless, the beginning,--but _only_ the beginning, of
  • wisdom. To look at God in this light, as the Lord, and the Lord alone,
  • is especially characteristic of Judaism and also of Mohammedanism.
  • The defect of these religions lies in their scant recognition of the
  • finite, which, be it as natural things or as finite phases of mind,
  • it is characteristic of the heathen and (as they also for that reason
  • are) polytheistic religions to maintain intact. Another not uncommon
  • assertion is that God, as the supreme Being, cannot be known. Such is
  • the view taken by modern 'enlightenment' and abstract understanding,
  • which is content to say, _Il y a un être suprême_: and there lets
  • the matter rest. To speak thus, and treat God merely as the supreme
  • other-world Being, implies that we look upon the world before us in
  • its immediacy as something permanent and positive, and forget that
  • true Being is just the superseding of all that is immediate. If God
  • be the abstract super-sensible Being, outside whom therefore lies all
  • difference and all specific character, He is only a bare name, a mere
  • _caput mortuum_ of abstracting understanding. The true knowledge of God
  • begins when we know that things, as they immediately are, have no truth.
  • In reference also to other subjects besides God the category of Essence
  • is often liable to an abstract use, by which, in the study of anything,
  • its Essence is held to be something unaffected by, and subsisting in
  • independence of, its definite phenomenal embodiment. Thus we say, for
  • example, of people, that the great thing is not what they do or how
  • they behave, but what they are. This is correct, if it means that a
  • man's conduct should be looked at, not in its immediacy, but only as
  • it is explained by his inner self, and as a revelation of that inner
  • self. Still it should be remembered that the only means by which the
  • Essence and the inner self can be verified, is their appearance in
  • outward reality; whereas the appeal which men make to the essential
  • life, as distinct from the material facts of conduct, is generally
  • prompted by a desire to assert their own subjectivity and to elude an
  • absolute and objective judgment.
  • 113.] Self-relation in Essence is the form of Identity or of
  • reflection-into-self, which has here taken the place of the immediacy
  • of Being. They are both the same abstraction,--self-relation.
  • The unintelligence of sense, to take everything limited and finite for
  • Being, passes into the obstinacy of understanding, which views the
  • finite as self-identical, not inherently self-contradictory.
  • 114.] This identity, as it has descended from Being, appears in the
  • first place only charged with the characteristics of Being, and
  • referred to Being as to something external. This external Being, if
  • taken in separation from the true Being (of Essence), is called the
  • Unessential. But that turns out a mistake. Because Essence is
  • Being-in-self, it is essential only to the extent that it has in itself
  • its negative, _e._ reference to another, or mediation. Consequently,
  • it has the unessential as its own proper seeming (reflection) in
  • itself. But in seeming or mediation there is distinction involved:
  • and since what is distinguished (as distinguished from the identity
  • out of which it arises, and in which it is not, or lies as seeming,)
  • receives itself the form of identity, the semblance is still in the
  • mode of Being, or of self-related immediacy. The sphere of Essence
  • thus turns out to be a still imperfect combination of immediacy and
  • mediation. In it every term is expressly invested with the character
  • of self-relatedness, while yet at the same time one is forced beyond
  • it. It has Being,--reflected being, a being in which another shows,
  • and which shows in another. And so it is also the sphere in which the
  • contradiction, still implicit in the sphere of Being, is made explicit.
  • As the one notion is the common principle underlying all logic, there
  • appear in the development of Essence the same attributes or terms as
  • in the development of Being, but in a reflex form. Instead of Being
  • and Nought we have now the forms of Positive and Negative; the former
  • at first as Identity corresponding to pure and uncontrasted Being, the
  • latter developed (showing in itself) as Difference. So also, we have
  • Becoming represented by the Ground of determinate Being: which itself,
  • when reflected upon the Ground, is Existence.
  • The theory of Essence is the most difficult branch of Logic. It
  • includes the categories of metaphysic and of the sciences in general.
  • These are products of reflective understanding, which, while it assumes
  • the differences to possess a footing of their own, and at the same
  • time also expressly affirms their relativity, still combines the two
  • statements, side by side, or one after the other, by an 'Also,' without
  • bringing these thoughts into one, or unifying them into the notion.
  • A.--ESSENCE AS GROUND OF EXISTENCE.
  • (a) _The pure principles or categories of Reflection._
  • (α) Identity.
  • 115.] The Essence lights up _in itself_ or is mere reflection: and
  • therefore is only self-relation, not as immediate but as reflected. And
  • that reflex relation is self-Identity.
  • This Identity becomes an Identity in form only, or of the
  • understanding, if it be held hard and fast, quite aloof from
  • difference. Or, rather, abstraction is the imposition of this Identity
  • of form, the transformation of something inherently concrete into this
  • form of elementary simplicity. And this may be done in two ways. Either
  • we may neglect a part of the multiple features which are found in the
  • concrete thing (by what is called analysis) and select only one of
  • them; or, neglecting their variety, we may concentrate the multiple
  • characters into one.
  • If we associate Identity with the Absolute, making the Absolute the
  • subject of a proposition, we get: The Absolute is what is identical
  • with itself. However true this proposition may be, it is doubtful
  • whether it be meant in its truth: and therefore it is at least
  • imperfect in the expression. For it is left undecided, whether it means
  • the abstract Identity of understanding,--abstract, that is, because
  • contrasted with the other characteristics of Essence, or the Identity
  • which is inherently concrete. In the latter case, as will be seen,
  • true Identity is first discoverable in the Ground, and, with a higher
  • truth, in the Notion.--Even the word Absolute is often used to mean no
  • more than 'abstract.' Absolute space and absolute time, for example, is
  • another way of saying abstract space and abstract time.
  • When the principles of Essence are taken as essential principles of
  • thought they become predicates of a pre-supposed subject, which,
  • because they are essential, is 'Everything,' The propositions thus
  • arising have been stated as universal Laws of Thought. Thus the first
  • of them, the maxim of Identity, reads: Everything is identical with
  • itself, A=A: and, negatively, A cannot at the same time be A and not
  • A.--This maxim, instead of being a true law of thought, is nothing
  • but the law of abstract understanding. The propositional form itself
  • contradicts it: for a proposition always promises a distinction
  • between subject and predicate; while the present one does not fulfil
  • what its form requires. But the Law is particularly set aside by
  • the following so-called Laws of Thought, which make laws out of its
  • opposite.--It is asserted that the maxim of Identity, though it
  • cannot be proved, regulates the procedure of every consciousness,
  • and that experience shows it to be accepted as soon as its terms
  • are apprehended. To this alleged experience of the logic-books may
  • be opposed the universal experience that no mind thinks or forms
  • conceptions or speaks, in accordance with this law, and that no
  • existence of any kind whatever conforms to it. Utterances after the
  • fashion of this pretended law (A planet is--a planet; Magnetism
  • is--magnetism; Mind is--mind) are, as they deserve to be, reputed
  • silly. That is certainly matter of general experience. The logic which
  • seriously propounds such laws and the scholastic world in which alone
  • they are valid have long been discredited with practical common sense
  • as well as with the philosophy of reason.
  • * * * * * *
  • Identity is, in the first place, the repetition of what we had earlier
  • as Being, but as _become,_ through supersession of its character of
  • immediateness. It is therefore Being as Ideality.--It is important
  • to come to a proper understanding on the true meaning of Identity:
  • and, for that purpose, we must especially guard against taking it
  • as abstract Identity, to the exclusion of all Difference. That is
  • the touchstone for distinguishing all bad philosophy from what alone
  • deserves the name of philosophy. Identity in its truth, as an Ideality
  • of what immediately is, is a high category for our religious modes
  • of mind as well as all other forms of thought and mental activity.
  • The true knowledge of God, it may be said, begins when we know Him as
  • identity,--as absolute identity. To know so much is to see that all
  • the power and glory of the world sinks into nothing in God's presence,
  • and subsists only as the reflection of His power and His glory. In
  • the same way, Identity, as self-consciousness, is what distinguishes
  • man from nature, particularly from the brutes which never reach the
  • point of comprehending themselves as 'I,' that is, pure self-contained
  • unity. So again, in connexion with thought, the main thing is not to
  • confuse the true Identity, which contains Being and its characteristics
  • ideally transfigured in it, with an abstract Identity, identity of bare
  • form. All the charges of narrowness, hardness, meaninglessness, which
  • are so often directed against thought from the quarter of feeling and
  • immediate perception, rest on the perverse assumption that thought
  • acts only as a faculty of abstract Identification. The Formal Logic
  • itself confirms this assumption by laying down the supreme law of
  • thought (so-called) which has been discussed above. If thinking were no
  • more than an abstract Identity, we could not but own it to be a most
  • futile and tedious business. No doubt the notion, and the idea too, are
  • identical with themselves: but identical only in so far as they at the
  • same time involve distinction.
  • (β) _Difference._
  • 116.] Essence is mere Identity and reflection in itself only as it is
  • self-relating negativity, and in that way self-repulsion. It contains
  • therefore essentially the characteristic of Difference.
  • Other-being is here no longer qualitative, taking the shape of the
  • character or limit. It is now in Essence, in self-relating essence, and
  • therefore the negation is at the same time a relation,--is, in short,
  • Distinction, Relativity, Mediation.
  • To ask, 'How Identity comes to Difference,' assumes that Identity as
  • mere abstract Identity is something of itself, and Difference also
  • something else equally independent. This supposition renders an answer
  • to the question impossible. If Identity is viewed as diverse from
  • Difference, all that we have in this way is but Difference; and hence
  • we cannot demonstrate the advance to difference, because the person
  • who asks for the How of the progress thereby implies that for him
  • the starting-point is non-existent. The question then when put to
  • the test has obviously no meaning, and its proposer may be met with
  • the question what he means by Identity; whereupon we should soon see
  • that he attaches no idea to it at all, and that Identity is for him
  • an empty name. As we have seen, besides, Identity is undoubtedly a
  • negative,--not however an abstract empty Nought, but the negation of
  • Being and its characteristics. Being so, Identity is at the same time
  • self-relation, and, what is more, negative self-relation; in other
  • words, it draws a distinction between it and itself.
  • 117.] Difference is, first of all, (1) immediate difference, _e.g._
  • Diversity or Variety. In Diversity the different things are each
  • individually what they are, and unaffected by the relation in which
  • they stand to each other. This relation is therefore external to them.
  • In consequence of the various things being thus indifferent to the
  • difference between them, it falls outside them into a third thing, the
  • agent of Comparison. This external difference, as an identity of the
  • objects related, is Likeness; as a non-identity of them, is Unlikeness.
  • The gap which understanding allows to divide these characteristics, is
  • so great, that although comparison has one and the same substratum for
  • likeness and unlikeness, which are explained to be different aspects
  • and points of view in it, still likeness by itself is the first of the
  • elements alone, viz. identity, and unlikeness by itself is difference.
  • Diversity has, like Identity, been transformed into a maxim:
  • 'Everything is various or different': or,'There are no two things
  • completely like each other.' Here Everything is put under a predicate,
  • which is the reverse of the identity attributed to it in the first
  • maxim; and therefore under a law contradicting the first. However there
  • is an explanation. As the diversity is supposed due only to external
  • comparison, anything taken _per se_ is expected and understood always
  • to be identical with itself, so that the second law need not interfere
  • with the first. But, in that case, variety does not belong to the
  • something or everything in question: it constitutes no intrinsic
  • characteristic of the subject: and the second maxim on this showing
  • does not admit of being stated at all. If, on the other hand, the
  • something _itself_ is as the maxim says diverse, it must be in virtue
  • of its own proper character: but in this case the specific difference,
  • and not variety as such, is what is intended. And this is the meaning
  • of the maxim of Leibnitz.
  • When understanding sets itself to study Identity, it has already passed
  • beyond it, and is looking at Difference in the shape of bare Variety.
  • If we follow the so-called law of Identity, and say,--The sea is the
  • sea, The air is the air, The moon is the moon, these objects pass for
  • having no bearing on one another. What we have before us therefore is
  • not Identity, but Difference. We do not stop at this point however, or
  • regard things merely as different. We compare them one with another,
  • and thus discover the features of likeness and unlikeness. The work of
  • the finite sciences lies to a great extent in the application of these
  • categories, and the phrase 'scientific treatment' generally means no
  • more than the method which has for its aim comparison of the objects
  • under examination. This method has undoubtedly led to some important
  • results;--we may particularly mention the great advance of modern times
  • in the provinces of comparative anatomy and comparative linguistic.
  • But it is going too far to suppose that the comparative method can be
  • employed with equal success in all branches of knowledge. Nor--and this
  • must be emphasised--can mere comparison ever ultimately satisfy the
  • requirements of science. Its results are indeed indispensable, but they
  • are still labours only preliminary to truly intelligent cognition.
  • If it be the office of comparison to reduce existing differences to
  • Identity, the science, which most perfectly fulfils that end, is
  • mathematics. The reason of that is, that quantitative difference is
  • only the difference which is quite external. Thus, in geometry, a
  • triangle and a quadrangle, figures qualitatively different, have this
  • qualitative difference discounted by abstraction, and are equalised to
  • one another in magnitude. It follows from what has been formerly said
  • about the mere Identity of understanding that, as has also been pointed
  • out (§ 99, note), neither philosophy nor the empirical sciences need
  • envy this superiority of Mathematics.
  • The story is told that, when Leibnitz propounded the maxim of Variety,
  • the cavaliers and ladies of the court, as they walked round the garden,
  • made efforts to discover two leaves indistinguishable from each other,
  • in order to confute the law stated by the philosopher. Their device was
  • unquestionably a convenient method of dealing with metaphysics,--one
  • which has not ceased to be fashionable. All the same, as regards the
  • principle of Leibnitz, difference must be understood to mean not an
  • external and indifferent diversity merely, but difference essential.
  • Hence the very nature of things implies that they must be different.
  • 118.] Likeness is an Identity only of those things which are not
  • the same, not identical with each other: and Unlikeness is a
  • relation of things unlike. The two therefore do not fall on different
  • aspects or points of view in the thing, without any mutual affinity:
  • but one throws light into the other. Variety thus comes to be reflexive
  • difference, or difference (distinction) implicit and essential,
  • determinate or specific difference.
  • * * * * * *
  • While things merely various show themselves unaffected by each other,
  • likeness and unlikeness on the contrary are a pair of characteristics
  • which are in completely reciprocal relation. The one of them cannot
  • be thought without the other. This advance from simple variety to
  • opposition appears in our common acts of thought, when we allow that
  • comparison has a meaning only upon the hypothesis of an existing
  • difference, and that on the other hand we can distinguish only on the
  • hypothesis of existing similarity.
  • Hence, if the problem be the discovery of a difference, we attribute
  • no great cleverness to the man who only distinguishes those objects,
  • of which the difference is palpable, _e.g._ a pen and a camel:
  • and similarly, it implies no very advanced faculty of comparison,
  • when the objects compared, _e.g._ a beech and an oak, a temple and
  • a church, are near akin. In the case of difference, in short, we
  • like to sec identity, and in the case of identity we like to see
  • difference. Within the range of the empirical sciences however, the
  • one of these two categories is often allowed to put the other out of
  • sight and mind. Thus the scientific problem at one time is to reduce
  • existing differences to identity; on another occasion, with equal
  • one-sidedness, to discover new differences. We see this especially in
  • physical science. There the problem consists, in the first place, in
  • the continual search for new 'elements,' new forces, new genera, and
  • species. Or, in another direction, it seeks to show that all bodies
  • hitherto believed to be simple are compound: and modern physicists and
  • chemists smile at the ancients, who were satisfied with four elements,
  • and these not simple. Secondly, and on the other hand, mere identity
  • is made the chief question. Thus electricity and chemical affinity
  • are regarded as the same, and even the organic processes of digestion
  • and assimilation are looked upon as a mere chemical operation. Modern
  • philosophy has often been nicknamed the Philosophy of Identity. But, as
  • was already remarked (§ 103, note), it is precisely philosophy, and in
  • particular speculative logic, which lays bare the nothingness of the
  • abstract, undifferentiated identity, known to understanding; though it
  • also undoubtedly urges its disciples not to rest at mere diversity, but
  • to ascertain the inner unity of all existence.
  • 119.] Difference implicit is essential difference, the Positive
  • and the Negative: and that is this way. The Positive is the
  • identical self-relation in such a way as not to be the Negative, and
  • the Negative is the different by itself so as not to be the Positive.
  • Thus either has an existence of its own in proportion as it is not the
  • other. The one is made visible in the other, and is only in so far as
  • that other is. Essential difference is therefore Opposition; according
  • to which the different is not confronted by _any_ other but by _its_
  • other. That is, either of these two (Positive and Negative) is stamped
  • with a characteristic of its own only in its relation to the other: the
  • one is only reflected into itself as it is reflected into the other.
  • And so with the other. Either in this way is the other's _own_ other.
  • Difference implicit or essential gives the maxim, Everything is
  • essentially distinct; or, as it has also been expressed, Of two
  • opposite predicates the one only can be assigned to anything, and
  • there is no third possible. This maxim of Contrast or Opposition
  • most expressly controverts the maxim of Identity: the one says a
  • thing should be only self-relation, the other says that it must be
  • an opposite, a relation to its other. The native unintelligence of
  • abstraction betrays itself by setting in juxtaposition two contrary
  • maxims, like these, as laws, without even so much as comparing
  • them.--The Maxim of Excluded Middle is the maxim of the definite
  • understanding, which would fain avoid contradiction, but in so doing
  • falls into it. A must be either + A or - A, it says. It virtually
  • declares in these words a third A which is neither + nor--, and which
  • at the same time is yet invested with + and - characters. If + W mean
  • 6 miles to the West, and - W mean 6 miles to the East, and if the +
  • and - cancel each other, the 6 miles of way or space remain what they
  • were with and without the contrast. Even the mere _plus_ and _minus_ of
  • number or abstract direction have, if we like, zero, for their third:
  • but it need not be denied that the empty contrast, which understanding
  • institutes between _plus_ and _minus,_ is not without its value in such
  • abstractions as number, direction, &c.
  • In the doctrine of contradictory concepts, the one notion is, say,
  • blue (for in this doctrine even the sensuous generalised image of a
  • colour is called a notion) and the other not-blue. This other then
  • would not be an affirmative, say, yellow, but would merely be kept at
  • the abstract negative.--That the Negative in its own nature is quite as
  • much Positive (see next §), is implied in saying that what is opposite
  • to another is _its_ other. The inanity of the opposition between what
  • are called contradictory notions is fully exhibited in what we may call
  • the grandiose formula of a general law, that Everything has the one and
  • not the other of _all_ predicates which are in such opposition. In this
  • way, mind is either white or not-white, yellow or not-yellow, &c, _ad
  • infinitum._
  • It was forgotten that Identity and Opposition are themselves opposed,
  • and the maxim of Opposition was taken even for that of Identity,
  • in the shape of the principle of Contradiction. A notion, which
  • possesses neither or both of two mutually contradictory marks, _e.g._
  • a quadrangular circle, is held to be logically false. Now though a
  • multangular circle and a rectilineal arc no less contradict this
  • maxim, geometers never hesitate to treat the circle as a polygon with
  • rectilineal sides. But anything like a circle (that is to say its mere
  • character or nominal definition) is still no notion. In the notion
  • of a circle, centre and circumference are equally essential: both
  • marks belong to it: and yet centre and circumference are opposite and
  • contradictory to each other.
  • The conception of Polarity, which is so dominant in physics, contains
  • by implication the more correct definition of Opposition. But physics
  • for its theory of the laws of thought adheres to the ordinary logic; it
  • might therefore well be horrified in case it should ever work out the
  • conception of Polarity, and get at the thoughts which are implied in it.
  • (1) With the positive we return to identity, but in its higher truth
  • as identical self-relation, and at the same time with the note that it
  • is not the negative. The negative _per se_ is the same as difference
  • itself. The identical as such is primarily the yet uncharacterised:
  • the positive on the other hand is what is self-identical, but with the
  • mark of antithesis to an other. And the negative is difference as such,
  • characterised as not identity. This is the difference of difference
  • within its own self.
  • Positive and negative are supposed to express an absolute difference.
  • The two however are at bottom the same: the name of either might be
  • transferred to the other. Thus, for example, debts and assets are not
  • two particular, self-subsisting species of property. What is negative
  • to the debtor, is positive to the creditor. A way to the east is also
  • a way to the west. Positive and negative are therefore intrinsically
  • conditioned by one another, and are only in relation to each other. The
  • north pole of the magnet cannot be without the south pole, and _vice
  • versâ._ If we cut a magnet in two, we have not a north pole in one
  • piece, and a south pole in the other. Similarly, in electricity, the
  • positive and the negative are not two diverse and independent fluids.
  • In opposition, the different is not confronted by any other, but by
  • _its_ other. Usually we regard different things as unaffected by each
  • other. Thus we say: I am a human being, and around me are air, water,
  • animals, and all sorts of things. Everything is thus put outside of
  • every other. But the aim of philosophy is to banish indifference, and
  • to ascertain the necessity of things. By that means the other is seen
  • to stand over against _its_ other. Thus, for example, inorganic nature
  • is not to be considered merely something else than organic nature, but
  • the necessary antithesis of it. Both are in essential relation to one
  • another; and the one of the two is, only in so far as it excludes the
  • other from it, and thus relates itself thereto. Nature in like manner
  • is not without mind, nor mind without nature. An important step has
  • been taken, when we cease in thinking to use phrases like: Of course
  • something else is also possible. While we so speak, we are still
  • tainted with contingency: and all true thinking, we have already said,
  • is a thinking of necessity.
  • In modern physical science the opposition, first observed to exist
  • in magnetism as polarity, has come to be regarded as a universal law
  • pervading the whole of nature. This would be a real scientific advance,
  • if care were at the same time taken not to let mere variety revert
  • without explanation, as a valid category, side by side with opposition.
  • Thus at one time the colours are regarded as in polar opposition to one
  • another, and called complementary colours: at another time they are
  • looked at in their indifferent and merely quantitative difference of
  • red, yellow, green, &c.
  • (2) Instead of speaking by the maxim of Excluded Middle (which is the
  • maxim of abstract understanding) we should rather say: Everything is
  • opposite. Neither in heaven nor in earth, neither in the world of
  • mind nor of nature, is there anywhere such an abstract 'Either--or'
  • as the understanding maintains. Whatever exists is concrete, with
  • difference and opposition in itself. The finitude of things will then
  • lie in the want of correspondence between their immediate being, and
  • what they essentially are. Thus, in inorganic nature, the acid is
  • implicitly at the same time the base: in other words, its only being
  • consists in its relation to its other. Hence also the acid is not
  • something that persists quietly in the contrast: it is always in effort
  • to realise what it potentially is. Contradiction is the very moving
  • principle of the world: and it is ridiculous to say that contradiction
  • is unthinkable. The only thing correct in that statement is that
  • contradiction is not the end of the matter, but cancels itself. But
  • contradiction, when cancelled, does not leave abstract identity; for
  • that is itself only one side of the contrariety. The proximate result
  • of opposition (when realised as contradiction) is the Ground, which
  • contains identity as well as difference superseded and deposed to
  • elements in the completer notion.
  • 120.] Contrariety then has two forms. The Positive is the aforesaid
  • various (different) which is understood to be independent, and yet
  • at the same not to be unaffected by its relation to its other. The
  • Negative is to be, no less independently, negative self-relating,
  • self-subsistent, and yet at the same time as Negative must on every
  • point have this its self-relation, _i.e._ its Positive, only in the
  • other. Both Positive and Negative are therefore explicit contradiction;
  • both are potentially the same. Both are so actually also; since either
  • is the abrogation of the other and of itself. Thus they fall to the
  • Ground.--Or as is plain, the essential difference, as a difference, is
  • only the difference of it from itself, and thus contains the identical:
  • so that to essential and actual difference there belongs itself as
  • well as identity. As self-relating difference it is likewise virtually
  • enunciated as the self-identical. And the opposite is in general that
  • which includes the one and its other, itself and its opposite. The
  • immanence of essence thus defined is the Ground.
  • (γ) _The Ground._
  • 121.] The Ground is the unity of identity and difference, the
  • truth of what difference and identity have turned out to be,--the
  • reflection-into-self, which is equally a reflection-into-an-other, and
  • _vice versâ._ It is essence put explicitly as a totality.
  • The maxim of the Ground runs thus: Everything has its Sufficient
  • Ground: that is, the true essentiality of any thing is not the
  • predication of it as identical with itself, or as different (various),
  • or merely positive, or merely negative, but as having its Being in
  • an other, which, being its self-same, is its essence. And to this
  • extent the essence is not abstract reflection into self, but into an
  • other. The Ground is the essence in its own inwardness; the essence is
  • intrinsically a ground; and it is a ground only when it is a ground of
  • somewhat, of an other.
  • We must be careful, when we say that the ground is the unity of
  • identity and difference, not to understand by this unity an abstract
  • identity. Otherwise we only change the name, while we still think the
  • identity (of understanding) already seen to be false. To avoid this
  • misconception we may say that the ground, besides being the unity,
  • is also the difference of identity and difference. In that case in
  • the ground, which promised at first to supersede contradiction, a new
  • contradiction seems to arise. It is however a contradiction which, so
  • far from persisting quietly in itself, is rather the expulsion of it
  • from itself. The ground is a ground only to the extent that it affords
  • ground: but the result which thus issued from the ground is only
  • itself. In this lies its formalism. The ground and what is grounded are
  • one and the same content: the difference between the two is the mere
  • difference of form which separates simple self-relation, on the one
  • hand, from mediation or derivativeness on the other. Inquiry into the
  • grounds of things goes with the point of view which, as already noted
  • (note to § 112), is adopted by Reflection. We wish, as it were, to see
  • the matter double, first in its immediacy, and secondly in its ground,
  • where it is no longer immediate. This is the plain meaning of the law
  • of sufficient ground, as it is called; it asserts that things should
  • essentially be viewed as mediated. The manner in which Formal Logic
  • establishes this law of thought, sets a bad example to other sciences.
  • Formal Logic asks these sciences not to accept their subject-matter as
  • it is immediately given; and yet herself lays down a law of thought
  • without deducing it,--in other words, without exhibiting its mediation.
  • With the same justice as the logician maintains our faculty of thought
  • to be so constituted that we must ask for the ground of everything,
  • might the physicist, when asked why a man who falls into water is
  • drowned, reply that man happens to be so organised that he cannot live
  • under water; or the jurist, when asked why a criminal is punished,
  • reply that civil society happens to be so constituted that crimes
  • cannot be left unpunished.
  • Yet even if logic be excused the duty of giving a ground for the law
  • of the sufficient ground, it might at least explain what is to be
  • understood by a ground. The common explanation, which describes the
  • ground as what has a consequence, seems at the first glance more lucid
  • and intelligible than the preceding definition in logical terms. If you
  • ask however what the consequence is, you are told that it is what has
  • a ground; and it becomes obvious that the explanation is intelligible
  • only because it assumes what in our case has been reached as the
  • termination of an antecedent movement of thought. And this is the
  • true business of logic: to show that those thoughts, which as usually
  • employed merely float before consciousness neither understood nor
  • demonstrated, are really grades in the self-determination of thought.
  • It is by this means that they are understood and demonstrated.
  • In common life, and it is the same in the finite sciences, this
  • reflective form is often employed as a key to the secret of the real
  • condition of the objects under investigation. So long as we deal with
  • what may be termed the household needs of knowledge, nothing can be
  • urged against this method of study. But it can never afford definitive
  • satisfaction, either in theory or practice. And the reason why it
  • fails is that the ground is yet without a definite content of its own;
  • I so that to regard anything as resting upon a ground merely gives
  • the formal difference of mediation in place of immediacy. We see an
  • electrical phenomenon, for example, and we ask for its ground (or
  • reason): we are told that electricity is the ground of this phenomenon.
  • What is this but the same content as we had immediately before us, only
  • translated into the form of inwardness?
  • The ground however is not merely simple self-identity, but also
  • different: hence various grounds may be alleged for the same sum
  • of fact. This variety of grounds, again, following the logic of
  • difference, culminates in opposition of grounds _pro_ and _contra._
  • In any action, such as a theft, there is a sum of fact in which
  • several aspects may be distinguished. The theft has violated the
  • rights of property: it has given the means of satisfying his wants to
  • the needy thief: possibly too the man, from whom the theft was made,
  • misused his property. The violation of property is unquestionably
  • the decisive point of view before which the others must give way:
  • but the bare law of the ground cannot settle that question. Usually
  • indeed the law is interpreted to speak of a sufficient ground, not
  • of any ground whatever: and it might be supposed therefore, in the
  • action referred to, that, although other points of view besides the
  • violation of property might be held as grounds, yet they would not be
  • sufficient grounds. But here comes a dilemma. If we use the phrase
  • 'sufficient ground,' the epithet is either otiose, or of such a kind
  • as to carry us past the mere category of ground. The predicate is
  • otiose and tautological, if it only states the capability of giving a
  • ground or reason: for the ground is a ground, only in so far as it has
  • this capability. If a soldier runs away from battle to save his life,
  • his conduct is certainly a violation of duty: but it cannot be held
  • that the ground which led him so to act was insufficient, otherwise
  • he would have remained at his post. Besides, there is this also to
  • be said. On one hand any ground suffices: on the other no ground
  • suffices as mere ground; because, as already said, it is yet void of
  • a content objectively and intrinsically determined, and is therefore
  • not self-acting and productive. A content thus objectively and
  • intrinsically determined, and hence self-acting, will hereafter come
  • before us as the notion: and it is the notion which Leibnitz had in his
  • eye when he spoke of sufficient ground, and urged the study of things
  • under its point of view. His remarks were originally directed against
  • that merely mechanical method of conceiving things so much in vogue
  • even now; a method which he justly pronounces insufficient. We may
  • see an instance of this mechanical theory of investigation, when the
  • organic process of the circulation of the blood is traced back merely
  • to the contraction of the heart; or when certain theories of criminal
  • law explain the purpose of punishment to lie in deterring people from
  • crime, in rendering the criminal harmless, or in other extraneous
  • grounds of the same kind. It is unfair to Leibnitz to suppose that he
  • was content with anything so poor as this formal law of the ground. The
  • method of investigation which he inaugurated is the very reverse of a
  • formalism which acquiesces in mere grounds, where a full and concrete
  • knowledge is sought. Considerations to this effect led Leibnitz to
  • contrast _causae efficientes_ and _causae finales,_ and to insist in
  • the place of final causes as the conception to which the efficient were
  • to lead up. If we adopt this distinction, light, heat, and moisture
  • would be the _causae efficientes,_ not the _causa finalis_ of the
  • growth of plants: the _causa finalis_ is the notion of the plant itself.
  • To get no further than mere grounds, especially on questions of law and
  • morality, is the position and principle of the Sophists. Sophistry,
  • as we ordinarily conceive it, is a method of investigation which aims
  • at distorting what is just and true, and exhibiting things in a false
  • light. Such however is not the proper or primary tendency of Sophistry:
  • the standpoint of which is no other than that of 'Raisonnement.' The
  • Sophists came on the scene at a time when the Greeks had begun to grow
  • dissatisfied with mere authority and tradition and felt the need of
  • intellectual justification for what they were to accept as obligatory.
  • That desideratum the Sophists supplied by teaching their countrymen
  • to seek for the various points of view under which things may be
  • considered: which points of view are the same as grounds. But the
  • ground, as we have seen, has no essential and objective principles of
  • its own, and it is as easy to discover grounds for what is wrong and
  • immoral as for what is moral and right. Upon the observer therefore it
  • depends to decide what points are to have most weight. The decision in
  • such circumstances is prompted by his individual views and sentiments.
  • Thus the objective foundation of what ought to have been of absolute
  • and essential obligation, accepted by all, was undermined: and
  • Sophistry by this destructive action deservedly brought upon itself
  • the bad name previously mentioned. Socrates, as we all know, met the
  • Sophists at every point, not by a bare re-assertion of authority and
  • tradition against their argumentations, but by showing dialectically
  • how untenable the mere grounds were, and by vindicating the obligation
  • of justice and goodness,--by reinstating the universal or notion of the
  • will. In the present day such a method of argumentation is not quite
  • out of fashion. Nor is that the case only in the discussion of secular
  • matters. It occurs even in sermons, such as those where every possible
  • ground of gratitude to God is propounded. To such pleading Socrates
  • and Plato would not have scrupled to apply the name of Sophistry.
  • For Sophistry has nothing to do with what is taught:--that may very
  • possibly be true. Sophistry lies in the formal circumstance of teaching
  • it by grounds which are as available for attack as for defence. In a
  • time so rich in reflection and so devoted to _raisonnement_ as our
  • own, he must be a poor creature who cannot advance a good ground for
  • everything, even for what is worst and most depraved. Everything in the
  • world that has become corrupt has had good ground for its corruption.
  • An appeal to grounds at first makes the hearer think of beating a
  • retreat: but when experience has taught him the real state of these
  • matters, he closes his ears against them, and refuses to be imposed
  • upon any more.
  • 122.] As it first comes, the chief feature of Essence is show in itself
  • and intermediation in itself. But when it has completed the circle
  • of intermediation, its unity with itself is explicitly put as the
  • self-annulling of difference, and therefore of intermediation. Once
  • more then we come back to immediacy or Being,--but Being in so far as
  • it is intermediated by annulling the intermediation. And that Being is
  • Existence.
  • The ground is not yet determined by objective principles of its
  • own, nor is it an end or final cause: hence it is not active, nor
  • productive. An Existence only _proceeds from_ the ground. The
  • determinate ground is therefore a formal matter: that is to say, any
  • point will do, so long as it is expressly put as self-relation, as
  • affirmation, in correlation with the immediate existence depending on
  • it. If it be a ground at all, it is a good ground: for the term 'good'
  • is employed abstractly as equivalent to affirmative; and any point (or
  • feature) is good which can in any way be enunciated as confessedly
  • affirmative. So it happens that a ground can be found and adduced for
  • everything: and a good ground (for example, a good motive for action)
  • may effect something or may not, it may have a consequence or it may
  • not. It becomes a motive (strictly so called) and effects something,
  • _e.g._ through its reception into a will; there and there only it
  • becomes active and is made a cause.
  • (b) _Existence._
  • 123.] Existence is the immediate unity of reflection-into-self and
  • reflection-into-another. It follows from this that existence is the
  • indefinite multitude of existents as reflected-into-themselves, which
  • at the same time equally throw light upon one another,--which, in
  • short, are co-relative, and form a world of reciprocal dependence and
  • of infinite interconnexion between grounds and consequents. The grounds
  • are themselves existences: and the existents in like manner are in many
  • directions grounds as well as consequents.
  • The phrase 'Existence' (derived from _existere_) suggests the fact of
  • having proceeded from something. Existence is Being which has proceeded
  • from the ground, and been reinstated by annulling its intermediation.
  • The Essence, as Being set aside and absorbed, originally came
  • before us as shining or showing in self, and the categories of this
  • reflection are identity, difference and ground. The last is the unity
  • of identity and difference; and because it unifies them it has at the
  • same time to distinguish itself from itself. But that which is in
  • this way distinguished from the ground is as little mere difference,
  • as the ground itself is abstract sameness. The ground works its
  • own suspension: and when suspended, the result of its negation is
  • existence. Having issued from the ground, existence contains the ground
  • in it 'the ground does not remain, as it were, behind existence, but by
  • its very nature supersedes itself and translates itself into existence.
  • This is exemplified even in our ordinary mode of thinking, when we
  • look upon the ground of a thing, not as something abstractly inward,
  • but as itself also an existent. For example, the lightning-flash
  • which has set a house on fire would be considered the ground of the
  • conflagration: or the manners of a nation and the condition of its
  • life would be regarded as the ground of its constitution. Such indeed
  • is the ordinary aspect in which the existent world originally appears
  • to reflection,--an indefinite crowd of things existent, which being
  • simultaneously reflected on themselves and on one another are related
  • reciprocally as ground and consequence. In this motley play of the
  • world, if we may so call the sum of existents, there is nowhere a
  • firm footing to be found: everything bears an aspect of relativity,
  • conditioned by and conditioning something else. The reflective
  • understanding makes it its business to elicit and trace these
  • connexions running out in every direction; but the question touching an
  • ultimate design is so far left unanswered, and therefore the craving of
  • the reason after knowledge passes with the further development of the
  • logical Idea beyond this position of mere relativity.
  • 124.] The reflection-on-another of the existent is however inseparable
  • from the reflection-on-self: the ground is their unity, from which
  • existence has issued. The existent therefore includes relativity, and
  • has on its own part its multiple interconnexions with other existents:
  • it is reflected on itself as its ground. The existent is, when so
  • described, a Thing.
  • The 'thing-by-itself' (or thing in the abstract), so famous in the
  • philosophy of Kant, shows itself here in its genesis. It is seen to be
  • the abstract reflection-on-self, which is clung to, to the exclusion of
  • reflection-on-other-things and of all predication of difference. The
  • thing-by-itself therefore is the empty substratum for these predicates
  • of relation.
  • If to know means to comprehend an object in its concrete character,
  • then the thing-by-itself, which is nothing but the quite abstract
  • and indeterminate thing in general, must certainly be as unknowable
  • as it is alleged to be. With as much reason however as we speak
  • of the thing-by-itself, we might speak of quality-by-itself or
  • quantity-by-itself, and of any other category. The expression would
  • then serve to signify that these categories are taken in their abstract
  • immediacy, apart from their development and inward character. It is
  • no better than a whim of the understanding, therefore, if we attach
  • the qualificatory 'in or by-itself' to the _thing_ only. But this
  • 'in or by-itself' is also applied to the facts of the mental as well
  • as the natural world: as we speak of electricity or of a plant in
  • itself, so we speak of man or the state in itself. By this 'in-itself'
  • in these objects we are meant to understand what they strictly and
  • properly are. This usage is liable to the same criticism as the
  • phrase 'thing-in-itself.' For if we stick to the mere 'in-itself' of
  • an object, we apprehend it not in its truth, but in the inadequate
  • form of mere abstraction. Thus the man, by or in himself, is the
  • child. And what the child has to do is to rise out of this abstract
  • and undeveloped 'in-himself,' and become 'for himself what he is at
  • first only 'in-himself,' a free and reasonable being. Similarly, the
  • state-in-itself is the yet immature and patriarchal state, where the
  • various political functions, latent in the notion of the state, have
  • not received the full logical constitution which the logic of political
  • principles demands. In the same sense, the germ may be called the
  • plant-in-itself. These examples may show the mistake of supposing
  • that the 'thing-in-itself' or the 'in-itself' of things is something
  • inaccessible to our cognition. All things are originally in-themselves,
  • but that is not the end of the matter. As the germ, being the
  • plant-in-itself, means self-development, so the thing in general passes
  • beyond its in-itself, (the abstract reflection on self,) to manifest
  • itself further as a reflection on other things. It is in this sense
  • that it has properties.
  • (c) _The Thing._
  • 125.] (α) The Thing is the totality--the development in explicit
  • unity--of the categories of the ground and of existence. On the side
  • of one of its factors, viz. reflection-on-other-things, it has in it
  • the differences, in virtue of which it is a characterised and concrete
  • thing. These characteristics are different from one another; they have
  • their reflection-into-self not on their own part, but on the part of
  • the thing. They are Properties of the thing: and their relation to the
  • thing is expressed by the word 'have.'
  • As a term of relation, 'to have' takes the place of 'to be.' True,
  • somewhat has qualities on its part too: but this transference of
  • 'Having' into the sphere of Being is inexact, because the character as
  • quality is directly one with the somewhat, and the somewhat ceases to
  • be when it loses its quality. But the thing is reflection-into-self:
  • for it is an identity which is also distinct from the difference,
  • _i.e._ from its attributes.--In many languages 'have' is employed
  • to denote past time. And with reason: for the past is absorbed or
  • suspended being, and the mind is its reflection-into-self; in the mind
  • only it continues to subsist,--the mind however distinguishing from
  • itself this being in it which has been absorbed or suspended.
  • * * * * *
  • In the Thing all the characteristics of reflection recur as existent.
  • Thus the thing, in its initial aspect, as the thing-by-itself, is the
  • self-same or identical. But identity, it was proved, is not found
  • without difference: so the properties, which the thing has, are the
  • existent difference in the form of diversity. In the case of diversity
  • or variety each diverse member exhibited an indifference to every
  • other, and they had no other relation to each other, save what was
  • given by a comparison external to them. But now in the thing we have a
  • bond which keeps the various properties in union. Property, besides,
  • should not be confused with quality. No doubt, we also say, a thing
  • has qualities. But the phraseology is a misplaced one: 'having' hints
  • at an independence, foreign to the 'Somewhat,' which is still directly
  • identical with its quality. Somewhat is what it is only by its
  • quality: whereas, though the thing indeed exists only as it has its
  • properties, it is not confined to this or that definite property, and
  • can therefore lose it, without ceasing to be what it is.
  • 126.] (ß) Even in the ground, however, the reflection-on-something-else
  • is directly convertible with reflection-on-self. And hence the
  • properties are not merely different from each other; they are also
  • self-identical, independent, and relieved from their attachment to the
  • thing. Still, as they are the characters of the thing distinguished
  • from one another (as reflected-into-self), they are not themselves
  • things, if things be concrete; but only existences reflected
  • into themselves as abstract characters. They are what are called
  • Matters.
  • Nor is the name 'things' given to Matters, such as magnetic and
  • electric matters. They are qualities proper, a reflected Being,--one
  • with their Being,--they are the character that has reached immediacy,
  • existence: they are 'entities.'
  • To elevate the properties, which the Thing has, to the independent
  • position of matters, or materials of which it consists, is a proceeding
  • based upon the notion of a Thing: and for that reason is also found
  • in experience. Thought and experience however alike protest against
  • concluding from the fact that certain properties of a thing, such
  • as colour, or smell, may be represented as particular colouring or
  • odorific matters, that we are then at the end of the inquiry, and
  • that nothing more is needed to penetrate to the true secret of things
  • than a disintegration of them into their component materials. This
  • disintegration into independent matters is properly restricted to
  • inorganic nature only. The chemist is in the right therefore when,
  • for example, he analyses common salt or gypsum into its elements, and
  • finds that the former consists of muriatic acid and soda, the latter of
  • sulphuric acid and calcium. So too the geologist does well to regard
  • granite as a compound of quartz, felspar, and mica. These matters,
  • again, of which the thing consists, are themselves partly things,
  • which in that way may be once more reduced to more abstract matters.
  • Sulphuric acid, for example, is a compound of sulphur and oxygen. Such
  • matters or bodies can as a matter of fact be exhibited as subsisting by
  • themselves: but frequently we find other properties of things, entirely
  • wanting this self-subsistence, also regarded as particular matters.
  • Thus we hear caloric, and electrical or magnetic matters spoken of.
  • Such matters are at the best figments of understanding. And we see
  • here the usual procedure of the abstract reflection of understanding.
  • Capriciously adopting single categories, whose value entirely depends
  • on their place in the gradual evolution of the logical idea, it employs
  • them in the pretended interests of explanation, but in the face of
  • plain, unprejudiced perception and experience, so as to trace back to
  • them every object investigated. Nor is this all. The theory, which
  • makes things consist of independent matters, is frequently applied in a
  • region where it has neither meaning nor force. For within the limits of
  • nature even, wherever there is organic life, this category is obviously
  • inadequate. An animal may be said to consist of bones, muscles, nerves,
  • &c.: but evidently we are here using the term 'consist' in a very
  • different sense from its use when we spoke of the piece of granite as
  • consisting of the above-mentioned elements. The elements of granite are
  • utterly indifferent to their combination: they could subsist as well
  • without it. The different parts and members of an organic body on the
  • contrary subsist only in their union: they cease to exist as such, when
  • they are separated from each other.
  • 127.] Thus Matter is the mere abstract or indeterminate
  • reflection-into-something-else, or reflection-into-self at the same
  • time as determinate; it is consequently Thinghood which then and there
  • is,--the subsistence of the thing. By this means the thing has on the
  • part of the matters its reflection-into-self (the reverse of § 125);
  • it subsists not on its own part, but consists of the matters, and is
  • only a superficial association between them, an external combination of
  • them.
  • 128.] (γ) Matter, being the immediate unity of existence with itself,
  • is also indifferent towards specific character. Hence the numerous
  • diverse matters coalesce into the one Matter, or into existence
  • under the reflective characteristic of identity. In contrast to this
  • one Matter these distinct properties and their external relation which
  • they have to one another in the thing, constitute the _Form_,--the
  • reflective category of difference, but a difference which exists and is
  • a totality.
  • This one featureless Matter is also the same as the Thing-by-itself
  • was: only the latter is intrinsically quite abstract, while the former
  • essentially implies relation to something else, and in the first place
  • to the Form.
  • * * * * *
  • The various matters of which the thing consists are potentially the
  • same as one another. Thus we get one Matter in general to which the
  • difference is expressly attached externally and as a bare form. This
  • theory which holds things all round to have one and the same matter at
  • bottom, and merely to differ externally in respect of form, is much in
  • vogue with the reflective understanding. Matter in that case counts for
  • naturally indeterminate, but susceptible of any determination; while at
  • the same time it is perfectly permanent, and continues the same amid
  • all change and alteration. And in finite things at least this disregard
  • of matter for any determinate form is certainly exhibited. For example,
  • it matters not to a block of marble, whether it receive the form of
  • this or that statue or even the form of a pillar. Be it noted however
  • that a block of marble can disregard form only relatively, that is, in
  • reference to the sculptor: it is by no means purely formless. And so
  • the mineralogist considers the relatively formless marble as a special
  • formation of rock, differing from other equally special formations,
  • such as sandstone or porphyry. Therefore we say it is an abstraction
  • of the understanding which isolates matter into a certain natural
  • formlessness. For properly speaking the thought of matter includes the
  • principle of form throughout, and no formless matter therefore appears
  • anywhere even in experience as existing. Still the conception of
  • matter as original and pre-existent, and as naturally formless, is a
  • very ancient one; it meets us even among the Greeks, at first in the
  • mythical shape of Chaos, which is supposed to represent the unformed
  • substratum of the existing world. Such a conception must of necessity
  • tend to make God not the Creator of the world, but a mere world-moulder
  • or demiurge. A deeper insight into nature reveals God as creating the
  • world out of nothing. And that teaches two things. On the one hand it
  • enunciates that matter, as such, has no independent subsistence, and on
  • the other that the form does not supervene upon matter from without,
  • but as a totality involves the principle of matter in itself. This free
  • and infinite form will hereafter come before us as the notion.
  • 129.] Thus the Thing suffers a disruption into Matter and Form. Each
  • of these is the totality of thinghood and subsists for itself. But
  • Matter, which is meant to be the positive and indeterminate existence,
  • contains, as an existence, reflection-on-another, every whit as
  • much as it contains self-enclosed being. Accordingly as uniting
  • these characteristics, it is itself the totality of Form. But Form,
  • being a complete whole of characteristics, _ipso facto_ involves
  • reflection-into-self; in other words, as self-relating Form it has the
  • very function attributed to Matter. Both are at bottom the same. Invest
  • them with this unity, and you have the relation of Matter and Form,
  • which are also no less distinct.
  • 130.] The Thing, being this totality, is a contradiction. On the side
  • of its negative unity it is Form in which Matter is determined and
  • deposed to the rank of properties (§ 125). At the same time it consists
  • of Matters, which in the reflection-of-the-thing-into-itself are as
  • much independent as they are at the same time negatived. Thus the thing
  • is the essential existence, in such a way as to be an existence that
  • suspends or absorbs itself in itself. In other words, the thing is an
  • Appearance or Phenomenon.
  • The negation of the several matters, which is insisted on in the
  • thing no less than their independent existence, occurs in Physics as
  • _porosity._ Each of the several matters (colouring matter, odorific
  • matter, and if we believe some people, even sound-matter,--not
  • excluding caloric, electric matter, &c:) is also negated: and in this
  • negation of theirs, or as interpenetrating their pores, we find the
  • numerous other independent matters, which, being similarly porous,
  • make room in turn for the existence of the rest. Pores are not
  • empirical facts; they are figments of the understanding, which uses
  • them to represent the element of negation in independent matters.
  • The further working-out of the contradictions is concealed by the
  • nebulous imbroglio in which all matters are independent and all no less
  • negated in each other.--If the faculties or activities are similarly
  • hypostatised in the mind, their living unity similarly turns to the
  • imbroglio of an action of the one on the others.
  • These pores (meaning thereby not the pores in an organic body, such as
  • the pores of wood or of the skin, but those in the so-called 'matters,'
  • such as colouring matter, caloric, or metals, crystals, &c.) cannot be
  • verified by observation. In the same way matter itself,--furthermore
  • form which is separated from matter,--whether that be the thing as
  • consisting of matters, or the view that the thing itself subsists and
  • only has proper ties,--is all a product of the reflective understanding
  • which, while it observes and professes to record only what it observes,
  • is rather creating a metaphysic, bristling with contradictions of which
  • it is unconscious.
  • B.--APPEARANCE.
  • 131.] The Essence must appear or shine forth. Its shining or reflection
  • in it is the suspension and translation of it to immediacy, which,
  • whilst as reflection-on-self it is matter or subsistence, is also form,
  • reflection-on-something-else, a subsistence which sets itself aside. To
  • show or shine is the characteristic by which essence is distinguished
  • from being,--by which it is essence; and it is this show which, when
  • it is developed, shows itself, and is Appearance. Essence accordingly
  • is not something beyond or behind appearance, but just because it
  • is the essence which exists--the existence is Appearance
  • (Forth-shining).
  • * * * * *
  • Existence stated explicitly in its contradiction is Appearance. But
  • appearance (forth-shining) is not to be confused with a mere show
  • (shining). Show is the proximate truth of Being or immediacy. The
  • immediate, instead of being, as we suppose, something independent,
  • resting on its own self, is a mere show, and as such it is packed or
  • summed up under the simplicity of the immanent essence. The essence
  • is, in the first place, the sum total of the showing itself, shining
  • in itself (inwardly); but, far from abiding in this inwardness, it
  • comes as a ground forward into existence; and this existence being
  • grounded not in itself, but on something else, is just appearance.
  • In our imagination we ordinarily combine with the term appearance
  • or phenomenon the conception of an indefinite congeries of things
  • existing, the being of which is purely relative, and which consequently
  • do not rest on a foundation of their own, but are esteemed only as
  • passing stages. But in this conception it is no less implied that
  • essence does not linger behind or beyond appearance. Rather it is, we
  • may say, the Infinite kindness which lets its own show freely issue
  • into immediacy, and graciously allows it the joy of existence. The
  • appearance which is thus created does not stand on its own feet, and
  • has its being not in itself but in something else. God who is the
  • essence, when He lends existence to the passing stages of His own show
  • in Himself, may be described as the goodness that creates a world: but
  • He is also the power above it, and the righteousness, which manifests
  • the merely phenomenal character of the content of this existing world,
  • whenever it tries to exist in independence.
  • Appearance is in every way a very important grade of the logical idea.
  • It may be said to be the distinction of philosophy from ordinary
  • consciousness that it sees the merely phenomenal character of what the
  • latter supposes to have a self-subsistent being. The significance of
  • appearance however must be properly grasped, or mistakes will arise.
  • To say that anything is a _mere_ appearance may be misinterpreted to
  • mean that, as compared with what is merely phenomenal, there is greater
  • truth in the immediate, in that which _is._ Now in strict fact, the
  • case is precisely the reverse. Appearance is higher than mere Being,--a
  • richer category because it holds in combination the two elements of
  • reflection-into-self and reflection-into-another: whereas Being (or
  • immediacy) still mere relationlessness and apparently rests upon itself
  • alone. Still, to say that anything is _only_ an appearance suggests a
  • real flaw, which consists in this, that Appearance is still divided
  • against itself and without intrinsic stability. Beyond and above mere
  • appearance comes in the first place Actuality, the third grade of
  • Essence, of which we shall afterwards speak.
  • In the history of Modern Philosophy, Kant has the merit of first
  • rehabilitating this distinction between the common and the philosophic
  • modes of thought. He stopped half-way however, when he attached to
  • Appearance a subjective meaning only, and put the abstract essence
  • immovable outside it as the thing-in-itself beyond the reach of our
  • cognition. For it is the very nature of the world of immediate objects
  • to be appearance only. Knowing it to be so, we know at the same time
  • the essence, which, far from staying behind or beyond the appearance,
  • rather manifests its own essentiality by deposing the world to a mere
  • appearance. One can hardly quarrel with the plain man who, in his
  • desire for totality, cannot acquiesce in the doctrine of subjective
  • idealism, that we are solely concerned with phenomena. The plain man,
  • however, in his desire to save the objectivity of knowledge, may very
  • naturally return to abstract immediacy, and maintain that immediacy
  • to be true and actual. In a little work published under the title,
  • _A Report, clear as day, to the larger Public touching the proper
  • nature of the Latest Philosophy: an Attempt to force the reader to
  • understand,'_ Fichte examined the opposition between subjective
  • idealism and immediate consciousness in a popular form, under the shape
  • of a dialogue between the author and the reader, and tried hard to
  • prove that the subjective idealist's point of view was right. In this
  • dialogue the reader complains to the author that he has completely
  • failed to place himself in the idealist's position, and is inconsolable
  • at the thought that things around him are no real things but mere
  • appearances. The affliction of the reader can scarcely be blamed when
  • he is expected to consider himself hemmed in by an impervious circle
  • of purely subjective conceptions. Apart from this subjective view of
  • Appearance, however, we have all reason to rejoice that the things
  • which environ us are appearances and not steadfast and independent
  • existences; since in that case we should soon perish of hunger, both
  • bodily and mental.
  • (a) _The World of Appearance._
  • 132.] The Apparent or Phenomenal exists in such a way, that its
  • subsistence is _ipso facto_ thrown into abeyance or suspended and
  • is only one stage in the form itself. The form embraces in it the
  • matter or subsistence as one of its characteristics. In this way
  • the phenomenal has its ground in this (form) as its essence, its
  • reflection-into-self in contrast with its immediacy, but, in so doing,
  • has it only in another aspect of the form. This ground of its is no
  • less phenomenal than itself, and the phenomenon accordingly goes on to
  • an endless mediation of subsistence by means of form, and thus equally
  • by non-subsistence. This endless inter-mediation is at the same time
  • a unity of self-relation; and existence is developed into a totality,
  • into a world of phenomena,--of reflected finitude.
  • (b) _Content and Form._
  • 133.] Outside one another as the phenomena in this phenomenal
  • world are, they form a totality, and are wholly contained in their
  • self-relatedness. In this way the self-relation of the phenomenon is
  • completely specified, it has the Form in itself: and because it
  • is in this identity, has it as essential subsistence. So it comes about
  • that the form is Content: and in its mature phase is the Law
  • of the Phenomenon. When the form, on the contrary, is not reflected
  • into self, it is equivalent to the negative of the phenomenon, to
  • the non-independent and changeable: and that sort of form is the
  • indifferent or External Form.
  • The essential point to keep in mind about the opposition of Form and
  • Content is that the content is not formless, but has the form in its
  • own self, quite as much as the form is external to it. There is thus
  • a doubling of form. At one time it is reflected into itself; and then
  • is identical with the content. At another time it is not reflected
  • into itself, and then is the external existence, which does not at
  • all affect the content. We are here in presence, implicitly, of the
  • absolute correlation of content and form: viz. their reciprocal
  • revulsion, so that content is nothing but the revulsion of form into
  • content, and form nothing but the revulsion of content into form. This
  • mutual revulsion is one of the most important laws of thought. But it
  • is not explicitly brought out before the Relations of Substance and
  • Causality.
  • Form and content are a pair of terms frequently employed by the
  • reflective understanding, especially with a habit of looking on the
  • content as the essential and independent, the form on the contrary as
  • the unessential and dependent. Against this it is to be noted that both
  • are in fact equally essential; and that, while a formless _content_ can
  • be as little found as a formless _matter,_ the two (content and matter)
  • are distinguished by this circumstance, that matter, though implicitly
  • not without form, still in its existence manifests a disregard of form,
  • whereas the content, as such, is what it is only because the matured
  • form is included in it. Still the form comes before us sometimes as
  • an existence indifferent and external to content, and does so for
  • the reason that the whole range of Appearance still suffers from
  • externality. In a book, for instance, it certainly has no bearing upon
  • the content, whether it be written or printed, bound in paper or in
  • leather. That however does not in the least imply that apart from such
  • an indifferent and external form, the content of the book is itself
  • formless. There are undoubtedly books enough which even in reference
  • to their content may well be styled formless: but want of form in this
  • case is the same as bad form, and means the defect of the right form,
  • not the absence of all form whatever. So far is this right form from
  • being unaffected by the content that it is rather the content itself. A
  • work of art that wants the right form is for that very reason no right
  • or true work of art: and it is a bad way of excusing an artist, to say
  • that the content of his works is good and even excellent, though they
  • want the right form. Real works of art are those where content and form
  • exhibit a thorough identity. The content of the Iliad, it may be said,
  • is the Trojan war, and especially the wrath of Achilles. In that we
  • have everything, and yet very little after all; for the Iliad is made
  • an Iliad by the poetic form, in which that content is moulded. The
  • content of Romeo and Juliet may similarly be said to be the ruin of two
  • lovers through the discord between their families: but something more
  • is needed to make Shakespeare's immortal tragedy.
  • In reference to the relation of form and content in the field of
  • science, we should recollect the difference between philosophy and
  • the rest of the sciences. The latter are finite, because their mode
  • of thought, as a merely formal act, derives its content from without.
  • Their content therefore is not known as moulded from within through
  • the thoughts which lie at the ground of it, and form and content do
  • not thoroughly interpenetrate each other. This partition disappears in
  • philosophy, and thus justifies its title of infinite knowledge. Yet
  • even philosophic thought is often held to be a merely formal act; and
  • that logic, which confessedly deals only with thoughts _quâ_ thoughts,
  • is merely formal, is especially a foregone conclusion. And if content
  • means no more than what is palpable and obvious to the senses, all
  • philosophy and logic in particular must be at once acknowledged to
  • be void of content, that is to say, of content perceptible to the
  • senses. Even ordinary forms of thought however, and the common usage of
  • language, do not in the least restrict the appellation of content to
  • what is perceived by the senses, or to what has a being in place and
  • time. A book without content is, as every one knows, not a book with
  • empty leaves, but one of which the content is as good as none. We shall
  • find as the last result on closer analysis, that by what is called
  • content an educated mind means nothing but the presence and power of
  • thought. But this is to admit that thoughts are not empty forms without
  • affinity to their content, and that in other spheres as well as in art
  • the truth and the sterling value of the content essentially depend on
  • the content showing itself identical with the form.
  • 134.] But immediate existence is a character of the subsistence itself
  • as well as of the form: it is consequently external to the character of
  • the content; but in an equal degree this externality, which the content
  • has through the factor of its subsistence, is essential to it. When
  • thus explicitly stated, the phenomenon is relativity or correlation:
  • where one and the same thing, viz. the content or the developed
  • form, is seen as the externality and antithesis of independent
  • existences, and as their reduction to a relation of identity, in which
  • identification alone the two things distinguished are what they are.
  • (c) _Relation or Correlation._
  • 135.] (α) The immediate relation is that of the Whole and the
  • Parts. The content is the whole, and consists of the parts (the
  • form), its counterpart. The parts are diverse one from another. It is
  • they that possess independent being. But they are parts, only when they
  • are identified by being related to one another; or, in so far as they
  • make up the whole, when taken together. But this 'Together' is the
  • counterpart and negation of the part.
  • Essential correlation is the specific and completely universal
  • phase in which things appear. Everything that exists stands in
  • correlation, and this correlation is the veritable nature of every
  • existence. The existent thing in this way has no being of its own, but
  • only in something else: in this other however it is self-relation; and
  • correlation is the unity of the self-relation and relation-to-others.
  • The relation of the whole and the parts is untrue to this extent, that
  • the notion and the reality of the relation are not in harmony. The
  • notion of the whole is to contain parts: but if the whole is taken
  • and made what its notion implies, _i.e._ if it is divided, it at once
  • ceases to be a whole. Things there are, no doubt, which correspond
  • to this relation: but for that very reason they are low and untrue
  • existences. We must remember however what 'untrue' signifies. When
  • it occurs in a philosophical discussion, the term 'untrue' does not
  • signify that the thing to which it is applied is non-existent. A bad
  • state or a sickly body may exist all the same; but these things are
  • untrue, because their notion and their reality are out of harmony.
  • The relation of whole and parts, being the immediate relation, comes
  • easy to reflective understanding; and for that reason it often
  • satisfies when the question really turns on profounder ties. The limbs
  • and organs, for instance, of an organic body are not merely parts of
  • it: it is only in their unity that they are what they are, and they
  • are unquestionably affected by that unity, as they also in turn affect
  • it. These limbs and organs become mere parts, only when they pass under
  • the hands of the anatomist, whose occupation, be it remembered, is not
  • with the living body but with the corpse. Not that such analysis is
  • illegitimate: we only mean that the external and mechanical relation of
  • whole and parts is not sufficient for us, if we want to study organic
  • life in its truth. And if this be so in organic life, it is the case
  • to a much greater extent when we apply this relation to the mind and
  • the formations of the spiritual world. Psychologists may not expressly
  • speak of parts of the soul or mind, but the mode in which this
  • subject is treated by the analytic understanding is largely founded
  • on the analogy of this finite relation. At least that is so, when the
  • different forms of mental activity are enumerated and described merely
  • in their isolation one after another, as so-called special powers and
  • faculties.
  • 136.] (β) The one-and-same of this correlation (the self-relation
  • found in it) is thus immediately a negative self-relation. The
  • correlation is in short the mediating process whereby one and the
  • same is first unaffected towards difference, and secondly is the
  • negative self-relation, which repels itself as reflection-into-self to
  • difference, and invests itself (as reflection-into-something-else) with
  • existence, whilst it conversely leads back this reflection-into-other
  • to self-relation and indifference. This gives the correlation of
  • Force and its Expression.
  • The relationship of whole and part is the immediate and therefore
  • unintelligent (mechanical) relation,--a revulsion of self-identity
  • into mere variety. Thus we pass from the whole to the parts, and from
  • the parts to the whole: in the one we forget its opposition to the
  • other, while each on its own account, at one time the whole, at another
  • the parts, is taken to be an independent existence. In other words,
  • when the parts are declared to subsist in the whole, and the whole
  • to consist of the parts, we have either member of the relation at
  • different times taken to be permanently subsistent, while the other is
  • non-essential. In its superficial form the mechanical nexus consists in
  • the parts being independent of each other and of the whole.
  • This relation may be adopted for the progression _ad infinitum,_
  • in the case of the divisibility of matter: and then it becomes an
  • unintelligent alternation with the two sides. A thing at one time is
  • taken as a whole: then we go on to specify the parts: this specifying
  • is forgotten, and what was a part is regarded as a whole: then the
  • specifying of the part comes up again, and so on for ever. But if this
  • infinity be taken as the negative which it is, it is the _negative_
  • self-relating element in the correlation,--Force, the self-identical
  • whole, or immanency; which yet supersedes this immanency and gives
  • itself expression;--and conversely the expression which vanishes and
  • returns into Force.
  • Force, notwithstanding this infinity, is also finite: for the content,
  • or the one and the same of the Force and its out-putting, is this
  • identity at first only for the observer: the two sides of the relation
  • are not yet, each on its own account, the concrete identity of that
  • one and same, not yet the totality. For one another they are therefore
  • different, and the relationship is a finite one. Force consequently
  • requires solicitation from without: it works blindly: and on account of
  • this defectiveness of form, the content is also limited and accidental.
  • It is not yet genuinely identical with the form: not yet is it _as_ a
  • notion and an end; that is to say, it is not intrinsically and actually
  • determinate. This difference is most vital, but not easy to apprehend:
  • it will assume a clearer formulation when we reach Design. If it be
  • overlooked, it leads to the confusion of conceiving God as Force, a
  • confusion from which Herder's God especially suffers.
  • It is often said that the nature of Force itself is unknown and only
  • its manifestation apprehended. But, in the first place, it may be
  • replied, every article in the import of Force is the same as what
  • is specified in the Exertion: and the explanation of a phenomenon
  • by a Force is to that extent a mere tautology. What is supposed to
  • remain unknown, therefore, is really nothing but the empty form of
  • reflection-into-self, by which alone the Force is distinguished from
  • the Exertion,--and that form too is something familiar. It is a form
  • that does not make the slightest addition to the content and to the
  • law, which have to be discovered from the phenomenon alone. Another
  • assurance always given is that to speak of forces implies no theory as
  • to their nature: and that being so, it is impossible to see why the
  • form of Force has been introduced into the sciences at all. In the
  • second place the nature of Force is undoubtedly unknown: we are still
  • without any necessity binding and connecting its content together in
  • itself, as we are without necessity in the content, in so far as it is
  • expressly limited and hence has its character by means of another thing
  • outside it.
  • (1) Compared with the immediate relation of whole and parts, the
  • relation between force and its putting-forth may be considered
  • infinite. In it that identity of the two sides is realised, which in
  • the former relation only existed for the observer. The whole, though
  • we can see that it consists of parts, ceases to be a whole when it
  • is divided: whereas force is only shown to be force when it exerts
  • itself, and in its exercise only comes back to itself. The exercise is
  • only force once more. Yet, on further examination even this relation
  • will appear finite, and finite in virtue of this mediation: just
  • as, conversely, the relation of whole and parts is obviously finite
  • in virtue of its immediacy. The first and simplest evidence for the
  • finitude of the mediated relation of force and its exercise is, that
  • each and every force is conditioned and requires something else than
  • itself for its subsistence. For instance, a special vehicle of magnetic
  • force, as is well known, is iron, the other properties of which, such
  • as its colour, specific weight, or relation to acids, are independent
  • of this connexion with magnetism. The same thing is seen in all other
  • forces, which from one end to the other are found to be conditioned
  • and mediated by something else than themselves. Another proof of
  • the finite nature of force is that it requires solicitation before
  • it can put itself forth. That through which the force is solicited,
  • is itself another exertion of force, which cannot put itself forth
  • without similar solicitation. This brings us either to a repetition of
  • the infinite progression, or to a reciprocity of soliciting and being
  • solicited. In either case we have no absolute beginning of motion.
  • Force is not as yet, like the final cause, inherently self-determining:
  • the content is given to it as determined, and force, when it exerts
  • itself, is, according to the phrase, blind in its working. That phrase
  • implies the distinction between abstract force-manifestation and
  • teleological action.
  • (2) The oft-repeated statement, that the exercise of the force and
  • not the force itself admits of being known, must be rejected as
  • groundless. It is the very essence of force to manifest itself, and
  • thus in the totality of manifestation, conceived as a law, we at the
  • same time discover the force itself. And yet this assertion that force
  • in its own self is unknowable betrays a well-grounded presentiment
  • that this relation is finite. The several manifestations of a force at
  • first meet us in indefinite multiplicity, and in their isolation seem
  • accidental: but, reducing this multiplicity to its inner unity, which
  • we term force, we see that the apparently contingent is necessary, by
  • recognising the law that rules it. But the different forces themselves
  • are a multiplicity again, and in their mere juxtaposition seem to be
  • contingent. Hence in empirical physics, we speak of the forces of
  • gravity, magnetism, electricity, &c, and in empirical psychology of
  • the forces of memory, imagination, will, and all the other faculties.
  • All this multiplicity again excites a craving to know these different
  • forces as a single whole, nor would this craving be appeased even if
  • the several forces were traced back to one common primary force. Such
  • a primary force would be really no more than an empty abstraction,
  • with as little content as the abstract thing-in-itself. And besides
  • this, the correlation of force and manifestation is essentially a
  • mediated correlation (of reciprocal dependence), and it must therefore
  • contradict the notion of force to view it as primary or resting on
  • itself.
  • Such being the case with the nature of force, though we may consent to
  • let the world be called a manifestation of divine forces, we should
  • object to have God Himself viewed as a mere force. For force is after
  • all a subordinate and finite category. At the so-called renascence of
  • the sciences, when steps were taken to trace the single phenomena of
  • nature back to underlying forces, the Church branded the enterprise
  • as impious. The argument of the Church was as follows. If it be the
  • forces of gravitation, of vegetation, &c. which occasion the movements
  • of the heavenly bodies, the growth of plants, &c., there is nothing
  • left for divine providence, and God sinks to the level of a leisurely
  • on-looker, surveying this play of forces. The students of nature, it is
  • true, and Newton more than others, when they employed the reflective
  • category of force to explain natural phenomena, have expressly pleaded
  • that the honour of God, as the Creator and Governor of the world, would
  • not thereby be impaired. Still the logical issue of this explanation
  • by means of forces is that the inferential understanding proceeds to
  • fix each of these forces, and to maintain them in their finitude as
  • ultimate. And contrasted with this deinfinitised world of independent
  • forces and matters, the only terms in which it is possible still to
  • describe God will present Him in the abstract infinity of an unknowable
  • supreme Being in some other world far away. This is precisely the
  • position of materialism, and of modern 'free-thinking,' whose theology
  • ignores what God is and restricts itself to the mere fact _that_ He
  • is. In this dispute therefore the Church and the religious mind have
  • to a certain extent the right on their side. The finite forms of
  • understanding certainly fail to fulfil the conditions for a knowledge
  • either of Nature or of the formations in the world of Mind as they
  • truly are. Yet on the other side it is impossible to overlook the
  • formal right which, in the first place, entitles the empirical sciences
  • to vindicate the right of thought to know the existent world in all
  • the speciality of its content, and to seek something further than the
  • bare statement of mere abstract faith that God creates and governs the
  • world. When our religious consciousness, resting upon the authority of
  • the Church, teaches us that God created the world by His almighty will,
  • that He guides the stars in their courses, and vouchsafes to all His
  • creatures their existence and their well-being, the question Why? is
  • still left to answer. Now it is the answer to this question which forms
  • the common task of empirical science and of philosophy. When religion
  • refuses to recognise this problem, or the right to put it, and appeals
  • to the unsearchableness of the decrees of God, it is taking up the same
  • agnostic ground as is taken by the mere Enlightenment of understanding.
  • Such an appeal is no better than an arbitrary dogmatism, which
  • contravenes the express command of Christianity, to know God in spirit
  • and in truth, and is prompted by a humility which is not Christian, but
  • born of ostentatious bigotry.
  • 137.] Force is a whole, which is in its own self negative
  • self-relation; and as such a whole it continually pushes
  • itself off from itself and puts itself forth. But since this
  • reflection-into-another (corresponding to the distinction between the
  • Parts of the Whole) is equally a reflection-into-self, this out-putting
  • is the way and means by which Force that returns back into itself is
  • as a Force. The very act of out-putting accordingly sets in abeyance
  • the diversity of the two sides which is found in this correlation,
  • and expressly states the identity which virtually constitutes their
  • content. The truth of Force and utterance therefore is that relation,
  • in which the two sides are distinguished only as Outward and Inward.
  • 138.] (γ) The Inward (Interior) is the ground, when it
  • stands as the mere form of the one side of the Appearance and
  • the Correlation,--the empty form of reflection-into-self. As a
  • counterpart to it stands the Outward (Exterior),--Existence,
  • also as the form of the other side of the correlation, with the
  • empty characteristic of reflection-into-something-else. But Inward
  • and Outward are identified: and their identity is identity brought
  • to fulness in the content, that unity of reflection-into-self and
  • reflection-into-other which was forced to appear in the movement of
  • force. Both are the same one totality, and this unity makes them the
  • content.
  • 139.] In the first place then, Exterior is the same content as
  • Interior. What is inwardly is also found outwardly, and _vice versâ._
  • The appearance shows nothing that is not in the essence, and in the
  • essence there is nothing but what is manifested.
  • 140.] In the second place, Inward and Outward, as formal terms,
  • are also reciprocally opposed, and that thoroughly. The one is the
  • abstraction of identity with self; the other, of mere multiplicity
  • or reality. But as stages of the one form, they are essentially
  • identical: so that whatever is at first explicitly put only in the one
  • abstraction, is also as plainly and at one step only in the other.
  • Therefore what is only internal is also only external: and what is only
  • external, is so far only at first internal.
  • It is the customary mistake of reflection to take the essence to be
  • merely the interior. If it be so taken, even this way of looking at
  • it is purely external, and that sort of essence is the empty external
  • abstraction.
  • Ins Innere der Natur
  • Dringt sein erschaffner Geist,
  • Zu glücklich wenn er nur
  • Die äußere Schaale weist.[1]
  • It ought rather to have been said that, if the essence of nature is
  • ever described as the inner part, the person who so describes it
  • only knows its outer shell. In Being as a whole, or even in mere
  • sense-perception, the notion is at first only an inward, and for that
  • very reason is something external to Being, a subjective thinking
  • and being, devoid of truth.--In Nature as well as in Mind, so long
  • as the notion, design, or law are at first the inner capacity, mere
  • possibilities, they are first only an external, inorganic nature,
  • the knowledge of a third person, alien force, and the like. As a man
  • is outwardly, that is to say in his actions (not of course in his
  • merely bodily outwardness), so is he inwardly: and if his virtue,
  • morality, &c. are only inwardly his,--that is if they exist only in his
  • intentions and sentiments, and his outward acts are not identical with
  • them, the one half of him is as hollow and empty as the other.
  • The relation of Outward and Inward unites the two relations that
  • precede, and at the same time sets in abeyance mere relativity and
  • phenomenality in general. Yet so long as understanding keeps the Inward
  • and Outward fixed in their separation, they are empty forms, the one
  • as null as the other. Not only in the study of nature, but also of the
  • spiritual world, much depends on a just appreciation of the relation
  • of inward and outward, and especially on avoiding the misconception
  • that the former only is the essential point on which everything turns,
  • while the latter is unessential and trivial. We find this mistake made
  • when, as is often done, the difference between nature and mind is
  • traced back to the abstract difference between inner and outer. As for
  • nature, it certainly is in the gross external, not merely to the mind,
  • but even on its own part. But to call it external 'in the gross' is
  • not to imply an abstract externality--for there is no such thing. It
  • means rather that the Idea which forms the common content of nature and
  • mind, is found in nature as outward only, and for that very reason only
  • inward. The abstract understanding, with its 'Either--or,' may struggle
  • against this conception of nature. It is none the less obviously found
  • in our other modes of consciousness, particularly in religion. It is
  • the lesson of religion that nature, no less than the spiritual world,
  • is a revelation of God: but with this distinction, that while nature
  • never gets so far as to be conscious of its divine essence, that
  • consciousness is the express problem of the mind, which in the matter
  • of that problem is as yet finite. Those who look upon the essence of
  • nature as mere inwardness, and therefore inaccessible to us, take up
  • the same line as that ancient creed which regarded God as envious and
  • jealous; a creed which both Plato and Aristotle pronounced against long
  • ago. All that God is, He imparts and reveals; and He does so, at first,
  • in and through nature.
  • Any object indeed is faulty and imperfect when it is only inward, and
  • thus at the same time only outward, or, (which is the same thing,) when
  • it is only an outward and thus only an inward. For instance, a child,
  • taken in the gross as human being, is no doubt a rational creature;
  • but the reason of the child as child is at first a mere inward, in the
  • shape of his natural ability or vocation, &c. This mere inward, at the
  • same time, has for the child the form of a more outward, in the shape
  • of the will of his parents, the attainments of his teachers, and the
  • whole world of reason that environs him. The education and instruction
  • of a child aim at making him actually and for himself what he is at
  • first potentially and therefore for others, viz. for his grown-up
  • friends. The reason, which at first exists in the child only as an
  • inner possibility, is actualised through education: and conversely, the
  • child by these means becomes conscious that the goodness, religion, and
  • science which he had at first looked upon as an outward authority, are
  • his own and inward nature. As with the child so it is in this matter
  • with the adult, when, in opposition to his true destiny, his intellect
  • and will remain in the bondage of the natural man. Thus, the criminal
  • sees the punishment to which he has to submit as an act of violence
  • from without: whereas in fact the penalty is only the manifestation of
  • his own criminal will.
  • From what has now been said, we may learn what to think of a man who,
  • when blamed for his shortcomings, it may be, his discreditable acts,
  • appeals to the (professedly) excellent intentions and sentiments of
  • the inner self he distinguishes therefrom. There certainly may be
  • individual cases, where the malice of outward circumstances frustrates
  • well-meant designs, and disturbs the execution of the best-laid plans.
  • But in general even here the essential unity between inward and outward
  • is maintained. We are thus justified in saying that a man is what he
  • does; and the lying vanity which consoles itself with the feeling of
  • inward excellence, may be confronted with the words of the gospel: 'By
  • their fruits ye shall know them.' That grand saying applies primarily
  • in a moral and religious aspect, but it also holds good in reference
  • to performances in art and science. The keen eye of a teacher who
  • perceives in his pupil decided evidences of talent, may lead him to
  • state his opinion that a Raphael or a Mozart lies hidden in the boy:
  • and the result will show how far such an opinion was well-founded.
  • But if a daub of a painter, or a poetaster, soothe themselves by the
  • conceit that their head is full of high ideals, their consolation is
  • a poor one; and if they insist on being judged not by their actual
  • works but by their projects, we may safely reject their pretensions
  • as unfounded and unmeaning. The converse case however also occurs. In
  • passing judgment on men who have accomplished something great and good,
  • we often make use of the false distinction between inward and outward.
  • All that they have accomplished, we say, is outward merely; inwardly
  • they were acting from some very different motive, such as a desire to
  • gratify their vanity or other unworthy passion. This is the spirit of
  • envy. Incapable of any great action of its own, envy tries hard to
  • depreciate greatness and to bring it down to its own level. Let us,
  • rather, recall the fine expression of Goethe, that there is no remedy
  • but Love against great superiorities of others. We may seek to rob
  • men's great actions of their grandeur, by the insinuation of hypocrisy;
  • but, though it is possible that men in an instance now and then may
  • dissemble and disguise a good deal, they cannot conceal the whole of
  • their inner self, which infallibly betrays itself in the _decursus
  • vitae._ Even here it is true that a man is nothing but the series of
  • his actions.
  • What is called the 'pragmatic' writing of history has in modern times
  • frequently sinned in its treatment of great historical characters, and
  • defaced and tarnished the true conception of them by this fallacious
  • separation of the outward from the inward. Not content with telling
  • the unvarnished tale of the great acts which have been wrought by
  • the heroes of the world's history, and with acknowledging that their
  • inward being corresponds with the import of their acts, the pragmatic
  • historian fancies himself justified and even obliged to trace the
  • supposed secret motives that lie behind the open facts of the record.
  • The historian, in that case, is supposed to write with more depth in
  • proportion as he succeeds in tearing away the aureole from all that
  • has been heretofore held grand and glorious, and in depressing it, so
  • far as its origin and proper significance are concerned, to the level
  • of vulgar mediocrity. To make these pragmatical researches in history
  • easier, it is usual to recommend the study of psychology, which is
  • supposed to make us acquainted with the real motives of human actions.
  • The psychology in question however is only that petty knowledge of
  • men, which looks away from the essential and permanent in human
  • nature to fasten its glance on the casual and private features shown
  • in isolated instincts and passions. A pragmatical psychology ought
  • at least to leave the historian, who investigates the motives at the
  • ground of great actions, a choice between the 'substantial' interests
  • of patriotism, justice, religious truth and the like, on the one hand,
  • and the subjective and 'formal' interests of vanity, ambition, avarice
  • and the like, on the other. The latter however are the motives which
  • must be viewed by the pragmatist as really efficient, otherwise the
  • assumption of a contrast between the inward (the disposition of the
  • agent) and the outward (the import of the action) would fall to the
  • ground. But inward and outward have in truth the same content; and the
  • right doctrine is the very reverse of this pedantic judicially. If the
  • heroes of history had been actuated by subjective and formal interests
  • alone, they would never have accomplished what they have. And if we
  • have due regard to the unity between the inner and the outer, we must
  • own that great men willed what they did, and did what they willed.
  • 141.] The empty abstractions, by means of which the one identical
  • content perforce continues in the two correlatives, suspend themselves
  • in the immediate transition, the one in the other. The content is
  • itself nothing but their identity (§ 138): and these abstractions are
  • the seeming of essence, put as seeming. By the manifestation of force
  • the inward is put into existence: but this putting is the mediation by
  • empty abstractions. In its own self the intermediating process vanishes
  • to the immediacy, in which the inward and the outward are absolutely
  • identical and their difference is distinctly no more than assumed and
  • imposed. This identity is Actuality.
  • C.--ACTUALITY.
  • 142.] Actuality is the unity, become immediate, of essence with
  • existence, or of inward with outward. The utterance of the actual
  • is the actual itself: so that in this utterance it remains just as
  • essential, and only is essential, in so far as it is in immediate
  • external existence.
  • We have ere this met Being and Existence as forms of the immediate.
  • Being is, in general, unreflected immediacy and transition into
  • another. Existence is immediate unity of being and reflection; hence
  • appearance: it comes from the ground, and falls to the ground. In
  • actuality this unity is explicitly put, and the two sides of the
  • relation identified. Hence the actual is exempted from transition, and
  • its externality is its energising. In that energising it is reflected
  • into itself: its existence is only the manifestation of itself, not of
  • an other.
  • Actuality and thought (or Idea) are often absurdly opposed. How
  • commonly we hear people saying that, though no objection can be urged
  • against the truth and correctness of a certain thought, there is
  • nothing of the kind to be seen in actuality, or it cannot be actually
  • carried out! People who use such language only prove that they have
  • not properly apprehended the nature either of thought or of actuality.
  • Thought in such a case is, on one hand, the synonym for a subjective
  • conception, plan, intention or the like, just as actuality, on the
  • other, is made synonymous with external and sensible existence. This
  • is all very well in common life, where great laxity is allowed in the
  • categories and the names given to them: and it may of course happen
  • that _e.g._ the plan, or so-called idea, say of a certain method of
  • taxation, is good and advisable in the abstract, but that nothing of
  • the sort is found in so-called actuality, or could possibly be carried
  • out under the given conditions. But when the abstract understanding
  • gets hold of these categories and exaggerates the distinction they
  • imply into a hard and fast line of contrast, when it tells us that in
  • this actual world we must knock ideas out of our heads, it is necessary
  • energetically to protest against these doctrines, alike in the name of
  • science and of sound reason. For on the one hand Ideas are not confined
  • to our heads merely, nor is the Idea, upon the whole, so feeble as to
  • leave the question of its actualisation or non-actualisation dependent
  • in our will. The Idea is rather the absolutely active as well I as
  • actual. And on the other hand actuality is not so bad and irrational,
  • as purblind or wrong-headed and muddle-brained would-be reformers
  • imagine. So far is actuality, as distinguished from mere appearance,
  • and primarily presenting a unity of inward and outward, from being in
  • contrariety with reason, that it is rather thoroughly reasonable, and
  • everything which is not reasonable must on that very ground cease to
  • be held actual. The same view may be traced in the usages of educated
  • speech, which declines to give the name of real poet or real statesman
  • to a poet or a statesman who can do nothing really meritorious or
  • reasonable.
  • In that vulgar conception of actuality which mistakes for it what is
  • palpable and directly obvious to the senses, we must seek the ground
  • of a wide-spread prejudice about the relation of the philosophy of
  • Aristotle to that of Plato. Popular opinion makes the difference to be
  • as follows. While Plato recognises the idea and only the idea as the
  • truth, Aristotle, rejecting the idea, keeps to what is actual, and is
  • on that account to be considered the founder and chief of empiricism.
  • On this it may be remarked: that although actuality certainly is
  • the principle of the Aristotelian philosophy, it is not the vulgar
  • actuality of what is immediately at hand, but the idea as actuality.
  • Where then lies the controversy of Aristotle against Plato? It lies in
  • this. Aristotle calls the Platonic idea a mere δίναμις, and establishes
  • in opposition to Plato that the idea, which both equally recognise to
  • be the only truth, is essentially to be viewed as an ἐνέργεια, in other
  • words, as the inward which is quite to the fore, or as the unity of
  • inner and outer, or as actuality, in the emphatic sense here given to
  • the word.
  • 143.] Such a concrete category as Actuality includes the
  • characteristics aforesaid and their difference, and is therefore also
  • the development of them, in such a way that, as it has them, they are
  • at the same time plainly understood to be a show, to be assumed or
  • imposed (§ 141).
  • (α) Viewed as an identity in general, Actuality is first of all
  • Possibility--the reflection-into-self which, as in contrast with
  • the concrete unity of the actual, is taken and made an abstract and
  • unessential essentiality. Possibility is what is essential to reality,
  • but in such a way that it is at the same time only a possibility.
  • It was probably the import of Possibility which induced Kant to regard
  • it along with necessity and actuality as Modalities, 'since these
  • categories do not in the least increase the notion as object, but only
  • express its relation to the faculty of knowledge.' For Possibility is
  • really the bare abstraction of reflection-into-self,--what was formerly
  • called the Inward, only that it is now taken to mean the external
  • inward, lifted out of reality and with the being of a mere supposition,
  • and is thus, sure enough, supposed only as a bare modality, an
  • abstraction which comes short, and, in more concrete terms, belongs
  • only to subjective thought. It is otherwise with Actuality and
  • Necessity. They are anything but a mere sort and mode for something
  • else: in fact the very reverse of that. If they are supposed, it is as
  • the concrete, not merely supposititious, but intrinsically complete.
  • As Possibility is, in the first instance, the mere form of
  • identity-with-self (as compared with the concrete which is actual),
  • the rule for it merely is that a thing must not be self-contradictory.
  • Thus everything is possible; for an act of abstraction can give any
  • content this form of identity. Everything however is as impossible as
  • it is possible. In every content,--which is and must be concrete,--the
  • speciality of its nature may be viewed as a specialised contrariety
  • and in that way as a contradiction. Nothing therefore can be more
  • meaningless than to speak of such possibility and impossibility. In
  • philosophy, in particular, there should never be a word said of showing
  • that 'It is possible,' or 'There is still another possibility,' or, to
  • adopt another phraseology, 'It is conceivable.' The same consideration
  • should warn the writer of history against employing a category which
  • has now been explained to be on its own merits untrue: but the subtlety
  • of the empty understanding finds its chief pleasure in the fantastic
  • ingenuity of suggesting possibilities and lots of possibilities.
  • Our picture-thought is at first disposed to see in possibility the
  • richer and more comprehensive, in actuality the poorer and narrower
  • category. Everything, it is said, is possible, but everything which
  • is possible is not on that account actual. In real truth, however, if
  • we deal with them as thoughts, actuality is the more comprehensive,
  • because it is the concrete thought which includes possibility as an
  • abstract element. And that superiority is to some extent expressed
  • in our ordinary mode of thought when we speak of the possible, in
  • distinction from the actual, as _only_ possible. Possibility is often
  • said to consist in a thing's being thinkable. 'Think,' however, in this
  • use of the word, only means to conceive any content under the form of
  • an abstract identity. Now every content can be brought under this form,
  • since nothing is required except to separate it from the relations in
  • which it stands. Hence any content, however absurd and nonsensical, can
  • be viewed as possible. It is possible that the moon might fall upon
  • the earth to-night; for the moon is a body separate from the earth,
  • and may as well fall down upon it as a stone thrown into the air does.
  • It is possible that the Sultan may become Pope; for, being a man, he
  • may be converted to the Christian faith, may become a Catholic priest,
  • and so on. In language like this about possibilities, it is chiefly
  • the law of the sufficient ground or reason which is manipulated in the
  • style already explained. Everything, it is said, is possible, for which
  • you can state some ground. The less education a man has, or, in other
  • words, the less he knows of the specific connexions of the objects
  • to which he directs his observations, the greater is his tendency to
  • launch out into all sorts of empty possibilities. An instance of this
  • habit in the political sphere is seen in the pot-house politician.
  • In practical life too it is no uncommon thing to see ill-will and
  • indolence slink behind the category of possibility, in order to escape
  • definite obligations. To such conduct the same remarks apply as were
  • made in connexion with the law of sufficient ground. Reasonable and
  • practical men refuse to be imposed upon by the possible, for the simple
  • ground that it is possible only. They stick to the actual (not meaning
  • by that word merely whatever immediately is now and here). Many of
  • the proverbs of common life express the same contempt for what is
  • abstractly possible. 'A bird in the hand is worth two in the bush.'
  • After all there is as good reason for taking everything to be
  • impossible, as to be possible: for every content (a content is always
  • concrete) includes not only diverse but even opposite characteristics.
  • Nothing is so impossible, for instance, as this, that I am: for 'I' is
  • at the same time simple self-relation and, as undoubtedly, relation
  • to something else. The same may be seen in every other fact in the
  • natural or spiritual world. Matter, it may be said, is impossible:
  • for it is the unity of attraction and repulsion. The same is true of
  • life, law, freedom, and above all, of God Himself, as the true, _e.g._
  • the triune God,--a notion of God, which the abstract 'Enlightenment'
  • of Understanding, in conformity with its canons, rejected on the
  • allegation that it was contradictory in thought. Generally speaking,
  • it is the empty understanding which haunts these empty forms: and
  • the business of philosophy in the matter is to show how null and
  • meaningless they are. Whether a thing is possible or impossible,
  • depends altogether on the subject-matter: that is, on the sum total of
  • the elements in actuality, which, as it opens itself out, discloses
  • itself to be necessity.
  • 144.] (ß) But the Actual in its distinction from possibility (which
  • is reflection-into-self) is itself only the outward concrete, the
  • unessential immediate. In other words, to such extent as the actual
  • is primarily (§ 142) the simple merely immediate unity of Inward
  • and Outward, it is obviously made an unessential outward, and thus
  • at the same time (§ 140) it is merely inward, the abstraction of
  • reflection-into-self. Hence it is itself characterised as a merely
  • possible. When thus valued at the rate of a mere possibility, the
  • actual is a Contingent or Accidental, and, conversely,
  • possibility is mere Accident itself or Chance.
  • 146.] Possibility and Contingency are the two factors of
  • Actuality,--Inward and Outward, put as mere forms which constitute the
  • externality of the actual. They have their reflection-into-self on the
  • body of actual fact, or content, with its intrinsic definiteness which
  • gives the essential ground of their characterisation. The finitude of
  • the contingent and the possible lies, therefore, as we now see, in the
  • distinction of the form-determination from the content: and, therefore,
  • it depends on the content alone whether anything is contingent and
  • possible.
  • As possibility is the mere _inside_ of actuality, it is for that
  • reason a mere _outside_ actuality, in other words, Contingency. The
  • contingent, roughly speaking, is what has the ground of its being
  • not in itself but in somewhat else. Such is the aspect under which
  • actuality first comes before consciousness, and which is often mistaken
  • for actuality itself. But the contingent is only one side of the
  • actual,--the side, namely, of reflection on somewhat else. It is the
  • actual, in the signification of something merely possible. Accordingly
  • we consider the contingent to be what may or may not be, what may be
  • in one way or in another, whose being or not-being, and whose being
  • on this wise or otherwise, depends not upon itself but on something
  • else. To overcome this contingency is, roughly speaking, the problem
  • of science on the one hand; as in the range of practice, on the other,
  • the end of action is to rise above the contingency of the will, or
  • above caprice. It has however often happened, most of all in modern
  • times, that contingency has been unwarrantably elevated, and had a
  • value attached to it, both in nature and the world of mind, to which
  • it has no just claim. Frequently Nature--to take it first,--has been
  • chiefly admired for the richness and variety of its structures. Apart,
  • however, from what disclosure it contains of the Idea, this richness
  • gratifies none of the higher interests of reason, and in its vast
  • variety of structures, organic and inorganic, affords us only the
  • spectacle of a contingency losing itself in vagueness. At any rate,
  • the chequered scene presented by the several varieties of animals and
  • plants, conditioned as it is by outward circumstances,--the complex
  • changes in the figuration and grouping of clouds, and the like, ought
  • not to be ranked higher than the equally casual fancies of the mind
  • which surrenders itself to its own caprices. The wonderment with which
  • such phenomena are welcomed is a most abstract frame of mind, from
  • which one should advance to a closer insight into the inner harmony and
  • uniformity of nature.
  • Of contingency in respect of the Will it is especially important to
  • form a proper estimate. The Freedom of the Will is an expression that
  • often means mere free-choice, or the will in the form of contingency.
  • Freedom of choice, or the capacity of determining ourselves towards one
  • thing or another, is undoubtedly a vital element in the will (which in
  • its very notion is free); but instead of being freedom itself, it is
  • only in the first instance a freedom in form. The genuinely free will,
  • which includes free choice as suspended, is conscious to itself that
  • its content is intrinsically firm and fast, and knows it at the same
  • time to be thoroughly its own. A will, on the contrary, which remains
  • standing on the grade of option, even supposing it does decide in
  • favour of what is in import right and true, is always haunted by the
  • conceit that it might, if it had so pleased, have decided in favour of
  • the reverse course. When more narrowly examined, free choice is seen
  • to be a contradiction, to this extent that its form and content stand
  • in antithesis. The matter of choice is given, and known as a content
  • dependent not on the will itself,'but on outward circumstances. In
  • reference to such a given content, freedom lies only in the form of
  • choosing, which, as it is only a freedom in form, may consequently be
  • regarded as freedom only in supposition. On an ultimate analysis it
  • will be seen that the same outwardness of circumstances, on which is
  • founded the content that the will finds to its hand, can alone account
  • for the will giving its decision for the one and not the other of the
  • two alternatives.
  • Although contingency, as it has thus been shown, is only one aspect in
  • the whole of actuality, and therefore not to be mistaken for actuality
  • itself, it has no less than the rest of the forms of the idea its due
  • office in the world of objects. This is, in the first place, seen in
  • Nature. On the surface of Nature, so to speak, Chance ranges unchecked,
  • and that contingency must simply be recognised, without the pretension
  • sometimes erroneously ascribed to philosophy, of seeking to find in it
  • a could-only-be-so-and-not-otherwise. Nor is contingency less visible
  • in the world of Mind. The will, as we have already remarked, includes
  • contingency under the shape of option or free-choice, but only as a
  • vanishing and abrogated element. In respect of Mind and its works,
  • just as in the case of Nature, we must guard against being so far
  • misled by a well-meant endeavour after rational knowledge, as to try
  • to exhibit the necessity of phenomena which are marked by a decided
  • contingency, or, as the phrase is, to construe them _a priori._ Thus
  • in language (although it be, as it were, the body of thought) Chance
  • still unquestionably plays a decided part; and the same is true of the
  • creations of law, of art, &c. The problem of science, and especially of
  • philosophy, undoubtedly consists in eliciting the necessity concealed
  • under the semblance of contingency. That however is far from meaning
  • that the contingent belongs to our subjective conception alone, and
  • must therefore be simply set aside, if we wish to get at the truth.
  • All scientific researches which pursue this tendency exclusively,
  • lay themselves fairly open to the charge of mere jugglery and an
  • over-strained precisianism.
  • 146.] When more closely examined, what the aforesaid outward side
  • of actuality implies is this. Contingency, which is actuality
  • in its immediacy, is the self-identical, essentially only as a
  • supposition which is no sooner made than it is revoked and leaves
  • an existent externality. In this way, the external contingency is
  • something pre-supposed, the immediate existence of which is at the
  • same time a possibility, and has the vocation to be suspended, to
  • be the possibility of something else. Now this possibility is the
  • Condition.
  • The Contingent, as the immediate actuality, is at the same time
  • the possibility of somewhat else,--no longer however that abstract
  • possibility which we had at first, but the possibility which _is._ And
  • a possibility existent is a Condition. By the Condition of a thing
  • we mean first, an existence, in short an immediate, and secondly
  • the vocation of this immediate to be suspended and subserve the
  • actualising of something else.--Immediate actuality is in general
  • as such never what it ought to be; it is a finite actuality with an
  • inherent flaw, and its vocation is to be consumed. But the other
  • aspect of actuality is its essentiality. This is primarily the inside,
  • which as a mere possibility is no less destined to be suspended.
  • Possibility thus suspended is the issuing of a new actuality, of which
  • the first immediate actuality was the pre-supposition. Here we see
  • the alternation which is involved in the notion of a Condition. The
  • Conditions of a thing seem at first sight to involve no bias anyway.
  • Really however an immediate actuality of this kind includes in it
  • the germ of something else altogether. At first this something else
  • is only a possibility: but the form of possibility is soon suspended
  • and translated into actuality. This new actuality thus issuing is the
  • very inside of the immediate actuality which it uses up. Thus there
  • comes into being quite an other shape of things, and yet itis not an
  • other: for the first actuality is only put as what it in essence was.
  • The conditions which are sacrificed, which fall to the ground and are
  • spent, only unite with themselves in the other actuality. Such in
  • general is the nature of the process of actuality. The actual is no
  • mere case of immediate Being, but, as essential Being, a suspension of
  • its own immediacy, and thereby mediating itself with itself.
  • 147.] (γ) When this externality (of actuality) is thus developed into
  • a circle of the two categories of possibility and immediate actuality,
  • showing the intermediation of the one by the other, it is what is
  • called Real Possibility. Being such a circle, further, it
  • is the totality, and thus the content, the actual fact or affair in
  • its all-round definiteness. Whilst in like manner, if we look at the
  • distinction between the two characteristics in this unity, it realises
  • the concrete totality of the form, the immediate self-translation
  • of inner into outer, and of outer into inner. This self-movement of
  • the form is Activity, carrying into effect the fact or affair as a
  • _real_ ground which is self-suspended to actuality, and carrying into
  • effect the contingent actuality, the conditions; _i.e._ it is their
  • reflection-in-self, and their self-suspension to an other actuality,
  • the actuality of the actual fact. If all the conditions are at hand,
  • the fact (event) _must_ be actual; and the fact itself is one of the
  • conditions: for being in the first place only inner, it is at first
  • itself only pre-supposed. Developed actuality, as the coincident
  • alternation of inner and outer, the alternation of their opposite
  • motions combined into a single motion, is Necessity.
  • Necessity has been defined, and rightly so, as the union of possibility
  • and actuality. This mode of expression, however, gives a superficial
  • and therefore unintelligible description of the very difficult notion
  • of necessity. It is difficult because it is the notion itself, only
  • that its stages or factors are still as actualities, which are yet at
  • the same time to be viewed as forms only, collapsing and transient. In
  • the two following paragraphs therefore an exposition of the factors
  • which constitute necessity must be given at greater length.
  • * * * * *
  • When anything is said to be necessary, the first question we ask is,
  • Why? Anything necessary accordingly comes before us as something due to
  • a supposition, the result of certain antecedents. If we go no further
  • than mere derivation from antecedents however, we have not gained a
  • complete notion of what necessity means. What is merely derivative,
  • is what it is, not through itself, but through something else; and in
  • this way it too is merely contingent. What is necessary, on the other
  • hand, we would have be what it is through itself; and thus, although
  • derivative, it must still contain the antecedent whence it is derived
  • as a vanishing element in itself. Hence we say of what is necessary,
  • 'It is.' We thus hold it to be simple self-relation, in which all
  • dependence on something else is removed.
  • Necessity is often said to be blind. If that means that in the process
  • of necessity the End or final cause is not explicitly and overtly
  • present, the statement is correct. The process of necessity begins
  • with the existence of scattered circumstances which appear to have no
  • inter-connexion and no concern one with another. These circumstances
  • are an immediate actuality which collapses, and out of this negation
  • a new actuality proceeds. Here we have a content which in point of
  • form is doubled, once as content of the final realised fact, and once
  • as content of the scattered circumstances which appear as if they
  • were positive, and make themselves at first felt in that character.
  • The latter content is in itself nought and is accordingly inverted
  • into its negative, thus becoming content of the realised fact. The
  • immediate circumstances fall to the ground as conditions, but are at
  • the same time retained as content of the ultimate reality. From such
  • circumstances and conditions there has, as we say, proceeded quite
  • another thing, and it is for that reason that we call this process of
  • necessity blind. If on the contrary we consider teleological action, we
  • have in the end of action a content which is already fore-known. This
  • activity therefore is not blind but seeing. To say that the world is
  • ruled by Providence implies that design, as what has been absolutely
  • pre-determined, is the active principle, so that the issue corresponds
  • to what has been fore-known and fore-willed.
  • The theory however which regards the world as determined through
  • necessity and the belief in a divine providence are by no means
  • mutually excluding points of view. The intellectual principle
  • underlying the idea of divine providence will hereafter be shown to be
  • the notion. But the notion is the truth of necessity, which it contains
  • in suspension in itself; just as, conversely, necessity is the notion
  • implicit. Necessity is blind only so long as it is not understood.
  • There is nothing therefore more mistaken than the charge of blind
  • fatalism made against the Philosophy of History, when it takes for its
  • problem to understand the necessity of every event. The philosophy of
  • history rightly understood takes the rank of a Théodicée; and those,
  • who fancy they honour Divine Providence by excluding necessity from
  • it, are really degrading it by this exclusiveness to a blind and
  • irrational caprice. In the simple language of the religious mind which
  • speaks of God's eternal and immutable decrees, there is implied an
  • express recognition that necessity forms part of the essence of God. In
  • his difference from God, man, with his own private opinion and will,
  • follows the call of caprice and arbitrary humour, and thus often finds
  • his acts turn out something quite different from what he had meant and
  • willed. But God knows what He wills, is determined in His eternal will
  • neither by accident from within nor from without, and what He wills He
  • also accomplishes, irresistibly.
  • Necessity gives a point of view which has important bearings upon our
  • sentiments and behaviour. When we look upon events as necessary, our
  • situation seems at first sight to lack freedom completely. In the
  • creed of the ancients, as we know, necessity figured as Destiny. The
  • modern point of view, on the contrary, is that of Consolation. And
  • Consolation means that, if we renounce our aims and interests, we do so
  • only in prospect of receiving compensation. Destiny, on the contrary,
  • leaves no room for Consolation. But a close examination of the ancient
  • feeling about destiny, will not by any means reveal a sense of bondage
  • to its power. Rather the reverse. This will clearly appear, if we
  • remember, that the sense of bondage springs from inability to surmount
  • the antithesis, and from looking at what _is,_ and what happens, as
  • contradictory to what _ought_ to be and happen. In the ancient mind the
  • feeling was more of the following kind: Because such a thing is, it
  • is, and as it is, so ought it to be. Here there is no contrast to be
  • seen, and therefore no sense of bondage, no pain, and no sorrow. True,
  • indeed, as already remarked, this attitude towards destiny is void of
  • consolation. But then, on the other hand, it is a frame of mind which
  • does not need consolation, so long as personal subjectivity has not
  • acquired its infinite significance. It is this point on which special
  • stress should be laid in comparing the ancient sentiment with that of
  • the modern and Christian world.
  • By Subjectivity, however, we may understand, in the first place, only
  • the natural and finite subjectivity, with its contingent and arbitrary
  • content of private interests and inclinations,--all, in short, that
  • we call person as distinguished from thing: taking 'thing' in the
  • emphatic sense of the word (in which we use the (correct) expression
  • that it is a question of _things_ and not of _persons)._ In this sense
  • of sub-activity we cannot help admiring the tranquil resignation of
  • the ancients to destiny, and feeling that it is a much higher and
  • worthier mood than that of the moderns, who obstinately pursue their
  • subjective aims, and when they find themselves constrained to resign
  • the hope of reaching them, console themselves with the prospect of a
  • reward in some other shape. But the term subjectivity is not to be
  • confined merely to the bad and finite kind of it which is contrasted
  • with the thing (fact). In its truth subjectivity is immanent in the
  • fact, and as a subjectivity thus infinite is the very truth of the
  • fact. Thus regarded, the doctrine of consolation receives a newer and
  • a higher significance. It is in this sense that the Christian religion
  • is to be regarded as the religion of consolation, and even of absolute
  • consolation. Christianity, we know, teaches that God wishes all men
  • to be saved. That teaching declares that subjectivity has an infinite
  • value. And that consoling power of Christianity just lies in the fact
  • that God Himself is in it known as the absolute subjectivity, so that,
  • inasmuch as subjectivity involves the element of particularity, _our_
  • particular personality too is recognised not merely as something to be
  • solely and simply nullified, but as at the same time something to be
  • preserved. The gods of the ancient world were also, it is true, looked
  • upon as personal; but the personality of a Zeus and an Apollo is not
  • a real personality: it is only a figure in the mind. In other words,
  • these gods are mere personifications, which, being such, do not know
  • themselves, and are only known. An evidence of this defect and this
  • powerlessness of the old gods is found even in the religious beliefs
  • of antiquity. In the ancient creeds not only men, but even gods,
  • were represented as subject to destiny (πεπρωμένον or εἱμαρμένη), a
  • destiny which we must conceive as necessity not unveiled, and thus as
  • something wholly impersonal, selfless, and blind. On the other hand,
  • the Christian God is God not known merely, but also self-knowing; He is
  • a personality not merely figured in our minds, but rather absolutely
  • actual.
  • We must refer to the Philosophy of Religion for a further discussion of
  • the points here touched. But we may note in passing how important it
  • is for any man to meet everything that befalls him with the spirit of
  • the old proverb which describes each man as the architect of his own
  • fortune. That means that it is only himself after all of which a man
  • has the usufruct. The other way would be to lay the blame of whatever
  • we experience upon other men, upon unfavourable circumstances, and the
  • like. And this is a fresh example of the language of unfreedom, and at
  • the same time the spring of discontent. If man saw, on the contrary,
  • that whatever happens to him is only the outcome of himself, and that
  • he only bears his own guilt, he would stand free, and in everything
  • that came upon him would have the consciousness that he suffered no
  • wrong. A man who lives in dispeace with himself and his lot, commits
  • much that is perverse and amiss, for no other reason than because of
  • the false opinion that he is wronged by others. No doubt too there is a
  • great deal of chance in what befalls us. But the chance has its root in
  • the 'natural' man. So long however as a man is otherwise conscious that
  • he is free, his harmony of soul and peace of mind will not be destroyed
  • by the disagreeables that befall him. It is their view of necessity,
  • therefore, which is at the root of the content and discontent of men,
  • and which in that way determines their destiny itself.
  • 148.] Among the three elements in the process of necessity--the
  • Condition, the Fact, and the Activity--
  • a. The Condition is (α) what is pre-supposed or ante-stated, _e.g._
  • it is not only supposed or stated, and so only a correlative to the
  • fact, but also prior, and so independent, a contingent and external
  • circumstance which exists without respect to the fact. While thus
  • contingent, however, this pre-supposed or ante-stated term, in respect
  • withal of the fact, which is the totality, is a complete circle of
  • conditions, (ß) The conditions are passive, are used as materials for
  • the fact, into the content of which they thus enter. They are likewise
  • intrinsically conformable to this content, and already contain its
  • whole characteristic.
  • b. The Fact is also (α) something pre-supposed or ante-stated, _i.e._
  • it is at first, and as supposed, only inner and possible, and also,
  • being prior, an independent content by itself, (ß) By using up the
  • conditions, it receives its external existence, the realisation of
  • the articles of its content, which reciprocally correspond to the
  • conditions, so that whilst it presents itself out of these as the fact,
  • it also proceeds from them.
  • c. The Activity similarly has (α) an independent existence of its own
  • (as a man, a character), and at the same time it is possible only
  • where the conditions are and the fact, (ß) It is the movement which
  • translates the conditions into fact, and the latter into the former as
  • the side of existence, or rather the movement which educes the fact
  • from the conditions in which it is potentially present, and which gives
  • existence to the fact by abolishing the existence possessed by the
  • conditions.
  • In so far as these three elements stand to each other in the shape
  • of independent existences, this process has the aspect of an outward
  • necessity. Outward necessity has a limited content for its fact. For
  • the fact is this whole, in phase of singleness. But since in its form
  • this whole is external to itself, it is self-externalised even in its
  • own self and in its content, and this externality, attaching to the
  • fact, is a limit of its content.
  • 149.] Necessity, then, is potentially the one essence, self-same but
  • now full of content, in the reflected light of which its distinctions
  • take the form of independent realities. This self-sameness is at the
  • same time, as absolute form, the activity which reduces into dependency
  • and mediates into immediacy.--Whatever is necessary is through an
  • other, which is broken up into the mediating ground (the Fact and
  • the Activity) and an immediate actuality or accidental circumstance,
  • which is at the same time a Condition. The necessary, being through
  • an other, is not in and for itself: hypothetical, it is a mere result
  • of assumption. But this intermediation is just as immediately however
  • the abrogation of itself. The ground and contingent condition is
  • translated into immediacy, by which that dependency is now lifted up
  • into actuality, and the fact has closed with itself. In this return
  • to itself the necessary simply and positively _is,_ as unconditioned
  • actuality. The necessary is so, mediated through a circle of
  • circumstances: it is so, because the circumstances are so, and at the
  • same time it is so, unmediated: it is so, because it is.
  • (a) _Relationship of Substantiality._
  • 150.] The necessary is in itself an absolute correlation of elements,
  • _i.e._ the process developed (in the preceding paragraphs), in which
  • the correlation also suspends itself to absolute identity.
  • In its immediate form it is the relationship of Substance and Accident.
  • The absolute self-identity of this relationship is Substance as such,
  • which as necessity gives the negative to this form of inwardness, and
  • thus invests itself with actuality, but which also gives the negative
  • to this outward thing. In this negativity, the actual, as immediate,
  • is only an accidental which through this bare possibility passes over
  • into another actuality. This transition is the identity of substance,
  • regarded as form-activity (§§ 148, 149).
  • 151.] Substance is accordingly the totality of the Accidents,
  • revealing itself in them as their absolute negativity, (that is to
  • say, as absolute power,) and at the same time as the wealth of all
  • content. This content however is nothing but that very revelation,
  • since the character (being reflected in itself to make content) is
  • only a passing stage of the form which passes away in the power of
  • substance. Substantiality is the absolute form-activity and the power
  • of necessity: all content is but a vanishing element which merely
  • belongs to this process, where there is an absolute revulsion of form
  • and content into one another.
  • * * * * *
  • In the history of philosophy we meet with Substance as the principle
  • of Spinoza's system. On the import and value of that much-praised and
  • no less decried philosophy there has been great misunderstanding and
  • a deal of talking since the days of Spinoza. The atheism and, as a
  • further charge, the pantheism of the system has formed the commonest
  • ground of accusation. These cries arise because of Spinoza's conception
  • of God as substance, and substance only. What we are to think of this
  • charge follows, in the first instance, from the place which substance
  • takes in the system of the logical idea. Though an essential stage in
  • the evolution of the idea, substance is not the same with absolute
  • Idea, but the idea under the still limited form of necessity. It is
  • true that God is necessity, or, as we may also put it, that He is the
  • absolute Thing: He is however no less the absolute Person. That He is
  • the absolute Person however is a point which the philosophy of Spinoza
  • never reached: and on that side it falls short of the true notion of
  • God which forms the content of religious consciousness in Christianity.
  • Spinoza was by descent a Jew; and it is upon the whole the Oriental way
  • of seeing things, according to which the nature of the finite world
  • seems frail and transient, that has found its intellectual expression
  • in his system. This Oriental view of the unity of substance certainly
  • gives the basis for all real further development. Still it is not the
  • final idea. It is marked by the absence of the principle of the Western
  • World, the principle of individuality, which first appeared under a
  • philosophic shape, contemporaneously with Spinoza, in the Monadology of
  • Leibnitz.
  • From this point we glance back to the alleged atheism of Spinoza. The
  • charge will be seen to be unfounded if we remember that his system,
  • instead of denying God, rather recognises that He alone really is.
  • Nor can it be maintained that the God of Spinoza, although he is
  • described as alone true, is not the true God, and therefore as good as
  • no God. If that were a just charge, it would only prove that all other
  • systems, where speculation has not gone beyond a subordinate stage
  • of the idea,--that the Jews and Mohammedans who know God only as the
  • Lord,--and that even the many Christians for whom God is merely the
  • most high, unknowable, and transcendent being, are as much atheists as
  • Spinoza. The so-called atheism of Spinoza is merely an exaggeration of
  • the fact that he defrauds the principle of difference or finitude of
  • its due. Hence his system, as it holds that there is properly speaking
  • no world, at any rate that the world has no positive being, should
  • rather be styled Acosmism, These considerations will also show what is
  • to be said of the charge of Pantheism. If Pantheism means, as it often
  • does, the doctrine which takes finite things in their finitude and in
  • the complex of them to be God, we must acquit the system of Spinoza of
  • the crime of Pantheism. For in that system, finite things and the world
  • as a whole are denied all truth. On the other hand, the philosophy
  • which is Acosmism is for that reason certainly pantheistic.
  • The shortcoming thus acknowledged to attach to the content turns out
  • at the same time to be a shortcoming in respect of form. Spinoza puts
  • substance at the head of his system, and defines it to be the unity
  • of thought and extension, without demonstrating how he gets to this
  • distinction, or how he traces it back to the unity of substance. The
  • further treatment of the subject proceeds in what is called the
  • mathematical method. Definitions and axioms are first laid down: after
  • them comes a series of theorems, which are proved by an analytical
  • reduction of them to these unproved postulates. Although the system
  • of Spinoza, and that even by those who altogether reject its contents
  • and results, is praised for the strict sequence of its method, such
  • unqualified praise of the form is as little justified as an unqualified
  • rejection of the content. The defect of the content is that the form
  • is not known as immanent in it, and therefore only approaches it as an
  • outer and subjective form. As intuitively accepted by Spinoza without a
  • previous mediation by dialectic, Substance, as the universal negative
  • power, is as it were a dark shapeless abyss which engulfs all definite
  • content as radically null, and produces from itself nothing that has a
  • positive subsistence of its own.
  • 152.] At the stage, where substance, as absolute power, is the
  • self-relating power (itself a merely inner possibility) which thus
  • determines itself to accidentality,--from which power the externality
  • it thereby creates is distinguished--necessity is a correlation
  • strictly so called, just as in the first form of necessity, it is
  • substance. This is the correlation of Causality.
  • (b) _Relationship of Causality._
  • 153.] Substance is Cause, in so far as substance reflects into
  • self as against its passage into accidentality and so stands as the
  • _primary_ fact, but again no less suspends this reflection-into-self
  • (its bare possibility), lays itself down as the negative of itself, and
  • thus produces an Effect, an actuality, which, though so far only
  • assumed as a sequence, is through the process that effectuates it at
  • the same time necessary.
  • As primary fact, the cause is qualified as having absolute independence
  • and a subsistence maintained in face of the effect: but in the
  • necessity, whose identity constitutes that primariness itself, it
  • is wholly passed into the effect. So far again as we can speak of a
  • definite content, there is no content in the effect that is not in
  • the cause. That identity in fact is the absolute content itself: but
  • it is no less also the form-characteristic. The primariness of the
  • cause is suspended in the effect in which the cause makes itself a
  • dependent being. The cause however does not for that reason vanish and
  • leave the effect to be alone actual. For this dependency is in like
  • manner directly suspended, and is rather the reflection of the cause
  • in itself, its primariness: in short, it is in the effect that the
  • cause first becomes actual and a cause. The cause consequently is in
  • its full truth _causa sui._--Jacobi, sticking to the partial conception
  • of mediation (in his Letters on Spinoza, second edit. p. 416), has
  • treated the _causa sui_ (and the _effectus sui_ is the same), which is
  • the absolute truth of the cause, as a mere formalism. He has also made
  • the remark that God ought to be defined not as the ground of things,
  • but essentially as cause. A more thorough consideration of the nature
  • of cause would have shown that Jacobi did not by this means gain what
  • he intended. Even in the finite cause and its conception we can see
  • this identity between cause and effect in point of content. The rain
  • (the cause) and the wet (the effect) are the self-same existing water.
  • In point of form the cause (rain) is dissipated or lost in the effect
  • (wet): but in that case the result can no longer be described as
  • effect; for without the cause it is nothing, and we should have only
  • the unrelated wet left.
  • In the common acceptation of the causal relation the cause is finite,
  • to such extent as its content is so (as is also the case with finite
  • substance), and so far as cause and effect are conceived as two several
  • independent existences; which they are, however, only when we leave
  • the causal relation out of sight. In the finite sphere we never get
  • over the difference of the form-characteristics in their relation: and
  • hence we turn the matter round and define the cause also as something
  • dependent or as an effect. This again has another cause, and thus there
  • grows up a progress from effects to causes _ad infinitum._ There is a
  • descending progress too: the effect, looked at in its identity with the
  • cause, is itself defined as a cause, and at the same time as another
  • cause, which again has other effects, and so on for ever.
  • The way understanding bristles up against the idea of substance is
  • equalled by its readiness to use the relation of cause and effect.
  • Whenever it is proposed to view any sum of fact as necessary, it
  • is especially the relation of causality to which the reflective
  • understanding makes a point of tracing it back. Now, although this
  • relation does undoubtedly belong to necessity, it forms only one aspect
  • in the process of that category. That process equally requires the
  • suspension of the mediation involved in causality and the exhibition
  • of it as simple self-relation. If we stick to causality as such, we
  • have it not in its truth. Such a causality is merely finite, and its
  • finitude lies in retaining the distinction between cause and effect
  • unassimilated. But these two terms, if they are distinct, are also
  • identical. Even in ordinary consciousness that identity may be found.
  • We say that a cause is a cause, only when it has an effect, and _vice
  • versâ._ Both cause and effect are thus one and the same content: and
  • the distinction between them is primarily only that the one lays down,
  • and the other is laid down. This formal difference however again
  • suspends itself, because the cause is not only a cause of something
  • else, but also a cause of itself; while the effect is not only an
  • effect of something else, but also an effect of itself. The finitude
  • of things consists accordingly in this. While cause and effect are in
  • their notion identical, the two forms present themselves severed so
  • that, though the cause is also an effect, and the effect also a cause,
  • the cause is not an effect in the same connexion as it is a cause, nor
  • the effect a cause in the same connexion as it is an effect. This
  • again gives the infinite progress, in the shape of an endless series
  • of causes, which shows itself at the same time as an endless series of
  • effects.
  • 154.] The effect is different from the cause. The former as such has
  • a being dependent on the latter. But such a dependence is likewise
  • reflection-into-self and immediacy: and the action of the cause, as it
  • constitutes the effect, is at the same time the pre-constitution of
  • the effect, so long as effect is kept separate from cause. There is
  • thus already in existence another substance on which the effect takes
  • place. As immediate, this substance is not a self-related negativity
  • and _active,_ but _passive._ Yet it is a substance, and it is therefore
  • active also: it therefore suspends the immediacy it was originally put
  • forward with, and the effect which was put into it: it reacts, _e.g._
  • suspends the activity of the first substance. But this first substance
  • also in the same way sets aside its own immediacy, or the effect which
  • is put into it; it thus suspends the activity of the other substance
  • and reacts. In this manner causality passes into the relation of
  • Action and Reaction, or Reciprocity.
  • In Reciprocity, although causality is not yet invested with its true
  • characteristic, the rectilinear movement out from causes to effects,
  • and from effects to causes, is bent round and back into itself, and
  • thus the progress _ad infinitum_ of causes and effects is, as a
  • progress, really and truly suspended. This bend, which transforms, the
  • infinite progression into a self-contained relationship, is here as
  • always the plain reflection that in the above meaningless repetition
  • there is only one and the same thing, viz. one cause and another, and
  • their connexion with one another. Reciprocity--which is the development
  • of this relation-itself however only distinguishes turn and turn
  • about (--not causes, but) factors of causation, in each of which--just
  • because they are inseparable (on the principle of the identity that the
  • cause is cause in the effect, and _vice versâ_)--the other factor is
  • also equally supposed.
  • (c) _Reciprocity or Action and Reaction._
  • 155.] The characteristics which in Reciprocal Action are retained as
  • distinct are (α) potentially the same. The one side is a cause, is
  • primary, active, passive, &c, just as the other is. Similarly the
  • pre-supposition of another side and the action upon it, the immediate
  • primariness and the dependence produced by the alternation, are one and
  • the same on both sides. The cause assumed to be first is on account
  • of its immediacy passive, a dependent being, and an effect. The
  • distinction of the causes spoken of as two is accordingly void: and
  • properly speaking there is only one cause, which, while it suspends
  • itself (as substance) in its effect, also rises in this operation only
  • to independent existence as a cause.
  • 156.] But this unity of the double cause is also (β) actual. All this
  • alternation is properly the cause in act of constituting itself and in
  • such constitution lies its being. The nullity of the distinctions is
  • not only potential, or a reflection of ours (§ 155). Reciprocal action
  • just means that each characteristic we impose is also to be suspended
  • and inverted into its opposite, and that in this way the essential
  • nullity of the 'moments' is explicitly stated. An effect is introduced
  • into the primariness; in other words, the primariness is abolished: the
  • action of a cause becomes reaction, and so on.
  • Reciprocal action realises the causal relation in its complete
  • development. It is this relation, therefore, in which reflection
  • usually takes shelter when the conviction grows that things can no
  • longer be studied satisfactorily from a causal point of view, on
  • account of the infinite progress already spoken of. Thus in historical
  • research the question may be raised in a first form, whether the
  • character and manners of a nation are the cause of its constitution and
  • its laws, or if they are not rather the effect. Then, as the second
  • step, the character and manners on one side and the constitution and
  • laws on the other are conceived on the principle of reciprocity: and
  • in that case the cause in the same connexion as it is a cause will at
  • the same time be an effect, and _vice versâ._ The same thing is done
  • in the study of Nature, and especially of living organisms. There
  • the several organs and functions are similarly seen to stand to each
  • other in the relation of reciprocity. Reciprocity is undoubtedly the
  • proximate truth of the relation of cause and effect, and stands, so
  • to say, on the threshold of the notion; but on that very ground,
  • supposing that our aim is a thoroughly comprehensive idea, we should
  • not rest content with applying this relation. If we get no further than
  • studying a given content under the point of view of reciprocity, we are
  • taking up an attitude which leaves matters utterly incomprehensible.
  • We are left with a mere dry fact; and the call for mediation, which
  • is the chief motive in applying the relation of causality, is still
  • unanswered. And it we look more narrowly into the dissatisfaction
  • felt in applying the relation of reciprocity, we shall see that it
  • consists in the circumstance, that this relation, instead of being
  • treated as an equivalent for the notion, ought, first of all, to be
  • known and understood in its own nature. And to understand the relation
  • of action and reaction we must not let the two sides rest in their
  • state of mere given facts, but recognise them, as has been shown in
  • the two paragraphs preceding, for factors of a third and higher, which
  • is the notion and nothing else. To make, for example, the manners of
  • the Spartans the cause of their constitution and their constitution
  • conversely the cause of their manners, may no doubt be in a way
  • correct. But, as we have comprehended neither the manners nor the
  • constitution of the nation, the result of such reflections can never
  • be final or satisfactory. The satisfactory point will be reached only
  • when these two, as well as all other, special aspects of Spartan life
  • and Spartan history are seen to be founded in this notion.
  • 157.] This pure self-reciprocation is therefore Necessity unveiled
  • or realised. The link of necessity _quâ_ necessity is identity, as
  • still inward and concealed, because it is the identity of what are
  • esteemed actual things, although their very self-subsistence is bound
  • to be necessity. The circulation of substance through causality
  • and reciprocity therefore only expressly makes out or states that
  • self-subsistence is the infinite negative self-relation--a relation
  • _negative,_ in general, for in it the act of distinguishing and
  • intermediating becomes a primariness of actual things independent
  • one against the other,--and _infinite self-relation,_ because their
  • independence only lies in their identity.
  • 158.] This truth of necessity, therefore, is _Freedom:_ and the
  • truth of substance is the Notion,--an independence which, though
  • self-repulsive into distinct independent elements, yet in that
  • repulsion is self-identical, and in the movement of reciprocity still
  • at home and conversant only with itself.
  • * * * * *
  • Necessity is often called hard, and rightly so, if we keep only to
  • necessity as such, _i.e._ to its immediate shape. Here we have,
  • first of all, some state or, generally speaking, fact, possessing an
  • independent subsistence: and necessity primarily implies that there
  • falls upon such a fact something else by which it is brought low.
  • This is what is hard and sad in necessity immediate or abstract. The
  • identity of the two things, which necessity presents as bound to each
  • other and thus bereft of their independence, is at first only inward,
  • and therefore has no existence for those under the yoke of necessity.
  • Freedom too from this point of view is only abstract, and is preserved
  • only by renouncing all that we immediately are and have. But, as we
  • have seen already, the process of necessity is so directed that it
  • overcomes the rigid externality which it first had and reveals its
  • inward nature. It then appears that the members, linked to one another,
  • are not really foreign to each other, but only elements of one whole,
  • each of them, in its connexion with the other, being, as it were, at
  • home, and combining with itself. In this way necessity is transfigured
  • into freedom,--not the freedom that consists in abstract negation,
  • but freedom concrete and positive. From which we may learn what a
  • mistake it is to regard freedom and necessity as mutually exclusive.
  • Necessity indeed _quâ_ necessity is far from being freedom: yet
  • freedom pre-supposes necessity, and contains it as an unsubstantial
  • element in itself. A good man is aware that the tenor of his conduct
  • is essentially obligatory and necessary. But this consciousness is
  • so far from making any abatement from his freedom, that without it
  • real and reasonable freedom could not be distinguished from arbitrary
  • choice,--a freedom which has no reality and is merely potential. A
  • criminal, when punished, may look upon his punishment as a restriction
  • of his freedom. Really the punishment is not foreign constraint to
  • which he is subjected, but the manifestation of his own act: and if he
  • recognises this, he comports himself as a free man. In short, man is
  • most independent when he knows himself to be determined by the absolute
  • idea throughout. It was this phase of mind and conduct which Spinoza
  • called _Amor intellectualis Dei._
  • 159.] Thus the Notion is the truth of Being and Essence, inasmuch as
  • the shining or show of self-reflection is itself at the same time
  • independent immediacy, and this being of a different actuality is
  • immediately only a shining or show on itself.
  • The Notion has exhibited itself as the truth of Being and Essence, as
  • the ground to which the regress of both leads. Conversely it has been
  • developed out of being as its ground. The former aspect of the advance
  • may be regarded as a concentration of being into its depth, thereby
  • disclosing its inner nature: the latter aspect as an issuing of the
  • more perfect from the less perfect. When such development is viewed on
  • the latter side only, it does prejudice to the method of philosophy.
  • The special meaning which these superficial thoughts of more imperfect
  • and more perfect have in this place is to indicate the distinction of
  • being, as an immediate unity with itself, from the notion, as free
  • mediation with itself. Since being has shown that it is an element in
  • the notion, the latter has thus exhibited itself as the truth of being.
  • As this its reflection in itself and as an absorption of the mediation,
  • the notion is the pre-supposition of the immediate--a pre-supposition
  • which is identical with the return to self; and in this identity lie
  • freedom and the notion. If the partial element therefore be called the
  • imperfect, then the notion, or the perfect, is certainly a development
  • from the imperfect; since its very nature is thus to suspend its
  • pre-supposition. At the same time it is the notion alone which, in the
  • act of supposing itself, makes its pre-supposition; as has been made
  • apparent in causality in general and especially in reciprocal action.
  • Thus in reference to Being and Essence the Notion is defined as Essence
  • reverted to the simple immediacy of Being,--the shining or show of
  • Essence thereby having actuality, and its actuality being at the same
  • time a free shining or show in itself. In this manner the notion has
  • being as its simple self-relation, or as the immediacy of its immanent
  • unity. Being is so poor a category that it is the least thing which can
  • be shown to be found in the notion.
  • The passage from necessity to freedom, or from actuality into the
  • notion, is the very hardest, because it proposes that independent
  • actuality shall be thought as having all its substantiality in the
  • passing over and identity with the other independent actuality. The
  • notion, too, is extremely hard, because it is itself just this very
  • identity. But the actual substance as such, the cause, which in its
  • exclusiveness resists all invasion, is _ipso facto_ subjected to
  • necessity or the destiny of passing into dependency: and it is this
  • subjection rather where the chief hardness lies. To think necessity, on
  • the contrary, rather tends to melt that hardness. For thinking means
  • that, in the other, one meets with one's self.--It means a liberation,
  • which is not the flight of abstraction, but consists in that which is
  • actual having itself not as something else, but as its own being and
  • creation, in the other actuality with which it is bound up by the force
  • of necessity. As existing in an individual form, this liberation is
  • called I: as developed to its totality, it is free Spirit; as feeling,
  • it is Love; and as enjoyment, it is Blessedness.--The great vision
  • of substance in Spinoza is only a potential liberation from finite
  • exclusiveness and egoism: but the notion itself realises for its own
  • both the power of necessity and actual freedom.
  • * * * * *
  • When, as now, the notion is called the truth of Being and Essence,
  • we must expect to be asked, why we do not begin with the notion? The
  • answer is that, where knowledge by thought is our aim, we cannot begin
  • with the truth, because the truth, when it forms the beginning, must
  • rest on mere assertion. The truth when it is thought must as such
  • verify itself to thought. If the notion were put at the head of Logic,
  • and defined, quite correctly in point of content, as the unity of
  • Being and Essence, the following question would come up: What are we
  • to think under the terms 'Being' and 'Essence,' and how do they come
  • to be embraced in the unity of the Notion? But if we answered these
  • questions, then our beginning with the notion would be merely nominal.
  • The real start would be made with Being, as we have here done: with
  • this difference, that the characteristics of Being as well as those
  • of Essence would have to be accepted uncritically from figurate
  • conception, whereas we have observed Being and Essence in their own
  • dialectical development and learnt how they lose themselves in the
  • unity of the notion.
  • [1] Compare Goethe's indignant outcry--'To Natural Science,' vol. i.
  • pt. 3:
  • Das hör' ich sechzig Jahre wiederholen,
  • Und fluche drauf, aber verstohlen,--
  • Natur hat weder Kern noch Schaale,
  • Alles ist sie mit einem Male.
  • CHAPTER IX.
  • THIRD SUB-DIVISION OF LOGIC.
  • THE DOCTRINE OF THE NOTION.
  • 160.] The Notion is the principle of freedom, the power of
  • substance self-realised. It is a systematic whole, in which each of its
  • constituent functions is the very total which the notion is, and is put
  • as indissolubly one with it. Thus in its self-identity it has original
  • and complete determinateness.
  • The position taken up by the notion is that of absolute idealism.
  • Philosophy is a knowledge through notions because it sees that what
  • on other grades of consciousness is taken to have Being, and to be
  • naturally or immediately independent, is but a constituent stage in the
  • Idea. In the logic of understanding, the notion is generally reckoned
  • a mere form of thought, and treated as a general conception. It is to
  • this inferior view of the notion that the assertion refers, so often
  • urged on behalf of the heart and sentiment, that notions as such are
  • something dead, empty, and abstract. The case is really quite the
  • reverse. The notion is, on the contrary, the principle of all life, and
  • thus possesses at the same time a character of thorough concreteness.
  • That it is so follows from the whole logical movement up to this point,
  • and need not be here proved. The contrast between form and content,
  • which is thus used to criticise the notion when it is alleged to be
  • merely formal, has, like all the other contrasts upheld by reflection,
  • been already left behind and overcome dialectically or through itself.
  • The notion, in short, is what contains all the earlier categories of
  • thought merged in it. It certainly is a form, but an infinite and
  • creative form, which includes, but at the same time releases from
  • itself, the fulness of all content. And so too the notion may, if it
  • be wished, be styled abstract, if the name concrete is restricted to
  • the concrete facts of sense or of immediate perception. For the notion
  • is not palpable to the touch, and when we are engaged with it, hearing
  • and seeing must quite fail us. And yet, as it was before remarked, the
  • notion is a true concrete; for the reason that it involves Being and
  • Essence, and the total wealth of these two spheres with them, merged in
  • the unity of thought.
  • If, as was said at an earlier point, the different stages of the
  • logical idea are to be treated as a series of definitions of the
  • Absolute, the definition which now results for us is that the Absolute
  • is the Notion. That necessitates a higher estimate of the notion,
  • however, than is found in formal conceptualist Logic, where the notion
  • is a mere form of our subjective thought, with no original content of
  • its own. But if Speculative Logic thus attaches a meaning to the term
  • notion so very different from that usually given, it may be asked why
  • the same word should be employed in two contrary acceptations, and an
  • occasion thus given for confusion and misconception. The answer is
  • that, great as the interval is between the speculative notion and the
  • notion of Formal Logic, a closer examination shows that the deeper
  • meaning is not so foreign to the general usages of language as it
  • seems at first sight. We speak of the deduction of a content from the
  • notion, _e.g._ of the specific provisions of the law of property from
  • the notion of property; and so again we speak of tracing back these
  • material details to the notion. We thus recognise that the notion is no
  • mere form without a content of its own: for if it were, there would be
  • in the one case nothing to deduce from such a form, and in the other
  • case to trace a given body of fact back to the empty form of the notion
  • would only rob the fact of its specific character, without making it
  • understood.
  • 161.] The onward movement of the notion is no longer either
  • a transition into, or a reflection on something else, but
  • Development. For in the notion, the elements distinguished are
  • without more ado at the same time declared to be identical with one
  • another and with the whole, and the specific character of each is a
  • free being of the whole notion.
  • * * * * *
  • Transition into something else is the dialectical process within the
  • range of Being: reflection (bringing something else into light), in
  • the range of Essence. The movement of the Notion is _development_: by
  • which that only is explicit which is already implicitly present. In
  • the world of nature it is organic life that corresponds to the grade
  • of the notion. Thus _e.g._ the plant is developed from its germ. The
  • germ virtually involves the whole plant, but does so only ideally or in
  • thought: and it would therefore be a mistake to regard the development
  • of the root, stem, leaves, and other different parts of the plant, as
  • meaning that they were _realiter_ present, but in a very minute form,
  • in the germ. That is the so-called 'box-within-box' hypothesis; a
  • theory which commits the mistake of supposing an actual existence of
  • what is at first found only as a postulate of the completed thought.
  • The truth of the hypothesis on the other hand lies in its perceiving
  • that in the process of development the notion keeps to itself and
  • only gives rise to alteration of form, without making any addition in
  • point of content. It is this nature of the notion--this manifestation
  • of itself in its process as a development of its own self,--which is
  • chiefly in view with those who speak of innate ideas, or who, like
  • Plato, describe all learning merely as reminiscence. Of course that
  • again does not mean that everything which is embodied in a mind, after
  • that mind has been formed by instruction, had been present in that mind
  • beforehand, in its definitely expanded shape.
  • The movement of the notion is as it were to be looked upon merely as
  • play: the other which it sets up is in reality not an other. Or, as
  • it is expressed in the teaching of Christianity: not merely has God
  • created a world which confronts Him as an other; He has also from all
  • eternity begotten a Son in whom He, a Spirit, is at home with Himself.
  • 162.] The doctrine of the notion is divided into three parts. (1) The
  • first is the doctrine of the Subjective or Formal Notion.
  • (2) The second is the doctrine of the notion invested with the
  • character of immediacy, or of Objectivity. (3) The third is the
  • doctrine of the Idea, the subject-object, the unity of notion
  • and objectivity, the absolute truth.
  • The Common Logic covers only the matters which come before us here
  • as a portion of the third part of the whole system, together with
  • the so-called Laws of Thought, which we have already met; and in the
  • Applied Logic it adds a little about cognition. This is combined with
  • psychological, metaphysical, and all sorts of empirical materials,
  • which were introduced because, when all was done, those forms of
  • thought could not be made to do all that was required of them. But
  • with these additions the science lost its unity of aim. Then there was
  • a further circumstance against the Common Logic. Those forms, which
  • at least do belong to the proper domain of Logic, are supposed to be
  • categories of conscious thought only, of thought too in the character
  • of understanding, not of reason.
  • The preceding logical categories, those viz. of Being and Essence, are,
  • it is true, no mere logical modes or entities: they are proved to be
  • notions in their transition or their dialectical element, and in their
  • return into themselves and totality. But they are only in a modified
  • form notions (cp. §§ 84 and 112), notions rudimentary, or, what is
  • the same thing, notions for us. The antithetical term into which each
  • category passes, or in which it shines, so producing correlation, is
  • not characterised as a particular. The third, in which they return
  • to unity, is not characterised as a subject or an individual: nor is
  • there any explicit statement that the category: is identical in its
  • antithesis,--in other words, its freedom is not expressly stated: and
  • all this because the category is not universality.--What generally
  • passes current under the name of a notion is a mode of understanding,
  • or, even, a mere general representation, and therefore, in short, a
  • finite mode of thought (cp. § 62).
  • The Logic of the Notion is usually treated as a science of form only,
  • and understood to deal with the form of notion, judgment, and syllogism
  • as form, without in the least touching the question whether anything
  • is true. The answer to that question is supposed to depend on the
  • content only. If the logical forms of the notion were really dead and
  • inert receptacles of conceptions and thoughts, careless of what they
  • contained, knowledge about them would be an idle curiosity which the
  • truth might dispense with. On the contrary they really are, as forms
  • of the notion, the vital spirit of the actual world. That only is
  • true of the actual which is true in virtue of these forms, through
  • them and in them. As yet, however, the truth of these forms has never
  • been considered or examined on their own account any more than their
  • necessary interconnexion.
  • A.--THE SUBJECTIVE NOTION.
  • (a) _The Notion as Notion._
  • 163.] The Notion as Notion contains the three following 'moments' or
  • functional parts. (1) The first is _Universality_--meaning that it
  • is in free equality with itself in its specific character. (2) The
  • second is Particularity--that is, the specific character, in
  • which the universal continues serenely equal to itself. (3) The third
  • is Individuality--meaning the reflection-into-self of the
  • specific characters of universality and particularity;--which negative
  • self-unity has complete and original determinateness, without any loss
  • to its self-identity or universality.
  • Individual and actual are the same thing: only the former has issued
  • from the notion, and is thus, as a universal, stated expressly as a
  • negative identity with itself. The actual, because it is at first no
  • more than a potential or immediate unity of essence and existence,
  • _may_ possibly have effect: but the individuality of the notion is
  • the very source of effectiveness, effective moreover no longer as the
  • cause is, with a show of effecting something else, but effective of
  • itself.--Individuality, however, is not to be understood to mean the
  • immediate or natural individual, as when we speak of individual things
  • or individual men: for that special phase of individuality does not
  • appear till we come to the judgment. Every function and 'moment' of
  • the notion is itself the whole notion (§ 160); but the individual or
  • subject is the notion expressly put as a totality.
  • (1) The notion is generally associated in our minds with abstract
  • generality, and on that account it is often described as a general
  • conception. We speak, accordingly, of the notions of colour, plant,
  • animal, &c. They are supposed to be arrived at by neglecting the
  • particular features which distinguish the different colours, plants,
  • and animals from each other, and by retaining those common to them all.
  • This is the aspect of the notion which is familiar to understanding;
  • and feeling is in the right when it stigmatises such hollow and empty
  • notions as mere phantoms and shadows. But the universal of the notion
  • is not a mere sum of features common to several things, confronted
  • by a particular which enjoys an existence of its own. It is, on the
  • contrary, self-particularising or self-specifying, and with undimmed
  • clearness finds itself at home in its antithesis. For the sake both of
  • cognition and of our practical conduct, it is of the utmost importance
  • that the real universal should not be confused with what is merely held
  • in common. All those charges which the devotees of feeling make against
  • thought, and especially against philosophic thought, and the reiterated
  • statement that it is dangerous to carry thought to what they call too
  • great lengths, originate in the confusion of these two things.
  • The universal in its true and comprehensive meaning is a thought
  • which, as we know, cost thousands of years to make it enter into the
  • consciousness of men. The thought did not gain its full recognition
  • till the days of Christianity. The Greeks, in other respects so
  • advanced, knew neither God nor even man in their true universality.
  • The gods of the Greeks were only particular powers of the mind; and
  • the universal God, the God of all nations, was to the Athenians still
  • a God concealed. They believed in the same way that an absolute gulf
  • separated themselves from the barbarians. Man as man was not then
  • recognised to be of infinite worth and to have infinite rights.
  • The question has been asked, why slavery has vanished from modern
  • Europe. One special circumstance after another has been adduced in
  • explanation of this phenomenon. But the real ground why there are
  • no more slaves in Christian Europe is only to be found in the very
  • principle of Christianity itself, the religion of absolute freedom.
  • Only in Christendom is man respected as man, in his infinitude and
  • universality. What the slave is without, is the recognition that he is
  • a person: and the principle of personality is universality. The master
  • looks upon his slave not as a person, but as a selfless thing. The
  • slave is not himself reckoned an 'I';--his 'I' is his master.
  • The distinction referred to above between what is merely in common, and
  • what is truly universal, is strikingly expressed by Rousseau in his
  • famous 'Contrat Social,' when he says that the laws of a state must
  • spring from the universal will (_volonté générale,_) but need not on
  • that account be the will of all (_volonté de tous._) Rousseau would
  • have made a sounder contribution towards a theory of the state, if he
  • had always keep this distinction in sight. The general will is the
  • notion of the will: and the laws are the special clauses of this will
  • and based upon the notion of it.
  • (2) We add a remark upon the account of the origin and formation of
  • notions which is usually given in the Logic of Understanding. It is
  • not _we_ who frame the notions. The notion is not something which
  • is originated at all. No doubt the notion is not mere Being, or the
  • immediate: it involves mediation, but the mediation lies in itself. In
  • other words, the notion is what is mediated through itself and with
  • itself. It is a mistake to imagine that the objects which form the
  • content of our mental ideas come first and that our subjective agency
  • then supervenes, and by the aforesaid operation of abstraction, and
  • by colligating the points possessed in common by the objects, frames
  • notions of them. Rather the notion is the genuine first; and things
  • are what they are through the action of the notion, immanent in them,
  • and revealing itself in them. In religious language we express this
  • by saying that God created the world out of nothing. In other words,
  • the world and finite things have issued from the fulness of the divine
  • thoughts and the divine decrees. Thus religion recognises thought and
  • (more exactly) the notion to be the infinite form, or the free creative
  • activity, which can realise itself without the help of a matter that
  • exists outside it.
  • 164.] The notion is concrete out and out: because the negative
  • unity with itself, as characterisation pure and entire, which is
  • individuality, is just what constitutes its self-relation, its
  • universality. The functions or 'moments' of the notion are to this
  • extent indissoluble. The categories of 'reflection' are expected to be
  • severally apprehended and separately accepted as current, apart from
  • their opposites. But in the notion, where their identity is expressly
  • assumed, each of its functions can be immediately apprehended only from
  • and with the rest.
  • Universality, particularity, and individuality are, taken in the
  • abstract, the same as identity, difference, and ground. But the
  • universal is the self-identical, with the express qualification,
  • that it simultaneously contains the particular and the individual.
  • Again, the particular is the different or the specific character, but
  • with the qualification that it is in itself universal and is as an
  • individual. Similarly the individual must be understood to be a subject
  • or substratum, which involves the genus and species in itself and
  • possesses a substantial existence. Such is the explicit or realised
  • inseparability of the functions of the notion in their difference (§
  • 160)--what may be called the clearness of the notion, in which each
  • distinction causes no dimness or interruption, but is quite as much
  • transparent.
  • No complaint is oftener made against the notion than that it is
  • _abstract._ Of course it is abstract, if abstract means that the medium
  • in which the notion exists is thought in general and not the sensible
  • thing in its empirical concreteness. It is abstract also, because the
  • notion falls short of the idea. To this extent the subjective notion
  • is still formal. This however does not mean that it ought to have
  • or receive another content than its own. It is itself the absolute
  • form, and so is all specific character, but as that character is in
  • its truth. Although it be abstract therefore, it is the concrete,
  • concrete altogether, the subject as such. The absolutely concrete is
  • the mind (see end of § 159)--the notion when it _exists_ as notion
  • distinguishing itself from its objectivity, which notwithstanding the
  • distinction still continues to be its own. Everything else which is
  • concrete, however rich it be, is not so intensely identical with itself
  • and therefore not so concrete on its own part,--least of all what is
  • commonly supposed to be concrete, but is only a congeries held together
  • by external influence.--What are called notions, and in fact specific
  • notions, such as man, house, animal, &c, are simply denotations
  • and abstract representations. These abstractions retain out of all
  • the functions of the notion only that of universality; they leave
  • particularity and individuality out of account and have no development
  • in these directions. By so doing they just miss the notion.
  • 165.] It is the element of Individuality which first explicitly
  • differentiates the elements of the notion. Individuality is the
  • negative reflection of the notion into itself, and it is in that way at
  • first the free differentiating of it as the first negation, by which
  • the specific character of the notion is realised, but under the form
  • of particularity. That is to say, the different elements are in the
  • first place only qualified as the several elements of the notion, and,
  • secondly, their identity is no less explicitly stated, the one being
  • said to be the other. This realised particularity of the notion is the
  • Judgment.
  • The ordinary classification of notions, as _clear, distinct_ and
  • _adequate,_ is no part of the notion; it belongs to psychology.
  • Notions, in fact, are here synonymous with mental representations;
  • a _clear_ notion is an abstract simple representation: a _distinct_
  • notion is one where, in addition to the simplicity, there is one 'mark'
  • or character emphasised as a sign for subjective cognition. There is
  • no more striking mark of the formalism and decay of Logic than the
  • favourite category of the 'mark.' The _adequate_ notion comes nearer
  • the notion proper, or even the Idea: but after all it expresses only
  • the formal circumstance that a notion or representation agrees with its
  • object, that is, with an external thing.--The division into what are
  • called _subordinate_ and _co-ordinate_ notions implies a mechanical
  • distinction of universal from particular which allows only a mere
  • correlation of them in external comparison. Again, an enumeration
  • of such kinds as _contrary_ and _contradictory, affirmative_ and
  • _negative_ notions, &c, is only a chance-directed gleaning of logical
  • forms which properly belong to the sphere of Being or Essence, (where
  • they have been already examined,) and which have nothing to do with
  • the specific notional character as such. The true distinctions in the
  • notion, universal, particular, and individual, may be said also to
  • constitute species of it, but only when they are kept severed from
  • each other by external reflection. The immanent differentiating and
  • specifying of the notion come to sight in the judgment: for to judge is
  • to specify the notion.
  • (b) _The Judgment._
  • 166.] The Judgment is the notion in its particularity, as a
  • connexion which is also a distinguishing of its functions, which are
  • put as independent and yet as identical with themselves, not with one
  • another.
  • One's first impression about the Judgment is the independence of the
  • two extremes, the subject and the predicate. The former we take to be
  • a thing or term _per se,_ and the predicate a general term outside
  • the said subject and somewhere in our heads. The next point is for us
  • to bring the latter into combination with the former, and in this way
  • frame a Judgment. The copula 'is' however enunciates the predicate _of_
  • the subject, and so that external subjective subsumption is again put
  • in abeyance, and the Judgment taken as a determination of the object
  • itself.--The etymological meaning of the Judgment (_Urtheil_) in
  • German goes deeper, as it were declaring the unity of the notion to be
  • primary, and its distinction to be the original partition. And that is
  • what the Judgment really is.
  • In its abstract terms a Judgment is expressible in the proposition:
  • 'The individual is the universal.' These are the terms under which
  • the subject and the predicate first confront each other, when the
  • functions of the notion are taken in their immediate character or
  • first abstraction. [Propositions such as, 'The particular is the
  • universal,' and 'The individual is the particular,' belong to the
  • further specialisation of the judgment.] It shows a strange want
  • of observation in the logic-books, that in none of them is the fact
  • stated, that in _every_ judgment there is such a statement made, as,
  • The individual is the universal, or still more definitely, The subject
  • is the predicate: (_e.g._ God is absolute spirit). No doubt there is
  • also a distinction between terms like individual and universal, subject
  • and predicate: but it is none the less the universal fact, that every
  • judgment states them to be identical.
  • The copula 'is' springs from the nature of the notion, to be
  • self-identical even in parting with its own. The individual and
  • universal are _its_ constituents, and therefore characters which
  • cannot be isolated. The earlier categories (of reflection) in their
  • correlations also refer to one another: but their interconnexion is
  • only 'having' and not 'being,' _i.e._ it is not the identity which is
  • realised as identity or universality. In the judgment, therefore, for
  • the first time there is seen the genuine particularity of the notion:
  • for it is the speciality or distinguishing of the latter, without
  • thereby losing universality.
  • * * * * *
  • Judgments are generally looked upon as combinations of notions, and,
  • be it added, of heterogeneous notions. This theory of judgment is
  • correct, so far as it implies that it is the notion which forms the
  • presupposition of the judgment, and which in the judgment comes up
  • under the form of difference. But on the other hand, it is false to
  • speak of notions differing in kind. The notion, although concrete,
  • is still as a notion essentially one, and the functions which it
  • contains are not different kinds of it. It is equally false to speak
  • of a combination of the two sides in the judgment, if we understand
  • the term 'combination' to imply the independent existence of the
  • combining members apart from the combination. The same external view
  • of their nature is more forcibly apparent when judgments are described
  • as produced by the ascription of a predicate to the subject. Language
  • like this looks upon the subject as self-subsistent outside, and the
  • predicate as found somewhere in our head. Such a conception of the
  • relation between subject and predicate however is at once contradicted
  • by the copula 'is.' By saying 'This rose is red,' or 'This picture
  • is beautiful,' we declare, that it is not we who from outside attach
  • beauty to the picture or redness to the rose, but that these are the
  • characteristics proper to these objects. An additional fault in the
  • way in which Formal Logic conceives the judgment is, that it makes
  • the judgment look as if it were something merely contingent, and
  • does not offer any proof for the advance from notion on to judgment.
  • For the notion does not, as understanding supposes, stand still in
  • its own immobility. It is rather an infinite form, of boundless
  • activity, as it were the _punctum saliens_ of all vitality, and
  • thereby self-differentiating. This disruption of the notion into the
  • difference of its constituent functions',--a disruption imposed by the
  • native act of the notion, is the judgment. A judgment therefore means
  • the particularising of the notion. No doubt the notion is implicitly
  • the particular. But in the notion as notion the particular is not yet
  • explicit, and still remains in transparent unity with the universal.
  • Thus, for example, as we remarked before (§ 160, note), the germ of a
  • plant contains its particular, such as root, branches, leaves, &c.:
  • but these details are at first present only potentially, and are not
  • realised till the germ uncloses. This unclosing is, as it were, the
  • judgment of the plant. The illustration may also serve to show how
  • neither the notion nor the judgment are merely found in our head, or
  • merely framed by us. The notion is the very heart of things, and makes
  • them what they are. To form a notion of an object means therefore to
  • become aware of its notion: and when we proceed to a criticism or
  • judgment of the object, we are not performing a subjective act, and
  • merely ascribing this or that predicate to the object. We are, on the
  • contrary, observing the object in the specific character imposed by its
  • notion.
  • 167.] The Judgment is usually taken in a subjective sense as an
  • operation and a form, occurring merely in self-conscious thought. This
  • distinction, however, has no existence on purely logical principles,
  • by which the judgment is taken in the quite universal signification
  • that all things are a judgment. That is to say, they are individuals,
  • which are a universality or inner nature in themselves,--a universal
  • which is individualised. Their universality and individuality are
  • distinguished, but the one is at the same time identical with the other.
  • The interpretation of the judgment, according to which it is assumed
  • to be merely subjective, as if _we_ ascribed a predicate to a subject,
  • is contradicted by the decidedly objective expression of the judgment.
  • The rose _is_ red; Gold _is_ a metal. It is not by us that something
  • is first ascribed to them.--A judgment is however distinguished from a
  • proposition. The latter contains a statement about the subject, which
  • does not stand to it in any universal relationship, but expresses some
  • single action, or some state, or the like. Thus, 'Caesar was born at
  • Rome in such and such a year, waged war in Gaul for ten years, crossed
  • the Rubicon, &c.,' are propositions, but not judgments. Again it is
  • absurd to say that such statements as, 'I slept well last night,' or
  • 'Present arms!' may be turned into the form of a judgment. 'A carriage
  • is passing by'--would be a judgment, and a subjective one at best, only
  • if it were doubtful, whether the passing object was a carriage, or
  • whether it and not rather the point of observation was in motion:--in
  • short, only if it were desired to specify a conception which was still
  • short of appropriate specification.
  • 168.] The judgment is an expression of finitude. Things from its point
  • of view are said to be finite, because they are a judgment, because
  • their definite being and their universal nature, (their body and their
  • soul,) though united indeed (otherwise the things would be nothing),
  • are still elements in the constitution which are already different and
  • also in any case separable.
  • 169.] The abstract terms of the judgment, 'The individual is the
  • universal,' present the subject (as negatively self-relating) as what
  • is immediately _concrete,_ while the predicate is what is _abstract,_
  • indeterminate, in short, the universal. But the two elements are
  • connected together by an 'is': and thus the predicate (in its
  • universality) must also contain the speciality of the subject, must,
  • in short, have particularity: and so is realised the identity between
  • subject and predicate; which, being thus unaffected by this difference
  • in form, is the content.
  • It is the predicate which first gives the subject, which till then was
  • on its own account a bare mental representation or an empty name, its
  • specific character and content. In judgments like 'God is the most
  • real of all things,' or 'The Absolute is the self-identical,' God and
  • the Absolute are mere names; what they _are_ we only learn in the
  • predicate. What the subject may be in other respects, as a concrete
  • thing, is no concern of _this_ judgment. (Cp. § 31.)
  • To define the subject as that of which something is said, and the
  • predicate as what is said about it, is mere trifling. It gives no
  • information about the distinction between the two. In point of
  • thought, the subject is primarily the individual, and the predicate
  • the universal. As the judgment receives further development, the
  • subject ceases to be merely the immediate individual, and the predicate
  • merely the abstract universal: the former acquires the additional
  • significations of particular and universal,--the latter the additional
  • significations of particular and individual. Thus while the same names
  • are given to the two terms of the judgment, their meaning passes
  • through a series of changes.
  • 170.] We now go closer into the speciality of subject and predicate.
  • The subject as negative self-relation (§§ 163, 166) is the stable
  • substratum in which the predicate has its subsistence and where it
  • is ideally present. The predicate, as the phrase is, _inheres_ in
  • the subject. Further, as the subject is in general and immediately
  • concrete, the specific connotation of the predicate is only one of the
  • numerous characters of the subject. Thus the subject is ampler and
  • wider than the predicate.
  • Conversely, the predicate as universal is self-subsistent, and
  • indifferent whether this subject is or not. The predicate outflanks
  • the subject, subsuming it under itself: and hence on its side is wider
  • than the subject. The specific content of the predicate (§ 169) alone
  • constitutes the identity of the two.
  • 171.] At first, subject, predicate, and the specific content or the
  • identity are, even in their relation, still put in the judgment
  • as different and divergent. By implication, however, that is, in
  • their notion, they are identical. For the subject is a concrete
  • totality,--which means not any indefinite multiplicity, but
  • individuality alone, the particular and the universal in an identity:
  • and the predicate too is the very same unity (§ 170).--The copula
  • again, even while stating the identity of subject and predicate,
  • does so at first only by an abstract 'is.' Conformably to such an
  • identity the subject has to be _put_ also in the characteristic of the
  • predicate. By this means the latter also receives the characteristic of
  • the former: so that the copula receives its full complement and full
  • force. Such is the continuous specification by which the judgment,
  • through a copula charged with content, comes to be a syllogism. As it
  • is primarily exhibited in the judgment, this gradual specification
  • consists in giving to an originally abstract, sensuous universality the
  • specific character of allness, of species, of genus, and finally of the
  • developed universality of the notion.
  • After we are made aware of this continuous specification of the
  • judgment, we can see a meaning and an interconnexion in what are
  • usually stated as the kinds of judgment. Not only does the ordinary
  • enumeration seem purely casual, but it is also superficial, and even
  • bewildering in its statement of their distinctions. The distinction
  • between positive, categorical and assertory judgments, is either a pure
  • invention of fancy, or is left undetermined. On the right theory, the
  • different judgments follow necessarily from one another, and present
  • the continuous specification of the notion; for the judgment itself is
  • nothing but the notion specified.
  • When we look at the two preceding spheres of Being and Essence, we see
  • that the specified notions as judgments are reproductions of these
  • spheres, but put in the simplicity of relation peculiar to the notion.
  • * * * * *
  • The various kinds of judgment are no empirical aggregate. They are
  • a systematic whole based on a principle; and it was one of Kant's
  • great merits to have first emphasised the necessity of showing
  • this. His proposed division, according to the headings in his table
  • of categories, into judgments of quality, quantity, relation and
  • modality, can not be called satisfactory, partly from the merely formal
  • application of this categorical rubric, partly on account of their
  • content. Still it rests upon a true perception of the fact that the
  • different species of judgment derive their features from the universal
  • forms of the logical idea itself. If we follow this clue, it will
  • supply us with three chief kinds of judgment parallel to the stages
  • of Being, Essence, and Notion. The second of these kinds, as required
  • by the character of Essence, which is the stage of differentiation,
  • must be doubled. We find the inner ground for this systematisation of
  • judgments in the circumstance that when the Notion, which is the unity
  • of Being and Essence in a comprehensive thought, unfolds, as it does in
  • the judgment, it must reproduce these two stages in a transformation
  • proper to the notion. The notion itself meanwhile is seen to mould and
  • form the genuine grade of judgment.
  • Far from occupying the same level, and being of equal value, the
  • different species of judgment form a series of steps, the difference
  • of which rests upon the logical significance of the predicate. That
  • judgments differ in value is evident even in our ordinary ways of
  • thinking. We should not hesitate to ascribe a very slight faculty of
  • judgment to a person who habitually framed only such judgments as,
  • 'This wall is green,' 'This stove is hot.' On the other hand we should
  • credit with a genuine capacity of judgment the person whose criticisms
  • dealt with such questions as whether a certain work of art was
  • beautiful, whether a certain action was good, and so on. In judgments
  • of the first-mentioned kind the content forms only an abstract quality,
  • the presence of which can be sufficiently detected by immediate
  • perception. To pronounce a work of art to be beautiful, or an action to
  • be good, requires on the contrary a comparison of the objects with what
  • they ought to be, _i.e._ with their notion.
  • (α) Qualitative Judgment.
  • 172.] The immediate judgment is the judgment of definite Being. The
  • subject is invested with a universality as its predicate, which is
  • an immediate, and therefore a sensible quality. It may be (1) a
  • Positive judgment: The individual is a particular. But the
  • individual is not a particular: or in more precise language, such
  • a single quality is not congruous with the concrete nature of the
  • subject. This is (2) a Negative judgment.
  • It is one of the fundamental assumptions of dogmatic Logic that
  • Qualitative judgments such as, 'The rose is red,' or 'is not red,' can
  • contain _truth. Correct_ they may be, _i.e._ in the limited circle
  • of perception, of finite conception and thought: that depends on the
  • content, which likewise is finite, and, on its own merits, untrue.
  • Truth, however, as opposed to correctness, depends solely on the form,
  • viz. on the notion as it is put and the reality corresponding to it.
  • But truth of that stamp is not found in the Qualitative judgment.
  • In common life the terms _truth_ and _correctness_ are often treated
  • as synonymous: we speak of the truth of a content, when we are only
  • thinking of its correctness. Correctness, generally speaking, concerns
  • only the formal coincidence between our conception and its content,
  • whatever the constitution of this content may be. Truth, on the
  • contrary, lies in the coincidence of the object with itself, that is,
  • with its notion. That a person is sick, or that some one has committed
  • a theft, may certainly be correct. But the content is untrue. A sick
  • body is not in harmony with the notion of body, and there is a want
  • of congruity between theft and the notion of human conduct. These
  • instances may show that an immediate judgment, in which an abstract
  • quality is predicated of an immediately individual thing, however
  • correct it may be, cannot contain truth. The subject and predicate of
  • it do not stand to each other in the relation of reality and notion.
  • We may add that the untruth of the immediate judgment lies in the
  • incongruity between its form and content. To say 'This rose is red,'
  • involves (in virtue of the copula 'is') the coincidence of subject and
  • predicate. The rose however is a concrete thing, and so is not red
  • only: it has also an odour, a specific form, and many other features
  • not implied in the predicate red. The predicate on its part is an
  • abstract universal, and does not apply to the rose alone. There are
  • other flowers and other objects which are red too. The subject and
  • predicate in the immediate judgment touch, as it were, only in a single
  • point, but do not cover each other. The case is different with the
  • notional judgment. In pronouncing an action to be good, we frame a
  • notional judgment. Here, as we at once perceive, there is a closer and
  • a more intimate relation than in the immediate judgment. The predicate
  • in the latter is some abstract quality which may or may not be applied
  • to the subject. In the judgment of the notion the predicate is, as it
  • were, the soul of the subject, by which the subject, as the body of
  • this soul, is characterised through and through.
  • 173.] This negation of a particular quality, which is the first
  • negation, still leaves the connexion of the subject with the predicate
  • subsisting. The predicate is in that manner a sort of relative
  • universal, of which a special phase only has been negatived. [To say,
  • that the rose is not red, implies that it is still coloured--in the
  • first place with another colour; which however would be only one more
  • positive judgment.] The individual however is not a universal. Hence
  • (3) the judgment suffers disruption into one of two forms. It is either
  • (a) the Identical judgment, an empty identical relation stating
  • that the individual is the individual; or it is (b) what is called the
  • Infinite judgment, in which we are presented with the total
  • incompatibility of subject and predicate.
  • Examples of the latter are: 'The mind is no elephant:' 'A lion is
  • no table;' propositions which are correct but absurd, exactly like
  • the identical propositions: 'A lion is a lion;' 'Mind is mind.'
  • Propositions like these are undoubtedly the truth of the immediate, or,
  • as it is called, Qualitative judgment. But they are not judgments at
  • all, and can only occur in a subjective thought where even an untrue
  • abstraction may hold its ground.--In their objective aspect, these
  • latter judgments express the nature of what is, or of sensible things,
  • which, as they declare, suffer disruption into an empty identity on the
  • one hand, and on the other a fully-charged relation--only that this
  • relation is the qualitative antagonism of the things related, their
  • total incongruity.
  • * * * * *
  • The negatively-infinite judgment, in which the subject has no relation
  • whatever to the predicate, gets its place in the Formal Logic solely as
  • a nonsensical curiosity. But the infinite judgment is not really a mere
  • casual form adopted by subjective thought. It exhibits the proximate
  • result of the dialectical process in the immediate judgments preceding
  • (the positive and simply-negative), and distinctly displays their
  • finitude and untruth. Crime may be quoted as an objective instance of
  • the negatively-infinite judgment. The person committing a crime, such
  • as a theft, does not, as in a suit about civil rights, merely deny
  • the particular right of another person to some one definite thing.
  • He denies the right of that person in general, and therefore he is
  • not merely forced to restore what he has stolen, but is punished in
  • addition, because he has violated law as law, _i.e._ law in general.
  • The civil-law suit on the contrary is an instance of the negative
  • judgment pure and simple where merely the particular law is violated,
  • whilst law in general is so far acknowledged. Such a dispute is
  • precisely paralleled by a negative judgment, like, 'This flower is not
  • red:' by which we merely deny the particular colour of the flower, but
  • not its colour in general, which may be blue, yellow, or any other.
  • Similarly death, as a negatively-infinite judgment, is distinguished
  • from disease as simply-negative. In disease, merely this or that
  • function of life is checked or negatived: in death, as we ordinarily
  • say, body and soul part, _i.e._ subject and predicate utterly diverge.
  • (ß) _Judgment of Reflection._
  • 174.] The individual put as individual (_i.e._ as reflected-into-self)
  • into the judgment, has a predicate, in comparison with which the
  • subject, as self-relating, continues to be still _an other_ thing.--In
  • existence the subject ceases to be immediately qualitative, it is in
  • correlation, and inter-connexion with an other thing,--with an external
  • world. In this way the universality of the predicate comes to signify
  • this relativity--(_e.g._) useful, or dangerous; weight or acidity; or
  • again, instinct; are examples of such relative predicates.
  • The Judgment of Reflection is distinguished from the Qualitative
  • judgment by the circumstance that its predicate is not an immediate
  • or abstract quality, but of such a kind as to exhibit the subject
  • as in relation to something else. When we say, _e.g._ 'This rose is
  • red.' we regard the subject in its immediate individuality, and
  • without reference to anything else. If, on the other hand, we frame
  • the judgment, 'This plant is medicinal,' we regard the subject, plant,
  • as standing in connexion with something else (the sickness which it
  • cures), by means of its predicate (its medicinality). The case is the
  • same with judgments like: This body is elastic: This instrument is
  • useful: This punishment has a deterrent influence. In every one of
  • these instances the predicate is some category of reflection. They all
  • exhibit an advance beyond the immediate individuality of the subject,
  • but none of them goes so far as to indicate the adequate notion of it.
  • It is in this mode of judgment that ordinary _raisonnement_ luxuriates.
  • The greater the concreteness of the object in question, the more points
  • of view does it offer to reflection; by which however its proper nature
  • or notion is not exhausted.
  • 175.] (1) Firstly then the subject, the individual as individual (in
  • the Singular judgment), is a universal. But (2) secondly, in
  • this relation it is elevated above its singularity. This enlargement is
  • external, due to subjective reflection, and at first is an indefinite
  • number of particulars. (This is seen in the Particular judgment,
  • which is obviously negative as well as positive: the individual is
  • divided in itself: partly it is self-related, partly related to
  • something else.) (3) Thirdly, Some are the universal: particularity is
  • thus enlarged to universality: or universality is modified through the
  • individuality of the subject, and appears as allness Community,
  • the ordinary universality of reflection.
  • * * * * *
  • The subject, receiving, as in the Singular judgment, a universal
  • predicate, is carried out beyond its mere individual self. To say,
  • 'This plant is wholesome,' implies not only that this single plant is
  • wholesome, but that some or several are so. We have thus the particular
  • judgment (some plants are wholesome, some men are inventive, &c). By
  • means of particularity the immediate individual comes to lose its
  • independence, and enters into an inter-connexion with something else.
  • Man, as _this_ man, is not this single man alone: he stands beside
  • other men and becomes one in the crowd, just by this means however he
  • belongs to his universal, and is consequently raised.--The particular
  • judgment is as much negative as positive. If only some bodies are
  • elastic, it is evident that the rest are not elastic.
  • On this fact again depends the advance to the third form of the
  • Reflective judgment, viz. the judgment of allness (all men are mortal,
  • all metals conduct electricity). It is as 'all' that the universal
  • is in the first instance generally encountered by reflection. The
  • individuals form for reflection the foundation, and it is only our
  • subjective action which collects and describes them as 'all.' So far
  • the universal has the aspect of an external fastening, that holds
  • together a number of independent individuals, which have not the least
  • affinity towards it. This semblance of indifference is however unreal:
  • for the universal is the ground and foundation, the root, and substance
  • of the individual. If _e.g._ we take Caius, Titus, Sempronius, and
  • the other inhabitants of a town or country, the fact that all of them
  • are men is not merely something which they have in common, but their
  • universal or kind, without which these individuals would not be at all.
  • The case is very different with that superficial generality falsely
  • so called, which really means only what attaches, or is common, to
  • all the individuals. It has been remarked, for example, that men,
  • in contradistinction from the lower animals, possess in common the
  • appendage of ear-lobes. It is evident, however, that the absence of
  • these ear-lobes in one man or another would not affect the rest of
  • his being, character, or capacities: whereas it would be nonsense
  • to suppose that Caius, without being a man, would still be brave,
  • learned, &c. The individual man is what he is in particular, only in so
  • far as he is before all things a man as man and in general. And that
  • generality is not something external to, or something in addition to
  • other abstract qualities, or to mere features discovered by reflection.
  • It is what permeates and includes in it everything particular.
  • 176.] The subject being thus likewise characterised as a universal,
  • there is an express identification of subject and predicate, by which
  • at the same time the speciality of the judgment form is deprived of
  • all importance. This unity of the content (the content being the
  • universality which is identical with the negative reflection-in-self of
  • the subject) makes the connexion in judgment a necessary one.
  • The advance from the reflective judgment of allness to the judgment
  • of necessity is found in our usual modes of thought, when we say that
  • whatever appertains to all, appertains to the species, and is therefore
  • necessary. To say all plants, or all men, is the same thing as to say
  • _the_ plant, or _the_ man.
  • (γ) _Judgment of Necessity._
  • 177.] The Judgment of Necessity, _i.e._ of the identity of the content
  • in its difference (1), contains, in the predicate, partly the substance
  • or nature of the subject, the concrete universal, the _genus_; partly,
  • seeing that this universal also contains the specific character as
  • negative, the predicate represents the exclusive essential character,
  • the _species._ This is the Categorical judgment.
  • (2) Conformably to their substantiality, the two terms receive the
  • aspect of independent actuality. Their identity is then inward only;
  • and thus the actuality of the one is at the same time not its own, but
  • the being of the other. This is the Hypothetical judgment.
  • (3) If, in this self-surrender and self-alienation of the notion,
  • its inner identity is at the same time explicitly put, the universal
  • is the genus which is self-identical in its mutually-exclusive
  • individualities. This judgment, which has this universal for both its
  • terms, the one time as a universal, the other time as the circle of
  • its self-excluding particularisation in which the 'either--or' as much
  • as the 'as well as' stands for the genus, is the Disjunctive
  • judgment. Universality, at first as a genus, and now also as the
  • circuit of its species, is thus described and expressly put as a
  • totality.
  • * * * * *
  • The Categorical judgment (such as 'Gold is a metal,' 'The rose is a
  • plant') is the un-mediated judgment of necessity, and finds within the
  • sphere of Essence its parallel in the relation of substance. All things
  • are a Categorical judgment. In other words, they have their substantial
  • nature, forming their fixed and unchangeable substratum. It is only
  • when things are studied from the point of view of their kind, and as
  • with necessity determined by the kind, that the judgment first begins
  • to be real. It betrays a defective logical training to place upon the
  • same level judgments like 'gold is dear,' and judgments like 'gold
  • is a metal.' That 'gold is dear' is a matter of external connexion
  • between it and our wants or inclinations, the costs of obtaining it,
  • and other circumstances. Gold remains the same as it was, though that
  • external reference is altered or removed. Metalleity, on the contrary,
  • constitutes the substantial nature of gold, apart from which it, and
  • all else that is in it, or can be predicated of it, would be unable to
  • subsist. The same is the case if we say, 'Caius is a man.' We express
  • by that, that whatever else he may be, has worth and meaning, only when
  • it corresponds to his substantial nature or manhood.
  • But even the Categorical judgment is to a certain extent defective. It
  • fails to give due place to the function or element of particularity.
  • Thus 'gold is a metal,' it is true; but so are silver, copper, iron:
  • and metalleity as such has no leanings to any of its particular
  • species. In these circumstances we must advance from the Categorical to
  • the Hypothetical judgment, which may be expressed in the formula: If
  • _A_ is, _B_ is. The present case exhibits the same advance as formerly
  • took place from the relation of substance to the relation of cause. In
  • the Hypothetical judgment the specific character of the content shows
  • itself mediated and dependent on something else: and this is exactly
  • the relation of cause and effect. And if we were to give a general
  • interpretation to the Hypothetical judgment, we should say that it
  • expressly realises the universal in its particularising. This brings
  • us to the third form of the Judgment of Necessity, the Disjunctive
  • judgment. _A_ is either _B_ or _C_ or _D._ A work of poetic art is
  • either epic or lyric or dramatic. Colour is either yellow or blue or
  • red. The two terms in the Disjunctive judgment are identical. The genus
  • is the sum total of the species, and the sum total of the species
  • is the genus. This unity of the universal and the particular is the
  • notion: and it is the notion which, as we now see, forms the content of
  • the judgment.
  • (δ) _Judgment of the Notion._
  • 178.] The Judgment of the Notion has for its content the notion, the
  • totality in simple form, the universal with its complete speciality.
  • The subject is, (1) in the first place, an individual, which has
  • for its predicate the reflection of the particular existence on its
  • universal; or the judgment states the agreement or disagreement of
  • these two aspects. That is, the predicate is such a term as good, true,
  • correct. This is the Assertory judgment.
  • Judgments, such as whether an object, action, &c. is good, bad, true,
  • beautiful, &c, are those to which even ordinary language first applies
  • the name of judgment. We should never ascribe judgment to a person who
  • framed positive or negative judgments like, This rose is red, This
  • picture is red, green, dusty, &c.
  • The Assertory judgment, although rejected by society as out of place
  • when it claims authority on its own showing, has however been made the
  • single and all-essential form of doctrine, even in philosophy, through
  • the influence of the principle of immediate knowledge and faith. In the
  • so-called philosophic works which maintain this principle, we may read
  • hundreds and hundreds of assertions about reason, knowledge, thought,
  • &c. which, now that external authority counts for little, seek to
  • accredit themselves by an endless restatement of the same thesis.
  • 179.] On the part of its at first un-mediated subject, the Assertory
  • judgment does not contain the relation of particular with universal
  • which is expressed in the predicate. This judgment is consequently
  • a mere subjective particularity, and is confronted by a contrary
  • assertion with equal right, or rather want of right. It is therefore
  • at once turned into (2) a Problematical judgment. But when we
  • explicitly attach the objective particularity to the subject and make
  • its speciality the constitutive feature of its existence, the subject
  • (3) then expresses the connexion of that objective particularity with
  • its constitution, _i.e._ with its genus; and thus expresses what
  • forms the content of the predicate (see § 178). [This (_the immediate
  • individuality_) house (_the genus,_) being so and so constituted
  • (_particularity,_) is good or bad.] This is the Apodictic
  • judgment. All things are a genus (_i.e._ have a meaning and purpose) in
  • an _individual_ actuality of a _particular_ constitution. And they are
  • finite, because the particular in them may and also may not conform to
  • the universal.
  • 180.] In this manner subject and predicate are each the whole judgment.
  • The immediate constitution of the subject is at first exhibited as
  • the intermediating ground, where the individuality of the actual
  • thing meets with its universality, and in this way as the ground of
  • the judgment. What has been really made explicit is the oneness of
  • subject and predicate, as the notion itself, filling up the empty 'is'
  • of the copula. While its constituent elements are at the same time
  • distinguished as subject and predicate, the notion is put as their
  • unity, as the connexion which serves to intermediate them: in short, as
  • the Syllogism.
  • (c) _The Syllogism._
  • 181.] The Syllogism brings the notion and the judgment into one.
  • It is notion,--being the simple identity into which the distinctions of
  • form in the judgment have retired. It is judgment,--because it is at
  • the same time set in reality, that is, put in the distinction of its
  • terms. The Syllogism is the reasonable, and everything reasonable.
  • Even the ordinary theories represent the Syllogism to be the form of
  • reasonableness, but only a subjective form; and no inter-connexion
  • whatever is shown to exist between it and any other reasonable content,
  • such as a reasonable principle, a reasonable action, idea, &c. The name
  • of reason is much and often heard, and appealed to: but no one thinks
  • of explaining its specific character, or saying what it is,--least of
  • all that it has any connexion with Syllogism. But formal Syllogism
  • really presents what is reasonable in such a reasonless way that it
  • has nothing to do with any reasonable matter. But as the matter in
  • question can only be rational in virtue of the same quality by which
  • thought is reason, it can be made so by the form only: and that
  • form is Syllogism. And what is a Syllogism but an explicit putting,
  • _i.e._ realising of the notion, at first in form only, as stated
  • above? Accordingly the Syllogism is the essential ground of whatever
  • is true: and at the present stage the definition of the Absolute is
  • that it is the Syllogism, or stating the principle in a proposition:
  • Everything is a Syllogism. Everything is a notion, the existence of
  • which is the differentiation of its members or functions, so that the
  • universal nature of the Notion gives itself external reality by means
  • of particularity, and thereby, and as a negative reflection-into-self,
  • makes itself an individual. Or, conversely: the actual thing is an
  • individual, which by means of particularity rises to universality and
  • makes itself identical with itself.--The actual is one: but it is also
  • the divergence from each other of the constituent elements of the
  • notion; and the Syllogism represents the orbit of intermediation of its
  • elements, by which it realises its unity.
  • The Syllogism, like the notion and the judgment, is usually described
  • as a form merely of our subjective thinking. The Syllogism, it is said,
  • is the process of proving the judgment. And certainly the judgment does
  • in every case refer us to the Syllogism. The step from the one to the
  • other however is not brought about by our subjective action, but by the
  • judgment itself which puts itself as Syllogism, and in the conclusion
  • returns to the unity of the notion. The precise point by which we
  • pass to the Syllogism is found in the Apodictic judgment. In it we
  • have an individual which by means of its qualities connects itself
  • with its universal or notion. Here we see the particular becoming the
  • mediating mean between the individual and the universal. This gives
  • the fundamental form of the Syllogism, the gradual specification of
  • which, formally considered, consists in the fact that universal and
  • individual also occupy this place of mean. This again paves the way for
  • the passage from subjectivity to objectivity.
  • 182.] In the 'immediate' Syllogism the several aspects of the notion
  • confront one another abstractly, and stand in an external relation
  • only. We have first the two extremes, which are Individuality and
  • Universality; and then the notion, as the mean for locking the two
  • together, is in like manner only abstract Particularity. In this way
  • the extremes are put as independent and without affinity either towards
  • one another or towards their mean. Such a Syllogism contains reason,
  • but in utter notionlessness,--the formal Syllogism of Understanding. In
  • it the subject is coupled with an _other_ character; or the universal
  • by this mediation subsumes a subject external to it. In the rational
  • Syllogism, on the contrary, the subject is by means of the mediation
  • coupled with itself. In this manner it first comes to be a subject: or,
  • in the subject we have the first germ of the rational Syllogism.
  • In the following examination, the Syllogism of Understanding, according
  • to the interpretation usually put upon it, is expressed in its
  • subjective shape; the shape which it has when _we_ are said to make
  • such Syllogisms. And it really is only a subjective syllogising. Such
  • Syllogism however has also an objective meaning; it expresses only the
  • finitude of things, but does so in the specific mode which the form
  • has here reached. In the case of finite things their subjectivity,
  • being only thinghood, is separable from their properties or their
  • particularity, but also separable from their universality: not only
  • when the universality is the bare quality of the thing and its external
  • inter-connexion with other things, but also when it is its genus and
  • notion.
  • * * * * *
  • On the above-mentioned theory of syllogism, as the rational form _par
  • excellence,_ reason has been defined as the faculty of syllogising,
  • whilst understanding is defined as the faculty of forming notions. We
  • might object to the conception on which this depends, and according to
  • which the mind is merely a sum of forces or faculties existing side
  • by side. But apart from that objection, we may observe in regard to
  • the parallelism of understanding with the notion, as well as of reason
  • with syllogism, that the notion is as little a mere category of the
  • understanding as the syllogism is without qualification definable
  • as rational. For, in the first place, what the Formal Logic usually
  • examines in its theory of syllogism, is really nothing but the mere
  • syllogism of understanding, which has no claim to the honour of being
  • made a form of rationality, still less to be held as the embodiment of
  • all reason. The notion, in the second place, so far from being a form
  • of understanding, owes its degradation to such a place entirely to
  • the influence of that abstract mode of thought. And it is not unusual
  • to draw such a distinction between a notion of understanding and a
  • notion of reason. The distinction however does not mean that notions
  • are of two kinds. It means that our own action often stops short at
  • the mere negative and abstract form of the notion, when we might also
  • have proceeded to apprehend the notion in its true nature, as at once
  • positive and concrete. It is _e.g._ the mere understanding, which
  • thinks liberty to be the abstract contrary of necessity, whereas the
  • adequate rational notion of liberty requires the element of necessity
  • to be merged in it. Similarly the definition of God, given by what is
  • called Deism, is merely the mode in which the understanding thinks God:
  • whereas Christianity, to which He is known as the Trinity, contains the
  • rational notion of God.
  • (α) _Qualitative Syllogism._
  • 183.] The first syllogism is a syllogism of definite being,--a
  • Qualitative Syllogism, as stated in the last paragraph. Its form (1) is
  • I--P--U: _i.e._ a subject as Individual is coupled (concluded) with a
  • Universal character by means of a (Particular) quality.
  • Of course the subject (_terminus minor_) has other characteristics
  • besides individuality, just as the other extreme (the predicate of the
  • conclusion, or _terminus major_) has other characteristics than mere
  • universality. But here the interest turns only on the characteristics
  • through which these terms make a syllogism.
  • The syllogism of existence is a syllogism of understanding merely, at
  • least in so far as it leaves the individual, the particular, and the
  • universal to confront each other quite abstractly. In this syllogism
  • the notion is at the very height of self-estrangement. We have in it
  • an immediately individual thing as subject: next some one particular
  • aspect or property attaching to this subject is selected, and by means
  • of this property the individual turns out to be a universal. Thus we
  • may say, This rose is red: Red is a colour: Therefore, this rose
  • is a coloured object. It is this aspect of the syllogism which the
  • common logics mainly treat of. There was a time when the syllogism was
  • regarded as an absolute rule for all cognition, and when a scientific
  • statement was not held to be valid until it had been shown to follow
  • from a process of syllogism. At present, on the contrary, the different
  • forms of the syllogism are met nowhere save in the manuals of Logic;
  • and an acquaintance with them is considered a piece of mere pedantry,
  • of no further use either in practical life or in science. It would
  • indeed be both useless and pedantic to parade the whole machinery of
  • the formal syllogism on every occasion. And yet the several forms of
  • syllogism make themselves constantly felt in our cognition. If any one,
  • when awaking on a winter morning, hears the creaking of the carriages
  • on the street, and is thus led to conclude that it has frozen hard in
  • the night, he has gone through a syllogistic operation:--an operation
  • which is every day repeated under the greatest variety of conditions.
  • The interest, therefore, ought at least not to be less in becoming
  • expressly conscious of this daily action of our thinking selves, than
  • confessedly belongs to the study of the functions of organic life, such
  • as the processes of digestion, assimilation, respiration, or even the
  • processes and structures of the nature around us. We do not, however,
  • for a moment deny that a study of Logic is no more necessary to teach
  • us how to draw correct conclusions, than a previous study of anatomy
  • and physiology is required in order to digest or breathe.
  • Aristotle was the first to observe and describe the different forms,
  • or, as they are called, figures of syllogism, in their subjective
  • meaning: and he performed his work so exactly and surely, that no
  • essential addition has ever been required. But while sensible of the
  • value of what he has thus done, we must not forget that the forms of
  • the syllogism of understanding, and of finite thought altogether,
  • are not what Aristotle has made use of in his properly philosophical
  • investigations. (See § 189.)
  • 184.] This syllogism is completely contingent (α) in the matter of its
  • terms. The Middle Term, being an abstract particularity, is nothing
  • but any quality whatever of the subject: but the subject, being
  • immediate and thus empirically concrete, has several others, and could
  • therefore be coupled with exactly as many other universalities as it
  • possesses single qualities. Similarly a single particularity may have
  • various characters in itself, so that the same _medius terminus_ would
  • serve to connect the subject with several different universals.
  • It is more a caprice of fashion, than a sense of its incorrectness,
  • which has led to the disuse of ceremonious syllogising. This and the
  • following section indicate the uselessness of such syllogising for the
  • ends of truth.
  • The point of view indicated in the paragraph shows how this style of
  • syllogism can 'demonstrate' (as the phrase goes) the most diverse
  • conclusions. All that is requisite is to find a _medius terminus_ from
  • which the transition can be made to the proposition sought. Another
  • _medius terminus_ would enable us to demonstrate something else, and
  • even the contrary of the last. And the more concrete an object is, the
  • more aspects it has, which may become such middle terms. To determine
  • which of these aspects is more essential than another, again, requires
  • a further syllogism of this kind, which fixing on the single quality
  • can with equal ease discover in it some aspect or consideration by
  • which it can make good its claims to be considered necessary and
  • important.
  • Little as we usually think on the Syllogism of Understanding in the
  • daily business of life, it never ceases to play its part there. In
  • a civil suit, for instance, it is the duty of the advocate to give
  • due force to the legal titles which make in favour of his client. In
  • logical language, such a legal title is nothing but a middle term.
  • Diplomatic transactions afford another illustration of the same, when,
  • for instance, different powers lay claim to one and the same territory.
  • In such a case the laws of inheritance, the geographical position of
  • the country, the descent and the language of its inhabitants, or any
  • other ground, may be emphasised as a _medius terminus._
  • 185.] (ß) This syllogism, if it is contingent in point of its terms,
  • is no less contingent in virtue of the form of relation which is
  • found in it. In the syllogism, according to its notion, truth lies in
  • connecting two distinct things by a Middle Term in which they are one.
  • But connexions of the extremes with the Middle Term (the so-called
  • _premisses,_ the major and the minor premiss) are in the case of this
  • syllogism much more decidedly _immediate_ connexions. In other words,
  • they have not a proper Middle Term.
  • This contradiction in the syllogism exhibits a new case of the infinite
  • progression. Each of the premisses evidently calls for a fresh
  • syllogism to demonstrate it: and as the new syllogism has two immediate
  • premisses, like its predecessor, the demand for proof is doubled at
  • every step, and repeated without end.
  • 186.] On account of its importance for experience, there has been
  • here noted a defect in the syllogism, to which in this form absolute
  • correctness had been ascribed. This defect however must lose itself in
  • the further specification of the syllogism. For we are now within the
  • sphere of the notion; and here therefore, as well as in the judgment,
  • the opposite character is not merely present potentially, but is
  • explicit. To work out the gradual specification of the syllogism,
  • therefore, there need only be admitted and accepted what is at each
  • step realised by the syllogism itself.
  • Through the immediate syllogism I--P--U, the Individual is mediated
  • (through a Particular) with the Universal, and in this conclusion put
  • as a universal. It follows that the individual subject, becoming itself
  • a universal, serves to unite the two extremes, and to form their ground
  • of intermediation. This gives the second figure of the syllogism, (2)
  • U--I--P. It expresses the truth of the first; it shows in other words
  • that the intermediation has taken place in the individual, and is thus
  • something contingent.
  • 187.] The universal, which in the first conclusion was specified
  • through individuality, passes over into the second figure and there
  • now occupies the place that belonged to the immediate subject. In the
  • second figure it is concluded with the particular. By this conclusion
  • therefore the universal is explicitly put as particular--and is now
  • made to mediate between the two extremes, the places of which are
  • occupied by the two others (the particular and the individual). This is
  • the third figure of the syllogism: (3) P--U--I.
  • What are called the Figures of the syllogism (being three in
  • number, for the fourth is a superfluous and even absurd addition of
  • the Moderns to the three known to Aristotle) are in the usual mode of
  • treatment put side by side, without the slightest thought of showing
  • their necessity, and still less of pointing out their import and value.
  • No wonder then that the figures have been in later times treated as an
  • empty piece of formalism. They have however a very real significance,
  • derived from the necessity for every function or characteristic
  • element of the notion to become the whole itself, and to stand as
  • mediating ground.--But to find out what 'moods' of the propositions
  • (such as whether they may be universals, or negatives) are needed
  • to enable us to draw a correct conclusion in the different figures,
  • is a mechanical inquiry, which its purely mechanical nature and its
  • intrinsic meaninglessness have very properly consigned to oblivion.
  • And Aristotle would have been the last person to give any countenance
  • to those who wish to attach importance to such inquiries or to the
  • syllogism of understanding in general. It is true that he described
  • these, as well as numerous other forms of mind and nature, and that
  • he examined and expounded their specialities. But in his metaphysical
  • theories, as well as his theories of nature and mind, he was very
  • far from taking as basis, or criterion, the syllogistic forms of the
  • 'understanding.' Indeed it might be maintained that not one of these
  • theories would ever have come into existence, or been allowed to exist,
  • if it had been compelled to submit to the laws of understanding. With
  • all the descriptiveness and analytic faculty which Aristotle after his
  • fashion is substantially strong in, his ruling principle is always the
  • speculative notion; and that syllogistic of 'understanding' to which he
  • first gave such a definite expression is never allowed to intrude in
  • the higher domain of philosophy.
  • * * * * *
  • In their objective sense, the three figures of the syllogism declare
  • that everything rational is manifested as a triple syllogism; that
  • is to say, each one of the members takes in turn the place of the
  • extremes, as well as of the mean which reconciles them. Such, for
  • example, is the case with the three branches of philosophy; the Logical
  • Idea, Nature, and Mind. As we first see them, Nature is the middle
  • term which links the others together. Nature, the totality immediately
  • before us, unfolds itself into the two extremes of the Logical Idea
  • and Mind. But Mind is Mind only when it is mediated through nature.
  • Then, in the second place, Mind, which we know as the principle of
  • individuality, or as the actualising principle, is the mean; and Nature
  • and the Logical Idea are the extremes. It is Mind which cognises the
  • Logical Idea in Nature and which thus raises Nature to its essence.
  • In the third place again the Logical Idea itself becomes the mean: it
  • is the absolute substance both of mind and of nature, the universal
  • and all-pervading principle. These are the members of the Absolute
  • Syllogism.
  • 188.] In the round by which each constituent function assumes
  • successively the place of mean and of the two extremes, their specific
  • difference from each other has been superseded. In this form, where
  • there is no distinction between its constituent elements, the syllogism
  • at first has for its connective link equality, or the external identity
  • of understanding. This is the Quantitative or Mathematical Syllogism:
  • if two things are equal to a third, they are equal to one another.
  • * * * * *
  • Everybody knows that this Quantitative syllogism appears as a
  • mathematical axiom, which like other axioms is said to be a principle
  • that does not admit of proof, and which indeed being self-evident does
  • not require such proof. These mathematical axioms however are really
  • nothing but logical propositions, which, so far as they enunciate
  • definite and particular thoughts, are deducible from the universal and
  • self-characterising thought. To deduce them, is to give their proof.
  • That is true of the Quantitative syllogism, to which mathematics
  • gives the rank of an axiom. It is really the proximate result of
  • the qualitative or immediate syllogism. Finally, the Quantitative
  • syllogism is the syllogism in utter formlessness. The difference
  • between the terms which is required by the notion is suspended.
  • Extraneous circumstances alone can decide what propositions are to be
  • premisses here: and therefore in applying this syllogism we make a
  • pre-supposition of what has been elsewhere proved and established.
  • 189.] Two results follow as to the form. In the first place, each
  • constituent element has taken the place and performed the function of
  • the mean and therefore of the whole, thus implicitly losing its partial
  • and abstract character (§ 182 and § 184); secondly, the mediation has
  • been completed (§ 185), though the completion too is only implicit,
  • that is, only as a circle of mediations which in turn pre-suppose each
  • other. In the first figure I--P--U the two premisses I is P and P is
  • U are yet without a mediation. The former premiss is mediated in the
  • third, the latter in the second figure. But each of these two figures,
  • again, for the mediation of its premisses pre-supposes the two others.
  • In consequence of this, the mediating unity of the notion must be put
  • no longer as an abstract particularity, but as a developed unity of the
  • individual and universal--and in the first place a reflected unity of
  • these elements. That is to say, the individuality gets at the same time
  • the character of universality. A mean of this kind gives the Syllogism
  • of Reflection.
  • (β) _Syllogism of Reflection._
  • 190.] If the mean, in the first place, be not only an abstract
  • particular character of the subject, but at the same time all the
  • individual concrete subjects which possess that character, but possess
  • it only along with others, (1) we have the Syllogism of Allness.
  • The major premiss, however, which has for its subject the particular
  • character, the _terminus medius,_ as allness, pre-supposes the very
  • conclusion which ought rather to have pre-supposed it. It rests
  • therefore (2) on an Induction, in which the mean is given by the
  • complete list of individuals as such,--a, b, c, d, &c. On account of
  • the disparity, however, between universality and an immediate and
  • empirical individuality, the list can never be complete. Induction
  • therefore rests upon (3) Analogy. The middle term of Analogy
  • is an individual, which however is understood as equivalent to its
  • essential universality, its genus, or essential character.--The first
  • syllogism for its intermediation turns us over to the second, and the
  • second turns us over to the third. But the third no less demands an
  • intrinsically determinate Universality, or an individuality as type of
  • the genus, after the round of the forms of external connexion between
  • individuality and universality has been run through in the figures of
  • the Reflective Syllogism.
  • By the Syllogism of Allness the defect in the first form of the
  • Syllogism of Understanding, noted in § 184, is remedied, but only to
  • give rise to a new defect. This defect is that the major premiss itself
  • pre-supposes what really ought to be the conclusion, and pre-supposes
  • it as what is thus an 'immediate' proposition. All men are mortal,
  • therefore Caius is mortal: All metals conduct electricity, therefore
  • _e.g._ copper does so. In order to enunciate these major premisses,
  • which when they say 'all' mean the 'immediate' individuals and are
  • properly intended to be empirical propositions, it is requisite that
  • the propositions about the individual man Caius, or the individual
  • metal copper, should previously have been ascertained to be correct.
  • Everybody feels not merely the pedantry, but the unmeaning formalism of
  • such syllogisms as: All men are mortal, Caius is a man, therefore Caius
  • is mortal.
  • The syllogism of Allness hands us over to the syllogism of Induction,
  • in which the individuals form the coupling mean. 'All metals conduct
  • electricity,' is an empirical proposition derived from experiments
  • made with each of the individual metals. We thus get the syllogism of
  • Induction I in the following shape P--I--U. I . . .
  • Gold is a metal: silver is a metal: so is copper, lead, &c. This is
  • the major premiss. Then comes the minor premiss: All these bodies
  • conduct electricity; and hence results the conclusion, that all metals
  • conduct electricity. The point which brings about a combination here
  • is individuality in the shape of allness. But this syllogism once
  • more hands us over to another syllogism. Its mean is constituted by
  • the complete list of the individuals. That pre-supposes that over
  • a certain region observation and experience are completed. But the
  • things in question here are individuals; and so again we are landed
  • in the progression _ad infinitum_ (i, i, i, &c.). In other words, in
  • no Induction can we ever exhaust the individuals. The 'all metals,'
  • 'all plants,' of our statements, mean only all the metals, all the
  • plants, which we have hitherto become acquainted with. Every Induction
  • is consequently imperfect. One and the other observation, many it may
  • be, have been made: but all the cases, all the individuals, have not
  • been observed. By this defect of Induction we are led on to Analogy.
  • In the syllogism of Analogy we conclude from the fact that some things
  • of a certain kind possess a certain quality, that the same quality is
  • possessed by other things of the same kind. It would be a syllogism of
  • Analogy, for example, if we said: In all planets hitherto discovered
  • this has been found to be the law of motion, consequently a newly
  • discovered planet will probably move according to the same law. In the
  • experiential sciences Analogy deservedly occupies a high place, and
  • has led to results of the highest importance. Analogy is the instinct
  • of reason, creating an anticipation that this or that characteristic,
  • which experience has discovered, has its root in the inner nature or
  • kind of an object, and arguing on the faith of that anticipation.
  • Analogy it should be added may be superficial or it may be thorough.
  • It would certainly be a very bad analogy to argue that since the man
  • Caius is a scholar, and Titus also is a man, Titus will probably be a
  • scholar too: and it would be bad because a man's learning is not an
  • unconditional consequence of his manhood. Superficial analogies of
  • this kind however are very frequently met with. It is often argued,
  • for example: The earth is a celestial body, so is the moon, and it
  • is therefore in all probability inhabited as well as the earth. The
  • analogy is not one whit better than that previously mentioned. That
  • the earth is inhabited does not depend on its being a celestial body,
  • but in other conditions, such as the presence of an atmosphere, and of
  • water in connexion with the atmosphere, &c.: and these are precisely
  • the conditions which the moon, so far as we know, does not possess.
  • What has in modern times been called the Philosophy of Nature consists
  • principally in a frivolous play with empty and external analogies,
  • which, however, claim to be considered profound results. The natural
  • consequence has been to discredit the philosophical study of nature.
  • (γ) _Syllogism of Necessity._
  • 191.] The Syllogism of Necessity, if we look to its purely abstract
  • characteristics or terms, has for its mean the Universal in the same
  • way as the Syllogism of Reflection has the Individual, the latter
  • being in the second, and the former in the third figure (§ 187).
  • The Universal is expressly put as in its very nature intrinsically
  • determinate. In the first place (1) the Particular, meaning by the
  • particular the specific genus or species, is the term for mediating
  • the extremes--as is done in the Categorical syllogism. (2) The
  • same office is performed by the Individual, taking the individual as
  • immediate being, so that it is as much mediating as mediated:--as
  • happens in the Hypothetical syllogism. (3) We have also the
  • mediating Universal explicitly put as a totality of its particular
  • members, and as a single particular, or exclusive individuality:--which
  • happens in the Disjunctive syllogism. It is one and the same
  • universal which is in these terms of the Disjunctive syllogism; they
  • are only different forms for expressing it.
  • 192.] The syllogism has been taken conformably to the distinctions
  • which it contains; and the general result of the course of their
  • evolution has been to show that these differences work out their own
  • abolition and destroy the notion's outwardness to its own self. And,
  • as we see, in the first place, (1) each of the dynamic elements has
  • proved itself the systematic whole of these elements, in short a whole
  • syllogism,--they are consequently implicitly identical. In the second
  • place, (2) the negation of their distinctions and of the mediation of
  • one through another constitutes independency; so that it is one and
  • the same universal which is in these forms, and which is in this way
  • also explicitly put as their identity. In this ideality of its dynamic
  • elements, the syllogistic process may be described as essentially
  • involving the negation of the characters through which its course runs,
  • as being a mediative process through the suspension of mediation,--as
  • coupling the subject not with another, but with a suspended other, in
  • one word, with itself.
  • * * * * *
  • In the common logic, the doctrine of syllogism is supposed to conclude
  • the first part, or what is called the 'elementary' theory. It is
  • followed by the second part, the doctrine of Method, which proposes
  • to show how a body of scientific knowledge is created by applying to
  • existing objects the forms of thought discussed in the elementary part.
  • Whence these objects originate, and what the thought of objectivity
  • generally speaking implies, are questions to which the Logic of
  • Understanding vouchsafes no further answer. It believes thought to
  • be a mere subjective and formal activity, and the objective fact,
  • which confronts thought, to have a separate and permanent being. But
  • this dualism is a half-truth: and there is a want of intelligence in
  • the procedure which at once accepts, without inquiring into their
  • origin, the categories of subjectivity and objectivity. Both of them,
  • subjectivity as well as objectivity, are certainly thoughts--even
  • specific thoughts: which must show themselves founded on the universal
  • and self-determining thought. This has here been done--at least for
  • subjectivity. We have recognised it, or the notion subjective (which
  • includes the notion proper, the judgment, and the syllogism) as the
  • dialectical result of the first two main stages of the Logical Idea,
  • Being and Essence. To say that the notion is subjective and subjective
  • only, is so far quite correct: for the notion certainly is subjectivity
  • itself. Not less subjective than the notion are also the judgment and
  • syllogism: and these forms, together with the so-called Laws of Thought
  • (the Laws of Identity, Difference, and Sufficient Ground), make up the
  • contents of what is called the 'Elements' in the common logic. But we
  • may go a step further. This subjectivity, with its functions of notion,
  • judgment, and syllogism, is not like a set of empty compartments which
  • has to get filled from without by separately-existing objects. It would
  • be truer to say that it is subjectivity itself which, as dialectical,
  • breaks through its own barriers and opens out into objectivity by means
  • of the syllogism.
  • 193.] This 'realisation' of the notion,--a realisation in which the
  • universal is this one totality withdrawn back into itself (of which
  • the different members are no less the whole, and) which has given
  • itself a character of 'immediate' unity by merging the mediation:--this
  • realisation of the notion is the Object.
  • I his transition from the Subject, the notion in general, and
  • especially the syllogism, to the Object, may, at the first glance,
  • appear strange, particularly if we look only at the Syllogism
  • of Understanding, and suppose syllogising to be only an act of
  • consciousness. But that strangeness imposes on us no obligation to seek
  • to make the transition plausible to the image-loving conception. The
  • only question which can be considered is, whether our usual conception
  • of what is called an 'object' approximately corresponds to the object
  • as here described. By 'object' is commonly understood not an abstract
  • being, or an existing thing merely, or any sort of actuality, but
  • something independent, concrete, and self-complete, this completeness
  • being the totality of the notion. That the object (_Objekt_) is also
  • an object to us (_Gegenstand_) and is external to something else,
  • will be more precisely seen, when it puts itself in contrast with
  • the subjective. At present, as that into which the notion has passed
  • from its mediation, it is only immediate object and nothing more,
  • just as the notion is not describable as subjective, previous to the
  • subsequent contrast with objectivity.
  • Further, the Object in general is the one total, in itself still
  • unspecified, the Objective World as a whole, God, the Absolute Object.
  • The object, however, has also difference attaching to it: it falls
  • into pieces, indefinite in their multiplicity (making an objective
  • world); and each of these individualised parts is also an object, an
  • intrinsically concrete, complete, and independent existence.
  • Objectivity has been compared with being, existence, and actuality;
  • and so too the transition to existence and actuality (not to being,
  • for _it_ is the primary and quite abstract immediate) maybe compared
  • with the transition to objectivity. The ground from which existence
  • proceeds, and the reflective correlation which is merged in actuality,
  • are nothing but the as yet imperfectly realised notion. They are only
  • abstract aspects of it,--the ground being its merely essence-bred
  • unity, and the correlation only the connexion of real sides which are
  • supposed to have only self-reflected being. The notion is the unity of
  • the two; and the object is not a merely essence-like, but inherently
  • universal unity, not only containing real distinctions, but containing
  • them as totalities in itself.
  • It is evident that in all these transitions there is a further purpose
  • than merely to show the indissoluble connexion between the notion or
  • thought and being. It has been more than once remarked that being is
  • nothing more than simple self-relation, and this meagre category is
  • certainly implied in the notion, or even in thought. But the meaning
  • of these transitions is not to accept characteristics or categories,
  • as only implied;--a fault which mars even the Ontological argument for
  • God's existence, when it is stated that being is one among realities.
  • What such a transition does, is to take the notion, as it ought to be
  • primarily characterised _per se_ as a notion, with which this remote
  • abstraction of being, or eve of objectivity, has as yet nothing to do,
  • and looking at its specific character as a notional character alone, to
  • see when and whether it passes over into a form which is different from
  • the character as it belongs to the notion and appears in it.
  • If the Object, the product of this transition, be brought into relation
  • with the notion, which, so far as its special form is concerned, has
  • vanished in it, we may give a correct expression to the result, by
  • saying that notion or, if it be preferred, subjectivity and object are
  • _implicitly_ the same. But it is equally correct to say that they are
  • different. In short, the two modes of expression are equally correct
  • and incorrect. The true state of the case can be presented in no
  • expressions of this kind. The 'implicit' is an abstraction, still more
  • partial and inadequate than the notion itself, of which the inadequacy
  • is upon the whole suspended, by suspending itself to the object with
  • its opposite inadequacy. Hence that implicitness also must, by its
  • negation, give itself the character of explicitness. As in every case,
  • speculative identity is not the above-mentioned triviality of an
  • _implicit_ identity of subject and object. This has been said often
  • enough. Yet it could not be too often repeated, if the intention were
  • really to put an end to the stale and purely malicious misconception in
  • regard to this identity:--of which however there can be no reasonable
  • expectation.
  • Looking at that unity in a quite general way, and raising no objection
  • to the one-sided form of its implicitness, we find it as the well-known
  • pre-supposition of the ontological proof for the existence of God.
  • There, it appears as supreme perfection. Anselm, in whom the notable
  • suggestion of this proof first occurs, no doubt originally restricted
  • himself to the question whether a certain content was in our thinking
  • only. His words are briefly these: '_Certe id quo majus cogitari
  • nequit, non potest esse in intellectu solo. Si enim vel in solo
  • intellectu est, potest cogitari esse_ et in re: _quod majus est.
  • Si ergo id quo majus cogitari non potest, est in solo intellectu; id
  • ipsum quo majus cogitari non potest, est quo majus cogitari potest.
  • Sed certe hoc esse non potest._' (Certainly that, than which nothing
  • greater can be thought, cannot be in the intellect alone. For even
  • if it is in the intellect alone, it can also be thought to exist in
  • fact: and that is greater. If then that, than which nothing greater
  • can be thought, is in the intellect alone; then the very thing, which
  • is greater than anything which can be thought, can be exceeded in
  • thought. But certainly this is impossible.) The same unity received
  • a more objective expression in Descartes, Spinoza and others: while
  • the theory of immediate certitude or faith presents it, on the
  • contrary, in somewhat the same subjective aspect as Anselm. These
  • Intuitionalists hold that _in our consciousness_ the attribute of being
  • is indissolubly associated with the conception of God. The theory of
  • faith brings even the conception of external finite things under the
  • same inseparable nexus between the consciousness and the being of
  • them, on the ground that _perception_ presents them conjoined with the
  • attribute of existence: and in so saying, it is no doubt correct. It
  • would be utterly absurd, however, to suppose that the association in
  • consciousness between existence and our conception of finite things
  • is of the same description as the association between existence and
  • the conception of God. To do so would be to forget that finite things
  • are changeable and transient, _i.e._ that existence is associated
  • with them for a season, but that the association is neither eternal
  • nor inseparable. Speaking in the phraseology of the categories before
  • us, we may say that, to call a thing finite, means that its objective
  • existence is not in harmony with the thought of it, with its universal
  • calling, its kind and its end. Anselm, consequently, neglecting any
  • such conjunction as occurs in finite things, has with good reason
  • pronounced that only to be the Perfect which exists not merely in a
  • subjective, but also in an objective mode. It does no good to put
  • on airs against the Ontological proof, as it is called, and against
  • Anselm thus denning the Perfect. The argument is one latent in every
  • unsophisticated mind, and it recurs in every philosophy, even against
  • its wish and without its knowledge--as may be seen in the theory of
  • immediate belief.
  • The real fault in the argumentation of Anselm is one which is
  • chargeable on Descartes and Spinoza, as well as on the theory of
  • immediate knowledge. It is this. This unity which is enunciated as the
  • supreme perfection or, it may be, subjectively, as the true knowledge,
  • is pre-supposed, _i.e._ it is assumed only as potential. This identity,
  • abstract as it thus appears, between the two categories may be at
  • once met and opposed by their diversity; and this was the very answer
  • given to Anselm long ago. In short, the conception and existence of
  • the finite is set in antagonism to the infinite; for, as previously
  • remarked, the finite possesses objectivity of such a kind as is at
  • once incongruous with and different from the end or aim, its essence
  • and notion. Or, the finite is such a conception and in such a way
  • subjective, that it does not involve existence. This objection and this
  • antithesis are got over, only by showing the finite to be untrue and
  • these categories in their separation to be inadequate and null. Their
  • identity is thus seen to be one into which they spontaneously pass
  • over, and in which they are reconciled.
  • B.--THE OBJECT.
  • 194.] The Object is immediate being, because insensible to difference,
  • which in it has suspended itself. It is, further, a totality in itself,
  • whilst at the same time (as this identity is only the _implicit_
  • identity of its dynamic elements) it is equally indifferent to its
  • immediate unity. It thus breaks up into distinct parts, each of which
  • is itself the totality. Hence the object is the absolute contradiction
  • between a complete independence of the multiplicity, and the equally
  • complete non-independence of the different pieces.
  • The definition, which states that the Absolute is the Object, is most
  • definitely implied in the Leibnizian Monad. The Monads are each an
  • object, but an object implicitly 'representative,' indeed the total
  • representation of the world. In the simple unity of the Monad, all
  • difference is merely ideal, not independent or real. Nothing from
  • without comes into the monad: It is the whole notion in itself, only
  • distinguished by its own greater or less development. None the less,
  • this simple totality parts into the absolute multeity of differences,
  • each becoming an independent monad. In the monad of monads, and the
  • Pre-established Harmony of their inward developments, these substances
  • are in like manner again reduced to 'ideality' and unsubstantiality.
  • The philosophy of Leibnitz, therefore, represents contradiction in its
  • complete development.
  • * * * * *
  • As Fichte in modern times has especially and with justice insisted,
  • the theory which regards the Absolute or God as the Object and there
  • stops, expresses the point of view taken by superstition and slavish
  • fear. No doubt God is the Object, and, indeed, the Object out and
  • out, confronted with which our particular or subjective opinions and
  • desires have no truth and no validity. As absolute object however, God
  • does not therefore take up the position of a dark and hostile power
  • over against subjectivity. He rather involves it as a vital element in
  • Himself. Such also is the meaning of the Christian doctrine, according
  • to which God has willed that all men should be saved and all attain
  • blessedness. The salvation and the blessedness of men are attained when
  • they come to feel themselves at one with God, so that God, on the other
  • hand, ceases to be for them mere object, and, in that way, an object
  • of fear and terror, as was especially the case with the religious
  • consciousness of the Romans. But God in the Christian religion is
  • also known as Love, because in His Son, who is one with Him, He has
  • revealed Himself to men as a man amongst men, and thereby redeemed
  • them. All which is only another way of saying that the antithesis of
  • subjective and objective is implicitly overcome, and that it is our
  • affair to participate in this redemption by laying aside our immediate
  • subjectivity (putting off the old Adam), and learning to know God as
  • our true and essential self.
  • Just as religion and religious worship consist in overcoming the
  • antithesis of subjectivity and objectivity, so science too and
  • philosophy have no other task than to overcome this antithesis by the
  • medium of thought. The aim of knowledge is to divest the objective
  • world that stands opposed to us of its strangeness, and, as the phrase
  • is, to find ourselves at home in it: which means no more than to trace
  • the objective world back to the notion,--to our innermost self. We
  • may learn from the present discussion the mistake of regarding the
  • antithesis of subjectivity and objectivity as an abstract and permanent
  • one. The two are wholly dialectical. The notion is at first only
  • subjective: but without the assistance of any foreign material or stuff
  • it proceeds, in obedience to its own action, to objectify itself. So,
  • too, the object is not rigid and processless. Its process is to show
  • itself as what is at the same time subjective, and thus form the step
  • onwards to the idea. Any one who, from want of familiarity with the
  • categories of subjectivity and objectivity, seeks to retain them in
  • their abstraction, will find that the isolated categories slip through
  • his fingers before he is aware, and that he says the exact contrary of
  • what he wanted to say.
  • (2) Objectivity contains the three forms of Mechanism, Chemism,
  • and Teleology. The object of mechanical type is the immediate and
  • undifferentiated object. No doubt it contains difference, but the
  • different pieces stand, as it were, without affinity to each other,
  • and their connexion is only extraneous. In chemism, on the contrary,
  • the object exhibits an essential tendency to differentiation, in such
  • a way that the objects are what they are only by their relation to
  • each other: this tendency to difference constitutes their quality.
  • The third type of objectivity, the teleological relation, is the
  • unity of mechanism and chemism. Design, like the mechanical object,
  • is a self-contained totality, enriched however by the principle of
  • differentiation which came to the fore in chemism, and thus referring
  • itself to the object that stands over against it. Finally, it is the
  • realisation of design which forms the transition to the Idea.
  • (a) _Mechanism._
  • 196.] The object (1) in its immediacy is the notion only potentially;
  • the notion as subjective is primarily outside it; and all its
  • specific character is imposed from without. As a unity of differents,
  • therefore, it is a composite, an aggregate; and its capacity of
  • acting on anything else continues to be an external relation. This is
  • Formal Mechanism.--Notwithstanding, and in this connexion and
  • non-independence, the objects remain independent and offer resistance,
  • external to each other.
  • Pressure and impact are examples of mechanical relations. Our knowledge
  • is said to be mechanical or by rote, when the words have no meaning
  • for us, but continue external to sense, conception, thought; and
  • when, being similarly external to each other, they form a meaningless
  • sequence. Conduct, piety, &c. are in the same way mechanical, when a
  • man's behaviour is settled for him by ceremonial laws, by a spiritual
  • adviser, &c.; in short, when his own mind and will are not in his
  • actions, which in this way are extraneous to himself.
  • * * * * *
  • Mechanism, the first form of objectivity, is also the category which
  • primarily offers itself to reflection, as it examines the objective
  • world. It is also the category beyond which reflection seldom goes.
  • It is, however, a shallow and superficial mode of observation, one
  • that cannot carry us through in connexion with Nature and still less
  • in connexion with the world of Mind. In Nature it is only the veriest
  • abstract relations of matter in its inert masses which obey the law of
  • mechanism. On the contrary the phenomena and operations of the province
  • to which the term 'physical' in its narrower sense is applied, such as
  • the phenomena of light, heat, magnetism, and electricity, cannot be
  • explained by any mere mechanical processes, such as pressure, impact,
  • displacement of parts, and the like. Still less satisfactory is it
  • to transfer these categories and apply them in the field of organic
  • nature; at least if it be our aim to understand the specific features
  • of that field, such as the growth and nourishment of plants, or, it
  • may be, even animal sensation. It is at any rate a very deep-seated,
  • and perhaps the main, defect of modern researches into nature, that,
  • even where other and higher categories than those of mere mechanism
  • are in operation, they still stick obstinately to the mechanical laws;
  • although they thus conflict with the testimony of unbiassed perception,
  • and foreclose the gate to an-adequate knowledge of nature. But even
  • in considering the formations in the world of Mind, the mechanical
  • theory has been repeatedly invested with an authority which it has no
  • right to. Take as an instance the remark that man consists of soul and
  • body. In this language, the two things stand each self-subsistent, and
  • associated only from without. Similarly we find the soul regarded as a
  • mere group of forces and faculties, subsisting independently side by
  • side.
  • Thus decidedly must we reject the mechanical mode of inquiry when it
  • comes forward and arrogates to itself the place of rational cognition
  • in general, and seeks to get mechanism accepted as an absolute
  • category. But we must not on that account forget expressly to vindicate
  • for mechanism the right and import of a general logical category. It
  • would be, therefore, a mistake to restrict it to the special physical
  • department from which it derives its name. There is no harm done, for
  • example, in directing attention to mechanical actions, such as that
  • of gravity, the lever, &c, even in departments, notably in physics
  • and in physiology, beyond the range of mechanics proper. It must
  • however be remembered, that within these spheres the laws of mechanism
  • cease to be final or decisive, and sink, as it were, to a subservient
  • position. To which may be added, that, in Nature, when the higher
  • or organic functions are in any way checked or disturbed in their
  • normal efficiency, the otherwise subordinate category of mechanism
  • is immediately seen to take the upper hand. Thus a sufferer from
  • indigestion feels pressure on the stomach, after partaking of certain
  • food in slight quantity; whereas those whose digestive organs are sound
  • remain free from the sensation, although they have eaten as much. The
  • same phenomenon occurs in the general feeling of heaviness in the
  • limbs, experienced in bodily indisposition. Even in the world of Mind,
  • mechanism has its place; though there, too, it is a subordinate one. We
  • are right in speaking of mechanical memory, and all sorts of mechanical
  • operations, such as reading, writing, playing on musical instruments,
  • &c. In memory, indeed, the mechanical quality of the action is
  • essential: a circumstance, the neglect of which has not unfrequently
  • caused great harm in the training of the young, from the misapplied
  • zeal of modern educationalists for the freedom of intelligence. It
  • would betray bad psychology, however, to have recourse to mechanism for
  • an explanation of the nature of memory, and to apply mechanical laws
  • straight off to the soul. The mechanical feature in memory lies merely
  • in the fact that certain signs, tones, &c. are apprehended in their
  • purely external association, and then reproduced in this association,
  • without attention being expressly directed to their meaning and inward
  • association. To become acquainted with these conditions of mechanical
  • memory requires no further study of mechanics, nor would that study
  • tend at all to advance the special inquiry of psychology.
  • 196.] The want of stability in itself which allows the object to suffer
  • violence, is possessed by it (see preceding §) only in so far as it
  • has a certain stability. Now as the object is implicitly invested
  • with the character of notion, the one of these characteristics is not
  • merged into its other; but the object, through the negation of itself
  • (its lack of independence), closes with itself, and not till it so
  • closes, is it independent. Thus at the same time in distinction from
  • the outwardness, and negativing that outwardness in its independence,
  • does this independence form a negative unity with self,--Centrality
  • (subjectivity). So conceived, the object itself has direction and
  • reference towards the external. But this external object is similarly
  • central in itself, and being so, is no less only referred towards the
  • other centre; so that it no less has its centrality in the other. This
  • is (2) Mechanism with Affinity (with bias, or 'difference'), and
  • may be illustrated by gravitation, appetite, social instinct, &c.
  • 197.] This relationship, when fully carried out, forms a syllogism. In
  • that syllogism the immanent negativity, as the central individuality
  • of an object, (abstract centre,) relates itself to non-independent
  • objects, as the other extreme, by a mean which unites the centrality
  • with the non-independence of the objects, (relative centre.) This is
  • (3) Absolute Mechanism.
  • 198.] The syllogism thus indicated (I--P--U) is a triad of syllogisms.
  • The wrong individuality of non-independent objects, in which formal
  • Mechanism is at home, is, by reason of that non-independence, no
  • less universality, though it be only external. Hence these objects
  • also form the mean between the absolute and the relative centre
  • (the form of syllogism being U--I--P): for it is by this want of
  • independence that those two are kept asunder and made extremes, as
  • well as related to one another. Similarly absolute centrality, as the
  • permanently-underlying universal substance (illustrated by the gravity
  • which continues identical), which as pure negativity equally includes
  • individuality in it, is what mediates between the relative centre and
  • the non-independent objects (the form of syllogism being P--U--I). It
  • does so no less essentially as a disintegrating force, in its character
  • of immanent individuality, than in virtue of universality, acting as an
  • identical bond of union and tranquil self-containedness.
  • Like the solar system, so for example in the practical sphere the state
  • is a system of three syllogisms. (1) The Individual or person, through
  • his particularity or physical or mental needs (which when carried
  • out to their full development give _civil_ society), is coupled with
  • the universal, _i.e._ with society, law, right, government. (2) The
  • will or action of the individuals is the intermediating force which
  • procures for these needs satisfaction in society, in law, &c, and
  • which gives to society, law, &c. their fulfilment and actualisation.
  • (3) But the universal, that is to say the state, government, and law,
  • is the permanent underlying mean in which the individuals and their
  • satisfaction have and receive their fulfilled reality, inter-mediation,
  • and persistence. Each of the functions of the notion, as it is brought
  • by intermediation to coalesce with the other extreme, is brought
  • into union with itself and produces itself: which production is
  • self-preservation.--It is only by the nature of this triple coupling,
  • by this triad of syllogisms with the name _termini,_ that a whole is
  • thoroughly understood in its organisation.
  • 199.] The immediacy of existence, which the objects have in Absolute
  • Mechanism, is implicitly negatived by the fact that their independence
  • is derived from, and due to, their connexions with each other, and
  • therefore to their own want of stability. Thus the object must be
  • explicitly stated as in its existence having an Affinity (or a
  • bias) towards its other,--as not-indifferent.
  • (b) _Chemism_.
  • 200.] The not-indifferent (biassed) object has an immanent mode which
  • constitutes its nature, and in which it has existence. But as it is
  • invested with the character of total notion, it is the contradiction
  • between this totality and the special mode of its existence.
  • Consequently it is the constant endeavour to cancel this contradiction
  • and to make its definite being equal to the notion.
  • * * * * *
  • Chemism is a category of objectivity which, as a rule, is not
  • particularly emphasised, and is generally put under the head of
  • mechanism. The common name of mechanical relationship is applied to
  • both, in contra-distinction to the teleological. There is a reason for
  • this in the common feature which belongs to mechanism and chemism. In
  • them the notion exists, but only implicit and latent, and they are thus
  • both marked off from teleology where the notion has real independent
  • existence. This is true: and yet chemism and mechanism are very
  • decidedly distinct. The object, in the form of mechanism, is primarily
  • only an indifferent reference to self, while the chemical object is
  • seen to be completely in reference to something else. No doubt even
  • in mechanism, as it develops itself, there spring up references to
  • something else: but the nexus of mechanical objects with one another is
  • at first only an external nexus, so that the objects in connexion with
  • one another still retain the semblance of independence. In nature, for
  • example; the several celestial bodies, which form our solar system,
  • compose a kinetic system, and thereby show that they are related to
  • one another. Motion, however, as the unity of time and space, is a
  • connexion which is purely abstract and external. And it seems therefore
  • as if these celestial bodies, which are thus externally connected with
  • each other, would continue to be what they are, even apart from this
  • reciprocal relation. The case is quite different with chemism. Objects
  • chemically biassed are what they are expressly by that bias alone.
  • Hence they are the absolute impulse towards integration by and in one
  • another.
  • 201.] The product of the chemical process consequently is the Neutral
  • object, latent in the two extremes, each on the alert. The notion
  • or concrete universal, by means of the bias of the objects (the
  • particularity), coalesces with the individuality (in the shape of the
  • product), and in that only with itself. In this process too the other
  • syllogisms are equally involved. The place of mean is taken both by
  • individuality as activity, and by the concrete universal, the essence
  • of the strained extremes; which essence reaches definite being in the
  • product.
  • 202.] Chemism, as it is a reflectional nexus of objectivity, has
  • pre-supposed, not merely the bias or non-indifferent nature of the
  • objects, but also their immediate independence. The process of chemism
  • consists in passing to and fro from one form to another; which forms
  • continue to be as external as before.--In the neutral product the
  • specific properties, which the extremes bore towards each other, are
  • merged. But although the product is conformable to the notion, the
  • inspiring principle of active differentiation does not exist in it; for
  • it has sunk back to immediacy. The neutral body is therefore capable
  • of disintegration. But the discerning principle, which breaks up the
  • neutral body into biassed and strained extremes, and which gives to
  • the indifferent object in general its affinity and animation towards
  • another;--that principle, and the process as a separation with tension,
  • falls outside of that first process.
  • * * * * *
  • The chemical process does not rise above a conditioned and finite
  • process. The notion as notion is only the heart and core of the
  • process, and does not in this stage come to an existence of its own.
  • In the neutral product the process is extinct, and the existing cause
  • falls outside it.
  • 203.] Each of these two processes, the reduction of the biassed
  • (not-indifferent) to the neutral, and the differentiation of the
  • indifferent or neutral, goes its own way without hindrance from the
  • other. But that want of inner connexion shows that they are finite,
  • by their passage into products in which they are merged and lost.
  • Conversely the process exhibits the nonentity of the pre-supposed
  • immediacy of the not-indifferent objects.--By this negation of
  • immediacy and of externalism in which the notion as object was sunk,
  • it is liberated and invested with independent being in face of that
  • externalism and immediacy. In these circumstances it is the End (Final
  • Cause).
  • * * * * *
  • The passage from chemism to the teleological relation is implied in the
  • mutual cancelling of both of the forms of the chemical process. The
  • result thus attained is the liberation of the notion, which in chemism
  • and mechanism was present only in the germ, and not yet evolved. The
  • notion in the shape of the aim or end thus comes into independent
  • existence.
  • (c) _Teleology._
  • 204.] In the End the notion has entered on free existence
  • and has a being of its own, by means of the negation of immediate
  • objectivity. It is characterised as subjective, seeing that this
  • negation is, in the first place, abstract, and hence at first the
  • relation between it and objectivity still one of contrast. This
  • character of subjectivity, however, compared with the totality of the
  • notion, is one-sided, and that, be it added, for the End itself, in
  • which all specific characters have been put as subordinated and merged.
  • For it therefore even the object, which it pre-supposes, has only
  • hypothetical (ideal) reality,--essentially no-reality. The End in short
  • is a contradiction of its self-identity against the negation stated in
  • it, _i.e._ its antithesis to objectivity, and being so, contains the
  • eliminative or destructive activity which negates the antithesis and
  • renders it identical with itself. This is the realisation of the End:
  • in which, while it turns itself into the other of its subjectivity and
  • objectifies itself, thus cancelling the distinction between the two, it
  • has only closed with itself, and retained itself.
  • The notion of Design or End, while on one hand called redundant, is on
  • another justly described as the rational notion, and contrasted with
  • the abstract universal of understanding. The latter only _subsumes_
  • the particular, and so connects it with itself: but has it not in its
  • own nature.--The distinction between the End or _final cause,_ and the
  • mere _efficient cause_ (which is the cause ordinarily so called), is of
  • supreme importance. Causes, properly so called, belong to the sphere of
  • necessity, blind, and not yet laid bare. The cause therefore appears
  • as passing into its correlative, and losing its primordiality there by
  • sinking into dependency. It is only by implication, or for us, that
  • the cause is in the effect made for the first time a cause, and that
  • it there returns into itself. The End, on the other hand, is expressly
  • stated as containing the specific character in its own self,--the
  • effect, namely, which in the purely causal relation is never free from
  • otherness. The End therefore in its efficiency does not pass over, but
  • retains itself, _i.e._ it carries into effect itself only, and is at
  • the end what it was in the beginning or primordial state. Until it thus
  • retains itself, it is not genuinely primordial.--The End then requires
  • to be speculatively apprehended as the notion, which itself in the
  • proper unity and ideality of its characteristics contains the judgment
  • or negation,--the antithesis of subjective and objective,--and which to
  • an equal extent suspends that antithesis.
  • By End however we must not at once, nor must we ever merely, think
  • of the form which it has in consciousness as a mode of mere mental
  • representation. By means of the notion of Inner Design Kant has
  • resuscitated the Idea in general and particularly the idea of life.
  • Aristotle's definition of life virtually implies inner design, and is
  • thus far in advance of the notion of design in modern Teleology, which
  • had in view finite and outward design only.
  • Animal wants and appetites are some of the readiest instances of
  • the End. They are the _felt_ contradiction, which exists _within_
  • the living subject, and pass into the activity of negating this
  • negation which mere subjectivity still is. The satisfaction of the
  • want or appetite restores the peace between subject and object. The
  • objective thing which, so long as the contradiction exists, _i.e._
  • so long as the want is felt, stands on the other side, loses this
  • quasi-independence, by its union with the subject. Those who talk of
  • the permanence and immutability of the finite, as well subjective as
  • objective, may see the reverse illustrated in the operations of every
  • appetite. Appetite is, so to speak, the conviction that the subjective
  • is only a half-truth, no more adequate than the objective. But appetite
  • in the second place carries out its conviction. It brings about the
  • supersession of these finites: it cancels the antithesis between the
  • objective which would be and stay an objective only, and the subjective
  • which in like manner would be and stay a subjective only.
  • As regards the action of the End, attention may be called to the fact,
  • that in the syllogism, which represents that action, and shows the end
  • closing with itself by the means of realisation, the radical feature is
  • the negation of the _termini._ That negation is the one just mentioned
  • both of the immediate subjectivity appearing in the End as such, and
  • of the immediate objectivity as seen in the means and the objects
  • pre-supposed. This is the same negation, as is in operation when the
  • mind leaves the contingent things of the world as well as its own
  • subjectivity and rises to God. It is the 'moment' or factor which (as
  • noticed in the Introduction and § 192) was overlooked and neglected in
  • the analytic form of syllogisms, under which the so-called proofs of
  • the Being of a God presented this elevation.
  • 205.] In its primary and immediate aspect the Teleological relation
  • is _external_ design, and the notion confronts a pre-supposed object.
  • The End is consequently finite, and that partly in its content,
  • partly in the circumstance that it has an external condition in the
  • object, which has to be found existing, and which is taken as material
  • for its realisation. Its self-determining is to that extent in form
  • only. The un-mediatedness of the End has the further result that
  • its particularity or content--which as form-characteristic is the
  • subjectivity of the End--is reflected into self, and so different from
  • the totality of the form, subjectivity in general, the notion. This
  • variety constitutes the finitude of Design within its own nature. The
  • content of the End. in this way, is quite as limited, contingent, and
  • given, as the object is particular and found ready to hand.
  • * * * * *
  • Generally speaking, the final cause is taken to mean nothing more
  • than external design. In accordance with this view of it, things are
  • supposed not to carry their vocation in themselves, but merely to be
  • means employed and spent in realising a purpose which lies outside
  • of them. That may be said to be the point of view taken by Utility,
  • which once played a great part even in the sciences, but of late has
  • fallen into merited disrepute, now that people have begun to see that
  • it failed to give a genuine insight into the nature of things. It is
  • true that finite things as finite ought in justice to be viewed as
  • non-ultimate, and as pointing beyond themselves. This negativity of
  • finite things however is their own dialectic, and in order to ascertain
  • it we must pay attention to their positive content.
  • Teleological observations on things often proceed from a well-meant
  • wish to display the wisdom of God as it is especially revealed in
  • nature. Now in thus trying to discover final causes for which the
  • things serve as means, we must remember that we are stopping short
  • at the finite, and are liable to fall into trifling reflections: as,
  • for instance, if we not merely studied the vine in respect of its
  • well-known use for man, but proceeded to consider the cork-tree in
  • connexion with the corks which are cut from its bark to put into the
  • wine-bottles. Whole books used to be written in this spirit. It is easy
  • to see that they promoted the genuine interest neither of religion nor
  • of science. External design stands immediately in front of the idea:
  • but what thus stands on the threshold often for that reason is least
  • adequate.
  • 206.] The teleological relation is a syllogism in which the subjective
  • end coalesces with the objectivity external to it, through a middle
  • term which is the unity of both. This unity is on one hand the
  • _purposive_ action, on the other the _Means, i.e._ objectivity made
  • directly subservient to purpose.
  • * * * * *
  • The development from End to Idea ensues by three stages, first,
  • Subjective End; second, End in process of accomplishment; and third,
  • End accomplished. First of all we have the Subjective End; and that,
  • as the notion in independent being, is itself the totality of the
  • elementary functions of the notion. The first of these functions
  • is that of self-identical universality, as it were the neutral
  • first water, in which everything is involved, but nothing as yet
  • discriminated. The second of these elements is the particularising
  • of this universal, by which it acquires a specific content. As this
  • specific content again is realised by the agency of the universal, the
  • latter returns by its means back to itself, and coalesces with itself.
  • Hence too when we set some end before us, we say that we 'conclude' to
  • do something: a phrase which implies that we were, so to speak, open
  • and accessible to this or that determination. Similarly we also at a
  • further step speak of a man 'resolving' to do something, meaning that
  • the agent steps forward out of his self-regarding inwardness and enters
  • into dealings with the environing objectivity. This supplies the step
  • from the merely Subjective End to the purposive action which tends
  • outwards.
  • 207.] (1) The first syllogism of the final cause represents the
  • Subjective End. The universal notion is brought to unite with
  • individuality by means of particularity, so that the individual
  • as self-determination acts as judge. That is to say, it not only
  • particularises or makes into a determinate content the still
  • indeterminate universal, but also explicitly puts an antithesis of
  • subjectivity and objectivity, and at the same time is in its own self
  • a return to itself; for it stamps the subjectivity of the notion,
  • pre-supposed as against objectivity, with the mark of defect, in
  • comparison with the complete and rounded totality, and thereby at the
  • same time turns outwards.
  • 208.] (2) This action which is directed outwards is the individuality,
  • which in the Subjective End is identical with the particularity
  • under which, along with the content, is also comprised the external
  • objectivity. It throws itself in the first place immediately upon the
  • object, which it appropriates to itself as a Means. The notion is this
  • immediate power; for the notion is the self-identical negativity, in
  • which the being of the object is characterised as wholly and merely
  • ideal.--The whole Means then is this inward power of the notion, in the
  • shape of an agency, with which the object as Means is 'immediately'
  • united and in obedience to which it stands.
  • In finite teleology the Means is thus broken up into two elements
  • external to each other, (a) the action and (b) the object which serves
  • as Means. The relation of the final cause as power to this object, and
  • the subjugation of the object to it, is immediate (it forms the first
  • premiss in the syllogism) to this extent, that in the teleological
  • notion as the self-existent ideality the object is put as potentially
  • null. This relation, as represented in the first premiss, itself
  • becomes the Means, which at the same time involves the syllogism, that
  • through this relation--in which the action of the End is contained and
  • dominant--the End is coupled with objectivity.
  • * * * * *
  • The execution of the End is the mediated mode of realising the End; but
  • the immediate realisation is not less needful. The End lays hold of the
  • object immediately, because it is the power over the object, because
  • in the End particularity, and in particularity objectivity also, is
  • involved.--A living being has a body; the soul takes possession of it
  • and without intermediary has objectified itself in it. The human soul
  • has much to do, before it makes its corporeal nature into a means. Man
  • must, as it were, take possession of his body, so that it may be the
  • instrument of his soul.
  • 209.] (3) Purposive action, with its Means, is still directed outwards,
  • because the End is also _not_ identical with the object, and must
  • consequently first be mediated with it. The Means in its capacity of
  • object stands, in this second premiss, in direct relation to the other
  • extreme of the syllogism, namely, the material or objectivity which is
  • pre-supposed. This relation is the sphere of chemism and mechanism,
  • which have now become the servants of the Final Cause, where lies their
  • truth and free notion. Thus the Subjective End, which is the power
  • ruling these processes, in which the objective things wear themselves
  • out on one another, contrives to keep itself free from them, and to
  • preserve itself in them. Doing so, it appears as the Cunning of reason.
  • * * * * *
  • Reason is as cunning as it is powerful. Cunning may be said to lie
  • in the inter-mediative action which, while it permits the objects to
  • follow their own bent and act upon one another till they waste away,
  • and does not itself directly interfere in the process, is nevertheless
  • only working out its own aims. With this explanation, Divine Providence
  • may be said to stand to the world and its process in the capacity of
  • absolute cunning. God lets men do as they please with their particular
  • passions and interests; but the result is the accomplishment of--not
  • their plans, but His, and these differ decidedly from the ends
  • primarily sought by those whom He employs.
  • 210.] The realised End is thus the overt unity of subjective and
  • objective. It is however essentially characteristic of this unity, that
  • the subjective and objective are neutralised and cancelled only in the
  • point of their one-sidedness, while the objective is subdued and made
  • conformable to the End, as the free notion, and thereby to the power
  • above it. The End maintains itself against and in the objective
  • for it is no mere one-sided subjective or particular, it is also the
  • concrete universal, the implicit identity of both. This universal, as
  • simply reflected in itself, is the content which remains unchanged
  • through all the three _termini_ of the syllogism and their movement.
  • 211.] In finite design, however, even the executed End has the same
  • radical rift or flaw as had the Means and the initial End. We have
  • got therefore only a form extraneously impressed on a pre-existing
  • material: and this form, by reason of the limited content of the End,
  • is also a contingent characteristic. The End achieved consequently is
  • only an object, which again becomes a Means or material for other Ends,
  • and so on for ever.
  • 212.] But what virtually happens in the realising of the End is that
  • the one-sided subjectivity and the show of objective independence
  • confronting it are both cancelled. In laying hold of the means, the
  • notion constitutes itself the very implicit essence of the object. In
  • the mechanical and chemical processes the independence of the object
  • has been already dissipated implicitly, and in the course of their
  • movement under the dominion of the End, the show of that independence,
  • the negative which confronts the notion, is got rid of. But in the fact
  • that the End achieved is characterised only as a Means and a material,
  • this object, viz. the teleological, is there and then put as implicitly
  • null, and only 'ideal.' This being so, the antithesis between form
  • and content has also vanished. While the End by the removal and
  • absorption of all form-characteristics coalesces with itself, the form
  • as self-identical is thereby put as the content, so that the notion,
  • which is the action of form, has only itself for content. Through this
  • process, therefore, there is made explicitly manifest what was the
  • notion of design: viz. the implicit unity of subjective and objective
  • is now realised. And this is the Idea.
  • * * * * *
  • This finitude of the End consists in the circumstance, that, in the
  • process of realising it, the material, which is employed as a means,
  • is only externally subsumed under it and made conformable to it. But,
  • as a matter of fact, the object is the notion implicitly: and thus
  • when the notion, in the shape of End, is realised in the object, we
  • have but the manifestation of the inner nature of the object itself.
  • Objectivity is thus, as it were, only a covering under which the notion
  • lies concealed. Within the range of the finite we can never see or
  • experience that the End has been really secured. The consummation of
  • the infinite End, therefore, consists merely in removing the illusion
  • which makes it seem yet unaccomplished. The Good, the absolutely Good,
  • is eternally accomplishing itself in the world: and the result is that
  • it needs not wait upon us, but is already by implication, as well as in
  • full actuality, accomplished. This is the illusion under which we live.
  • It alone supplies at the same time the actualising force on which the
  • interest in the world reposes. In the course of its process the Idea
  • creates that illusion, by setting an antithesis to confront it; and its
  • action consists in getting rid of the illusion which it has created.
  • Only out of this error does the truth arise. In this fact lies the
  • reconciliation with error and with finitude. Error or other-being, when
  • superseded, is still a necessary dynamic element of truth: for truth
  • can only be where it makes itself its own result.
  • C.--THE IDEA.
  • 213.] The Idea is truth in itself and for itself,--the absolute
  • unity of the notion and objectivity. Its 'ideal' content is nothing
  • but the notion in its detailed terms: its 'real' content is only the
  • exhibition which the notion gives itself in the form of external
  • existence, whilst yet, by enclosing this shape in its ideality, it
  • keeps it in its power, and so keeps itself in it.
  • The definition, which declares the Absolute to be the Idea, is itself
  • absolute. All former definitions come back to this. The Idea is
  • the Truth: for Truth is the correspondence of objectivity with the
  • notion:--not of course the correspondence of external things with my
  • conceptions,--for these are only _correct_ conceptions held by _me,_
  • the individual person. In the idea we have nothing to do with the
  • individual, nor with figurate conceptions, nor with external things.
  • And yet, again, everything actual, in so far as it is true, is the
  • Idea, and has its truth by and in virtue of the Idea alone. Every
  • individual being is some one aspect of the Idea: for which, therefore,
  • yet other actualities are needed, which in their turn appear to have
  • a self-subsistence of their own. It is only in them altogether and
  • in their relation that the notion is realised. The individual by
  • itself does not correspond to its notion. It is this limitation of its
  • existence which constitutes the finitude and the ruin of the individual.
  • The Idea itself is not to be taken as an idea of something or other,
  • any more than the notion is to be taken as merely a specific notion.
  • The Absolute is the universal and one idea, which, by an act of
  • 'judgment,' particularises itself to the system of specific ideas;
  • which after all are constrained by their nature to come back to the one
  • idea where their truth lies. As issued out of this 'judgment' the Idea
  • is _in the first place_ only the one universal _substance:_ but its
  • developed and genuine actuality is to be as a _subject_ and in that way
  • as mind.
  • Because it has no _existence_ for starting-point and _point d'appui,_
  • the Idea is frequently treated as a mere logical form. Such a view must
  • be abandoned to those theories, which ascribe so-called reality and
  • genuine actuality to the existent thing and all the other categories
  • which have not yet penetrated as far as the Idea. It is no less false
  • to imagine the Idea to be mere abstraction. It is abstract certainly,
  • in so far as everything untrue is consumed in it: but in its own self
  • it is essentially concrete, because it is the free notion giving
  • character to itself, and that character, reality. It would be an
  • abstract form, only if the notion, which is its principle, were taken
  • as an abstract unity, and not as the negative return of it into self
  • and as the subjectivity which it really is.
  • * * * * *
  • Truth is at first taken to mean that I _know_ how something _is._ This
  • is truth, however, only in reference to consciousness; it is formal
  • truth, bare correctness. Truth in the deeper sense consists in the
  • identity between objectivity and the notion. It is in this deeper sense
  • of truth that we speak of a true state, or of a true work of art. These
  • objects are true, if they are as they ought to be, _i.e._ if their
  • reality corresponds to their notion. When thus viewed, to be untrue
  • means much the same as to be bad. A bad man is an untrue man, a man
  • who does not behave as his notion or his vocation requires. Nothing
  • however can subsist, if it be _wholly_ devoid of identity between the
  • notion and reality. Even bad and untrue things have being, in so far
  • as their reality still, somehow, conforms to their notion. Whatever
  • is thoroughly bad or contrary to the notion, is for that very reason
  • on the way to ruin. It is by the notion alone that the things in the
  • world have their subsistence; or, as it is expressed in the language of
  • religious conception, things are what they are, only in virtue of the
  • divine and thereby creative thought which dwells within them.
  • When we hear the Idea spoken of, we need not imagine something far
  • away beyond this mortal sphere. The idea is rather what is completely
  • present: and it is found, however confused and degenerated, in
  • every consciousness. We conceive the world to ourselves as a great
  • totality which is created by God, and so created that in it God has
  • manifested Himself to us. We regard the world also as ruled by Divine
  • Providence: implying that the scattered and divided parts of the world
  • are continually brought back, and made conformable, to the unity from
  • which they have issued. The purpose of philosophy has always been the
  • intellectual ascertainment of the Idea; and everything deserving the
  • name of philosophy has constantly been based on the consciousness
  • of an absolute unity where the understanding sees and accepts only
  • separation.--It is too late now to ask for proof that the Idea is
  • the truth. The proof of that is contained in the whole deduction and
  • development of thought up to this point. The idea is the result of
  • this course of dialectic. Not that it is to be supposed that the idea
  • is mediate only, _i.e._ mediated through something else than itself.
  • It is rather its own result, and being so, is no less immediate than
  • mediate. The stages hitherto considered, viz. those of Being and
  • Essence, as well as those of Notion and of Objectivity, are not, when
  • so distinguished, something permanent, resting upon themselves. They
  • have proved to be dialectical; and their only truth is that they are
  • dynamic elements of the idea.
  • 214.] The Idea may be described in many ways. It may be called reason
  • (and this is the proper philosophical signification of reason);
  • subject-object; the unity of the ideal and the real, of the finite and
  • the infinite, of soul and body; the possibility which has its actuality
  • in its own self; that of which the nature can be thought only as
  • existent, &c. All these descriptions apply, because the Idea contains
  • all the relations of understanding, but contains them in their infinite
  • self-return and self-identity.
  • It is easy work for the understanding to show that everything said
  • of the Idea is self-contradictory. But that can quite as well be
  • retaliated, or rather in the Idea the retaliation is actually made. And
  • this work, which is the work of reason, is certainly not so easy as
  • that of the understanding. Understanding may demonstrate that the Idea
  • is self-contradictory: because the subjective is subjective only and is
  • always confronted by the objective,--because being is different from
  • notion and therefore cannot be picked out of it,--because the finite
  • is finite only, the exact antithesis of the infinite, and therefore
  • not identical with it; and so on with every term of the description.
  • The reverse of all this however is the doctrine of Logic. Logic shows
  • that the subjective which is to be subjective only, the finite which
  • would be finite only, the infinite which would be infinite only, and so
  • on, have no truth, but contradict themselves, and pass over into their
  • opposites. Hence this transition, and the unity in which the extremes
  • are merged and become factors, each with a merely reflected existence,
  • reveals itself as their truth.
  • The understanding, which addresses itself to deal with the Idea,
  • commits a double misunderstanding. It takes _first_ the extremes of
  • the Idea (be they expressed as they will, so long as they are in their
  • unity), not as they are understood when stamped with this concrete
  • unity, but as if they remained abstractions outside of it. It no less
  • mistakes the relation between them, ever when it has been expressly
  • stated. Thus, for example it overlooks even the nature of the copula
  • in the judgment, which affirms that the individual, or subject, is
  • after all not individual, but universal. But, in the _second_ place,
  • the understanding believes _its_ 'reflection,'--that the self-identical
  • Idea contains its own negative, or contains contradiction,--to be an
  • external reflection which does not lie within the Idea itself. But the
  • reflection is really no peculiar cleverness of the understanding. The
  • Idea itself is the dialectic which for ever divides and distinguishes
  • the self-identical from the differentiated, the subjective from the
  • objective, the finite from the infinite, soul from body. Only on
  • these terms is it an eternal creation, eternal vitality, and eternal
  • spirit. But while it thus passes or rather translates itself into the
  • abstract understanding, it for ever remains reason. The Idea is the
  • dialectic which again makes this mass of understanding and diversity
  • understand its finite nature and the pseudo-independence in its
  • productions, and which brings the diversity back to unity. Since this
  • double movement is not separate or distinct in time, nor indeed in any
  • other way--otherwise it would be only a repetition of the abstract
  • understanding--the Idea is the eternal vision of itself in the other,
  • --notion which in its objectivity _has_ carried out _itself,_--object
  • which is inward design, essential subjectivity.
  • The different modes of apprehending the Idea as unity of ideal and
  • real, of finite and infinite, of identity and difference, &c. are more
  • or less formal. They designate some one stage of the _specific_ notion.
  • Only the notion itself, however, is free and the genuine universal:
  • in the Idea, therefore, the specific character of the notion is
  • only the notion itself,--an objectivity, viz. into which it, being
  • the universal, continues itself, and in which it has only its own
  • character, the total character. The Idea is the infinite judgment, of
  • which the terms are severally the independent totality; and in which,
  • as each grows to the fulness of its own nature, it has thereby at the
  • same time passed into the other. None of the other specific notions
  • exhibits this totality complete on both its sides as the notion itself
  • and objectivity.
  • 215.] The Idea is essentially a process, because its identity is the
  • absolute and free identity of the notion, only in so far as it is
  • absolute negativity and for that reason dialectical. It is the round of
  • movement, in which the notion, in the capacity of universality which
  • is individuality, gives itself the character of objectivity and of the
  • antithesis thereto; and this externality which has the notion for its
  • substance, finds its way back to subjectivity through its immanent
  • dialectic.
  • As the idea is (a) a process, it follows that such an expression for
  • the Absolute as _unity_ of thought and being, of finite and infinite,
  • &c. is false; for unity expresses an abstract and merely quiescent
  • identity. As the Idea is (b) subjectivity, it follows that the
  • expression is equally false on another account. That unity of which
  • it speaks expresses a merely virtual or underlying presence of the
  • genuine unity. The infinite would thus seem to be merely _neutralised_
  • by the finite, the subjective by the objective, thought by being. But
  • in the negative unity of the Idea, the infinite overlaps and includes
  • the finite, thought overlaps being, subjectivity overlaps objectivity.
  • The unity of the Idea is thought, infinity, and subjectivity, and
  • is in consequence to be essentially distinguished from the Idea as
  • _substance,_ just as this overlapping subjectivity, thought, or
  • infinity is to be distinguished from the one-sided subjectivity,
  • one-sided thought, one-sided infinity to which it descends in judging
  • and defining.
  • * * * * *
  • The idea as a process runs through three stages in its development.
  • The first form of the idea is Life: that is, the idea in the form of
  • immediacy. The second form is that of mediation or differentiation;
  • and this is the idea in the form of Knowledge, which appears under
  • the double aspect of the Theoretical and Practical idea. The process
  • of knowledge eventuates in the restoration of the unity enriched by
  • difference. This gives the third form of the idea, the Absolute Idea:
  • which last stage of the logical idea evinces itself to be at the same
  • time the true first, and to have a being due to itself alone.
  • (a) _Life._
  • 216.] The _immediate_ idea is Life. As _soul,_ the notion is
  • realised in a body of whose externality the soul is the immediate
  • self-relating universality. But the soul is also its particularisation,
  • so that the body expresses no other distinctions than follow from the
  • characterisations of its notion. And finally it is the Individuality
  • of the body as infinite negativity,--the dialectic of that bodily
  • objectivity, with its parts lying out of one another, conveying
  • them away from the semblance of independent subsistence back into
  • subjectivity, so that all the members are reciprocally momentary
  • means as well as momentary ends. Thus as life is the initial
  • particularisation, so it results in the negative self-asserting unity:
  • in the dialectic of its corporeity it only coalesces with itself.
  • In this way life is essentially something alive, and in point of
  • its immediacy this individual living thing. It is characteristic of
  • finitude in this sphere that, by reason of the immediacy of the idea,
  • body and soul are separable. This constitutes the mortality of the
  • living being. It is only, however, when the living being is dead, that
  • these two sides of the idea are different _ingredients._
  • * * * * *
  • The single members of the body are what they are only by and in
  • relation to their unity. A hand _e.g._ when hewn off from the body is,
  • as Aristotle has observed, a hand in name only, not in fact. From the
  • point of view of understanding, life is usually spoken of as a mystery,
  • and in general as incomprehensible. By giving it such a name, however,
  • the Understanding only confesses its own finitude and nullity. So far
  • is life from being incomprehensible, that in it the very notion is
  • presented to us, or rather the immediate idea existing as a notion. And
  • having said this, we have indicated the defect of life. Its notion and
  • reality do not thoroughly correspond to each other. The notion of life
  • is the soul, and this notion has the body for its reality. The soul is,
  • as it were, infused into its corporeity; and in that way it is at first
  • sentient only, and not yet freely self-conscious. The process of life
  • consists in getting the better of the immediacy with which it is still
  • beset: and this process, which is itself threefold, results in the idea
  • under the form of judgment, _i.e._ the idea as Cognition.
  • 217.] A living being is a syllogism, of which the very elements are in
  • themselves systems and syllogisms (§§ 198, 201, 207). They are however
  • active syllogisms or processes; and in the subjective unity of the
  • vital agent make only one process. Thus the living being is the process
  • of its coalescence with itself, which runs on through three processes.
  • 218.] (1) The first is the process of the living being inside itself.
  • In that process it makes a split on its own self, and reduces its
  • corporeity to its object or its inorganic nature. This corporeity, as
  • an aggregate of correlations, enters in its very nature into difference
  • and opposition of its elements, which mutually become each other's
  • prey, and assimilate one another, and are retained by producing
  • themselves. Yet this action of the several members (organs), is only
  • the living subject's one act to which their productions revert; so that
  • in these productions nothing is produced except the subject: in other
  • words, the subject only reproduces itself.
  • * * * * *
  • The process of the vital subject within its own limits has in Nature
  • the threefold form of Sensibility, Irritability, and Reproduction. As
  • Sensibility, the living being is immediately simple self-relation--it
  • is the soul omnipresent in its body, the outsideness of each member of
  • which to others has for it no truth. As Irritability, the living being
  • appears split up in itself; and as Reproduction, it is perpetually
  • restoring itself from the inner distinction of its members and organs.
  • A vital agent only exists as this continually self-renewing process
  • within its own limits.
  • 219.] (2) But the judgment of the notion proceeds, as free, to
  • discharge the objective or bodily nature as an independent totality
  • from itself; and the negative relation of the living thing to itself
  • makes, as immediate individuality, the pre-supposition of an inorganic
  • nature confronting it. As this negative of the animate is no less a
  • function in the notion of the animate itself, it exists consequently
  • in the latter (which is at the same time a concrete universal) in the
  • shape of a defect or want. The dialectic by which the object, being
  • implicitly null, is merged, is the action of the self-assured living
  • thing, which in this process against an inorganic nature thus retains,
  • develops, and objectifies itself.
  • * * * * *
  • The living being stands face to face with an inorganic nature, to which
  • it comports itself as a master and which it assimilates to itself.
  • The result of the assimilation is not, as in the chemical process, a
  • neutral product in which the independence of the two confronting sides
  • is merged; but the living being shows itself as large enough to embrace
  • its other which cannot withstand its power. The inorganic nature
  • which is subdued by the vital agent suffers this fate, because it is
  • _virtually_ the same as what life is _actually._ Thus in the other the
  • living being only coalesces with itself. But when the soul has fled
  • from the body, the elementary powers of objectivity begin their play.
  • These powers are, as it were, continually on the spring, ready to begin
  • their process in the organic body; and life is the constant battle
  • against them.
  • 220.] (3) The living individual, which in its first process comports
  • itself as intrinsically subject and notion, through its second
  • assimilates its external objectivity and thus puts the character of
  • reality into itself. It is now therefore implicitly a Kind, with
  • essential universality of nature. The particularising of this Kind is
  • the relation of the living subject to another subject of its Kind: and
  • the judgment is the tie of Kind over these individuals thus appointed
  • for each other. This is the Affinity of the Sexes.
  • 221.] The process of Kind brings it to a being of its own. Life being
  • no more than the idea immediate, the product of this process breaks
  • up into two sides. On the one hand, the living individual, which was
  • at first pre-supposed as immediate, is now seen to be mediated and
  • generated. On the other, however, the living individuality, which, on
  • account of its first immediacy, stands in a negative attitude towards
  • universality, sinks in the superior power of the latter.
  • * * * * *
  • The living being dies, because it is a contradiction. Implicitly it is
  • the universal or Kind, and yet immediately it exists as an individual
  • only. Death shows the Kind to be the power that rules the immediate
  • individual. For the animal the process of Kind is the highest point of
  • its vitality. But the animal never gets so far in its Kind as to have
  • a being of its own; it succumbs to the power of Kind. In the process
  • of Kind the immediate living being mediates itself with itself, and
  • thus rises above its immediacy, only however to sink back into it
  • again. Life thus runs away, in the first instance, only into the false
  • infinity of the progress _ad infinitum._ The real result, however,
  • of the process of life, in the point of its notion, is to merge and
  • overcome that immediacy with which the idea, in the shape of life, is
  • still beset.
  • 222.] In this manner however the idea of life has thrown off not some
  • one particular and immediate 'This,' but this first immediacy as a
  • whole. It thus comes to itself, to its truth: it enters upon existence
  • as a free Kind self-subsistent. The death of merely immediate and
  • individual vitality is the 'procession' of spirit.
  • (b) _Cognition in general._
  • 223.] The idea exists free for itself, in so far as it has universality
  • for the medium of its existence,--as objectivity itself has
  • notional being,--as the idea is its own object. Its subjectivity,
  • thus universalised, is _pure_ self-contained distinguishing of the
  • idea,--intuition which keeps itself in this identical universality.
  • But, as _specific_ distinguishing, it is the further judgment of
  • repelling itself as a totality from itself, and thus, in the first
  • place, pre-supposing itself as an external universe. There are two
  • judgments, which though implicitly identical are not yet explicitly put
  • as identical.
  • 224.] The relation of these two ideas, which implicitly and as life are
  • identical, is thus one of correlation: and it is that correlativity
  • which constitutes the characteristic of finitude in this sphere. It
  • is the relationship of reflection, seeing that the distinguishing of
  • the idea in its own self is only the first judgment--presupposing the
  • other and not yet supposing itself to constitute it. And thus for the
  • subjective idea the objective is the immediate world found ready to
  • hand, or the idea as life is in the phenomenon of individual existence.
  • At the same time, in so far as this judgment is pure distinguishing
  • within its own limits (§ 223), the idea realises in one both itself and
  • its other. Consequently it is the certitude of the virtual identity
  • between itself and the objective world.--Reason comes to the world
  • with an absolute faith in its ability to make the identity actual, and
  • to raise its certitude to truth; and with the instinct of realising
  • explicitly the nullity of that contrast which it sees to be implicitly
  • null.
  • 225.] This process is in general terms Cognition. In Cognition
  • in a single act the contrast is virtually superseded, as regards both
  • the one-sidedness of subjectivity and the one-sidedness of objectivity.
  • At first, however, the supersession of the contrast is but implicit.
  • The process as such is in consequence immediately infected with the
  • finitude of this sphere, and splits into the twofold movement of the
  • instinct of reason, presented as two different movements. On the one
  • hand it supersedes the one-sidedness of the Idea's subjectivity by
  • receiving the existing world into itself, into subjective conception
  • and thought; and with this objectivity, which is thus taken to be
  • real and true, for its content it fills up the abstract certitude of
  • itself. On the other hand, it supersedes the one-sidedness of the
  • objective world, which is now, on the contrary, estimated as only a
  • mere semblance, a collection of contingencies and shapes at bottom
  • visionary. It modifies and informs that world by the inward nature of
  • the subjective, which is here taken to be the genuine objective. The
  • former is the instinct of science after Truth, Cognition properly so
  • called:--the Theoretical action of the idea. The latter is the instinct
  • of the Good to fulfil the same--the Practical activity of the idea or
  • Volition.
  • (α) _Cognition proper._
  • 226.] The universal finitude of Cognition, which lies in the
  • one judgment, the pre-supposition of the contrast (§ 224),--a
  • pre-supposition in contradiction of which its own act lodges protest,
  • specialises itself more precisely on the face of its own idea. The
  • result of that specialisation is, that its two elements receive the
  • aspect of being diverse from each other, and, as they are at least
  • complete, they take up the relation of 'reflection,' not of 'notion,'
  • to one another. The assimilation of the matter, therefore, as a datum,
  • presents itself in the light of a reception of it into categories which
  • at the same time remain external to it, and which meet each other in
  • the same style of diversity. Reason is active here, but it is reason in
  • the shape of understanding. The truth which such Cognition can reach
  • will therefore be only finite: the infinite truth (of the notion) is
  • isolated and made transcendent, an inaccessible goal in a world of its
  • own. Still in its external action cognition stands under the guidance
  • of the notion, and notional principles form the secret clue to its
  • movement.
  • * * * * *
  • The finitude of Cognition lies in the pre-supposition of a world
  • already in existence, and in the consequent view of the knowing subject
  • as a _tabula rasa._ The conception is one attributed to Aristotle;
  • but no man is further than Aristotle from such an outside theory of
  • Cognition. Such a style of Cognition does not recognise in itself the
  • activity of the notion--an activity which it is implicitly, but not
  • consciously. In its own estimation its procedure is passive. Really
  • that procedure is active.
  • 227.] Finite Cognition, when it pre-supposes what is distinguished
  • from it to be something already existing and confronting it,--to be
  • the various facts of external nature or of consciousness--has, in the
  • first place, (1) Formal identity or the abstraction of universality for
  • the form of its action. Its activity therefore consists in analysing
  • the given concrete object, isolating its differences, and giving them
  • the form of abstract universality. Or it leaves the concrete thing as
  • a ground, and by setting aside the unessential-looking particulars,
  • brings into relief a concrete universal, the Genus, or Force and Law.
  • This is the Analytical Method.
  • * * * * *
  • People generally speak of the analytical and synthetical methods,
  • as if it depended solely on our choice which we pursued. This is
  • far from the case. It depends on the form of the objects of our
  • investigation, which of the two methods, that are derivable from the
  • notion of finite cognition, ought to be applied. In the first place,
  • cognition is analytical. Analytical cognition deals with an object
  • which is presented in detachment, and the aim of its action is to
  • trace back to a universal the individual object before it. Thought
  • in such circumstances means no more than an act of abstraction or of
  • formal identity. That is the sense in which thought is understood by
  • Locke and all empiricists. Cognition, it is often said, can never do
  • more than separate the given concrete objects into their abstract
  • elements, and then consider these elements in their isolation. It is,
  • however, at once apparent that this turns things upside down, and that
  • cognition, if its purpose be to take things as they are, thereby falls
  • into contradiction with itself. Thus the chemist _e.g._ places a piece
  • of flesh in his retort, tortures it in many ways, and then informs us
  • that it consists of nitrogen, carbon, hydrogen, &c. True: but these
  • abstract matters have ceased to be flesh. The same defect occurs in
  • the reasoning of an empirical psychologist when he analyses an action
  • into the various aspects which it presents, and then sticks to these
  • aspects in their separation. The object which is subjected to analysis
  • is treated as a sort of onion from which one coat is peeled off after
  • another.
  • 228.] This universality is (2) also a specific universality. In this
  • case the line of activity follows the three 'moments' of the notion,
  • which (as it has not its infinity in finite cognition) is the specific
  • or definite notion of understanding. The reception of the object into
  • the forms of this notion is the Synthetic Method.
  • * * * * *
  • The movement of the Synthetic method is the reverse of the Analytical
  • method. The latter starts from the individual, and proceeds to the
  • universal; in the former the starting-point is given by the universal
  • (as a definition), from which we proceed by particularising (in
  • division) to the individual (the theorem). The Synthetic method thus
  • presents itself as the development of the 'moments' of the notion on
  • the object.
  • 229.] (α) When the object has been in the first instance brought by
  • cognition into the form of the specific notion in general, so that
  • in this way its genus and its universal character or speciality are
  • explicitly stated, we have the Definition. The materials and the
  • proof of Definition are procured by means of the Analytical method (§
  • 227). The specific character however is expected to be a 'mark' only:
  • that is to say it is to be in behoof only of the purely subjective
  • cognition which is external to the object.
  • * * * * *
  • Definition involves the three organic elements of the
  • notion: the universal or proximate genus _genus proximum,_
  • the particular or specific character of the genus (_qualitas
  • specified,_) and the individual, or object defined.--The first
  • question that definition suggests, is where it comes from.
  • The general answer to this question is to say, that definitions
  • originate by way of analysis. This will explain how it
  • happens that people quarrel about the correctness of proposed
  • definitions; for here everything depends on what
  • perceptions we started from, and what points of view we
  • had before our eyes in so doing. The richer the object to
  • be defined is, that is, the more numerous are the aspects
  • which it offers to our notice, the more various are the definitions
  • we may frame of it. Thus there are quite a host of
  • definitions of life, of the state, &c. Geometry, on the contrary,
  • dealing with a theme so abstract as space, has an easy
  • task in giving definitions. Again, in respect of the matter or
  • contents of the objects defined, there is no constraining
  • necessity present. We are expected to admit that space
  • exists, that there are plants, animals, &c, nor is it the business
  • of geometry, botany, &c. to demonstrate that the objects
  • in question necessarily are. This very circumstance makes
  • the synthetical method of cognition as little suitable for
  • philosophy as the analytical: for philosophy has above all
  • things to leave no doubt of the necessity of its objects. And
  • yet several attempts have been made to introduce the synthetical
  • method into philosophy. Thus Spinoza, in particular,
  • begins with definitions. He says, for instance, that
  • substance is the _causa sui._ His definitions are unquestionably
  • a storehouse of the most speculative truth, but it takes the
  • shape of dogmatic assertions. The same thing is also true
  • of Schelling.
  • 230.] (ß) The statement of the second element of the notion, _i.e._ of
  • the specific character of the universal as particularising, is given by
  • Division in accordance with some external consideration.
  • * * * * *
  • Division we are told ought to be complete. That requires a principle
  • or ground of division so constituted, that the division based upon it
  • embraces the whole extent of the region designated by the definition
  • in general. But, in division, there is the further requirement that
  • the principle of it must be borrowed from the nature of the object in
  • question. If this condition be satisfied, the division is natural and
  • not merely artificial, that is to say, arbitrary. Thus, in zoology,
  • the ground of division adopted in the classification of the mammalia
  • is mainly afforded by their teeth and claws. That is so far sensible,
  • as the mammals themselves distinguish themselves from one another by
  • these parts of their bodies; back to which therefore the general type
  • of their various classes is to be traced. In every case the genuine
  • division must be controlled by the notion. To that extent a division,
  • in the first instance, has three members: but as particularity
  • exhibits itself as double, the division may go to the extent even
  • of four members. In the sphere of mind trichotomy is predominant, a
  • circumstance which Kant has the credit of bringing into notice.
  • 231.] (γ) In the concrete individuality, where the mere unanalysed
  • quality of the definition is regarded as a correlation of elements,
  • the object is a synthetical nexus of distinct characteristics. It is
  • a Theorem. Being different, these characteristics possess but
  • a mediated identity. To supply the materials, which form the middle
  • terms, is the office of Construction: and the process of mediation
  • itself, from which cognition derives the necessity of that nexus, is
  • the Demonstration.
  • As the difference between the analytical and synthetical methods is
  • commonly stated, it seems entirely optional which of the two we employ.
  • If we assume, to start with, the concrete thing which the synthetic
  • method presents as a result, we can analyse from it as consequences
  • the abstract propositions which formed the pre-suppositions and the
  • material for the proof. Thus, algebraical definitions of curved lines
  • are theorems in the method of geometry. Similarly even the Pythagorean
  • theorem, if made the definition of a right-angled triangle, might yield
  • to analysis those propositions which geometry had already demonstrated
  • on its behoof. The optionalness of either method is due to both alike
  • starting from an external pre-supposition. So far as the nature of
  • the notion is concerned, analysis is prior; since it has to raise the
  • given material with its empirical concreteness into the form of general
  • abstractions, which may then be set in the front of the synthetical
  • method as definitions.
  • That these methods, however indispensable and brilliantly successful
  • in their own province, are unserviceable for philosophical cognition,
  • is self-evident. They have pre-suppositions; and their style of
  • cognition is that of understanding, proceeding under the canon of
  • formal identity. In Spinoza, who was especially addicted to the use of
  • the geometrical method, we are at once struck by its characteristic
  • formalism. Yet his ideas were speculative in spirit; whereas the system
  • of Wolf, who carried the method out to the height of pedantry, was
  • even in subject-matter a metaphysic of the understanding. The abuses
  • which these methods with their formalism once led to in philosophy
  • and science have in modern times been followed by the abuses of what
  • is called 'Construction.' Kant brought into vogue the phrase that
  • mathematics 'construes' its notions. All that was meant by the phrase
  • was that mathematics has not to do with notions, but with abstract
  • qualities of sense-perceptions. The name 'Construction (_construing_)
  • of notions' has since been given to a sketch or statement of sensible
  • attributes which were picked up from perception, quite guiltless
  • of any influence of the notion, and to the additional formalism of
  • classifying scientific and philosophical objects in a tabular form
  • on some pre-supposed rubric, but in other respects at the fancy and
  • discretion of the observer. In the background of all this, certainly,
  • there is a dim consciousness of the Idea, of the unity of the notion
  • and objectivity,--a consciousness, too, that the idea is concrete. But
  • that play of what is styled 'construing' is far from presenting this
  • unity adequately--a unity which is none other than the notion properly
  • so called: and the sensuous concreteness of perception is as little the
  • concreteness of reason and the idea.
  • Another point calls for notice. Geometry works with the sensuous but
  • abstract perception of space; and in space it experiences no difficulty
  • in isolating and defining certain simple analytic modes. To geometry
  • alone therefore belongs in its perfection the synthetical method of
  • finite cognition. In its course, however (and this is the remarkable
  • point), it finally stumbles upon what are termed irrational and
  • incommensurable quantities; and in their case any attempt at further
  • specification drives it beyond the principle of the understanding.
  • This is only one of many instances in terminology, where the title
  • rational is perversely applied to the province of understanding,
  • while we stigmatise as irrational that which shows a beginning and a
  • trace of rationality. Other sciences, removed as they are from the
  • simplicity of space or number, often and necessarily reach a point
  • where understanding permits no further advance: but they get over the
  • difficulty without trouble. They make a break in the strict sequence
  • of their procedure, and assume whatever they require, though it be
  • the reverse of what preceded, from some external quarter,--opinion,
  • perception, conception or any other source. Its inobservancy as to
  • the nature of its methods and their relativity to the subject-matter
  • prevents this finite cognition from seeing that, when it proceeds by
  • definitions and divisions, &c., it is really led on by the necessity
  • of the laws of the notion. For the same reason it cannot see when it
  • has reached its limit; nor, if it have transgressed that limit, does it
  • perceive that it is in a sphere where the categories of understanding,
  • which it still continues rudely to apply, have lost all authority.
  • 232.] The necessity, which finite cognition produces in the
  • Demonstration, is, in the first place, an external necessity, intended
  • for the subjective intelligence alone. But in necessity as such,
  • cognition itself has left behind its presupposition and starting-point,
  • which consisted in accepting its content as given or found.
  • Necessity _quâ_ necessity is implicitly the self-relating notion. The
  • subjective idea has thus implicitly reached an original and objective
  • determinateness,--a something not-given, and for that reason immanent
  • in the subject. It has passed over into the idea of Will.
  • * * * * *
  • The necessity which cognition reaches by means of the demonstration is
  • the reverse of what formed its starting-point. In its starting-point
  • cognition had a given and a contingent content; but now, at the close
  • of its movement, it knows its content to be necessary. This necessity
  • is reached by means of subjective agency. Similarly, subjectivity
  • at starting was quite abstract, a bare _tabula rasa._ It now shows
  • itself as a modifying and determining principle. In this way we pass
  • from the idea of cognition to that of will. The passage, as will be
  • apparent on a closer examination, means that the universal, to be
  • truly apprehended, must be apprehended as subjectivity, as a notion
  • self-moving, active, and form-imposing.
  • (ß) _Volition._
  • 233.] The subjective idea as original and objective determinateness,
  • and as a simple uniform content, is the Good. Its impulse
  • towards self-realisation is in its behaviour the reverse of the idea of
  • truth, and rather directed towards moulding the world it finds before
  • it into a shape conformable to its purposed End.--This Volition has,
  • on the one hand, the certitude of the nothingness of the pre-supposed
  • object; but, on the other, as finite, it at the same time pre-supposes
  • the purposed End of the Good to be a mere subjective idea, and the
  • object to be independent.
  • 234.] This action of the Will is finite: and its finitude lies in
  • the contradiction that in the inconsistent terms applied to the
  • objective world the End of the Good is just as much not executed
  • as executed,--the end in question put as unessential as much as
  • essential,--as actual and at the same, time as merely possible. This
  • contradiction presents itself to imagination as an endless progress in
  • the actualising of the Good; which is therefore set up and fixed as
  • a mere 'ought,' or goal of perfection. In point of form however this
  • contradiction vanishes when the action supersedes the subjectivity of
  • the purpose, and along with it the objectivity, with the contrast which
  • makes both finite; abolishing subjectivity as a whole and not merely
  • the one-sidedness of this form of it. (For another new subjectivity of
  • the kind, that is, a new generation of the contrast, is not distinct
  • from that which is supposed to be past and gone.) This return into
  • itself is at the same time the content's own 'recollection' that it
  • is the Good and the implicit identity of the two sides,--it is a
  • 'recollection' of the pre-supposition of the theoretical attitude
  • of mind (§ 224) that the objective world is its own truth and
  • substantiality.
  • * * * * *
  • While Intelligence merely proposes to take the world as it is, Will
  • takes steps to make the world what it ought to be. Will looks upon
  • the immediate and given present not as solid being, but as mere
  • semblance without reality. It is here that we meet those contradictions
  • which are so bewildering from the standpoint of abstract morality.
  • This position in its 'practical' bearings is the one taken by the
  • philosophy of Kant, and even by that of Fichte. The Good, say these
  • writers, has to be realised: we have to work in order to produce it:
  • and Will is only the Good actualising itself. If the world then were
  • as it ought to be, the action of Will would be at an end. The Will
  • itself therefore requires that its End should not be realised. In
  • these words, a correct expression is given to the _finitude_ of Will.
  • But finitude was not meant to be the ultimate point: and it is the
  • process of Will itself which abolishes finitude and the contradiction
  • it involves. The reconciliation is achieved, when Will in its result
  • returns to the pre-supposition made by cognition. In other words, it
  • consists in the unity of the theoretical and practical idea. Will
  • knows the end to be its own, and Intelligence apprehends the world as
  • the notion actual. This is the right attitude of rational cognition.
  • Nullity and transitoriness constitute only the superficial features
  • and not the real essence of the world. That essence is the notion in
  • _posse_ and in _esse:_ and thus the world is itself the idea. All
  • unsatisfied endeavour ceases, when we recognise that the final purpose
  • of the world is accomplished no less than ever accomplishing itself.
  • Generally speaking, this is the man's way of looking; while the young
  • imagine that the world is utterly sunk in wickedness, and that the
  • first thing needful is a thorough transformation. The religious mind,
  • on the contrary, views the world as ruled by Divine Providence, and
  • therefore correspondent with what it ought to be. But this harmony
  • between the 'is' and the 'ought to be' is not torpid and rigidly
  • stationary. Good, the final end of the world, has being, only while it
  • constantly produces itself. And the world of spirit and the world of
  • nature continue to have this distinction, that the latter moves only in
  • a recurring cycle, while the former certainly also makes progress.
  • 235.] Thus the truth of the Good is laid down as the unity of the
  • theoretical and practical idea in the doctrine that the Good is
  • radically and really achieved, that the objective world is in itself
  • and for itself the Idea, just as it at the same time eternally lays
  • itself down as End, and by action brings about its actuality. This life
  • which has returned to itself from the bias and finitude of cognition,
  • and which by the activity of the notion has become identical with it,
  • is the Speculative or Absolute Idea.
  • (c) _The Absolute Idea._
  • 236.] The Idea, as unity of the Subjective and Objective Idea, is
  • the notion of the Idea,--a notion whose object (_Gegenstand_) is the
  • Idea as such, and for which the objective (_Objekt_) is Idea,--an
  • Object which embraces all characteristics in its unity. This unity
  • is consequently I the absolute and all truth, the Idea which thinks
  • itself,--and here at least as a thinking or Logical Idea.
  • * * * * *
  • The Absolute Idea is, in the first place, the unity of the theoretical
  • and practical idea, and thus at the same time the unity of the idea
  • of life with the idea of cognition. In cognition we had the idea in a
  • biassed, one-sided shape. The process of cognition has issued in the
  • overthrow of this bias and the restoration of that unity, which as
  • unity, and in its immediacy, is in the first instance the Idea of Life.
  • The defect of life lies in its being only the idea implicit or natural:
  • whereas cognition is in an equally one-sided way the merely conscious
  • idea, or the idea for itself. The unity and truth of these two is the
  • Absolute Idea, which is both in itself and for itself. Hitherto _we_
  • have had the idea in development through its various grades as _our_
  • object, but now the idea comes to be its _own object._ This is the
  • νόησις νοήσεως which Aristotle long ago termed the supreme form of the
  • idea.
  • 237.] Seeing that there is in it no transition, or presupposition,
  • and in general no specific character other than what is fluid and
  • transparent, the Absolute Idea is for itself the pure form of the
  • notion, which contemplates its content as its own self. It is its own
  • content, in so far as it ideally distinguishes itself from itself,
  • and the one of the two things distinguished is a self-identity in
  • which however is contained the totality of the form as the system of
  • terms describing its content. This content is the system of Logic. All
  • that is at this stage left as form for the idea is the Method of this
  • content,--the specific consciousness of the value and currency of the
  • 'moments' in its development.
  • * * * * *
  • To speak of the absolute idea may suggest the conception that we are
  • at length reaching the right thing and the sum of the whole matter.
  • It is certainly possible to indulge in a vast amount of senseless
  • declamation about the idea absolute. But its true content is only the
  • whole system of which we have been hitherto studying the development.
  • It may also be said in this strain that the absolute idea is the
  • universal, but the universal not merely as an abstract form to which
  • the particular content is a stranger, but as the absolute form, into
  • which all the categories, the whole fullness of the content it has
  • given being to, have retired. The absolute idea may in this respect be
  • compared to the old man who utters the same creed as the child, but
  • for whom it is pregnant with the significance of a lifetime. Even if
  • the child understands the truths of religion, he cannot but imagine
  • them to be something outside of which lies the whole of life and the
  • whole of the world. The same may be said to be the case with human life
  • as a whole and the occurrences with which it is fraught. All work is
  • directed only to the aim or end; and when it is attained, people are
  • surprised to find nothing else but just the very thing which they had
  • wished for. The interest lies in the whole movement. When a man traces
  • up the steps of his life, the end may appear to him very restricted:
  • but in it the whole _decursus vitae_ is comprehended. So, too, the
  • content of the absolute idea is the whole breadth of ground which has
  • passed under our view up to this point. Last of all comes the discovery
  • that the whole evolution is what constitutes the content and the
  • interest. It is indeed the prerogative of the philosopher to see that
  • everything, which, taken apart, is narrow and restricted, receives
  • its value by its connexion with the whole, and by forming an organic
  • element of the idea. Thus it is that we have had the content already,
  • and what we have now is the knowledge that the content is the living
  • development of the idea. This simple retrospect is contained in the
  • _form_ of the idea. Each of the stages hitherto reviewed is an image
  • of the absolute, but at first in a limited mode, and thus it is forced
  • onwards to the whole, the evolution of which is what we termed Method.
  • 238.] The several steps or stages of the Speculative Method are,
  • first of all, (a) the Beginning, which is Being or Immediacy:
  • self-subsistent, for the simple reason that it is the beginning. But
  • looked at from the speculative idea, Being is its self-specialising
  • act, which as the absolute negativity or movement of the notion makes
  • a judgment and puts itself as its own negative. Being, which to the
  • beginning as beginning seems mere abstract affirmation, is thus rather
  • negation, dependency, derivation, and pre-supposition. But it is the
  • notion, of which Being is the negation: and the notion is completely
  • self-identical in its otherness, and is the certainty of itself. Being
  • therefore is the notion implicit, before it has been explicitly put as
  • a notion. This Being therefore, as the still unspecified notion,--a
  • notion that is only implicitly or 'immediately' specified--is equally
  • describable as the Universal.
  • When it means immediate being, the beginning is taken from sensation
  • and perception--the initial stage in the analytical method of finite
  • cognition. When it means universality, it is the beginning of the
  • synthetic method. But since the Logical Idea is as much a universal as
  • it is in being--since it is pre-supposed by the notion as much as it
  • itself immediately _is,_ its beginning is a synthetical as well as an
  • analytical beginning.
  • * * * * *
  • Philosophical method is analytical as well as synthetical, not indeed
  • in the sense of a bare juxtaposition or mere alternating employment
  • of these two methods of finite cognition, but rather in such a way
  • that it holds them merged in itself. In every one of its movements
  • therefore it displays an attitude at once analytical and synthetical.
  • Philosophical thought proceeds analytically, in so far as it only
  • accepts its object, the Idea, and while allowing it its own way, is
  • only, as it were, an on-looker at its movement and development. To this
  • extent philosophising is wholly passive. Philosophic thought however is
  • equally synthetic, and evinces itself to be the action of the notion
  • itself. To that end, however, there is required an effort to keep back
  • the incessant impertinence of our own fancies and private opinions.
  • 239.] (b) The Advance renders explicit the _judgment_ implicit in
  • the Idea. The immediate universal, as the notion implicit, is the
  • dialectical force which on its own part deposes its immediacy and
  • universality to the level of a mere stage or 'moment.' Thus is put
  • the negative of the beginning, its specific character: it supposes a
  • correlative, a relation of different terms,--the stage of Reflection.
  • Seeing that the immanent dialectic only states explicitly what was
  • involved in the immediate notion, this advance is Analytical; but
  • seeing that in this notion this distinction was not yet stated,--it is
  • equally Synthetical.
  • * * * * *
  • In the advance of the idea, the beginning exhibits itself as what
  • it is implicitly. It is seen to be mediated and derivative, and
  • neither to have proper being nor proper immediacy. It is only for
  • the consciousness which is itself immediate, that Nature forms the
  • commencement or immediacy, and that Spirit appears as what is mediated
  • by Nature. The truth is that Nature is the creation of Spirit, and it
  • is Spirit itself which gives itself a pre-supposition in Nature.
  • 240.] The abstract form of the advance is, in Being, an other and
  • transition into an other; in Essence showing or reflection in the
  • opposite; in Notion, the distinction of individual from universality,
  • which continues itself as such into, and is as an identity with, what
  • is distinguished from it.
  • 241.] In the second sphere the primarily implicit notion has come as
  • far as shining, and thus is already the idea in germ. The development
  • of this sphere becomes a regress into the first, just as the
  • development of the first is a transition into the second.
  • It is only by means of this double movement, that the difference first
  • gets its due, when each of the two members distinguished, observed
  • on its own part, completes itself to the totality, and in this way
  • works out its unity with the other. It is only by both merging their
  • one-sidedness on their own part, that their unity is kept from becoming
  • one-sided.
  • 242.] The second sphere developes the relation of the differents to
  • what it primarily is,--to the contradiction in its own nature. That
  • contradiction which is seen in the infinite progress is resolved
  • (c) into the end or terminus, where the differenced is explicitly
  • stated as what it is in notion. The end is the negative of the first,
  • and as the identity with that, is the negativity of itself. It is
  • consequently the unity in which both of these Firsts, the immediate
  • and the real First, are made constituent stages in thought, merged,
  • and at the same time preserved in the unity. The notion, which from
  • its implicitness thus comes by means of its differentiation and the
  • merging of that differentiation to close with itself, is the realised
  • notion,--the notion which contains the relativity or dependence of its
  • special features in its own independence. It is the idea which, as
  • absolutely first (in the method), regards this terminus as merely the
  • disappearance of the show or semblance, which made the beginning appear
  • immediate, and made itself seem a result. It is the knowledge that the
  • idea is the one systematic whole.
  • 243.] It thus appears that the method is not an extraneous form,
  • but the soul and notion of the content, from which it is only
  • distinguished, so far as the dynamic elements of the notion even on
  • their own part come in their own specific character to appear as the
  • totality of the notion. This specific character, or the content, leads
  • itself with the form back to the idea; and thus the idea is presented
  • as a systematic totality which is only one idea, of which the several
  • elements are each implicitly the idea, whilst they equally by the
  • dialectic of the notion produce the simple independence of the idea.
  • The science in this manner concludes by apprehending the notion of
  • itself, as of the pure idea for which the idea is.
  • 244.] The Idea which is independent or for itself, when viewed on the
  • point of this its unity with itself, is Perception or Intuition, and
  • the percipient Idea is Nature. But as intuition the idea is, through
  • an external 'reflection,' invested with the one-sided characteristic
  • of immediacy, or of negation. Enjoying however an absolute liberty,
  • the Idea does not merely pass over into life, or as finite cognition
  • allow life to show in it: in its own absolute truth it resolves to let
  • the 'moment' of its particularity, or of the first characterisation
  • and other-being, the immediate idea, as its reflected image, go forth
  • freely as Nature.
  • * * * * *
  • We have now returned to the notion of the Idea with which we began.
  • This return to the beginning is also an advance. We began with Being,
  • abstract Being: where we now are we also have the Idea as Being: but
  • this Idea which has Being is Nature.
  • NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS
  • CHAPTER I.
  • Page 5, § 2. After-thought = Nachdenken, _e.g._ thought which retraces
  • and reproduces an original, but submerged, thought (cf. Hegel's
  • _Werke_, vi. p. xv): to be distinguished from Reflexion (cf.
  • _Werke_, i. 174).
  • P. 7, § 3. On the blending of universal (thought) and individual
  • (sensation) in what is called perception (Wahrnehmen) see _Encycl._ §§
  • 420, 421.
  • P. 8, § 3. Cf. Fichte, _Werke_, ii. 454: 'Hence for the common sort of
  • hearers and readers the uncommon intelligibility of certain sermons and
  • lectures and writings, not one word of which is intelligible to the
  • man who thinks for himself,--because there is really no intelligence
  • in them. The old woman who frequents the church--for whom by the way I
  • cherish all possible respect--finds a sermon very intelligible and very
  • edifying which contains lots of texts and verses of hymns she knows
  • by rote and can repeat. In the same way readers, who fancy themselves
  • far superior to her, find a work very instructive and clear which
  • tells them what they already know, and proofs very stringent which
  • demonstrate what they already believe. The pleasure the reader takes in
  • the writer is a concealed pleasure in himself. What a great man! (he
  • says to himself); it is as if I heard or read myself.
  • P. 10, § 6. Cf. Hegel, _Werke>_ viii. 17: 'In this conviction (that
  • what is reasonable is actual, and what is actual is reasonable) stands
  • every plain man, as well as the philosopher; and from it philosophy
  • starts in the study both of the spiritual and of the natural
  • universe----The great thing however is, in the show of the temporal
  • and the transient to recognise the substance which is immanent and the
  • eternal which is present. For the work of reason (which is synonymous
  • with the Idea), when in its actuality it simultaneously enters external
  • existence, emerges with an infinite wealth of forms, phenomena and
  • phases, and envelopes its kernel with the motley rind with which
  • consciousness is earliest at home,--a rind which the notion must
  • penetrate before it can find the inward pulse and feel it still beating
  • even in the outward phases. But the infinite variety of circumstance
  • which is formed in this externality by the light of the essence shining
  • in it,--all this infinite material, with its regulations,--is not
  • the object of philosophy.... To comprehend _what is,_ is the task of
  • philosophy: for _what is_ is reason. As regards the individual, each,
  • whatever happens, is a son of his time. So too philosophy is its
  • time apprehended in thoughts. It is just as foolish to fancy that a
  • philosophy can overleap its present world as that an individual can
  • overleap his time. If his theory really goes beyond actualities, if it
  • constructs an ideal, a world as it ought to be, then such existence
  • as it has is only in his intentions--a yielding element in which
  • anything you please may be fancy-formed.' Cf. Schelling, _Werke,_ iv.
  • 390: 'There are very many things, actions, &c. of which we may judge,
  • after vulgar semblance, that they are unreasonable. All the same we
  • presuppose and assume that everything which is or which happens is
  • reasonable, and that reason is, in one word, the prime matter and the
  • real of all being.'
  • P. 11, § 6. Actuality (Wirklichkeit) in _Werke,_ iv. 178 _seqq._
  • P. 12, § 7. Cf. Fichte, _Werke,_ ii. 333: 'Man has nothing at all
  • but experience; and everything he comes to be comes to only through
  • experience, through life itself. All his thinking, be it loose or
  • scientific, common or transcendental, starts from experience and has
  • experience ultimately in view. Nothing has unconditional value and
  • significance but life; all other thinking, conception, knowledge has
  • value only in so far as in some way or other it refers to the fact of
  • life, starts from it, and has in view a subsequent return to it.'
  • P. 13, § 7 (note). Thomas Thomson (1773-1852), Professor of Chemistry
  • at Glasgow, distinguished in the early history of chemistry and allied
  • sciences. The _Annals of Philosophy_ appeared from 1813 to 1826.--_The
  • art of preserving the hair_ was published (anonymous) at London in 1825.
  • P. 14, § 7 (note). The speech from the throne was read on Feb. 3rd,
  • 1825.
  • The shipowners' dinner was on Feb. 12. The _Times_ of Feb. 14 gives as
  • Canning's the words 'the just and wise maxims of sound not spurious
  • philosophy.'
  • P. 17, § 10. 'Scholasticus' is the guileless 'freshman,' hero of
  • certain Facetiae (attributed to the Pythagorean philosopher Hierocles)
  • which used occasionally to form part of the early Greek reading of
  • schoolboys.
  • K. L. Reinhold (1754-1823) presents in his intellectual history a
  • picture of the development of ideas in his age. At the beginning
  • his _Attempt of a new theory of the human representative faculty_
  • (1789) is typical of the tendency to give a subjective psychological
  • interpretation of Kant's theory of knowledge But the period of
  • Reinhold's teaching here referred to is that of _Contributions to an
  • easier survey of the condition of philosophy at the beginning of the
  • nineteenth century_ (Beiträge, 1801): the tendency which Hegel, who
  • reviewed him in the _Critical Journal of Philosophy_ (_Werke,_ i. 267
  • _seqq._), calls 'philosophising before philosophy.'--A similar spirit
  • is operative in Krug's proposal (in his _Fundamental Philosophy,_ 1803)
  • to start with what he called 'philosophical problematics.'
  • P. 19, § 11. Plato, _Phaedo,_ p. 89, where Socrates protests against
  • the tendency to confound the defect of a particular piece of reasoning
  • with the incompetence of human reason altogether.
  • P. 22, § 13. The dictum that the historical succession of philosophical
  • systems is identical with their logical sequence should not be
  • taken too literally and mechanically. Its essential point is simply
  • the theorem that history is not a casual series of unconnected
  • events--the deeds of particular persons, but is an evolution under
  • laws and uniformities:--it is this theorem applied to philosophies.
  • But difficulties may easily arise in the application of the general
  • principle: _e.g._ it will be seen (by comparison of § 86 and §
  • 104) that though Pythagoras precedes Parmenides, and number is a
  • stepping-stone to pure thought still pure Being comes at an earlier
  • stage than Quantity.
  • P. 23, § 13. There is a silent reference to what Reinhold professed
  • to make the subject of his teaching at Jena--'philosophy without
  • surnames' (ohne Beinamen),--_i.e._ not a 'critical' philosophy;--or
  • to the 'Philosophy which may not bear any man's name of Beck. As Hegel
  • says, _Werke,_ xvi. 138, 'The solicitude and apprehension against being
  • one-sided is only too often part of the weakness which is capable only
  • of many-sided illogical superficiality.'
  • P. 27, § 16. By 'anthropology' is meant not the anthropology of modern
  • writers, who use the name to denote mainly the history of human culture
  • in its more rudimentary stages, and as exhibited chiefly in material
  • products, but the study of those aspects of psychology which are most
  • closely allied with physiological conditions.
  • With the power of the intuition of genius to give almost all that
  • logical synthesis can produce, cf. _Werke,_ I. 331: 'In this way
  • a grand and pure intuition is able, in the purely architectonic
  • features of its picture, though the inter-connection of necessity and
  • the mastery of form does not come forward into visibility, to give
  • expression to the genuine ethical organism--like a building which
  • silently exhibits the spirit of its author in the several features of
  • its mass, without the image of that spirit being set forth anywhere
  • in one united shape. In such a delineation, made by help of notions,
  • it is only a want of technical skill which prevents reason from
  • raising the principle it embraces and pervades into the "ideal" form
  • and becoming aware of it as the Idea. If the intuition only remains
  • true to itself and does not let analytic intellect disconcert it, it
  • will probably--just because it cannot dispense with notions for its
  • expression--behave awkwardly in dealing with them, assume distorted
  • shapes in its passage through consciousness, and be (to the speculative
  • eye) both incoherent and contradictory: but the arrangement of the
  • parts and of the self-modifying characters betray the inward spirit of
  • reason, however invisible. And so far as this appearance of that spirit
  • is regarded as a product and a result, it will as product completely
  • harmonise with the Idea.' Probably Goethe is before Hegel's mind.
  • P. 28, § 17. The triplicity in unity of thought--its forthgoing
  • 'procession,' (cf. p. 362 _seqq._) and its return, which is yet an
  • abiding in itself (Bei:sich:sein) was first explicitly schematised
  • by Proclus, the consummator of Neo-Platonism. In his _Institutio
  • Theologica_ he lays it down that the essential character of all
  • spiritual reality (aσώματον) is to be πρὸς ἑαυτὸ ἐπιστρεπτικόν, _e.g._
  • to return upon itself, or to be a unity in and with difference,--to
  • be an original and spontaneous principle of movement (c. 15): or, as
  • in C 31: πὰν τὸ πρoῒὸν ἀπό τινος κατ' οὐσίαν ἐπιστρέφεται πρὸς ἐκεῖνο
  • ἀφ' οὗ πρόεισιν. Its movement, therefore, is circular κυκλικὴν ἔχει
  • τὴν ἐνέργειαν (c. 33): for everything must at the same time remain
  • altogether in the cause, and proceed from it, and revert to it (c. 35).
  • Such an essence is self-subsistent (αὐθυπόςτατον),--is at once agent
  • (πάραγον) and patient (παραγόμενον). This 'mysticism' (of a trinity
  • which is also unity of motion which is also rest), with its πρόοδoς,
  • ἐπιστroφή, and μονή, is taken up, in his own way, by Scotus Erigena
  • (De Divisione Naturae) as _processio_ (or _divisio_), _reditus,_
  • and _adunatio._ From God 'proceed'--by an _eternal_ creation--the
  • creatures, who however are not outside the divine nature; and to God
  • all things created _eternally_ return.
  • CHAPTER II.
  • P. 31, § 19. Truth:--as early as _Werke,_ i. 82, _i.e._ 1801, Hegel had
  • come--perhaps influenced by the example of Jacobi--to the conclusion
  • that 'Truth is a word which, in philosophical discourse, deserves to be
  • used only of the certainty of the Eternal and non-empirical Actual.'
  • (And so Spinoza, ii. 310.)
  • P. 32. 'The young have been flattered'--_e.g._ by Fichte, _Werke,_ i.
  • 435: 'Hence this science too promises itself few proselytes amongst men
  • already formed: if it can hope for any at all, it hopes for them rather
  • from the young world, whose inborn force has not yet been ruined in the
  • laxity of the age.'
  • P. 38, § 20. What Kant actually said (_Kritik der reinen Vernunft:
  • Elementarlehre,_ § 16), was 'The _I think_ must be able to accompany
  • all my conceptions' (Vorstellungen). Here, as often elsewhere. Hegel
  • seems to quote from memory,--with some shortcoming from absolute
  • accuracy.
  • From this point Fichte's idealism takes its spring, _e.g. Werke,_ ii.
  • 505: 'The ground of all certainty,--of all consciousness of fact in
  • life, and of all demonstrative knowledge in science, is this: _In_ and
  • _with_ the single thing we affirm (setzen) (and whatever we affirm is
  • necessarily something single) we also affirm the absolute totality as
  • such.... Only in so far as we have so affirmed anything, is it certain
  • for us,--from the single unit we have comprehended under it away to
  • every single thing in the infinity we shall comprehend under it,--from
  • the one individual who has comprehended it, to all individuals who
  • will comprehend it.... Without this absolute "positing" of the absolute
  • totality in the individual, we cannot (to employ a phrase of Jacobi's)
  • come to bed and board.'
  • 'Obviously therefore you enunciate not the judgment of a single
  • observation, but you embrace and "posit" the sheer infinitude and
  • totality of all possible observations:--an infinity which is not at
  • all compounded out of finites, but out of which, conversely, the
  • finites themselves issue, and of which finite things are the mere
  • always-uncompleted analysis. This--how shall I call it, procedure,
  • positing, or whatever you prefer--this "manifestation" of the absolute
  • totality, I call intellectual vision (Anschauung). I regard it--just
  • because I cannot in any way get beyond intelligence--as immanent in
  • intelligence, and name it so far egoity (Ichheit),--not objectivity
  • and not subjectivity, but the absolute identity of the two:--an
  • egoity, however, which it was to be hoped would not be taken to mean
  • individuality. There lies in it, what you' (he is addressing Reinhold,
  • who here follows Bardili)' call a repetibility _ad infinitum._ For me,
  • therefore, the essence of the finite is composed of an immediate vision
  • of the absolutely timeless infinite (with an absolute identity of
  • subjectivity and objectivity), and of a separation of the two latter,
  • and an analysis (continued _ad infinitum_) of the infinite. In that
  • analysis consists the temporal life: and the starting-point of this
  • temporal life is the separation into subject and object, which through
  • the intellectual vision (intuition) are still both held together.'
  • P. 44, § 22, _the mere fact of conviction._ Cf. _Rechtsphilosophie,_
  • § 140 (_Werke,_ viii. 191): 'Finally the mere conviction which holds
  • something to be right is given out as what decides the morality of
  • an action. The good we will to do not yet having any content, the
  • principle of conviction adds the information that the subsumption of an
  • action under the category of good is purely a personal matter. If this
  • be so, the very pretence of an ethical objectivity is utterly lost. A
  • doctrine like this is closely allied with the self-styled philosophy
  • which denies that the true is cognoscible: because for the Will,
  • truth--_i.e._ the rationality of the Will--lies in the moral laws.
  • Giving out, as such a system does, that the cognition of the true is an
  • empty vanity, far transcending the range of science (which recognises
  • only appearance), it must, in the matter of conduct, also find its
  • principle in the apparent; whereby moral distinctions are reduced to
  • the peculiar theory of life held by the individual and to his private
  • conviction. At first no doubt the degradation into which philosophy has
  • thus sunk seems an affair of supreme indifference, a mere incident in
  • the futilities of the scholastic world: but the view necessarily makes
  • itself a home in ethics, which is an essential part of philosophy; and
  • it is then in the actual world that the world learns the true meaning
  • of such theories.
  • 'As the view spreads that subjective conviction, and it alone, decides
  • the morality of an action, it follows that the charge of hypocrisy,
  • once so frequent, is now rarely heard. You can only qualify wickedness
  • as hypocrisy on the assumption that certain actions are inherently
  • and actually misdeeds, vices, and crimes, and that the defaulter
  • necessarily is aware of them as such, because he is aware of and
  • recognises the principles and outward acts of piety and honesty, even
  • in the pretence to which he misapplies them. In other words, it was
  • generally assumed as regards immorality that it is a duty to know the
  • good, and to be aware of its distinction from the bad. In any case it
  • was an absolute injunction which forbade the commission of vicious and
  • criminal acts, and which insisted on such actions being imputed to the
  • agent, so far as he was a man, not a beast. But if the good heart,
  • the good intention, the subjective conviction, are set forth as the
  • true sources of moral worth, then there is no longer any hypocrisy, or
  • immorality at all: for whatever one does, he can always justify it by
  • the reflection on it of good aims and motives; and by the influence of
  • that conviction it is good. There is no longer anything _inherently_
  • vicious or criminal: instead of the frank and free, hardened and
  • unperturbed sinner, comes the person whose mind is completely justified
  • by intention and conviction. My good intention in my act, and my
  • conviction of its goodness, make it good. We speak of judging and
  • estimating an _act._ But on this principle it is only the aim and
  • conviction of the agent--his faith--by which he ought to be judged.
  • And that not in the sense in which Christ requires faith in objective
  • truth, so that for one who has a bad faith, _e.g._ a conviction bad
  • in its content, the judgment to be pronounced must be bad, _e.g._
  • conformable to this bad content. But faith here means only fidelity to
  • conviction. Has the man (we ask) in acting kept true to his conviction?
  • It is formal subjective conviction on which alone the obligation of
  • duty is made to depend.
  • 'A principle like this, where conviction is expressly made something
  • subjective, cannot but suggest the thought of possible error, with the
  • further implied presupposition of an absolutely-existing law. But the
  • law is no agent: it is only the actual human being who acts; and in the
  • aforesaid principle the only question in estimating human actions is
  • how far he has received the law into his conviction. If, therefore, it
  • is not the actions which are to be estimated and generally measured by
  • that law, it is impossible to see what the law is for, and what end it
  • can serve. Such a law is degraded to a mere outside letter, in fact an
  • empty word; which is only made a law, _i.e._ invested with obligatory
  • force, by my conviction.
  • 'Such a law may claim its authority from God or the State: it may even
  • have the authority of tens of centuries during which it served as
  • the bond that gave men, with all their deed and destiny, subsistence
  • and coherence. And these are authorities in which are condensed the
  • convictions of countless individuals. And for me to set against that
  • the authority of my single conviction--for as my subjective conviction
  • its sole validity is authority--that self-conceit, monstrous as it at
  • first seems, is, in virtue of the principle that subjective conviction
  • is to be the rule, pronounced to be no self-conceit at all.
  • 'Even if reason and conscience--which shallow science and bad sophistry
  • can never altogether expel--admit, with a noble illogicality, that
  • error is possible, still by describing crime and wickedness as
  • only an error we minimise the fault. For to err is human:--Who has
  • not been mistaken on one point or another, whether he had fresh or
  • pickled cabbage for dinner, and about innumerable things more or less
  • important? But the difference of more or less importance disappears if
  • everything turns on the subjectivity of conviction and on persistency
  • in it. But the said noble illogicality which admits error to be
  • possible, when it comes round to say that a wrong conviction is only an
  • error, really only falls into a further illogicality--the illogicality
  • of dishonesty. One time conviction is made the basis of morality and
  • of man's supreme value, and is thus pronounced the supreme and holy.
  • Another time all we have to do with is an error: my conviction is
  • something trivial and casual, strictly speaking something outside,
  • that may turn out this way or that. And, really, my being convinced
  • _is_ something supremely trivial? if I cannot _know_ truth, it is
  • indifferent how I think; and all that is left to my thinking is that
  • empty good,--a mere abstraction of generalisation.
  • 'It follows further that, on this principle of justification by
  • conviction, logic requires me, in dealing with the way others act
  • against my action, to admit that, so far as they in their belief and
  • conviction hold my actions to be crimes, they are quite in the right.
  • On such logic not merely do I gain nothing, I am even deposed from the
  • post of liberty and honour into a situation of slavery and dishonour.
  • Justice--which in the abstract is mine as well as theirs--I feel only
  • as a foreign subjective conviction, and in the execution of justice I
  • fancy myself to be only treated by an external force.'
  • P. 44, § 23. Selbstdenken--to think and not merely to read or listen is
  • the recurrent cry of Fichte (_e.g. Werke,_ ii. 329). According to the
  • editors of _Werke,_ xv. 582, the reference here is to Schleiermacher
  • and to his Monologues. Really it is to the Romantic principle in
  • general, especially F. Schlegel.
  • P. 45, § 23. 'Fichte' _Werke,_ ii, 404: 'Philosophy
  • (Wissenschaftslehre), besides (for the reason above noted that it has
  • no auxiliary, no vehicle of the intuition at all, except the intuition
  • itself), elevates the human mind higher than any geometry can It gives
  • the mind not only attentiveness, dexterity, stability, but at the same
  • time absolute independence, forcing it to be alone with itself, and
  • to live and manage by itself. Compared with it, every other mental
  • operation is infinitely easy; and to one who has been exercised in
  • it nothing comes hard. Besides as it prosecutes all objects of human
  • lore to the centre it accustoms the eye to hit the proper point at
  • first glance' in everything presented to it, and to prosecute it
  • undeviatingly For such a practical philosopher therefore there can be
  • nothing dark, complicated, and confused, if only he is acquainted with
  • the object of discussion. It comes always easiest to him to construct
  • everything afresh and _ab initio,_ because he carries within him plans
  • for every scientific edifice. He finds his way easily, therefore, in
  • any complicated structure. Add to this the security and confidence of
  • glance which he has acquired in philosophy--the guide which conducts in
  • all _raisonnement_ and the imperturbability with which his eye meets
  • every divergence from the accustomed path and every paradox. It would
  • be quite different with all human concerns, if men could only resolve
  • to believe their eyes. At present they inquire at their neighbours and
  • at antiquity what they really see, and by this distrust in themselves
  • errors are eternalised. Against this distrust the possessor of
  • philosophy is for ever protected. In a word, by philosophy the mind
  • of man comes to itself, and from henceforth rests on itself without
  • foreign aid, and is completely master of itself, as the dancer of his
  • feet, or the boxer of his hands.'
  • P. 45, § 23. Aristotle, _Metaph._ i. 2, 19 (cf. _Eth._ x. 7). See also
  • _Werke,_ xiv. 280 _seqq._
  • P. 46, § 24. Schelling's expression, 'petrified intelligence.' The
  • reference is to some verses of Schelling in _Werke,_ iv. 546 (first
  • published in _Zeitschrift für speculative Physik,_ 1800). We have no
  • reason to stand in awe of the world, he says, which is a tame and quiet
  • beast--
  • Sterft zwar ein Riesengeist darinnen,
  • Ist aber versteinert mit allen Sinnen;
  • In todten und lebendigen Dingen
  • Thut nach Bewustseyn mächtig ringen.
  • In human shape he at length awakes from the iron sleep, from the long
  • dream: but as man he feels himself a stranger and exile; he would
  • fain return to great Nature; he fears what surrounds him and imagines
  • spectres, not knowing he might say of Nature to himself--
  • Ich bin der Gott, den sie im Busen hegt,
  • Der Geist, der sich in allem bewegt:
  • Vom frühsten Ringen dunkler Kräfte
  • Bis zum Erguss der ersten Lebenssäfte,
  • . . . . . . .
  • herauf zu des Gedankens Jugendkraft
  • Wodurch Natur verjüngt sich wieder schafft,
  • Ist eine kraft, ein Wechselspiel und Weben,
  • Ein Trieb und Drang nach immer höherm Leben.
  • Cf. Oken, _Naturphilosophie,_§ 2913: 'A natural body is a thought of
  • the primal act, turned rigid and crystallised,--a word of God.'
  • Phrases of like import are not infrequent in Schelling's works (about
  • 1800-1), _e.g. Werke,_1. Abth. iii. 341: 'The dead and unconscious
  • products of nature are only unsuccessful attempts to "reflect" itself;
  • so-called dead nature is in all cases an immature intelligence'
  • (unreife Intelligenz), or iv. 77, 'Nature itself is an intelligence,
  • as it were, turned to rigidity (erstarrte) with all its sensations and
  • perceptions'; and ii. 226 (_Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur,_
  • 1797), 'Hence nature is only intelligence turned into the rigidity of
  • being; its qualities are sensations extinguished to being; bodies are
  • its perceptions, so to speak, killed.'
  • A close approach to the phrase quoted is found in the words of another
  • of the 'Romantic' philosophers: 'Nature is a petrified magic-city'
  • (versteinerte Zauberstadt). (Novalis, _Schriften,_ ii. 149.)
  • P. 48, § 24. Cf. Fichte to Jacobi: (Jacobi's _Briefwechsel,_ ii. 208)
  • 'My absolute Ego is obviously not the individual: that explanation
  • comes from injured snobs and peevish philosophers, seeking to
  • impute to me the disgraceful doctrine of practical egoism. But the
  • _individual must be deduced from the absolute ego._ To that task my
  • philosophy will proceed in the "Natural Law." A finite being--it may
  • be deductively shown--can only think itself as a sense-being in a
  • sphere of sense-beings,--on one part of which (that which has no power
  • of origination) it has causality, while with the other part (to which
  • it attributes a subjectivity like its own) it stands in reciprocal
  • relations. In such circumstances it is called an individual, and the
  • conditions of individuality are called rights. As surely as it affirms
  • its individuality, so surely does it affirm such a sphere the two
  • conceptions indeed are convertible. So long as we look upon ourselves
  • as individuals--and we always so regard ourselves in life, though not
  • in philosophy and abstract imagination--we stand on what I call the
  • "practical" point of view in our reflections (while to the standpoint
  • of the absolute ego I give the name "speculative"). From the former
  • point of view there exists for us a world independent of us,--a world
  • we can only modify; whilst the pure ego (which even on this altitude
  • does not altogether disappear from us,) is put outside us and called
  • God. How else could we get the properties we ascribe to God and deny to
  • ourselves, did we not after all find them within us, and only refuse
  • them to ourselves in a certain respect, i.e., as individuals? When this
  • "practical" point of view predominates in our reflections, realism
  • is supreme: when speculation itself deduces and recognises that
  • standpoint, there results a complete reconciliation between philosophy
  • and common sense as premised in my system.
  • 'For what good, then, is the speculative standpoint and the whole of
  • philosophy therewith, if it be not for life? Had humanity not tasted
  • of this forbidden fruit, it might dispense with all philosophy. But in
  • humanity there is a wish implanted to behold that region lying beyond
  • the individual; and to behold it not merely in a reflected light but
  • face to face. The first who raised a question about God's existence
  • broke through the barriers, he shook humanity in its main foundation
  • pillars, and threw it out of joint into an intestine strife which is
  • not yet settled, and which can only be settled by advancing boldly
  • to that supreme point from which the speculative and the practical
  • appear to be at one. We began to philosophise from pride of heart, and
  • thus lost our innocence: we beheld our nakedness, and ever since we
  • philosophise from the need of our redemption.'
  • P. 50. Physics and Philosophy of Nature: cf. _Werke,_ vii. i, p. 18:
  • 'The Philosophy of Nature takes up the material, prepared for it by
  • physics out of experience, at the point to which physics has brought
  • it, and again transforms it, without basing it ultimately on the
  • authority of experience. Physics therefore must work into the hands of
  • philosophy, so that the latter may translate into a true comprehension
  • (Begriff) the abstract universal transmitted to it, showing how it
  • issues from that comprehension as an intrinsically necessary whole. The
  • philosophic way of putting the facts is no mere whim once in a way,
  • by way of change, to walk on the head, after walking a long while on
  • the legs, or once in a way to see our every-day face besmeared with
  • paint. No; it is because the method of physics does not satisfy the
  • comprehension, that we have to go on further.'
  • P. 51, § 24. The distinction of ordinary and speculative Logic
  • is partly like that made by Fichte (i. 68) between Logic and
  • Wissenschaftslehre. 'The former,' says Fichte, 'is conditioned and
  • determined by the latter.' Logic deals only with form; epistomology
  • with import as well.
  • P. 54, § 24. The Mosaic legend of the Fall; cf. similar interpretations
  • in Kant: _Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft_,
  • 1ster Stück; and Schelling, _Werke,_ i. (1. Abth.) 34.
  • CHAPTER III.
  • P. 61, § 28. Fichte--to emphasise the experiential truth of his
  • system--says (_Werke,_ ii. 331): 'There was a philosophy which
  • professed to be able to expand by mere _inference_ the range thus
  • indicated for philosophy. According to it, thinking was--not, as we
  • have described it, the analysis of what was given and the recombining
  • of it in other forms, but at the same time--a production and creation
  • of something quite new. In this system the philosopher found himself
  • in the exclusive possession of certain pieces of knowledge which the
  • vulgar understanding had to do without. In it the philosopher could
  • reason out for himself a God and an immortality and talk himself into
  • the conclusion that he was wise and good.'
  • Wolfs definition of philosophy is 'the Science of the possible in so
  • far as it can be'; and the possible = the non-contradictory.
  • P. 64, § 29. The oriental sage corresponds (cf. Hegel, _Werke,_ xii.
  • 229) to the writer known as Dionysius the Areopagite (_De Mystica
  • Theologia,_ and _De Divitus Nominibus._)--The same problem as to the
  • relation of the Infinite (God) to the Finite (world) is discussed in
  • Jewish speculation (by Saadia, Mamuni, _&c._) as the question of the
  • divine names,--a dogma founded on the thirteen names (or attributes)
  • applied to God in Exodus xxxiv. 6. (Cf. D. Kaufmann, _Geschichte der
  • Attributenlehre._) The same spirit has led to the list of ninety-nine
  • 'excellent names' of Allah in Islam, a list which tradition derives
  • from Mohammed.
  • P. 65, § 31. Cf. _Werke,_ ii. 47 _seqq.:_ 'The nature of the judgment
  • or proposition--involving as it does a distinction of subject and
  • predicate--is destroyed by the "speculative" proposition. This conflict
  • of the propositional form with the unity of comprehension which
  • destroys it is like the antagonism in rhythm between metre and accent.
  • The rhythm results from the floating "mean" and unification of the two.
  • Hence even in the "philosophical" proposition the identity of subject
  • and predicate is not meant to annihilate their difference (expressed by
  • the propositional form): their unity is meant to issue as a _harmony._
  • The propositional form lets appear the definite shade or accent
  • pointing to a distinction in its fulfilment: whereas in the predicate
  • giving expression to the substance, and the subject itself falling
  • into the universal, we have the unity in which that accent is heard no
  • more. Thus in the proposition "God is Being" the predicate is Being; it
  • represents the substance in which the subject is dissolved away. Being
  • is here meant not to be predicate but essence: and in that way God
  • seems to cease to be what he is--by his place in the proposition--viz.
  • the permanent subject. The mind--far from getting further forward in
  • the passage from subject to predicate--feels itself rather checked,
  • through the loss of the subject, and thrown back, from a sense of its
  • loss, to the thought of the subject. Or,--since the predicate itself
  • is enunciated as a subject (as Being or as Essence) which exhausts the
  • nature of the subject, it again comes face to face with the subject
  • even in the predicate.--Thought thus loses its solid objective ground
  • which it had on the subject: yet at the same time in the predicate it
  • is thrown back upon it, and instead of getting to rest in itself it
  • returns upon the subject of the content.--To this unusual check and
  • arrest are in the main due the complaints as to the unintelligibility
  • of philosophical works,--supposing the individual to possess any other
  • conditions of education needed for understanding them.'
  • P. 66, § 32. On the relation of dogmatism and scepticism see the
  • introduction to Kant's _Criticism of Pure Reason,_ and compare Caird's
  • _Critical Philosophy of I. Kant,_ vol. i. chap. i.
  • P. 67, § 33. The subdivision of 'theoretical' philosophy or metaphysics
  • into the four branches, Ontology, Cosmology, Psychology (rational and
  • empirical), and Natural Theology, is more or less common to the whole
  • Wolfian School. Wolf's special addition to the preceding scholastic
  • systems is found in the conception of a general Cosmology. Metaphysics
  • precedes physics, and the departments of practical philosophy. In
  • front of all stands logic or rational philosophy. Empirical psychology
  • belongs properly to physics, but reasons of practical convenience put
  • it elsewhere.
  • P. 69, § 34. The question of the 'Seat of the Soul' is well known in
  • the writings of Lotze (_e.g. Metaphysic,_ § 291).
  • Absolute actuosity. The _Notio Dei_ according to Thomas Aquinas, as
  • well as the dogmatics of post-Reformation times, is _actus purus_
  • (or _actus purissimus_). For God _nihil potentialitatis habet._ Cf.
  • _Werke, xii._228: 'Aristotle especially has conceived God under the
  • abstract category of activity. Pure activity is knowledge (Wissen)--in
  • the scholastic age, _actus purus_--: but in order to be put as
  • activity, it must be put in its "moments." For knowledge we require
  • another thing which is known: and which, when knowledge knows it, is
  • thereby appropriated. It is implied in this that God--the eternal and
  • self-subsistent--eternally begets himself as his Son,--distinguishes
  • himself from himself. But what he thus distinguishes from himself,
  • has not the shape of an otherness: but what is distinguished is
  • _ipso facto_ identical with what it is parted from. God is spirit:
  • no darkness, no colouring or mixture enters this pure light. The
  • relationship of father and son is taken from organic life and used
  • metaphorically--the natural relation is only pictorial and hence does
  • not quite correspond to what is to be expressed. We say, God eternally
  • begets his Son, God distinguishes himself from himself: and thus we
  • begin from God, saying he does this, and in the other he creates is
  • utterly with himself (the form of Love): but we must be well aware
  • that God is this _whole action itself_ God is the beginning; he does
  • this: but equally is he only the end, the totality: and as such
  • totality he is spirit. God as merely the Father is not yet the true
  • (it is the Jewish religion where he is thus without the Son): He is
  • rather beginning and end: He is his presupposition, makes himself a
  • presupposition (this is only another form of distinguishing): He is the
  • eternal process.'
  • Nicolaus Cusanus speaks of God (_De docta Ignorantia,_ ii. I) as
  • _infinita actualitas quae est actu omnis essendi possibilitas._ The
  • term 'actuosity' seems doubtful.
  • P. 73, § 36. _Sensus eminentior._ Theology distinguishes three modes in
  • which the human intelligence can attain a knowledge of God. By the _via
  • causalitatis_ it argues that God is; by the _via negationis,_ what he
  • is not; by the _via eminentiae,_ it gets a glimpse of the relation in
  • which he stands to us. It regards God _i.e._ as the cause of the finite
  • universe; but as God is infinite, all that is predicated of him must be
  • taken as merely approximative (_sensu eminentiori_) and there is left
  • a vast remainder which can only be filled up with negations [Durandus
  • de S. Porciano on the Sentent, i. 3. I]. The _sensus eminentior_ is
  • the subject of Spinoza's strictures, Ep. 6 (56 in Opp. ii. 202): while
  • Leibniz adopts it in the preface to _Théodicée,_ 'Les perfections de
  • Dieu sont celles de nos âmes, mais il les possède sans bornes: il est
  • un océan, dont nous n'avons reçu que les gouttes; il y a en nous
  • quelque puissance, quelque connaissance, quelque bonté; mais elles sont
  • toutes entières en Dieu.'
  • The _via causalitatis_ infers _e.g.,_ from the existence of morality
  • and intelligence here, a Being whose will finds expression therein: the
  • _via eminentiae_ infers that that will is good, and that intelligence
  • wise in the highest measure, and the _via negationis_ sets aside in the
  • conception of God all the limitations and conditions to which human
  • intelligence and will are subject.
  • CHAPTER IV.
  • P. 80, § 38. The verses (forming part of the advice which
  • Mephistopheles, personating Faust, gives to the recently-arrived
  • pupil) stand in the original in a different order: beginning "Dann hat
  • er die Theile in seiner Hand," &c. The meaning of these and the two
  • preceding lines is somewhat as follows, in versification even laxer
  • than Goethe's:--
  • If you want to describe life and gather its meaning,
  • To drive out its spirit most be your beginning,
  • Then though fast in your hand lie the parts one by one
  • The spirit that linked them, alas! is gone.
  • And 'Nature's Laboratory' is only a name
  • That the chemist bestows on't to hide his own shame.
  • One may compare _Wilhelm Meister's Wanderjahre,_ iii. 3, where it is
  • remarked, in reference to some anatomical exercises: 'You will learn
  • ere long that building-up is more instructive than tearing-down,
  • combining more than separating, animating the dead more than killing
  • again what was killed already.... Combining means more than separating:
  • reconstructing more than onlooking.' The first part of _Faust_ appeared
  • 1808: the _Wanderjahre,_ 1828-9.
  • P. 82, § 39. The article on the 'Relation of scepticism to philosophy,
  • an exposition of its various modifications, and comparison of the
  • latest with the ancient'--in form a review of G. E. Schulze's
  • _Criticism of Theoretical Philosophy_'--was republished in vol. xvi. of
  • Hegel's _Werke_ (vol. i. of the _Vermischte Schriften_).
  • P. 87, § 42. In an earlier review of Kant's work (_Werke,_ i. 83) on
  • Glauben und Wissen (an article in Sendling and Hegel's _Journal_)
  • Hegel attaches more weight to a factor in the critical theory of
  • knowledge, here neglected. Kant, he says, has--within the limits
  • allowed by his psychological terms of thought--'put (in an excellent
  • way) the _à priori_ of sensibility into the original identity and
  • multiplicity, and that as transcendental imagination in the "higher
  • power" of an immersion of unity in multiplicity: whilst Understanding
  • (Verstand) he makes to consist in the elevation to universality of this
  • _à priori_ synthetic unity of sensibility,--whereby this identity is
  • invested with a comparative antithesis to the sensibility: and Reason
  • (Vernunft) is presented as a still higher power over the preceding
  • comparative antithesis, without however this universality and infinity
  • being allowed to go beyond the stereotyped formal pure infinity.
  • This genuinely rational construction by which, though the bad name
  • "faculties" is left, there is in truth presented a single identity
  • of them all, is transformed by Jacobi into a series of faculties,
  • _resting_ one upon another.'
  • P. 87, § 42. Fichte: cf. _Werke,_ i. 420: 'I have said before, and
  • say it here again, that my system is no other than the Kantian. That
  • means: it contains the same view of facts, but in its method is quite
  • independent of the Kantian exposition.' 'Kant, up to now, is a closed
  • book.'--i. 442. There are two ways of critical idealism. 'Either' (as
  • Fichte) 'it actually deduces from the fundamental laws of intelligence,
  • that system of necessary modes of action, and with it, at the same
  • time, the objective conceptions thus arising, and thus lets the whole
  • compass of our conceptions gradually arise under the eyes of the reader
  • or hearer; or' (like Kant and his unprogressive disciples) 'it gets
  • hold of these laws from anywhere and anyhow, as they are immediately
  • applied to objects, therefore on their lowest grade (--on this grade
  • they are called _categories),_ and then asseverates that it is by
  • these that objects are determined and arranged.' And i. 478: 'I know
  • that the categories which Kant laid down are in no way _proved_ by
  • him to be conditions of self-consciousness, but only said to be so:
  • I know that space and time and what in the original consciousness is
  • inseparable from them and fills them both, are still less deduced as
  • such conditions, for of them it is not even said expressly--as of the
  • categories--that they are so, but only inferentially. But I believe
  • quite as surely that I know that Kant had the thought of such a system:
  • that everything he actually propounds are fragments and results of this
  • system; and that his statements have meaning and coherence only on this
  • presupposition.' Cf. viii. 362.
  • P. 89, § 42. Transcendental unity of self-consciousness. Kant's _Kritik
  • der reinen Vernunft,_ § 16: 'The _I think_ must be able to accompany
  • all my ideas.... This idea is an act of spontaneity. ... I name it
  • pure apperception ... or original apperception ... because it is that
  • self-consciousness which can be accompanied by none further. The unity
  • of it I also call the transcendental unity of self-consciousness, in
  • order to denote the possibility of cognition _à priori_ from it.'
  • P. 92, § 44. _Caput mortuum:_ a term of the Alchemists to denote the
  • non-volatile precipitate left in the retort after the spirit had been
  • extracted: the fixed or dead remains, 'quando spiritus animam sursum
  • vexit.'
  • P. 92, § 45. Reason and Understanding. In the Wolfian School (_e.g._
  • in Baumgarten's _Metaphysik,_ § 468) the term intellect (Verstand)
  • is used of the general faculty of higher cognition, while _ratio_
  • (Vernunft) specially denotes the power of seeing distinctly the
  • connexions of things. So Wolff (_Vernünftige Gedanken von Gott, &c._ §
  • 277) defines Verstand as 'the faculty of distinctly representing the
  • possible,' and Vernunft (§ 368) as 'the faculty of seeing into the
  • connexion of truths.' It is on this use of _Reason_ as the faculty of
  • inference that Kant's use of the term is founded: though it soon widely
  • departs from its origin. For upon the 'formal' use of reason as the
  • faculty of syllogising, Kant superinduces a transcendental use as a
  • 'faculty of _principles_,' while the understanding is only 'a faculty
  • of _rules.'_ 'Reason,' in other words, 'itself begets conceptions,'
  • and 'maxims, which it borrows neither from the senses nor from the
  • understanding.' (_Kritik d. r. Vern., Dialektik,_ Einleit. ii. A.) And
  • the essential aim of Reason is to give unity to the various cognitions
  • of understanding. While the unity given by understanding is 'unity of
  • a possible experience,' that sought by reason is the discovery of an
  • unconditioned which will complete the unity of the former (_Dial._
  • Einleit. iv), or of 'the totality of the conditions to a given
  • conditioned.' (_Dial,_ vii.)
  • It is this distinction of the terms which is dominant in Fichte and
  • Hegel, where Verstand is the more practical intellect which seeks
  • definite and restricted results and knowledges, while Vernunft is
  • a deeper and higher power which aims at completeness. In Goethe's
  • more reflective prose we see illustrations of this usage: _e.g.
  • Wilh. Meister's Wanderjahre,_ i. it is said to be the object of
  • the 'reasonable' man 'das entgegengesetzte zu überschauen und in
  • Uebereinstimmung zu bringen': or Bk. ii. Reasonable men when they have
  • devised something verständig to get this or that difficulty out of the
  • way, &c. Goethe, in his _Sprüche in Prosa_ (896), _Werke,_ iii. 281,
  • says 'Reason has for its province the thing in process (das Werdende),
  • understanding the thing completed (das Gewordene): the former does not
  • trouble itself about the purpose, the latter asks not whence. Reason
  • takes delight in developing; understanding wishes to keep everything as
  • it is, so as to use it.' (Similarly in Eckermann's Convers. Feb. 13,
  • 1829.) Cf. Oken, Naturphilosophie, § 2914. Verstand ist Microcosmus,
  • Vernunft Macrocosmus.
  • Kant's use of the term Reason, coupled with his special view of
  • Practical Reason and his use of the term Faith (Glaube), leads on to
  • the terminology of Jacobi. In earlier writings Jacobi had insisted on
  • the contrast between the superior authority of feeling and faith (which
  • are in touch with truth) and the mechanical method of intelligence and
  • reasoning (Verstand and Vernunft). At a later period however he changed
  • and fixed the nomenclature of his distinction. What he had first called
  • Glaube he latterly called Vernunft,--which is in brief a 'sense for
  • the supersensible'--an intuition giving higher and complete or total
  • knowledge--an immediate apprehension of the real and the true. As
  • contrasted with this reasonable faith or feeling, he regards Verstand
  • as a mere faculty of inference or derivative knowledge, referring one
  • thing to another by the rule of identity.
  • This distinction which is substantially reproduced by Coleridge
  • (though with certain clauses that show traces of Schellingian
  • influence) has connexions--like so much else in Jacobi--with the
  • usage of Schopenhauer, 'Nobody,' says Jacobi, 'has ever spoken of an
  • animal Vernunft: a mere animal Verstand however we all know and speak
  • of.' (Jacobi's _Werke,_ iii. 8.) Schopenhauer repeats and enforces
  • the remark. All animals possess, says Schopenhauer, the power of
  • apprehending causality, of cognising objects: a power of immediate and
  • intuitive knowledge of real things: this is Verstand. But Vernunft,
  • which is peculiar to man, is the cognition of _truth_ (not of reality):
  • it is an abstract judgment with a sufficient reason (_Welt als W._ i. §
  • 6).
  • One is tempted to connect the modern distinction with an older one
  • which goes back in its origin to Plato and Aristotle, but takes form in
  • the Neo-Platonist School, and enters the Latin world through Boëthius.
  • _Consol. Phil._ iv. 6: _Igitur uti est ad intellectum ratiocinatio,
  • ad id quod est id quod gignitur, ad aeternitatem tempus,_ and in v.
  • 4 there is a full distinction of _sensus, imaginatio, ratio_ and
  • _intelligentia_ in ascending order. _Ratio_ is the discursive knowledge
  • of the idea (_universali consideratione perpendit): intelligentia_
  • apprehends it at once, and as a simple _forma (pura mentis acie
  • contuetur)_: [cf. Stob. _Ed._ i. 826-832: Porphyr. _Sentent._15].
  • Reasoning belongs to the human species, just as intelligence to the
  • divine alone. Yet it is assumed--in an attempt to explain divine
  • foreknowledge and defend freedom--that man may in some measure place
  • himself on the divine standpoint (v. 5).
  • This contrast between a higher mental faculty (_mens_) and a lower
  • (_ratio_) which even Aquinas adopts from the interpretation of
  • Aristotle (_Summa Theol._ i. 79, 9) is the favourite weapon in the
  • hands of mysticism. After the example of Dionysius Areop., Nicolaus of
  • Cusa, Reuchlin, and other thinkers of the Renaissance depreciate mere
  • discursive thought and logical reasoning. It is the inner _mens_--like
  • a simple ray of light--penetrating by an immediate and indivisible
  • act to the divine--which gives us access to the supreme science. This
  • _simplex intelligentia,--_ superior to imagination or reasoning--as
  • Gerson says, _Consid. de Th._ 10, is sometimes named _mens,_ sometimes
  • _Spiritus,_ the light of intelligence, the shadow of the angelical
  • intellect, the divine light. From Scotus Erigena to Nicolas of Cusa
  • one tradition is handed down: it is taken up by men like Everard Digby
  • (in his _Theoria Analytica_) and the group of Cambridge Platonists and
  • by Spinoza in the seventeenth century, and it reappears, profoundly
  • modified, in the German idealism between 1790 and 1820.
  • P. 99, § 48. 'Science of Logic'; Hegel's large work on the subject,
  • published between 1812-16. The discussions on the Antinomies belong
  • chiefly to the first part of it.
  • P. 102, § 50. 'Natural Theology,' here to be taken in a narrower sense
  • than in p. 73, where it is equivalent to Rational Theology in general.
  • Here it means 'Physico-theology'--the argument from design in nature.
  • P. 103, § 50. Spinoza--defining God as 'the union of thought with
  • extension.' This is not verbally accurate; for according to _Ethica,_
  • i. pr. 11, God, or the substance, consists of infinite attributes,
  • each of which expresses the eternal and infinite essence. But Spinoza
  • mentions of 'attributes' only two: _Ethica,_ ii. pr. 1. I Thought is
  • an attribute of God: pr. 2, Extension is an attribute of God. And he
  • adds, _Ethica,_ i. pr. 10, Schol. 'All the attributes substance has
  • were always in it together, nor can one be produced by another.' And
  • in _Ethica,_ ii. 7. Sch. it is said: 'Thinking substance and extended
  • substance is one and the same substance which is comprehended now under
  • this, now under that attribute.'
  • P. 110, § 54. 'Practical in the true sense of the word.' Cf. Kant,
  • _Werke,_ Ros. and Sch. i. 581: 'A great misunderstanding, exerting an
  • injurious influence on scientific methods, prevails with regard to what
  • should be considered "practical" in such sense as to justify its place
  • in practical philosophy. Diplomacy and finance, rules of economy no
  • less than rules of social intercourse, precepts of health and dietetic
  • of the soul no less than the body, have been classed as practical
  • philosophy on the mere ground that they all contain a collection of
  • practical propositions. Hut although such practical propositions
  • differ in mode of statement from the theoretical propositions which
  • have for import the possibility of things and the exposition of their
  • nature, they have the same content. "Practical," properly so called,
  • are only those propositions which relate to _Liberty_ under laws. All
  • others whatever are nothing but the theory of what pertains to the
  • _nature_ of things--only that theory is brought to bear on the way in
  • which the things may be produced by us in conformity with a principle;
  • _i.e._ the possibility of the things is presented as the result of
  • a voluntary action which itself too may be counted among physical
  • causes.' And Kant, _Werke,_ iv. 10. 'Hence a sum of practical precepts
  • given by philosophy does not form a special part of it (co-ordinate
  • with the theoretical) merely because they are practical. Practical
  • they might be, even though their principle were wholly derived from
  • the theoretical knowledge of nature,--as _technico-practical_ rules.
  • They are practical in the true sense, when and because their principle
  • is not borrowed from the nature-conception (which is always sensuously
  • conditioned) and rests therefore on the supersensible, which the
  • conception of liberty alone makes knowable by formal laws. They are
  • therefore ethico-practical, _i.e._ not merely _precepts and rules_ with
  • this or that intention, but laws without antecedent reference to ends
  • and intentions.'
  • P. 111, § 54. Eudaemonism. But there is Eudaemonism and Eudaemonism;
  • as Cf. Hegel, _Werke,_ i. 8. 4 The time had come when the infinite
  • longing away beyond the body and the world had reconciled itself
  • with the reality of existence. Yet the reality which the soul was
  • reconciled to--the objective which the subjectivity recognised--was
  • actually only empirical existence, common world and actuality.... And
  • though the reconciliation was in its heart and ground sure and fast,
  • it still needed an objective form for this ground: the very necessity
  • of nature made the blind certitude of immersion in the reality of
  • empirical existence seek to provide itself with a justification and a
  • good conscience. This reconciliation for consciousness was found in the
  • Happiness-doctrine: the fixed point it started from being the empirical
  • subject, and what it was reconciled to, the vulgar actuality, whereon
  • it might now confide, and to which it might surrender itself without
  • sin. The profound coarseness and utter vulgarity, which is at the basis
  • of this happiness-doctrine, has its only elevation in its striving
  • after justification and a good conscience, which however can get no
  • further than the objectivity of mere intellectualism.
  • 'The dogmatism of eudaemonism and of popular philosophy (Aufklärung)
  • therefore did not consist in the fact that it made happiness and
  • enjoyment the supreme good. For if Happiness be comprehended as an
  • _Idea,_ it ceases to be something empirical and casual--as also to be
  • anything sensuous. In the supreme existence, reasonable act (Thun) and
  • supreme enjoyment are one. So long as supreme blessedness is supreme
  • _Idea_ it matters not whether we try to apprehend the supreme existence
  • on the side of its ideality,--which, as isolated may be first called
  • reasonable act--or on the side of its reality--which as isolated may
  • be first called enjoyment and feeling. For reasonable act and supreme
  • enjoyment, ideality and reality are both alike in it and identical.
  • Every philosophy has only one problem--to construe supreme blessedness
  • as supreme Idea. So long as it is by reason that supreme enjoyment is
  • ascertained, the distinguishability of the two at once disappears:
  • for this comprehension and the infinity which is dominant in act, and
  • the reality and finitude which is dominant in enjoyment, are taken up
  • into one another. The controversy with happiness becomes a meaningless
  • chatter, when happiness is known as the blessed enjoyment of the
  • eternal intuition. But what was called eudaemonism meant--it must
  • be said--an empirical happiness, an enjoyment of sensation, not the
  • eternal intuition and blessedness.'
  • P. 112, § 55. Schiller. _Ueber die aesthetische Erziehung des
  • Menschen_(1795), 18th letter. 'Through beauty the sensuous man is led
  • to form and to thought; through beauty the intellectual man is led back
  • to matter and restored to the sense-world. Beauty combines two states
  • which are opposed to one another.' Letter 25. 'We need not then have
  • any difficulty about finding a way from sensuous dependence to moral
  • liberty, after beauty has given a case where liberty can completely
  • co-exist with dependence, and where man in order to show himself an
  • intelligence need not make his escape from matter. If--as the fact
  • of beauty teaches--man is free even in association with the senses,
  • and if--as the conception necessarily involves--liberty is something
  • absolute and supersensible, there can no longer be any question how
  • he comes to elevate himself from limitations to the absolute: for
  • in beauty this has already come to pass.' Cf. _Ueber Anmuth und
  • Würde_(1793). 'It is in a beautiful soul, then, that sense and reason,
  • duty and inclination harmonize; and grace is their expression in the
  • appearance. Only in the service of a beautiful soul can nature at the
  • same time possess liberty.' (See Bosanquet's _History of Aesthetic._)
  • P. 115, § 60. The quotation in the note comes from § 87 of the _Kritik
  • der Urtheilskraft_ (_Werke,_ ed. Ros. and Sch. iv. 357).
  • P. 120, § 60. Fichte, _Werke,_ i. 279. 'The principle of life and
  • consciousness, the ground of its possibility, is (as has been shown)
  • certainly contained in the Ego: yet by this means there arises no
  • actual life, no empirical life in time--and another life is for us
  • utterly unthinkable. If such an actual life is to be possible, there
  • is still needed for that a special impulse (Aufstoss) striking the
  • Ego from the Non-ego. According to my system, therefore, the ultimate
  • ground of all actuality for the Ego is an original action and re-action
  • between the Ego and something outside it, of which all that can be said
  • is that it must be completely opposed to the Ego. In this reciprocal
  • action nothing is brought into the Ego, nothing foreign imported;
  • everything that is developed from it _ad infinitum_ is developed from
  • it solely according to its own laws. The Ego is merely put in motion by
  • that opposite, so as to act; and without such a first mover it would
  • never have acted; and, as its existence consists merely in action, it
  • would not even have existed. But the source of motion has no further
  • attributes than to set in motion, to be an opposing force which as such
  • is only felt.
  • 'My philosophy therefore is realistic. It shows that the consciousness
  • of finite natures cannot at all be explained, unless we assume a force
  • existing independently of them, and completely opposed to them;--on
  • which as regards their empirical existence they are dependent. But
  • it asserts nothing further than such an opposed force, which is
  • merely _felt,_ but not _cognised,_ by finite beings. All possible
  • specifications of this force or non-ego, which may present themselves
  • _ad infinitum_ in our consciousness, my system engages to deduce from
  • the specifying faculty of the Ego....
  • 'That the finite mind must necessarily assume outside it something
  • absolute (a Ding:an:sich), and yet must on the other hand acknowledge
  • that this something only exists for the mind (is a necessary noümenon):
  • this is the circle which may be infinitely expanded, but from which the
  • finite mind can never issue.' Cf. Fichte's _Werke,_ i. 248, ii. 478.
  • CHAPTER V.
  • P. 121, § 62. F. H. Jacobi (_Werke,_ v. 82) in his _Woldemar_ (a
  • romance contained in a series of letters, first published _as a whole_
  • in 1781) writes: 'The philosophical understanding (Verstand) is jealous
  • of everything unique, everything immediately certain which makes itself
  • true, without proofs, solely by its existence. It persecutes this
  • faith of reason even into our inmost consciousness, where it tries to
  • make us distrust the feeling of our identity and personality.' 'What
  • is absolutely and intrinsically true,' he adds (v. 122), 'is not got
  • by way of reasoning and comparison: both our immediate consciousness
  • (Wissen)--I am--and our conscience (Gewissen) are the work of a secret
  • something in which heart, understanding, and sense combine.' 'Notions
  • (Begriffe), far from embalming the living, really turn it into a
  • corpse' (v. 380).
  • Cf. Fichte's words (_Werke,_ ii. 255), Aus dem Gewissen allein stammt
  • die Wahrheit, &c.
  • P. 122, § 62. The Letters on the doctrine of Spinoza, published in
  • 1785, were re-issued in 1789 with eight supplements.
  • 'A science,' says Jacobi in his latest utterance (_Werke,_ iv. pref.
  • xxx.) 'is only a systematic register of cognitions mutually referring
  • to one another--the first and last point in the series is wanting.'
  • P. 123, § 62. Lalande's dictum is referred to by Fries (_Populäre
  • Vorlesungen über Sternkunde,_ 1813) quoted by Jacobi in his _Werke,_
  • ii. 55. What Lalande has actually written in the preface to his work on
  • astronomy is that the science as he understands it has no relation to
  • natural theology--in other words, that he is not writing a Bridgewater
  • treatise.
  • P. 123, § 63. Jacobi, _Werke,_ ii. 222. 'For my part, I regard the
  • principle of reason as all one with the principle of life.' And ii.
  • 343: 'Evidently reason is the true and proper life of our nature.'
  • It is in virtue of our inner tendency and instinct towards the
  • eternal (Richtung und Trieb auf das Ewige),--of our sense for the
  • supersensible--that we, human beings, really subsist (iv. 6. 152). And
  • this Organ der Vernehmung des Uebersinnlichen is Reason (iii. 203, &c).
  • The language of Jacobi fluctuates, not merely in words, but in the
  • intensity of his intuitionalism. Thus, _e.g._ iii. 32: 'The reason man
  • has is no faculty giving the science of the true, but only a presage'
  • (Ahndung des Wahren). 'The belief in a God,' he says, at one time (iii.
  • 206) 'is as natural to man as his upright position': but that belief
  • is, he says elsewhere, only 'an inborn devotion (Andacht) before an
  • unknown God.' Thus, if we have an immediate awareness (Wissen) of
  • God, this is not knowledge or science (Wissenschaft). Such intuition
  • of reason is described (ii. 9) as 'the faculty of _presupposing_ the
  • intrinsically (an sich) true, good, and beautiful, with full confidence
  • in the objective validity of the presupposition.' But that object we
  • are let see only in feeling (ii. 61). 'Our philosophy,' he says (iii.
  • 6) 'starts from feeling--of course an objective and pure feeling.'
  • P. 124, § 63. Jacobi (_Werke,_ iv. a, p. 211): 'Through faith (Glaube)
  • we know that we have a body.' Such immediate knowledge of our own
  • activity--'the feeling of I am, I act' (iii. 411)--the sense of
  • 'absolute self-activity' or freedom (of which the 'possibility cannot
  • be cognised,' because logically a contradiction) is what Jacobi calls
  • Anschauung (Intuition). He distinguishes a sensuous, and a rational
  • intuition (iii. 59).
  • P. 125, § 63. Jacobi expressly disclaims identification of his Glaube
  • with the faith of Christian doctrine (_Werke,_ iv. a, p. 210). In
  • defence he quotes from Hume, Inquiry V, and from Reid, passages to
  • illustrate his usage of the term 'belief--by the distinction between
  • which and faith certain ambiguities are no doubt avoided.
  • P. 129, § 66. Kant had said _'Concepts without intuitions are empty'_
  • It is an exaggeration of this half-truth (the other half is _Intuitions
  • without concepts are blind_) that is the basis of these statements of
  • Jacobi (and of Schopenhauer)--a view of which the following passage
  • from Schelling (_Werke,_ ii. 125) is representative. 'Concepts
  • (Begriffe) are only silhouettes of reality. They are projected by
  • a serviceable faculty, the understanding, which only comes into
  • action when reality is already on the scene,--which only comprehends,
  • conceives, retains what it required a creative faculty to produce....
  • The mere concept is a word without meaning.... All reality that can
  • attach to it is lent to it merely by the intuition (Anschauung) which
  • preceded it. ... Nothing is real for us except what is _immediately
  • given_ us, without any mediation by concepts, without our feeling at
  • liberty. But nothing reaches us immediately except through intuition.'
  • He adds, however, 'Intuition is due to the activity of mind (Sein):
  • it demands a disengaged sense (freier Sinn) and an intellectual organ
  • (geistiges Organ).'
  • P. 134. Cicero: _De Natura Deorum,_ i. 16; ii. 4, _De quo autem omnium
  • natura consentit, id verum esse necesse est_; cf. Seneca, Epist. cxvii.
  • 6. The principle is common to Stoics and Epicureans: it is the maxim
  • of Catholic truth _Quod semper, quod ubique, quod ab omnibus creditum
  • est_--equivalent to Aristotle's ὄ πᾶσι δοκεῖ, τοῦτ' εἷναι φάμεν--But as
  • Aristotle remarks (_An. Post._ i. 31) τὸ καθόλον καὶ ἐπὶ πᾶσιν ἀδίνατον
  • αἰσθάνεσθαι.
  • Jacobi: _Werke,_ vi. 145. 'The general opinion about what is true and
  • good must have an authority equal to reason.'
  • P. 136, § 72. Cf. _Encyclop._ § 400: 'That the heart and the feeling
  • is not the form by which anything is justified as religious, moral,
  • true, and just, and that an appeal to heart and feeling either means
  • nothing or means something bad, should hardly need enforcing. Can any
  • experience be more trite than that hearts and feelings are also bad,
  • evil, godless, mean, &c.? Ay, that the heart is the source of such
  • feelings only, is directly said in the words: Out of the heart proceed
  • evil thoughts, &c. In times when the heart and the sentiment are, by
  • scientific theology and philosophy, made the criterion of goodness,
  • religion, and morality, it is necessary to recall these trivial
  • experiences.'
  • CHAPTER VI.
  • P. 145, § 80. Goethe; the reference is to _Werke,_ ii. 268 (Natur und
  • Kunst):
  • Wer Groszes will, muß sich zusammenraffen:
  • In der Beschränkung zeigt sich erst der Meister,
  • Und das Gesetz nur kann uns Freiheit geben.
  • Such 'limitation' of aim and work is a frequent lesson in _Wilhelm
  • Meister's Wanderjahre, e.g._ i. ch. 4. 'Many-sidedness prepares,
  • properly speaking, only the element in which the one-sided can act....
  • The best thing is to restrict oneself to a handi-work.' And i. ch. 12:
  • 'To be acquainted with and to exercise one thing rightly gives higher
  • training than mere tolerableness (halfness) in a hundred sorts of
  • things.' And ii. ch. 12: 'Your general training and all establishments
  • for the purpose are fool's farces.'
  • P. 147, § 81. Cf. Fichte, _Werke,_ ii. 37. 'Yet it is not _we_ who
  • analyse: but knowledge analyses itself, and can do so, because in all
  • its being it is a _for-self_ (Für:sich),' &c.
  • P. 149, § 81. Plato, the inventor of Dialectic. Sometimes on the
  • authority of Aristotle, as reported by _Diog. Laert._ ix. 25, Zeno of
  • Elea gets this title; but Hegel refers to such statements as _Diog.
  • Laer,',_ ii. 34 τρίτον δὲ Πλάτων προσέθηκε τὸν διαλεκτικὸν λόγον, καὶ
  • ἐτελεσιουργῆσε φιλοσοφίαν.
  • Protagoras. But it is rather in the dialogue _Meno,_ pp. 81-97,
  • that Plato exhibits this view of knowledge. Cf. _Phaedo,_72 E, and
  • _Phaedrus,_ 245.
  • Parmenides; especially see Plat. _Parmen._ pp. 142, 166; cf. Hegel,
  • _Werke,_ xi v. 204.
  • With Aristotle dialectic is set in contrast to apodictic, and treated
  • as (in the modern sense) a quasi-inductive process (Ar. _Top._ Lib.
  • viii.): with the Stoics, dialectic is the name of the half-rhetorical
  • logic which they, rather than Aristotle, handed on to the schoolmen of
  • the Middle Ages.
  • P. 150, § 81. The physical elements are fire, air, earth, and water.
  • Earthquakes, storms, &c, are examples of the 'meteorological process.'
  • Cf. _Encyclop._ §§ 281-289.
  • P. 152, § 82. Dialectic; cf: _Werke,_ v. 326 seqq.
  • P. 154, § 82. Mysticism; cf. Mill's _Logic,_ bk. v, ch. 3, § 4:
  • 'Mysticism is neither more nor less than ascribing objective existence
  • to the subjective creations of the mind's own faculties, to mere ideas
  • of the intellect; and believing that by watching and contemplating
  • these ideas of its own making, it can read in them what takes place in
  • the world without.' Mill thus takes it as equivalent to an ontological
  • mythology--probably a rare use of the term.
  • CHAPTER VII.
  • P. 156, § 85. The Absolute. The term, in something like its modern
  • usage, is at least as old as Nicolaus Cusanus. God, according to him,
  • is the _absoluta omnium quidditas (Apol._406), the _esse absolutum,_ or
  • _ipsum esse in existentibus_ (_De ludo Globi,_ ii. 161 a), the _unum
  • absolutum,_ the _vis absoluta,_ or _possibilitas absoluta,_ or _valor
  • absolutus: absoluta vita, absoluta ratio: absoluta essendi forma._ On
  • this term and its companion _infinities_ he rings perpetual changes.
  • But its distinct employment to denote the 'metaphysical God' is much
  • more modern. In Kant, _e.g._ the 'Unconditioned' (Das Unbedingte)
  • is the metaphysical, corresponding to the religious, conception of
  • deity; and the same is the case with Fichte, who however often makes
  • use of the adjective 'absolute.' It is with Schelling that the term
  • is naturalised in philosophy: it already appears in his works of 1793
  • and 1795: and from him apparently it finds its way into Fichte's
  • _Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre_ of 1801 (_Werke,_ ii. 13) 'The
  • absolute is neither knowing nor being; nor is it identity, nor is it
  • indifference of the two; but it is throughout merely and solely the
  • absolute.'
  • The term comes into English philosophical language through Coleridge
  • and later borrowers from the German. See Ferrier's _Institutes of
  • Metaphysic,_ Prop. xx, and Mill's _Examination of Hamilton,_ chap. iv.
  • P. 158, § 86. Cf. Schelling, iii. 372: I = I expresses the identity
  • between the 'I,' in so far as it is the producing, and the 'I' as the
  • produced; the original synthetical and yet identical proposition: the
  • _cogito=sum_ of Schelling.
  • P. 159. Definition of God as _Ens realissimum, e.g._ Meier's
  • _Baumgarten's Metaphysic,_ § 605.
  • Jacobi, _Werke,_ iv. 6, thus describes Spinoza's God.
  • As to the beginning cf. Fichte, _Werke,_ ii. 14 (speaking of 'absolute
  • knowing'): 'It is not a knowing of something, nor is it a knowing of
  • nothing (so that it would be a knowing of somewhat, but this somewhat
  • be nothing): it is not even a knowing of itself, for it is no knowledge
  • at all _of_;--nor is it _a_ knowing (quantitatively and in relation),
  • but it is (the) knowing (absolutely qualitatively). It is no act, no
  • event, or that somewhat is in knowing; but it is just the knowing, in
  • which alone all acts and all events, which are there set down, can be
  • set down.'
  • History of Philosophy; cf. Hegel, _Werke,_ i. 165. 'If the Absolute,
  • like its phenomenon Reason, be (as it is) eternally one and the same,
  • then each reason, which has turned itself upon and cognised itself,
  • has produced a true philosophy and solved the problem which, like its
  • solution, is at all times the same. The reason, which cognises itself,
  • has in philosophy to do only with itself: hence in itself too lies
  • its whole work and its activity; and as regards the inward essence of
  • philosophy there are neither predecessors nor successors.
  • 'Just as little, as of constant improvements, can there be talk of
  • "peculiar views" of philosophy.... The true peculiarity of a philosophy
  • is the interesting individuality, in which reason has organised itself
  • a form from the materials of a particular age; in it the particular
  • speculative reason finds spirit of its spirit, flesh of its flesh; it
  • beholds itself in it as one and the same, as another living being.
  • Each philosophy is perfect in itself, and possesses totality, like a
  • work of genuine art. As little as the works of Apelles and Sophocles,
  • if Raphael and Shakespeare had known them, could have seemed to them
  • mere preliminary exercises for themselves--but as cognate spiritual
  • powers;--so little can reason in its own earlier formations perceive
  • only useful preparatory exercises.' Cf. Schelling, iv. 401.
  • P. 160, § 86. Parmenides (ap. Simplic. _Phys._): of the two ways of
  • investigation the first is that _it is,_ and that not-to-be is not.
  • ἡ μὲν ὅπως ἓστι τε καὶ ὡς οὐκ ἓστι μὴ εἶναι
  • P. 161, § 87. The Buddhists. Cf. Hegel, _Werke,_ xi. 387. Modern
  • histories of Buddhism insist upon the purely ethico-religious character
  • of the teaching. Writers like von Hartmann (_Religionsphilosophie,_ p.
  • 320) on the contrary hold that Buddhism carried out the esoteric theory
  • of Brahmanism to the consequence that the abstract one is nothing.
  • According to Vassilief, _Le Bouddhisme,_ p. 318 seqq., one of the
  • Buddhist metaphysical schools, the Madhyamikas, founded by Nâgârdjuna
  • 400 years after Buddha, taught that All is Void.--Such metaphysics were
  • probably reactions of the underlying Brahmanist idea.
  • But generally Buddhism (as was not unnatural 60 years ago) is hardly
  • taken here in its characteristic historical features.
  • P. 167, § 88. Aristotle, _Phys,_ i. 8 (191 a. 26): 'Those philosophers
  • who first sought the truth and the real substance of things got on a
  • false track, like inexperienced travellers who fail to discover the
  • way, and declared that nothing can either come into being or disappear,
  • because it is necessary that what comes into being should come into
  • being either from what is or from what is not, and that it is from both
  • of these impossible: for what is does not become (it already is), and
  • nothing would become from what is not.'
  • (5) is an addition of ed. 3 (1830); cf. _Werke,_ xvii. 181.
  • P. 168, § 88. The view of Heraclitus here taken is founded on the
  • interpretation given by Plato (in the _Theaetetus,_152; _Cratylus,_
  • 401) and by Aristotle, of a fundamental doctrine of the Ephesian--which
  • however is expressed in the fragments by the name of the everliving
  • fire. The other phrase (Ar. _Met._ i. 4) is used by Aristotle to
  • describe the position, not of Heraclitus, but of Leucippus and
  • Democritus. Cf. Plutarch, _adv. Colotem,_ 4. 2 Δημόκριτος διορίζεται μὴ
  • μᾱλλον τὸ δὲν ἥ τὸ μηδν εἶναι; cf. Simplic. in Ar. _Phys._ fol. 7.
  • P. 169, § 89. Daseyn: Determinate being. Cf. Schelling, i. 209.
  • 'Being (Seyn) expresses the absolute, Determinate being (Daseyn) a
  • conditional, 'positing': Actuality, one conditioned in a definite sort
  • by a definite condition. The single phenomenon in the whole system
  • of the world has _actuality;_ the world of phenomena in general has
  • Daseyn; but the absolutely-posited, the Ego, _is. I am_ is all the Ego
  • can say of itself.'
  • P. 171, § 91. Being-by-self: An:sich:seyn.
  • Spinoza, _Epist._ 50, _figura non aliud quam determinatio et
  • determinatio negatio est._
  • P. 172, § 92. Grenze (limit or boundary), and Schranke (barrier or
  • check) are distinguished in _Werke,_ iii. 128-139 (see Stirling's
  • _Secret of Hegel,_ i. 377 seqq.). Cf. Kant's remark, _Krit. d. r.
  • Vernunft,_ p. 795, that Hume only erschränkt our intellect, ohne ihn zu
  • begrenzen.
  • P. 173, § 92. Plato, _Timaeus,_ c. 35 (formation of the world-soul):
  • 'From the individual and ever-identical essence (ὀυσία) and the
  • divisible which is corporeal, he compounded a third intermediate
  • species of essence.... And taking these, being three, he compounded
  • them all into one form (ἰδέα), adjusting perforce the unmixable nature
  • of the other and the same, and mingling them all with the essence, and
  • making of three one again, he again distributed this total into as many
  • portions as were fitting, but each of them mingled out of the same and
  • the other and the essence.'
  • P. 175, § 94. Philosophy. Cf. Schelling, _Werke,_ ii. 377. 'A various
  • experience has taught me that for most men the greatest obstacle to the
  • understanding and vital apprehension of philosophy is their invincible
  • opinion that its object is to be sought at an infinite distance.
  • The consequence is, that while they should fix their eye on what is
  • present (das Gegenwärtige), every effort of their mind is called out
  • to get hold of an object which is not in question through the whole
  • inquiry.' ... 'The aim of the sublimest science can only be to show the
  • actuality,--in the strictest sense the actuality, the presence, the
  • vital existence (Daseyn)--of a God in the whole of things and in each
  • one.... Here we deal no longer with an extra-natural or supernatural
  • thing, but with the immediately near, the alone-actual to which we
  • ourselves also belong, and in which we are.'
  • P. 177, § 95. Plato's _Philebus,_ ch. xii-xxiii (pp. 23-38): cf.
  • _Werke,_ xiv. 214 seqq.: 'The absolute is therefore what in one unity
  • is finite and infinite.'
  • P. 178. Idealism of Philosophy: cf. Schelling, ii. 67. 'Every
  • philosophy therefore is and remains Idealism; and it is only under
  • itself that it embraces realism and idealism; only that the former
  • Idealism should not be confused with the latter, which is of a merely
  • relative kind.'
  • Hegel, _Werke,_ iii. 163. 'The proposition that the finite is "ideal"
  • constitutes Idealism. In nothing else consists the Idealism of
  • philosophy than in recognising that the finite has no genuine being....
  • The contrast of idealistic and realistic philosophy is therefore of
  • no importance. A philosophy that attributed to finite existences as
  • such a genuine ultimate absolute being would not deserve the name
  • philosophy.... By "ideal" is meant existing as a representation in
  • consciousness: whatever is in a mental concept, idea or imagination is
  • "ideal": "ideal" is just another word for "in imagination,"--something
  • not merely distinct from the real, but essentially not real. The mind
  • indeed is the great idealist: in the sensation, representation, thought
  • of the mind the fact has not what is called _real_ existence; in the
  • simplicity of the Ego such external being is only suppressed, existing
  • _for me,_ and "ideally" in me. This subjective idealism refers only to
  • the representational form, by which an import is mine.'
  • P. 180, § 96. The distinction of nature and mind as real and ideal is
  • especially Schelling's: See _e.g._ his _Einleitung,_ &c. iii. 272. 'If
  • it is the problem of Transcendental Philosophy to subordinate the real
  • to the ideal, it is on the contrary the problem of the philosophy of
  • nature to explain the ideal from the real.'
  • P. 183, § 98. Newton: see _Scholium_ at the end of the _Principia,_ and
  • cf. _Optics,_ iii. qu. 28.
  • Modern Atomism, besides the conception of particles or molecules, has
  • that of mathematical centres of force.
  • Kant, _Werke,_ v. 379 (ed. Rosenk.). 'The general principle of the
  • _dynamic_ of material nature is that all reality in the objects of the
  • external senses must be regarded as moving force: whereby accordingly
  • so-called solid or absolute impenetrability is banished from natural
  • science as a meaningless concept, and repellent force put in its
  • stead; whereas true and immediate attraction is defended against all
  • the subtleties of a self-misconceiving metaphysic and declared to be a
  • fundamental force necessary for the very possibility of the concept of
  • matter.'
  • P. 184, § 98. Abraham Gottheit Kästner (1719-1800), professor
  • forty-four years at Göttingen, enjoyed in the latter half of the
  • eighteenth century a considerable repute, both in literature and in
  • mathematical science. Some of, his epigrams are still quoted.
  • P. 190, § 102. The two 'moments' of number Unity, and Sum (Anzahl),
  • may be compared with the Greek distinction between one and ἀριθμός
  • (cf. Arist. _Phys._ iv. 12 ἐλάχίστος ἀριθμός ἡ δυάς). According
  • to Rosenkranz (_Leben Hegels_) the classification of arithmetical
  • operations often engaged Hegel's research. Note the relation in Greek
  • between λογικόν and λογιστικόν. Cf. Kant's view of the 'synthesis' in
  • arithmetic.
  • P. 193, § 103. Intensive magnitude. Cf. Kant, _Kritik der reinen
  • Vernunft,_ p. 207, on Anticipation of Perception (Wahrnehmung), and p.
  • 414, in application to the question of the soul's persistence.
  • P. 195, § 104. Not Aristotle, but rather Simplicius on the _Physics_
  • of Aristotle, fol. 306: giving Zeno's argument against the alleged
  • composition of the line from a series of points. What you can say of
  • one supposed small real unit, you can say of a smaller, and so on _ad
  • infinitum._ (Cf. Burnet's _Early Greek Philosophy,_ p. 329.)
  • P. 196, § 104. The distinction between imagination and intellect made
  • by Spinoza in _Ep._ xii. (olim xxix.) in _Opp._ ed. Land vol. ii. 40
  • seqq. is analogous to that already noted (p. 402) between _ratio_ and
  • _intellegentia,_ and is connected, as by Boëthius, with the distinction
  • which Plato, _Timaeus,_ 37, draws between eternity (αἰών) and time.
  • The infinite (_Eth._ i. prop. 8. Schol. I) is the 'absolute affirmation
  • of a certain nature's existence,' as opposed to finitude which is
  • really _ex parte negatio._ 'The problem has always been held extremely
  • difficult, if not inextricable, because people did not distinguish
  • between what is concluded to be infinite by its own nature and the
  • force of its definition, and what has no ends, not in virtue of its
  • essence, but in virtue of its cause. It was difficult also because
  • they did not distinguish between what is called infinite because it
  • has no ends, and that whose parts (though we may have a maximum and
  • minimum of it) we cannot equate or explicate by any number. Lastly
  • because they lid not distinguish between what we can only understand
  • (_intelligere,_) but not imagine, and what we can also imagine.'
  • To illustrate his meaning, Spinoza calls attention to the distinction
  • of substance from mode, of eternity from duration. We can 'explicate'
  • the existence only of modes by duration: that of substance, 'by
  • eternity, _i.e._ by an infinite fruition of existence or being' (_per
  • aeternitatem, hoc est, infinitam existendi, sive, invita latinitate,
  • essendi fruitionem._) The attempt therefore to show that extended
  • _substance_ is composed of parts is an illusion,--which arises because
  • we look at quantity 'abstractly or superficially, as we have it in
  • imagination by means of the senses.' So looking at it, as we are liable
  • to do, a quantity will be found divisible, finite, composed of parts
  • and manifold. But if we look at it as it really is,--as a Substance
  • --as it is in the intellect alone--(which is a work of difficulty), it
  • will be found infinite, indivisible, and unique. 'It is only therefore
  • when we abstract duration and quantity from substance, that we use
  • time to determine duration and measure to determine quantity, so as to
  • be able to imagine them. Eternity and substance, on the other hand,
  • are no objects of imagination but only of intellect; and to try to
  • explicate them by such notions as measure, time, and number--which are
  • only modes of thinking or rather of imagining--is no better than to
  • fall into imaginative raving.' 'Nor will even the modes of Substance
  • ever be rightly understood, should they be confounded with this sort
  • of _entia rationis_' (_i.e. modi cogitandi_ subserving the easier
  • retention, explication and _imagination_ of things _understood_)'
  • or aids to imagination. For when we do so, we separate them from
  • substance, and from the mode in which they flow from eternity, without
  • which they cannot be properly understood.' (Cf. Hegel's _Werke,_ i. 63.)
  • The verses from Albr. von Haller come from his poem on Eternity (1736).
  • Hegel seems to quote from an edition before 1776, when the fourth line
  • was added in the stanza as it thus finally stood:--
  • Ich häufe ungeheure Zahlen,
  • Gebürge Millionen auf,
  • Ich welze Zeit auf Zeit und Welt auf Welten hin,
  • Und wenn ich auf der March des endlichen nun bin,
  • Und von der fürchterlichen Höhe
  • Mit Schwindeln wieder nach dir sehe,
  • Ist alle Macht der Zahl, vermehrt mit tausend Malen,
  • Noch nicht ein Theil von dir.
  • Ich tilge sie, und du liegst ganz vor mir.
  • Kant, _Kritik d. r. Vernunft,_ p. 641. 'Even Eternity, however _eerily_
  • sublime may be its description by Haller,' &c.
  • P. 197, § 104. Pythagoras in order of time probably comes between
  • Anaximenes (of Ionia) and Xenophanes (of Elea). But the mathematical
  • and metaphysical doctrines attributed to the Pythagorean are known
  • to us only in the form in which they are represented in Plato and
  • Aristotle, _i.e._ in a later stage of development. The Platonists (cf.
  • Arist. _Met._ i. 6; xi. 1. 12; xii. 1. 7; cf. Plat. _Rep._ p. 510)
  • treated mathematical fact as mid-way between 'sensibles' and 'ideas';
  • and Aristotle himself places mathematics as a science between physical
  • and metaphysical (theological) philosophy.
  • The tradition (referred to p. 198) about Pythagoras is given by
  • Iamblichus, _Vita Pyth._ §115 seqq.: it forms part of the later
  • Neo-Pythagorean legend, which entered literature in the first centuries
  • of the Christian era.
  • P. 201, § 107. Hebrew hymns: _e.g. Psalms_ lxxiv. and civ.; Proverbs
  • viii. and Job xxxviii. _Vetus verbum est,_ says Leibniz (ed. Erdmann,
  • p. 162), _Deum omnia pondere, mensura, numero, fecisse._
  • P. 202, § 108. The antinomy of measure. These logical puzzles
  • are the so-called fallacy of Sorites (a different thing from the
  • chain-syllogism of the logic-books); cf. Cic. _Acad._ ii. 28, 29; _De
  • Divin._ ii. 4--and the φαλακρός cf. Horace, _Epist._ ii. 1-45.
  • CHAPTER VIII.
  • P. 211, § 113. Self-relation--(sich) auf sich beziehen.
  • P. 213, § 115. The 'laws of thought' is the magniloquent title given
  • in the Formal Logic since Kant's day to the principles or maxims
  • (_principia_, Grundsätze) which Kant himself described as 'general and
  • formal criteria of truth.' They include the so-called principle of
  • contradiction, with its developments, the principle of identity and
  • excluded middle: to which, with a desire for completeness, eclectic
  • logicians have added the Leibnizian principle of the reason. Hegel
  • has probably an eye to Krug and Fries in some of his remarks. The
  • three laws may be compared and contrasted with the three principles,
  • --homogeneity, specification, and continuity of forms, in Kant's
  • _Kritik d. r. Vern._ p. 686.
  • P. 217, § 117. Leibniz, _Nouveaux Essais,_ Liv. ii. ch. 27, § 3 (ed.
  • Erdmann, p. 273: cf. fourth Letter to Clarke). _Il n'y a point deux
  • individus indiscernables. Un gentilhomme d'esprit de mes amis, en
  • parlant avec moi en présence de Madame l'Electrice dans le jardin de
  • Herrenhausen, crut qu'il trouverait bien deux feuilles entièrement
  • semblables. Madame l'Electrice l'en défia, et il courut longtems en
  • vain pour en chercher._
  • The principle of individuation or indiscernibility is: 'If two
  • individuals were perfectly alike and equal and, in a word,
  • indistinguishable by themselves, there would be no principle of
  • individuation: (Leibniz, ed. Erdm. p. 277) _Poser deux choses
  • indiscernables est poser la même chose sous deux noms_ (p. 756).
  • _Principium individuationis idem est quod absolutae specificationis quâ
  • res ita sit determinata, ut ab aliis omnibus distingui possit._
  • P. 221, § 119. Polarity. Schelling, ii. 489. 'The law of Polarity is a
  • universal law of nature'; cf. ii. 459: 'It is a first principle of a
  • philosophic theory of nature to have a view (in the whole of nature),
  • on polarity and dualism.' But he adds (476), 'It is time to define
  • more accurately the concept of polarity.' So Oken, _Naturphilosophie_:
  • §76: 'A force consisting of two principles is called Polarity.' § 77:
  • 'Polarity is the first force which makes its appearance in the world.'
  • § 81: 'The original movement is a result of the original polarity.'
  • P. 223, § 119. Cf. Fichte, ii. 53. 'To everything but this the
  • logically trained thinker can rise. He is on his guard against
  • contradiction. But, in that case, how about the possibility of the
  • maxim of his own logic that we can think no contradiction. In some way
  • he must have got hold of contradiction and thought it, or he could
  • make no communications about it. Had such people only once regularly
  • asked themselves how they came to think the _merely_ possible or
  • contingent (the not-necessary), and how they actually do so! Evidently
  • they here leap through a not-being, not-thinking, &c, into the utterly
  • unmediated, self-initiating, free,--into beënt non-being,--in short,
  • the above contradiction, as it was laid down. With consistent thinkers
  • the result of this incapacity is nothing but the utter abolition of
  • freedom,--the most absolute fatalism and Spinozism.
  • P. 227, §121. Leibniz (ed. Erdmann, p. 515). 'The principle of _la
  • raison déterminante_ is that nothing ever occurs without there being a
  • cause for it, or at least a determinant reason, _i.e._ something which
  • may serve to render a reason _à priori_ why that is existent rather
  • than in any other way. This great principle holds good in all events.'
  • Cf. p. 707. 'The principle of "sufficient reason" is that in virtue
  • of which we consider that no fact could be found true or consistent,
  • no enunciation truthful, without there being a sufficient reason why
  • it is so and not otherwise.... When a truth is necessary, we can find
  • the reason of it by analysis, resolving it into simpler ideas and
  • truths, until we come to primitive ideas.... But the sufficient reason
  • ought also to be found in contingent truths or truths of fact, _i.e._
  • in the series of things spread through the universe of creatures,
  • or the resolution into particular reasons might go into a limitless
  • detail: ... and as all this detail embraces only other antecedent, or
  • more detailed contingencies, ... the sufficient or final (_dernière_)
  • reason must be outside the succession or series of this detail of
  • contingencies, however infinite it might be. And it is thus that the
  • final reason of things must be in a "necessary substance," in which the
  • detail of the changes exists only _eminenter,_ as in the source,--and
  • it is what we call God.' _(Monadology_ §§ 32-38.)
  • Hence the supremacy of final causes. Thus _Opp._ ed. Erdmann, p. 678:
  • _Ita fit ut efficientes causae pendeant a finalibus, et spiritualia
  • sint natura priora materialibus._ Accordingly he urges, p. 155, that
  • final cause has not merely a moral and religious value in ethics and
  • theology, but is useful even in physics for the detection of deep-laid
  • truths. Cf. p. 106: _C'est sanctifier la Philosophie que de faire
  • couler ses ruisseaux de la fontaine des attributs de Dieu. Bien loin
  • d'exclure les causes finales et la considération d'un être agissant
  • avec sagesse, c'est de là qu'il faut tout déduire en Physique._ Cf.
  • also _Principes de la Nature_ (Leibn. ed. Erdm. p. 716): 'It is
  • surprising that by the sole consideration of efficient causes or
  • of matter, we could not render a reason for those laws of movement
  • discovered in our time. _Il y faut recourir aux causes finales_.'
  • P. 228, § 121 Socrates. The antitheses between Socrates and the
  • Sophists belongs in the main to the Platonic dialogues,--not co the
  • historical Socrates. It is the literary form in which the philosophy of
  • Plato works out its development through the criticism of contemporary
  • opinions and doctrines. And even in Plato's writings the antagonism is
  • very unlike what later interpretations have made out of it.
  • P. 231, § 124. Thing by itself (thing in itself) the Ding:an:sich.
  • P. 235, § 126. Cf. _Encycl._ § 334 (_Werke,_ viii. 1. p. 411). 'In
  • empirical chemistry the chief object is the _particularity_ of the
  • matters and products, which are grouped by superficial abstract
  • features which make impossible any system in the special detail. In
  • these lists, metals, oxygen, hydrogen, &c.--metalloids, sulphur,
  • phosphorus appear side by side as _simple_ chemical bodies on the same
  • level. The great physical variety of these bodies must of itself create
  • a prepossession against such coordination; and their chemical origin,
  • the process from which they issue, is clearly no less various. But
  • in an equally chaotic way, more abstract and more real processes are
  • put on the same level. If all this is to get scientific form, every
  • product ought to be determined according to the grade of the concrete
  • and completely developed process from which it essentially issues, and
  • which gives it its peculiar significance; and for that purpose it is
  • not less essential to distinguish grades in abstractness or reality
  • of the process. Animal and vegetable substances in any case belong
  • to a quite other order: so little can their nature be understood from
  • the chemical process, that they are rather destroyed in it, and only
  • the way of their death is apprehended. These substances, however,
  • ought above all to serve to counter-act the metaphysic predominant
  • in chemistry as in physics,--the ideas or rather wild fancies of the
  • _unalterability of matters_ under all circumstances, as well as the
  • categories of the _composition_ and the _consistence_ of bodies from
  • such matters. We see it generally admitted that chemical matters lose
  • in combination the _properties_ which they show in separation: and yet
  • we find the idea prevailing that they are the same things _without_ the
  • properties as they are _with_ them,--so that as things _with_ these
  • properties they are not results of the process.'--Cf. _Werke,_ vii. a.
  • 372: 'Air does not consist of oxygen and nitrogen: but these are the
  • forms under which air is put,' cf. _ib._403.
  • P. 241, § 131. Fichte's _Sonnenklarer Bericht_ appeared in 1801.
  • P. 247, § 136. Herder's _Gott: Gespräche über Spinoza's System,_ 1787,
  • 2nd ed. 1800. 'God is, in the highest and unique sense of the word,
  • Force, _i.e._ the primal force of all forces, the soul of all souls'
  • (p. 63), 'All that we call matter, therefore, is more or less animate:
  • it is a realm of efficient forces. One force predominates: otherwise
  • there were no _one,_ no whole' (p. 207). 'The supreme being (Daseyn)
  • could give its creatures nothing higher than being. (_Theophron._) But,
  • my friend, being and being, however simple in the concept, are in their
  • estate very different; and what do you suppose, Philolaus, marks its
  • grades and differences? (_Phil._) Nothing but forces. In God himself
  • we found no higher conception; but all his forces were only one. The
  • supreme force could not be other than supreme goodness and wisdom,
  • ever-living, ever-active. (_Theoph._) Now you yourself see, Philolaus,
  • that the supreme, or rather the All (for God is not a supreme unit in
  • a scale of beings like himself), could not reveal himself otherwise
  • than in the universe as active. In him nothing could slumber, and what
  • he expressed was himself. He is before everything, and everything
  • subsists in him: the whole world an expression, an appearance of his
  • ever-living, ever-acting forces' (p. 200).
  • 'It was the mistake of Spinoza,' says Herder, 'to be unduly influenced
  • by the Cartesian phraseology. Had he chosen the conception of force and
  • effect, everything would have gone easier, and his system become much
  • more distinct and coherent. 'Had he developed the conception of power,
  • and the conception of matter, he must in conformity with his system
  • necessarily have come to the conception of forces, which work as well
  • in matter as in organs of thinking: he would in that case have regarded
  • power and thought as forces, _e.g._ as one.' (Cf. H. Spencer, 'Force,
  • the Ultimate of Ultimates.' First Princ. p 169)
  • According to Rosenkranz (_Leben Hegels,_ p. 223) there exists in
  • manuscript a criticism by Hegel on the second edition of Herder's
  • _God._ Herder's Dialogue belongs to the controversy aroused by Jacobi's
  • letters on Spinoza.
  • P. 250, § 136. Newton. Leibniz charges him with the view that God needs
  • from time to time _remonter sa montre,_ otherwise it would cease going:
  • that his machine requires to be cleaned (_décrasser_) by extraordinary
  • aid' (ed. Erdm. p. 746).
  • P. 252, § 140. The verses quoted occur in Goethe's _Werke_ ii. 376,
  • under the heading Allerdings. Originally the first four lines appeared
  • in Haller's poem _Die menschlichen Tugenden_ thus--
  • Ins Innre der Natur bringt sein erschaffner Geist:
  • Zu glücklich, wenn sie noch die äußre Schale weist!
  • (To nature's heart there penetrates no mere created mind:
  • Too happy if she but display the outside of her rind.)
  • Hegel--reading weizt for weist--takes the second line as
  • Too happy, if he can but know the outside of her rind.
  • Goethe's attack upon a vulgar misuse of the lines belongs to his
  • dispute with the scientists. His verses appeared in 1820 as _Heiteres
  • Reimstück_ at the end of Heft 3 _zur Morphologie,_--of which the
  • closing section is entitled _Freundlicher Zuruf_ (_Werke_ xxvii. 161),
  • as follows:--
  • "Ins Innre der Natur,"
  • O du Philister!--
  • "Dringt kein erschaffner Geist."
  • . . . . . .
  • "Glückselig! wem sie nur
  • Die äußre Schale weis't."
  • Das hör' ich sechzig Jahre wiederholen,
  • Ich fluche drauf, aber verstohlen:
  • Sage mir taufend tausendmale:
  • Alles giebt sie reichlich und gern;
  • Natur hat weder Stern
  • Noch Schale,
  • Alles ist sie mit einem Male.
  • [The last seven lines may be thus paraphrased in continuation:
  • I swear--of course but to myself--as rings within my ears
  • That same old warning o'er and o'er again for sixty years,
  • And thus a thousand thousand times I answer in my mind:
  • --With gladsome and ungrudging hand metes nature from her store:
  • She keeps not back the core,
  • Nor separates the rind,
  • But all in each both rind and core has evermore combined.]
  • P. 254, § 140. Plato and Aristotle: cf. Plato, _Phaedrus,_ 247 A
  • (φθόνoς γὰρ ξω θείον χόρoυ ἴσταται); _Timaeus,_ 29 E; and Aristotle,
  • _Metaph._ i. 2. 22.
  • P. 256, § 140. Goethe: _Sämmtl. Werke,_ iii. 203 (_Maxime und
  • Reflexionen_). Gegen große Vorzüge eines Andern giebt es kein
  • Rettungsmittel als die Liebe. Cf. Schiller to Goethe, 2 July, 1796.
  • 'How vividly I have felt on this occasion ... that against surpassing
  • merit nothing but Love gives liberty' (daß es dem Vortrefflichen
  • gegenüber seine Freiheit giebt als die Liebe).
  • 'Pragmatic.' This word, denoting a meddlesome busybody in older English
  • and sometimes made a vague term of abuse, has been in the present
  • century used in English as it is here employed in German.
  • According to Polybius, ix. I. 2, the πραγματικὸς τρόπος τῆς ἱστορίας
  • is that which has a directly utilitarian aim. So Kant, _Foundation of
  • Metaph. of Ethic (Werke,_ viii. 41, note): 'A history is pragmatically
  • composed when it renders prudent, _i.e._ instructs the world how it may
  • secure its advantage better or at least as well as the ages preceding.'
  • Schelling (v. 308) quotes in illustration of pragmatic history-writing
  • the words of Faust to Wagner (Goethe, xi. 26):
  • Was ihr den Geist der Zeiten heisst,
  • Das ist im Grund der herren eigner Geist,,
  • In dem die Zeiten sich bespiegeln.
  • Cf. also Hegel, _Werke,_ ix. 8. 'A second kind of reflectional history
  • is the pragmatic. When we have to do with the past and are engaged
  • with a distant world, the mind sees rising before it a present, which
  • it has from its own action as a reward for its trouble. The events are
  • different; but their central and universal fact, their structural
  • plan is identical. This abolishes the past and makes the event
  • present. Pragmatic reflections, however abstract they be, are thus in
  • reality the present, and vivify the tales of the past with the life of
  • to-day.--Here too a word should specially be given to the moralising
  • and the moral instructions to be gained through history,--for which it
  • was often studied.... Rulers, statesmen, nations, are especially bidden
  • learn from the experience of history. But what experience and history
  • teach is that nations and governments never have learned anything from
  • history, or acted upon teaching which could have been drawn from it.'
  • Cf. Froude: _Divorce of Catherine,_ p. 2. 'The student (of history)
  • looks for an explanation (of political conduct) in elements which he
  • thinks he understands--in pride, ambition, fear, avarice, jealousy, or
  • sensuality.'
  • P. 257, § 141. Cf. Goethe, xxiii, 298. 'What is the outside of an
  • organic nature but the ever-varied phenomenon of the inside? This
  • outside, this surface is so exactly adapted to a varied, complex,
  • delicate, inward structure that it thus itself becomes an inside:
  • both aspects, the outside and the inside, standing in most direct
  • correlation alike in the quietest existence and in the most violent
  • movement.'
  • P. 260, § 143. Kant, _Kritik der reinen Vernunft,_ 2nd ed. p. 266.
  • P. 269, § 147. Cf. Schelling, _Werke,_ v. 290 (cf. iii. 603). 'There
  • are three periods of history, that of nature, of destiny, and of
  • providence. These three ideas express the same identity, but in a
  • different way. Destiny too is providence, but recognised in the real,
  • as providence, is also destiny, but beheld (angeschaut) in the ideal.'
  • P. 275, § 151. On the relation between Spinoza and Leibniz cf. Hegel,
  • _Werke,_ iv. 187-193. It would be a mistake, however, to represent
  • Leibniz as mainly engaged in a work of conscious antagonism to Spinoza.
  • P. 277, § 153. Jacobi.--Jacobi (like Schopenhauer) insists specially on
  • the distinction between grounds (Gründe)--which are formal, logical,
  • and verbal, and causes (Ursachen)--which carry us into reality and
  • life and nature. To transform the mere _Because_ into the _cause_
  • we must (he says) pass from logic and the analytical understanding
  • to experience and the inner life. Instead of the timelessness of
  • simultaneity which characterises the logical relation cf ground and
  • consequent, the nexus of cause and effect introduces the element
  • of time,--thereby acquiring reality (Jacobi, _Werke,_ iii. 452).
  • The conception of Cause--meaningless as a mere category of abstract
  • thought--gets reality as a factor in experience, ein Erfahrungsbegriff,
  • and is immediately given to us in the consciousness of our own
  • causality (Jacobi, _Werke,_ iv. 145-158). Cf. Kant, _Kritik der reinen
  • Vern._ p. 116.
  • P. 283, § 158. The _Amor intellectualis Dei_ (Spinoza, _Eth._ v. 32)
  • is described as a consequence of the third grade of cognition, viz.
  • the _scientia intuitiva_ which 'proceeds from an adequate idea of the
  • formal essence of certain attributes of God to the adequate cognition
  • of the essence of things (ii. 40, Schol. 2). From it arises (v.
  • 27), the highest possible _acquiescentia mentis,_ in which the mind
  • contemplates all things _sub specie aeternitatis_ (v. 29), knows itself
  • to be in God and sees itself and all things in their divine essence.
  • But this intellectual love of mind towards God is part of the infinite
  • love wherewith God loves himself (v. 36) 'From these things we clearly
  • understand in what our salvation or blessedness or liberty consists: to
  • wit, in the constant and eternal love towards God, or in the love of
  • God towards men' (Schol. to v. 36).
  • CHAPTER IX.
  • Page 289, § 161. Evolution and development in the stricter sense
  • in which these terms were originally used in the seventeenth and
  • eighteenth centuries imply a theory of preformation, according
  • to which the growth of an organic being is simply a process of
  • enlarging and filling out a miniature organism, actual but invisible,
  • because too inconspicuous. Such was the doctrine adopted by Leibniz
  • (_Considérations sur le principe de vie; Système nouveau de la Nature_,
  • &c). According to it development is no real generation of new parts,
  • but only an augmentation into bulk and visibility of parts already
  • outlined. This doctrine of preformation (as opposed to epigenesis)
  • is carried out by Charles Bonnet, who in his _Considérations sur les
  • corps organisés_ (1762) propounds the further hypothesis that the
  • 'germs' from which living beings proceed contain, enclosed one within
  • another, the germs of all creatures yet to be. This is the hypothesis
  • of '_Emboîtement._' 'The system which regards generations as mere
  • educts' says Kant (_Kritik der Urteilskraft,_ § 80; _Werke,_ iv. 318)
  • 'is called that of _individual_ preformation or the evolution theory:
  • the system which regards them as products is called Epigenesis.--which
  • might also be called the theory of _generic_ preformation, considering
  • that the productive powers of the générants follow the inherent
  • tendencies belonging to the family characteristics, and that the
  • specific form is therefore a 'virtual' preformation, in this way the
  • opposing theory of individual preformation might be better called
  • the involution theory, or theory of Einschachtelung (_Emboîtement._)
  • Cf. Leibniz (_Werke,_ Erdmann, 715). 'As animals generally are not
  • entirely born at conception or _generation,_ no more do they entirely
  • perish at what we call _death_; for it is reasonable that what does
  • not commence naturally, does not finish either in the order of nature.
  • Thus quitting their mask or their rags, they only return to a subtler
  • theatre, where however they can be as sensible and well regulated as
  • in the greater.... Thus not only the souls, but even the animals are
  • neither generable nor perishable: they are only developed, enveloped,
  • re-clothed, unclothed,--transformed. The souls never altogether quit
  • their body, and do not pass from one body into another body which is
  • entirely new to them. There is therefore no metempsychosis, but there
  • is metamorphosis. The animals change, take and quit only parts: which
  • takes place little by little and by small imperceptible parcels, but
  • continually, in nutrition: and takes place suddenly notably but rarely,
  • at conception, or at death, which make them gain or lose much all at
  • once.'
  • The theory of _Emboîtement_ or _Envelopment,_ according to Bonnet
  • (_Considérations,_ &c. ch. I) is that 'the germs of all the organised
  • bodies of one species were inclosed (_renfermés_) one in another,
  • and have been developed successively.' So according to Haller
  • (_Physiology,_ Tome vii. § 2) 'it is evident that in plants the
  • mother-plant contains the germs of several generations; and there is
  • therefore no inherent improbability in the view that _tous les enfans,
  • excepté un, fussent renfermés dans l'ovaire de la première Fille
  • d'Eve.'_ Cf. Weismann's _Continuity of the Germ-plasma._ Yet Bonnet
  • (_Contemplation de la Nature,_ part vii. ch. 9, note 2), says, 'The
  • germs are not enclosed like boxes or cases one in another, but a germ
  • forms part of another germ, as a grain forms part of the plant in which
  • it is developed.'
  • P. 293, § 163. Rousseau, _Contrat Social,_ liv. ii. ch. 3.
  • P. 296, § 165. The 'adequate' idea is a sub-species of the 'distinct.'
  • When an idea does not merely distinguish a thing from others (when
  • it is _clear),_ or in addition represent the characteristic marks
  • belonging to the object so distinguished (when it is _distinct),_ but
  • also brings out the farther characteristics of these characteristics,
  • the idea is _adequate._ Thus adequate is a sort of second power of
  • distinct. (Cf. Baumeister's _Instit. Philos. Ration._ 1765, §§ 64-94.)
  • Hegel's description rather agrees with the 'complete idea' 'by which
  • I put before my mind singly marks sufficient to discern the thing
  • represented from all other things in every case, state, and time'
  • (Baumeister, _ib._ § 88). But cf. Leibniz, ed. Erdm. p. 79: _notitia
  • adaequata._
  • P. 298, § 166. Cf. Baumeister, _Instit. Phil. Rat._ § 185: _Judicium
  • est idearum conjunctio vel separatio._
  • P. 299, § 166. _Punctum saliens:_ the _punctum sanguineum saliens_ of
  • Harvey (_de Generat. Animal, exercit._ 17), or first appearance of the
  • heart: the _στιγμὴ αἱματίνη_ in the egg, of which Aristotle (_Hist.
  • Anim._ vi. 3) says τoῡτο τὸ σημεῖον πηδᾷ καὶ κινεῖται ὥσπερ ἓμψυχον.
  • P. 301, § 169. Cf. Whately, _Logic_ (Bk. ii. ch. I, § 2), 'Of these
  • terms that which is spoken of is called the _subject;_ that which is
  • said of it, the _predicate._'
  • P. 303, § 171. Kant, _Kritik der reinen Vernunft_ (p. 95, 2nd ed.) § 9.
  • P. 304, § 172. Cf. Jevons, _Principles of Science,_ ch. 3, 'on limited
  • identities' and 'negative propositions.'
  • P. 309. Ear-lobes. The remark is due to Blumenbach: cf. Hegel's
  • _Werke,_ v. 285.
  • P. 312. Colours, _i.e._ painters' colours; cf. _Werke,_ vii. 1. 314
  • (lecture-note). 'Painters are not such fools as to be Newtonians: they
  • have red, yellow, and blue, and out of these they make their other
  • colours.'
  • P. 315, § 181. For the genetic classification of judgments and
  • syllogisms and the passage from the former to the latter compare
  • especially Lotze's _Logic,_ Book i. And for the comprehensive
  • exhibition of the systematic process of judgment and inference see B.
  • Bosanquet's _Logic, or the Morphology of Knowledge._ The passage from
  • Hegel's _Werke,_ v. 139, quoted at the head of that work is parallel to
  • the sentence in p. 318, 'The interest, therefore,' &c.
  • P. 320, § 186. The letters I-P-U, of course, stand for Individual,
  • Particular, and Universal.
  • P. 321, § 187. Fourth figure. This so-called Galenian figure was
  • differentiated from the first figure by the separation of the five
  • moods, which (after Arist. _An._ pr. i. 7 and ii. I) Theophrastus and
  • the later pupils, down at least to Boëthius, had subjoined to the four
  • recognised types of perfect syllogism. But its Galenian origin is more
  • than doubtful.
  • P. 325, § 190. Cf. Mill's _Logic,_ Bk. ii. ch. 3. 'In every syllogism
  • considered as an argument to prove the conclusion there is a _petitio
  • principii._'
  • Hegel's Induction is that strictly so called or complete induction, the
  • argument from the sum of actual experiences--that _per enumerationem
  • simplicem,_ and _διὰ πάντων._ Of course except by accident or by
  • artificial arrangement such completeness is impossible _in rerum
  • natura._
  • P. 326, § 190. The 'philosophy of Nature' referred to here is probably
  • that of Oken and the Schellingians; but later critics (_e.g._ Riehl,
  • _Philosoph. Criticismus,_ iii. 120) have accused Hegel himself of even
  • greater enormities in this department.
  • P. 328, § 192. _Elementarlehre:_ Theory of the Elements, called by
  • Hamilton (_Lectures on Logic,_ i. 65) Stoicheiology as opposed to
  • methodology. Cf. the Port Royal Logic. Kant's _Kritik_ observes the
  • same division of the subject.
  • P. 332, § 193. Anselm, _Proslogium,_ c. 2. In the _Monologium_ Anselm
  • expounds the usual argument from conditioned to unconditioned (_Est
  • igitur unum aliquid, quod solum maxime et summe omnium est; per quod
  • est quidquid est bonum vel magnum, el omnino quidquid aliquid est.
  • Monol._ c. 3). But in the Proslogium he seeks an argument _quod nullo
  • ad se probandum quam se solo indigeret--i.e._ from the conception of
  • (God as) the highest and greatest that can be (_aliquid quo nihil majus
  • cogitari potest_) he infers its being (_sic ergo vere_ EST _aliquid
  • quo majus cogitari non potest, ut nec cogitari possit non esse._) The
  • absolute would not be absolute if the idea of it did not _ipso facto_
  • imply existence.
  • Gaunilo of Marmoutier in the _Liber pro insipiente_ made the objection
  • that the fact of such argument being needed showed that idea and
  • reality were _prima facie_ different. And in fact the argument of
  • Anselm deals with an Absolute which is object rather than subject,
  • thought rather than thinker; in human consciousness realised, but
  • not essentially self-affirming--implicit (an:sich) only, as said in
  • pp. 331, 333. And Anselm admits c. 15 _Domine, non solum es, quo
  • majus cogitari nequit, sed es quiddam majus quam cogitari potest_
  • (transcending our thought).
  • P. 333, line 2. This sentence has been transposed in the translation.
  • In the original it occurs after the quotation from the Latin in p. 332.
  • P. 334, § 194. Leibniz: for a brief account of the Monads see Caird's
  • _Crit. Philosophy of J. Kant,_ i. 86-95.
  • A monad is the simple substance or indivisible unity corresponding
  • to a body. It is as simple what the world is as a multiplicity: it
  • 'represents,' _i.e._ concentrates into unity, the variety of phenomena:
  • is the expression of the material in the immaterial, of the compound in
  • the simple, of the extended outward in the inward. Its unity and its
  • representative capacity go together (cf. Lotze, _Mikrokosmus._) It is
  • the 'present which is full of the future and laden with the past' (ed.
  • Erdm. p. 197); the point which is all-embracing, the totality of the
  • universe. And yet there are monads--in the plural.
  • P. 334, § 194. Fichte, _Werke,_ i. 430. 'Every thorough-going dogmatic
  • philosopher is necessarily a fatalist.'
  • P. 338, § 195. Cf. _Encyclop._ § 463. 'This supreme inwardising of
  • ideation (Vorstellung) is the supreme self-divestment of intelligence,
  • reducing itself to the mere being, the general space of mere names and
  • meaningless words. The ego, which is this abstract being, is, because
  • subjectivity, at the same time the power over the different names, the
  • empty link which fixes in itself series of them and keeps them in fixed
  • order.'
  • Contemporaneously with Hegel, Herbart turned psychology in the line of
  • a 'statics and dynamics of the mind.' See (besides earlier suggestions)
  • his _De Attentionis mensura causisque primariis_ (1822) and his
  • _Ueber die Möglichkeit und Notwendigkeit, Mathematik auf Psychologie
  • anzuwenden_ (1822).
  • P. 340, § 198. _Civil_ society: distinguished as the social
  • and economical organisation of the _bourgeoisie,_ with their
  • particularist-universal aims, from the true universal unity of
  • _citoyens_ in the state or ethico-political organism.
  • P. 345, § 204. Inner design: see Kant's _Kritik der Urtheilskraft,_ §
  • 62.
  • Aristotle, _De Anima,_ ii. 4 (415. b. 7) φανερὸν δ' ὠς καὶ οὗ ἕνεκα ἡ
  • ψυχὴ ατία: ii. 2 ζωὴν λέγομεν τὴν δι' αὑτοῦ τροφήν τε καὶ αὔξησιν καὶ
  • φθίσιν.
  • P. 347, § 206. Neutral first water, cf. _Encyclop._§ 284, 'without
  • independent individuality, without rigidity and intrinsic
  • determination, a thorough-going equilibrium.' Cf. _Werke,_ vii. 6.
  • 168. 'Water is absolute neutrality, not like salt, an individualised
  • neutrality; and hence it was at an early date called the mother of
  • everything particular.' 'As the neutral it is the solvent of acids and
  • alkalis.' Cf. Oken's _Lehrbuch der Naturphilosophie,_ §§ 294 and 432.
  • P. 348, § 206. Conclude = beschliessen: Resolve = entschliessen. Cf.
  • Chr. Sigwart, _Kleine Schriften,_ ii. 115, _seqq._
  • P. 359, § 216. Aristotle, _De Anim. Generat._ i. (726. b. 24) ἡ χεὶρ
  • ἄνεν ψυχικῆς δυνάμεως οὐκ ἔστι χεὶρ ἀλλὰ μόνον ὁμώνυμον.
  • Arist. _Metaph._ viii. 6 (1045. b. 11) ο δὲ (λέγoυσi) σύνθεσιν ἥ
  • σύνδεσμον ψυχῆς σώματι τὸ ζῆν.
  • P. 360, § 218. Sensibility, &c. This triplicity (as partly
  • distinguished by Haller after Glisson) of the functions of organic life
  • is largely worked out in Schelling, ii. 491.
  • P. 361, § 219. Cf. Schelling, ii. 540. As walking is a constantly
  • prevented falling, so life is a constantly prevented extinction of the
  • vital process.
  • P. 367, § 229. Spinoza (_Eth._ i. def. I) defines _causa sui_ as
  • _id cujus essentia involvit existentiam,_ and (in def. 3) defines
  • _substantia_ as _id quod in se est et per se concipitur._
  • Schelling: _e.g. Darstellung meines Systems der Philosophie_ (1801),
  • (_Werke,_ iv. 114): 'I call reason the absolute reason, or reason,
  • in so far as it is thought as total indifference of subjective and
  • objective.'
  • P. 367, § 230. 'Mammals distinguish themselves': unter; unter:scheiden,
  • instead of scheiden: cf. _Werke,_ ii. 181. 'The distinctive marks of
  • animals, _e.g._ are taken from the claws and teeth: for in fact it
  • is not merely cognition which by this means distinguishes one animal
  • from another: but the animal thereby separates itself off: by these
  • weapons it keeps itself to itself and separate from the universal.'
  • Cf. _Werke,_ vii. a. 651 _seqq._ (_Encycl._ § 370) where reference is
  • made to Cuvier, _Recherches sur les ossements fossiles des quadrupèdes_
  • (1812), &c.
  • P. 368, § 230. Kant, _Kritik der Urtheilskraft:_ Einleitung, § 9
  • (note), (_Werke,_ ed. Ros. iv. 39); see Caird's _Critical Philosophy of
  • I. Kant,_ Book i. ch. 5; also Hegel's _Werke,_ ii. 3.
  • P. 369, § 231. An example of Wolfs pedantry is given in Hegel, _Werke,_
  • v. 307, from Wolfs _Rudiments of Architecture,_ Theorem viii. 'A window
  • must be broad enough for two persons to recline comfortably in it, side
  • by side. _Proof._ It is customary to recline with another person on the
  • window to look about. But as the architect ought to satisfy the main
  • views of the owner (§ I) he must make the window broad enough for two
  • persons to recline comfortably side by side.'
  • 'Construction': cf. _Werke,_ ii. 38. 'Instead of its own internal life
  • and spontaneous movement, such a simple mode (as subject, object,
  • cause, substance, &c.) has expression given to it by perception (here
  • = sense-consciousness) on some superficial analogy: and this external
  • and empty application of the formula is called "Construction." The
  • procedure shares the qualities of all such formalism. How stupid-headed
  • must be the man, who could not in a quarter of an hour master the
  • theory of asthenic, sthenic and indirectly asthenic diseases' (this is
  • pointed at Schelling's _Werke,_ iii. 236) 'and the three corresponding
  • curative methods, and who, when, no long time since, such instruction
  • was sufficient, could not in this short period be transformed from
  • a mere practitioner into a "scientific" physician? The formalism of
  • _Naturphilosophie_ may teach _e.g._ that understanding is electricity,
  • or that the animal is nitrogen, or even that it is _like_ the South or
  • the North, or that it represents it,--as baldly as is here expressed
  • or with greater elaboration in terminology. At such teachings the
  • inexperienced may fall into a rapture of admiration, may reverence the
  • profound genius it implies,--may take delight in the sprightliness
  • of language which instead of the abstract _concept_ gives the more
  • pleasing _perceptual_ image, and may congratulate itself on feeling its
  • soul akin to such splendid achievement. The trick of such a wisdom is
  • as soon learnt as it is easy to practice; its repetition, when it grows
  • familiar, becomes as intolerable as the repetition of juggling once
  • detected. The instrument of this monotonous formalism is not harder to
  • manipulate than a painter's palette with two colours on it, say red and
  • green, the former to dye the surface if a historic piece, the latter if
  • a landscape is asked for.'
  • Kant (_Werke,_ iii. 36) in the 'Prolegomena to every future
  • Metaphysic,' § 7, says: 'We find, however, it is the peculiarity
  • of mathematical science that it must first exhibit its concept in
  • a percept, and do so _à priori_,--hence in a pure percept. This
  • observation with regard to the nature of mathematics gives a hint as to
  • the first and supreme condition of its possibility: it must be based
  • on some pure percept in which it can exhibit all its concepts _in
  • concreto_ and yet _à priori,_ or, as it is called, _construe_ them.'
  • The phrase, and the emphasis on the doctrine, that perception must be
  • taken as an auxiliary in mathematics,' belong specially to the second
  • edition of the _Kritik, e.g._ Pref. xii. To learn the properties of
  • the isosceles triangle the mathematical student must 'produce (by
  • 'construction') what he himself thought into it and exhibited _à
  • priori_ according to concepts.'
  • 'Construction, in general,' says Schelling (_Werke,_ v. 252:
  • cf. iv. 407) 'is the exhibition of the universal and particular
  • in unity':--'absolute unity of the ideal and the real.' v. 225.
  • Darstellung in intellektueller Anschauung ist philosophische
  • Konstruktion.
  • P. 372. 'Recollection' = Erinnerung: _e.g._ the return from
  • differentiation and externality to simplicity and inwardness:
  • distinguished from Gedächtniss = memory (specially of words).
  • P. 373, § 236. Cf. Schelling, _Werke,_ iv. 405. 'Every particular
  • object is in its absoluteness the Idea; and accordingly the Idea is
  • also the absolute object (Gegenstand) itself,--as the absolutely ideal
  • also the absolutely real.'
  • P. 374, § 236. Aristotle, _Metaphys._ xi. 9 (1074. 6. 34) αὑτὸν ἅρα
  • νοεῖ (ὁ νοῦς = θεος), εἵπερ ἐστὶ τὸ κράτιστον, καὶ ἐστιν ἡ νόησις
  • νοήσεως νόησις. Cf. Arist. _Metaph._ xii. 7.
  • P. 377, §239. 'Supposes a correlative' = ist für Eines. On Seyn: für
  • Eines, cf. _Werke,_ iii. 168. Das Ideëlle ist notwendig für:Eines, aber
  • es ist nicht für ein Anderes: das Eine für welches es ist, ist nur es
  • selbst.... God is therefore for-self (to himself) in so far as he
  • himself is that which is for him.
  • P. 379, § 244. The percipient idea (anschauende Idee), of course both
  • object and subject of intuition, is opposed to the Idea (as logical)
  • in the element of _Thought_: but still _as Idea_ and not--to use
  • Kant's phrase (_Kritik der r. Vern._ § 26)--as _natura materialiter
  • spectata._
  • THE END.
  • End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of The Logic of Hegel, by G. W. F. Hegel
  • *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE LOGIC OF HEGEL ***
  • ***** This file should be named 55108-0.txt or 55108-0.zip *****
  • This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
  • http://www.gutenberg.org/5/5/1/0/55108/
  • Produced by Marc D'Hooghe at Free Literature (online soon
  • in an extended version, also linking to free sources for
  • education worldwide ... MOOC's, educational materials,...)
  • Images generously made available by the Hathi Trust.
  • Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will
  • be renamed.
  • Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
  • law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
  • so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
  • States without permission and without paying copyright
  • royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
  • of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm
  • concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
  • and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive
  • specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this
  • eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook
  • for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports,
  • performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given
  • away--you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks
  • not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the
  • trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
  • START: FULL LICENSE
  • THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  • PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
  • To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
  • distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
  • (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
  • Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at
  • www.gutenberg.org/license.
  • Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
  • and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
  • (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
  • the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
  • destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your
  • possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
  • Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
  • by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the
  • person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph
  • 1.E.8.
  • 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
  • used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
  • agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
  • things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
  • paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this
  • agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  • 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the
  • Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
  • of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual
  • works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
  • States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
  • United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
  • claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
  • displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
  • all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
  • that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting
  • free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
  • Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily
  • comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
  • same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when
  • you share it without charge with others.
  • 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
  • what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
  • in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
  • check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
  • agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
  • distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
  • other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no
  • representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
  • country outside the United States.
  • 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
  • 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
  • immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear
  • prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work
  • on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the
  • phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed,
  • performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
  • This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
  • most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no
  • restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it
  • under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this
  • eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the
  • United States, you'll have to check the laws of the country where you
  • are located before using this ebook.
  • 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is
  • derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
  • contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
  • copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
  • the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
  • redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project
  • Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
  • either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
  • obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
  • with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
  • must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
  • additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
  • will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works
  • posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
  • beginning of this work.
  • 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
  • work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
  • 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
  • electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
  • prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
  • active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm License.
  • 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
  • compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
  • any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
  • to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format
  • other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official
  • version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site
  • (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
  • to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
  • of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain
  • Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the
  • full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
  • 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
  • performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
  • unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  • 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
  • access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  • provided that
  • * You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
  • the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
  • you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
  • to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has
  • agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
  • within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
  • legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
  • payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
  • Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation."
  • * You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
  • you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
  • does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  • License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
  • copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
  • all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • works.
  • * You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
  • any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
  • electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
  • receipt of the work.
  • * You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
  • distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  • 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than
  • are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
  • from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and The
  • Project Gutenberg Trademark LLC, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm
  • trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
  • 1.F.
  • 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
  • effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
  • works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
  • contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
  • or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
  • intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
  • other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
  • cannot be read by your equipment.
  • 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
  • of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
  • Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
  • liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
  • fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
  • LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
  • PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
  • TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
  • LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
  • INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
  • DAMAGE.
  • 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
  • defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
  • receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
  • written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
  • received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
  • with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
  • with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
  • lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
  • or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
  • opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
  • the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
  • without further opportunities to fix the problem.
  • 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
  • in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO
  • OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
  • LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
  • 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
  • warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
  • damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
  • violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
  • agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
  • limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
  • unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
  • remaining provisions.
  • 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
  • trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
  • providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in
  • accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
  • production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
  • including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
  • the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
  • or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or
  • additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any
  • Defect you cause.
  • Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
  • Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
  • electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
  • computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
  • exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
  • from people in all walks of life.
  • Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
  • assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
  • goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
  • remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
  • Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
  • and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future
  • generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
  • Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
  • www.gutenberg.org
  • Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
  • The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
  • 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
  • state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
  • Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
  • number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
  • U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
  • The Foundation's principal office is in Fairbanks, Alaska, with the
  • mailing address: PO Box 750175, Fairbanks, AK 99775, but its
  • volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous
  • locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt
  • Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to
  • date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and
  • official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact
  • For additional contact information:
  • Dr. Gregory B. Newby
  • Chief Executive and Director
  • gbnewby@pglaf.org
  • Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
  • Literary Archive Foundation
  • Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
  • spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
  • increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
  • freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
  • array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
  • ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
  • status with the IRS.
  • The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
  • charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
  • States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
  • considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
  • with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
  • where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
  • DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular
  • state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
  • have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
  • against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
  • approach us with offers to donate.
  • International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
  • any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
  • outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
  • Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
  • methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
  • ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
  • donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate
  • Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works.
  • Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
  • Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be
  • freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
  • distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of
  • volunteer support.
  • Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
  • editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
  • the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
  • necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
  • edition.
  • Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search
  • facility: www.gutenberg.org
  • This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
  • including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  • Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
  • subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.